Theory of Asset Pricing - Pennacchi
Theory of Asset Pricing - Pennacchi
Theory of Asset Pricing - Pennacchi
George Pennacchi
Part I
Single-period Portfolio Choice and Asset Pricing
Chapter 1
individuals sometimes behave in ways inconsistent with standard forms of expected utility.
of investor preferences.
expected utility paradigm are being developed, and examples of such advances
are presented in later chapters of this book.
1.1
the dierence in their future payos. With the exception of assets that pay a
risk-free return, assets payos are random. Thus, a theory of the demand for
assets needs to specify investors preferences over dierent, uncertain payos.
In other words, we need to model how investors choose between assets that
have dierent probability distributions of returns. In this chapter we assume
an environment where an individual chooses among assets that have random
payos at a single future date.
One possible
future date, and this payo has a discrete distribution with n possible outcomes,
n
P
pi = 1 and
(x1 , ..., xn ), and corresponding probabilities (p1 , ..., pn ), where
i=1
pi 0.1 Then the expected value of the payo (or, more simply, the expected
n
P
pi xi .
payo) is x
E [e
x] =
i=1
Is it logical to think that individuals value risky assets based solely on the
until 1713 when Nicholas Bernoulli pointed out a major weakness. He showed
that an assets expected payo was unlikely to be the only criterion that individuals use for valuation.
Interpreting Pauls prize from this coin flipping game as the payo of a risky
asset, how much would he be willing to pay for this asset if he valued it based
on its expected value? If the number of coin flips taken to first arrive at a heads
i
is i, then pi = 12 and xi = 2i1 so that the expected payo equals
1 As is the case in the following example, n, the number of possible outcomes, may be
infinite.
2 A ducat was a 3.5 gram gold coin used throughout Europe.
x =
=
=
X
pi xi = 12 1 + 14 2 + 18 4 +
i=1
1
2 (1
1
2 (1
1
16 8
+ ...
(1.1)
+ 12 2 + 14 4 + 18 8 + ...
+ 1 + 1 + 1 + ... =
The "paradox" is that the expected value of this asset is infinite, but, intuitively, most individuals would pay only a moderate, not infinite, amount to play
this game. In a paper published in 1738, Daniel Bernoulli, a cousin of Nicholas,
provided an explanation for the St. Petersberg Paradox by introducing the concept of expected utility.3 His insight was that an individuals utility or "felicity"
from receiving a payo could dier from the size of the payo and that people
cared about the expected utility of an assets payos, not the expected value of
Pn
its payos. Instead of valuing an asset as x = i=1 pi xi , its value, V , would
be
V E [U (e
x)] =
Pn
i=1 pi Ui
(1.2)
than the rate that probabilities decline. Hence, Daniel Bernoulli introduced the
principle of a diminishing marginal utility of wealth (as expressed in his quote
above) to resolve this paradox.
The first complete axiomatic development of expected utility is due to John
von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (von Neumann and Morgenstern 1944).
Von Neumann, a renowned physicist and mathematician, initiated the field of
game theory, which analyzes strategic decision making. Morgenstern, an economist, recognized the fields economic applications and, together, they provided
a rigorous basis for individual decision-making under uncertainty. We now outline one aspect of their work, namely, to provide conditions that an individuals
preferences must satisfy for these preferences to be consistent with an expected
utility function.
Define a lottery as an asset that has a risky payo and consider an individuals optimal choice of a lottery (risky asset) from a given set of dierent lotteries. All lotteries have possible payos that are contained in the set {x1 , ..., xn }.
In general, the elements of this set can be viewed as dierent, uncertain outcomes. For example, they could be interpreted as particular consumption levels
(bundles of consumption goods) that the individual obtains in dierent states
of nature or, more simply, dierent monetary payments received in dierent
states of the world. A given lottery can be characterized as an ordered set
n
P
pi = 1 and pi 0. A
of probabilities P = {p1 , ..., pn }, where, of course,
i=1
utility function defined over a given lotterys probabilities, that is, an expected
utility function V (p1 , ..., pn ).
Axioms:
1) Completeness
For any two lotteries P and P , either P P , or P P , or P P .
2) Transitivity
If P P and P P , then P P .
3) Continuity
If P P P , there exists some [0, 1] such that P P +(1)P ,
where P + (1 )P denotes a compound lottery, namely with probability
one receives the lottery P and with probability (1 ) one receives the
lottery P .
These three axioms are analogous to those used to establish the existence
of a real-valued utility function in standard consumer choice theory.5
The
fourth axiom is unique to expected utility theory and, as we later discuss, has
important implications for the theorys predictions.
4) Independence
For any two lotteries P and P , P P if for all (0,1] and all P :
P + (1 )P P + (1 )P
Moreover, for any two lotteries P and P , P P if for all (0,1] and all
P :
5A
P + (1 )P P + (1 )P
To better understand the meaning of the independence axiom, note that P
is preferred to P by assumption. Now the choice between P + (1 )P
and P + (1 )P is equivalent to a toss of a coin that has a probability
(1 ) of landing tails, in which case both compound lotteries are equivalent
to P , and a probability of landing heads, in which case the first compound
lottery is equivalent to the single lottery P and the second compound lottery
is equivalent to the single lottery P . Thus, the choice between P + (1 )P
and P + (1 )P is equivalent to being asked, prior to the coin toss, if one
would prefer P to P in the event the coin lands heads.
It would seem reasonable that should the coin land heads, we would go
ahead with our original preference in choosing P over P . The independence
axiom assumes that preferences over the two lotteries are independent of the
way in which we obtain them.6 For this reason, the independence axiom is
also known as the no regret axiom.
Morgenstern expected utility theory continues to be a useful and common ap6 In the context of standard consumer choice theory, would be interpreted as the amount
(rather than probability) of a particular good or bundle of goods consumed (say C) and
(1 ) as the amount of another good or bundle of goods consumed (say C ). In this case,
it would not be reasonable to assume that the choice of these dierent bundles is independent.
This is due to some goods being substitutes or complements with other goods. Hence, the
validity of the independence axiom is linked to outcomes being uncertain (risky), that is, the
interpretation of as a probability rather than a deterministic amount.
7 A similar example is given as an exercise at the end of this chapter.
10
11
corresponding to xj .
From the continuity axiom, we know that for each ei , there exists a Ui [0, 1]
such that
ei Ui en + (1 Ui )e1
(1.3)
and for i = 1, this implies U1 = 0 and for i = n, this implies Un = 1. The values
of the Ui weight the most and least preferred outcomes such that the individual
is just indierent between a combination of these polar payos and the payo of
xi . The Ui can adjust for both dierences in monetary payos and dierences
in the states of nature during which the outcomes are received.
Now consider a given arbitrary lottery, P = {p1 , ..., pn }. This can be considered a compound lottery over the n elementary lotteries, where elementary
lottery ei is obtained with probability pi . By the independence axiom, and using
equation (1.3), the individual is indierent between the compound lottery, P ,
and the following lottery given on the right-hand-side of the equation below:
p1 e1 + ... + pn en
(1.4)
where we have used the indierence relation in equation (1.3) to substitute for
ei on the right hand side of (1.4). By repeating this substitution for all i,
i = 1, ..., n, we see that the individual will be indierent between P , given by
the left hand side of (1.4), and
n
!
!
n
X
X
pi Ui en + 1
pi Ui e1
p1 e1 + ... + pn en
i=1
i=1
(1.5)
12
n
P
i=1
Thus, we know from the dominance axiom that P P if and only if > ,
n
n
P
P
pi Ui >
pi Ui . So defining an expected utility function as
which implies
i=1
i=1
V (p1 , ..., pn ) =
n
X
pi Ui
(1.6)
i=1
will imply that P P if and only if V (p1 , ..., pn ) > V (p1 , ..., pn ).
The function given in equation (1.6) is known as von Neumann - Morgenstern
expected utility. Note that it is linear in the probabilities and is unique up to
a linear monotonic transformation.9 This implies that the utility function has
cardinal properties, meaning that it does not preserve preference orderings
for all strictly increasing transformations.10 For example, if Ui = U (xi ), an
individuals choice over lotteries will be the same under the transformation
aU (xi ) + b, but not a non-linear transformation that changes the shape of
U (xi ).
The von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility framework may only partially explain the phenomenon illustrated by the St. Petersberg Paradox. Suppose an individuals utility is given by the square root of a monetary payo, that
13
X
X
1 i1 X 2i
pi Ui =
2
=
2
2i
i=1
i=1
i=2
2
(1.7)
= 2 2 + 2 2 + ...
i
X
1
1
1
=
1 =
= 1.707
2
2
2
2
i=0
which is finite. This individual would get the same expected utility from receiving a certain payment of 1.7072
= 2.914 ducats since V =
expected (and actual) utility of 1.707.
2.914also gives
Petersberg gamble would be worth 2.914 ducats to this square-root utility maximizer.
However, the reason that this is not a complete resolution of the paradox
is that one can always construct a super St. Petersberg paradox where even
expected utility is infinite. Note that in the regular St. Petersberg paradox,
the probability of winning declines at rate 2i while the winning payo increases
at rate 2i . In a super St. Petersberg paradox, we can make the winning payo
increase at a rate xi = U 1 (2i1 ) and expected utility would no longer be finite.
If we take the example of square-root utility, let the winning payo be xi = 22i2 ,
that is, x1 = 1, x2 = 4, x3 = 16, etc. In this case, the expected utility of the
super St. Petersberg payo by a square-root expected utility maximizer is
V =
X
X
1 2i2
pi Ui =
2
=
2i
i=1
i=1
(1.8)
Should we be concerned by the fact that if we let the prizes grow quickly
enough, we can get infinite expected utility (and valuations) for any chosen form
of expected utility function? Maybe not. One could argue that St. Petersberg
14
games are unrealistic, particularly ones where the payos are assumed to grow
rapidly. The reason is that any person oering this asset has finite wealth (even
Bill Gates). This would set an upper bound on the amount of prizes that could
feasibly be paid, making expected utility, and even the expected value of the
payo, finite.
The von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility approach can be generalized to the case of a continuum of outcomes and lotteries having continuous
probability distributions. For example, if outcomes are a possibly infinite number of purely monetary payos or consumption levels denoted by the variable
x, a subset of the real numbers, then a generalized version of equation (1.6) is
V (F ) = E [U (e
x)] =
U (x) dF (x)
(1.9)
where F (x) is a given lotterys cumulative distribution function over the payos,
x.11 Hence, the generalized lottery represented by the distribution function F
is analogous to our previous lottery represented by the discrete probabilities
P = {p1 , ..., pn }.
Thus far, our discussion of expected utility theory has said little regarding
an appropriate specification for the utility function, U (x). We now turn to a
discussion of how the form of this function aects individuals risk preferences.
1.2
15
the individual would not accept a fair lottery (asset), where a fair or pure
risk lottery is defined as one that has an expected value of zero. To see the
relationship between fair lotteries and concave utility, consider the following
example. Let there be a lottery that has a random payo, e
, where
1 with probability p
e
=
with probability 1 p
(1.10)
The requirement that it be a fair lottery restricts its expected value to equal
zero:
E [e
] = p1 + (1 p)2 = 0
(1.11)
Of
U (W ) > E [U (W + e
)] = pU (W + 1 ) + (1 p)U (W + 2 )
(1.12)
To show that this is equivalent to having a concave utility function, note that
U (W ) can be re-written as
16
(1.13)
(1.14)
E[U (
x)] < U (E[
x])
(1.15)
Therefore, substituting x = W + e
, with E[e
] = 0, we have
E [U (W + e
)] < U (E [W + e
]) = U (W )
(1.16)
Utility
17
U(W + 1 )
U(W )
[- 2 U(W + 1 )+
1 U (W + 2 )]/( 1 - 2 )
U(W + 2 )
= p U (W + 1 ) +
(1-p) U (W + 2 )
W + 2
W + 1
W ealth
avoid a particular risk. John W. Pratt (Pratt 1964) defined the risk premium
for lottery (asset) e
as
U (W ) = E [U (W + e
)]
(1.17)
18
would accept a level of wealth lower than her expected level of wealth following
the lottery, E [W + e
], if the lottery could be avoided.
To analyze this Pratt (1964) risk premium, we continue to assume the indi-
U (W )
= U(W ) U 0 (W )
(1.18)
(1.19)
= U (W ) + 12 2 U 00 (W )
h i
2 is the lotterys variance. Equating the results in (1.18) and
where 2 E e
(1.19), we have
= 12 2
U 00 (W )
12 2 R(W )
U 0 (W )
(1.20)
19
U (W ) = ebW , b > 0
(1.21)
lim U 0 (W ) = lim U 00 (W ) = 0
(1.22)
the same utility function. However, this is not true because the marginal utility
of wealth is also very small. This neutralizes the eect of smaller concavity.
20
Indeed:
R(W ) =
b2 ebW
=b
bebW
(1.23)
which is a constant. Thus, we can see why this utility function is sometimes
referred to as a constant absolute risk aversion utility function.
If we want to assume that absolute risk aversion is declining in wealth, a
necessary, though not sucient, condition for this is that the utility function
have a positive third derivative, since
U 000 (W )U 0 (W ) [U 00 (W )]2
R(W )
=
W
[U 0 (W )]2
(1.24)
Also, it can be shown that the coecient of risk aversion contains all relevant
information about the individuals risk preferences. To see this, note that
R(W ) =
(ln [U 0 (W )])
U 00 (W )
=
U 0 (W )
W
(1.25)
(1.26)
R(W )dW
= U 0 (W )ec1
(1.27)
R(W )dW
dW = ec1 U(W ) + c2
(1.28)
21
are unique up to a linear transformation, ec1 U(W ) + c1 reflects the same risk
preferences as U (W ). Hence, this shows one can recover the risk-preferences of
U (W ) from the function R (W ).
Relative risk aversion is another frequently used measure of risk aversion and
is defined simply as
Rr (W ) = W R(W )
(1.29)
U (W ) = 1 W , < 1
(1.30)
14 The mean estimate was lower, indicating a skewed distribution. Robert Barsky, Thomas
Juster, Miles Kimball, and Matthew Shapiro (Barsky, Juster, Kimball, and Shapiro 1997)
computed these estimates of relative risk aversion from a survey that asked a series of questions regarding whether the respondent would switch to a new job that had a 50-50 chance
of doubling their lifetime income or decreasing their lifetime income by a proportion . By
varying in the questions, they estimated the point where an individual would be indierent
between keeping their current job or switching. Essentially, they attempted to find such
that 12 U (2W ) + 12 U ( W ) = U (W ). Assuming utility displays constant relative risk aversion of the form U (W ) = W /, then the coecient of relative risk aversion, 1 satisfies
2 + = 2. The authors warn that their estimates of risk aversion may be biased upward if
individuals attach non-pecuniary benefits to maintaining their current occupation. Interestingly, they confirmed that estimates of relative risk aversion tended to be lower for individuals
who smoked, drank, were uninsured, held riskier jobs, and invested in riskier assets.
22
(1)
W
and, therefore, Rr (W ) = 1
. Hence, this form of utility is also known as constant relative risk aversion.
Logarithmic utility is a limiting case of power utility.
power utility function as 1 W 1 =
W 1 15
.
W 1
e ln(W ) 1
ln(W )W
= lim
= lim
= ln(W )
0
0
0
(1.31)
lim
R(W ) = W
W 1 =
1
W
and Rr (W ) = 1.
U (W ) = W 2b W 2 , b > 0
(1.32)
1
W
. Thus, this utility function makes sense (in that more wealth is
preferred to less) only when W < 1b . The point of maximum utility, 1b , is known
as the bliss point. We have R(W ) =
b
1bW
and Rr (W ) =
bW
1bW
W
+
1
(1.33)
15 Recall that we can do this because utility functions are unique up to a linear transformation.
23
W
subject to the restrictions 6= 1, > 0, 1
+ > 0, and = 1 if = .
1
W
+
. Since R(W ) must be > 0, it implies > 0 when
Thus, R(W ) = 1
1
W
> 1. Rr (W ) = W 1
+
. HARA utility nests constant absolute risk
Pratts definition of a risk premium in (1.17) is commonly used in the insurance literature because it can be interpreted as the payment that an individual
is willing to make to insure against a particular risk. However, in the field of
financial economics, a somewhat dierent definition is often employed. Financial economists seek to understand how the risk of an assets payo determines
the assets rate of return. In this context, an assets risk premium is defined as
its expected rate of return in excess of the risk-free rate of return. This alternative concept of a risk premium was used by Kenneth Arrow (Arrow 1971) who
independently derived a coecient of risk aversion that is identical to Pratts
measure. Let us now outline Arrows approach. Suppose that an asset (lottery), e
, has the following payos and probabilities (this could be generalized to
where
0.
+ with probability
e
=
with probability
1
2
(1.34)
1
2
question. By how much should we change the expected value (return) of the
asset, by changing the probability of winning, in order to make the individual
24
indierent between taking and not taking the risk? If p is the probability of
winning, we can define the risk premium as
= prob (e
= + ) prob (e
= ) = p (1 p) = 2p 1
(1.35)
(1.36)
These new probabilities of winning and losing are equal to the old probabilities,
1
2,
plus half of the increment, . Thus, the premium, , that makes the individual
U (W ) =
1
1
(1 + )U (W + ) + (1 )U(W )
2
2
U (W ) =
= 0, gives
1
(1 + ) U (W ) + U 0 (W ) + 12 2 U 00 (W )
2
1
+ (1 ) U (W ) U 0 (W ) + 12 2 U 00 (W )
2
= U (W ) + U 0 (W ) +
(1.37)
(1.38)
1 2 00
2 U (W )
1
2
R(W )
(1.39)
25
=
Since
1 2
2 R(W )
(1.40)
Pratt and Arrow measures of risk premia are equivalent. Both were obtained
as a linearization of the true function around e
= 0.
The results of this section showed how risk aversion depends on the shape of
1.3
Having developed the concepts of risk aversion and risk premiums, we now
consider the relation between risk aversion and an individuals portfolio choice
in a single period context. While the portfolio choice problem that we analyze
is very simple, many of its insights extend to the more complex environments
that will be covered in later chapters of this book. We shall demonstrate that
absolute and relative risk aversion play important roles in determining how
portfolio choices vary with an individuals level of wealth. Moreover, we show
that when given a choice between a risk-free asset and a risky asset, a risk-averse
individual always chooses at least some positive investment in the risky asset if
it pays a positive risk premium.
The models assumptions are as follows. Assume there is a riskless security
that pays a rate of return equal to rf . In addition, for simplicity suppose there
is just one risky security that pays a stochastic rate of return equal to re. Also,
26
let W0 be the individuals initial wealth, and let A be the dollar amount that
the individual invests in the risky asset at the beginning of the period. Thus,
W0 A is the initial investment in the riskless security. Denoting the individuals
, it satisfies:
end-of-period wealth as W
(1.41)
= W0 (1 + rf ) + A(
r rf )
Note that in the second line of equation (1.41), the first term is the individuals
return on wealth when the entire portfolio is invested in the risk-free asset, while
the second term is the dierence in return gained by investing A dollars in the
risky asset.
We assume that the individual cares only about consumption at the end of
this single period. Therefore, maximizing end-of-period consumption is equivalent to maximizing end-of-period wealth. Assuming that the individual is a von
Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility maximizer, she chooses her portfolio by
maximizing the expected utility of end-of-period wealth:
)] = maxE [U (W0 (1 + rf ) + A(
r rf ))]
maxE[U (W
A
(1.42)
The solution to the individuals problem in (1.42) must satisfy the following
first order condition with respect to A:
i
h
(
r rf ) = 0
E U0 W
(1.43)
This condition determines the amount, A, that the individual invests in the
27
turn on the risky asset equals the risk-free rate. In that case A = 0 satisfies the first order condition.
reminiscent of our earlier finding that a risk-averse individual would not choose
to accept a fair lottery. Here, the fair lottery is interpreted as a risky asset that
has an expected rate of return just equal to the risk-free rate.
Next, consider the case in which E[
r]rf > 0. Clearly, A = 0 would not sati
h
(
r rf ) = U 0 (W0 (1 + rf )) E[
r
isfy the first order condition because E U 0 W
rf ] > 0 when A = 0. Rather, when E[
r] rf > 0 condition (1.43) is satisfied
only when A > 0. To see this, let rh denote a realization of r such that it exceeds
. Also let rl denote a realization
rf , and let W h be the corresponding level of W
.
of r such that it is lower than rf , and let W l be the corresponding level of W
(
r rf )
Obviously, U 0 (W h )(rh rf ) > 0 and U 0 (W l )(rl rf ) < 0. For U 0 W
to average to zero for all realizations of r, it must be the case that W h > W l
so that U 0 W h < U 0 W l due to the concavity of the utility function. This is
because since E[
r]rf > 0, the average realization of rh is farther above rf than
(
r rf )
the average realization of rl is below rf . Therefore, to make U 0 W
realizations. This can occur only if A > 0 so that W h > W l . The implication
is that an individual will always hold at least some positive amount of the risky
asset if its expected rate of return exceeds the risk-free rate.17
k
2 l
r rf
second order condition for a maximum, E U 00 W
0, is satisfied be
0 due to the assumed concavity of the utility function.
cause U 00 W
17 Related to this is the notion that a risk-averse expected utility maximizer should accept
a small lottery with a positive expected return. In other words, such an individual should
be close to risk-neutral for small-scale bets. However, Matthew Rabin and Richard Thaler
(Rabin and Thaler 2001) claim that individuals frequently reject lotteries (gambles) that are
16 The
28
i
h
i
h
)(
)(
E U 00 (W
r rf )(1 + rf ) dW0 + E U 00 (W
r rf )2 dA = 0
(1.44)
or
h
i
)(
r rf )
(1 + rf )E U 00 (W
dA
i
h
=
dW0
)(
E U 00 (W
r rf )2
(1.45)
objective function when the control variable, A, is optimally chosen. Also define A (W0 ) as
the value of A that maximizes f for a given value of W0 . Then applying the chain rule, we
dv(W )
f (A,W0 ) dA(W0 )
f (A(W0 ),W0 )
f(A,W0 )
have dW 0 =
+
. But since
= 0, from the first
A
dW
W
A
0
dv(W0 )
0 ),W0 )
= f(A(W
. Again applying the chain rule
dW0
W0
(f(A(W0 ),W0 )/A)
2 f (A(W0 ),W0 ) dA(W0 )
=0=
+
to the first order condition, one obtains
W0
dW0
A2
2 f (A(W0 ),W0 )
dA(W0 )
2 f (A(W0 ),W0 ) 2 f(A(W0 ),W0 )
. Re-arranging gives us dW
=
/
, which is
AW0
AW0
A2
0
equation (1.45).
29
implies
R W h 6 R (W0 (1 + rf ))
(1.46)
(1.47)
Next, we again let rl denote a realization of r that is lower than rf and define W l
. Then for A > 0, we have W l 6 W0 (1 + rf ).
to be the corresponding level of W
If absolute risk aversion is decreasing in wealth, this implies
(1.48)
(1.49)
Notice that inequalities (1.47) and (1.49) are of the same form. The inequality
holds whether the realization is r = rh or r = rl . Therefore, if we take expectations over all realizations, where r can be either higher than or lower than rf ,
we obtain
h
i
h
i
)(
)(
E U 00 (W
r rf ) > E U 0 (W
r rf ) R (W0 (1 + rf ))
(1.50)
Since the first term on the right-hand-side is just the first order condition,
inequality (1.50) reduces to
30
i
h
)(
r rf ) > 0
E U 00 (W
(1.51)
Thus, the first conclusion that can be drawn is that declining absolute risk aversion implies dA/dW0 > 0, that is, the individual invests an increasing amount of
wealth in the risky asset for larger amounts of initial wealth. For two individuals
with the same utility function but dierent initial wealths, the more wealthy one
invests a greater dollar amount in the risky asset if utility is characterized by
decreasing absolute risk aversion. While not shown here, the opposite is true,
namely, that the more wealthy individual invests a smaller dollar amount in the
risky asset if utility is characterized by increasing absolute risk aversion.
Thus far, we have not said anything about the proportion of initial wealth
invested in the risky asset. To analyze this issue, we need the concept of relative
risk aversion. Define
dA W0
dW0 A
(1.52)
which is the elasticity measuring the proportional increase in the risky asset for
an increase in initial wealth. Adding 1 A
A to the right hand side of (1.52) gives
=1+
(dA/dW0 )W0 A
A
(1.53)
(1.54)
i
h
)(
r rf ){W0 (1 + rf ) + A(
r rf )}
E U 00 (W
i
h
= 1+
)(
AE U 00 (W
r rf )2
h
i
)(
E U 00 (W
r rf )W
i
h
= 1+
)(
AE U 00 (W
r rf )2
31
(1.55)
greater than one, so that the individual invests proportionally more in the risky
i
h
)(
> 0. Can we relate
r rf )W
asset with an increase in wealth, if E U 00 (W
this to the individuals risk aversion? The answer is yes and the derivation is
almost exactly the same as that just given.
Consider the case where the individual has relative risk aversion that is
decreasing in wealth. Let rh denote a realization of r such that it exceeds
W h R(W h ) 6 W0 (1 + rf )R (W0 (1 + rf ))
(1.56)
32
(1.58)
(1.59)
Notice that inequalities (1.57) and (1.59) are of the same form. The inequality
holds whether the realization is r = rh or r = rl . Therefore, if we take expectations over all realizations, where r can be either higher than or lower than rf ,
we obtain
h
i
h
i
U 00 (W
)(
)(
E W
r rf ) > E U 0 (W
r rf ) W0 (1+rf )R(W0 (1+rf )) (1.60)
Since the first term on the right-hand-side is just the first order condition,
inequality (1.60) reduces to
i
h
)(
U 00 (W
r rf ) > 0
E W
(1.61)
Thus, we see that an individual with decreasing relative risk aversion has > 1
and invests proportionally more in the risky asset as wealth increases. The
opposite is true for increasing relative risk aversion: < 1 so that this individual
invests proportionally less in the risky asset as wealth increases. The following
table provides another way of writing this sections main results.
1.4. SUMMARY
33
Risk Aversion
Investment Behavior
Decreasing Absolute
A
W0
>0
Constant Absolute
A
W0
=0
Increasing Absolute
A
W0
<0
Decreasing Relative
A
W0
>
A
W0
Constant Relative
A
W0
A
W0
Increasing Relative
A
W0
<
A
W0
A point worth emphasizing is that absolute risk aversion indicates how the
investors dollar amount in the risky asset changes with changes in initial wealth
while relative risk aversion indicates how the investors portfolio proportion
(or portfolio weight) in the risky asset, A/W0 , changes with changes in initial
wealth.
1.4
Summary
the monetary payment that the individual is willing to pay to avoid a risk, an
example being a premium paid to insure against a property/casualty loss. The
second is the rate of return in excess of a riskless rate that the individual requires
to hold a risky asset, which is the common definition of a security risk premium
used in the finance literature. Finally, it was shown how an individuals absolute
and relative risk aversion aects his choice between a risky and risk-free asset. In
34
1.5
Exercises
1. Suppose there are two lotteries P = {p1 , ..., pn } and P = {p1 , ..., pn }. Let
n
P
pi Ui be an individuals expected utility function defined
V (p1 , ..., pn ) =
i=1
n
P
i=1
If oered the
x
that ea = lim 1 + xa .
x
As-
1.5. EXERCISES
35
rf with probability 1
2
of initial wealth invested in the risky asset, A/W0 .
Asset A =
Asset C =
X with probability px
0 with probability 1 px
X with probability px
0 with probability 1 px
Asset B =
Y with probability py
0 with probability 1 py
Asset D =
Y with probability py
0 with probability 1 py
36
Chapter 2
Mean-Variance Analysis
The preceding chapter studied an investors choice between a risk-free asset
and a single risky asset.
As a University of
allocating wealth among various risky assets, a risk-averse investor should focus
on the expectation and the risk of her combined portfolios return, a return
that is aected by the individual assets diversification possibilities. Because of
diversification, the attractiveness of a particular asset when held in a portfolio
can dier from its appeal when it is the sole asset held by an investor.
Markowitz proxied the risk of a portfolios return by the variance of its return. Of course, the variance of an investors total portfolio return depends on
the return variances of the individual assets included in the portfolio. But portfolio return variance also depends on the covariances of the individual assets
1 His work on portfolio theory, of which this article was the beginning, won him a share of
the Nobel prize in economics in 1990. Initially, the importance of his work was not widelyrecognized. Milton Friedman, a member of Markowitzs doctoral dissertation committee and
who also became a Nobel laureate, questioned whether the work met the requirements for an
economics Ph.D. See Bernstein (Bernstein 1992).
37
38
returns.
Interestingly,
not all portfolios that an investor can create are ecient in this sense. Given
the expected returns and covariances of returns on individual assets, Markowitz
solved the investors problem of constructing an ecient portfolio. His work has
had an enormous impact on the theory and practice of portfolio management
and asset pricing.
Intuitively, it makes sense that investors would want their wealth to earn
a high average return with as little variance as possible.
However, in gen-
eral, an individual who maximizes expected utility may care about moments
of the distribution of wealth in addition to its mean and variance.2
Though
Markowitzs mean - variance analysis fails to consider the eects of these other
moments, in later chapters of this book we will see that his models insights can
be generalized to more complicated settings.
The next section outlines the assumptions on investor preferences and the
distribution of asset returns that would allow us to simplify the investors portfolio choice problem to one that considers only the mean and variance of portfolio
returns. We then analyze a risk-averse investors preferences by showing that
he has indierence curves that imply a trade-o of expected return for variance.
2 For
example, expected utility can depend on the skewness (the third moment) of the return
on wealth. The observation that some people purchase lottery tickets, even though these
investments have a negative expected rate of return, suggests that their utility is enhanced
by positive skewness. Alan Kraus and Robert Litzenberger (Kraus and Litzenberger 1976)
developed a single-period portfolio selection and asset pricing model that extends Markowitzs
analysis to consider investors who have a preference for skewness. Their results generalize
Markowitzs model, but his fundamental insights are unchanged. For simplicity, this chapter
focuses on the orginal Markowitz framework. Recent empirical work by Campbell Harvey
and Akhtar Siddique (Harvey and Siddique 2000) examines the eect of skewness on asset
pricing.
39
2.1
Suppose an expected utility maximizing individual invests her beginning-ofep be the random
period wealth, W0 , in a particular portfolio of assets. Let R
=
return on this portfolio, so that the individuals end-of-period wealth is W
ep ) , because W
ep as just U (R
) = U W0 R
notational simplicity we write U (W
ep .
is completely determined by R
3 Thus,
40
ep ]
ep ] + R
ep E[R
ep ] U 0 E[R
ep ) = U E[R
U (R
ep E[R
ep ] + ...
ep ] U 00 E[R
+ 12 R
1
ep E[R
ep ] + ...
ep ] U (n) E[R
R
+ n!
(2.1)
Now let us investigate the conditions that would make this individuals expected utility depend only on the mean and variance of the portfolio return.
We first analyze the restrictions on the form of utility, and then the restrictions
on the distribution of asset returns, that would produce this result.
Note that if the utility function is quadratic, so that all derivatives of order 3
and higher are equal to zero (U (n) = 0, n 3), then the individuals expected
utility is
h
00
ep E[R
ep ]
ep ] + 1 E R
ep ]
ep ) = U E[R
E[
R
E U (R
U
2
ep ]
ep ]U 00 E[R
ep ] + 1 V [R
= U E[R
2
(2.2)
Next, suppose that utility is not quadratic, but any general increasing, con-
cave form. Are there particular probability distributions for portfolio returns
that make expected utility, again, depend only on the portfolio returns mean
4 The
k
l
hp E[R
hp ] U 0 E[R
hp ] ,
R
41
A portfolio (sum)
of assets whose returns are multivariate normally distributed also has a return
that is normally distributed.
To verify that expected utility depends only on the portfolio returns mean
and variance when this return is normally distributed, note that the third,
fourth, and all higher central moments of the normal distribution are either
n i
h
ep ]
ep E[R
= 0, for n odd, and
zero or a function of the variance: E R
h
n i
n/2
n!
1
ep ]
e
ep E[R
= (n/2)!
E R
, for n even. Therefore, for this case
2 V [Rp ]
the individuals expected utility equals
h
i
ep ] + 0 + 1 V [ R
ep ]
ep ] U 0000 E[R
ep ) = U E[R
ep ] + 1 V [R
ep ]U 00 E[R
E U(R
2
8
n/2
1 e
1
ep ] + ...
V [Rp ]
U (n) E[R
(2.3)
+0 + ... +
(n/2)! 2
42
which depends only on the mean and variance of the portfolio return.
In summary, restricting utility to be quadratic or restricting the distribution
h
i
ep ) as a function of only
of asset returns to be normal allows us to write E U (R
5 A related problem is that many standard utility functions, such as constant relative risk
aversion, are not defined for negative values of portfolio wealth.
43
see that the results derived here assuming a single-period, discrete-time model
continue to hold, under particular conditions, in the more realistic multi-period
context.
2.2
represented by the combinations of portfolio risk and expected return that can
be created from dierent portfolios of individual assets.
Historically, mean
- variance analysis has been illustrated graphically, and we will follow that
convention while also providing analytic results.
Note that an investors expected utility can then be written
h i Z
ep =
E U R
p , 2p )dR
U (R)f (R; R
(2.4)
To gain insight regarding this investors preferences over portfolio risk and expected return, we wish to determine the characteristics of this individuals indifference curves in portfolio mean-variance space. An indierence curve represents
44
the combinations of portfolio mean and variance that would give the individual
the same level of expected utility.6 To understand this relation, let us begin by
defining x
e
p
p R
R
p .
Then
h i Z
ep =
E U R
p + x p )n(x)dx
U(R
(2.5)
(2.6)
since U 0 is always greater than zero. Next, take the partial derivative of (2.5)
with respect to 2p :
h i
ep
E U R
2p
h i
Z
ep
E
U R
1
1
=
=
U 0 xn(x)dx
2p
p
2p
(2.7)
p + xi p )xi n(xi ) + U 0 (R
p xi p )(xi )n(xi )
U 0 (R
45
(2.8)
p + xi p )xi n(xi ) U 0 (R
p xi p )xi n(xi )
= U 0 (R
p + xi p ) U 0 (R
p xi p ) < 0
= xi n(xi ) U 0 (R
because
+ xi p ) < U 0 (R
xi p )
U 0 (R
(2.9)
due to the assumed concavity of U, that is, the individual is risk averse so that
U 00 < 0. Thus, comparing U 0 xi n(xi ) for each positive and negative pair, we
conclude that
h i
ep
E U R
2p
1
2 p
U 0 xn(x)dx < 0
(2.10)
which is the intuitive result that higher portfolio variance, without higher portfolio expected return, reduces a risk-averse individuals expected utility.
Finally, an indierence curve is the combinations of portfolio mean and variance that leaves expected utility unchanged. In other words, it is combinations
h i
h i
h i
ep
ep
h i E U R
E U R
2
p = 0
ep =
d
+
dR
dE U R
p
p
2p
R
(2.11)
which, based on our previous results, tells us that each indierence curve is
p , 2 space:
positively sloped in R
p
46
Rp
Increasing Utility
/
>0
p
d2p
2p
R
(2.12)
Thus, the indierence curves slope in (2.12) quantifies the extent to which
the individual requires a higher portfolio mean for accepting a higher portfolio
variance.
Indierence curves are typically drawn in mean - standard deviation space,
rather than mean - variance space, because standard deviations of returns are in
the same unit of measurement as returns or interest rates (rather than squared
returns).
47
portfolio means and standard deviations (or variances), let us consider next
what portfolio means and standard deviations are possible given the available
distributions of returns for individual assets.
2.3
As we shall later
prove, ecient portfolios have the attractive characteristic that any two ecient
portfolios can be used to create any other ecient portfolio.
2.3.1
A Simple Example
48
A + (1 )R
B
Rp = R
(2.13)
p = 2 2A + 2(1 )A B + (1 )2 2B 2
(2.14)
In general, portfolio risk, as measured by the portfolios return standard deviation, is a nonlinear function of the individual assets variances and covariances.
Thus, risk is altered in a relatively complex way when individual assets are
combined in a portfolio.
Let us consider some special cases regarding the correlation between the two
assets. Suppose = 1, so that the two assets are perfectly positively correlated.
Then the portfolio standard deviation equals
1
2 2
A + 2(1 ) A B + (1 )2 2B 2
(2.15)
= | A + (1 )B |
p
R
B + p B (R
A)
B R
= R
B A
B R
A A R
B
A
B R
R
=
p
B A
B A
49
(2.16)
Thus, the relationship between portfolio risk and expected return are two straight
A AR
B / (B A )
p space. They have the same intercept of B R
lines in p , R
and have slopes of the same magnitude but opposite signs. The positively sloped
A ) and (B , R
B ) when = 1 and = 0,
line goes through the points (A , R
respectively. When = B / (B A ) > 1, indicating a short position in asset
B, we see from (2.15) that all portfolio risk is eliminated (p = 0). Figure 2.2
provides a graphical illustration of these relationships.
Next, suppose = 1, so that the assets are perfectly negatively correlated.
Then
( A (1 ) B )2 2
(2.17)
= | A (1 )B |
p = A RB + B RA RB RA p
R
A + B
A + B
(2.18)
50
=1
Rp
RB
-1 < < 1
= -1
RA
= -1
=1
These lines
represent the so-called ecient portfolio frontier. The exact portfolio chosen by
the individual would be where her indierence curve is tangent to the frontier.
When correlation between the assets is imperfect (1 < < 1), the relationship between portfolio expected return and standard deviation is not linear, but,
as illustrated in Figure 2.2, is hyperbolic. In this case, it is no longer possible
to create a riskless portfolio, so that the portfolio having minimum standard
deviation is one where p > 0. We now set out to prove these assertions for
the general case of n assets.
2.3.2
51
Robert C. Merton (Merton 1972) provided an analytical solution to the following portfolio choice problem: Given the expected returns and the matrix of
covariances of returns for n individual assets, find the set of portfolio weights
that minimizes the variance of the portfolio for each feasible portfolio expected
return. The locus of these points in portfolio expected return - variance space is
the portfolio frontier. This section presents the derivation of Mertons solution.
We begin by specifying the problems notation and assumptions.
2 ... R
n )0 be an n 1 vector of the expected returns of the
= (R
1 R
Let R
n assets.
portfolio is given by
p = 0 R
(2.19)
2p = 0 V
(2.20)
The constraint that the portfolio proportions must sum to 1 can be written as
0 e = 1 where e is defined to be an n 1 vector of ones.
The problem of finding the portfolio frontier now can be stated as a quadratic
optimization exercise: minimize the portfolios variance subject to the con9 This implies that there are no redundant assets among the n assets. An asset would be
redundant if its return was an exact linear combination of the the returns on other assets.
If such an asset exists, it can be ignored, since its availability does not aect the ecient
portfolio frontier.
52
straints that the portfolios expected return equals Rp and the portfolios weights
sum to one.10
+ [1 0 e]
min 21 0 V + Rp 0 R
(2.21)
The first order conditions with respect to and the two Lagrange multipliers,
and , are:
e = 0
V R
(2.22)
=0
Rp 0 R
(2.23)
1 0 e = 0
(2.24)
+ V 1 e
= V 1 R
(2.25)
0 , we have
Pre-multiplying equation (2.25) by R
0 = R
0 V 1 R
+ R
0 V 1 e
Rp = R
(2.26)
+ e0 V 1 e
1 = e0 = e0 V 1 R
(2.27)
Equations (2.26) and (2.27) are two linear equations in two unknowns, and .
10 In (2.21), the problem actually minimizes one-half the portfolio variance to avoid carrying
an extra "2" in the first order condition (2.22). The solution is the same as minimizing the
total variance and only changes the scale of the Lagrange multipliers.
53
The solution is
Rp
2
(2.28)
Rp
2
(2.29)
R
0 V 1 R,
and e0 V 1 e are scalars. Note
0 V 1 e = e0 V 1 R,
where R
that the denominators of and , given by 2 , are guaranteed to be positive
when V is of full rank.11 Substituting for and in equation (2.25), we have
Rp 1 Rp 1
V R+
V e
2
2
(2.30)
p gives
Collecting terms in R
= a + bRp
where a
(2.31)
V 1 e
V 1 R
V 1 e V 1 R
and
b
.
2
2
11
1
To see
this, note thatsince V is positive definite,
so is V . Therefore the quadratic form
R e V 1 R e = 2 22 + 2 = 2 is positive. But since RV 1 R
is a positive quadratic form, then 2 must also be positive.
54
p2
2
mv
Rmv
Rp
= 0 V = (a + bRp )0 V (a + bRp )
2p
=
=
(2.32)
2
Rp
2Rp +
2
2
1 Rp
+
where the second line in equation (2.32) results from substituting in the definitions of a and b and simplifying the resulting expression.
Equation (2.32)
line in equation (2.32), it is obvious that the unique minimum is at the point
Rp = Rmv
Substituting Rp =
weights mv = 1 V 1 e.
Each point on the parabola in Figure 2.3 represents an investors lowest possible portfolio variance given some target level of expected return, Rp . However,
55
an investor whose utility is increasing in expected portfolio return and is decreasing in portfolio variance would never choose a portfolio having Rp < Rmv ,
that is, points on the parabola to the left of Rmv . This is because the frontier
portfolios variance actually increases as the target expected return falls when
Rp < Rmv , making this target expected return region irrelevant to an optimizing investor. Hence, the ecient portfolio frontier is represented only by the
region Rp Rmv .
Traditionally, portfolios satisfying (2.32) are graphed in p , Rp space. Taking the square root of both sides of equation (2.32), p becomes a hyperbolic
function of Rp . When this is graphed as in Figure 2.4 with Rp on the vertical
axis and p on the horizontal one, only the upper arc of the hyperbola is relevant because, as stated above, investors would not choose target levels of Rp <
Rmv . Dierentiating (2.32), we can also see that the hyperbolas slope equals
Rp
2
p
=
p
Rp
(2.33)
q
2
p,
while the
2.3.3
Portfolio Separation
56
Rp
Asymptote of upper arc
R p = Rmv +
2
p
Efficient Frontier
Rmv
R p = Rmv
R p2 2 R p +
2
2
p
mv
returns are distributed N R, V and, therefore, the frontier is (2.32), then they
can form their individually preferred frontier portfolios by trading in as little as
two frontier portfolios. For example, if a security market oered two mutual
funds, each invested in a dierent frontier portfolio, any mean-variance investor
could replicate his optimal portfolio by appropriately dividing his wealth between only these two mutual funds.13
1p and R
2p be the
The proof of this separation result is as follows. Let R
3p be the expected
expected returns on any two distinct frontier portfolios. Let R
13 To form his preferred frontier portfolio, an investor may require a short position in one
of the frontier mutual funds. Since short positions are not possible with typical open ended
mutual funds, the better analogy would be that these funds are exchange-traded funds (ETFs)
which do permit short positions.
57
= xR
1p + (1 x)R
2p
R
3p
(2.34)
In addition, because portfolios 1 and 2 are frontier portfolios, we can write their
portfolio proportions as a linear function of their expected returns. Specifically,
1p and 2 = a +bR
2p where i is the n 1 vector of optimal
we have 1 = a +bR
portfolio weights for frontier portfolio i. Now create a new portfolio with an n1
vector of portfolio weights given by x 1 + (1 x)2 . The portfolio proportions
of this new portfolio can be written as
x1 + (1 x) 2
1p ) + (1 x)(a + bR
2p )
= x(a + bR
(2.35)
1p + (1 x)R
2p )
= a + b(xR
3p = 3
= a + bR
where, in the last line of (2.35) we have substituted in equation (2.34). Based
on the portfolio weights of the composite portfolio, x 1 + (1 x) 2 ,equalling
3p , which is the portfolio weights of the third frontier portfolio, 3 , this
a + bR
composite portfolio equals the third frontier portfolio. Hence, any given ecient
portfolio can be replicated by two frontier portfolios.
Portfolios on the mean-variance frontier have an additional property that will
prove useful to the next sections analysis of portfolio choice when a riskless asset
14 x
58
1V 2
= (a + bR1p )0 V (a + bR2p )
+
=
R
1p
2p
2
(2.36)
Setting this equal to zero and solving for R2p , the expected return on the portfolio that has zero covariance with portfolio 1 is
R2p
R1p
= Rmv
(2.37)
R1p Rmv
2
Note that if R1p Rmv > 0 so that frontier portfolio 1 is ecient, then
equation (2.37) indicates that R2p < Rmv , implying that frontier portfolio 2
must be inecient.
Rp = R0 +
where
Rp
p
Rp
p
p p =1p
(2.38)
59
Tangent to Portfolio 1
Rp
R1 p
R mv
2
R0 = R 2 p
mv 2 p
1p
Rp
2
1p 1p
p =1p 1p = R1p
p
R1p
"
2 #
1 R1p
2
+
= R1p
2
R1p
= R1p
(2.39)
R1p
= R2p
Hence, as shown in Figure 2.5, the intercept of the line tangent to frontier portfolio 1 equals the expected return of its zero covariance counterpart, frontier
portfolio 2 .
60
2.4
Thus far, we have assumed that investors can hold only risky assets. An implication of our analysis was that while all investors would choose ecient portfolios
of risky assets, these portfolios would dier based on the particular investors
level of risk aversion. However, as we shall now see, introducing a riskless asset
can simplify the investors portfolio choice problem. This augmented portfolio
choice problem, whose solution was first derived by James Tobin (Tobin 1958),
is one that we now consider.15
Assume that there is a riskless asset with return Rf . Let continue to
be the n 1 vector of portfolio proportions invested in the risky assets. Now,
however, the constraint 0 e = 1 does not apply, because 1 0 e is the portfolio
proportion invested in the riskless asset. We can impose the restriction that the
portfolio weights for all n + 1 assets sum to one by writing the expected return
on the portfolio as
Rf e)
p = Rf + 0 (R
R
(2.40)
Rf e)
min 21 0 V + Rp Rf + 0 (R
(2.41)
In a manner similar to the previous derivation, the first order conditions lead
to the solution
Rf e)
= V 1 (R
(2.42)
15 Tobins work on portfolio selection was one of his contributions cited by the selection
committee that awarded him the Nobel prize in economics in 1981.
61
Rp Rf
Rp Rf
1
where
is posi=
0
2 . Since V
1
2R
+
R
f
R Rf e V (R Rf e)
f
tive definite, is non-negative when Rp Rf , the region of the ecient frontier
where investors expected portfolio return is at least as great as the risk-free
return. Given (2.42), the amount optimally invested in the riskless asset is determined by 1 e0 w . Note that since is linear in Rp , so is , similar to the
previous case of no riskless asset. The variance of the portfolio now takes the
form
2p = 0 V =
(Rp Rf )2
2Rf + Rf2
(2.43)
Rp = Rf 2Rf + R2f 2 p
(2.44)
slope of 2Rf + Rf2 . Of course, only the positively sloped line is the
ecient portion of the frontier.
62
Efficient Frontier
Rp
Rp = R f +
RA
RA R f
Rmv
Rf
mv A
asset.
Let us start by proving this result for the situation where Rf < Rmv . We as 12
sert that the ecient frontier given by the line Rp = Rf + 2Rf + R2f p
can be replicated by a portfolio consisting of only the riskless asset and a portfo-
lio on the risky asset only frontier that is determined by a straight line tangent
to this frontier whose intercept is Rf . This situation is illustrated in Figure 2.6
where A denotes the portfolio of risky assets determined by the tangent line
having intercept Rf . If we can show that the slope of this tangent line equals
12
portfolio. Then the results of (2.37) and (2.39) allow us to write the slope of
17 Note that if a proportion x is invested in any risky asset portfolio having expected return
and standard deviation of RA and A , respectively, and a proportion 1 x is invested in the
riskless asset having certain return Rf , then the combined portfolio has an expected return
and standard deviation of Rp = Rf + x RA Rf and p = x A , respectively. When
graphed in Rp , p space, we can substitute for x to show that these combination portfolios
RA Rf
A
p whose intercept is Rf .
63
the tangent as
"
#
2
Rf /A
2
=
Rf
"
#
2Rf Rf2
=
/ A
Rf
RA Rf
A
(2.45)
2A
=
=
=
2
1 RA
+
2
2
1
+ 3
Rf 2
(2.46)
Rf2 2Rf +
2
2 Rf
RA Rf
A
"
2Rf Rf2
Rf
2
1
Rf 2Rf + 2
Rf
12
R2f 2Rf +
(2.47)
64
they choose to allocate to this portfolio of risky assets versus the risk-free asset.
Along the ecient frontier depicted in Figure 2.7, the proportion of an investors
total wealth held in the tangency portfolio, e , increases as one moves to the
case if, say, investor 1 had an indierence curve tangent to the ecient frontier
at point 1 , Rp1 , then 0 < e < 1 and positive proportions of wealth are
invested in the risk-free asset and the tangency portfolio of risky assets. At
if, say, investor 2 had an indierence curve tangent to the ecient frontier at
the risk-free asset. The interpretation is that investor 2 borrows at the risk-free
rate to invest more than 100 percent of her wealth in the tangency portfolio of
risky assets.
risky assets "on margin," that is leveraging her asset purchases with borrowed
money.
It will later be argued that Rf < Rmv , the situation depicted in Figures
2.6 and 2.7, is required for asset market equilibrium.
However, we briefly
describe the implications of other parametric cases. When Rf > Rmv , the
12
2Rf + Rf2 p becomes tangent. The proceeds from this short selling
are then wholly invested in the risk-free asset.
It is
65
Efficient Frontier
Rp
Indifference Curve
Investor 2
Rp2
RA
Indifference Curve
Investor 1
R p1
Rf
short-selling particular risky assets are used to finance long positions in other
risky assets.
2.4.1
To illustrate our results, let us specify a form for an individuals utility function.
This enables us to determine the individuals preferred ecient portfolio, that
is, the point of tangency between the individuals highest indierence curve and
the ecient frontier. Given a specific utility function and normally distributed
asset returns, we show how the individuals optimal portfolio weights can be
derived directly by maximizing expected utility.
be the individuals end-of-period wealth and assume that
As before, let W
66
) = ebW
U(W
(2.48)
(2.49)
p is the total return (one plus the rate of return) on the portfolio.
where R
In this problem, we assume that initial wealth can be invested in a riskless
asset and n risky assets. As before, denote the return on the riskless asset as
Also as before,
Rf and the returns on the n risky assets as the n 1 vector R.
let = (1 ... n )0 be the vector of portfolio weights for the n risky assets. The
risky assets returns are assumed to have a joint normal distribution where R
is the n 1 vector of expected returns on the n risky assets and V is the n n
covariance matrix of returns. Thus, the expected return on the portfolio can be
Rf e) and the variance of the return on the portfolio
p Rf + 0 (R
written R
is 2p 0 V .
Now recall the properties of the lognormal distribution. If x
is a normally
distributed random variable, for example, x
N(, 2 ), then z = exh is lognor-
E[
z ] = e+ 2
(2.50)
h i
1 2 0
f e)]+ 2 br V
f = ebr [Rf +0 (RR
E U W
67
(2.51)
f e)]+ 2 br V
f = max ebr [Rf +0 (RR
maxE U W
(2.52)
Because the expected utility function is monotonic in its exponent, the maximization problem in (2.52) is equivalent to
Rf e) 1 br 0 V
max 0 (R
2
(2.53)
Rf e br V = 0
R
(2.54)
1 1
V (R Rf e)
br
(2.55)
Rf e)
br
R Rf e V 1 (R
(2.56)
so that the greater the investors relative risk aversion, br , the smaller is her
target mean portfolio return, Rp , and the smaller is the proportion of wealth
invested in the risky assets. In fact, multiplying both sides of (2.55) by W0 , we
see that the absolute amount of wealth invested in the risky assets is
68
1
Rf e)
W0 = V 1 (R
b
(2.57)
Therefore, the individual with constant absolute risk aversion, b, invests a fixed
dollar amount in the risky assets, independent of her initial wealth. As wealth
increases, each additional dollar is invested in the risk-free asset. Recall that
this same result was derived at the end of Chapter 1 for the special case of a
single risky asset.
As in this example, constant absolute risk aversions property of making risky
asset choice independent of wealth often allows for simple solutions to portfolio
choice problems when asset returns are assumed to be normally distributed.
However, the unrealistic implication that both wealthy and poor investors invest
the same dollar amount in risky assets limits the empirical applications of using
this form of utility. As we shall see in later chapters of this book, models where
utility displays constant relative risk aversion is more typical.
2.5
An Application to Cross-Hedging
Conversely, y < 0
example of this case would be a utility that generates electricity from oil.
69
00
=
001
01
11
(2.58)
70
W = ps0 s p1 y
(2.59)
What the operator must decide is the date 0 positions in the financial securities. We assume that the operator chooses s in order to maximize the following
objective function that depends linearly on the mean and variance of profit:
maxE[W ] 12 V ar[W ]
s
(2.60)
As was shown in the previous sections (2.53), this objective function results
from maximizing expected utility of wealth when portfolio returns are normally
distributed and utility displays constant absolute risk aversion.21 Substituting
in for the operators profit, we have
(2.61)
ps [11 s y001 ] = 0
(2.62)
s =
=
1 1 s
0
p + y1
11 01
11
1 1 s
0
(p ps0 ) + y1
11 01
11 1
(2.63)
21 Similar to the previous derivation, the objective function (2.60) can be derived from an
expected utility function of the form E [U (W )] = exp [W ] where is the operators
coecient of absolute risk aversion. Unlike the previous example, here the objective function
is written in terms of total profit (wealth) not portfolio returns per unit wealth. Also, risky
asset holdings, s, are in terms of absolute amounts purchased, not portfolio proportions.
Hence, is the coecient of absolute risk aversion, not relative risk aversion.
71
Let us first consider the case of y = 0. This can be viewed as the situation
faced by a pure speculator, by which we mean a trader who has no requirement to
hedge. If n = 1 and ps1 > ps0 , the speculator takes a long position in (purchases)
the security, while if ps1 < ps0 , the speculator takes a short position in (sells)
the security. The magnitude of the position is tempered by the volatility of the
security (1
11 = 1/ 11 ), and the speculators level of risk aversion, . However,
for the general case of n > 1, an expected price decline or rise is not sucient
to determine whether a speculator takes a long or short position in a particular
security. All of the elements in 1
11 need to be considered, since a position in
a given security may have particular diversification benefits.
For the general case of y 6= 0, the situation faced by a hedger, the demand for
financial securities is similar to that of a pure speculator in that it also depends
on price expectations. In addition, there are hedging components to the demand
for financial assets, call them sh :
0
sh y1
11 01
(2.64)
This is the solution to the problem min V ar(W ). Thus, even for a hedger,
s
(2.65)
22 Note that if the correlation between the commodity price and the financial security return
were equal to 1, so that a perfect hedge exists, then (2.65) beomces sh /y = 00 / 11 , that
is, the hedge ratio equals the ratio of the commodity prices standard deviation to that of the
security price.
72
0
For the general case, n > 1, the elements of the vector 1
11 01 equal the coe-
(2.66)
2.6
Summary
sucient to satisfy all investors, because any ecient portfolio can be created
from any other two.
lios has the characteristic that the portfolios mean returns are linear in their
portfolio variances. In such a case, a more risk averse investor optimally holds
a positive amount of the riskless asset and a positive amount of a particular
risky asset portfolio, while a less risk averse investor optimally borrows at the
riskless rate to purchase the same risky asset portfolio in an amount exceeding
his wealth.
This chapter provided insights on how individuals should optimally allocate
2.7. EXERCISES
their wealth among various assets.
73
Taking the distribution of returns for all
2.7
Exercises
1. Prove that the indierence curves graphed in Figure 2.1 are convex if
the utility function is concave. Hint: Suppose there are two portfolios,
portfolios 1 and 2, that lie on the same indierence curve, where this
indierence curve has expected utility of U.
74
Rf e 0 V 1 (R
Rf e)
R
Rp Rf
. The derivation is similar to the case with no riskless
2Rf + Rf2
asset.
4. Show that when Rf = Rmv , the optimal portfolio involves e = 0.
deviation space Rp , p .
b. Explain why only three portfolios are needed to construct this ecient
frontier, and locate these three portfolios on your graph. (Note these
portfolios may not be unique.)
c. At least one of these portfolios will sometimes need to be sold short
to generate the entire ecient frontier. Which portfolio(s) is it (label it
on the graph) and in what range(s) of the ecient frontier will it be sold
short? Explain.
2.7. EXERCISES
75
6. Suppose there are n risky assets whose returns are multi-variate normally
distributed. Denote their n 1 vector of expected returns as R and their
nn covariance matrix as V . Let there also be a riskless asset with return
Rf . Let portfolio a be on the mean-variance ecient frontier and have an
expected return and standard deviation of Ra and a , respectively. Let
portfolio b be any other (not necessarily ecient) portfolio having expected
return and standard deviation Rb and b , respectively.
correlation between portfolios a and b equals portfolio bs Sharpe ratio divided by portfolio as Sharpe ratio, where portfolio is Sharpe ratio equals
qe is the number of bushels of corn harvested and pe is the spot price, net
enter into a corn futures contract having a current price of f0 and a random
price at harvest time of fe. If k is the number of short positions in this
futures contract taken by the farmer, then the farmers wealth at harvest
76
e Rf e where w is an nx1
ep = Rf + w0 R
where the portfolio return is R
frontier and consider the range of the probability distribution of the tangency portfolio. Also consider what would be the individuals marginal
utility should end-of-period wealth be non-postive. This marginal utility
will restrict the individuals optimal portfolio choice.
Chapter 3
However, it
enced financial practice in highly diverse ways. It has provided foundations for
capital budgeting rules, for the regulation of utilities rates of return, for performance evaluation of money managers, and for the creation of indexed mutual
funds.
This chapter starts by deriving the CAPM and studying its consequences
for assets rates of return. The notion that investors might require higher rates
of return for some types of risks, but not others, is an important insight of
CAPM and extends to other asset pricing models. CAPM predicts that assets
risk premia result from a single risk factor, the returns on the market portfolio
of all risky assets which, in equilibrium, is a mean-variance ecient portfolio.
However, it is not hard to imagine that a weakening of CAPMs restrictive
assumptions could generate risk premia deriving from multiple factors. Hence,
we then consider how assets risk premia may be related when multiple riskfactors generate assets returns.
We look at
some simple applications of arbitrage pricing and then study the multi-factor
Arbitrage Pricing Theory (APT) developed by Stephen Ross (Ross 1976). APT
is the basis of the most popular empirical multi-factor models of asset pricing.
1 William Sharpe, a student of Harry Markowitz, shared the 1990 Nobel prize with
Markowitz and Merton Miller. See (Treynor 1961), (Sharpe 1964), (Lintner 1965), and
(Mossin 1966).
3.1
79
risky assets and a riskfree asset, the optimal portfolio weights for the n risky
assets were shown to be
Rf e
= V 1 R
(3.1)
Rp Rf
R
0 V 1 R,
and
0 V 1 e = e0 V 1 R,
, R
2Rf + R2f
e0 V 1 e. The amount invested in the riskfree asset is then 1 e0 . Since
where
(3.2)
Efficient Frontier
Rp
Rm
Rp = R f +
Rm R f
Rmv
Rf
mv m
3.1.1
The ecient frontier, given by the line through Rf and m , implies that investors optimally choose to hold combinations of the riskfree asset and the
ecient frontier portfolio of risky assets having portfolio weights wm . We can
easily solve for this unique tangency portfolio of risky assets since it is the
point where an investor would have a zero position in the riskfree asset, that is,
0 . Pre-multiplying (3.1) by e0 , setting the result to 1,
e0 = 1, or Rp = R
and solving for , we obtain = m [ Rf ]1 , so that
Rf e)
m = mV 1 (R
(3.3)
81
Let us now investigate the relationship between this tangency portfolio and
individual assets. Consider the covariance between the tangency portfolio and
the individual risky assets. Define M as the n 1 vector of covariances of the
tangency portfolio with each of the n risky assets. Then using (3.3) we see that
Rf e)
M = V wm = m(R
(3.4)
2m
Rf e)
= m0 M = m m0 (R
(3.5)
m Rf )
= m(R
m m0 R
is the expected return on the tangency portfolio.2 Rewhere R
arranging (3.4) and substituting in for m from (3.5), we have
Rf e) =
(R
where
M
2m
1
M
M = 2 (R
m Rf ) = (Rm Rf )
m
m
m ,R
hi )
Cov(R
m ) .
V ar(R
(3.6)
Equation
(3.6) shows that a simple relationship links the excess expected return (expected
m Rf ), to
return in excess of the risk-free rate) on the tangency portfolio, (R
Rf e).
the excess expected returns on the individual risky assets, (R
2 Note that the elements of m sum to 1 since the tangency portfolio has zero weight in
the riskfree asset.
3.1.2
Market Equilibrium
Now suppose that individual investors, each taking the set of individual assets
expected returns and covariances as fixed (exogenous), all choose mean-variance
ecient portfolios. Thus, each investor decides to allocate his or her wealth
between the riskfree asset and the unique tangency portfolio. Because individual
investors demand the risky assets in the same relative proportions, we know
that the aggregate demands for the risky assets will have the same relative
proportions, namely those of the tangency portfolio. Recall that our derivation
of this result does not assume a representative investor in the sense of requiring
all investors to have identical utility functions or beginning-of-period wealth.
It does assume that investors have identical beliefs regarding the probability
distribution of asset returns, that all risky assets can be traded, that there are
no indivisibilities in asset holdings, and that there are no limits on borrowing
or lending at the riskfree rate.
We can now define an equilibrium as a situation where asset returns are such
that the investors demands for the assets equal the assets supplies.
What
determines the assets supplies? One way to model asset supplies is to assume
they are fixed. For example, the economy could be characterized by a fixed
quantity of physical assets that produce random output at the end of the period.
Such an economy is often referred to as an endowment economy, and we detail a
model of this type in Chapter 6. In this case, equilibrium occurs by adjustment
of the date 0 assets prices so that investors demands conform to the inelastic
assets supplies. The change in the assets date 0 prices eectively adjusts the
assets return distributions to those which make the tangency portfolio and the
net demand for the riskfree asset equal to the fixed supplies of these assets.
An alternative way to model asset supplies is to assume that the economys
asset return distributions as fixed but allow the quantities of these assets to be
83
This
insight has led to the growth of "indexed" mutual funds and exchange traded
funds (ETFs) that hold market-weighted portfolios of stocks and bonds.
Lets now consider some additional implications of CAPM when we consider
realized, rather than expected, asset returns. Note that asset is realized return,
i , can be defined as R
i +
R
i where i is the unexpected component of the assets
m , can be defined
return. Similarly the realized return on the market portfolio, R
m + m , where m is the unexpected part of the market portfolios return.
as R
Substituting these into (3.6) we have
i
R
m m Rf ) + i
= Rf + i (R
(3.7)
m Rf ) + i i m
= Rf + i (R
m Rf ) + e
= Rf + i (R
i
where e
i i i m . Note that
m, e
m , i ) i Cov(R
m , m )
Cov(R
i ) = Cov(R
(3.8)
m, R
i ) i Cov(R
m, R
m)
= Cov(R
m ) i V ar(R
m) = 0
= i V ar(R
which, along with (3.7), implies that the total variance of risky asset i, 2i , has
two components
2i = 2i 2m + 2i
(3.9)
85
correlated with the return on the market portfolio, this implies that equation
(3.7) represents a regression equation.
of i can be obtained by running an Ordinary Least Squares regression of asset is excess return on the market portfolios excess return. The orthogonal,
mean zero residual, e
i , is sometimes referred to as idiosyncratic, unsystematic,
or diversifiable risk. This is the particular assets risk that is eliminated or di-
versified away when the asset is held in the market portfolio. Since this portion
of the assets risk can be eliminated by the individual who invests optimally,
there is no price or risk premium attached to it in the sense that the assets
equilibrium expected return is not altered by it.
To make clear what risk is priced, let us denote the covariance between
the return on the ith asset and the return on the market portfolio as Mi =
ei ), which is the ith element of M . Also let im be the correlation
m, R
cov(R
between the return on the ith asset and the return on the market portfolio.
i Rf
R
m Rf )
Mi (R
m
m
m Rf )
(R
= im i
m
(3.10)
= im i Se
where Se
m Rf )
(R
m
per unit of market risk and known as the market Sharpe ratio, named after
William Sharpe, one of the developers of the CAPM. Se can be interpreted as
the market price of systematic or non-diversifiable risk. It is also referred to as
the slope of the capital market line, where the capital market line is defined as
N
1 2m
1 mV m
1
1 X m
m
m
=
=
=
2V
=
ij
i
m
2 m m
2 m m
2m
m j=1 j
i
i
i
m =
where ij is the i, j th element of V . Since R
n
P
(3.11)
m
j Rj , then Cov(Ri , Rm ) =
j=1
n
n
i , P mR
j ) = P m
Cov(R
j
j ij . Hence, (3.11) can be re-written
j=1
j=1
1
m
i, R
m ) = im i
=
Cov(R
m
i
m
(3.12)
I
X
Wi i =
i=1
= a
I
X
i=1
I
X
i=1
Wi + b
ip
Wi a + bR
I
X
87
(3.13)
ip = a + bR
m
Wi R
i=1
m PI Wi R
ip and where the last equality of (3.13) uses the fact that
where R
i=1
the sum of the proportions of total wealth must equal 1. Equation (3.13) shows
that the market portfolio, the aggregation of all individual investors portfolios,
is a frontier portfolio.
em , R
e0p
m 0 V 0
Cov R
= m0 V 0 = a + bR
(3.14)
1
0
V 1 R
V 1 e
V e V 1 R
m V 0
+
R
=
2
2
0 1
0
0
1
0
V V
e V V R
=
2
mR
0 V 1 V 0 R
m e0 V 1 V 0
R
+
2
m
R0p + Rm R0p R
=
2
Rearranging 3.14 gives
R0p =
2
m
R
em , R
e0p
+
Cov
R
m
m
R
R
(3.15)
Re-writing the first term on the right-hand side of equation (3.15) and multiplying and dividing the second term by the definition of a frontier portfolios
variance given in equation (2.32), equation (3.15) becomes
R0p
e0p
em , R
Cov R
1
2 !
Rm
2
+
m
2m
2
R
!
e0p
em , R
Cov R
2
2
2
Rm + 2
2m
Rm
Rm
(3.16)
2
+
2
Rm
From equation (2.39), we recognize that the first two terms on the right-hand
side of (3.16) equal the expected return on the portfolio that has zero-covariance
with the market portfolio, call it Rzm . Thus, equation (3.16) can be written as
R0p
e0p
em , R
Cov R
= Rzm +
Rm Rzm
2m
= Rzm + 0 Rm Rzm
(3.17)
Since the portfolio having weights 0 can be any risky-asset portfolio, it includes
a portfolio that invests solely in a single asset.4 In this light, 0 becomes the
covariance of the individual assets return with that of the market portfolio,
and the relationship equation (3.17) is identical to the previous CAPM result in
equation (3.10) except that Rzm replaces Rf . Hence, when a riskless asset does
not exist, we measure an assets excess returns relative to Rzm , the expected
return on a portfolio that has a zero beta.
4 One
3.2. ARBITRAGE
89
3.2
Arbitrage
3.2. ARBITRAGE
91
However, as a word of caution, not all asset markets meet the conditions
required to justify arbitrage pricing. For some markets, It may be impossible
to execute pure arbitrage trades due significant transactions costs and/or restrictions on short-selling or borrowing. In such cases of limited arbitrage, the
law of one price can fail.7 Alternative methods, such as those based on a model
of investor preferences, are required to price assets.
3.2.1
An early use of the arbitrage principle is the covered interest parity condition
which links spot and forward foreign exchange markets to foreign and domestic
money markets. To illustrate, let F0 be the current date 0 forward price for
exchanging one unit of a foreign currency periods in the future. This forward
price represents the dollar price to be paid periods in the future for delivery
of one unit of foreign currency periods in the future. In contrast, let S0 be
the spot price of foreign exchange, that is, the current date 0 dollar price of
one unit of foreign currency to be delivered immediately. Also let Rf be the
per-period risk free (money market) return for borrowing or lending in dollars
over the period 0 to , and denote as Rf the per-period risk free return for
borrowing or lending in the foreign currency over the period 0 to .8
Now construct the following portfolio that requires zero net wealth. First,
we sell forward (take a short forward position in) one unit of foreign exchange
at price F0 .9 This contract means that we are committed to delivering one
unit of foreign exchange at date in return for receiving F0 dollars at date .
Second, let us also purchase the present value of one unit of foreign currency,
7 Andrei Shleifer and Robert Vishny (Shleifer and Vishny 1997) discuss why the conditions
needed to apply arbitrage pricing are not present in many asset markets.
8 For example, if the foreign currency is the Japanese yen, R would be the per period
f
return for a yen-denominated risk-free investment or loan.
9 Taking a long or short position in a forward contract requires zero initial wealth, as
payment and delivery all occur at the future date .
F0 Rf S0 /Rf
(3.18)
Note that these proceeds are non-random, that is, the amount is known at date
0 since it depends only on prices and riskless rates quoted at date 0. If this
amount is positive, then we should indeed create this portfolio as it represents
an arbitrage. If, instead, this amount is negative, then an arbitrage would be
for us to sell this portfolio, that is, we reverse each trade discussed above (take
a long forward position, invest in the domestic currency financed by borrowing
in foreign currency markets). Thus, the only instance in which arbitrage would
not occur is if the net proceeds are zero, which implies
F0 = S0 Rf /R
f
(3.19)
3.2. ARBITRAGE
93
expectations regarding the future value of the foreign currency. The reason
for this simplification is due to the law of one price, which states that in the
absence of arbitrage, equivalent assets (or contracts) must have the same price.
A forward contract to purchase a unit of foreign currency can be replicated by
buying, at the spot exchange rate S0 , a foreign currency investment paying the
per-period risk-free return Rf and financing this by borrowing at the dollar riskfree return Rf . In the absence of arbitrage, these two methods for obtaining
foreign currency in the future must be valued the same. Given the spot exchange
rate, S0 , and the foreign and domestic money market returns, Rf and Rf ,
the forward rate is pinned down. Thus, when applicable, pricing assets or
contracts by ruling out arbitrage is attractive in that assumptions regarding
investor preferences or beliefs are not required.
To motivate how arbitrage pricing might apply to a very simple version of the
CAPM, suppose that there is a risk free asset that returns Rf and multiple risky
assets. However, assume that only a single source of (market) risk determines
all risky asset returns and that these returns can be expressed by the linear
relationship
ei = ai + bi f
R
(3.20)
ei is the return on the ith asset and f is the single risk factor generating
where R
= 0. ai is asset is expected
all asset returns, where it is assumed that E[f]
example in that all risky assets are perfectly correlated with each other. Assets
have no idiosyncratic risk (residual component e
i ). A generalized model with
idiosyncratic risk will be presented in the next section.
ep
R
= ai + (1 )aj + bi f + (1 )bj f
(3.21)
= (ai aj ) + aj + [(bi bj ) + bj ] f
bj
bj bi
(3.22)
Rp = (ai aj ) + aj = Rf
(3.23)
or
bj (ai aj )
+ aj = Rf
bj bi
which implies
ai Rf
aj Rf
=
bi
bj
(3.24)
This condition states that the expected return in excess of the risk free rate,
per unit of risk, must be equal for all assets, and we define this ratio as .
is the risk premium per unit of the factor risk. The denominator, bi , can be
interpreted as asset is quantity of risk from the single risk factor, while ai Rf
can be thought of as asset is compensation or premium in terms of excess
expected return given to investors for holding asset i. Thus, this no-arbitrage
95
condition is really a law of one price in that the price of risk, , which is the
risk premium divided by the quantity of risk, must be the same for all assets.
Equation (3.24) is a fundamental relationship, and similar law of one price
conditions hold for virtually all asset pricing models.
(3.25)
i Rf , to its quantity
so that the ratio of an assets expected return premium, R
of market risk, im i , is the same for all assets and equals the slope of the
capital market line, Se . We next turn to a generalization of the CAPM that
derives from arbitrage pricing.
3.3
The CAPM assumption that all assets can be held by all individual investors is
clearly an over-simplification. Transactions costs and other trading "frictions"
that arise from distortions such as capital controls and taxes might prevent individuals from holding a global portfolio of marketable assets. Furthermore, many
assets simply are non-marketable and cannot be traded.10 The preeminent example of a non-marketable asset is the value of an individuals future labor
income, what economists refer to as the individuals human capital.
There-
j .
risk factors, f1 ,...,fk , and the specific risk component of any other asset j, e
e
i must be independent of the risk factors or else it would aect all assets, thus
not being truly a specific source of risk to just asset i. If ai is the expected
return on asset i, then the return generating process for asset i is given by the
linear factor model
11 Ravi Jagannathan and Ellen McGrattan (Jagannathan and McGrattan 1995) review the
empirical evidence for CAPM.
12 This is not much dierent from the CAPM. CAPM determined each assets risk premium
based on the single factor market risk premium, Rm Rf , and the assets sensitivity to this
single factor, i . The only dierence is that CAPM provides somewhat more guidance as to
the identity of the risk factor, namely, the return on a market portfolio of all assets.
ei = ai +
R
97
k
X
z=1
biz fz + e
i
(3.26)
h
i
h i
i fz = 0, and E [e
ie
j ] = 0 for i 6= j. For simplicity,
where E [e
i ] = E fz = E e
i
h
we also assume that E fz fx = 0 for z 6= x, that is, the risk factors are
mutually independent. In addition, let us further assume that the risk factors
h i
are normalized to have a variance equal to one, so that E fz2 = 1. As it turns
out, these last two assumptions are not important, as a linear transformation
of correlated risk factors can allow them to be redefined as independent, unit
variance risk factors.13
A final assumption is that the idiosyncratic risk (variance) for each asset be
finite, that is
h i
E e
2i s2i < S 2
(3.27)
ei , fz =
where S 2 is some finite number. Under these assumptions, note that Cov R
Cov biz fz , fz = biz Cov fz , fz = biz . Thus, biz is the covariance between
1 E [h
gh
g 0 ] 1 = Ik where Ik is a kxk identify matrix.
Win = 0
i=1
lim
n X
n
X
Win Wjn ij = 0
i=1 j=1
Win ai > 0
ai = 0 +
99
k
X
biz z + i
()
z=1
where 0 is a constant, z is the risk premium for risk factor fez , z = 1, ..., k,
and the expected return deviations, i , satisfy
n
X
i = 0
(i)
biz i = 0, z = 1, ..., k
(ii)
i=1
n
X
i=1
1X 2
i = 0
n n
i=1
lim
(iii)
Note that condition (iii) says that the average squared error (deviation) from
the pricing rule () goes to zero as n becomes large. Thus, as the number of
assets increase relative to the risk factors, expected returns will, on average,
P
become closely approximated by the relation ai = 0 + kz=1 biz z . Also note
that if the economy contains a risk free asset (implying biz = 0, z), the risk
free return will be approximated by 0 .
Proof : For a given number of assets, n > k, think of running a cross-sectional
regression of the ai s on the biz s. More precisely, project the dependent variable
vector a = [a1 a2 ... an ]0 on the k explanatory variable vectors bz = [b1z b2z ... bnz ]
, z = 1, ..., k. Define i as the regression residual for observation i, i = 1, ..., n.
Denote 0 as the regression intercept and z , z = 1, ..., k, as the estimated
coecient on explanatory variable z. The regression estimates and residuals
must then satisfy
ai = 0 +
k
X
z=1
biz z + i
(3.28)
(ii), can be satisfied. The last, but most important part of the proof, is to show
that (iii) must hold in the absence of asymptotic arbitrage.
Thus, let us construct a zero-net investment arbitrage portfolio with the
following investment amounts
i
Wi = pPn
(3.29)
2
i=1 i n
so that greater amounts are invested in assets having the greatest relative expected return deviation. The total arbitrage portfolio return is given by
p
R
n
X
i=1
Since
ei
Wi R
1
pPn
2
i=1 i n
Pn
i=1 biz i
(3.30)
"
n
X
i=1
ei = pP
iR
n
2
i=1 i n
" n
X
i ai +
i=1
k
X
z=1
biz fz + e
i
!#
p = pP
R
n
2
i=1 i n
" n
X
i=1
i (ai + e
i )
(3.31)
h i
p = pP 1
E R
n
2
i=1 i n
since E[e
i ] = 0. Substituting in for ai = 0 +
" n
X
i=1
Pk
i ai
z=1 biz z
(3.32)
+ i , we have
h i
p = pP 1
E R
n
2
i=1 i n
and since
Pn
i=1 i
= 0 and
h
p
E R
"
n
X
i +
i=1
Pn
101
i=1 i biz
k
X
z=1
n
X
i biz
i=1
n
X
2i
i=1
(3.33)
= 0, this simplifies to
v
u n
u1 X
2
t
= pPn
=
2
i
2
n i=1 i
i=1 i n i=1
n
X
(3.34)
2
i=1 i n
" n
X
i=1
ie
i
(3.35)
h i2 Pn 2 s2
2 2
S2
i i
i=1
i=1 i S
P
E Rp E Rp
<
=
= Pn
n
n
n i=1 2i
n i=1 2i
(3.36)
(3.37)
1X 2
i = 0
n n
i=1
lim
(3.38)
Pk
z=1 biz z ,
can be inter-
gene Fama and Kenneth French (Fama and French 1993) model is an example of
this. Its risk factors are returns on three dierent portfolios: a market portfolio
of stocks (like CAPM), a portfolio that is long the stocks of small firms and
short the stocks of large firms, and a portfolio that is long the stocks having
high book-to-market ratios (value stocks) and short stocks having low book-tomarket ratios (growth stocks). The latter two portfolios capture the empirical
finding that the stocks of smaller firms and those of value firms tend to have
higher expected returns than would be predicted solely by the one-factor CAPM
model. The Fama-French model predicts that a given stocks expected return is
determined by its three betas for these three portfolios.16 It has been criticized
for lacking a theoretical foundation for its risk factors.17
However, there have been some attempts to provide a rationale for the Fama15 Gregory
Connor and Robert Korajczk (Connor and Korajczyk 1995) survey empirical
tests of the APT.
16 A popular extension of the Fama-French three-factor model is the four-factor model proposed by Mark Carhart (Carhart 1997). His model adds a proxy for stock momentum.
17 Moreover, some researchers argue that what the model interprets as risk factors may
be evidence of market ineciency. For example, the relatively low returns on growth stocks
relative to value stocks may represent market mis-pricing due to investor over-reaction to high
growth firms. Josef Lakonishok, Andrei Shleifer, and Robert Vishny (Lakonishok, Shleifer,
and Vishny 1994) find that various measures of risk cannot explain the higher average returns
of value stocks relative to growth stocks.
3.4. SUMMARY
103
French models good fit of asset returns. Heaton and Lucas (Heaton and Lucas
2000) provide a rationale for the additional Fama-French risk factors. They note
that many stockholders may dislike the risks of small firm and value stocks, the
latter often being stocks of firms in financial distress, thereby requiring higher
average returns on these stocks. They provide empirical evidence that many
stockholders are, themselves, entrepreneurs and owners of small businesses, so
that their human capital is already subject to the risks of small firms with
relatively high probabilities of failure.
justify the APT, the static (single-period) APT framework may not be compatible with some of the predictions of the more dynamic (multi-period) ICAPM.
In general, the ICAPM allows for changing risk-free rates and predicts that
assets expected returns should be a function of such changing investment opportunities. The model also predicts that an assets multiple betas are unlikely
to remain constant through time, which can complicate deriving estimates of
betas from historical data.18
3.4
Summary
In this chapter, we took a first step in understanding the equilibrium determinants of individual assets prices and returns. The Capital Asset Pricing Model
18 Ravi Jagannathan and Zhenyu Wang (Jagannathan and Wang 1996) find that the
CAPM better explains stock returns when stocks betas are permitted to change over
time and a proxy for the return on human capital is included in the market portfolio.
3.5
Exercises
max Rk
{k
i}
1
Vk
k
n
P
ki Ri
i=1
and Vk =
n
n P
P
i=1j=1
turn on risky asset i and ij is the covariance between the returns on risky
asset i and risky asset j. ki is investor ks portfolio weight invested in
n
P
ki = 1. k is a positive constant and equals
risky asset i, so that
i=1
(a) Write down the Lagrangian for this problem and show the first order
conditions.
(b) Re-write the first order condition to show that the expected return
3.5. EXERCISES
105
ei = ai + bi1 f1 + bi2 f2 + e
i
R
where ai
= f 0 + bi1 f 1 + bi2 f 2 . Maintain all of the assumptions made in
the notes and, in addition, assume that both f 1 and f 2 are positive. Thus,
the positive risk premia imply that both of the two orthogonal risk factors are
priced sources of risk. Now define two new risk factors from the original risk
Chapter 4
Consumption-Savings
Decisions and State Pricing
Previous chapters studied the portfolio choice problem of an individual who
maximizes the expected utility of his end-of-period wealth. This specification
of an individuals decision making problem may be less than satisfactory since,
traditionally, economists have presumed that individuals derive utility from consuming goods and services, not by possessing wealth per se. Taking this view,
our prior analysis can be interpreted as implicitly assuming that the individual
consumes only at the end of the single investment period, and all end-of-period
wealth is consumed.
tial beginning-of-period wealth was not modeled, so that all initial wealth was
assumed to be saved and invested in a portfolio of assets.
In this chapter we consider the more general problem where an individual
obtains utility from consuming at both the initial and terminal dates of her
decision period and where non-traded labor income also may be received. This
allows us to model the individuals initial consumption-savings decision as well
107
108
as her portfolio choice decision. In doing so, we can derive relationships between
asset prices and the individuals optimal levels of consumption that extend many
of our previous results.
This stochastic
After deriving this stochastic discount factor, we demonstrate that its volatility restricts the feasible excess expected returns and volatilities of all assets.
Importantly, we discuss empirical evidence that appears inconsistent this restriction for standard, time-separable utility functions, casting doubt on the
usefulness of a utility-of-consumption-based stochastic discount factor. Fortunately, however, a stochastic discount factor for pricing assets need not rely on
this consumption-based foundation. We provide an alternative derivation of a
stochastic discount factor based on the assumptions of an absence of arbitrage
and market completeness.
The chapter concludes by showing how the stochastic discount factor approach can be modified to derive an asset valuation relationship based on riskneutral probabilities.
Valuation
4.1
109
(4.1)
where is a subjective discount factor that reflects the individuals rate of time
preference and E [] is the expectations operator conditional on information
at date 0.1
110
ei = Pe1i + D
e 1i , where f
date 1 random payo of X
P 1i is the date 1 stock price and
C1 = y1 + (W0 + y0 C0 )
n
X
i Ri
(4.2)
i=1
where (W0 + y0 C0 ) is the individuals date 0 savings. The individuals maximization problem can then be stated as
(4.3)
C0 ,{i }
Pn
i=1 i
#
n
X
i Ri = 0
U (C0 ) E U (C1 )
(4.4)
E [U 0 (C1 ) Ri ] = 0,
(4.5)
i=1
i = 1, ..., n
111
chooses between dierent assets. Substitute out for and one obtains:
E [U 0 (C1 ) Ri ] = E [U 0 (C1 ) Rj ]
(4.6)
for any two assets, i and j. Equation (4.6) tells us that the investor trades o
investing in asset i for asset j until their expected marginal utility-weighted
returns are equal. If this were not the case, the individual could raise his total
expected utility by investing more in assets whose marginal utility weighted
returns were relatively high and investing less in assets whose marginal utility
weighted returns were low.
How does the investor act to make the optimal equality of expected marginal
utility weighted returns in (4.6) come about? Note from (4.2) that C1 becomes
more positively correlated with Ri the greater is i . Thus, the greater is asset is
portfolio weight, the lower will be U 0 (C1 ) when Ri is high due to the concavity of
utility. Hence, as i becomes large, smaller marginal utility weights multiply
the high realizations of asset is return, and E [U 0 (C1 ) Ri ] falls.
Intuitively,
this occurs because the investor becomes more undiversified by holding a larger
proportion of asset i. By adjusting the portfolio weights for asset i and each
of the other n 1 assets, the investor changes the random distribution of C1 in
a way that equalizes E [U 0 (C1 ) Rk ] for all assets k = 1, ..., n, thereby attaining
the desired level of diversification.
Another result of the first order conditions involves the intertemporal allocation of resources. Substituting (4.5) into (4.4) gives
"
#
n
n
X
X
i Ri =
i E [U 0 (C1 ) Ri ]
U (C0 ) = E U (C1 )
0
n
X
=
i =
i=1
i=1
i=1
(4.7)
112
E [U 0 (C1 ) Ri ] = U 0 (C0 ) ,
i = 1, ..., n
(4.8)
or since Ri = Xi /Pi
Pi U 0 (C0 ) = E [U 0 (C1 ) Xi ] ,
i = 1, ..., n
(4.9)
U 0 (C0 ) = Rf E [U 0 (C1 )]
(4.10)
which states that the investor trades o date 0 for date 1 consumption until the
marginal utility of giving up $1 of date 0 consumption just equals the expected
marginal utility of receiving $Rf of date 1 consumption. For example, suppose
that utility is of a constant relative risk aversion form: U (C) = C /, for < 1.
Then equation (4.10) can be re-written as
1
= E
Rf
"
C0
C1
1 #
(4.11)
Hence, when the interest rate is high, so will be the expected growth in consump-
113
tion. For the special case of there being only one risk-free asset and non-random
labor income, so that C1 is non-stochastic, equation (4.11) becomes
Rf =
C1
C0
(4.12)
ln (Rf ) = ln + (1 ) ln
C1
C0
(4.13)
Since ln(Rf ) is the continuously-compounded risk-free interest rate and ln(C1 /C0 )
is the growth rate of consumption, then we can define the elasticity of intertemporal substitution, , as
1
ln (C1 /C0 )
=
ln (Rf )
1
(4.14)
is the reciprocal
of the coecient of relative risk aversion. That is, the single parameter determines both risk aversion and the rate of intertemporal substitution.4 When
0 < < 1,
risk-aversion than logarithmic utility, this individual increases his savings as the
interest rate rises. Conversely, when < 0, then < 1 and a rise in the interest
rate raises second period consumption less than one-for-one, implying that such
an individual decreases her initial savings when the return to savings is higher.
For the logarithmic utility individual ( = 0 and, therefore
= 1), a change in
the interest rate has no eect on savings. These results can be interpreted as
4 An end-of-chapter exercise shows that this result extends to an environment with risky
assets. In Chapter 14, we will examine a recursive utility generalization of multi-period
power utility for which the elasticity of intertemporal substitution is permitted to dier from
the inverse of the coecient of relative risk aversion. There these two characteristics of
multi-period utility are modeled by separate parameters.
114
< 1.
When
If this were not the case, the individuals expected utility could
be raised by investing more (less) in assets whose average marginal utilityweighted returns are relatively high (low). It was also demonstrated that an
individuals optimal consumption-savings decision involves trading-o higher
current marginal utility of consuming for higher expected future marginal utility
obtainable from invested saving.
4.2
115
of asset returns.
To see this, let us begin by re-writing equation (4.9) as:
Pi
U 0 (C1 )
Xi
= E
U 0 (C0 )
= E [m01 Xi ]
(4.15)
where m01 U 0 (C1 ) /U 0 (C0 ) is the marginal rate of substitution between initial and end-of-period consumption. For any individual who can trade freely in
asset i, equation (4.15) provides a condition that equilibrium asset prices must
satisfy. Condition (4.15) appears in the form of an asset pricing formula. The
current asset price, Pi , is an expected discounted value of its payos, where the
discount factor, m01 , is a random quantity because it depends on the random
level of future consumption.
discount factor for valuing asset returns. In states of nature where future consumption turns out to be high (due to high asset portfolio returns or high labor
income), marginal utility, U 0 (C1 ), is low and the assets payos in these states
are not highly valued. Conversely, in states where future consumption is low,
marginal utility is high so that the assets payos in these states are much desired. This insight explains why m01 is also known as the state price deflator.
It provides a dierent discount factor (deflator) for dierent states of nature.
It should be emphasized that the stochastic discount factor, m01 , is the same
for all assets that a particular investor can hold. It prices these assets payos
only by dierentiating in which state of nature the payo is made. Since m01
provides the core or kernel for pricing all risky assets, it is also referred to as
the pricing kernel. Note that the random realization of m01 may dier across
investors because of dierences in random labor income that can cause the
random distribution of C1 to vary across investors. Nonetheless, the expected
116
product of the pricing kernel and asset is payo, E [m01 Xi ], will be the same
for all investors who can trade in asset i.
4.2.1
U (C1 ) XiN
PiN
=E
CP I0
U 0 (C0 ) CP I1
(4.16)
or if we define Its = CP Is /CP It as one plus the inflation rate between dates t
and s, equation (4.16) can be re-written as
PiN
1 U 0 (C1 ) N
X
= E
I01 U 0 (C0 ) i
= E M01 XiN
(4.17)
where M01 (/I01 ) U 0 (C1 ) /U 0 (C0 ) is the stochastic discount factor (pricing
kernel) for discounting nominal returns. Hence, this nominal pricing kernel is
simply the real pricing kernel, m01 , discounted at the (random) rate of inflation
117
4.2.2
The relation in (4.15) can be re-written to shed light on an assets risk premium.
Dividing each side of equation (4.15) by Pi results in
= E [m01 Ri ]
(4.18)
Cov [m01 , Ri ]
= E [m01 ] E [Ri ] +
E [m01 ]
Recall from (4.10) that for the case of a risk-free asset, E [U 0 (C1 ) /U 0 (C0 )] =
E [m01 ] = 1/Rf . Then (4.18) can be re-written as
Rf = E [Ri ] +
Cov [m01 , Ri ]
E [m01 ]
(4.19)
or
Cov [m01 , Ri ]
E [m01 ]
Cov [U 0 (C1 ) , Ri ]
= Rf
E [U 0 (C1 )]
E [Ri ] = Rf
(4.20)
Equation (4.20) states that the risk premium for asset i equals minus the
covariance between the marginal utility of end-of-period consumption and the
asset return divided by the expected end-of-period marginal utility of consumption. If an asset pays a higher return when consumption is high, its return has
a negative covariance with the marginal utility of consumption, and therefore
118
the investor demands a positive risk premium over the risk free rate.
Conversely, if an asset pays a higher return when consumption is low, so
that its return positively covaries with the marginal utility of consumption,
then it has an expected return less than the risk-free rate. Investors will be
satisfied with this lower return because the asset is providing a hedge against
low consumption states of the world, that is, it is helping to smooth consumption
across states.
4.2.3
em that is perfectly
Now suppose there exists a portfolio with a random return of R
e1 ,
negatively correlated with the marginal utility of date 1 consumption, U 0 C
implying that it is also perfectly negatively correlated with the pricing kernel,
m01 :
em ,
U 0 (C1 ) = R
> 0.
(4.21)
(4.22)
(4.23)
and
Cov[U 0 (C1 ), Rm ]
V ar[Rm ]
= Rf +
0
E[U (C1 )]
E[U 0 (C1 )]
(4.24)
Using (4.20) and (4.24) to substitute for E[U 0 (C1 )], and using (4.23), we obtain
V ar[Rm ]
E[Rm ] Rf
=
E[Ri ] Rf
Cov[Rm , Ri ]
(4.25)
119
and re-arranging
E[Ri ] Rf =
Cov[Rm , Ri ]
(E[Rm ] Rf )
V ar[Rm ]
(4.26)
or
E[Ri ] = Rf + i (E[Rm ] Rf ) .
(4.27)
So we obtain the CAPM if the return on the market portfolio is perfectly negatively correlated with the marginal utility of end-of-period consumption, that
is, perfectly negatively correlated with the pricing kernel.
arbitrary distribution of asset returns and non-random labor income, this will
always be the case if utility is quadratic because marginal utility is linear in consumption, and consumption also depends linearly on the markets return. In
addition, for the case of general utility, normally distributed asset returns, and
non-random labor income, marginal utility of end-of-period consumption is also
perfectly negatively correlated with the return on the market portfolio because
each investors optimal portfolio is simply a combination of the market portfolio
and the (non-random) risk-free asset. Thus, consistent with Chapters 2 and 3,
under the assumptions needed for mean-variance analysis to be equivalent with
expected utility maximization, asset returns satisfy the CAPM.
4.2.4
m01 Ri
E [m01 ]
(4.28)
120
where m01 , Ri , and m01 ,Ri are the standard deviation of the discount factor,
the standard deviation of the return on asset i, and the correlation between the
discount factor and the return on asset i, respectively. Re-arranging (4.28) leads
to
m01
E [Ri ] Rf
= m01 ,Ri
Ri
E [m01 ]
(4.29)
The left hand side of (4.29) is the Sharpe ratio for asset i. Since 1 m01 ,Ri
1, we know that
E [Ri ] Rf
m01 = m01 Rf
E [m01 ]
Ri
(4.30)
This equation was derived by Robert Shiller (Shiller 1982), was generalized by
Lars Hansen and Ravi Jagannathan (Hansen and Jagannathan 1991), and is
known as a Hansen-Jagannathan bound.
the risk-free rate, equation (4.30) sets a lower bound on the volatility of the
economys stochastic discount factor.
discount factor, equation (4.30) sets an upper bound on the maximum Sharpe
ratio that any asset, or portfolio of assets, can attain.
If there exists an asset (or portfolio of assets) whose return is perfectly
negatively correlated with the discount factor, m01 , then the bound in (4.30)
holds with equality. As we just showed in equations (4.21) to (4.27), such
a situation implies the CAPM, so that the slope of the capital market line,
Se
E[Rm ]Rf
Rm
which represents (ecient) portfolios that have a maximum Sharpe ratio, can
be related to the standard deviation of the discount factor.
The inequality in (4.30) has empirical implications. m01 can be estimated
if we could observe an individuals consumption stream and if we knew his or
121
her utility function. Then, according to (4.30), the Sharpe ratio of any portfolio
of traded assets should be less than or equal to m01 /E [m01 ]. For power utility,
U (C) = C /, < 1, so that m01 (C1 /C0 )1 = e(1) ln(C1 /C0 ) .
If
m01
E [m01 ]
=
=
=
2
E e2(1) ln(C1 /C0 ) E e(1) ln(C1 /C0 )
2
E e2(1) ln(C1 /C0 ) /E e(1) ln(C1 /C0 ) 1
q
p
2
2
2
e2(1)c +2(1) 2c /e2(1)c +(1) 2c 1 = e(1) 2c 1
(1 ) c
(4.31)
where in the fourth line of (4.31) the expectations are evaluated assuming C1
is lognormally distributed.5 Hence, with power utility and lognormally distributed consumption, we have
E [Ri ] Rf
(1 ) c
Ri
(4.32)
annual real return in excess of the risk-free (U.S. Treasury bill) interest rate
has averaged 8.3 percent, suggesting E [Ri ] Rf = .083. The portfolios annual standard deviation has been approximately Ri = 0.17, implying a Sharpe
ratio of
E[Ri ]Rf
Ri
5 The fifth line of (4.31) is based on taking a two-term approximation of the series ex =
2
3
1 + x + x2! + x3! + ..., which is reasonable when x is a small positive number.
122
capita U.S. consumption data to estimate the standard deviation of consumption growth, researchers have come up with annualized estimates of c between
0.01 and 0.0386.6 Thus, even if a diversified portfolio of U.S. stocks was an ecient portfolio of risky assets, so that (4.32) held with equality, it would imply a
E[Ri ]Rf
/c between -11.7 and -48.7 Since reasonable levels
value of = 1
R
i
of risk aversion estimated from other sources imply values of much smaller
in magnitude, say in the range of -1 to -5, the inequality (4.32) appears to not
hold for U.S. stock market data and standard specifications of utility.8 In other
1
Rf
123
= E [m01 ]
i
h
= E e(1) ln(C1 /C0 )
2
= e(1)c + 2 (1)
(4.33)
2c
and therefore
ln (Rf ) = ln () + (1 ) c
1
(1 )2 2c
2
(4.34)
ln (Rf ) = ln () + (1 ) c
1
(1 )2 2c
2
(4.35)
which is a real risk-free interest rate of 13.3%. Since short-term real interest
rates have averaged about 1% in the U.S., we end up with a risk-free rate puzzle.
The notion that assets can be priced using a stochastic discount factor, m01 ,
is attractive because the discount factor is independent of the asset being priced:
it can be used to price any asset no matter what its risk. We derived this discount factor from a consumption - portfolio choice problem and, in this context,
showed that it equaled the marginal rate of substitution between current and
end-of-period consumption. However, the usefulness of this approach is in doubt
since empirical evidence using aggregate consumption data and standard specifications of utility appears inconsistent with the discount factor equaling the
124
the form Pi = E0 [m01 Xi ] can be shown to hold without assuming that m01
represents a marginal rate of substitution.
4.3
We need not assume a consumption- portfolio choice structure to derive a stochastic discount factor pricing formula. Instead, our derivation can be based
on the assumptions of a complete market and the absence of arbitrage, an
approach pioneered by Kenneth Arrow and Gerard Debreu.11
ternative assumptions, one can show that a law of one price holds and that a
unique stochastic discount factor exists. This new approach makes transparent
the derivation of relative pricing relationships and is an important technique for
valuing contingent claims (derivatives).
4.3.1
To illustrate, suppose once again that an individual can freely trade in n dierent
assets. Also, let us assume that there are a finite number of end-of-period states
of the nature, with state s having probability s .12 Let Xsi be the cashflow
generated by one share (unit) of asset i in state s. Also assume that there are
k states of nature and n assets. The following vector describes the payos to
10 As will be shown in Chapter 14, some specifications of time-inseparable utility can improve
the consumption-based stochastic discount factors ability to explain asset prices.
11 See Kenneth Arrow (Arrow 1953) reprinted in (Arrow 1964) and Gerard Debreu (Debreu
1959).
12 As is discussed later, this analysis can be extended to the case of an infinite number of
states.
X1i
.
.
Xi =
.
Xki
(4.36)
Thus, the per-share cashflows of the universe of all assets can be represented by
the k n matrix
X =
X11
..
.
..
.
X1n
..
.
Xk1
Xkn
(4.37)
We will assume that n = k and that X is of full rank. This implies that the
n assets span the k states of nature, an assumption that indicates a complete
market. We would still have a complete market (and, as we will show, unique
state-contingent prices) if n > k, as long as the payo matrix X has rank k. If
the number of assets exceeds the number of states, some assets are redundant,
that is, their cashflows in the k states are linear combinations of others. In such
a situation, we could reduce the number of assets to k by combining them into
k linearly independent (portfolios of) assets.
An implication of the assumption that the assets returns span the k states
of nature is that an individual can purchase amounts of the k assets so that
she can obtain target levels of end-of-period wealth in each of the states. To
show this complete markets result, let W denote an arbitrary kx1 vector of
end-of-period levels of wealth.
W1
.
.
W =
. .
Wk
(4.38)
126
(4.39)
N = X 1 W.
(4.40)
Hence, because the assets payos span the k states, arbitrary levels of wealth in
the k states can be attained if initial wealth is sucient to purchase the required
shares, N. Denoting P = [P1 . . . Pk ]0 as the kx1 vector of beginning-of-period
per share prices of the k assets, then the amount of initial wealth required to
produce the target level of wealth given in (4.38) is simply P 0 N .
4.3.2
Given our assumption of complete markets, the absence of arbitrage opportunities implies that the price of a new, redundant security or contingent claim can
be valued based on the prices of the original k securities. For example, suppose
a new asset pays a vector of end-of-period cashflows of W . In the absence of
arbitrage, its price must be P 0 N . If its price exceeded P 0 N , an arbitrage would
be to sell this new asset and purchase the original k securities in amounts N .
Since the end-of-period liability from selling the security is exactly oset by the
returns received from the k original securities, the arbitrage profit equals the
dierence between the new assets price and P 0 N . Conversely, if the new assets
price was less than P 0 N , an arbitrage would be to purchase the new asset and
sell the portfolio N of the k original securities.
Lets apply this concept of complete markets, no-arbitrage pricing to the
W1
..
.
es = Ws =
.
..
Wk
0
..
.
1
..
.
0
(4.41)
Let ps be the beginning of period price of elementary security s, that is, the
price of receiving 1 in state s. Then as we just showed, its price in terms of the
payos and prices of the original k assets must equal
ps = P 0 X 1 es , s = 1, ..., k
(4.42)
Hence the
equations in (4.42) along with the conditions ps > 0 s restrict the payos, X,
and the prices, P , of the original k securities.
We can now derive a stochastic discount factor formula by considering the
value of any other security or contingent claim in terms of these elementary state
security prices. Note that the portfolio composed of the sum of all elementary
13 If markets were incomplete, for example, if n was the rank of X and k > n, then state
prices would not be uniquely determined by the absence of arbitrage. The no-arbitrage
conditions would place only n linear restrictions on the set of k prices, implying that there
could be an infinity of possible state prices.
14 This would be the case whenever individuals marginal utilities are positive for all levels
of end-of-period consumption.
128
securities gives a cashflow of 1 unit with certainty. The price of this portfolio
defines the risk free return, Rf , by the relation:
k
X
ps =
s=1
1
.
Rf
(4.43)
Pa =
k
X
ps Xsa
(4.44)
s=1
Note that the relative pricing relationships that we have derived did not require
using information on the state probabilities.
these probabilities to see their relationship to state prices and the stochastic
discount factor.
s divided by the probability that state s occurs. Note that if, as was argued
earlier, a sensible equilibrium requires ps > 0 s, then ms > 0 s when there is a
positive probability of each state occurring. Using this new definition, equation
(4.44) can be written as
Pa
k
X
s=1
k
X
ps
Xsa
s
(4.45)
s ms Xsa
s=1
= E [m Xa ]
Pk
s=1
s ms ,
alizations of an individuals non-traded labor income, and there did not exist
assets that could span or insure against this wage income, then a unique stochastic discount factor may not exist. In this case of market incompleteness, a
utility-based derivation of stochastic discount factor may be required for asset
pricing.
While the stochastic discount factor relationship (4.45) is based on state
prices derived from assumptions of market completeness and the absence of arbitrage, it is interesting to interpret these state prices in terms of the previouslyderived consumption-based discount factor.
4.3.3
Risk-Neutral Probabilities
130
Pa
k
X
ps Xsa
(4.46)
s=1
k
1 X
ps Rf Xsa
Rf s=1
k
1 X
bs Xsa
Rf s=1
Now these
bs , s = 1, ..., k, have the characteristics of probabilities because
Pk
Pk
bs =
they are positive,
bs = ps / s=1 ps > 0, and they sum to 1,
s=1
Pk
Rf s=1 ps = Rf /Rf = 1. Using this insight, we can re-write equation (4.46)
as
Pa
k
1 X
bs Xsa
Rf s=1
1 b
E [Xa ]
Rf
(4.47)
abilities
bs rather than the true probabilities s . Since the expectation in (4.47)
count factor approach, the formula works by modifying the probabilities of the
cashflows in each of the dierent states, rather than discounting the cashflows
by a dierent discount factor.
bs can be written as
Rf = 1/E [m],
bs
= Rf ms s
=
ms
s
E [m]
(4.48)
In states
of the world where the stochastic discount factor is greater than its average
value, the pseudo probability exceeds the true probability.
For example, if
As a special case, suppose that in each state of nature, the stochastic discount
factor equaled the risk-free discount factor, that is, ms =
1
Rf
= E [m].
This
circumstance implies that the pseudo probability equals the true probability
and Pa = E [mXa ] = E [Xa ] /Rf . Because the price equals the expected payo
discounted at the risk-free rate, the asset is priced as if investors are risk-neutral.
b []
Hence, this explains why
bs is referred to as the risk-neutral probability and E
4.3.4
The complete markets pricing framework that we have just outlined is also
known as State Preference Theory and can be generalized to an infinite number
of states and elementary securities. Basically, this is done by defining probability
densities of states and replacing the summations in expressions like (4.43) and
(4.44) with integrals. For example, let states be indexed by all possible points
on the real line between 0 and 1, that is, the state s (0, 1). Also let p(s)
132
p(s) ds =
1
Rf
(4.49)
Pa =
(4.50)
15 See
4.4. SUMMARY
4.4
133
Summary
factor equal to the marginal rate of substitution between present and future
consumption. Importantly, the stochastic discount factor is independent of the
asset being priced and determines the assets risk premium based on the covariance of the assets return with the marginal utility of consumption. Moreover,
this consumption-based stochastic discount factor approach places restrictions
on assets risk premia relative to the volatility of consumption. However, these
restrictions appear to be violated when empirical evidence is interpreted using
standard utility specifications.
This contrary empirical evidence does not automatically invalidate the stochastic discount factor approach to pricing assets.
count factors as the marginal rate of substituting present for future consumption, we showed that they can be derived based on the alternative assumptions
of market completeness and an absence of arbitrage.
spanned the economys states of nature, state prices for valuing any derivative
asset could be derived. Finally, we showed how an alternative risk-neutral pricing formula could be derived by transforming the states physical probabilities
to reflect an adjustment for risk. Risk-neutral pricing is an important valuation
tool in many areas of asset pricing, and it will be applied frequently in future
134
chapters.
4.5
Exercises
1. Consider the one-period model of consumption and portfolio choice. Suppose that individuals can invest in a one-period bond that pays a riskless
real return of Rrf and in a one-period bond that pays a riskless nominal
return of Rnf . Derive an expression for Rrf in terms of Rnf , E [I01 ], and
Cov (M01 , I01 ).
2. Assume there is an economy with k states of nature and where the following asset pricing formula holds:
Pa
k
X
s ms Xsa
s=1
= E [mXa ]
1 = E [m01 Rs ]
where m01 is the stochastic discount factor between dates 0 and 1 and Rs
is the one-period stochastic return on any security in which the individual
can invest. Let there be a finite number of date 1 states where s is the
4.5. EXERCISES
135
probability of state s. Also assume markets are complete and consider the
above relationship for primitive security s, that is, let Rs be the rate of
return on primitive (or elementary) security s. The individuals elasticity
of intertemporal substitution is defined as
Rs d (Cs /C0 )
Cs /C0
dRs
where C0 is the individuals consumption at date 0 and Cs is the individuals consumption at date 1 in state s. If the individuals expected utility
is given by
h i
e1
U (C0 ) + E U C
4.
16
"bad" state. There are two assets, a risk free asset with Rf = 1.05, and a
second risky asset that pays cashflows
10
X2 =
5
The current price of the risky asset is 6.
4.a Solve for the prices of the elementary securities, p1 and p2 and the riskneutral probabilities of the two states.
4.b Suppose that the physical probabilities of the two states are 1 = 2 = 0.5.
What is the stochastic discount factor for the two states?
16 I
136
E [Ri ] = Rf + i
m = a + bRm
where a and b are constants and Rm is the realized return on the market
portfolio. Also, denote the variance of the return on the market portfolio
as 2m .
6.a Derive an expression for as a function of a, b, E [Rm ], and 2m . (Hint:
you may want to start from the equilibrium expression 0 = E [m (Ri Rf )].)
6.b Note that the equation 1 = E [mRi ] holds for all assets.
Consider the
case of the risk-free asset and the case of the market portfolio, and solve
for a and b as a function of Rf , E [Rm ], and 2m .
6.c Using the formula for a and b in part b, show that = E [Rm ] Rf .
7. Consider a two factor economy with multiple risky assets and a risk-free
asset whose return is denoted Rf . The economys first factor is the return
4.5. EXERCISES
137
on the market portfolio, Rm , and the second factor is the return on a zero
net-investment portfolio, Rz . In other words, one can interpret the second
factor as the return on a portfolio that is long one asset and short another
asset, where the long and short positions are equal in magnitude (e.g.,
Rz = Ra Rb ) where Ra and Rb are the returns on the assets that are
long and short, respectively. It is assumed that Cov (Rm , Rz ) = 0. The
expected returns on all assets in the economy satisfy the APT relationship
E [Ri ] = 0 + im m + iz z
(*)
(**)
Part II
Multiperiod Consumption, Portfolio Choice, and
Asset Pricing
Chapter 5
A Multi-Period Discrete
Time Model of
Consumption and Portfolio
Choice
This chapter considers an expected utility maximizing individuals consumption and portfolio choices over many periods. In contrast to our previous single
period or static models, here the intertemporal or dynamic nature of the problem is explicitly analyzed. Solving an individuals multi-period consumption
and portfolio choice problem is of interest in that it provides a theory for an
individuals optimal life-time savings and investment strategies. Hence, it has
normative value as a guide for individual financial planning. In addition, just as
our single-period mean-variance portfolio selection model provided the theory
of asset demands for the Capital Asset Pricing Model, a multi-period portfolio
141
142
choice model provides a theory of asset demands for a general equilibrium theory of intertemporal capital asset pricing. Combining this model of individuals
preferences over consumption and securities with a model of firm production
technologies can lead to an equilibrium model of the economy that determines
asset price processes.1
In the 1920s, Frank Ramsey (Ramsey 1928) derived optimal multi-period
consumption - savings decisions, but assumed that the individual could invest in
only a single asset paying a certain return. It was not until the late 1960s that
Paul A. Samuelson (Samuelson 1969) and Robert C. Merton (Merton 1969) were
able to solve for an individuals multi-period consumption and portfolio choice
decisions under uncertainty, that is, where both a consumption - savings choice
and a portfolio allocation decision involving risky assets was assumed to occur
each period.2
ming.
to solving problems of this type, it can sometimes be the most convenient and
intuitive way of deriving solutions.3
The model we present allows an individual to make multiple consumption
and portfolio decisions over a single planning horizon. This planning horizon,
which can be interpreted as the individuals remaining lifetime, is composed of
many decision periods, with consumption and portfolio decisions occurring once
each period.
period models that we presented earlier. This is because with only one period,
an investors decision period and planning horizon coincide. Still, the results
1 Important examples of such models were developed by John Cox, Jonathan Ingersoll, and
Stephen Ross (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985a) and Robert Lucas (Lucas 1978).
2 Jan Mossin (Mossin 1968) solved for an individuals optimal multi-period portfolio decisions but assumed the individual had no interim consumption decisions, only a utility of
terminal consumption.
3 An alternative martingale approach to solving consumption and portfolio choice problems
is given by John C. Cox and Chi-Fu Huang (Cox and Huang 1989). This approach will be
presented in Chapter 12 in the context of a continuous time consumption and portfolio choice
problem.
143
from our single-period analysis will be useful because often we can transform
multi-period models into a series of single-period ones, as will be illustrated
below.
The consumption - portfolio choice model presented in this chapter assumes
that the individuals decision interval is a discrete time period. Later in this
book, we change the assumption to make the interval instantaneous, that is,
the individual may make consumption and portfolio choices continuously. This
latter assumption often simplifies problems and can lead to sharper results.
When we move from discrete time to continuous time, continuous time stochastic
processes are used to model security prices.
4 Time-inseparable utility, where current utility can depend on past or expected future
consumption, is discussed in Chapter 14.
144
5.1
individual takes the stochastic processes followed by the prices of the dierent
assets as given. The implicit assumption is that security markets are perfectly
competitive in the sense that the (small) individual is a price-taker in security
markets. An individuals trades do not impact the price (or the return) of
the security. For most investors trading in liquid security markets, this is a
reasonably realistic assumption. In addition, it is assumed that there are no
transactions costs or taxes when buying or selling assets, so that security markets
can be described as friction-less.
An individual is assumed to make consumption and portfolio choice decisions
at the start of each period during a T period planning horizon. Each period is
of unit length, with the initial date being 0 and the terminal date being T .5
A.1 Preferences:
The individual is assumed to maximize an expected utility function defined
over consumption levels and a terminal bequest. Denote consumption at date
t as Ct , t = 0, ..., T 1, and the terminal bequest as WT , where Wt indicates
the individuals level of wealth at date t.
However,
5.1.
E0 [ (C0 , C1 , ..., CT 1 , WT )] = E0
"T 1
X
U (Ct , t) + B (WT , T )
t=0
145
(5.1)
Wt+1
= (Wt + yt Ct ) Rf t +
= St Rt
n
X
i=1
it (Rit Rft )
(5.2)
6 Dynamic programming, the solution technique presented in this chapter, can also be
applied to consumption and portfolio choice problems where an individuals utility is time
inseparable.
7 Wage income can be random. The present value of wage income, referrred to as human
capital, is assumed to be a non-tradeable asset. The individual can re-balance how his financial
wealth is allocated among risky assets, but cannot trade his human capital.
146
f 0
FR f | I 0
F y | I 0
F R i | I 0
In fo rm a tio n V a ria b le s
Wt
W T 1
y1
y T 1
yt
R f1
R ft
R f ,T 1
FR | I1
| I T 1
FR | I t FR
F y | I 1
F y | I t
FR | I1
FR | I t
W1
i ,T 1
D e c isio n s
C0
C1
{ i 0 }
{ i 1 }
Ct
{ it }
C T 1
{ i , T 1 }
T -1
T
D a te
Note that we have not restricted the distribution of asset returns in any
way.
time, so that the distribution of Rit could dier from the distribution of Ri
for t 6= . Moreover, the one-period risk-free return could be changing, so that
Rf t 6= Rf . Asset distributions that vary from one period to the next means
that the individual faces changing investment opportunities. Hence, in a multiperiod model, the individuals current consumption and portfolio decisions may
be influenced not only by the asset return distribution for the current period,
but also by the possibility that asset return distributions could change in the
future.
147
known at date t that aect the distributions of future wages, risk-free rates, and
risky asset returns. Based on this information, the individuals date t decision
variables are consumption, Ct , and the portfolio weights for the n risky assets,
{ it } for i = 1, ..., n.
5.2
We begin by defining an important concept that will help us simplify the solution
to this multi-period optimization problem. Let J (Wt , t) denote the derived
utility of wealth function. It is defined as follows:
J (Wt , It , t)
max
Et
Cs ,{is },s,i
T 1
P
s=t
U (Cs , s) + B (WT , T )
(5.3)
148
describing a changing distribution of risky asset returns and/or a changing riskfree interest rate, where these state variables are assumed to be exogenous to
the individuals consumption and portfolio choices. However, by definition J is
not a function of the individuals current or future decision variables since they
are assumed to be set to those values that maximize lifetime expected utility.
Hence, J can be described as a derived utility of wealth function.
We will solve the individuals consumption and portfolio choice problem using backward dynamic programming. This entails considering the individuals
multi-period planning problem starting from her final set of decisions, because,
with one period remaining in the individuals planning horizon, the multi-period
problem has become a single period one. We know from Chapter 4 how to solve
for consumption and portfolio choices in a single period context. Once we characterize the last periods solution for some given wealth and distribution of asset
returns faced by the individual at date T 1, we can solve for the individuals
optimal decisions for the preceding period, those decisions made at date T 2.
This procedure is continued until we can solve for the individuals optimal decisions at the current date 0.
5.2.1
149
(5.4)
J (WT 1 , T 1) =
max
max
U (CT 1 , T 1) + ET 1 [B (WT , T )]
CT 1 ,{i,T 1 }
CT 1 ,{i,T 1 }
J (WT 1 , T 1) =
max
U (CT 1 , T 1) + ET 1 [B (ST 1 RT 1 , T )]
CT 1 ,{i,T 1 }
(5.6)
(5.7)
(5.8)
150
Using the
n
P
UC (CT 1 , T 1) = ET 1 BW (WT , T ) Rf,T 1 +
i,T 1 (Ri,T 1 Rf,T 1 )
i=1
Conditions (5.8) and (5.9) represent n + 1 equations that determine the opti
model conditions (4.6) and (4.10) derived in the previous chapter but with the
JW
CT 1
dWT
+ ET 1 BWT
WT 1
dWT 1
"
n
X
CT 1
WT
WT i,T 1
+ ET 1 BWT
+
= UC
WT 1
WT 1 i=1 i,T 1 WT 1
WT CT 1
+
CT 1 WT 1
n
"
X
i,T 1
CT 1
= UC
+ ET 1 BWT
[Ri,T 1 Rf,T 1 ] ST 1
WT 1
WT 1
i=1
CT 1
+RT 1 1
(5.10)
WT 1
= UC
(5.9)
JW (WT 1 , T 1) = UC CT 1 , T 1
151
(5.11)
which is known as the envelope condition. It says that the individuals optimal
policy equates her marginal utility of current consumption, UC , to her marginal
utility of wealth (future consumption).
5.2.2
Having solved the individuals problem with one period to go in her planning
horizon, we next consider her optimal consumption and portfolio choices with
two periods remaining, at date T 2. The individuals objective at this date is
(5.12)
152
max
(Y ) = max
max
(Y )
(5.13)
J (WT 2 , T 2) =
max
CT 2 ,{i,T 2 }
ET 2
{U (CT 2 , T 2) +
max
(5.14)
ET 1 [U (CT 1 , T 1) + B (WT , T )]
CT 1 ,{i,T 1 }
Then, using the definition of J (WT 1 , T 1) from (5.5), equation (5.14) can
be re-written as
J (WT 2 , T 2) =
max
CT 2 ,{i,T 2 }
(5.15)
5.2.3
10 Using the envelope condition, it can be shown that the concavity of U and B ensures
that J (W, t) is a concave and continuously dierentiable function of W . Hence, an interior
solution to the second-to-last period problem exists.
153
UC CT 2 , T 2 = ET 2 [JW (WT 1 , T 1) RT 2 ]
(5.16)
(5.17)
Based on the above pattern, inductive reasoning implies that for any t =
0, 1, ..., T 1, we have the Bellman equation
(5.18)
(5.19)
(5.20)
154
The insights of the multi-period model conditions (5.19) and (5.20) are similar
to those of a single-period model of Chapter 4.
days consumption such that the marginal utility of current consumption equals
the derived marginal utility of wealth (the marginal utility of future consumption).
assets expected marginal utility weighted asset returns. However, solving for
the individuals actual consumption and portfolio weights at each date, Ct and
{ i,t }, t = 0, ..., T 1, is more complex than for a single-period model. The
conditions dependence on the derived utility of wealth function implies that
they depend on future contingent investment opportunities (the distributions
of future asset returns (Ri,t+j , Rf,t+j , j 1), future income flows, yt+j , and,
possibly, states of the world that might aect future utilities (U (, t + j)).
Solving the above system involves starting from the end of the planning
horizon and dynamically programing backwards toward the present. Thus, for
the last period, T , we know that J (WT , T ) = B (WT , T ). As we did previously,
we substitute B (WT , T ) for J (WT , T ) in conditions (5.18) to (5.20) for date
T 1 and solve for J (WT 1 , T 1). This is then substituted into conditions
(5.18) to (5.20) for date T 2 and one then solves for J (WT 2 , T 2). If
we proceed in this recursive manner, we eventually obtain J (W0 , 0) and the
solution is complete. These steps are summarized in the following table.
Step
Action
Construct J (WT , T )
155
By following this recursive procedure, we find that the optimal policy will
be of the form:11
Ct = g [Wt , yt , It , t]
(5.21)
it = h [Wt , yt , It , t]
(5.22)
Deriving analytical expressions for the functions g and h are not always possible, in which case numerical solutions satisfying the first order conditions at
each date can be computed. However, for particular assumptions regarding the
form of utility, wage income, and the distribution of asset returns, such explicit
solutions may be possible. The next section considers an example where this
is the case.
5.3
To illustrate how solutions of the form (5.21) and (5.22) can be obtained, consider the following example where the individual has log utility and no wage
income. Assume that U (Ct , t) t ln [Ct ], B (WT , T ) T ln [WT ], and yt 0
t, where =
1
1+
156
(5.23)
UC (CT 1 , T 1) = ET 1 [BW (WT , T ) RT 1 ]
1
RT 1
RT 1
T 1
= ET 1 T
= ET 1 T
CT 1
WT
ST 1 RT 1
=
T
T
=
ST 1
WT 1 CT 1
or
CT 1 =
1
WT 1
1+
(5.24)
Ri,T 1
1
T ET 1
= T Rf,T 1 ET 1
ST 1 RT 1
ST 1 RT 1
Ri,T 1
1
ET 1
= Rf,T 1 ET 1
RT 1
RT 1
(5.25)
Furthermore, for the case of log utility we see that equation (5.25) equals unity,
since from (5.9) we have
T 1
1
T
= Rf,T 1 ET 1
CT 1
ST 1 RT 1
CT 1 Rf,T 1
1
1 =
E
T
1
WT 1 CT 1
RT 1
1
1 = Rf,T 1 ET 1
RT 1
157
(5.26)
where we have substituted equation (5.24) in going from the third to the fourth
line of (5.26). While we would need to make specific assumptions regarding the
distribution of asset returns in order to derive the portfolio weights { i,T 1 }
satisfying (5.25), note that the conditions in (5.25) are rather special in that
they do not depend on WT 1 , CT 1 , or , but only on the particular distribution
of asset returns that one assumes. The implication is that a log utility investor
chooses assets in the same relative proportions, independent of his initial wealth.
This, of course, is a consequence of log utility being a special case of constant
relative risk-aversion utility.12
12 Recall from section 1.3 that a one-period investor with constant relative risk aversion
places constant proportions of wealth in a risk-free and a single risky asset.
158
J (WT 1 , T 1) = T 1 ln CT 1 + T ET 1 ln RT 1 WT 1 CT 1
= T 1 ( ln [1 + ] + ln [WT 1 ]) +
ET 1 ln RT 1 + ln
+ ln [WT 1 ]
1+
= T 1 [(1 + ) ln [WT 1 ] + HT 1 ]
where HT 1 ln [1 + ] + ln
1+
+ ET 1 ln RT 1 .
(5.27)
Notably, from
equation (5.25) we saw that i,T 1 did not depend on WT 1 , and, therefore,
RT 1 and HT 1 do not depend on WT 1 .
Next, lets move back one more period and consider the individuals optimal
consumption and portfolio decisions at time T 2. From equation (5.15) we
have
J (WT 2 , T 2) =
=
max
max
T 2 ln [CT 2 ]
CT 2 ,{i,T 2 }
CT 2 ,{i,T 2 }
+ T 1 ET 2 [(1 + ) ln [WT 1 ] + HT 1 ]
(5.28)
UC CT 2 , T 2 = ET 2 [JW (WT 1 , T 1) RT 2 ]
T 2
RT 2
T 1
= (1 + )
ET 2
CT 2
ST 2 RT 2
=
or
(1 + ) T 1
WT 2 CT 2
(5.29)
CT 2 =
1
WT 2
1 + + 2
159
(5.30)
Using (5.17), we then see that the optimality conditions for { i,T 2 } turn out
to be of the same form as at T 1:
ET 2
Ri,T 2
1
E
=
R
, i = 1, ..., n
f,T 2 T 2
RT 2
RT 2
(5.31)
T 2
1+
T 1
= Rf,T 2
ET 2
CT 2
ST 2 RT 2
(1 + ) CT 2 Rf,T 2
1
1 =
E
T
2
WT 2 CT 2
RT 2
1
1 = Rf,T 2 ET 2
RT 2
(5.32)
Recognizing the above pattern, we see that the optimal consumption and
portfolio rules for any prior date, t, are
1
1
Wt =
Wt
1 + + ... + T t
1 T t+1
Ri,t
1
E
Et
=
R
= 1, i = 1, ..., n
f
t
t
Rt
Rt
Ct =
(5.33)
(5.34)
Hence, we find that the consumption and portfolio rules are separable for a
log utility individual. Equation (5.33) shows that the consumption-savings decision does not depend on the distribution of asset returns. Moreover, equation
(5.34) indicates that the optimal portfolio proportions depend only on the distribution of one-period returns and not the distribution of asset returns beyond
the current period. This is described as myopic behavior because investment
160
allocation decisions made by the multi-period log investor are identical to those
of a one-period log investor. Hence, the log utility individuals current period
decisions are independent of the possibility of changing investment opportunities
in future periods. It should be emphasized that these independence results are
highly specific to the log utility assumption and do not occur with other utility
functions.
For example,
suppose that the distribution of a risky assets return had no lower bound, as
would be the case if the distribution was normal.
the optimality conditions (5.34) imply that the individual avoids holding any
normally distributed risky asset, since there is positive probability that a large
negative return would make wealth negative as well.13
In Chapter 12, we
13 Note that this would not be the case for a risky asset having a return distribution that is
bounded at zero, such as the lognormal distribution.
5.4. SUMMARY
161
hold assets having returns that are instantaneously normally distributed. The
intuition behind this dierence in the discrete- versus continuous-time results
is that the probability of wealth becoming negative decreases when the time
interval between portfolio revisions decreases.
5.4
Summary
162
5.5
Exercises
1
1+
Further, assume that n = 0 so that there are no risky assets but there is a
single-period riskless asset yielding a return of Rf t = 1/ that is constant
each period. (Equivalently, the risk-free interest rate rf = .) Note that
in this problem labor income is stochastic and there is only one (riskless)
asset for the individual consumer-investor to hold. Hence, the individual
has no portfolio choice decision but must decide only what to consume
each period. In solving this problem, assume that the individuals optimal level of consumption remains below the bliss point of the quadratic
utility function, that is, Ct < 12 a/b, t.
1.a Write down the individuals wealth accumulation equation from period t
to period t + 1.
1.b Solve for the individuals optimal level of consumption at date T 1 and
evaluate J (WT 1 , T 1). (This is trivial.)
5.5. EXERCISES
163
2. Consider the consumption and portfolio choice problem with power utility
U (Ct , t) t Ct / and a power bequest function B (WT , T ) T WT /.
/ and a constant risk-free
Assume there is no wage income ( yt 0 t)
return equal to Rf t = Rf . Also, assume that n = 1 and the return of the
single risky asset, Rrt , is independently and identically distributed over
time. Denote the proportion of wealth invested in the risky asset at date
t as t .
2.a Derive the first order conditions for the optimal consumption level and
portfolio weight at date T 1, CT 1 and T 1 , and give an explicit expression for CT 1 .
2.b Solve for the form of J (WT 1 , T 1) .
2.c Derive the first order conditions for the optimal consumption level and
portfolio weight at date T 2, CT 2 and T 2 , and give an explicit expression for CT 2 .
2.d Solve for the form of J (WT 2 , T 2).
max Et
Cs ,s s
T 1
P
s=t
U (Cs , s) + B (WT , T )
164
period.
date s as s .
max E0
Ct ,t t
T 1
P
t=0
ln [Ct ] + ln [WT ]
t
(4.1)
where each period the individual can choose between a risk-free asset
paying a time-varying return of Rf t over the period from t to t + 1 and
5.5. EXERCISES
165
a single risky asset. The individual receives no wage income. The risky
assets return over the period from t to t + 1 is given by
Rrt
(1 + ut ) Rf t
=
(1 + d ) R
ft
with probability
1
2
with probability
1
2
(4.2)
Chapter 6
Multi-Period Market
Equilibrium
The previous chapter showed how stochastic dynamic programming can be used
to solve for an individuals optimal multi-period consumption and portfolio decisions. In general, deriving an individuals decision rules for particular forms
of utility and distributions of asset returns can be complex.
However, even
though simple solutions for individuals decision rules may not exist, a number
of insights regarding equilibrium asset pricing relationships often can be derived
for an economy populated by such optimizing individuals. This is the topic of
the first section of this chapter. Similar to what was shown in the context of
Chapter 4s single period consumption - portfolio choice model, here we find
that an individuals first order conditions from the multi-period problem can be
re-interpreted as equilibrium conditions for asset prices. This leads to empirically testable implications even when analytical expressions for the individuals
lifetime consumption and portfolio decisions cannot be derived.
As we shall
see, these equilibrium implications generalize those that we derived earlier for a
167
168
gives rise to the possibility of speculative bubbles in asset prices. The last section of the chapter examines the nature of rational bubbles and considers what
conditions could give rise to these non-fundamental price dynamics.
6.1
Recall that the previous chapters Samuelson-Merton model of multi-period consumption and portfolio choices assumed that an individuals objective was
max
Et
Cs ,{is },s,i
T 1
P
s=t
U (Cs , s) + B (WT , T )
(6.1)
and that this problem of maximizing time separable multi-period utility could
be transformed into a series of one-period problems where the individual solved
the Bellman equation
(6.2)
(6.3)
169
(6.4)
6.1.1
Let us illustrate how equilibrium asset pricing implications can be derived from
the individuals envelope condition (6.3), UC (Ct , t) = JW (Wt , t). This condition conveys that under an optimal policy, the marginal value of financial wealth
equals the marginal utility of consumption. Substituting the envelope condition
evaluated at date t + 1 into the right-hand-side of the first line of (6.3), we have
= Rf,t Et UC Ct+1
,t +1
(6.5)
Furthermore, substituting (6.4) into (6.3) and, again, using the envelope condition at date t + 1 allows us to write
170
= Et Rit UC Ct+1
,t +1
(6.6)
or
1 = Et [mt,t+1 Rit ]
= Rf,t Et [mt,t+1 ]
(6.7)
our previous asset pricing results derived from a single period consumption portfolio choice problem, such as equation (4.18), hold on a period-by-period
basis even when we allow the consumption - portfolio choice problem to be a
more complex multi-period one.
this is substituted into the right-hand-side of the original (6.6), one obtains
,t + 2
UC (Ct , t) = Et Rit Et+1 Rj,t+1 UC Ct+2
(6.8)
171
or
1 = Et [Rit Rj,t+1 mt,t+2 ]
(6.9)
In the above
expressions, Rit Rj,t+1 is the return from a trading strategy that first invests in
asset i over the period from t to t + 1 then invests in asset j over the period
t + 1 to t + 2. Of course, i could equal j but need not, in general. By repeated
substitution, (6.9) can be generalized to
1 = Et [Rt,t+k mt,t+k ]
(6.10)
trading strategy involving multiple assets over the period from dates t to t + k.
Equation (6.10) says that optimizing consumers equate their expected marginal
utilities across all time periods and all states. Its equilibrium implication is that
the stochastic discount relationship holds for multi-period returns generated
from any particular trading strategy. This result implies that empirical tests
of multi-period, time - separable utility models using consumption data and
asset returns can be constructed using a wide variety of investment returns
and holding periods. Expressions such as (6.10) represent moment conditions
that are often tested using generalized method of moments techniques.1
As
172
6.2
The Lucas model (Lucas 1978) derives the equilibrium prices of risky assets for
an endowment economy.
process generating the economys real output (e.g., Gross Domestic Product or
GDP) is taken to be exogenous. Moreover, it is assumed that output obtained
at a particular date cannot be reinvested to produce more output in the future.
Rather, all output on a given date can only be consumed immediately, implying
that equilibrium aggregate consumption equals the exogenous level of output
at each date. Assets in this economy represent ownership claims on output, so
that output (and consumption) on a given date can also be interpreted as the
cash dividends paid to asset holders. Because re-investment of output is not
permitted, so that the scale of the production process is fixed, assets can be
viewed as being perfectly inelastically supplied.2
As we will make explicit below, these endowment economy assumptions essentially fix the process for aggregate consumption. Along with the assumption
that all individuals are identical, that is, that there is a representative individual, the endowment economy assumptions fix the processes for individuals
consumptions. Thus, individuals marginal rates of substitution between current and future consumptions are pinned down, and the economys stochastic
discount factor becomes exogenous. Furthermore, since the exogenous outputconsumption process also represents the process for the market portfolios ag2 An endowment economy is sometimes described as a "fruit tree" economy. The analogy
refers to an economy whose production is represented by a fixed number of fruit trees. Each
season (date), the trees produce a random amount of output in the form of perishable fruit.
The only value to this fruit is to consume it immediately, as it cannot be reinvested to produce
more fruit in the future. (Planting seeds from the fruit to increase the number of fruit trees is
ruled out.) Assets represent ownership claims on the fixed number of fruit trees (orchards),
so that the fruit produced on each date also equals the dividend paid to asset holders.
173
gregate dividends, that, too, is exogenous. This makes it easy to solve for the
equilibrium price of the market portfolio.
In contrast, a production economy is, in a sense, the polar opposite of an endowment economy. A production economy allows for an aggregate consumption
- savings (investment) decision. Not all of current output need be consumed,
but some can be physically invested to produce more output using constant
returns to scale (linear) production technologies. The random distribution of
rates of return on these productive technologies is assumed to be exogenous.
Assets can be interpreted as ownership claims on these technological processes
and, therefore, their supplies are perfectly elastic, varying in accordance to the
individuals reinvestment decision. Hence, the main dierence between production and endowment economies is that production economies pin down assets
rates of return distribution and make consumption (and output) endogenous
while endowment economies pin down consumption and make assets rates of
return distribution endogenous. Probably the best known asset pricing model
based on a production economy was derived John C. Cox, Jonathan E. Ingersoll, and Stephen A. Ross (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985a). We will study this
continuous time, general equilibrium model in Chapter 13.
6.2.1
The Lucas model builds on the multi-period, time separable utility model of
consumption and portfolio choice.
factor pricing relationship of (6.7) but put more structure on the returns of each
asset. Let the return on the ith risky asset, Rit , include a dividend payment
made at date t + 1, di,t+1 , along with a capital gain, Pi,t+1 Pit . Hence Pit
174
Rit =
di,t+1 + Pi,t+1
.
Pit
(6.11)
Pit = Et
"
,t +1
UC Ct+1
(di,t+1 + Pi,t+1 )
UC (Ct , t)
(6.12)
Similar to what was done in equation (6.8), if we substitute for Pi,t+1 using equation (6.12) updated one period, and use the properties of conditional
expectation, we have
Pit
!#
UC Ct+2
,t +1
,t +2
UC Ct+1
(di,t+2 + Pi,t+2 )
= Et
di,t+1 +
UC (Ct , t)
UC Ct+1
,t +1
#
"
UC Ct+2
,t + 1
,t +2
UC Ct+1
= Et
di,t+1 +
(di,t+2 + Pi,t+2 ) (6.13)
UC (Ct , t)
UC (Ct , t)
"
Repeating this type of substitution, that is, solving forward the dierence equation (6.13) gives us
Pit
T
X
UC Ct+j
,t +j
UC Ct+T
,t +T
di,t+j +
Pi,t+T
= Et
UC (Ct , t)
UC (Ct , t)
j=1
(6.14)
Now suppose
1
1+
< 1, so that the rate of time preference > 0. Then (6.14) becomes
Pit
C
u
C
u
C
C
t+j
t+T
T
= Et
j
) di,t+j +
) Pi,t+T
u
(C
u
(C
C
C
t
t
j=1
T
X
(6.15)
175
T uC (Ct+T )
infinity. If limT Et uC (C ) Pi,t+T = 0, which, as discussed in the next
t
Pit
X
C
u
C
t+j
= Et
j
) di,t+j
u
(C
C
t
j=1
X
mt, t+j di,t+j
= Et
(6.16)
j=1
Equation (6.16) is a present value formula, where the stochastic discount factors
are the marginal rates of substitution between the present and the dates when
the dividends are paid. This "discounted dividend" asset pricing formula holds
for any individual following an optimal consumption - portfolio choice policy.
Thus far, we have not made any strong assumptions about consumer homogeneity or the structure of the economy. For example, (6.16) would hold for a
production economy with heterogeneous individuals.
6.2.2
The Lucas model makes (6.16) into a general equilibrium model of asset pricing
by assuming there is an infinitely-lived representative individual, meaning that
all individuals are identical with respect to utility and initial wealth. It also
assumes that each asset is a claim on a real output process, where risky asset i
pays a real dividend of dit at date t. Moreover, the dividend from each asset is
assumed to come in the form of a non-storable consumption good that cannot
176
n
X
dit
(6.17)
i=1
Given the assumption of a representative individual, this individuals consumption can be equated to aggregate consumption.3
6.2.3
With these endowment economy assumptions, the specific form of utility for
the representative agent and the assumed distribution of the assets dividend
processes fully determine equilibrium asset prices. For example, if the representative individual is risk-neutral, so that uC is a constant, then (6.16) becomes
Pit
X
= Et
j di,t+j
(6.18)
j=1
In words, the price of risky asset i is the expected value of dividends discounted
by a constant constant factor, reflecting the constant rate of time preference.
Consider another example where utility is logarithmic, u (Ct ) = ln Ct . Also
Pn
denote dt = i=1 dit be the economys aggregate dividends, which we know by
(6.17) equals aggregate consumption. Then the price of risky asset i is given
3 If one assumes that there are many representative individuals, each will have indentical
per capita consumption and receive identical per capita dividends. Hence, in (6.17) Ct and
dit can be interpreted as per capita quantities.
177
by
Pit
X
C
= Et
j t di,t+j
Ct+j
j=1
X
d
t
j
di,t+j
= Et
d
t+j
j=1
(6.19)
Given assumptions regarding the distribution of the individual assets, the expectation in (6.19) can be computed. However, under this logarithmic utility
assumption, we can obtain the price of the market portfolio of all assets even
without any distributional assumptions. To see this, let Pt represent a claim
on aggregate dividends. Then (6.19) becomes
Pt
X
dt
= Et
j
dt+j
d
t+j
j=1
= dt
(6.20)
implying that the value of the market portfolio moves in step with the current
level of dividends. It does not depend on the distribution of future dividends.
Why?
expected marginal utility of consumption, mt, t+j = j dt /dt+j , leaving the value
of a claim on this output process unchanged. This is consistent with our earlier
results showing that a log utility individuals savings (and consumption) are
independent of the distribution of asset returns. Since aggregate savings equals
the aggregate demand for the market portfolio, no change in savings implies no
change in asset demand. Note that this will not be the case for the more general
specification of power (constant relative risk aversion) utility. If u (Ct ) = Ct /,
then
178
Pt
= Et
X
j=1
dt+j
dt
X
Et
j dt+j
= d1
t
dt+j
(6.21)
j=1
Note from (6.21) that for the case of certainty (Et dt+j = dt+j ), when < 0
higher future aggregate dividends reduce the value of the market portfolio, that
1
< 0. While this seems counter-intuitive, recall
is, Pt /dt+j = j (dt+j /dt )
that for < 0, individuals desire less savings (and more current consumption)
when investment opportunities improve. Since current consumption is fixed at
dt in this endowment economy, the only way to bring higher desired consumption
back down to dt is for total wealth to decrease.
when the price of the market portfolio falls as individuals attempt to sell some
of their portfolio in an (unsuccessful) attempt to raise consumption. Of course
the reverse story occurs when 0 < < 1, as a desired rise in savings is oset by
an increase in wealth via an appreciation of the market portfolio.
If we continue to assume power utility, we can also derive the value of a
hypothetical riskless asset that pays a one-period dividend of $1:
Pf t
1
=
= Et
Rf t
"
dt+1
dt
1 #
(6.22)
Using aggregate U.S. consumption data, Rajnish Mehra and Edward C. Prescott
(Mehra and Prescott 1985) used equations such as (6.21) and (6.22) with dt =
Ct to see if a reasonable value of would produce a risk-premium (excess
average return over a risk-free return) for a market portfolio of U.S. common
179
stocks that matched these stocks historical average excess returns. They found
that for reasonable values of , they could not come close to the historical riskpremium, which at that time they estimated to be around 6 percent.
described this finding as the equity premium puzzle.
They
As mentioned earlier in
Chapter 4, the problem is that for reasonable levels of risk aversion, aggregate
consumption appears to vary too little to justify the high Sharpe ratio for the
market portfolio of stocks. The moment conditions in (6.21) and (6.22) require
a highly negative value of to fit the data.
6.2.4
The Lucas endowment economy model has been modified to study a wide array
of issues. For example, Gurdip Bakshi and Zhiwu Chen (Bakshi and Chen 1996)
study a monetary endowment economy by assuming that a representative individual obtains utility from both real consumption and real money balances. In
future chapters, we will present other examples of Lucas-type economies where
utility is non-time separable and where utility reflects psychological biases. In
this section, we present a simplified version of a model by
Stephen Cecchetti, Pok-sang Lam, and Nelson Mark (Cecchetti, Lam, and
Mark 1993) that modifies the Lucas model to consider non-traded labor income.4
As before, suppose that there is a representative agent whose financial wealth
consists of a market portfolio of traded assets that pays an aggregate real dividend of dt at date t. We continue to assume that these assets are in fixed supply
and their dividend consists of a non-storable consumption good. However, now
4 They use a regime-switching version of this model to analyze the equity premium and
risk-free rate puzzles. Based on Generalized Method of Moments (GMM) tests, they find
that their model fits the first moments of the risk-free rate and the return to equity, but not
the second moments.
180
Ct = dt + yt
(6.23)
Pt
X
C
u
C
t+j
Et
j
dt+j
u
(C
C
t)
j=1
X
C
t+j
j
dt+j
Et
C
t
j=1
(6.24)
/Ct = c + c t+1
ln Ct+1
(6.25)
t
0 1
N ,
t
0
1
(6.26)
181
in (6.24) to be
Pt = dt
e
1 e
(6.27)
where
d (1 ) c +
i
1h
(1 )2 2c + 2d (1 ) c d
2
(6.28)
substitution eect exceeding the income or wealth eect. Market clearing then
requires the value of the market portfolio to rise, raising income or wealth to
make desired consumption rise to equal the fixed supply. The reverse occurs
when < 0, as the income or wealth eect will exceed the substitution eect.
For the general case of labor income where is given by (6.28), note that a
lower correlation between consumption and dividends (decline in ) increases .
Since Pt / > 0, this lower correlation raises the value of the market portfolio. Intuitively, this greater demand for the market portfolio results because it
provides better diversification with uncertain labor income.
182
6.3
In this section, we examine whether there are solutions other than (6.16) that
can satisfy the asset price dierence equation (6.15).
that there are, and that these alternative solutions can be interpreted as bubble
solutions where the asset price deviates from its fundamental value. Potentially,
these bubble solutions may be of interest because there appear to be numerous
historical episodes during which movements in asset prices appear inconsistent
with reasonable dynamics for dividends or outputs. In other words, assets do
not appear to be valued according to their fundamentals.
Examples include
the Dutch tulip bulb bubble during the 1620s, the Japanese stock price bubble
during the late 1980s, and the U.S. stock price bubble (particularly internetrelated stocks) during the late 1990s.5
Et [pt+1 ] = 1 pt Et uC Ct+1
di,t+1
(6.29)
di,t+j
j uC Ct+j
pt = ft Et
183
(6.30)
j=1
(6.31)
di,t+1
Et [ft+1 + bt+1 ] = 1 (ft + bt ) Et uC Ct+1
(6.32)
where in the last line of (6.32) we use the fact that ft satisfies the dierence
equation. Note that since 1 > 1, bt explodes in expected value:
+ if bt > 0
lim Et [bt+i ] = lim i bt =
i
i
if bt < 0
(6.33)
184
6.3.1
bt = b0 t
(6.34)
pt = ft + b0 t
(6.35)
implies that the marginal utility-weighted asset price grows exponentially forever. In other words, we have an ever-expanding speculative bubble.
Next, consider a possibly more realistic modeling of a "bursting" bubble
proposed by Olivier Blanchard (Blanchard 1979).
bt+1
(q)1 bt + et+1
=
z
t+1
with probability q
(6.36)
with probability 1 q
with Et [et+1 ] = Et [zt+1 ] = 0. Note that this process satisfies the condition in
(6.31), so that pt = ft + bt is again a valid bubble solution. In this case, the
bubble continues with probability q each period but bursts with probability
1 q. If it bursts, it returns in expected value to zero, but then a new bubble
would start.
7 The
6.3.2
185
While these examples of bubble solutions indeed satisfy the asset pricing dierence equation in (6.29), there may be additional economic considerations that
rule them out. One issue involves negative bubbles, that is, cases where bt < 0.
From (6.33) we see that individuals must expect that at some future date > t
that the marginal utility-weighted price p = f + b will become negative. Of
course since marginal utility is always positive, this implies that the asset price,
Pit = pt /uC (Ct ) will also be negative. A negative price would be inconsistent
with limited-liability securities, such as typical shareholders equity (stocks).
Moreover, if an individual can freely dispose of an asset, its price cannot be
negative. Hence, negative bubbles can be ruled out.
Based on similar reasoning, Behzad Diba and Herschel Grossman (Diba and
Grossman 1988) argue that many types of bubble processes, including bubbles
that burst and start again, can also be ruled out. Their argument is as follows.
Note that the general process for a bubble can be written as
bt = t b0 +
t
P
st s
(6.37)
s=1
(6.38)
For example, suppose that bt = 0, implying that at the current date t a bubble
does not exist.
Then from (6.38) and the requirement that t+1 have mean
This implies
that if a bubble currently does not exist, it cannot get started next period or
any future period. The only possibility would be if a positive bubble exists on
186
the first day of trading of the asset, that is, b0 > 0.8
and then restarting bubble in (6.36) could only avoid a negative value of bt+1 if
zt+1 = 0 with probability 1 and et+1 = 0 whenever bt = 0.
bubble would need to be positive on the first trading day, and once it bursts it
could never restart.
Note, however, that arbitrage trading is unlikely to be a strong argument
against a bursting bubble. While short selling an asset with bt > 0 would result
in a profit when the bubble bursts, the short seller could incur substantial losses
beforehand. Over the near term, if the bubble continues, the market value of
the short sellers position could become suciently negative so as to wipe out
his personal wealth.
Other arguments have been used to rule out positive bubbles.
Similar to
the assumptions underlying the Lucas model of the previous section, Jean Tirole
(Tirole 1982) considers a situation with a finite number of rational individuals
and where the dividend processes for risky assets are exogenously given.
In
such an economy, individuals who trade assets at other than their fundamental
prices are playing a zero-sum game, since the aggregate amounts of consumption
and wealth are exogenous. Trading assets at prices having a bubble component
only transfers claims on this fixed supply of wealth between individuals. Hence,
a rational individual will not purchase an asset whose price already reflects a
positive bubble component. This is because at a positive price, previous traders
in the asset have already realized their gains and left a negative-sum game to
the subsequent traders. The notion that an individual would believe that he
can buy an asset at a positive bubble price and later sell it to another at a price
reflecting an even greater bubble component might be considered a "greater
8 An implication is that an initial public oering (IPO) of stock should have a first-day
market price that is above its fundamental value. Interestingly, Jay Ritter (Ritter 1991)
documents that many IPOs initially appear to be overpriced since their subsequent returns
tend to be lower than comparable stocks.
6.4. SUMMARY
187
6.4
Summary
When individuals choose lifetime consumption and portfolio holdings in an optimal fashion, a multi-period stochastic discount factor can be used to price
assets. This is an important generalization of our earlier single-period pricing
result. We also demonstrated that if an assets dividends (cashflows) are modeled explicitly, the assets price satisfies a discounted dividend formula.
The
Lucas endowment economy model took this discounted dividend formula a step
further by equating aggregate dividends to aggregate consumption. This simplified valuing a claim on aggregate dividends, since now the value of this market
portfolio could be expressed as an expectation of a function of only the future
dividend (output) process.
In an infinite horizon model, the possibility of rational asset price bubbles
needs to be considered.
188
environment are considered, the conditions that would give rise to rational bubbles appear to be rare.
6.5
Exercises
be the stochastic discount factor over the period from dates 0 to i where
i = 1, 2, and let E0 [] be the expectations operator at date 0. What is
the value of E0 [m02 f2 ]? Explain your answer.
2. Assume that there is an economy populated by infinitely-lived representative individuals who maximize the lifetime utility function
E0
"
X
t=0
t act
The economy is
a Lucas (1978) endowment economy having multiple risky assets paying date t
dividends that total dt per capita. Write down an expression for the equilibrium
per capita price of the market portfolio in terms of the assets future dividends.
3. For the Lucas model with labor income, show that assumptions (6.25) and
(6.26) lead to the pricing relationship (6.27) and (6.28).
4. Consider a special case of the model of rational speculative bubbles discussed in this chapter.
6.5.
EXERCISES
189
which is declared at date t and paid at the end of the period, date t + 1.
Consider the price pt = ft + bt where
ft =
X
Et [dt+i ]
i=0
Rf i+1
(1)
and
bt+1 =
Rf
qt bt
zt+1
+ et+1
with probability qt
(2)
with probability 1 qt
4.c Suppose pt is the price of a bond that matures at date T < . In this
context, the dt for t T denotes the bonds coupon and principal payments. Can a rational speculative bubble exist for the price of this bond?
Explain why or why not.
5. Consider an endowment economy with representative agents who maxi-
190
max
Cs ,{is },s,i
where T < .
Et
T
P
s=t
s u (Cs )
Part III
Contingent Claims Pricing
Chapter 7
Because research has given new insights into how potential contingent
securities might be priced and hedged, financial service providers are more willing to introduce such securities to the market. In addition, existing contingent
securities motivate further research by academics and practitioners whose goal
is to improve the pricing and hedging of these securities.
1 The topics in this chapter are covered in greater detail in undergraduate- and masterslevel financial derivatives texts such as (McDonald 2002) and (Hull 2000). Readers with a
background in derivatives at this level may wish to skip this chapter. For others without this
knowledge, this chapter is meant to present some fundamentals of derivatives that provide a
foundation for more advanced topics covered in later chapters.
193
194
alone may lead to an exact pricing formula. However, in the case of options,
these no-arbitrage restrictions cannot determine an exact price for the derivative, but only bounds on the options price. An exact option pricing formula
requires additional assumptions regarding the probability distribution of the
underlying assets returns. The second section of this chapter illustrates how
options can be priced using the well-known binomial option pricing technique.
This is followed by a section covering dierent binomial model applications.
The next section begins with a re-examination of forward contracts and how
they are priced. We then compare them to option contracts and analyze how
the absence of arbitrage opportunities restricts option values.
7.1
Chapter 3s discussion of arbitrage derived the link between spot and forward
contracts for foreign exchange. Now we show how that result can be generalized
to valuing forward contracts on any dividend-paying asset. Following this, we
compare option contracts to forward contracts and see how arbitrage places
limits on option prices.
2 Derivatives have been written on a wide assortment of other variables, including commodity prices, weather conditions, catastrophic insurance losses, and credit (default) losses.
3 Thus, our approach is in the spirit of considering the underlying asset as an elementary
security and using no-arbitrage restrictions to derive implications for the derivatives price.
7.1.1
195
partys payo. When the forward contract is initiated at date 0, the parties set
the forward price, F0 , to make the value of the contract equal zero. That is,
by setting F0 at date 0, the parties agree to the contract without one of them
needing to make an initial payment to the other.
Let Rf > 1 be one plus the per period risk-free rate for borrowing or lending
over the time interval from date 0 to date . Also, let us allow for the possibility
that the underlying asset might pay dividends during the life of the forward
contract, and use the notation D to denote the date 0 present value of dividends
paid by the underlying asset over the period from date 0 to date .5
The
assets dividends over the life of the forward contract are assumed to be known
at the initial date 0, so that D can be computed by discounting each dividend
payment at the appropriate date 0 risk-free rate corresponding to the time until
the dividend payment is made.
that risk-free interest rates are non-random, though most of our results in this
section and the next continue to hold when interest rates are assumed to change
4 Obviously
196
Date 0 Cashflow
Date Cashflow
S F0
S0 + D
2) Borrow
R
f F0
F0
Net Cashflow
S0 + D + Rf F0
S F0
Replicating Trades
Note that the payo of the long forward party involves two cashflows: a
positive cashflow of S , which is random as of date 0, and a negative cashflow
equal to F0 , which is certain as of date 0.
replicated by purchasing one share of the underlying asset but selling ownership
of the dividends paid by the asset between dates 0 and .7
S0 D, where S0 is the date 0 spot price of one share of the underlying asset.
6 This is especially true for cases in which the underlying asset pays no dividends over the
life of the contract, that is, D = 0. Also, some results can generalize to cases where the
underlying asset pays dividends that are random, such as the case when dividend payments
are proportional to the assets value.
7 In the absence of an explict market for selling the assets dividends, the individual could
borrow the present value of dividends, D, and repay this loan at the future dates when the
dividends are received. This will generate a date 0 cashflow of D, and net future cashflows
of zero since the dividend payments exactly cover the loan repayments.
197
In the absence of
arbitrage, this cost must be the same as the cost of initiating the long position
in the forward contract, which is zero.8
condition
S0 D Rf F0 = 0
(7.1)
F0 = (S0 D) Rf
(7.2)
or
Equation (7.2) determines the equilibrium forward price of the contract. Note
that if this contract had been initiated at a previous date, say date 1, at the
forward price F1 = X, then the date 0 value (replacement cost) of the long
partys payo, which we denote as f0 , would still be the cost of replicating the
two cashflows:
f0 = S0 D Rf X
8 If
(7.3)
0: 1) purchase one share of the stock and sell ownership of the dividends; 2) borrow R
f F0 ;
3) take a short position in the forward contract. The date 0 net cashflow of these three
transactions is (S0 D) + Rf F0 + 0 > 0, by assumption. At date the individual
would:1) deliver the one share of the stock to satisfy the short forward position; 2) receive F0
as payment for delivering this one share of stock; 3) repay borrowing equal to F0 . The date
net cashflow of these three transactions is 0+ F0 F0 = 0. Hence, this arbitrage generates a
positive cashflow at date 0 and a zero cashflow at date . Conversely, if S0 DR
f F0 > 0 ,
an arbitrage would be to perform the following trades at date 0: 1) short sell one share of
the stock and purchase rights to the dividends to be paid to the lender of the stock. (In
the absence of an explict market for buying the assets dividends, the individual could lend
out the present value of dividends, D, and receive payment on this loan at the future dates
when the dividends to be paid.); 2) lend R
f F0 ; 3) take a long position in the forward
contract. The date 0 net cashflow of these three transactions is (S0 D) Rf F0 + 0 > 0,
by assumption. At date the individual would:1) obtain one share of the stock from the long
forward position and deliver it to satisfy the short sale obligation; 2) pay F0 to short party
in forward contract; 3) receive F0 from lending agreement. The date net cashflow of these
three transactions is 0 F0 + F0 = 0. Hence, this arbitrage generates a positive cashflow
at date 0 and a zero cashflow at date .
198
However, as long as date 0 is following the initiation of the contract, the value
of the payo would not, in general, equal zero. Of course, the replacement cost
of the short partys payo would be simply f0 = Rf X +D S0 .
It should be pointed out that our derivation of the forward price in (7.2) did
not require any assumption regarding the random distribution of the underlying
asset price, S . The reason for this is due to our ability to replicate the forward
contracts payo using a static replication strategy: all trades needed to replicate
the forward contracts date payo were done at the initial date 0. As we shall
see, such a static replication strategy is not possible, in general, when pricing
other contingent claims such as options. Replicating option payos will entail,
in general, a dynamic replication strategy: trades to replicate a options payo
at date will involve trades at multiple dates during the interval between dates
0 and .
7.1.2
The owner of a call option has the right, but not the obligation, to buy a given
asset in the future at a pre-agreed price, known as the exercise price or strike
price. Similarly, the owner of a put option has the right, but not the obligation,
to sell a given asset in the future at a pre-agreed price. For each owner (buyer)
9 Much of the next sections results are due to Robert C. Merton (Merton 1973b).
greater details, see this article.
For
199
of the option contract, while an American option can be exercised at any time
prior to the maturity of the contract.
Let us define the following notation, similar to that used to describe a forward
contract. Let S0 denote the current date 0 price per share of the underlying
asset, and let this assets price at the maturity date of the option contract, ,
be denoted as S . We let X be the exercise price of the option and denote the
date t price of European call and put options be ct and pt , respectively. Then
based on our description of the payos of call and put options, we can write the
maturity values of European call and put options as:
max [S X, 0]
(7.4)
max [X S , 0]
(7.5)
Now we recall that the payos to the long and short parties of a forward contract
are S F0 and F0 S , respectively. If we interpret the pre-agreed forward
price, F0 , as analogous to an options pre-agreed exercise price, X, then we
see that a call options payo equals that of long forward payo whenever the
long forward payo is positive, and it equals 0 when the long forward payo is
10 The owner of an option will choose to exercise it only if it is profitable to do so. The
owner can always let the option expire unexercised, in which case its resulting payo would
be zero.
200
negative. Similarly, the payo of the put option equals the short forward payo
when this payo is positive, and it equals 0 when the short forward payo is
negative.
weakly dominates that of a long forward position while the payo of a put
option weakly dominates that of a short forward position.11 This is due to the
consequence of option payos always being non-negative while forward contract
payos can be of either sign.
(7.6)
Furthermore, since the call options payo is always non-negative, its current
value must also be non-negative, that is, c0 0.
with (7.6) implies
h
i
c0 max S0 D Rf X, 0
(7.7)
(7.8)
11 A payo is said to dominate another when its value is strictly greater in all states of
nature. A payo weakly dominates another when its value is greater in some states of nature
and the same in other states of nature.
201
Similar logic can be used to derive an important relationship that links the value
of European call and put options that are written on the same underlying asset
and that have the same maturity date and exercise price. This relationship is
referred to as put-call parity:
c0 + Rf X + D = p0 + S0
To show this, consider forming the following two portfolios at date 0:
Date 0:
(7.9)
202
the current values of American call and put options, respectively, then comparing them to European call and put options having equivalent underlying asset,
maturity, and exercise price features, it must be the case that C0 c0 and
P0 p0 .
There are, however, cases where an American options early exercise feature
has no value because it would not be optimal to exercise the option early. This
situation occurs for the case of an American call option written on an asset
203
that pays no dividends over the life of the option. To see this, note that (7.7)
says that prior to maturity, the value of a European call option must satisfy
c0 S0 R
f X.
receive the assets dividend payment, a payment that would be lost if exercise
was delayed.
For an American put option that is suciently in the money, that is, S0 is
significantly less than X, it may be optimal to exercise the option early, selling
the asset immediately and receiving $X now, rather than waiting and receiving
$X at date (which would have a present value of Rf X).
7.2
The previous section demonstrated that the absence of arbitrage restricts the
price of an option in terms of its underlying asset. However, the no-arbitrage
assumption, alone, cannot determine an exact option price as a function of the
underlying asset price. To do so, one needs to make an additional assumption
regarding the distribution of returns earned by the underlying asset. As we shall
see, particular distributional assumptions for the underlying asset can lead to a
204
situation where the options payo can be replicated by trading in the underlying
asset and a risk-free asset and, in general, this trading occurs at multiple dates.
When such a dynamic replication strategy is feasible, the option market is said
to be dynamically complete.
us to equate the value of the options payo to the prices of more primitive
securities, namely, the prices of the underlying asset and the risk-free asset.
We now turn to a popular discrete-time, discrete-state model that produces this
result.
The model presented in this section was developed John Cox, Stephen Ross,
and Mark Rubinstein (Cox, Ross, and Rubinstein 1979). It makes the assumption that the underlying asset, hereafter referred to as a stock, takes on one
of only two possible values each period. While this may seem unrealistic, the
assumption leads to a formula that often can accurately price options. This binomial option pricing technique is frequently applied by finance practitioners to
numerically compute the prices of complex options. Here, we start by considering the pricing of a simple European option written on a non-dividend-paying
stock.
In addition to assuming the absence of arbitrage opportunities, the binomial
model assumes that the current underlying stock price, S, either moves up, by
a proportion u, or down, by a proportion d, each period. The probability of an
up move is , so that the probability of a down move is 1 . This two-state
stock price process can be illustrated as
uS
S
with probability
(7.10)
&
dS
with probability 1
205
Denote Rf as one plus the risk-free interest rate for the period of unit length.
This risk-free return is assumed to be constant over time. To avoid arbitrage
between the stock and the risk-free investment, we must have d < Rf < u.12
7.2.1
Our valuation of an option whose maturity can span multiple periods will use
a backward dynamic programming approach.
when it has only one period left until maturity, then we will value it when it has
two periods left until maturity, and so on until we establish an option formula
for an arbitrary number of periods until maturity.
Let c equal the value of a European call option written on the stock and
having a strike price of X. At maturity, c = max[0, S X]. Thus:
One period prior to maturity:
(7.11)
&
cd max [0, dS X]
with probability 1
12 If R < d, implying that the return on the stock is always higher than the risk-free return,
f
an arbitrage would be to borrow at the risk free rate and use the proceeds to purchase the
stock. A profit is assured because the return on the stock would always exceed the loan
repayment. Conversely, if u < Rf , implying that the return on the stock is always lower
than the risk free return, an arbitrage would be to short sell the stock and use the proceeds to
invest at the risk free rate. A profit is assured because the risk free return will always exceed
the value of the stock to be repaid to the stock lender.
206
uS + Rf B with probability
S + B
(7.12)
&
dS + Rf B
with probability 1
With two securities (the bond and stock) and two states of nature (up or down),
and B can be chosen to replicate the payo of the call option:
uS + Rf B = cu
(7.13)
dS + Rf B = cd
(7.14)
cu cd
(u d) S
(7.15)
B =
ucd dcu
(u d) Rf
(7.16)
states and assets having independent returns so that trading in the stock and
bond produce payos that span the two states. Now since the portfolios return
replicates that of the option, the absence of arbitrage implies
13 , the number of shares of stock per option contract needed to replicate (or hedge) the
options payo, is referred to as the options hedge ratio. It can be verified from the formulas
that for standard call options, this ratio is always between 0 and 1. For put options, it is
always between -1 and 0. B , the investment in bonds, is negative for call options but positive
for put options. In other words, the replicating trades for a call option involve buying shares
in the underlying asset partially financed by borrowing at the risk-free rate. The replicating
trades for a put option involve investing at the risk-free rate partially financed by short-selling
the underlying asset.
c = S + B
207
(7.17)
This analysis provides practical insights for option traders. Suppose an option
writer wishes to hedge her position from selling an option, that is, insure that
she will be able to cover her liability to the option buyer in all states of nature.
Then her appropriate hedging strategy is to purchase shares of stock and
$B of bonds, since, from equations (7.13) and (7.14) the proceeds from this
hedge portfolio will cover her liability in both states of nature. Her cost for this
hedge portfolio is S + B , and in a perfectly competitive options market, the
premium received for selling the option, c, will equal this hedging cost.
Example: If S = $50, u = 2, d = .5, Rf = 1.25, X = $50, then
uS = $100, dS = $25, cu = $50, cd = $0.
Therefore:
B =
2
50 0
=
(2 .5) 50
3
40
0 25
=
(2 .5) 1.25
3
so that
c = S + B =
40
60
2
(50)
=
= $20
3
3
3
208
ucd dcu
cu cd
+
c = S + B =
(u d) (u d) Rf
h
i
Rf d
uRf
ud max [0, uS X] + ud max [0, dS X]
=
Rf
(7.18)
which does not depend on the probability of an up or down move of the stock, .
Thus, given S, investors will agree on the no-arbitrage value of the call option
even if they do not agree on . The call option formula does not directly depend
on investors attitudes toward risk. It is a relative (to the stock) pricing formula.
This is reminiscent of Chapter 4s result (4.44) in which contingent claims could
be priced based on state prices but without knowledge of the probability of
dierent states occurring.
However, we do need to
know u and d, the size of movements per period, which determine the stocks
volatility.
Note also that we can re-write c as
c=
where
b
Rf d
ud .
1
[b
cu + (1
b) cd ]
Rf
(7.19)
Since 0 <
b < 1,
b has the properties of a probability. In fact, this is the
note that if the expected return on the stock equals the risk free return, Rf ,
then
209
[u + d (1 )] S = Rf S
(7.20)
Rf d
=
b.
ud
(7.21)
so that
b does equal under risk-neutrality. Thus, (7.19) can be expressed as
ct =
1 b
E [ct+1 ]
Rf
7.2.2
u2 S
uS
%
&
duS
&
dS
%
&
d2 S
(7.22)
210
cu
cuu max 0, u2 S X
%
&
&
cd
(7.23)
%
&
cdd max 0, d2 S X
Using the results from our analysis when there was only one period to maturity, we know that
cu =
cd =
bcuu + (1
b) cdu
Rf
bcdu + (1
b) cdd
Rf
(7.24)
(7.25)
cu cd
(ud)S
c = S + B =
which, as before says that ct =
1
Rf
ucd dcu
(ud)Rf
1
[b
cu + (1
b) cd ]
Rf
(7.26)
over the last period but over the second-to-last period as well. Substituting in
for cu and cd , we have
211
i
1 h 2
2
b
(7.27)
c
+
2b
(1
b
)
c
+
(1
b
)
c
uu
ud
dd
Rf2
i
2
1 h 2
=
b
max
0,
u
S
X
+
2b
(1
b
)
max
[0,
duS
X]
Rf2
i
1 h
b)2 max 0, d2 S X
+ 2 (1
Rf
c =
1
R2f
market is complete each period, it becomes complete over the sequence of these
individual periods. In other words, the option market is said to be dynamically
complete. Even though the tree diagrams in (7.22) and (7.23) indicate that there
are four states of nature two periods in the future (and three dierent payos
for the option), these states can be spanned by a dynamic trading strategy
involving just two assets. That is, we have shown that by appropriate trading
in just two assets, payos in greater than two states can be replicated.
Note that c depends only on S, X, u, d, Rf , and the time until maturity,
two periods. Repeating this analysis for three, four, five, ..., n periods prior to
maturity, we always obtain
c = S + B =
1
[b
cu + (1
b) cd ]
Rf
By repeated substitution for cu , cd , cuu , cud , cdd , cuuu , etc., we obtain the
formula:
n periods prior to maturity:
n
X
1
n!
nj
b)
max 0, uj dnj S X
c= n
bj (1
Rf j=0 j! (n j)!
Similar to before, equation (7.28) can be interpreted as ct =
1 b
E [ct+n ],
Rn
f
(7.28)
imply-
212
ing that the market is dynamically complete over any number of periods prior
to the options expiration. The formula in (7.28) can be further simplified by
defining a as the minimum number of upward jumps of S for it to exceed X.
Thus a is the smallest non-negative integer such that ua dna S > X. Taking the
natural logarithm of both sides, a is the minimum integer > ln(X/Sdn )/ln(u/d).
Therefore for all j < a (the option matures out-of-the money),
max 0, uj dnj S X = 0,
(7.29)
(7.30)
n
X
1
n!
c= n
b)nj uj dnj S X
bj (1
Rf j=a j! (n j)!
(7.31)
n
X
"
j nj
u d
n!
b)nj
bj (1
j!
(n
j)!
Rnf
j=a
n
X
n!
b)nj
XRfn
bj (1
j!
(n
j)!
j=a
c = S
(7.32)
where
b0
u
Rf
b]
c = S[a; n,
b0 ] XRn
f [a; n,
213
(7.33)
b and [a; n,
b] = the probability that the sum of n random
% #
ln
where z
S
XR
f
c = SN (z) XR
f N z
+ 12 2
( )
distribution function.
7.3
&
(7.34)
The Cox, Ross, and Rubinsteins binomial technique is useful for valuing relatively complicated options, such as those having American (early exercise) features. In this section we show how the model can be used to value an American
put option and an option written on an asset that pays dividends.
Similar to our earlier presentation, assume that over each period of length
14 The intuition for why (7.34) is a limit of (7.33) is due to the Central Limit Theorem. As
the number of periods becomes large, the sum of binomially distributed random stock rates
of return becomes normally distributed. Note that in the Black-Scholes-Merton formula,
Rf is now the risk-free return per unit time rather than the risk-free return for each period.
The relationship between and u and d will be discussed shortly. The binomial model (??)
also can have a dierent continuous-time limit, namely, the jump diusion model that will be
presented in Chapter 11.
214
uS
S
with probability
(7.35)
&
dS
with probability 1
The results of our earlier analysis showed that the assumption of an absence
of arbitrage allowed us to apply risk-neutral valuation techniques to derive the
price of an option. Recall that, in general, this method of valuing a derivative
security can be implemented by:
i) setting the expected rate of return on all securities equal to the risk-free
rate
ii) discounting the expected value of future cashflows generated from i) by
this risk-free rate
For example, suppose we examine the value of the stock, S, in terms of the
risk-neutral valuation method. Similar to the previous analysis, define Rf as the
risk-free return per unit time, so that the risk-free return over a time interval
t is Rft . Then we have
[St+t ]
= Rt
E
f
(7.36)
= Rt
[b
uS + (1
b)dS]
f
Rt
bu + (1
b)d
f =
(7.37)
215
which implies
b=
Rft d
ud
(7.38)
Hence, risk-neutral
7.3.1
To use the binomial model to value actual options, the parameters u and d
must be calibrated to fit the variance of the underlying stock. When estimating a stocks volatility, it is often assumed that stock prices are lognormally
distributed. This implies that the continuously-compounded rate of return on
the stock over a period of length t, given by ln (St+t ) ln (St ), is normally
distributed with a constant per-period variance of t2 .
As we shall see in
compounded) expected rate of return kon the stock per unit time.
This implies
that the
l
this expression in a series using ex = 1 + x + 12 x2 + 16 x3 + ... and then ignoring all terms of
order (t)2 and higher, it equals t 2 .
216
u = e
(7.39)
1
=e
u
d =
u4 S
u3 S
%
&
u2 S
u2 S
&
uS
uS
&
S
&
S
&
(7.40)
&
dS
dS
&
%
&
d2 S
d2 S
&
d3 S
%
&
d4 S
Given the stock price, S, and its volatility, , the above tree or lattice can be
7.3.2
217
and d = e
We can numerically value an option on this stock by starting at the last period
and working back toward the first period. Recall that an American put option
that is not exercised early will have a final period (date ) value
P = max [0, X S ]
(7.41)
The value of the put at date t is then the risk-neutral expected value
discounted by Rft .
P t
[P ]
= Rft E
bP ,u + (1
= Rft
b) P ,d
(7.42)
where P ,u is the date value of the option if stock price changes by proportion
u, while P ,d is the date value of the option if stock price changes by proportion
d. However, with an American put option, we need to check whether this value
exceeds the value of the put if it were exercised early. Hence, the put options
value can be expressed as
i
bP ,u + (1
b) P ,d
P t = max X S t , Rft
(7.43)
Let us illustrate this binomial valuation technique with the following example:
A stock has a current price of S = $80.50 and a volatility = 0.33.
t =
1
9
year, then u = e
.33
1
u
= .8958.
If
218
Date : 0
3
111.98
100.32
%
&
89.86
89.86
&
S = 80.50
80.50
&
%
&
72.12
72.12
&
64.60
%
&
57.86
Next, consider valuing an American put option on this stock that matures in
=
1
3
years (4 months) and has an exercise price of X = $75. Assume that the
b=
0.09
Rt
e 9 .8958
f d
=
= .5181
ud
1.1163 .8958
We can now start at date 3 and begin filling in the tree for the put option.
Date : 0
219
3
Puuu
Puu
%
&
Pu
Puud
&
P
Pud
%
&
&
Pd
Pudd
&
Pdd
%
&
Pddd
220
Date : 0
3
0.00
Puu
%
&
Pu
0.00
&
P
Pud
%
&
&
Pd
2.88
&
Pdd
%
&
17.14
Next, using
i
bP3,u + (1
b) P3,d
P2 = max X S2 , Rft
Date : 0
221
3
0.00
0.00
%
&
Pu
0.00
&
P
1.37
&
%
&
Pd
2.88
&
10.40
%
&
17.14
bP3,u + (1
b) P3,d
Pdd = max X S2 , Rt
f
b
P
+
(1
b
)
P
P1 = max X S1 , Rt
2,u
2,d
f
222
Date : 0
3
0.00
0.00
%
&
0.65
0.00
&
P
1.37
&
%
&
5.66
2.88
&
10.40
%
&
17.14
bP2,u + (1
b) P2,d
Pd = max X S1 , Rt
f
= max [75 72.12, 5.66] = $5.66
Finally, we calculate the value of the put at date 0 using
h
i
bP1,u + (1
b) P1,d
P0 = max X S0 , Rft
= max [5.5, 3.03] = $3.03
and the final tree for the put is
Date : 0
223
3
0.00
0.00
%
&
0.65
0.00
&
3.03
1.37
&
%
&
5.66
2.88
&
10.40
%
&
17.14
7.3.3
One can generalize the above procedure to allow for the stock (or portfolio of
stocks such as a stock index) to continuously pay dividends that have a per
unit time yield equal to , that is, for t suciently small, the owner of the
stock receives a dividend of St. For this case of a dividend-yielding asset, we
simply redefine
t
d
Rf e
b=
ud
(7.44)
This is because when the asset pays a dividend yield of , its expected riskt
neutral appreciation is Rf e
rather than Rft .
For the case in which a stock is assumed to pay a known dividend yield, , at
a single point in time, then if date it is prior to the stock going ex-dividend,
the nodes of the stock price tree equal
224
uj dij S
j = 0, 1, ..., i.
(7.45)
If the date it is after the stock goes ex-dividend, the nodes of the stock price
tree equal
uj dij S (1 )
j = 0, 1, ..., i.
(7.46)
7.4
Summary
7.5. EXERCISES
225
If one
assumes that investors can trade continuously in the underlying asset, and the
underlyings returns follow a continuous time diusion process, then these alternative assumptions can also lead to market completeness. The next chapter
prepares us for this important topic by introducing the mathematics of continuous time stochastic processes.
7.5
Exercises
c2
1
(c1 + c3 )
2
226
(Hint: Consider a portfolio that is long the option having a strike price of X1 ,
long the option having the strike price of X3 , and short two options having the
strike price of X2 .)
c2 = max
S1 + S2
5, 0
2
where S1 and S2 are the prices of the stock at dates 1 and 2, respectively. Solve
for the no-arbitrage value of this call option at date 0, c0 .
5. Calculate the price of a three-month American put option on a nondividend-paying stock when the stock price is $60, the strike price is $60,
the annualized, risk-free return is Rf = e0.10 , and the annual standard deviation of the stocks rate of return is = .45, so that u = 1/d = e
.45
6. Let the current date be t and let T > t be a future date, where T t
is the number of periods in the interval. Let A (t) and B (t) be the date
t prices of single shares of assets A and B, respectively. Asset A pays no
dividends but asset B does pay dividends, and the present (date t) value
of asset Bs known dividends per share paid over the interval from t to T
7.5. EXERCISES
227
Give the no-arbitrage lower bound for the date t value of this
Chapter 8
Essentials of Diusion
Processes and Its Lemma
This chapter covers the basic properties of continuous time stochastic processes
having continuous sample paths, commonly referred to as diusion processes.
It describes the characteristics of these processes that are helpful for modeling
many financial and economic time series. Modeling a variable as a continuous time, rather than a discrete time, random process can allow for dierent
behavioral assumptions and sharper model results. A variable that follows a
continuous time stochastic process can display constant change yet be observable at each moment in time. In contrast, a discrete time stochastic process
implies that there is no change in the value of the variable over a fixed interval,
or that the change cannot be observed between the discrete dates. If an asset
price is modeled as a discrete time process, it is natural to presume that no trading in the asset occurs over the discrete interval. Often this makes problems
that involve hedging the assets risk dicult, since portfolio allocations cannot
be re-balanced over the non-trading period. Thus, hedging risky asset returns
229
230
231
level rather than a mathematically rigorous one.3 The first section examines
Brownian motion, which is the fundamental building block of diusion processes.
We show how Brownian motion is a continuous time limit of a discrete time
random walk. How diusion processes can be developed by generalizing a pure
Brownian motion process is the topic of the second section. The last section
introduces Its Lemma, which tells us how to derive the stochastic process for
a function of a variable that follows a diusion process. Its Lemma is applied
extensively in continuous time financial modeling.
8.1
Here we show how a Brownian motion process can be defined as the limit of
a discrete time process.4 Consider the following stochastic process observed at
date t, z(t). Let t be a discrete change in time, that is, some time interval.
The change in z(t) over the time interval t is given by
z(t + t) z(t) z =
(8.1)
232
n
X
zi
(8.2)
i=1
z(T ) z(0) =
n
n
X
X
t i = t
i .
i=1
(8.3)
i=1
Now note that the first two moments of z(T ) z(0) are
E0 [ z(T ) z(0) ] =
V ar0 [ z(T ) z(0) ]
n
X
E0 [ i ] = 0
(8.4)
i=1
n
2 X
t
V ar0 [i ] = t n 1 = T (8.5)
i=1
where Et [] and V art [] are the mean and variance operators, respectively, conditional on information at date t. We see that holding T , the length of the time
interval, fixed, the mean and variance of z(T ) z(0) are independent of n.
8.1.1
Now let us perform the following experiment. Suppose we keep T fixed but let
n, the number of intervening increments of length t, go to infinity. Can we
say something else about the distribution of z(T ) z(0) besides what its first
two moments are? The answer is yes. Assuming that the i are independent
233
(8.6)
t0
In other words, z(T ) z(0) has a normal distribution with mean zero and
variance T .
This follows from the Central Limit Theorem which states that
the sum of n independent, identically distributed random variables has a distribution that converges to the normal distribution as n .
Thus, the
generality, we can assume that each of the i have a standard (mean 0 variance
1) normal distribution.5
The limit of one of these minute independent increments can be defined as
t0
(8.7)
where N (0, 1). Hence, E[ dz(t) ] = 0 and V ar[ dz(t) ] = dt.6 dz is referred
to as a pure Brownian motion process or a Wiener process, named after the
mathematician Norbert Wiener who in 1923 first proved its existence. We can
now write the change in z(t) over any finite interval [ 0, T ] as
z(T ) z(0) =
dz(t) N (0, T ).
(8.8)
234
As n
8.2
235
Diusion Processes
To illustrate how we can build on the basic Wiener process, consider the process
for dz multiplied by a constant, . Define a new process x(t) by
dx(t) = dz(t)
(8.9)
x(T ) x(0) =
dx =
dz(t) =
dz(t) N(0, 2 T ).
(8.10)
dx = (t)dt + dz
(8.11)
x(T ) x(0)
dx =
(t)dt +
0
(t)dt +
dz(t)
(8.12)
Z
dz(t) N (
(t)dt, 2 T ).
RT
0
dz(t)
We permit them to be
236
describing x(t) is
dx(t) = [x(t), t] dt + [x(t), t] dz
(8.13)
and is a continuous time Markov process, by which we mean that the instantaneous change in the process at date t has a distribution that depends only on
t and the current level of the state variable x (t), and not prior values of the
x (s), for s < t. The function [x(t), t] which denotes the processs instantaneous expected change per unit time is referred to as processs drift while the
instantaneous standard deviation per unit time, [x(t), t], is also described as
the processs volatility.
The process in (8.13) can also be written in terms of its corresponding integral equation
x(T ) x(0) =
dx =
[x(t), t] dt +
[x(t), t] dz
(8.14)
8.2.1
Definition of an It Integral
237
Z
n
X
lim E0
[x ([i 1] t) , [i 1] t] zi
i=1
!2
[x(t), t] dz = 0
(8.15)
where we see that within the parentheses of (8.15) is the dierence between the
It integral and its discrete-time approximation. An important It integral
RT
that will be used below is 0 [dz (t)]2 . In this case, (8.15) gives its definition as
Z
n
X
lim E0
[zi ]2
i=1
"
RT
0
" n
X
i=1
n
X
i=1
!2
[dz (t)]2 = 0
(8.16)
zi
!2
n
X
zi
= E0
i=1
[zi ]2 = T
(8.17)
Further, straightforward
!2
n
X
2
E0
[zi ] T = 2T t
(8.18)
i=1
k
l
calculation uses the result that E0 (zi )2 (zj )2 = (t) (t) = (t)2 for i 6= j
k
l
and E0 (zi )4 = 3 (t)2 because the fourth moment of a normally distributed random
variable equals 3 times its squared variance.
10 This
238
!2
n
X
[zi ]2 T = lim 2T t = 0
lim E0
(8.19)
t0
i=1
Comparing (8.16) with (8.19) implies that in the sense of mean-square convergence, we have the equality
[dz (t)]2
= T
(8.20)
T
dt
Since
RT
0
RT
0
8.3
Here, we state
Its lemma for the case of a function of a single variable that follows a diusion
process.
Its Lemma (univariate case): Let the variable x(t) follow the stochastic
239
least a twice dierentiable function. Then the dierential of F (x, t) is given by:
dF =
F
1 2F
F
dx +
dt +
(dx)2
x
t
2 x2
(8.21)
where the product (dx)2 = (x, t)2 dt. Hence, substituting in for dx and (dx)2 ,
the above can be re-written:
dF =
F
1 2F 2
F
F
(x, t) +
+
(x, t) dz.
(x,
t)
dt +
x
t
2 x2
x
(8.22)
Proof: A formal proof is rather lengthy and only a brief, intuitive outline of
a proof is given here.11
where x x(t+t)x (t) and H refers to terms that are multiplied by higher
orders of x and t. Now a discrete time approximation of x can be written
as
x = (x, t) t + (x, t) t
(8.24)
11 For more details, see Chapter 3 of Merton (Merton 1992), Chapter 16 of Ingersoll (Ingersoll
1987) or Chapter 10 in Neftci (Neftci 1996). A rigorous proof is given in Karatzas and Shreve
(Karatzas and Shreve 1991).
240
F
(x, t) t + (x, t) t +
t
x
t
2
1 2F
+
(x,
t)
t
+
(x,
t)
t
(8.25)
2 x2
2
2
F
1 F
2
(x, t) t + (x, t) t t +
+
(t) + H
xt
2 t2
The final step is to consider the limit of equation (8.25) as t becomes infini
tesimal, that is, t dt and F dF . Recall from (8.7) that t becomes
i h
i
h
t
t becomes [dz (t)]2 and converges to dt.
dz and from (8.20) that
Furthermore, it can be shown that all terms of the form (t)n where n > 1 go to
3
zero as t dt. Hence, terms that are multiplied by (t) 2 , (t)2 , (t) 2 , ...,
including all of the terms in H, vanish.
(dx)2
(8.26)
Note from (8.22) that the dF process is similar to the dx process in that
both depend on the same Brownian motion dz.
mean (drift) and variance (volatility) that diers from dx, they both depend on
the same source of uncertainty.
it may be helpful to remember that in the continuous-time limit (dz)2 = dt, but
dzdt = 0, and dtn = 0 for n >1. This follows from thinking of the discrete approximation
of dz as being proportional to t, and any product that results in (t)n will go to zero as
t dt when n is strictly greater than 1.
12 Thus,
8.3.1
241
(8.27)
dF
= d (ln x) =
(ln x)
1 2 (ln x)
(ln x)
2
x +
+
(x) dt
x
t
2 x2
(ln x)
x dz
+
x
1 2
=
+ 0 dt + dz.
2
(8.28)
1
F (T ) F (0) N ( 2 ) T, 2 T
2
(8.29)
then x(t) = eF (t) has a lognormal distribution over any discrete interval (by the
definition of a lognormal random variable). Hence, geometric Brownian motion
is lognormally distributed over any time interval.
Figure 8.2 illustrates 300 simulated sample paths of geometric Brownian
242
8.3.2
Kolmogorov Equation
There are many instances where knowledge of a diusion processs discrete time
probability distribution is very useful.
243
Because time series data is
dp =
1 2p 2
p
p
p
+
(xt , t) +
(xt , t) dt +
(xt , t) dz
xt
t
2 x2t
xt
(8.30)
Intuitively, one can see that only new information that was unexpected at date
t should change the probability density of x at date T. In other words, for small
< T t, E [p (x, T ; xt+ , t + ) |x (t) = xt ] = p (x, T ; xt , t).14 This implies
that the expected change in p should be zero, that is, the drift term in (8.30)
should be zero:
2p
p
p
1 2
(xt , t) 2 + [xt , t]
=0
+
2
xt
xt
t
(8.31)
Condition (8.31) is referred to as the backward Kolmogorov equation. This partial dierential equation for p (x, T ; xt , t) can be solved subject to the boundary
condition that when t becomes equal to T , then x must equal xt with probability
1. Formally, this boundary condition can be written as p (x, t; xt , t) = (x xt ),
13 In order to invoke Its lemma, we assume that the density function p (x, T, x , t) is diert
entiable in t and twice dierentiable in xt . Under particular conditions, the dierentiability
of p can be proved, but this issue will not be dealt with here.
14 Essentially, this result derives from the Law of Iterated Expectations.
244
(8.32)
By substitution into (8.32), it can be verified that the solution to this partial dierential equation subject to the boundary condition that p (x, t; xt , t) =
(x xt ) is15
"
2 #
ln x ln xt 12 2 (T t)
1
p (x, T, xt , t) = p
exp
22 (T t)
x 22 (T t)
(8.33)
which is the lognormal probability density function for the random variable
x (0, ).
For a
diusion process with general drift and volatility functions, (x, t) and (x, t),
it may not be easy or possible to find a closed-form expression solution for
p (x, T, xt , t) such as in (8.33). Still, there are a number of instances where the
Kolmogorov equation is valuable in deriving or verifying a diusions discrete
time distribution.16
15 Methods for solving partial dierential equations are beyond the scope of this course.
However, if one makes the change in variable yt = ln (xt ), then equation (8.32) can be transformed to a more simple partial dierential equation with constant coecients. Its solution
is the probability density function of a normally distributed random variable. Reversing the
change in variables to xt = eyt results in the lognormal density function.
16 Andrew Lo (Lo 1988) provides additional examples where the backward Kolmogorov equation is used to derive discrete time distributions. These examples include not only diusion
processes, but the type of mixed jump-diusion processes that we will examine in Chapter 11.
8.3.3
245
In a number of portfolio choice and asset pricing applications that we will encounter in future chapters, one needs to derive the stochastic process for a function of several variables, each of which follows a diusion process. So suppose
we have m dierent diusion processes of the form:17
dxi = i dt + i dzi
i = 1, . . . , m,
(8.34)
and dzi dzj = ij dt, where ij has the interpretation of a correlation coecient
of the two Wiener processes. What is meant by this correlation? Recall that
dzi dzi = (dzi )2 = dt. Now the Wiener process dzj can be written as a linear
combination of two other Wiener processes, one being dzi , and another process
that is uncorrelated with dzi , call it dziu :
dzj = ij dzi +
q
1 2ij dziu
(8.35)
dzj dzj
= 2ij dt + 1 2ij dt + 0
= dt
and
17 Note and may be functions of calendar time, t, and the current values of x , j =
i
j
i
1, ..., m.
246
dzi dzj
(8.37)
= ij dt + 0
dF =
m
m m
X
1 X X 2F
F
F
dt +
dxi +
dxi dxj
xi
t
2 i=1 j=1 xi xj
i=1
(8.38)
dF
m
m X
m
2
2
X
X
1
F
F
F
F
+
i +
i j ij dt
+
2 i
x
2
x
t
xi xj
i
i
i=1
i=1 j>i
+
m
X
F
i dzi .
xi
i=1
(8.39)
Equation (8.39) generalizes our earlier statement of Its lemma for a univariate
diusion, equation (8.22).
8.4
Summary
8.4. SUMMARY
247
Diusion processes and Its Lemma are important tools for modeling financial
time series, especially when individuals are assumed to be able to trade continuously.
Finally, we
saw that multivariate diusions are natural extensions of univariate ones, and
the process followed by a function of several diusions can be derived from a
multi-variate version of Its Lemma.
8.5
Exercises
dx = dt + dz
ex(t)t .
2. Let P be a price index, such as the Consumer Price Index (CPI). Let M
equal the nominal supply (stock) of money in the economy. For example,
M might be designated as the amount of bank deposits and currency in
248
dP
P
dM
M
= p dt + p dzp
= m dt + m dzm
with dzp dzm = dt. Monetary economists define real money balances, m, to be
m=
M
P .
3. The value (price) of a portfolio of stocks, S(t), follows a geometric Brownian motion process
dS/S = s dt + s dzs
while the dividend yield for this portfolio, y(t), follows the process
dy = (S y) dt + y y 2 dzy
where dzs dzy = dt and , , and y are positive constants. Solve for the
process followed by the portfolios dividends paid per unit time, D(t) = yS.
4. The Ornstein-Uhlenbeck process can be useful for modeling a time series
whose value changes stochastically but which tends to revert to a longrun value (its unconditional or steady state mean). This continuous time
process is given by
8.5. EXERCISES
249
(tt0 )
x(t) = y(t)
e
and apply Its lemma to find the stochastic process for x(t). The distribution and first two moments of x(t) should be obvious. From this, derive the
distribution and moments of y(t).
Chapter 9
contingent claim have a continuous distribution over any finite time interval,
implying an infinite number of states for their future values, the future values of
the contingent claim can be replicated by a dynamic trading strategy involving
its underlying asset and the risk-free asset.
1 Frictionless markets are characterized as having no direct trading costs or restrictions,
that is, markets for which there are no transactions costs, taxes, short sales restrictions, or
indivisibilities when trading assets.
251
252
9.1
The major insight of Black and Scholes (Black and Scholes 1973) is that when assets follow diusion processes, an options payo can be replicated by continuous
trading in its underlying asset and a risk-free asset. In the absence of arbitrage,
the ability to replicate or "hedge" the option with the underlying stock and a
risk-free asset restricts the options value to bear a particular relationship to its
underlying asset and the risk-free return. The Black-Scholes hedging argument
is similar to that presented earlier in the context of the binomial option pricing model.
253
changed only once per period in the binomial model, while in the Black-Scholes
environment the replicating portfolio changes continuously.
In the binomial
model, market completion resulted from the assumption that at the end of each
period there was only two states for the underlying assets value. Under BlackScholes assumptions, markets become dynamically complete due to the ability
to trade continuously in the underlying asset whose price follows a continuous
sample path.
9.1.1
(9.1)
where its instantaneous expected return and variance, i and 2i , may be functions of time and possibly other asset prices or state variables that follow diffusion processes. For simplicity, assets are assumed to pay no cashflows (dividends or coupon payments), so that their total returns are given by their price
changes.2
general, the portfolio may experience cash inflows and outflows. Thus, let F (t)
2 This is not a critical assumption. What matters is the assets expected rates of return and
covariances, rather than their price changes, per se. If an asset, such as a common stock or
mutual fund, paid a dividend that was re-invested into new shares of the asset, then equation
(9.1) would represent the percentage change in the value of the asset holding and, thus, the
total rate of return.
254
be the net cash outflow per unit time from the portfolio at date t. For example, F (t) may be positive because the individual chooses to liquidate some of
the portfolio to pay for consumption expenditures.
be negative because the individual receives wage income that is invested in the
securities.
To derive the proper continuous time dynamics for this investors portfolio,
we will first consider the analogous discrete time dynamics where each discrete
period is of length h.
Therefore, let
wi (t) be the number of shares held by the investor in asset i from date t to t + h.
The value of the portfolio at the beginning of date t is denoted as H (t) and
equals the prior periods holdings at date t prices:
H (t) =
n
X
i=1
wi (t h)Si (t)
(9.2)
Given these date t prices, the individual may chose to liquidate some of the
portfolio or augment it with new funds. The net cash outflow over the period
is F (t) h, which must equal the net sales of assets. Note that F (t) should be
interpreted as the average liquidation rate over the interval from t to t + h.
F (t) h =
n
X
[wi (t) wi (t h)] Si (t)
(9.3)
i=1
255
period, t + h, we have:
F (t + h) h =
n
X
[wi (t + h) wi (t)] Si (t + h)
i=1
n
X
=
[wi (t + h) wi (t)] [Si (t + h) Si (t)]
i=1
n
X
[wi (t + h) wi (t)] Si (t)
(9.4)
i=1
and
H (t + h) =
n
X
wi (t) Si (t + h)
(9.5)
i=1
n
X
i=1
n
X
(9.6)
i=1
and
H (t) =
n
X
wi (t) Si (t)
(9.7)
i=1
Applying Its Lemma to (9.7), we can derive the dynamics of the portfolios
value to be
dH (t) =
n
X
i=1
n
X
i=1
n
X
(9.8)
i=1
dH (t) =
n
X
i=1
(9.9)
Equation (9.9) says that the portfolios value changes due to capital gains income
256
dH (t)
n
X
=
=
i=1
n
X
i=1
(9.10)
Now, in some cases, rather than write a portfolios dynamics in terms of the
number of shares of each asset, wi (t), i = 1, . . . , n, we may wish to write it in
terms of each assets proportion of the total portfolio value. If we define the
proportion of H (t) invested in asset i as i (t) = wi (t)Si (t)/H (t), then (9.10)
becomes
dH (t) =
n
X
i=1
(9.11)
or
dH (t) =
"
n
X
i=1
Pn
i=1 i
n
X
(9.12)
i=1
invested in the n risky assets must sum to 1. However, consider the introduction
of a new risk-free asset. If, in addition to n risky assets, there is an asset that
pays an instantaneously risk-free rate of return, then this would correspond to
an asset having an instantaneous standard deviation, i , of zero and an expected
rate of return, i , equal to the instantaneous risk-free rate, which we denote as
r (t). In this case, the portfolio proportion invested in the risk-free asset equals
Pn
1 i=1 i (t). With this extension, equation (9.12) becomes
dH (t) =
"
n
X
i=1
n
X
i=1
(9.13)
257
9.1.2
The Black-Scholes model assumes that there is a contingent claim whose underlying asset pays no dividends. We will refer to this underlying asset as a stock,
and its date t price per share, S(t), is assumed to follow the diusion process
dS = S dt + S dz.
(9.14)
there is a risk-free asset that earns a constant rate of return equal to r per unit
time.
(9.15)
Now consider a European call option on this stock that matures at date T and
has an exercise price of X. Denote the options date t value as c(S, t).
We
assume it is a function of both calendar time, t, and the current stock price,
S (t), since at the maturity date t = T , the options payo depends on S (T ):
(9.16)
Given that the options value depends on the stock price and calendar time,
what process does it follow prior to maturity?3
258
verify that the no-arbitrage value of c (S, t) does, indeed, satisfy these conditions.
Then we can apply Its lemma to state that the options value must follow a
process of the form
dc =
c
1 2c 2 2
c
c
S +
+
S dz.
S
dt +
2
S
t
2 S
S
(9.17)
Hence, the call option inherits the same source of risk as the underlying stock,
reflected in the Wiener process dz.
9.1.3
Now consider forming a portfolio that includes 1 unit of the option and a
position in the underlying stock and the risk-free asset. Such a portfolio would
reflect the wealth position of an option dealer who has just sold one call option
to a customer and now attempts to hedge this liability by purchasing some of the
underlying stock and investing or borrowing at the risk-free rate. We restrict
this portfolio to require zero net investment, that is, after selling one unit of the
call option and taking a hedge position in the underlying stock, the remaining
surplus or deficit of funds is made up by borrowing or lending at the risk-free
rate. Moreover, we require that the portfolio be self-financing, that is, F (t) = 0
t, by which we mean that any surplus or deficit of funds from the option and
stock positions are made up by investing or acquiring funds at the risk-free rate.
Hence, if we let w(t) be the number of shares invested in the stock, then this
zero net investment, self-financing restriction implies that the amount invested
in the risk-free asset for all dates t must be B (t) = c (t)w (t) S (t). Therefore,
denoting the value of this hedge portfolio as H (t) implies that its instantaneous
return satisfies
(9.18)
259
dH (t) =
c
c
1 2c 2 2
c
S +
+
S dz
S
dt
S
t
2 S 2
S
(9.19)
Now consider selecting the number of shares invested in the stock in such a way
as to oset the risk of the return on the option. Specifically, suppose that the
option dealer chooses w (t) = c/S units (shares) of the stock, which is the
local sensitivity of the options value to the value of the underlying stock, also
known as the "hedge ratio."4 Hence, the hedging portfolio involves maintaining
a unit short position in the option and a position of c/S shares of stock, with
any surplus or deficit of funds required to maintain this hedge being invested
or acquired at the risk-free rate.
c
1 2c 2 2
c
c
S +
+
S dz
S
dt
S
t
2 S 2
S
c
c
+
(S dt + S dz) + c (t)
S (t) rdt
S
S
2
c
1
c
c
=
2 S 2 2 + rc (t) rS (t)
dt
t
2
S
S
dH (t) =
(9.20)
4 c/S is analogous to the hedge ratio in the binomial option pricing model. Recall that
the optimal choice of this hedge ratio was = (cu cd ) / (uS dS), which is essentially the
same partial derivative.
5 Since c (S, t) is yet to be determined, the question arises as to how w (t) = c/S would
be known to create the hedge portfolio. We will verify that if such a position in the stock
is maintained, then a no-arbitrage value for the option, c (S, t), is determined which, in turn,
makes known the hedge ratio w (t) = c/S.
260
9.1.4
Since the rate of return on this hedge portfolio is riskless, to avoid arbitrage
it must equal the competitive risk-free rate of return, r. But since we restricted
the hedge portfolio to require zero-net investment at the initial date, say t = 0,
then H (0) = 0 and
dH (0) = rH (0) dt = r0dt = 0
(9.21)
(9.22)
which is the Black-Scholes partial dierential equation. The call options value
must satisfy this partial dierential equation subject to the boundary condition
(9.23)
261
(9.24)
where
d1
d2
ln (S(t)/X) + r + 12 2 (T t)
T t
d1 T t.
(9.25)
(9.26)
6 The solution can be derived using a separation of variables method (Churchill and Brown
1978) or a LaPlace transform method (Shimko 1992). Also, in Chapter 10, we will show how
(9.24) can be derived using risk-neutral valuation.
7 The last line uses the symmetry property of the normal distribution 1 N (x) = N (x).
8 Deriving these partial derivatives is more tedious than it might first appear since d and d
1
2
1 Xer(T t) n (d ) d2
are both functions of S (t). Note that c/S = N (d1 ) +Sn (d1 ) d
2 S
S
where n (d) = 1 exp 12 d2 is the standard normal probability density function. This re2
1 = Xer(T t) n (d )
duces to (9.27) because it can be shown that Sn (d1 ) d
2
S
refer to the hedge ratios in (9.27) and (9.28) as the options deltas.
d2
.
S
Practioners
262
c
= N (d1 )
S
(9.27)
p
= N (d1 )
S
(9.28)
option requires a long position in less than one share of the underlying stock,
while hedging a put option requires a short position in less than one share of
the underlying stock.
portfolio for a call option increases the share amount in the stock as its price
rises.
A similar argument shows that the hedge portfolio for a put option
increases the share amount sold short as the price of the stock falls.
Thus,
because S (t) moves in a continuous fashion, so will the hedge portfolios position
in the stock. Finally, based on the solution in (9.24), we can verify that both
2 c/S 2 and c/t exist, which justifies our use of Its lemma in deriving the
process followed by the options price.9
We now turn to another application of the Black-Scholes-Merton hedging
argument for deriving security prices.
into the literature on the term structure of interest rates (or bond yields).
9 Using
2
n (d1 ) / S T t > 0 where n (x) = N (x) /x = ex /2 / 2 is the standard normal
probability density function. Hence, both call and put options are convex functions of the
underlying asset price. Practitioners refer to this second derivative as the options gamma.
The larger is an options gamma, the larger is the required change in the hedge ratio for a
given change in the underlying assets price. The options theta or time decay is given by
c/ (T t) = Sn (d1 ) / [2 (T t)] rXer(T t) N (d2 ).
9.2
263
The previous section showed that in a continuous time environment, the absence
of arbitrage restricts a derivatives price in terms of its underlying assets price.
We now consider a second example of how the absence of arbitrage links security
prices.
a single source of uncertainty aects bonds of all maturities. For these onefactor bond pricing models, it is often convenient to think of this uncertainty as
being summarized by the yield on the shortest (instantaneous) maturity bond,
r (t).10
"pure discount" bonds time until maturity. The instantaneous rate of return
on the bond is given by
dP (t, )
P (t, ) .
lim
dP (t, )
r (t) dt
P (t, )
(9.29)
(9.30)
10 Other approaches to modeling the term structure of interest rates are considered in Chapter 17. For example, we will discuss research by David Heath, Robert Jarrow, and Andrew
Morton (Heath, Jarrow, and Morton 1992) that assumes that forward interest rates of all
maturities are aected by one or more sources of risk.
264
In dis-
11 The
discrete time expected value and variance implied by the continuous time process
2
in (9.30) are Et [r (t + )] = r + e (r (t) r) and V art [r (t + )] = 2r 1 e2 . See
problem 4 at the end of Chapter 8.
12 For example, a central bank may implement monetary policy by changing the level of the
short-term interest rate. Other macro-economic eects on bond prices might be summarized
in the level of the short rate.
P
2P
P
dr +
dt + 12 2 (dr)2
r
t
r
= Pr (r r) + Pt + 12 Prr 2r dt + Pr r dzr
dP (r, ) =
265
(9.31)
where
the subscriptsl on P denote partial derivatives and where p (r, )
k
1
Pr (rr)+Pt + 2 Prr 2r
P (r, )
r r
and p () PP(r,
) are the mean and standard devi-
Since both bonds are driven by the same Wiener process, dzr ,
p ( 1 ) P (r, 1 )
P (r, 2 )
H (t) = P (r, 1 )
p ( 2 ) P (r, 2 )
p ( 1 )
= P (r, 1 ) 1
p ( 2 )
(9.32)
266
dH (t) = dP (r, 1 )
p ( 1 ) P (r, 1 )
dP (r, 2 )
p ( 2 ) P (r, 2 )
(9.33)
p ( 1 )
P (r, 1 ) p (r, 2 ) dt + p ( 1 ) P (r, 1 ) dzr
p ( 2 )
p ( 1 )
P (r, 1 ) p (r, 2 ) dt
= p (r, 1 ) P (r, 1 ) dt
p ( 2 )
Since the
p ( 1 )
p (r, 2 ) P (r, 1 ) dt
p (r, 1 )
p ( 2 )
p ( 1 )
= r (t) H (t) dt = r (t) 1
P (r, 1 ) dt
p ( 2 )
dH (t) =
(9.34)
Equating the terms that precede P (r, 1 ) on the first and second lines of (9.34),
we see that an implication of this equation is
p (r, 1 ) r (t)
p (r, 2 ) r (t)
=
p ( 1 )
p ( 2 )
(9.35)
9.2.1
Equation (9.35) says that bonds expected rates of return in excess of the instantaneous maturity rate, divided by their standard deviations, must be equal at
267
all points in time. This equality of Sharpe ratios must hold for any set of bonds
1 , 2 , 3 , etc. Each of the dierent bonds reward-to-risk ratios (Sharpe ratios) derives from the single source of risk represented by the dzr process driving
the short-term interest rate, r (t). Hence, condition (9.35) can be interpreted
as a law of one price that requires all bonds to have a uniform market price of
interest rate risk.
To derive the equilibrium prices for bonds, we must specify the form of
this market price of bond risk.
model by John Cox, Jonathan Ingersoll, and Stephen Ross, (Cox, Ingersoll, and
Ross 1985a) and (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985b), that shows how this bond
risk premium can be derived from individuals preferences (utilities) and the
economys technologies. For now, however, we simply assume that the market
price of bond risk is constant over time and equal to q. Thus, we have for any
bond maturity, ,
p (r, ) r (t)
=q
p ()
(9.36)
p (r, ) = r (t) + qp ()
(9.37)
or
which says that the expected rate of return on a bond with maturity equals
the instantaneous risk-free rate plus a risk premium proportional to the bonds
standard deviation.
Pr (r r) + Pt + 12 Prr 2r = rP q r Pr
This can be re-written as
(9.38)
268
2r
2 Prr
+ (r + q r r) Pr rP + Pt = 0
(9.39)
Equation (9.39) is the equilibrium partial dierential equation that all bonds
must satisfy. Since T t, so that Pt
P
t
= P
P , equation (9.39)
can be re-written as
2r
2 Prr
+ [ (r r) + q r ] Pr rP P = 0
(9.40)
and solved subject to the boundary condition that at = 0, the bond price
equals $1, that is, P (r, 0) = 1. Doing so, gives the following solution14
(9.41)
where
B ()
1 e
"
(9.42)
2
2
r
2r B ( )
1 r
A () exp (B ( ) ) r + q
2 2
9.2.2
(9.43)
p () = r
r
Pr
= r B ( ) =
1 e
P
(9.44)
14 The solution can be derived by "guessing" a solution of the form in (9.41) and substituting
it into (9.40). Noting that the terms multiplied by r (t) and those terms not multiplied by
r (t) must each be zero for all r (t) leads to simple ordinary dierential equations for A ( ) and
B ( ). These equations are solved sub ject to the boundary condition P (r, = 0) = 1, which
implies A ( = 0) = 1 and B ( = 0) = 0. See Chapter 17 for details and a generalization to
bond prices that are influenced by multiple factors.
269
1
Y (r (t) , ) ln [P (r (t) , )]
B ()
1
r (t)
= ln [A ( )] +
B () 2r B ( )2
+
= Y + [r (t) Y ]
(9.45)
maturity on a very long maturity bond approaches Y . Hence, the yield curve,
15 See
(Dimson, Marsh, and Staunton 2002) for an account of the historical evidence.
270
r
3r
r
asymptotes to Y for large. When r (t) Y 4
2 = r +q 42 , the yield
2
curve is monotonically increasing. When Y 4r2 < r (t) < Y + 2r2 = r+q r ,
the yield curve has a humped shape. An "inverted" or monotonically downward
sloping yield curve occurs when r+q r r (t). Since the unconditional mean of
the short rate is r, and, empirically, the yield curve is normally upward sloping,
32
3r
4 .
9.3
valuing a European call option when the risk-free interest rate is stochastic and
bond prices satisfy the Vasicek model. The main alteration to the Black-Scholes
derivation is to realize that the call options payo, max [S (T ) X, 0], depends
not only on the maturity date, T , and the stock price at that date, S (T ), but
on the present value of the exercise price, X, which can be interpreted as the
value of a default-free bond that pays X at its maturity date of T . Given the
randomness of interest rates, even the value of this exercise price is stochastic
prior to the options maturity. This motivates us to consider the process of a
bond maturing in T t periods to be another underlying asset, in addition
to the stock, aecting the options value. Writing this bond price as P (t, ),
the options value can now be expressed as c (S (t) , P (t, ) , t). Consistent with
271
(9.46)
where from (9.31) we define dzp dzr . In general, the bonds return will be
correlated with that of the stock, and we allow for this possibility by assuming
dzp dz = dt. Given the options dependence on both the stock and the bond,
Its lemma says that the option price satisfies
dc
c
1 2c 2 2 1 2c 2 2
c
c
S +
p P +
+
S +
P
S
P
t
2 S 2
2 P 2 p
c
2c
c
p SP dt +
S dz +
p P dzp
+
(9.47)
SP
S
P
c
c
S dz +
p P dzp
c cdt +
S
P
where c c is defined as the terms in brackets in the first two lines of (9.47).
Similar to our first example in which a dealer wishes to hedge the sale of an
option, let us form a hedge portfolio consisting of a unit short position in the
option, and a purchase of ws (t) units of the underlying stock, and a purchase
of wp (t) units of the -maturity bond, where we also restrict the portfolio to
require a zero net investment. The zero net investment restriction implies
(9.48)
272
= c c + ws (t) S + wp (t) p P dt
c
S + ws (t) S dz
+
S
c
p P + wp (t) p P dzp
+
P
= ws (t) ( c ) S + wp (t) p c P dt
c
+ ws (t)
Sdz
S
c
+ wp (t)
p P dzp
P
(9.49)
where in the last equality of (9.49) we have substituted in for c using the zero
net investment condition (9.48). If ws (t) and wp (t) can be chosen to make the
hedge portfolios return to be riskless, then it must be the case that the terms
in brackets in the last line of (9.49) can be made to equal zero. In other words,
the following two conditions must hold:
ws (t) =
c
S
(9.50)
wp (t) =
c
P
(9.51)
but from the zero net investment condition (9.48), this can only be possible if
it happens to be the case that
c = ws (t) S + wp (t) P
= S
c
c
+P
S
P
(9.52)
273
later verify that the solution indeed satisfies this homogeneity condition.
Given that condition (9.52) does hold, so that we can choose ws (t) = c/S
and wp (t) = c/P to make the hedge portfolios return to be riskless, then
as in the first example the zero net investment portfolios riskless return must
equal zero in the absence of arbitrage:
ws (t) ( c ) S + wp (t) p c P = 0
(9.53)
or
c
c
( c ) S +
c P = 0
S
P p
(9.54)
(9.55)
c
1 2c 2 2 1 2c 2 2
2c
p SP = 0
p
t
2 S 2
2 P 2
SP
(9.56)
274
2c 2 2
2c
c
1 2c 2 2
=0
S
+
P
+
2
SP
p
p
2
2
2 S
P
SP
(9.57)
Equation (9.57) is the equilibrium partial dierential equation that the options
value must satisfy.
rate of return on the stock, , or the expected rate of return on the bond, p .
The appropriate boundary condition for a European call option is similar to
before, with c (S (T ) , P (T, 0) , T ) = c (S (T ) , 1, T ) = max [S (T ) X, 0], where
we impose the condition P (t = T, = 0) = 1. Robert Merton (Merton 1973b)
shows that the solution to this equation is
(9.58)
where
ln
where
v2 =
h1
h2
S(t)
P (t, )X
1 2
2v
(9.59)
h1 v .
2 + p (y)2 2p (y) dy
(9.60)
The solution is essentially the same as the Black-Scholes constant interest rate
formula (9.24) but where the parameter v2 replaces 2 . v2 is the total variance
of the ratio of the stock price to the discounted exercise price over the life of
the option.18 In other words, it is the variance of the ratio
S(t)
P (t, )X
from date t
18 As one would expect, when interest rates are non-stochastic so that the volatility of bond
prices is zero, that is, p (y) = 0, then v 2 = 2 , and we obtain the standard Black-Scholes
formula.
9.4. SUMMARY
275
(1 ey ), then
(9.60) becomes
r
2r
2
y
2y
y
1e
2
=
+e
+ 2 1 2e
dt
(9.61)
2
1 e2
r
2 1 e
= 2 + r3 +
2 2 1 e
9.4
Summary
Fischer Black, Myron Scholes, and Robert Merton made a fundamental discovery that profoundly changed the pricing of contingent securities. They showed
that when an underlying asset follows a diusion, and trade is allowed to occur continuously, a portfolio can be created that fully hedges the risk of the
contingent claim. Therefore, in the absence of arbitrage the hedge portfolios
return must be riskless, and this implies that the contingent claims price must
satisfy a particular partial dierential equation subject to a boundary condition
that its value must equal its terminal payo.
surprising result: the contingent claims value did not depend directly on the
underlying securitys expected rate of return, but only its volatility. This was
an attractive feature because estimating a risky assets expected rate of return
276
9.5
Exercises
dS = Sdt + S dz
9.5. EXERCISES
277
(r, ) r (t)
= r
p (r, )
then write down the equilibrium partial dierential equation and boundary
condition that this bond price satisfies.
3. The date t price of stock A, A (t), follows the process
dA/A = A dt + A dz
dB/B = B dt + B dq
ropean option written on the dierence between these two stocks prices.
Specifically, at this options maturity date, T , the value of the option
equals
c (T ) = max [0, A (T ) B (T )]
278
3.a Using Its lemma, derive the process followed by this option.
3.b Suppose that you are an option dealer who has just sold (wrote) one of
these options for a customer. You now wish to form a hedge portfolio
composed of your unit short position in the option and positions in the
two stocks. Let H (t) denote the date t value of this hedge portfolio. Write
down an equation for H (t) that indicates the amount of shares of stocks
A and B that should be held.
3.c Write down the dynamics for dH (t), showing that its return is riskless.
3.d Assuming the absence of arbitrage, derive the equilibrium partial dierential equation that this option must satisfy.
4. Let S (t) be the date t price of an asset that continuously pays a dividend
that is a fixed proportion of its price.
dividend of S (t) dt over the time interval dt. The process followed by
this assets price can be written as
dS = ( ) Sdt + Sdz
where is the standard deviation of the assets rate of return and is the
assets total expected rate of return, which includes its dividend payment
and price appreciation. Note that the total rate of return earned by the
owner of one share of this asset is dS/S+ dt = dt+ dz. Consider a
European call option written on this asset that has an exercise price of X
and a maturity date of T > t. Assuming a constant interest rate equal to
r, use a Black-Scholes hedging argument to derive the equilibrium partial
dierential equation that this options price, c (t), must satisfy.
Chapter 10
The
We
formally show that when asset prices follow diusion processes and trading is
continuous, then the absence of arbitrage may allow us to value assets using a
martingale pricing technique, a generalization of risk-neutral pricing.
Under
280
The first section reviews the derivation of the Black Scholes partial dierential equation and points out that this equation also implies that the market
price of risk must be uniform for a contingent claim and its underlying asset. It
also shows how the contingent claims price process can be transformed into a
driftless process by adjusting its Brownian motion process by the market price
of risk and then deflating the contingent claims price by that of a riskless asset.
This driftless (zero expected change) process is known as a martingale.
The
contingent claims value then can be computed as the expectation of its terminal
value under this transformed process.
The second section derives the form of a continuous time state price deflator that can also be used to price contingent claims.
It also demonstrates
how the continuous time state price deflator transforms actual probabilities into
risk-neutral probabilities. The third section shows how problems of valuing a
contingent claim sometimes can be simplified by deflating the contingent claims
price by that of another risky asset. It gives an example of this by valuing an
option written on the dierence between the prices of two risky assets.
The
10.1
281
dS = Sdt + Sdz
(10.1)
processes can be handled by the theory, such that and can depend on
other variables that follow diusion processes (driven by additional Brownian
motions) in addition to S (t). In this way, asset values can depend on multiple
sources of uncertainty.
Next let c (S, t) denote the value of a contingent claim whose payo depends
solely on S and t. From Its lemma, we know that this value satisfies
dc = c cdt + c cdz
(10.2)
H = c + cS S
(10.3)
and the change in value of this portfolio over the next instant is
1 Unlike last chapters derivation, we do not restrict this portfolio to be a zero-net investment portfolio. As will be clear, the lack of this restriction does not change the nature of our
results.
282
dH
= dc + cS dS
(10.4)
(10.5)
cS S c c = r[c + cS S]
(10.6)
which implies
If we substitute c c = ct + ScS + 12 2 S 2 cSS into (10.6), we obtain the BlackScholes equilibrium partial dierential equation (PDE).
1 2 2
S cSS + rScS rc + ct = 0
2
(10.7)
c c
S
2 For simplicity, we have assumed that the contingent claims value depends only on a single
risky asset price, S (t). However, when the interest rate is stochastic, the contingent claims
value might be also a function of r (t), that is, c (S, r, t). If, for example, the interest rate
followed the process dr = r (r) dt + r (r) dzr where dzr is an additional Wiener process
aecting interest rate movements, then the contingent claims process would be given by a
bi-variate version of Its lemma. Also, to create a portfolio that earns an instantaneous riskfree rate, the portfolio would need to include a bond whose price is driven by dzr . Later,
we discuss how our results generalize to multiple sources of uncertainty. However, the current
univariate setting can be fully consistent with stochastic interest rates if the risky asset is,
itself, a bond so that S (r, t) and dz = dzr . The contingent claim could then be interpreted
as a fixed-income (bond) derivative security.
r
r
= c
(t)
283
(10.8)
(10.9)
Note that the drift of this process depends on the market price of risk, (t),
which may not be directly observable or easily estimated. We now consider an
approach to valuing contingent claims which is an alternative to solving the PDE
in (10.7) but which shares with it the benefit of not having to know (t). The
next topic discusses how a contingent claims risk-premium can be eliminated
by reinterpreting the probability distribution generating asset returns.
10.1.1
Girsanovs Theorem says that by shifting the Brownian motion process, one can
change the drift of a diusion process when this process is interpreted under a
new probability distribution. Moreover, this shift in Brownian motion changes
the future probability distribution for asset prices in a particular way. To
Rt
zt =
see how this works, consider a new process zbt = zt + 0 (s) ds, so that db
zt (t) dt in (10.9), it can be rewritten:
dzt + (t) dt. Then substituting dzt = db
dc = [rc + c c] dt + c c [db
z dt]
= rcdt + c cdb
z
(10.10)
284
(u)
du
< , which is known as the
t
t
Novikov condition. Ioannis Karatzas and Steven Shreve (Karatzas and Shreve 1991) give a
formal statement and proof of Girsonovs Theorem.
5 Recall that since a probability distribution function, P , is an integral over the probabilU
ity density function, dP , the density function can be interpreted as the derivative of the
probability distribution function.
285
Girsonovs theorem says that at some date t where 0 < t < T , the relationship
between the two probability densities at date T is
dQT
" Z
= exp
T
t
1
(u) dz
2
= ( T / t ) dPT
(u) du dPT
(10.11)
where t is positive random process that depends on (t) and zt and is given
by
Z
= exp
1
(u) dz
2
(u) ds
2
(10.12)
Since from (10.12) we see that T / t > 0, equation (10.11) implies that
whenever dPT has positive probability, so does dQT . Because they share this
characteristic, the physical P measure and the risk-neutral Q measure are called
equivalent probability measures in that any future value of c that has positive
probability (density) under the physical measure also has positive probability
(density) under the risk-neutral measure.6 We can re-arrange (10.11) to obtain
dQT
= T / t
dPT
(10.13)
286
10.1.2
dB/B = r(t)dt
UT
r(u)du
(10.14)
Now define C(t)
Essentially,
C (t) is the value of the contingent claim measured in terms of the value of the
riskless safe investment that grows at rate r (t). A trivial application of Its
lemma gives
dC
=
=
1
dc
B
rc
dt +
B
c
dB
B2
cc
c
db
z r dt
B
B
(10.15)
= c Cdb
z
7 An investment that earns the instantaneous maturity risk-free rate is sometimes referred
to as a money market fund because money market mutual funds invest in short maturity, high
credit quality (nearly risk free) debt instruments.
287
Thus, the deflated price process under the equivalent probability measure generated by db
z is a driftless process: its expected change is zero. An implication
of (10.15) is that the expectation under the risk-neutral or Q measure of any
future value of C is the current value of C. This can be stated as
bt [C (T )]
C (t) = E
T t
(10.16)
generated by db
z .8 The mathematical name for a process such as (10.16) is a
martingale, which is essentially a random walk in discrete time.9
10.1.3
Feynman-Kac Solution
bt c (T ) 1
c(t) = B(t)E
B (T )
h UT
i
bt e t r(u)du c (T )
= E
(10.17)
288
10.2
This is not the first time that we have computed an expectation to value a
security. Recall from the single- or multi-period consumption - portfolio choice
problem with time separable utility that we obtained an Euler condition of the
form11
10 To solve (10.7), a boundary condition for the derivative is needed. For example, in the
case of a European call option it would be c (T ) = max [0, S (T ) X]. The solution given by
(10.17) incorporates this boundary condition, c (T ).
11 In equation (10.18) we are assuming that the contingent claim pays no dividends between
dates t and T .
289
c (t) = Et [mt,T c (T )]
MT
= Et
c (T )
Mt
(10.18)
where date T t, mt,T MT /Mt and Mt = Uc (Ct , t) was the marginal utility
of consumption at date t.
- discrete state model that the absence of arbitrage implies that a stochastic
discount factor, mt,T , exists whenever markets are complete.
We now show
that this same result applies in a continuous time environment whenever markets
are dynamically complete. The absence of arbitrage opportunities, which earlier
guaranteed the existence of an equivalent martingale measure, also determines a
pricing kernel or state price deflator, Mt . In fact, the concepts of an equivalent
martingale measure and state pricing kernel are one and the same.
Note that we can rewrite (10.18) as
c (t) Mt = Et [c (T ) MT ]
(10.19)
which says that the deflated price process, c (t) Mt , is a martingale. But note the
dierence here versus our earlier analysis: the expectation in (10.19) is taken
under the physical probability measure, P , while in (10.16) and (10.17) the
expectation is taken under the risk-neutral measure, Q.
Since in the standard time-separable utility portfolio choice model, Mt is
the marginal utility of consumption, this suggests that Mt should be a positive
process even when we consider more general environments where a stochastic
discount factor pricing relationship would hold.
state price deflator, Mt , follows a strictly positive diusion process of the general
form:
290
dM = m dt + m dz
(10.20)
dcm
(10.21)
= [cm + M c c + c c m ] dt + [c m + M c c] dz
If cm = cM satisfies (10.19), that is, cm is a martingale, then its drift in (10.21)
must be zero, implying
c =
m c m
M
M
(10.22)
Now consider the case in which c is the instantaneously riskless asset, that is,
c (t) = B (t) is the money market investment following the process in equation
(10.14). This implies that c = 0 and c = r (t). Using (10.22), requires
r (t) =
m
M
(10.23)
In other words, the expected rate of change of the pricing kernel must equal
minus the instantaneous risk-free interest rate. Next, consider the general case
where the asset c is risky, so that c 6= 0. Using (10.22) and (10.23) together,
we obtain
c = r (t)
or
cm
M
(10.24)
m
c r
=
c
M
291
(10.25)
m
= (t)
M
(10.26)
Thus, the no-arbitrage condition implies that the form of the pricing kernel
must be
(10.27)
using the pricing kernel to value any contingent claim, we can re-write (10.18)
as
c (t) = Et [c (T ) MT /Mt ] = Et c (T ) em T m t
h
i
UT
UT
1 2
= Et c (T ) e t [r(u)+ 2 (u)]du t (u)dz
(10.28)
Given processes for r (t), (t) and the contingent claims payo, c (T ), in some
instances it may be easier to compute (10.28) rather than, say, (10.16) or (10.17).
Of course, in computing (10.28), we need to use the actual drift for c, that is,
we compute expectations under the P measure, not the Q measure.
10.2.1
To better understand the connection between the pricing kernel (stochastic discount factor) approach and the martingale (risk-neutral) valuation approach,
we now show how Mt is related to the change in probability distribution accom-
292
(10.29)
i
UT
1 2
2 (u)du t (u)dz
bt [C (T )] = Et [C (T ) ( T / t )]
E
Z
C (T ) dQT =
C (T ) ( T / t ) dPT
(10.30)
where recall that C (t) = c (t) /B (t). From the first two lines of (10.30), we see
that on both sides of the equation, the terms in brackets are exactly the same
except that the expectation under P includes the Radon-Nikodym derivative
T / t . As predicted by Girsonovs theorem, this factor transforms the physical
probability density at date T to the risk-neutral probability density at date T .
Furthermore, relating (10.29) to (10.30) implies
MT /Mt = e
UT
t
r(u)du
( T / t )
(10.31)
so that the continuous time pricing kernel (stochastic discount factor) is the
product of a risk-free rate discount factor and the Radon-Nikodym derivative.
Hence, MT /Mt can be interpreted as providing both discounting at the risk-free
rate and transforming the probability distribution to the risk-neutral one. Indeed, if contingent security prices are deflated by the money market investment,
thereby removing the risk-free discount factor, the second line of (10.30) shows
that the pricing kernel, MT /Mt , and the Radon-Nikodym derivative, T / t , are
exactly the same.
293
Similar to the discrete time case discussed in Chapter 4, the role of this
derivative ( T / t or MT /Mt ) is to adjust the risk-neutral probability, Q, to give
it greater probability density for "bad" outcomes and less probability density for
"good" outcomes relative to the physical probability, P . In continuous time,
the extent to which an outcome, as reflected by a realization of dz, is "bad"
or "good" depends on the sign and magnitude of its market price of risk, (t).
This explains why in equation (10.27) the stochastic component of the pricing
kernel is of the form (t) dz.
10.2.2
The previous analysis has assumed that contingent claims prices depend on only
a single source of uncertainty, dz. In a straightforward manner, the results can
be generalized to permit multiple independent sources of risk. Suppose we had
asset returns depending on an n 1 vector of independent Brownian motion
processes, dZ = (dz1 ...dzn )0 where dzi dzj = 0 for i 6= j.12 A contingent claim
whose payo depended on these asset returns then would have a price that
followed the process
dc/c = c dt + c dZ
where c is a 1 n vector c = ( c1 ...cn ).13
(10.32)
Let the corresponding n 1
vector of market prices of risks associated with each of the Brownian motions
0
be = (1 ... n ) . Then, it is straightforward to show that we would have the
no-arbitrage condition
c r = c
(10.33)
12 The independence assumption is not important. If there are correlated sources of risk
(Brownian motions), they can be re-defined by a linear transformation to be represented by
n orthogonal risk sources.
13 Both and the elements of may be functions of state variables driven by the Brownian
c
c
motion components of dZ.
294
Equations (10.16) and (10.17) would still hold, and now the pricing kernels
process would be given by
10.3
(10.34)
(10.35)
(10.36)
where 1 and 2 are assumed to be constants and dz1 and dz2 are Brownian
motion processes for which dz1 dz2 = dt.
a European option written on the dierence between these two stocks prices.
Specifically, at this options maturity date, T , the value of the option equals
C (T ) = max [0, S1 (T ) S2 (T )]
(10.37)
295
Now define c (t) = C (t) /S2 (t) , s (t) S1 (t) /S2 (t), and B (t) = S2 (t) /S2 (t)
= 1 as the deflated price processes, where the prices of the option, stock 1, and
stock 2 all are normalized by the price of stock 2. With this normalized price
system, the terminal payo corresponding to (10.37) is now
c (T ) = max [0, s (T ) 1]
(10.38)
ds/s = s dt + s dz3
(10.39)
price of stock 2 becomes the riskless asset, with the riskless rate of return given
by dB/B = 0dt. That is, because the deflated price of stock 2 never changes,
it returns a riskless rate of zero.
1
2 2
dc = cs s s + ct + css s s dt + cs s s dz3 .
2
(10.40)
With this normalized price system, the usual Black-Scholes hedge portfolio can
be created from the option and stock 1. The hedge portfolios value is given by
H = c + cs s
and the instantaneous change in value of the portfolio is
(10.41)
296
dH
=
=
=
(10.42)
dc + cs ds
1
cs s s + ct + css 2s s2 dt cs s s dz3 + cs s s dt + cs s s dz3
2
1
2 2
ct + css s s dt
2
1
2 2
dH = ct + css s s dt = 0
2
(10.43)
which implies
ct +
1
css 2s s2 = 0
2
(10.44)
which is the Black-Scholes partial dierential equation but with the risk-free
rate, r, set to zero. Solving it subject to the boundary condition (10.38), which
implies a unit exercise price, gives the usual Black-Scholes formula
(10.45)
where
d1
d2
ln (s(t)) + 12 2s (T t)
s T t
d1 s T t.
(10.46)
10.4. APPLICATIONS
297
C( t) = S1 N (d1 ) S2 N (d2 )
(10.47)
Note that the option price does not depend on the non-deflated price systems
risk-free rate, r (t). Hence, the formula holds even for stochastic interest rates.
10.4
Applications
This section illustrates the usefulness of the martingale pricing technique. The
first set of applications deal with options written on assets that continuously
pay dividends. Examples include an option written on a foreign currency and
an option written on a futures price. The second application is to value bonds
of dierent maturities, which determines the term structure of interest rates.
10.4.1
Continuous Dividends
dS = ( ) Sdt + Sdz
(10.48)
where is the standard deviation of the assets rate of return and is the
assets total expected rate of return, which includes its dividend payment and
price appreciation. Similar to the assumptions of Black and Scholes, and
298
Now note
that the total rate of return earned by the owner of one share of this asset is
dS/S+ dt = dt+ dz. Consider a European call option written on this asset
that has an exercise price of X and a maturity date of T > t, where we define
T t. Assuming a constant interest rate equal to r, we use equation (10.17)
to write the date t price of this option as
bt er c (T )
c (t) = E
(10.49)
bt [max [S (T ) X, 0]]
= er E
dS = (r ) Sdt + Sdb
z
(10.50)
ln [S (T )] N
1
ln [S (t)] + (r 2 ) , 2
2
(10.51)
10.4. APPLICATIONS
299
c (t)
bt [max [S (T ) X, 0]]
= er E
Z
= er
(S (T ) X) g(S (T )) dS (T )
(10.52)
where g(ST ) is the lognormal probability density function. This integral can
be evaluated by making the change in variable
ln [S (T ) /S (t)] r 12 2
Y =
(10.53)
which from (10.51) transforms the lognormally distributed S (T ) into the variable Y distributed N (0, 1). The result is the modified Black-Scholes formula
(10.54)
where
d1
d2
ln (S/X) + r + 12 2
= d1
=
(10.55)
Comparing this formula to (9.24) and (9.25), the value of an option written
on an asset that pays no dividends, the only dierence is that the non-dividend
paying assets price, S (t), is replaced with the dividend-discounted price of the
dividend paying asset, S (t) e .
t [S (T )] = S (t) er . However,
realizing that if no dividends are paid, then E
with dividends, the risk-neutral expected asset price appreciates at rate r ,
rather than r. This is because with dividends paid out at rate , expected price
300
appreciation must be at rate r to keep the total expected rate of return equal
to + r = r. Thus, the risk-neutral expectation of S (T ) is
t [S (T )] = S (t) e(r)
E
(10.56)
= S (t) e er = S (t) er
where we define S (t) S (t) e . This shows that the value of an option on
a dividend-paying asset with current price S equals the value of an option on a
non-dividend paying asset having current price S = Se .
Formula (10.54) can be applied to an option on a foreign currency. If S (t)
is defined as the domestic currency value of a unit of foreign currency, that is,
the spot exchange rate, then assuming this rate has a constant volatility gives
it a process satisfying (10.48).
the date t forward exchange rate having a time until maturity of , that is,
Ft, = Se(rrf ) .14 Therefore, (10.54) can be written as
where d1 =
ln[Ft, /X]+ 2
(10.57)
and d2 = d1 .
10.4. APPLICATIONS
301
prices are similar to forward prices.15 Like a forward contract, futures contracts
involve long and short parties, and if both parties maintain their positions until
the maturity of the contract, their total profits equal the dierence between the
underlying assets maturity value and the initial future price. The main dierence between futures contracts and forward contracts is that a futures contract
is marked-to-market daily: that is, the futures price for a particular maturity
contract is re-computed daily and profits equal to the dierence between todays and yesterdays future price are transferred (settled) from the short party
to the long party on a daily basis.
for a contract maturing at date t , then the undiscounted profit (loss) earned
by the long (short) party over the period from date t to date T t is simply
FT,t Ft,t . Like forward contracts, there is no initial cost for the parties who
enter into a futures contract.
t [FT,t Ft,t ] = 0
E
(10.58)
t [FT,t ] = Ft,t
E
(10.59)
Thus, while under the Q measure a non-dividend paying asset price would be
expected to grow at rate r, a futures price would be expected to grow at rate
0. Hence, futures are like assets with a dividend yield = r.
can derive the value of a futures call option that matures in periods where
15 See (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1981) and (Jarrow and Oldfield 1981) for a comparison of
forward and futures contracts. If markets are frictionless, there are no arbitrage opportunities,
and default-free interest rates are non-stochastic, then it can be shown that forward and
futures prices are equivalent for contracts written on the same underlying asset and having
the same maturity date. When interest rates are stochastic, then futures price will be greater
(less) than equivalent contract forward prices if the underlying asset is positively (negatively)
correlated with short-term interest rates.
302
(t t) as:
c (t) = er [Ft,t N (d1 ) XN (d2 )]
2
where d1 =
ln[Ft,t /X ]+ 2
(10.60)
10.4.2
The martingale pricing equation (10.17) can be applied to deriving the date
t price of a default-free bond that matures in periods and pays $1 at the
maturity date T = t + .
h U
i
bt e tT r(u)du 1
P (t, ) = E
(10.61)
To apply equation
(10.61), we need to find the risk-neutral (Q measure) process for the instantaneous maturity interest rate, r (t). Recall that the physical (P measure) process
for the interest rate was assumed to be the Ornstein-Uhlenbeck process
(10.62)
and that the market price of bond risk, q, was assumed to be a constant. This
implied that the expected rate of return on all bonds satisfied
p (r, ) = r (t) + qp ( )
(10.63)
10.4. APPLICATIONS
303
(10.64)
(10.65)
= r (t) dt p ( ) db
zr
which is the risk-neutral, Q measure process for the bond price.
This is so
because under this transformation all bond prices now have an expected rate
of return equal to the instantaneously risk-free rate, r (t). Therefore, applying
this same Brownian motion transformation to equation (10.62), we find that the
instantaneous maturity interest rate process under the Q measure is
zr + qdt]
dr(t) = [r r (t)] dt + r [db
i
h
qr
r (t) dt + r db
= r+
zr
(10.66)
Hence, we see that the risk-neutral process for r (t) continues to be an OrnsteinUhlenbeck process but with a dierent unconditional mean, r + q r /. Thus,
we can use the valuation equation (10.61) to compute the discounted value of
h
R
i
bt exp T r (u) du assuming r (t) follows
the bonds $1 payo, P (t, ) = E
t
the process in (10.66). Doing so leads to the same solution given in the previous
304
10.5
Summary
10.6. EXERCISES
305
10.6
Exercises
1. In this problem, you are asked to derive the equivalent martingale measure
and the pricing kernel for the case to two sources of risk. Let S1 and S2
be the values of two risky assets which follow the processes
where both i and i may be functions of S1 , S2 , and t, and dz1 and dz2
are two independent Brownian motion processes, implying dz1 dz2 = 0. Let
f (S1 , S2 , t) denote the value of a contingent claim whose payo depends
solely on S1 , S2 , and t. Also let r (t) be the instantaneous risk-free interest
rate. From Its lemma, we know that the derivatives value satisfies
1 r
1 ,
and 2
2 r
2 .
306
1.c Let B (t) be the value of a money market fund which invests in the
instantaneous maturity risk-free asset. Show that F (t) f (t) /B (t) is a
martingale under the risk-neutral probability measure.
1.d Let M (t) be the state price deflator such that f (t) M (t) is a martingale
under the physical probability measure. If
dM = m dt + m1 dz1 + m2 dz2 ,
2. The Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985b) model of
the term structure of interest rates assumes that the process followed by
the instantaneous maturity risk-free interest rate is
dr = ( r) dt + rdz
where , , and are constants.
= r
p (t, )
where is a constant.
10.6. EXERCISES
307
2.a Write down the stochastic process followed by the pricing kernel (state
price deflator), M (t), for this problem, that is, the process dM/M. Also,
apply Its lemma to derive the process for m(t) ln (M ), that is, the
process dm.
2.b Let the current date be 0 and write down the formula for the bond price,
P (0, ), in terms of an expectation of m m0 . Show how this can be
written in terms of an expectation of functions of integrals of r (t) and .
3. If the price of a non-dividend paying stock follows the process dS/S =
dt + dz where is constant, and there is a constant risk-free interest rate equal to r, then the Black-Scholes showed that the no-arbitrage
value of a standard call option having periods to maturity and an exercise price of X is given by c = SN (d1 ) Xer N (d2 ) where d1 =
ln (S/X) + r + 12 2 / ( ) and d2 = d1 .
A forward start call option is similar to this standard option but with the
308
stock price follows the process dS/S = dt + dz, the risk-free interest
rate equals r, and the options time until maturity equals .
F if S (T ) > X
cncT =
0 if S (T ) X
where F is a fixed amount. Derive the value of this option when its time
until maturity is and the current stock price is S. Explain your reasoning.
S (T ) if S (T ) > X
ancT =
0 if S (T ) X
Derive the value of this option when its time until maturity is and the
current stock price is S. Explain your reasoning.
10.6. EXERCISES
309
dgt /gt = dt + dz
E0
U (Ct , t) dt
6.b Let mt,t+ Mt+ /Mt be the stochastic discount factor (pricing kernel)
for this economy. Based on your answer in part a, write down the stochastic process for Mt . (Hint: find an expression for Mt and then use Its
lemma.)
6.c Based on your previous answers, write down the instantaneous risk-free
real interest rate. Is it constant or time-varying?
Chapter 11
In some situations,
For
312
Section 2 shows
how Its lemma can be extended to derive the process of a variable that is a
function of a mixed jump-diusion process. It comes as no surprise that this
function inherits the risk of both the Brownian motion component as well as the
jump component of the underlying process. Section 3 revisits the problem of
valuing a contingent claim, but now assumes the underlying assets price follows
a mixed jump diusion process.
(Merton 1976) who first analyzed this subject. In general, the inclusion of a
jump process means that a contingent claims risk cannot be perfectly hedged
by trading in the underlying asset. In this situation of market incompleteness,
additional assumptions regarding the price of jump risk need to be made in
order to value derivative securities.
when the underlying assets jump risk is perfectly diversifiable. The problem of
option valuation when the underlying asset is the market portfolio of all assets
is also discussed.
11.1
dS/S = ( k) dt + dz + (Y ) dq
(11.1)
where dz is a standard Wiener (Brownian motion) process and q (t) is a Poisson counting process that increases by 1 whenever a Poisson-distributed event
313
1 if a jump occurs
dq =
0 otherwise
(11.2)
During each time interval, dt, the probability that q (t) will augment by 1
is (t) dt, where (t) is referred to as the Poisson intensity. When a Poisson
event does occur, say at date b
t, then there is a discontinuous change in S equal
to dS = (Y ) S where is a function of Y b
t , which may be a random variable
t, then
realized at date b
t.1 In other words, if a Poisson event occurs at date b
+
t = (Y ) S b
t or
dS b
t =S b
t S b
+
t
S b
t = [1 + (Y )] S b
(11.3)
if we wish to let the parameter denote the instantaneous total expected rate
of return (rate of change) on S, we need to subtract o k dt from the drift
term of S:
E[dS/S]
( k) dt + 0 + k dt = dt
(11.4)
The sample path of S(t) for a process described by equation (11.1) will be
1 The date or "point" of a jump, e
t . Hence,
t, is associated with the attribute or "mark" Y e
e
t, Y e
t is referred to as a marked point process or space-time point process.
314
continuous most of the time, but can have finite jumps of diering signs and
amplitudes at discrete points in time, where the timing of the jumps depends
on the Poisson random variable q (t) and the jump sizes depend on the random
variable Y (t). If S(t) is an asset price, these jump events can be thought of as
times when important information aecting the value of the asset is released.
gives an excellent review of univariate and multivariate specifications for jumpdiusion models.
univariate models.2
11.2
315
dc
cs [ ( k)S dt + S dz ] +
1
css 2 S 2 dt + ct dt
2
(11.5)
on the right-hand-side of equation (11.5) is the standard form for Its lemma
when S (t) is restricted to following a diusion process.
what is new. It states that when S jumps, the contingent claims value has a
corresponding jump and moves from c(S, t) to c ([1 + (Y )] S, t). Now define
c dt as the instantaneous expected rate of return on c per unit time, that is,
E[dc/c].
equation (11.5) as
dc/c = [c kc (t)] dt + c dz + c (Y ) dq
(11.6)
where
1
1
2 2
cs ( k) S + css S + ct + kc (t)
c
2
cs
S
c
(11.7)
(11.8)
(11.9)
(11.10)
Here, kc (t) is the expected proportional jump of the variable c (S, t) given that
a Poisson event occurs. In general, kc (t) is time varying. Let us now apply
these results to valuing a contingent claim that depends on an asset whose price
316
11.3
For simplicity,
the analysis that follows assumes that is constant over time and that (Y ) =
(Y 1) . Thus, if a jump occurs, the discontinuous change in S is dS = (Y 1)S.
+
t =YS b
t , where b
t is the date of the jump.
In other words, S b
t goes to S b
It is also assumed that successive random jump sizes, (Ye 1), are independently
and identically distributed.
S(t)
= S(0) e( 2 k) t + (hzt z0 ) y(n)
(11.11)
where zt z0 N (0, t) is the change in the Brownian motion process from date
0 to date t. Jump uncertainty is reflected in the random variable ye (n), where
n
Y
Yi for n 1 where {Yi }ni=1 is a set of independent
y(0) = 1 and y(n) =
i=1
317
the underlying assets price follows the jump-diusion process given in equation
(11.1) with (Y ) = (Y 1). Furthermore, assume the risk-free interest rate
is a constant equal to r per unit time. Denote the proportions of the portfolio
invested in the underlying asset, contingent claim, and risk-free asset as 1 , 2 ,
and 3 = 1 1 2 , respectively. The instantaneous rate of return on this
portfolio, denoted dH/H, is given by:
dH/H
1 dS/S + 2 dc/c + (1 1 2 )r dt
[ 1 ( r) + 2 (c r) + r (1 k + 2 kc ) ] dt
(11.12)
+ ( 1 + 2 c ) dz + [ 1 (Y ) + 2 c (Y )] dq
11.3.1
An Imperfect Hedge
the contingent claim, that is, jump risk is perfectly dependent for these two
securities, these risks are not necessarily linearly dependent. This is because
the contingent claim price, c(S, t), is, in general, a nonlinear function of the
asset price.
(Y 1) is random, the ratio between the size of the jump in S and the size
of the jump in c, which is Ye / c Ye is unpredictable. Hence, a pre-
determined hedge ratio, 1 /2 , that would eliminate all portfolio risk does not
exist.4
claims payo by a portfolio composed of the underlying asset and the risk-free
4 If the size of the jump is deterministic, a hedge that eliminates jump risk is possible.
Alternatively, Phillip Jones (Jones 1984) shows that if the underlying assets jump size has a
discrete (finite state) distribution, and a sucient number of dierent contingent claims are
written on this asset, a hedge portfolio that combines the underlying asset and these multiple
contingent claims could also eliminate jump risk.
318
asset. In this sense, the market for the contingent claim is incomplete.
Instead, suppose we pick 1 and 2 to eliminate only the risk from the continuous Brownian motion movements. This Black-Scholes hedge implies setting
1 / 2 = c / = cs S/c from our definition of c . This leads to the process
for the value of the portfolio:
dH/H
[ 1 ( r) + 2 (c r) + r ( 1 k + 2 kc )] dt
+ [ 1 (Y ) + 2 c (Y )] dq
(11.13)
The return on this portfolio is a pure jump process. The return is deterministic,
except when jumps occur. Using the definitions of , c , and 1 = 2 cs S/c,
we see that the portfolio jump term, [ 1 (Y ) + 2 c (Y )] dq, equals
h
i
(11.14)
otherwise
Now consider the case when the contingent claim is a European option on a
stock with a time until expiration of and a strike price X.
What would
We can
answer this question by noting that if the rate of return on the underlying asset
is independent of its price level, as is the case in (11.1), then the absence of
arbitrage restricts the option price to be a convex function of the asset price.5
The options convexity implies that c(SY, t) c(S, t) cs (S, t)[SY S] 0 for
all Y and t. This is illustrated in Figure 11.1 where the convex solid line gives
the value of a call option as a function of its underlying assets price.
From this fact and (11.14), we see that the unanticipated return on the
hedge portfolio has the same sign as 2 . This means that 1 k + 2 kc , the
5 For a proof, see Theorem 8.10 in Chapter 8 of Robert Merton (Merton 1992) which
reproduces (Merton 1973b).
319
Option
Price
c(SY)
c S[SY-S]
c(S)
S
Xe -r
SY
Asset Price
Therefore,
an option writer who follows this Black-Scholes hedge by being short the option
( 2 < 0) and long the underlying asset earns, most of the time, more than the
portfolios expected rate of return. However, on those rare occasions when the
underlying asset price jumps, a relatively large loss is incurred. Thus in quiet
times, option writers appear to make positive excess returns. However, during
infrequent active times, option writers suer large losses.
11.3.2
Since the hedge portfolio is not riskless, but is exposed to jump risk, we cannot
use the previous no-arbitrage argument to equate the hedge portfolios rate of
return to the risk-free rate. The hedge portfolio is exposed to jump risk, and, in
general, there may be a market price to such risk. One assumption might be
that this jump risk is the result of purely firm specific information and, hence,
the jump risk is perfectly diversifiable.
320
price of jump risk is zero. In this case, all of the risk of the hedge portfolio is
diversifiable, so that its expected rate of return must equal the risk-free rate, r.
Making this assumption implies
1 ( r) + 2 (c r) + r = r
(11.15)
1 / 2 = c / = (c r)/( r)
(11.16)
or
Now denote T as the maturity date of the contingent claim, and let us use the
time until maturity T t as the second argument for c (S, ) rather than
calendar time, t. Hence, c (S, ) is the price of the contingent claim when the
current asset price is S and the time until maturity of the contingent claim is .
With this redefinition, note that c = ct . Using (11.16) and substituting in
for c and c from the definitions (11.7) and (11.8), we obtain the equilibrium
partial dierential equation
h
i
1 2 2
S css + (r k)Scs c rc + Et c(S Y , ) c(S, ) = 0 (11.17)
2
For a call option, this is solved subject to the boundary conditions c(0, ) = 0
and c(S (T ) , 0) = max[S (T ) X, 0]. Note that when = 0, equation (11.17)
is the standard Black-Scholes equation which we know has the solution
(11.18)
c(S, ) =
e ( )n
Et b(S y(n) ek , , X, 2 , r)
n!
n=0
(11.19)
n
Y
i=1
321
e ( )n
n!
11.3.3
n=0
(11.20)
where g( | n) is the conditional density function given that n jumps occur during
the interval between t and t + , and h(n) is the probability that n jumps occur
between t and t + . The values of these expressions are
6 Recall that since the drift is k, and risk-neutral valuation sets = r, then k is like
a dividend yield. Hence b(Se k , , X, 2 , r) is the Black-Scholes formula for an asset with
a dividend yield of k.
322
S (t + )
g ln
|n
S(t)
h (n)
exp
2
2
)
n
n
ln[ S(t+
S(t) ] k+ 2
e ()n
n!
2 2n
p
2 2n
(11.21)
(11.22)
Et [ b(S y(n)e k , , X, 2 , r) ]
= e k (1 + k)n b(S, , X, 2n , rn )
= e k (1 + k)n bn (S, )
(11.23)
c(S, )
=
=
11.3.4
X
e ( )n k
e
(1 + k)n bn (S, )
n!
n=0
0
X
e (0 )n
bn (S, )
n!
n=0
(11.24)
323
11.3.5
Having derived a model for pricing options written on an underlying asset whose
price follows a jump-diusion process, the natural question to ask is whether this
makes any dierence vis-a-vis the Black-Scholes option pricing model which does
not permit the underlyings price to jump. The answer is yes, and the jump-
324
diusion model appears to better fit the actual prices of many options written
on stocks, stock indices, and foreign exchange. In most types of options, the
Black-Scholes model underprices out-of-the money and in-the-money options
relative to at-the-money-options. What this means is that the prices of actual
options whose exercise price is substantially dierent from the current price of
the underlying are priced higher than the theoretical Black-Scholes price while
the prices of actual options whose exercise price is close to the current price of
the underlying are priced lower than the theoretical Black-Scholes price. This
phenomenon has been described as a volatility smile or volatility smirk.7
This empirical deficiency can be traced to the Black-Scholes models assumption that the underlyings terminal price has a risk-neutral distribution
that is lognormal.
lief that the risk-neutral distribution has much fatter "tails" than those of the
lognormal distribution. In other words, investors price securities as if they believe that extreme asset prices are more likely than what would be predicted by
a lognormal distribution because actual in- and out-of-the-money options are
priced relatively high versus the Black-Scholes theoretical prices. A model that
permits the underlying assets price to jump, with jumps possibly being both
positive and negative, can generate a distribution for the assets price that has
fatter tails than the lognormal. The possibility of jumps makes extreme price
changes more likely and, indeed, the jump-diusion option pricing model can
7 Note that if the Black-Scholes model correctly priced all options having the same maturity
date and the same underlying asset but dierent exercise prices, there would be one volatility
parameter, , consistent with all of these options. However, the implied volatilities, , needed
to fit in- and, especially, out-of the money call options are greater than the volatility parameter
needed to fit at-the-money options. Hence, when implied volatility is graphed versus call
options exercise prices, it forms an inverted hump or "smile," or, in the case of equity index
options, a downward sloping curve or "smirk." These characteristics of option prices are
equivalent to the Black-Scholes model giving relatively low prices for in- and out-of-the-money
options because options prices are increasing functions of the underlyings volatility, . The
Black-Scholes model needs relatively high estimated volatility for in- and out-of-the-money
options versus at-the-money options. If a (theoretically correct) single volatility parameter
was used for all options, in- and out-of-the-money options would be relatively underpriced by
the model. See Hull (Hull 2000) for a review of this issue.
11.4. SUMMARY
325
ters implied by actual option prices change over time and appear to follow a
mean-reverting stochastic process. To account for this empirical time variation,
stochastic volatility option pricing models have been developed. These models
start by assuming that the underlying asset price follows a diusion process such
as dS/S = dt + dz but where the volatility, , is stochastic. The volatility
follows a mean reverting process of the form d = () dt + () dz where
dz is another Brownian motion process possibly correlated with dz. Similar
to the jump-diusion model, one must assign a market price of risk associated
with the volatility uncertainty reflected in the dz term.8
While stochastic volatility option pricing models also produce fatter-tailed
distributions relative to the lognormal, empirically these distributions do not
tend to be fat enough to explain volatility smiles and smirks. To capture both
time variation in volatilities and cross-sectional dierences in volatility due to
dierent degrees of "moneyness" (volatility smiles or smirks), it appears that
an option pricing model that allows for both stochastic volatility and jumps
is required.9 For recent reviews of the empirical option pricing literature, see
(Bates 2002) and (Bakshi, Cao, and Chen 1997).
11.4
Summary
Allowing for the possibility of discontinuous movements can add realism to the
modeling of asset prices.
326
corporate merger. While the mixed jump-diusion process captures such asset
price dynamics, it complicates the valuation of contingent claims written on
such an asset. In general, we showed that the contingent claims payo cannot
be perfectly replicated by a dynamic trading strategy involving the underlying
asset and risk-free asset. In this situation of market incompleteness, additional
theory that assigns a market risk premium to jump risk is required to determine
the contingent claims value.
The additional complications in deriving jump-diusion models of option
pricing appear worthwhile. Because jumps increase the likelihood of extreme
price movements, they generate a risk-neutral distribution of asset prices whose
tails are fatter than the Black-Scholes models lognormal distribution. Since the
actual prices of many types of options appear to reflect significant probabilities
of extreme movements in the underlyings price, the jump-diusion model has
better empirical performance.
Having seen that pricing contingent claims sometimes requires specifying
market prices of risk, the following chapters turn to the subject of deriving
equilibrium risk premia for assets in continuous time economies.
As a pre-
11.5
Exercises
1. Verify that (11.11) holds by using Its lemma to find the process followed
by ln (S (t)).
11.5. EXERCISES
327
2. Let S (t) be the U.S. dollar price of a stock. It is assumed to follow the
process
dS/S = [s k] dt + s dzs + Ye dq
(*)
foreign exchange rate between U.S. dollars and Japanese yen, denominated
as U.S. dollars per yen. F follows the process
dF/F = f dt + f dzf
where dzs dzf = dt. Define x (t) as the Japanese yen price of the stock
whose U.S. dollar price follows the process in (*). Derive the stochastic
process followed by x (t).
3. Suppose that the instantaneous-maturity, default-free interest rate follows
the jump-diusion process
dr(t) = [ r(t)] dt + dz + r (Y ) dq
where dz is a standard Wiener process and q (t) is a Poisson counting process
having the arrival rate of dt. The arrival of jumps is assumed to be independent
of the Wiener process, dz. (Y ) = (Y 1) where Y > 1 is a known positive
constant.
3.a Define P (r, ) as the price of a default-free discount bond that pays $1
in periods. Using Its lemma for the case of jump-diusion processes,
write down the process followed by dP (r, ).
328
3.b Assume that the market price of jump risk is zero, but that the market
price of Brownian motion (dz) risk is given by , so that = [p r(t)] /p ,
where p (r, ) is the expected rate of return on the bond and p ( ) is
the standard deviation of the bonds rate of return from Brownian motion
risk (not including the risk from jumps). Derive the equilibrium partial
dierential equation that the value P (r, ) must satisfy.
4. Suppose that a securitys price follows a jump-diusion process and yields
a continuous dividend at a constant rate of dt. For example, its price,
S (t), follows the process
dS/S = [ (S, t) k ] dt + (S, t) dz + Ye dq
continuously in the security, derive the equilibrium date t forward price using
an argument that rules out arbitrage. (Hint: Some information in this problem
is extraneous. The solution is relatively simple.)
Part IV
Asset Pricing in Continuous Time
Chapter 12
Continuous Time
Consumption and Portfolio
Choice
Until now, our applications of continuous time stochastic processes have focused
on the valuation of contingent claims. We now re-consider the topic introduced
in Chapter 5, namely, an individuals intertemporal consumption and portfolio choice problem.
now examine this problem where asset prices are subject to continuous, random
changes and an individual can adjust consumption and portfolio allocations at
any time.
time-separable expected utility function that depends on the rate of consumption at all future dates.
assets whose prices follow the sorts of continuous time stochastic processes first
introduced in Chapter 8. Hence, in this environment, the values of the individ325
326
uals portfolio holdings and total wealth change constantly and, in general, it is
optimal for the individual to make continuous re-balancing decisions.
The continuous time consumption and portfolio choice problem described
above was formulated and solved in two papers by Robert Merton (Merton 1969)
and (Merton 1971). This work was the foundation of his model of intertemporal asset pricing (Merton 1973a) that we will study in the next chapter. As is
discussed below, allowing individuals to rebalance their portfolios continuously
can lead to qualitatively dierent portfolio choices compared to restricting rebalancing to only discrete dates. This, in turn, means that the asset pricing
implications of individuals decisions in continuous time can dier from those
of a discrete time model.
namically complete and lead to sharper asset pricing results. For this reason,
continuous time consumption and portfolio choice models are often used in financial research on asset pricing. Much of our analysis in later chapters will
be based on such models.
By studying consumption and portfolio choices in continuous time, the eects
of time variation in assets return distributions, that is, changing investment
opportunities, become transparent.
choices include demands for assets that are the same as those derived from
the single period mean-variance analysis of Chapter 2.
However, portfolio
choices also include demands for assets that hedge against changes in investment
opportunities. This is a key insight which dierentiates single-period and multiperiod models and has implications for equilibrium asset pricing.
The next section outlines the assumptions of an individuals consumption
and portfolio choice problem for a continuous time environment.
Then, sim-
ilar to what was done in solving for an individuals decisions in discrete time,
we introduce and apply a continuous time version of stochastic dynamic pro-
327
This al-
12.1
Model Assumptions
at date t, and Si (t) as the price of risky asset i at date t, where i = 1, ..., n.
The instantaneous rate of return on the ith risky asset is assumed to satisfy the
process
dSi (t) / Si (t) = i (x, t) dt + i (x, t) dzi
where i = 1, ..., n, and (i dzi )(j dzj ) = ij dt.
(12.1)
instantaneous risk-free return as r (x, t). For simplicity, risky assets are assumed
to pay no cashflows (dividends or coupon payments), so that their total returns
are given by their price changes.1
328
(12.2)
dW
=
=
"
n
X
i=1
n
X
i=1
i dSi /Si + 1
n
X
i=1
! #
i r W Cdt
i (i r)W dt + (rW C) dt +
n
X
(12.3)
i W i dzi
i=1
max
Cs ,{ i,s },s,i
Et
"Z
U (Cs , s) ds + B(WT , T )
(12.4)
329
individual has time-separable utility of consumption, is analogous to the discrete time problem studied in Chapter 5. The variables Ws and x (s) are the
date s state variables while the individual chooses the control variables Cs and
i (s), i = 1, ..., n, at each date s over the interval from dates t to T .
Note that some possible constraints have not been imposed. For example,
one might wish to impose the constraint Ct 0 (nonnegative consumption)
and/or i 0 (no short sales). However, for some utility functions, negative
consumption is never optimal, so that solutions satisfying Ct 0 would result
even without the constraint.3
Before we attempt to solve this problem, lets digress to consider how stochastic dynamic programing applies to a continuous time setting.
12.2
max Et
{c}
"Z
U (cs , xs ) ds
(12.5)
subject to
dx = a(x, c) dt + b(x, c) dz
(12.6)
example, if lim
Ct 0
U (Ct ,t)
Ct
displayed constant relative risk aversion (power utility), then the individual would always
avoid non-positive consumption. However, other utility functions, such as constant absoute
risk aversion (negative exponential) utility, do not display this property.
330
changes investment opportunities, that is, a variable that aects the i s and/or
i s). Define the indirect utility function, J(xt , t), as
J(xt , t)
= max Et
{c}
"Z
U (cs , xs ) ds
= max Et
{c}
"Z
t+t
U(cs , xs ) ds +
(12.7)
Z
U(cs , xs ) ds .
t+t
Now let us apply Bellmans Principle of Optimality. Recall that this concept
says that an optimal policy must be such that for a given future realization of
the state variable, xt+t , (whose value may be aected by the optimal control
policy at date t and earlier), any remaining decisions at date t + t and later
must be optimal with respect to xt+t . In other words, an optimal policy must
be time consistent. This allows us to write
J(xt , t) = max Et
{c}
max Et
{c}
"Z
t+t
"Z
t+t
"Z
##
U (cs , xs ) ds
t+t
U (cs , xs ) ds + J(xt+t , t + t) .
(12.8)
Now think of t as a short interval of time and approximate the first integral
as U (ct , xt ) t. Also expand J(xt+t , t + t) around the points xt and t in a
Taylor series to get
J(xt , t)
(12.9)
1
1
+ Jxx (x)2 + Jxt (x)(t) + Jtt (t)2 + o(t)
2
2
{c}
331
y(t)
t0 t
where o (t) represents higher order terms, say y (t), where lim
= 0.
(12.10)
te
and e
N (0, 1). Substituting (12.10) into (12.9), and sub-
where
J =
1
Jt + Jx a + Jxx b2 t + Jx bz.
2
(12.11)
(12.12)
Next, note
that in equation (12.11) the term Et [Jx bz] = 0 and then divide both sides of
(12.11) by t. Finally, take the limit as t 0 to obtain
1
0 = max U (ct , xt ) + Jt + Jx a + Jxx b2
{c}
2
(12.13)
(12.14)
where L[] is the Dynkin operator. This operator is the drift term (expected
change per unit time) in dJ(x, t) that one obtains by applying Its Lemma to
J(x, t).
stochastic control policy, ct , must satisfy. Let us now return to the complete
consumption and portfolio choice problem and apply this solution technique.
332
12.3
J(W, x, t) =
max
Cs ,{ i,s },s,i
Et
"Z
U (Cs , s) ds + B(WT , T )
(12.15)
and define L as the Dynkin operator with respect to the state variables W and
xi , i = 1, . . . , k. In other words
L [J]
J
+
t
+
"
n
X
i=1
n
n
1 XX
i (i r)W + (rW C)
k
ij i j W 2
i=1 j=1
k X
n
X
+
W i ij
j=1 i=1
k
X
J
J
+
ai
W
xi
i=1
1 XX
2J
2J
+
b
ij
W 2
2 i=1 j=1 xi xj
2J
W xj
(12.16)
0 =
Ct ,{ i,t }
(12.17)
Given the concavity of U and B, equation (12.17) implies that the optimal
choices of Ct and i,t satisfy the conditions we obtain from dierentiating
U (Ct , t) + L[J] and setting the result equal to zero. Hence, the first order
conditions are:
0 =
0 =
J (W, x, t)
U (C , t)
C
W
(12.18)
n
k
J
2J X
2J X
2
(i r)W +
W
+
W ij , i = 1, . . . , n
ij
j
W
W 2 j=1
xi W j=1
(12.19)
333
Equation (12.18) is the envelope condition that we earlier derived in a discrete time framework as equation (5.20) while equation (12.19) has the discrete time analogue (5.21).
1
G = [U/C]
C = G (JW , t)
(12.20)
Denote
i =
JW
JW W W
n
X
j=1
ij (j r)
n
k X
X
JW xm
ij , i = 1, . . . , n (12.21)
J
W jm
m=1 j=1 W W
334
12.3.1
Let us consider the special case for which asset prices are lognormally distributed, that is, all of the i s (including r) and i s are constants.5 This means
that each assets expected rate of return and variance of its rate of return do
not change; there is a constant investment opportunity set. Hence, investment
and portfolio choice decisions are independent of the state variables, x, since
they do not aect U , B, the i s, or the i s. The only state variable aecting
consumption and portfolio choice decisions is wealth, W .
above analysis, since now the indirect utility function J depends only on W and
t, but not x.
For this constant investment opportunity set case, the optimal portfolio
weights in (12.21) simplify to:
JW
JW W W
n
X
j=1
ij (j r), i = 1, . . . , n.
(12.22)
Plugging (12.20) and (12.22) back into the optimality equation (12.17), and
using the fact that [ ij ] 1 , we have
0 = U (G, t) + Jt + JW (rW G)
n
n X
2
X
JW
ij (i r)(j r). (12.23)
2JW W i=1 j=1
The non-linear partial dierential equation (12.23) may not have an analytic
solution for an arbitrary utility function, U. However, we can still draw some
conclusions about the individuals investment behavior by looking at equation
(12.22).
Talay 1997).
5 Recall that if and are constants, then dS /S follows geometric Brownian motion and
i
i
i
i
1 2
Si (t) = Si (0) e(i 2 i )t+ i (zi (t)zi (0)) is lognormally distributed over any discrete period
since zi (t)zi (0) N (0, t). Therefore, the return on a unit initial investment over this period,
1 2
distributed.
The continuouslySi (t) /Si (0) = e(i 2 i )t+ i (zi (t)zi (0)) , is also lognormally
compounded rate of return, equal to ln [Si (t) /Si (0)] = i 12 2i t + i (zi (t) zi (0)) is
normally distributed.
335
i
j=1
= n
X
k
j=1
ij (j r)
(12.24)
kj (j r)
k = Pn
i=1 i
n
X
kj (j
j=1
n X
n
X
i=1 j=1
r)
.
(12.25)
ij (j r)
This means that each individual, no matter what her utility function, allocates
her portfolio between the risk-free asset, paying return r, and a portfolio of
the risky assets that holds the n risky assets in constant proportions, given by
(12.25).
Hence, two mutual funds, one holding only the the risk-free asset
and the other holding a risky asset portfolio with the weights in (12.25) would
satisfy all investors. Only the investors preferences, current level of wealth, Wt ,
and the investors time horizon determine the amounts allocated to the risk-free
fund and the risky one.
The implication is that with a constant investment opportunity set, one can
think of the investment decision as being just a two-asset decision, where the
choice is between the risk-free asset paying rate of return r and a risky asset
336
n
X
i i
i=1
n X
n
X
(12.26)
i j ij .
i=1 j=1
These results are reminiscent of those derived from the single period meanvariance analysis of Chapter 2. In fact, the relative asset proportions given in
(12.24) and (12.25) are exactly the same as those implied by the single period
mean-variance portfolio proportions given in (2.42).6 The instantaneous means
and covariances for the continuous time asset price processes simply replace the
previous means and covariances of the single period multi-variate normal asset
returns distribution.
ecient frontier, where the tangency portfolio is given by the weights in (12.25).
But what is dierent in this continuous time analysis is the assumption regarding
the distribution in asset prices.
Sn
j=1
ij Rj Rf , which
337
essentially a very short one, that is the "period" is instantaneous. Since diusion processes can be thought of as being instantaneously (locally) normally distributed, our continuous-time environment is as if the individual faces a infinite
sequence of similar short portfolio selection periods with normally distributed
asset returns.
Lets now look at a special case of the above general solution. Specifically,
we assume that utility is of the hyperbolic absolute risk aversion (HARA) class.
HARA Utility
U (C, t) = et
C
+
1
(12.27)
and that this class of utility nests power (constant relative risk-aversion) utility,
exponential (constant absolute risk aversion), and quadratic utility. Robert C.
Merton (Merton 1971) derived explicit solutions for this class of utility functions.
With HARA utility, optimal consumption given in equation (12.20) becomes
1
1 et JW 1
(1 )
=
(12.28)
and using (12.22) and (12.26), the proportion put in the risky asset portfolio is
JW r
.
JW W W 2
(12.29)
338
(12.23) to obtain
(1 )2 t et JW 1
e
+ Jt
2
(1 )
JW
( r)2
+ rW JW
+
.
JW W 22
(12.30)
This is the partial dierential equation for J that can be solved subject to
a boundary condition for J(W, T ).
The
It is
interesting to note that for this class of HARA utility, C is of the form
Ct = aWt + b
(12.31)
and
t = g +
h
Wt
(12.32)
where a, b, g, and h are, at most, functions of time. For the special case of
constant relative risk aversion where U (C, t) = et C /, the solution is
J (W, t) = e
Ct =
1 ea(T t)
a
a
ea(T t)
Wt
W /
(12.33)
(12.34)
and
=
r
(1 ) 2
(12.35)
(r)2
2(1)2
339
i
. Note that the individuals optimal portfolio
weight for the risky asset is independent of the time horizon, T , and declines as
risk aversion increases ( becomes more negative). For the case of an infinite
horizon, a solution exists only if a > 0. In this case we can see that by taking
the limit at T becomes infinite J (W, t) = et a1 W / and consumption is a
constant proportion of wealth, Ct = aWt .
12.3.2
Next, let us generalize the individuals consumption and portfolio choice problem
by considering the eects of changing investment opportunities. To keep the
analysis fairly simple, assume that there is a single state variable, x. That is,
let k = 1 so that x is a scalar.
process as
dx = a (x, t) dt + b (x, t) d
(12.36)
where b d i dzi = i dt. This allows us to write the optimal portfolio weights
in (12.21) as:
i =
n
n
JW X
JW x X
ij j r
ij j , i = 1, . . . , n
W JW W j=1
W JW W j=1
(12.37)
A 1
H 1
( re) +
W
W
(12.38)
where = ( 1 ... n )0 is the n1 vector of portfolio weights for the n risky assets,
= (1 ...n )0 is the n 1 vector of these assets expected rates of return, e is an
n-dimensional vector of ones, = (1 , ..., n )0 , A = JJWWW , and H = JJWWWx .
340
We will use bold type to denote vector or matrix variables, while normal type
is used for scalar variables.
Note that A and H will, in general, dier from one individual to another,
depending on the form of the particular individuals utility function and level
of wealth. Thus, unlike in the constant investment opportunity set case (where
JW x = H = 0), i /j is not the same for all investors, that is, a Two Mutual
Fund Theorem does not hold. However, with one state variable, x, a Three-Fund
Theorem does hold. Investors will be satisfied choosing between a fund holding
only the risk-free asset, a second fund of risky assets that provides optimal
instantaneous diversification, and a third fund composed of a portfolio of the
risky assets that has the maximum absolute correlation with the state variable,
x.
The portfolio weights of the second fund are 1 ( re) and are the
same ones representing the mean-variance ecient tangency portfolio that were
derived for the case of constant investment opportunities. The portfolio weights
for the third fund are 1 .
equation (2.64), which are the hedging demands derived in Chapter 2s crosshedging example.
of changes in the state variable on the returns of the risky assets. A/W and
H/W , which depend on the individuals preferences, then determine the relative
amounts that the individual invests in the second and third risky portfolios.
To gain more insight regarding the nature of the individuals portfolio holdings, recall the envelope condition JW = UC , which allows us to write JW W =
UCC C/W . Therefore, A can be re-written as
A=
UC
>0
UCC (C/W )
(12.39)
H=
C/x
R0
C/W
341
(12.40)
Now the first vector of terms on the right-hand side of (12.38) is the usual
demand functions for risky assets chosen by a single-period mean-variance utility
maximizer. Since A is proportional to the reciprocal of the individuals absolute
risk aversion, we see that the more risk averse is the individual, the smaller is
A and the smaller in magnitude is the individuals demand for any risky asset.
The second vector of terms on the right-hand side of (12.38) captures the
individuals desire to hedge against "unfavorable" shifts in investment opportunities that would reduce optimal consumption. An unfavorable shift is defined
as a change in x such that consumption falls for a given level of current wealth,
that is, an increase in x if C/x < 0 and a decrease in x if C/x > 0. For
example, suppose that is a diagonal matrix, so that ij = 0 for i 6= j, and
ii = 1/ii > 0, and also assume that i 6= 0.7 Then in this special case the
hedging demand term for risky asset i in (12.38) simplifies to
H ii i =
C/x
C
ii i > 0 i
<0
C/W
x i
(12.41)
342
(C/W > 0). Hence, the individuals optimal portfolio holdings are designed
to reduce fluctuations in consumption over his planning horizon.
Let us continue to assume that there is a single state variable aecting investment opportunities, but now also specify that the individual have logarithmic utility and a logarithmic bequest function, so that in (12.15) U (Cs , s) =
es ln (Cs ) and B (WT , T ) = eT ln (WT ). Logarithmic utility is one of the
few cases in which analytical solutions for consumption and portfolio choices
can be obtained when investment opportunities are changing.
To derive the
solution to (12.17) for log utility, let us consider a "trial" solution for the
indirect utility function of the form J (W, x, t) = d (t) U (Wt , t) + F (x, t) =
d (t) et ln (Wt ) + F (x, t). Then optimal consumption in (12.20) would be
Ct =
Wt
d (t)
(12.42)
and the first order conditions for the portfolio weights (12.37) simplify to
i =
n
X
j=1
ij j r
(12.43)
343
1
JW
+ b (x, t)2 Jxx +
ij j r (i r)
2
2JW W i=1 j=1
Wt
t
t d (t)
d (t) ln [Wt ] + Ft + et d (t) r et
ln
= e
+e
d (t)
t
n
n
1
d (t) et X X
+a (x, t) Fx + b (x, t)2 Fxx
ij j r (i r)
2
2
i=1 j=1
(12.44)
or
d (t)
d (t) ln [Wt ] + et Ft + d (t) r 1
0 = ln [d (t)] + 1 +
t
n
n
1
d (t) X X
2
ij j r (i r)
+a (x, t) et Fx + b (x, t) et Fxx
2
2 i=1 j=1
(12.45)
Note that a solution to this equation must hold for all values of wealth. Hence,
it must be the case that
d (t)
d (t) + 1 = 0
t
(12.46)
d (t) =
i
1h
1 (1 ) e(T t)
(12.47)
344
1
d (t) X X
+ b (x, t)2 et Fxx
ij j r (i r)
2
2 i=1 j=1
(12.48)
are made regarding these variables relationships to the state variable x, they
will influence only the level of indirect utility via the value of F (x, t) and will
not change the form of the optimal consumption and portfolio rules. Thus, this
verifies that our trial solution is, indeed, a valid form for the solution to the
individuals problem. Substituting (12.47) into (12.42), consumption satisfies
Ct =
Wt
1 (1 ) e(T t)
(12.49)
which is the continuous time counterpart to the log utility investors optimal
consumption that we derived for the discrete time problem in Chapter 5, equation (5.34). Note, also, that the log utility investors optimal portfolio weights
given in (12.43) are of the same form as in the case of a constant investment
opportunity set, equation (12.35) with = 0. The log utility investor may be
described as behaving "myopically" in that, similar to the discrete time case,
she has no desire to hedge against changes in investment opportunities.8 However, note that even with log utility, a dierence from the constant investment
opportunity set case is that since r, the i s, and depend, in general, on the
constantly changing state variable xt , the portfolio weights in equation (12.43)
8 The portfolio weights for the discrete time case are given by (5.35). As discussed earlier,
the log utility investor acts myopically because income and substitution eects from changing
investment opportunities exactly cancel for this individual.
345
12.4
346
12.4.1
As before, let there be n risky assets and a risk-free asset which has an instantaneous return r (t).
(12.50)
i , the elements of i , and r (t) may be functions of state variables driven by the
Brownian motion elements of dZ. Further, we assume that the n risky assets
are non-redundant in the sense that their instantaneous covariance matrix is
non-singular. Specifically, if we let be the n n matrix whose ith row equals
i , then the instantaneous covariance matrix of the assets returns, 0 ,
has rank equal to n.
Importantly, we are assuming that any uncertain changes in the means and
covariances of the asset return processes in (12.50) are driven only by the vector
dZ.
hedged by the n assets, and such an assumption makes this market dynamically
complete. This diers from the assumptions of (12.1) and (12.2) because we
exclude state variables driven by other, arbitrary Brownian motion processes,
d i , that cannot be perfectly hedged by the n assets returns. Equivalently, if
we assume there is a state variable aecting asset returns, say xi as represented
10 Note
that in (12.50), the independent Brownian motion components of dZ, dzi , i = 1, ..., n
are dierent from the possibly correlated Brownian motion processes dzi defined in (12.1).
Accordingly, the return on asset i in (12.50) depends on all n of the independent Brownian
motion processes while the return on asset i in (12.1) depends on only one of the correlated
Brownian motion processes, namely, the ith one, dzi . These dierent ways of writting the
risky asset returns are not important because an orthogonal transformation of the n correlated
Brownian motion processes in (12.1) can allow us to write asset returns as (12.50) where each
asset return depends on all n independent processes. The reason for writing asset returns as
(12.50) is that individual market prices of risk can be identified with each of the independent
risk sources.
347
(12.51)
0
where = (1 ... n ) is an n 1 vector of market prices of risks associated with
i r = i , i = 1, ..., n
(12.52)
Notice that if we take the form of the assets expected rate of returns and
volatilities as given, then equation (12.52) is a system of n linear equations that
determine the n market prices of risk, . Alternatively, if and the assets
volatilities are taken as given, (12.52) determines the assets expected rates of
return.
12.4.2
Now consider the individuals original consumption and portfolio choice problem
in (12.4), (12.3), and (??).
348
pays over the individuals planning horizon plus discounted terminal wealth.
Wt = Et
"Z
MT
Ms
Cs ds +
WT
Mt
Mt
(12.53)
max
Cs s[t,T ],WT
Et
"Z
U (Cs , s) ds + B (WT , T )
t
+ Mt Wt Et
"Z
Ms Cs ds + MT WT
#!
(12.54)
Note that the problem in (12.54) does not explicitly address the portfolio choice
decision.
U (Cs , s)
= Ms ,
Cs
s [t, T ]
B (WT , T )
= MT
WT
(12.55)
(12.56)
Similar to what we did earlier, define the inverse marginal utility function as
G = [U/C]1 and the inverse marginal utility of bequest function GB =
349
Cs = G (Ms , s) ,
s [t, T ]
WT = GB (MT , T )
(12.57)
(12.58)
Wt = Et
"Z
#
MT
Ms
G (Ms , s) ds +
GB (MT , T )
Mt
Mt
(12.59)
As demonstrated in Chapter
10, since wealth represents an asset or contingent claim that pays a dividend
equal to consumption, Wt must satisfy a particular Black-Scholes-Merton partial
dierential equation (PDE) similar to equation (10.7). The equivalence of the
stochastic discount factor relationship in (12.59) and this PDE solution was
shown to be a result of the assumptions of market completeness and an absence
of arbitrage.
To derive the PDE corresponding to (12.59), let us assume, for simplicity,
350
that there is a single state variable that aects the distribution of asset returns.
That is, i , the elements of i , and r (t) may be functions of a single state
variable, say xt . This state variable follows the process
(12.60)
W (Mt , xt , t) satisfies
dW
1
W
dt + WMM (dM)2
t
2
1
+WMx (dM ) (dx) + Wxx (dx)2
2
= WM dM + Wx dx +
= W dt + 0W dZ
(12.61)
where
W rM WM + aWx +
1
W
1
+ 0 M 2 WMM 0 BM WMx + B0 BWxx
t
2
2
(12.62)
and
W WM M + Wx B
(12.63)
Following the arguments of Black and Scholes in Chapter 10, the expected
return on wealth must earn the instantaneous risk-free rate plus a risk premium,
11 This is because the expectation in (12.59) depends on the distribution of future values of
the pricing kernel. From (12.51) and (12.52), the distribution clearly depends on its initial
level, Mt , but also on r and which can vary with the state variable x.
351
where this risk premium equals the market prices of risk times the sensitivities
(volatilities) of wealth to these sources of risk. Specifically,
W + G (Mt , t) = rWt + 0W
(12.64)
Wealths expected return, given by the left-hand side of (12.64) equals the expected change in wealth plus its consumption dividend. Substituting in for W
and 0W leads to the PDE
0 =
1
1 0
M 2 WMM 0 BM WMx + B0 BWxx + (0 r) M WM
2
2
W
0
+ G (Mt , t) rW
+ (a B ) Wx +
(12.65)
t
which is solved subject to the boundary condition that terminal wealth is optimal given the bequest motive, that is, W (MT , xT , T ) = GB (MT , T ). Because
this PDE is linear, as opposed to the non-linear PDE for the indirect utility function, J (W, x, t), that results from the dynamic programming approach, it may
be relatively easy to solve, either analytically or numerically.
352
12.4.3
The final step is to derive the portfolio allocation policy that finances these
consumption and terminal wealth rules.
process for wealth in (12.61) to the dynamics of wealth where the portfolio
weights in the n risky assets are explicitly represented. Based on the assumed
dynamics of asset returns in (12.50), equation (12.3) is
dW
n
X
i=1
0
i (i r)W dt + (rW Ct ) dt +
n
X
i i dZ
i=1
0
= ( re) W dt + (rW Ct ) dt + W dZ
(12.66)
return.
0
wealth processes in (12.66) and (12.61), we obtain W 0 = W . Substituting
Wx 0 1
M WM 0 1
+
B
W
W
(12.67)
Next, recall equation (12.52), and note that it can be written in the following
matrix form
re =
(12.68)
M WM 1 0 1
Wx 0 1
( re) +
B
W
W
Wx 0 1
M WM 1
( re) +
B
=
W
W
=
(12.69)
353
These optimal portfolio weights are of the same form as what was derived earlier
in (12.38) for the case where the state variable is perfectly correlated with
asset returns.12
JW x /JW W .
12.4.4
An Example
It
considers an environment where a single state variable aects investment opportunities and, to ensure market completeness, this state variable is perfectly
correlated with asset returns. In particular, let there be a risk-free asset paying
a constant rate of return of r > 0, and also assume there is a single risky asset
so that equation (12.50) can be written simply as
dS/S = (t) dt + dz
(12.70)
The risky assets volatility, , is assumed to be a positive constant but the assets
drift is permitted to vary over time. Specifically, let the single market price of
risk be (t) = [ (t) r] /.
process
d = a dt bdz
12 In
this case 1 = 0 1 B.
(12.71)
354
perfectly negatively correlated with the risky assets return.13 Wachter justifies
the assumption of perfect negative correlation as being reasonable based on
empirical studies of stock returns.
d = d, this model implies that the expected rate of return on the risky asset
is mean-reverting, becoming lower (higher) after its realized return has been
high (low).14
The individual is assumed to have constant relative risk aversion utility and
a zero bequest function, so that (12.54) becomes
max Et
Cs s[t,T ]
"Z
s C
ds + Mt Wt Et
"Z
#!
Ms Cs ds
(12.72)
where we have used the fact that it is optimal to set terminal wealth to zero
in the absence of a bequest motive. The first order condition corresponding to
(12.57) is then
Cs = e 1 (Ms ) 1 ,
s [t, T ]
(12.73)
Therefore, the relationship between current wealth and this optimal consumption policy, equation (12.59), is
Wt
#
1
s
Ms 1
1
= Et
e
(Ms )
ds
Mt
t
Z T
h i
s
1
1
1
Mt
e 1 Et Ms 1 ds
=
"Z
(12.74)
13 Robert Merton (Merton 1971) considered a similar problem where the market price of
risk was perfectly positively correlated with a risky assets return.
14 Straightforward algebra shows that (t) follows the similar Ornstein-Uhlenbeck process
d = a + r dt bdz.
355
Since dM/M = rdt dz, the expectation in (12.74) depends only on Mt and
the distribution of which follows the Ornstein-Uhlenbeck process in (12.71).
A solution for Wt can be obtained by computing the expectation in (12.74)
directly. Alternatively, one can solve for Wt using the PDE (12.65). For this
example, the PDE is
0 =
1 2 2
M WMM + bMWM +
2
W
+ a + b W +
t
1 2
b W + 2 r M WM
2
t
+ e 1 (Mt ) 1 rW (12.75)
Wt = (Mt ) 1 e 1
T t
H ( t , ) d
(12.76)
H (t , ) e
1
1
2
A1 ( ) 2t +A2 ( )t +A3 ( )
(12.77)
and
2c1 (1 ec3 )
2c3 (c2 + c3 ) (1 ec3 )
2
4c1 a 1 ec3 /2
A2 ()
c3 [2c3 (c2 + c3 ) (1 ec3 )]
Z
b2
b2
A3 ()
A22 (s) + A1 (s) + aA2 (s) + r ds
2 (1 )
2
0
A1 ()
15 This
356
p
c22 4c1 b2 / (1 ). Equa-
tion (12.76) can be inverted to solve for the Lagrange multiplier, , but since we
1
Ct = R T t
0
Wt
H (t , ) d
(12.78)
equals the value of consumption periods in the future scaled by current consumption.
Wachter shows that when < 0 and t > 0, so that the excess return on the
risky asset, (t)r, is positive, then (Ct /Wt ) /t > 0, that is, the individual
consumes a greater proportion of wealth the larger is the excess rate of return
on the risky asset. This is what we would expect given our earlier analysis that
the "income" eect dominates the "substitution" eect when risk-aversion is
greater than that of log utility. The higher expected rate of return on the risky
asset allows the individual to aord more current consumption, which outweighs
the desire to save more in order to take advantage of the higher expected return
on wealth.
Let us next solve for this individuals optimal portfolio choice. The risky
assets portfolio weight that finances the optimal consumption plan is given by
(12.69) for the case of a single risky asset:
M WM (t) r W b
W
2
W
(12.79)
12.5. SUMMARY
357
b
(t) r
(1 ) 2 (1 )
(t) r
b
(1 ) 2 (1 )
R T t
0
H ( t , ) [A1 ( ) t + A2 ()] d
R T t
H (t , ) d
0
T t
(12.80)
H ( t , )
[A1 ( ) t + A2 ( )] d
R T t
H ( t , ) d
0
The first term is the familiar risky asset demand whose form is the same as for
the case of constant investment opportunities, equation (12.35).
The second
term on the right-hand side of (12.80) is the demand for hedging against changing investment opportunities. It can be interpreted as a consumption weighted
average of separate demands for hedging against changes in investment opportunities at all horizons from 0 to T t periods in the future, where the weight
R T t
at horizon is H (t , ) / 0 H ( t , ) d.
It can be shown that A1 () and A2 ( ) are negative when < 0, so that if
t > 0, the term [A1 ( ) t + A2 ( )] is unambiguously negative and, therefore,
the hedging demand is positive. Hence, for individuals who are more risk averse
that log utility, they place more of their wealth in the risky asset than would
be the case if investment opportunities were constant. Because of the negative
correlation between risky asset returns and future investment opportunities,
overweighting ones portfolio in the risky asset means that unexpectedly good
returns today hedge against returns that are expected to be poorer tomorrow.
12.5
Summary
358
opportunities are constant, the individuals optimal portfolio weights equal those
of Chapter 2s single period mean - variance model that assumed normally
distributed asset returns. The fact that the mean - variance optimal portfolio
weights could be derived in a multi-period model with lognormal returns is an
attractive result because lognormality is consistent with the limited liability
characteristics of most securities such as bonds and common stocks.
When assets means and variances are time varying, so that investment opportunities are randomly changing, we found that portfolio allocation rules no
longer satisfy the simple mean variance demands.
utility, portfolio choices will include additional demand components that reflect
a desire to hedge against unfavorable shifts in investment opportunities.
We presented two techniques for finding an individuals optimal consumption
and portfolio decisions.
This approach
12.6. EXERCISES
12.6
359
Exercises
dPt /Pt = dt + d.
The nominal (currency value) of the stock is given by St . This nominal stock
price satisfies
1.a What processes do the real (consumption good value) rates of return on
the stock and the bond satisfy?
1.b Let Ct be the individuals date t real rate of consumption and be the
proportion of real wealth, Wt , that is invested in the stock. Give the
process followed by real wealth, Wt .
360
max E0
C,
U (Ct , t) dt
subject to the real wealth dynamic budget constraint given in part b. Assuming
U (Ct , t) is a concave utility function, solve for the individuals optimal choice
of in terms of the indirect utility of wealth function.
1.d How does vary with ? What is the economic intuition for this comparative static result?
E0
"Z
T
t
u (Ct ) dt
The price of the risky asset, S, is assumed to follow the geometric Brownian
motion process
dS/S = dt + dz
where and are constants. The instantaneously risk-free asset pays an instantaneous rate of return of rt . Thus, an investment that takes the form of
continually re-investing at this risk-free rate has a value (price), Bt , that follows
the process
dB/B = rt dt
12.6. EXERCISES
361
where rt is assumed to change over time, following the Vasicek (1977) meanreverting process
drt = a [b rt ] dt + sd
where dzdq = dt.
2.a Write down the intertemporal budget constraint for this problem.
2.b What are the two state variables for this consumption-portfolio choice
problem? Write down the stochastic, continuous-time Bellman equation
for this problem.
2.c Take the first order conditions for the optimal choices of consumption and
the demand for the risky asset.
2.d Show how the demand for the risky asset can be written as two terms:
one term that would be present even if r where constant and another term
that exists due to changes in r (investment opportunities).
362
E0
dS/S = s dt + s d
where s and s may be functions of S.
The university is assumed to fund its consumption of arts and sciences activities from its endowment. The value of its endowment is denoted Wt . It can
be invested in either a risk-free asset or a risky asset. The risk-free asset pays
a constant rate of return equal to r. The price of the risky asset is denoted P
and is assumed to follow the process
dP/P = dt + dz
where and are constants and dzd = dt. Let denote the proportion of
the universitys endowment invested in the risky asset, and thus (1 ) is the
proportion invested in the risk-free asset. The universitys problem is then to
maximize its expected utility by optimally selecting Ca , Cs , and .
3.a Write down the universitys intertemporal budget constraint, that is, the
dynamics for its endowment, Wt .
12.6. EXERCISES
363
3.b What are the two state variables for this problem? Define a derived
utility of endowment (wealth) function and write down the stochastic,
continuous-time Bellman equation for this problem.
3.c Write down the first order conditions for the optimal choices of Ca , Cs ,
and .
3.d Show how the demand for the risky asset can be written as two terms, a
standard (single-period) portfolio demand term and a hedging term.
3.e For the special case in which utility is given by u (Ca ,Cs ) = Ca Cs , solve
for the universitys optimal level of arts activity in terms of the level and
price of the science activity.
E0
(Z
et u (Ct , Lt ) dt + B (WT )
dS/S = dt + dz
where and are constants. For each unit of labor eort exerted at date t, the
364
dy = y (y) dt + y (y) d
where dzd = dt.
4.a Letting be the proportion of wealth invested in the risky asset, write
down the intertemporal budget constraint for this problem.
4.b What are the state variables for this problem? Write down the stochastic,
continuous-time Bellman equation for this problem.
4.c Take the first order conditions with respect to each of the individuals
decision variables.
4.d Show how the demand for the risky asset can be written as two terms:
one term that would be present even if y were constant and another term
that exists due to changes in y.
4.e If u (Ct , Lt ) = ln [Ct ] + ln [Lt ], solve for the optimal amount of labor
eort in terms of the optimal level of consumption.
E0
et u (Ct ) dt
12.6. EXERCISES
365
dS/S = dt + dz
and a default-risky bond whose price, B, follows the process
dB = rBdt Bdq
where dq is a Poisson process defined as
dq =
1
0
if a default occurs
otherwise
5.a Letting be the proportion of wealth invested in the stock, write down
the intertemporal budget constraint for this problem.
5.b Write down the stochastic, continuous-time Bellman equation for this
problem. (Hint: Recall that the Dynkin operator, L [J], reflects the driftterms from applying Its lemma to J. In this problem, these terms need
to include the expected change in J from jumps in wealth due to bond
default.)
366
5.c Take the first order conditions with respect to each of the individuals
decision variables.
5.d Since this problem reflects constant investment opportunities, it can be
shown that when u (Ct ) = c /, < 1, the derived utility of wealth function takes the form J (W, t) = aet W / where a is a positive constant.
For this constant relative risk-aversion case, derive the conditions for optimal C and in terms of current wealth and the parameters of the asset
price processes. (Note: An explicit formula for in terms of all of the
other parameters may not be possible because the condition is non-linear
in .)
5.e Maintaining the constant relative risk-aversion assumption, what is the
optimal if = 0? Assuming the parameters are such that 0 < < 1 for
this case, how would a small increase in aect , the proportion of the
portfolio held in the stock?
6. Show that a log utility investors optimal consumption for the continuous
time problem, (12.49) is comparable to that of the discrete time problem,
(5.34).
Chapter 13
Equilibrium Prices of
Assets
This chapter considers the equilibrium pricing of assets for a continuous time
economy when individuals have time separable utility. It derives the Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing Model (ICAPM) that was developed by Robert
Merton (Merton 1973a). This model shows that if investment opportunities
are constant through time and asset prices are log-normally distributed, the
standard single-period CAPM results hold. This is an important modification
of the CAPM, not only because the results are extended to a multi-period environment but because the single-period models assumption of a normal asset
return distribution is replaced with a more attractive assumption of lognormally
distributed returns. Since assets such as stocks and bonds have limited liability, the assumption of lognormal returns, which bounds returns at zero, is more
realistic.
When investment opportunities are changing, the standard "single-beta"
CAPM no longer holds. Rather, a multi-beta ICAPM is necessary for pricing
367
368
assets, where the additional betas reflect priced sources of risk from additional
state variables that aect investment opportunities. However, as was shown by
Douglas Breeden (Breeden 1979), the multi-beta ICAPM can be collapsed into
a single "consumption" beta model, the so-called Consumption Capital Asset
Pricing Model (CCAPM).
The Merton ICAPM is not a fully general equilibrium analysis, since it takes
the form of the asset prices processes faced by individuals as given. However,
as is also shown in this chapter, these asset price processes turn out to be of the
same form as those derived by John Cox, Jonathan Ingersoll, and Stephen Ross
(CIR) (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985a) in their general equilibrium production
economy model. The CIR model is an example of a production economy where
the form of the economys productive technologies are given. These technologies
are assumed to display constant returns to scale and provides us with a model of
asset supplies that is an alternative to the Lucas endowment economy discussed
in Chapter 6.
CIR model can be used to solve for the prices of various maturity bonds that
are assumed to be in zero net supply.
13.1
(13.1)
369
where i = 1, ..., n, and (i dzi )(j dzj ) = ij dt. The risk-free return and the
means and standard deviations of the risky assets can be functions of time and
a k 1 vector of state variables that follow the processes
(13.2)
where i = 1, ..., k, and (bi d i )(bj d j ) = bij dt and ( i dzi )(bj d j ) = ij dt.
Now we wish to consider what must be the equilibrium relationships between
the parameters of the asset return processes characterized by (13.1) and (13.2).
Let us start by analyzing the simplest case first, namely, when investment opportunities are constant through time.
13.1.1
As shown in the previous chapter, when the risk-free rate and the parameters
of assets return processes are constants (r, the i s, i s, and ij s are all constants), the asset price processes in (13.1) are geometric Brownian motions and
asset returns are lognormally distributed.
choices of all individuals lead them to choose the same portfolio of risky assets.
Individuals dier only in how they divide their total wealths between this common risky asset portfolio and the risk-free asset.
portfolio, it was shown in (12.25) that the proportion of risky asset k to all risky
assets is
k =
n
X
kj (j
j=1
n
n X
X
i=1 j=1
r)
.
ij (j r)
and in (12.26) that this portfolios mean and variance are given by
(13.3)
370
n
X
i i
i=1
n X
n
X
(13.4)
i j ij .
i=1 j=1
i r = i (m r) ,
i = 1, ...n
(13.5)
where i im /2m and im is the covariance between the ith assets rate of
return and the markets rate of return. Thus, the constant investment opportunity set assumption replicates the standard, single-period CAPM. Yet, rather
than asset returns being normally distributed as in the single-period CAPM,
the ICAPM has asset returns being lognormally distributed.
While the standard CAPM results continue to hold for this more realistic
intertemporal environment, the assumptions of a constant risk-free rate and
unchanging asset return means and variances are untenable. Clearly, interest
rates vary over time, as do the volatilities of assets such as common stocks.1
Moreover, there is substantial evidence that mean returns on assets display
1 Not only do nominal interest rates vary over time, but there is also evidence that real
interest rates do as well (Pennacchi 1991). Also, volatilities of stock returns have been found
to follow mean-reverting processes. See, for example, (Bollerslev, Chou, and Kroner 1992)
and (Andersen, Bollerslev, Diebold, and Ebens 2001).
371
13.1.2
To keep the analysis simple, let us start by assuming that there is a single
state variable, x. The system of n equations that a given individuals portfolio
weights satisfy is given by the previous chapters equation (12.19) with k = 1.
It can be re-written as
0 = A(i r) +
n
X
j=1
ij j W Hi , i = 1, . . . , n
(13.6)
Ap ( re) = p W p H p
(13.7)
(13.8)
372
where a
pW
p
pA ,
Hp/
p
pA ,
and
W p/
pW
is
the average investment in each asset across investors. These must be the market
weights, in equilibrium. Hence, the ith row (ith risky asset excess return) of
equation (13.8) is:
i r = aim hi
(13.9)
To find the excess return on the market portfolio, we can pre-multiply (13.8) by
0 and obtain:
m r = a2m h mx
(13.10)
where mx = 0 is the covariance between the market portfolio and the state
variable, x.
Next, define
1
e0 1 .
By construction, is a vector of
portfolio weights for the risky assets, where this portfolio has the maximum
absolute correlation with the state variable, x.
r = a m h x
(13.11)
where m is the covariance between the optimal hedge portfolio and the market
portfolio and x is the covariance between the optimal hedge portfolio and the
state variable, x. Equations (13.10) and (13.11) are two linear equations in the
two unknowns, a and h. Solving for a and h and substituting them back into
equation (13.9), we obtain:
3 Note that the numerator of , 1 , is the nx1 vector of coecients from a regression
of dx on the n risky asset returns, dSi /Si , i 1, ..., n. Dividing these individual coecients
by their sum, e0 1 , transforms them into portfolio weights.
i r =
im x i m
i 2m im mx
r
(
r)
+
m
2
2
m x mx m
m x mx m
373
(13.12)
While the derivation is somewhat lengthy, it can be shown that (13.12) is equivalent to
i r
im 2 i m
i 2m im m
r
(m r) +
2
2
2
2
2
2
m m
m m
m
i (m r) + i r
(13.13)
=
where i is the covariance between the return on asset i and that of the hedge
portfolio. Note that i = 0 if and only if i = 0. For the case in which the
state variable, x, is uncorrelated with the market, equation (13.13) simplifies to:
i r =
im
i
(m r) + 2 r
2
m
(13.14)
In this case, the first term on the right-hand side of (13.14) is that found in
the standard CAPM. The assumption that x is uncorrelated with the market is
not as restrictive as one might first believe, since one could re-define the state
variable x as a factor that cannot be explained by current market returns, that
is, a factor that is uncorrelated with the market.
An equation such as (13.13) can be derived when more than one state variable
exists. In this case, there will be an additional beta for each state variable.
The intertemporal capital asset pricing relations (ICAPM) given by (13.13)
and (13.14) have a form similar to the Arbitrage Pricing Model of Chapter 3.
Indeed, the multi-factor ICAPM has been used to justify empirical APT-type
factor models. The ICAPM predicts that APT risk factors should be related
to changes in investment opportunities. However, it should be noted that, in
374
general, the ICAPMs betas may be time varying and not easy to estimate in a
constant-coecients multi-factor regression model.
13.1.3
JW x = UCC
C
+ UCx
x
(13.15)
so that
H=
UCx
C/x
C
C/W
UCC W
(13.16)
It can be shown that in this case individuals do not hold consumption variance minimizing portfolios, but marginal utility variance-minimizing portfolios.
13.2
375
expected rate of return depends upon its covariance with the marginal utility
of consumption can be generalized to a multi-period, continuous time context.
Breeden considers the same model as Merton, and hence in the case of multiple state variables, derives equation (12.38). Substituting in for A and H,
equation (12.38) can be written in matrix form, and for the case of k (multiple)
state variables the optimal portfolio weights for the pth investor are given by:
p W p =
UCp
p
1
( re) 1 Cp
p
p
x /CW
UCC
CW
p
where CW
= C p /W p , Cp
x =
C p
C p
x1 ... xk
(13.17)
covariances of asset returns with changes in the state variables, that is, its i,j th
p
element is ij . Pre-multiplying (13.17) by CW
and rearranging terms, we have
UCp
p
p
p ( re) = Wp CW + Cx
UCC
(13.18)
p
( p1 W p 1 dz1 + ... + pn W p n dzn ) + (b1 d 1 + ... + bk d k ) Cp
CW
x
(13.19)
376
p
+Cp
Cp = Wp CW
x
(13.20)
Note that the right-hand side of (13.20) equals the right-hand side of (13.18),
and therefore
Cp =
UCp
p ( re)
UCC
(13.21)
Equation (13.21) holds for each individual, p. Next, define C as the aggregate
rate of consumption and define T as an aggregate rate of risk tolerance, where
X
p
UCp
p
UCC
(13.22)
re = T 1 C
(13.23)
re = (T /C)
ln C
(13.24)
m r = (T /C)1 m,ln C
(13.25)
377
where m is the expected return on portfolio m and m,ln C is the (scalar) covariance between returns on portfolio m and changes in the log of consumption.
Using (13.25) to substitute for (T /C)1 in (13.24), we have
re = (ln C /m,ln C ) (m r)
= ( C / mC ) (m r)
(13.26)
where C and mC are the consumption betas of asset returns and of portfolio
ms return. The consumption beta for any asset is defined as
(13.27)
Portfolio m may be any portfolio of assets, not necessarily the market portfolio. Equation (13.26) says that the ratio of expected excess returns on any
two assets or portfolios of assets is equal to the ratio of their betas measured
relative to aggregate consumption. Hence, the risk of a securitys return can
be summarized by a single consumption beta. Aggregate optimal consumption,
C (W, x, t), encompasses the eects of levels of wealth and the state variables,
and in this way is a sucient statistic for the value of asset returns in dierent
states of the world.
Breedens consumption CAPM (CCAPM) is a considerable simplification
relative to Mertons multi-beta ICAPM. Furthermore, while the multiple state
variables in Mertons model may not be directly identified or observed, and hence
the multiple state variable betas may not be computed, Breedens consumption beta can be computed given that we have data on aggregate consumption.
However, as discussed earlier, the results of empirical tests using aggregate consumption data are unimpressive. As in all of our earlier asset pricing models
378
specifying the form of their utilities, they determine the equilibrium relations
between the parameters of the asset returns generation processes in (13.1) and
(13.2) by taking the form of these processes as given.
librium model would not start by specifying these assets return process but,
rather, specify the economys "technologies." In other words, it would specify
the economys productive opportunities that determine the supplies of assets
in the economy. By matching individuals asset demands with the asset supplies, the returns on assets would then be determined endogenously. The Lucas
endowment economy model in Chapter 6 was an example of this, and we now
turn to another general equilibrium model, namely, Cox, Ingersoll, and Rosss
production economy model.
13.3
In two companion articles (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985a)(Cox, Ingersoll, and
Ross 1985b), John Cox, Jonathan Ingersoll, and Stephen Ross (CIR) develop
a continuous time model of a production economy that is a general equilibrium framework for many of the asset pricing results of this chapter.
Their
model starts from basic assumptions regarding individuals preferences and the
economys production possibilities. Individuals are assumed to have identical
379
preferences and initial wealth, and to maximize standard, time separable utility similar to the lifetime utility previously specified in this and the previous
chapter, namely (12.4).4
Individuals cannot
Individuals can save some of the economys output and reinvest it,
thereby changing the productive capacity of the economy. Assets rates of return are pinned-down by the economys technologies, and the amounts invested
in these technologies become endogenous.
Specifically, CIR assume that there is a single good that can be either consumed or invested.
(13.28)
where (i dzi )(j dzj ) = ij dt. i i is the instantaneous expected change in the
amount of the invested good and i i is the instantaneous standard deviation
of the change. Note that because i and i are independent of i , the change
4 When individuals are assumed to have the same utility and initial wealth, we can think
of there being a "representative" individual.
380
Hence, each
(13.29)
where i = 1, ..., k, and (bi d i )(bj d j ) = bij dt and ( i dzi )(bj d j ) = ij dt.
Note that equations (13.28) and (13.29) are nearly identical to our earlier
modeling of financial asset prices, equations (13.1) and (13.2). The only difference is that Si (t) in (13.1) is the price of a financial asset while i (t) in
(13.28) is a physical quantity invested.
preted as being owned by an individual firm, and each of these firms is financed
entirely by shareholders equity, then the value of shareholders equity of firm
i, Si (t), equals the value of the firms physical assets (capital), i (t). Hence,
i (t) can be interpreted as the value or price of firm i in terms of units of the
capital-consumption good.
In the CIR model, investors decide how much of their wealth (the capitalconsumption good) to consume versus save and, of the amount saved, how to
allocate it between the n dierent technologies (or firms). Because equations
(13.28) and (13.29) model an economys production possibilities as constant
returns to scale technologies, the distributions of assets rates of return available
to investors are exogenous.
This is
381
done by imagining there to be other securities that have zero net supplies. For
example, there may be no technology that produces an instantaneously risk-free
return, that is, i 6= 0 i. However, one can solve for the equilibrium risk-less
borrowing or lending rate, call it r (t), for which the representative individuals
would be just indierent between borrowing or lending. In other words, r would
be the riskless rate such that individuals choose to invest zero amounts of the
consumption good at this rate. Since all individuals are identical, this amounts
to the riskless investment having a zero supply in the economy, so that r is really
a "shadow" riskless rate.
An equilibrium is
382
max
Cs ,{ i,s },s,i
Et
"Z
(13.30)
i W i dzi
(13.31)
U (Cs , s) ds + B(WT , T )
subject to
dW =
n
X
i=1
i W i dt Ct dt +
Pn
i=1 i
n
X
i=1
The individuals first order condition for consumption is the usual one
0 =
J (W, x, t)
U (C , t)
C
W
(13.32)
but the first order conditions with respect to the portfolio weights are modified
slightly. If we let be the Lagrange multiplier associated with the equality
Pn
i=1 i = 1, then the appropriate first order conditions for the portfolio weights
are
n
k
J
2J X
2J X
2
W+
ij j W +
W 0
W i
W 2 j=1
xi W j=1 ij
0 = i i
i = 1, . . . , n
(13.33)
JW
JW W W
n
X
j=1
ij j
n
k X
n
X
X
JW xm
ij jm +
ij (13.34)
J
W
JW W W 2 j=1
m=1 j=1 W W
for i = 1, ..., n. Using our previously defined matrix notation, (13.34) can be
383
re-written as
k
X
A 1
A
Hj 1
1
j
e+
2
W
JW W
W
j=1
(13.35)
Since in the CIR economy the riskless asset is in zero net supply, we know
that the portfolio weights in (13.35) must be those chosen by the representative
individual even if oered the opportunity to borrow or lend at rate r. Recall
from the previous chapters equations (12.21) that these conditions, re-written
in matrix notation, are
k
X
A 1
Hj 1
(re) +
j , i = 1, . . . , n
W
W
j=1
(13.36)
Hence, since the individual takes prices and rates as given, the portfolio choices
5 Recall that a linear combination of any two portfolios on the mean variance frontier can
create any other portfolio on the frontier.
384
given by the first order conditions in (13.36), the case when a riskless asset
exists, must be the same as (13.35). By inspection, the weights in (13.35) and
(13.36) are identical when r = / (JW W ). Hence, substituting for in terms
of the optimal portfolio weights, we can write the equilibrium interest as6
W JW
= 0
(13.37)
k
X
W 0
Hj 0
j
A
A
j=1
Note that equation (13.37) is the same as the previously derived relationship
(13.10) except that (13.37) is extended to k state variables. Hence, Mertons
ICAPM, as well as Breedens CCAPM, holds for the CIR economy.
The CIR model also can be used to find the equilibrium shadow prices of
other securities that are assumed to have zero net supplies. Such "contingent
claims" could include securities such as longer maturity bonds or options and
futures. For example, suppose a zero net supply contingent claim has a payo
whose value could depend on wealth, time, the state variables, P (W, t, {xi }).7
Its lemma implies that its price will follow a process of the form
dP = uP dt + PW W
n
X
i i dzi +
i=1
k
X
Pxi bi d i
(13.38)
i=1
where
uP
= PW (W 0 C) +
+
k
X
i=1
k
X
Pxi ai + Pt +
i=1
PW xi W 0 i +
PW W W 2 0
2
1 XX
Px x bij
2 i=1 j=1 i j
(13.39)
6 To derive the second line in (13.37), it is easiest to write in matrix form the first order
condtions in (13.33) and assume these conditions all hold as equalities. Then solve for by
pre-multiplying by 0 and noting that 0 e = 1.
7 A contingent claim whose payo depends on the returns or prices of the technologies can
be found by the Black-Scholes methodolgy described in Chapter 9.
385
Using the Merton ICAPM result (13.9) extended to k state variables, the expected rate of return on the contingent claim must also satisfy8
u=r+
k
X
W
Hi
Cov (dP/P, dW/W )
Cov (dP/P, dxi )
A
A
i=1
(13.40)
or
uP
k
X
1
Hi
Cov (dP, dW )
Cov (dP, dxi )
A
A
i=1
!
k
X
1
Pxi W 0 i
= rP +
PW W 2 0 +
A
i=1
k
k
X Hi
X
PW W 0 i +
Pxj bij
A
i=1
j=1
= rP +
(13.41)
where in (13.40) we make use of the fact that the market portfolio equals the
optimally invested wealth of the representative individual.
Equating (13.39)
and (13.41) and recalling the value of the equilibrium risk-free rate in (13.37),
we obtain a partial dierential equation for the contingent claims value.9
k
k
k
X
PW W W 2 0
1 XX
0
+
0 =
PW xi W i +
Px x bij + Pt +
2
2 i=1 j=1 i j
i=1
k
k
X
X
W 0
Hj bij
PW (rW C) +
i +
rP (13.42)
Pxi ai
A
A
i=1
j=1
The next section illustrates how (13.37) and (13.42) can be used to find
8 Condition (13.9) can be derived for the case of a contingent claim by using the fact that
the contingent claims weight in the market portfolio is zero.
9 It is straightforward to derive the valuation equation for a contingent claim that pays a
continuous dividend at rate (W, x, t) dt. In this case the additional term (W, x, t) appears
on the right hand side of equation (13.42).
386
the risk free rate and particular contingent claims for a specific case of a CIR
economy.
13.3.1
The example in this section is based on (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985b). It assumes that the representative individuals utility and bequest functions are logarithmic and of the form U(Cs , s) = es ln (Cs ) and B (WT , T ) = eT ln (WT ).
For this specification, we showed in the previous chapter that the indirect utility function was separable and equalled J (W, x, t) = d (t) et ln (Wt ) + F (x, t)
= 1 (re)
(13.43)
where we have used the result that r = / (JW W ). Using the market clearing
condition e0 = 1, we can solve for the equilibrium risk free rate.
r=
e0 1 1
e0 1 e
(13.44)
Substituting (13.44) into (13.43), we see that the optimal portfolio weights are
0 1
e 1
= 1
e
e0 1 e
(13.45)
Let us next assume that a single state variable, x (t) , aects all production
processes in the following manner.
bi x dt +
bi xdzi , i = 1, ..., n
di /i =
(13.46)
387
where
bi and
bi are assumed to be constants and the state variable follows the
dx = (a0 + a1 x) dt + b0 xd
(13.47)
where dzi d = i dt. Note that this specification implies that the means and
variances of the technologies rates of returns are proportional to the state variable. If a0 > 0 and a1 < 0, x is a non-negative, mean-reverting random variable.
A rise in x raises all technologies expected rates of return but also increases
their variances.
We can write the technologies nx1 vector of expected rates of return as =
b
b x and their nxn matrix of rate of return covariances as = x.
Using these
r=
b 1
b 1
e0
x = x
0
1
b
e e
b 1
b 1 e is a constant.
b 1 /e0
where e0
(13.48)
This implies that the risk
dr = dx = (r r) dt + rd
(13.49)
388
Next, let us consider how to value contingent claims based on this examples
assumptions.
bond that pays one unit of the consumption good when it matures at date T t.
Since this bonds payo is independent of wealth, and since logarithmic utility
implies that the equilibrium interest rate and optimal portfolio proportions are
independent of wealth, the price of this bond will also be independent of wealth.
Hence, the derivatives PW , PW W , and PW x in the valuation equation (13.42)
will all be zero. Moreover, since r = x, it will be insightful to think of r as
the state variable rather than x, so that the date t bond price can be written
as P (r, t, T ). With these changes, the valuation equation (13.42) becomes12
2r
Prr + [ (r r) r] Pr rP + Pt = 0
2
(13.50)
b
b equals the right hand side of equation
b 0 .
where is a constant equal to
b while
b is an nx1
b and replaced by
(13.45) but with replaced by
vector of constants whose ith element is b
i i . r = 0 is the covariance of
interest rate changes with the proportional change in optimally invested wealth.
In other words, it is the interest rates "beta" (covariance with the market
portfolios return).
The partial dierential equation (13.50), when solved subject to the boundary condition P (r, T, T ) = 1, leads to the bond pricing formula
P (r, t, T ) = A ( ) eB( )r
(13.51)
rate since r can become negative. See Pennacchi (Pennacchi 1991) for such an application.
It can be shown that the discrete time distribution for the CIR interest rate process in (13.49)
is a non-central chi-square.
12 Recall that logarithmic utility implies A = W and H = 0.
389
where = T t,
2e(++) 2
A ( )
( + + ) (e 1) + 2
B ()
and
2r/2
2 e 1
( + + ) (e 1) + 2
(13.52)
(13.53)
q
( + )2 + 2 2 . This CIR bond price can be contrasted with that of
the Vasicek model derived in Chapter 9, equation (9.39). They are similar in
having the same structure given in equation (13.51) but with dierent values for
A ( ) and B ( ). Hence, the discount bond yield, Y (r, ) ln [P (r, t, T )] /
= ln [A ( )] / +B ( ) r/ is linear in the state variable for both models.13
But the two models dier in a number of ways. Recall that Vasicek directly
assumed that the short rate, r, followed an Ornstein Uhlenbeck process and
derived the result that, in the absence of arbitrage, the market price of interest
rate risk must be the same for bonds of all maturities.
390
technologies.
Lets solve for the market risk premium implicit in CIR bond
prices.
Note that Its lemma says that the bond price follows the process
dP
1
= Pr dr + Prr 2 rdt + Pt dt
2
1
Prr 2 r + Pr [ (r r)] + Pt dt + Pr rd
=
2
1
2
2 Prr r
(13.54)
+ Pr [ (r r)] + Pt =
dP/P
Pr
Pr
= r 1+
rd
dt +
P
P
= r (1 B ( )) dt B ( ) rd
(13.55)
p (r, ) r
rB ( )
r
=
=
p (r, )
rB ( )
(13.56)
so that the market price of interest rate risk is not constant as in the Vasicek
model, but is proportional to the square root of the interest rate. When < 0,
which occurs when the interest rate is negatively correlated with the return
on the market portfolio (and bond prices are positively correlated with the
market portfolio), bonds will carry a positive risk premium. CIR (Cox, Ingersoll,
and Ross 1985b) argue that their equilibrium approach to deriving a market
risk premium avoids problems that can occur when, following the no-arbitrage
approach, an arbitrary form for a market risk premium is assumed. They show
that some functional forms for market risk premia are inconsistent with the no
arbitrage assumption.
13.4. SUMMARY
13.4
391
Summary
interest rate and the shadow prices of contingent claims that are assumed to be
in zero net supply. One important application of the model is a derivation of
the equilibrium term structure of interest rates.
The next chapter builds on our results to this point by generalizing individuals lifetime utility functions.
separable. Allowing for time inseparable utility can lead to dierent equilibrium
relationships between asset returns that can better describe empirical findings.
13.5
Exercises
1. Consider a CIR economy similar to the log utility example given in this
chapter.
392
bi x dt + i dzi , i = 1, ..., n
di /i =
In addition, rather than assume that the state variable follows the process
(13.47), suppose that it is given by
dx = (a0 + a1 x) dt + b0 d
13.5. EXERCISES
393
Chapter 14
Time-Inseparable Utility
In previous chapters, individuals multi-period utility functions were assumed to
be time separable. For example, in a continuous time context, time separable
expected lifetime utility was specified as
Et
"Z
U (Cs , s) ds
(14.1)
(14.2)
so that utility at date s depends only on consumption at date s and not consumption at previous or future dates. However, as was noted earlier, there is
substantial evidence that standard time separable utility appears inconsistent
with the empirical time series properties of U.S. consumption data and the average returns on risky assets (common stocks) and risk-free investments. These
empirical contradictions, referred to as the equity premium puzzle and the riskfree interest rate puzzle, have led researchers to explore lifetime utility functions
395
396
These
utility functions can be interpreted as displaying habit persistence. We summarize two models of this type that are based the articles of George Constantinides
(Constantinides 1990) and of John Campbell and John Cochrane (Campbell and
Cochrane 1999). In addition to modeling habit persistence dierently, these
models provide an interesting contrast in terms of their assumptions regarding the economys aggregate supplies of assets and the techniques we use to
solve them. The model in the Constantinides paper is a simple example of a
Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985a) production economy
where asset supplies are perfectly elastic. It is solved using a Bellman equation approach. In contrast, the Campbell - Cochrane paper assumes a Lucas
(Lucas 1978) endowment economy where asset supplies are perfectly inelastic.
Its solution is based on the economys stochastic discount factor.
The second type of time-inseparable utility that we discuss is known as
recursive utility. From one perspective, recursive utility is the opposite of habit
persistence because recursive utility functions make current utility depend on
expected values of future utility, which in turn depends on future consumption.
We illustrate this type of utility by considering the general equilibrium of an
economy where representative consumer-investors have recursive utility. The
specific model that we analyze is a continuous-time version of a discrete-time
model by Maurice Obstfeld (Obstfeld 1994).
By generalizing utility functions to permit habit persistence or to be recursive, we hope to provide better models of individuals actual preferences and
their resulting consumption and portfolio choice decisions. In this way, greater
397
insights into the nature of equilibrium asset returns may be possible. Specifically, we can analyze these models in terms of their ability to resolve various
asset pricing "puzzles," such as the equity premium puzzle and the risk-free
rate puzzle that arise when utility is time-separable.
how utility can be extended from the standard time-separable, constant relative
risk aversion case to display habit persistence.
14.1
The notion of habit persistence can be traced to the writings of Alfred Marshall
(Marshall 1920), James Duesenberry (Duesenberry 1949), and, more recently,
Harl Ryder and Georey Heal (Ryder and Heal 1973).
It is based on the
idea that an individuals choice of consumption aects not only utility today,
but it directly aects utility in the near future because the individual becomes
accustomed to todays consumption standard.
Let us illustrate this idea by presenting Constantinides internal habit formation model, which derives a representative individuals consumption and portfolio choices in a simple production economy.
assumptions.
14.1.1
Assumptions
A.1. Technology:
A single capital-consumption good can be invested in up to two dierent
technologies. The first is a risk-free technology whose output, Bt , follows the
process
dB/B = r dt.
(14.3)
398
d/ = dt + dz.
(14.4)
Note that the specification of technologies fixes the expected rates of return
and variances of the safe and risky investments.1 In this setting, individuals
asset demands determine equilibrium quantities of the assets supplied rather
than asset prices. Since r, , and are assumed to be constants, there is a
constant investment opportunity set.
A.2 Preferences:
Representative agents maximize expected utility of consumption, Ct , of the
form
E0
bt dt
u C
(14.5)
bt /, < 1, C
bt = C
bt = Ct bxt , and
where u C
xt eat x0 +
ea(ts) Cs ds.
(14.6)
Note that if b = 0, utility is of the standard time separable form and displays
constant relative risk aversion with a coecient of relative risk aversion equal to
(1 ). The variable xt is an exponentially weighted sum of past consumption,
so that when b > 0, the quantity bxt can be interpreted as a subsistence
bt = Ct bxt can be interpreted as
or habit level of consumption and C
399
to a standard of living (habit), and current utility derives from only the part
of consumption that is in excess of this standard.
Alternatively, if b < 0, so
that past consumption adds to, rather than subtracts from, current utility, then
the model can be interpreted as one displaying durability in consumption, rather
than habit persistence.2 Empirical evidence seems to support habit persistence,
rather than consumption durability, so our analysis focuses on the case of b > 0.3
With this modeling of habit persistence, current utility is a linear function
of not only current consumption but of past consumption through the variable
xt , so it is not time-separable. An increase in consumption at date t decreases
current marginal utility but it also increases the marginal utility of consumption
at future dates because it raises the level of subsistence consumption.
Of
course, there are more general ways of modeling habit persistence, for example,
u (Ct , wt ) where wt is any function of past consumption levels.4 However, we
use the linear habit persistence specification in (14.5) and (14.6) for its analytical
tractability.
A.3 Additional Parametric Assumptions:
Let W0 be the initial wealth of the representative individual. The following
parametric assumptions are made to have a well-specified consumption and
portfolio choice problem.
W0 >
bx0
> 0
r+ab
( r)2
> 0
2(1 )2
(14.7)
(14.8)
(14.9)
Hindy and Chi-Fu Huang (Hindy and Huang 1993) consider such a model.
asset pricing tests by Wayne Ferson and George Constantinides (Ferson and
Constantinides 1991) that used aggregate consumption data provided more support for habit
persistence relative to consumption durability.
4 Jerome Detemple and Fernando Zapatero (Detemple and Zapatero 1991) consider a model
that displays non-linear habit persistence.
3 Empirical
400
r
1
(1 ) 2
(14.10)
The reasons for making these parametric assumptions are the following. Note
that Ct needs to be greater than bxt for the individual to avoid infinite marginal utility.5 Conditions (14.7) and (14.8) ensure that an admissible (feasible)
consumption and portfolio choice strategy exists that enables Ct > bxt .6 To see
this, note that the dynamics for the individuals wealth is given by
dW = {[( r) t + r]W Ct } dt + t W dz
(14.11)
(14.12)
(14.13)
so that wealth always stays positive. This implies Ct = (r +ab) W0 e(ba)t > 0
401
and
Ct bxt
Z t
(r + a b)W0 e(ba)t b eat x0 +
ea(ts) (r + a b) W0 e(ba)s ds
0
Z t
(r + a b) W0 e(ba)t eat bx0 + b(r + a b)W0 eat
ebs ds
0
(14.14)
vidual follows an optimal policy (which will be derived below), the expected
utility of consumption over an infinite horizon is finite. As will be seen, condition (14.10) ensures that the individual wishes to put positive levels of wealth in
both the safe and risky technologies, that is, the individuals optimal portfolio
choice has an interior solution. Recall from (12.35) that m is the optimal choice
of the risky asset portfolio weight for the time-separable, constant relative risk
aversion case.
14.1.2
402
tion problem is
max Et
{Cs , s }
(14.15)
tion depends on two state variables, wealth, Wt , and the state variable xt , the
dx/dt = aeat x0 + Ct a
ea(ts) Cs ds,
or
(14.16)
(14.17)
max
{Ct ,t }
max
{Ct ,t }
U (Ct , xt , t) + L[et J]
t 1
e (Ct bxt ) + et JW [(( r) t + r)W Ct ]
1 t
e JW W 2 2t W 2 + et Jx (Ct axt ) et J }.
2
(14.18)
403
or
(14.19)
Ct = bxt +[JW Jx ] 1 ,
and
( r)W JW + t 2 W 2 JW W = 0,
or
(14.20)
( r)
JW
.
t =
2 (W JW W )
Note that the additional term Jx in (14.19) reflects the fact that an increase
in current consumption has the negative eect of raising the level of subsistence consumption, which decreases future utility. The form of (14.20), which
determines the portfolio weight of the risky asset, is more traditional.
Substituting (14.19) and (14.20) back into (14.18), we obtain the equilibrium
partial dierential equation:
J 2 ( r)2
1
[JW Jx ] 1 W
+ (rW bx)JW + (b a)xJx J = 0.
JW W 2 2
(14.21)
From our previous discussion of the time-separable, constant relative risk aversion case (a = b = x = 0), when the horizon is infinite, we saw from (12.33) that
a solution for J is of the form J(W ) = kW . For this previous case, u = C /,
uc = JW , and optimal consumption was a constant proportion of wealth:
1
( r)2
1
)
/ (1 )
C = (k) (1) W = W r (
2 1
2
(14.22)
and
= m
(14.23)
404
J(W, x) = k0 [W + k1 x] .
(14.24)
Making this guess, substituting it into (14.21), and setting the coecients on x
and W equal to zero, we find
k0 =
where
(r + a b)h1
(r + a)
(14.25)
r+ab
( r)2
h
> 0
r
(r + a)(1 )
2(1 )2
(14.26)
and
k1 =
b
< 0.
r+ab
(14.27)
Ct = bxt + h Wt
and
bxt
r+ab
bxt /Wt
t = m 1
.
r+ab
(14.28)
(14.29)
405
d Wt
bxt
r+ab
C axt
[ ( r) t + r]Wt Ct b t
dt + t Wt dz.
r+ab
(14.30)
d Wt
bxt
r+ab
Wt
bxt
[ n dt + m dz]
r+ab
(14.31)
where
n
r ( r)2 (2 )
+
.
1
2(1 )2 2
(14.32)
(n + a)bxt
Ct bxt
n+b
dt +
m dz.
Ct
Ct
(14.33)
bxt
Ct bxt
bxt
m dz,
ution.9 However, one sees from the stochastic term in (14.33), CtC
t
that consumption growth is smoother than in the case of no habit persistence.
For a given equity (risky asset) risk premium, this can imply relatively smooth
consumption paths, even though risk aversion, , may not be of a very high magnitude. To see this, recall from inequality (4.32) that the Hansen-Jagannathan
(H-J) bound for the time separable case can be written as
(1 ) c
(14.34)
In the current case of habit persistence, from (14.33) we see that the instanta-
8 See
9 See
406
c,t
=
=
Ct bxt
m
Ct
!
bt
C
r
Ct
(1 ) 2
(14.35)
to obtain
(1 ) c,t
r
=
St
Since St
Ct bxt
Ct
(14.36)
habit persistence can reconcile the empirical violation of the H-J bound. With
habit persistence, the lower demand for the risky asset, relative to the timeseparable case, can result in a higher equilibrium excess return on the risky
asset and, hence, help explain the puzzle of a large equity premium. However, empirical work by Wayne Ferson and George Constantinides (Ferson and
Constantinides 1991) that tests linear models of habit persistence suggests that
these models cannot produce an equity risk premium as large as that found in
historical equity returns.
14.2
407
The Campbell-Cochrane external habit persistence model is based on the following assumptions.
14.2.1
Assumptions
A.1 Technology:
Campbell and Cochrane consider a discrete-time endowment economy. Date
t aggregate consumption, which also equals aggregate output, is denoted Ct ,
and it is assumed to follow an independent and identically distributed lognormal
process
(14.37)
where vt+1 N 0, 2 .
A.2 Preferences:
It is assumed that there is a representative individual who maximizes expected utility of the form
E0
"
X
t (Ct
t=0
Xt ) 1
(14.38)
where < 1 and Xt denotes the habit level. Xt is related to past consumption
in the following non-linear manner. Define the surplus consumption ratio, St ,
as
St
Ct Xt
Ct
(14.39)
408
process10
ln (St+1 ) = (1 ) ln S + ln (St ) + (St ) t+1
(14.40)
where (St ), the sensitivity function, measures the proportional change in the
surplus consumption ratio resulting from a shock to output growth. It is assumed to take the form
(St ) =
1
S
1 2 ln (St ) ln S 1
(14.41)
and
S=
1
1
(14.42)
The lifetime utility function in (14.38) looks somewhat similar to (14.5) of the
Constantinides model. However, while Constantinides assumes that an individuals habit level depends on his or her own level of past consumption, Campbell
and Cochrane assume the an individuals habit level depends on everyone elses
current and past consumption. Thus, in the Constantinides model, the individuals choice of consumption, Ct , aects his future habit level, bxs , for all s > t,
and he takes this into account in terms of how it aects his expected utility when
he chooses Ct . This type of habit formation is referred to as internal habit. In
contrast, in the Campbell and Cochrane model, the individuals choice of consumption, Ct , does not aect her future habit level, Xs , for all s t, so that
she views Xt as exogenous when choosing Ct . This type of habit formation is
referred to as external habit or keeping up with the Joneses.11 The external
10
SThis iprocess is locally equivalent to ln (Xt ) = ln (Xt1 ) + ln (Ct ) or ln (Xt ) =
i=0 ln (Cti ). The reason for the more complicated form in (14.40) is that it ensures
that consumption is always above habit since St is always positive. This precludes infinite
marginal utility.
11 A similar modeling was developed by Andrew Abel (Abel 1990).
409
14.2.2
(14.43)
mt,t+1 =
uc (Ct+1 , Xt+1 )
=
uc (Ct , Xt )
Ct+1
Ct
St+1
St
(14.44)
If we define r as the continuously-compounded risk-free real interest rate between dates t and t + 1, then it equals
h
i
(14.45)
= ln (Et [mt,t+1 ]) = ln Et e(1) ln(Ct+1 /Ct )(1) ln(St+1 /St )
2
1
= ln e(1)Et [ln(Ct+1 /Ct )](1)Et [ln(St+1 /St )]+ 2 (1) V art [ln(Ct+1 /Ct )+ln(St+1 /St )]
(1 )2 2
[1 + (St )]2
= ln () + (1 ) g + (1 ) (1 ) ln S ln St
2
Substituting in for (St ) from (14.41), equation (14.45) becomes
r = ln () + (1 ) g
1
(1 ) (1 )
2
(14.46)
which, by construction, turns out to be constant over time. One can also derive
a relationship for the date t price of the market portfolio of all assets, denoted
Pt . Recall that since we have an endowment economy, aggregate consumption
410
equals the economys aggregate output, which equals the aggregate dividends
paid by the market portfolio. Therefore,
(14.47)
or, equivalently, one can solve for the price - dividend ratio for the market
portfolio.
Pt
Ct
Ct+1
Pt+1
= Et mt,t+1
1+
Ct
Ct+1
"
1
#
St+1
Ct+1
Pt+1
= Et
1+
St
Ct
Ct+1
(14.48)
"
1
1
!#
St+1
St+2
Ct+1
Ct+2
Pt+2
= Et
1+
1+
St
Ct
St+1
Ct+1
Ct+2
#
"
1
St+1
Ct+1
St+2
Ct+2
= Et
+ 2
+ ...
St
Ct
St
Ct
"
#
X i St+i 1 Ct+i
= Et
(14.49)
St
Ct
i=1
portfolio relative to current output, Pt /Ct , varies only with the current surplus
consumption ratio, St . By numerically calculating Pt /Ct as a function of St ,
12 Note that from (14.37) expected consumption growth, g, is a constant, but from (14.40) the
expected growth in the surplus consumption ratio, (1 ) ln S ln (St ) is mean-reverting.
411
Campbell and Cochrane can determine the market portfolios expected returns
and the standard deviation of returns as the level of St varies.
Note that in this model, the coecient of relative risk aversion is given by
Ct ucc
1
=
uc
St
(14.50)
and, as was shown in (4.32), the relationship between the Sharpe ratio for any
asset and the coecient of relative risk aversion when consumption is lognormally distributed is approximately:
E [ri ] r
Ct ucc c = (1 ) c
r
uc
St
i
(14.51)
which has a similar form to that of the Constantinides internal habit model
except, here, c is a constant and, for the case of the market portfolio E [ri ] and
ri will be time-varying functions of St . The coecient of relative risk aversion
will be relatively high when St is relatively low, that is, when consumption is
low (a recession). Moreover, the model predicts that the equity risk-premium
increases during a recession (when Ctuuccc is high), a phenomenon that seems to
be present in the post-war U.S. stock market. Campbell and Cochrane calibrate
the model to U.S. consumption and stock market data.13 Due to the dierent
(non-linear) specification for St vis-a-vis the model of Constantinides, they have
relatively more success in fitting this model to the data.
The next section introduces a class of time-inseparable utility that is much
dierent from habit persistence in that current utility depends on expected
future utility which, in turn, depends on future consumption.
Hence, unlike
habit persistence in which utility depends on past consumption and is backward13 They generalize the model to allow dividends on the (stock) market portfolio to dier from
consumption, so that dividend growth is not perfectly correlated with consumption growth.
Technically, this violates the assumption of an endowment economy but, empirically, there is
low correlation between growth rates of stock market dividends and consumption.
412
14.3
Recursive Utility
in a discrete-time setting, while Darrell Due and Larry Epstein (Due and
Epstein 1992a) study the continuous-time limit. In continuous-time, recall that
standard, time-separable utility can be written as:
Vt = Et
"Z
U (Cs , s) ds
(14.52)
Vt = Et
"Z
f (Cs , Vs ) ds
(14.53)
413
In the example to follow, we consider a form of recursive utility that is a generalization of standard power (constant relative risk aversion) utility in that it
separates an individuals risk-aversion from her elasticity of intertemporal substitution. This generalization is potentially important because, as was shown
in Chapter 4 equation (4.14), multi-period power utility restricts the elasticity
of intertemporal substitution, , to equal 1/ (1 ), the reciprocal of the coefficient of relative risk aversion. Conceptually, this may be a strong restriction.
Risk-aversion characterizes an individuals (portfolio) choices between assets of
dierent risks, and is well-defined concept even in an atemporal (single-period)
setting, as was illustrated in Chapter 1. In contrast, the elasticity of intertemporal substitution characterizes an individuals choice of consumption at dierent
points in time, and is inherently a temporal concept.
14.3.1
A Model by Obstfeld
following assumptions:
A.1 Technology:
A single capital-consumption good can be invested in up to two dierent
technologies. The first is a risk-free technology whose output, Bt , follows the
process
dB/B = rdt
(14.54)
d/ = dt + dz
(14.55)
414
Vt = Et
f (Cs , Vs ) ds
(14.56)
Cs
[Vs ]
f(Cs , Vs ) =
1
1 1 [Vs ] 1
(14.57)
Clearly, this specification is recursive in that current lifetime utility, Vt , depends on expected values of future lifetime utility, Vs , s > t. The form of equation (14.57) is ordinally equivalent to the continuous-time limit of the discretetime utility function specified in (Obstfeld 1994). Recall that utility functions
are ordinally equivalent, that is, they result in the same consumer choices, if the
utility functions evaluated at equivalent sets of decisions produce values that
are linear transformations of each other. It can be shown (see (Epstein and
Zin 1989) and (Due and Epstein 1992a)) that > 0 is the continuously compounded subjective rate of time preference,
415
Vt = Et
es
Cs
ds
(14.58)
dW = [( r)W + rW C] dt + W dz
(14.59)
J (Wt ) =
=
max Et
{Cs ,s }
max Et
{Cs ,s }
f (Cs , Vs ) ds
(14.60)
f (Cs , J (Ws )) ds
Since this is an infinite horizon problem with constant investment opportunities, and the aggregator function, f (C, V ), is not an explicit function of
calendar time, the only state variable is W .
The solution to the individuals consumption and portfolio choice problem
is given by the continuous-time stochastic Bellman equation
or
(14.61)
416
0 =
1
max f [C, J (W )] + JW [ ( r) W + rW C] + JW W 2 2 W 2 (14.62)
{Ct ,t }
2
1
C 1 [J]
1
= max
+ JW [ ( r) W + rW C] + JW W 2 2 W 2
1
1
2
{Ct ,t }
1 1 [J]
Taking the first order condition with respect to C,
C
[J]
1
1
JW = 0
(14.63)
or
C=
JW
[J]
(14.64)
JW ( r) W + JW W 2 W 2 = 0
(14.65)
or
JW r
JW W W 2
(14.66)
Substituting the optimal values for C and given by (14.64) and (14.66)
into the Bellman equation (14.62) we obtain the dierential equation:
+JW
"
JW
1
( 1)[1 1
]
[J]
[J]
1
1 1 [J] 1
JW ( r)2
+ rW
JW W
2
JW
[J]
(14.67)
2
1 JW
( r)2
=0
2 JW W
2
417
or
+JW
"
"
JW
[J]
JW
JW ( r)2
+ rW
JW W
2
[J]
(14.68)
2
1 JW
( r)2
=0
2 JW W
2
"
where
( r)2
+ (1 ) r +
2 (1 ) 2
#!
(14.69)
Thus, substituting this value for J into (14.64) we find that optimal consumption is a fixed proportion of wealth
= W
"
+ (1 ) r +
( r)
2 (1 ) 2
#!
(14.70)
W
r
(1 ) 2
(14.71)
which is the same as for an individual with standard constant relative riskaversion and time-separable utility. The result that the optimal portfolio choice
depends only on risk-aversion turns out to be an artifact of the models assumption that investment opportunities are constant. Harjoat Bhamra and Raman
Uppal (Bhamra and Uppal 2003) demonstrate that when investment opportu-
418
nities are stochastic, the portfolio weight, , can depend on both and .
Note that if = 1/ (1 ), then equation (14.70) is the same as optimal consumption for the time separable, constant relative risk aversion, infinite horizon
case given in equation (12.34). Similar to the time separable case, for an infinite
horizon solution to exist we need consumption to be positive in (14.70) which
14.3.2
For example,
2
Note that the term r + [ r] / 2 (1 ) 2 in (14.70) can be rewritten using
(14.71) as
r+
( r)2
r
=r+
2
2 (1 )
2
(14.72)
and can be interpreted as relating to the risk-adjusted investment returns available to individuals. From (14.70) we see that an increase in (14.72) increases
consumption when
> 1.
This result
< 1, the
dW/W
419
(14.73)
= [ ( r) + r ] dt + dz
"
!#
2
2
( r)
( r)
r
dz
=
+ r (1 ) r +
dt +
2
2
(1 )
2 (1 )
(1 )
"
!
#
( r)2
( r)2
r
=
r+
dz
+
dt +
2 (1 ) 2
2 (1 ) 2
(1 )
Since C = W , the drift and volatility of wealth in (14.73) are also the
drift and volatility of the consumption process, dC/C. Thus, consumption and
wealth are both lognormally distributed and their continuously-compounded
growth, d ln C, has a volatility, c , and mean, gc , equal to
c =
r
(1 )
(14.74)
and
gc
=
=
!
( r)2
( r)2
1
r+
+
2
2 (1 ) 2
2 (1 ) 2 2 c
!
( r)2
( r)2
r+
2 (1 ) 2
2 (1 )2 2
(14.75)
Also, consider how an economys rate varies with the squared Sharpe
2
ratio, [ r] /2 , a measure of the relative attractiveness of the risky asset.
= 1/ (1 ),
420
from (14.71) individuals put a large proportion of their wealth into the faster
growing risky asset as the Sharpe ratio rises, a higher Sharpe ratio leads to
greater consumption (and less savings) when
< 1.
For
< / (1 ), the
eect of less savings dominates the portfolio eect and the economy is expected
to grow slower.
Obstfeld points out that the integration of global financial markets that
allows residents to hold risky foreign, as well as domestic, investments increases
diversification and eectively reduces individuals risky portfolio variance, 2 .
This reduction in would lead individuals to allocate a greater proportion of
their wealth to the higher yielding risky assets.
If
> / (1 ), financial
market integration would also predict that countries will tend to grow faster.
It is natural to ask whether this recursive utility specification, which distinguishes between risk-aversion and the intertemporal elasticity of substitution,
can provide a better fit to historical asset returns compared to time separable
power utility. In terms of explaining the equity premium puzzle, from (14.74)
we see that the risky asset Sharpe ratio, ( r) /, equals (1 ) c , the same
form as with time separable utility.
need to assume that the coecient of relative risk aversion (1 ) is quite high
in order to justify the equity risk premium. However, recursive utility has more
hope of explaining the risk-free rate puzzle because of the additional degree of
freedom added by the elasticity of substitution parameter, . If we substitute
(14.74) into (14.75) and solve for the risk-free rate, we find
r =+
gc
h
i 2c
1+
2
(14.76)
14.4. SUMMARY
421
= 1/ (1 ) we have
2
r = + (1 ) gc (1 )
2c
2
(14.77)
state level (Beaudry and van Wincoop 1996) or at the household level (Attanasio
and Weber 1993) find higher estimates for , often around 1. From (14.76) we
see that a value of
assuming is small, could produce a reasonable value for the real interest rate.
14.4
Summary
The models presented in this chapter generalize the standard model of timeseparable, power utility.
sumption and portfolio choice problem can be solved using the same techniques
15 Philippe Weil ((Weil 1989)) appears to be the first to examine the equity premium and
risk-free rate puzzles in the context of recursive utility.
422
that were previously applied to the time-separable case. For utility that displays
habit persistence, we saw that the standard coecient of relative risk aversion,
(1 ), is transformed to the expression (1 ) /St where St < 1 is the surplus
consumption ratio. Hence, habit persistence can make individuals behave in a
very risk averse fashion in order to avoid consuming below their habit or subsistence level. As a result, these models have the potential to produce sucient
aversion to holding risky assets that could justify a high equity risk premium.
An attraction of recursive utility is that it distinguishes between an individuals level of risk aversion and his elasticity of intertemporal substitution, a
distinction that is not possible with time-separable, power utility which makes
these characteristics reciprocals of one another.
can permit an individual to have high risk aversion while, at the same time,
have a high elasticity of intertemporal substitution. Such a utility specification
has the potential to produce both a high equity risk premium and a low risk-free
interest rate that is present in historical data.
While recursive utility and utility displaying habit persistence might be considered non-standard forms of utility, they are preference specifications that are
considered to be those of rational individuals. In the next chapter, we study
utility that is influenced by psychological biases which might be described as
irrational behavior. Such biases have been identified in experimental settings
but have also been shown to be present in the actual investment behavior of
some individuals. We examine how these biases might influence the equilibrium
prices of assets.
14.5. EXERCISES
14.5
423
Exercises
dB/B
= rdt
dS1 /S1
= 1 dt + 1 dz1
dS2 /S2
= 2 dt + 2 dz2
where dz1 dz2 = dt. Also assume that the parameters are such that there
is an interior solution for the portfolio weights (all portfolio weights are
positive). What would be the optimal consumption and portfolio weights
for this case?
max
t=0
(Ct Xt )
2.b If consumption growth, Ct+1 /Ct follows an independent and identical distribution, is the one-period riskless interest rate, Rf,t constant over time?
424
Et
et ln (Ct Xt ) dt
dCt /Ct = dt + dz
1
1(Xt /Ct )
Ct
Ct Xt
dYt = k Y Yt dt (Yt ) dz
where Y > 1 is the long run mean of the inverse surplus, k > 0 reflects
the speed of mean reversion, > 0. The parameter sets a lower bound
for Yt , and the positivity of (Yt ) implies that a shock to the aggregate output (dividend-consumption) process decreases the inverse surplus
consumption ratio (and increases the surplus consumption ratio). Let Pt
be the price of the market portfolio. Derive a closed-form expression for
the price - dividend ratio of the market portfolio, Pt /Ct . How does Pt /Ct
vary with an increase in the surplus consumption ratio?
4. Consider an individuals consumption and portfolio choice problem when
her preferences display habit persistence. The individuals lifetime utility
satisfies
Et
"Z
es u (Cs , xs ) ds
(1)
14.5. EXERCISES
425
i = 1, ..., n
(2)
where dzi dzj = ij dt and i , i , and ij are constants. Thus, the individuals level of wealth, W , follows the process
dW =
n
X
i=1
i (i r)W dt + (rW Ct ) dt +
n
X
i W i dzi .
(3)
i=1
dx = f C t , xt dt
(4)
4.b Derive the first order conditions with respect to the portfolio weights, i .
Does the optimal portfolio proportion of risky asset i to risky asset j,
i / j , depend on the individuals preferences? Why or why not?
4.c Assume that the consumption, C t , in equation (4) is such that the individuals preferences display an internal habit, similar to the Constantinides
(1990) model. Derive the first order condition with respect to the individuals date t optimal consumption, Ct .
426
4.d Assume that the consumption, C t , in equation (4) is such that the individuals preferences display an external habit, similar to the Campbell
- Cochrane (1999) model.
Derive the first order condition with respect to the individuals date t
optimal consumption, Ct .
Part V
Additional Topics in Asset Pricing
Chapter 15
Incorporating
430
viduals.
Thaler 2002) describe the evidence for these behavioral phenomena. However,
to date there have been relatively few models that analyze how irrationality
might aect equilibrium asset prices. This chapter examines two recent behavioral asset pricing models.
The first is an intertemporal consumption and portfolio choice model by
Nicholas Barberis, Ming Huang, and Jesus Santos (Barberis, Huang, and Santos
2001) that incorporates two types of biases that are prominent in the behavioral
finance literature. They are loss aversion and the house money eect. These
biases fall within the general category of Prospect Theory. Prospect Theory
deviates from von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility maximization because
investor utility is a function of recent changes in, rather than simply the current
level of, financial wealth. In particular, investor utility characterized by Prospect
Theory may be more sensitive to recent losses than recent gains in financial
wealth, this phenomenon being referred to as loss aversion. Moreover, losses
following previous losses create more disutility than losses following previous
gains. After a run-up in asset prices, the investor is less risk-averse because
subsequent losses would be cushioned by the previous gains. This is the socalled house money eect.1
An implication of this intertemporal variation in risk-aversion is that after a
substantial rise in asset prices, lower investor risk aversion can drive prices even
higher. Hence, asset prices display volatility that is greater than that predicted
by observed changes in fundamentals, such as changes in dividends. This also
generates predictability in asset returns. A substantial recent fall (rise) in asset
prices increases (decreases) risk aversion and expected asset returns. It can also
1 This expression derives from the psychological misperception that a gamblers (unexpected) winnings are the casino houses money. The gambler views these winnings as dierent
from his initial wealth upon entering the casino. Hence, the gambler is willing to bet more
agressively in the future because if the houses money is lost, the disutility of this loss will be
small relative to the disutility of losing the same amount of his initial wealth.
431
imply a high equity risk premium because the excess volatility in stock prices
leads loss-averse investors to demand a relatively high average rate of return on
stocks.
Prospect theory assumes that investors are overly concerned with changes
in financial wealth, that is, they care about wealth changes more than would be
justified by how these changes aect consumption. This psychological notion
was advanced by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (Kahneman and Tversky
1979) and is based primarily on experimental evidence.2 For example, Richard
Thaler and Eric Johnson (Thaler and Johnson 1990) find that individuals faced
with a sequence of gambles are more willing to take risk if they have made
gains from previous gambles, evidence consistent with the house money eect.
However, in a recent study of the behavior of traders of the Chicago Board of
Trades Treasury bond futures, Joshua Coval and Tyler Shumway (Coval and
Shumway 2003) find evidence consistent with loss aversion but not the house
money eect.
The second model presented in this chapter examines how equilibrium asset prices are aected when some investors are rational but others suer from
systematic optimism or pessimism. Leonid Kogan, Stephen Ross, Jiang Wang,
and Mark Westerfied (Kogan, Ross, Wang, and Westerfield 2006) construct a
simple endowment economy where rational and irrational investors are identical except that the irrational investors systematically mis-perceive the expected
growth rate of the aggregate dividend process. Interestingly, it is shown that
this economy can be transformed into one where the irrational traders can be
viewed as acting rationally but that their utilities are state dependent.
This
432
not necessarily lose wealth to rational investors and be driven out of the asset
market.3
wealth relative to the rational individuals, so that they do not survive in the long
run, their trading behavior can significantly aect asset prices for substantial
periods of time.
We now turn to the Barberis, Huang, and Santos model, which generalizes
a standard consumption and portfolio choice to incorporate aspects of Prospect
Theory.
15.1
The Barberis, Huang, and Santos model is based on the following assumptions.
15.1.1
Assumptions
ln C t+1 /C t = gC + C t+1
(15.1)
t
0 1
N ,
t
0
1
(15.2)
The return on the risky asset from date t to date t + 1 is denoted Rt+1 . A oneperiod risk-free investment is assumed to be in zero-net supply, and its return
from date t to date t + 1 is denoted Rf,t .4 The equilibrium value for Rf,t is
derived below.
A.2 Preferences:
Representative, infinitely-lived individuals maximize lifetime utility of the
form
E0
"
X
t Ct
t+1
+ bt v (Xt+1 , wt , zt )
t=0
(15.3)
434
earned from holding the risky asset between date t and date t + 1. Specifically,
this risky asset gain is assumed to be measured relative to the alternative of
holding wealth in the risk-free asset and is given by:
(15.4)
zt = (1 ) + zt1
R
Rt
(15.5)
Xt+1 if Xt+1 0
v (Xt+1 , wt , 1) =
X
(15.6)
Xt+1
if Rt+1 zt Rf,t
v (Xt+1 , wt , zt ) =
(15.7)
The interpretation of this function is that when a return exceeds the cushion
built by prior gains, that is, Rt+1 zt Rf,t , it aects utility one-for-one. However, when the gain is less than the amount of prior gains, Rt+1 < zt Rf,t , it
has a greater than one-for-one impact on disutility. In the case of prior losses
(zt > 1), the function becomes
Xt+1
v (Xt+1 , wt , zt ) =
(z ) X
t+1
if Xt+1 0
(15.8)
if Xt+1 < 0
where (zt ) = + k (zt 1), k > 0. Here we see that losses that follow previous
losses are penalized at the rate, (zt ), which exceeds and grows larger as prior
losses become larger (zt exceeds unity).
Finally, the prospect theory term in the utility function is scaled to make the
risky asset price-dividend ratio and the risky asset risk premium be stationary
variables as aggregate wealth increases over time.6 The form of this scaling
factor is chosen to be
bt = b0 C t
(15.9)
the scaling factor, as wealth (output) grows at rate gD , the prospect theory term
would dominate the conventional constant relative risk aversion term.
7 Because C is assumed to be aggregate consumption, the individual views b as an exot
t
geneous variable.
436
15.1.2
The state variables for the individuals consumption - portfolio choice problem
are wealth, Wt , and zt . Intuitively, since the aggregate consumption - dividend
growth process in (15.1) is an independent, identical distribution, the dividend
level is not a state variable. We start by assuming that the ratio of the risky
asset price to its dividend is a function of only the state variable zt , that is
ft Pt /Dt = ft (zt ), and then show that an equilibrium exists in which this is
true.8 Given this assumption, the return on the risky asset can be written as
Rt+1
=
=
Pt+1 + Dt+1
1 + f (zt+1 ) Dt+1
=
Pt
f (zt )
Dt
1 + f (zt+1 ) gD +D t+1
e
f (zt )
(15.10)
zt < 1
Rt+1 Rf
if Rt+1 zt Rf
vb (Rt+1 , zt ) =
(15.11)
8 This is plausible because the standard part of the utility function displays constant relative
risk aversion. With this type of utility, optimal portfolio proportions would not be a function
of wealth.
Rt+1 Rf
if Rt+1 Rf
vb (Rt+1 , zt ) =
(z ) (R
t
t+1 Rf ) if Rt+1 < Rf
(15.12)
X
t Ct
t+1 1
+ b0 C t wt vb (Rt+1 , zt )
t=0
(15.13)
(15.14)
max E0
{Ct ,wt }
"
and the dynamics for zt given in (15.5). Define t J (Wt , zt ) as the derived utility
of wealth function. Then the Bellman equation for this problem is
h
i
Ct
1
+Et b0 C t wt vb (Rt+1 , zt ) + J (Wt+1 , zt+1 ) (15.15)
{Ct ,wt }
J (Wt , zt ) = max
Taking the first order conditions with respect to Ct and wt one obtains
(15.16)
h
i
1
0 = Et b0 C t vb (Rt+1 , zt ) + JW (Wt+1 , zt+1 ) (Rt+1 Rf )
1
= b0 C t
Et [b
v (Rt+1 , zt )] + Et [JW (Wt+1 , zt+1 ) Rt+1 ]
(15.17)
It is straightforward to show that (15.16) and (15.17) imply the standard envelope condition
438
Ct1 = JW (Wt , zt )
(15.18)
1 = Rf Et
"
Ct+1
Ct
1 #
(15.19)
h
i
h
i
1
1
Et [b
v (Rt+1 , zt )] + Et Ct+1
Rt+1 Rf Et Ct+1
h
i
1
1
= b0 C t Et [b
v (Rt+1 , zt )] + Et Ct+1
Rt+1 Ct1 /
(15.20)
1
0 = b0 C t
or
1 = b0
Ct
Ct
"
Et [b
v (Rt+1 , zt )] + Et Rt+1
Ct+1
Ct
1 #
(15.21)
Rf = e(1)gC 2 (1)
2C
(15.22)
v (Rt+1 , zt )] + Et
1 = b0 Et [b
or
1 + f (zt+1 ) gD +D t+1
e
1 = b0 Et vb
, zt
(15.24)
f (zt )
2 2
2
1
1 + f (zt+1 ) (D (1)C )t+1
e
+egD (1)gC + 2 (1) C (1 ) Et
f (zt )
1
and Rt+1 =
cally from (15.24). However, because zt+1 = 1 + zt RR
t+1
1+f(zt+1 ) gD + D t+1
,
f (zt ) e
(15.25)
Therefore, (15.24) and (15.25) need to be solved jointly. Barberis, Huang, and
Santos describe an iterative numerical technique for finding the function f ().
Given all other parameters, they guess an initial function, f (0) , and then use
it to solve for zt+1 in (15.25) for given zt and t+1 . Then, they find a new
candidate solution, f (1) , using the following recursion that is based on (15.24):
2 2
2
1
f (i+1) (zt ) = egD (1)gC + 2 (1) C (1 ) x
hh
i
i
Et 1 + f (i) (zt+1 ) e(D (1)C )t+1
(15.26)
where the expectations are computed using a Monte Carlo simulation of the
t+1 . Given the new candidate function, f (1) , zt+1 is again found from (15.25).
The procedure is repeated until the function f (i) converges.
440
15.1.3
Model Results
For reasonable parameter values, Barberis, Huang, and Santos find that Pt /Dt =
ft (zt ) is a decreasing function of zt . The intuition was described earlier: if there
were prior gains from holding the risky asset (zt is low), then investors become
less risk averse and bid up the price of the risky asset.
Using their estimate of f (), the unconditional distribution of stock returns
is simulated from a randomly generated sequence of t s. Because dividends and
consumption follow separate processes and stock prices have volatility exceeding
that of dividend fundamentals, the volatility of stock prices can be made substantially higher than that of consumption. Moreover, because of loss aversion,
the model can generate a significant equity risk premium for reasonable values
of the consumption risk aversion parameter .
explanation for the "equity premium puzzle." Because the investor cares about
stock volatility, per se, a large premium can exist even though stocks may not
have a high correlation with consumption.9
The model also generates predictability in stock returns: returns tend to be
higher following crashes and smaller following expansions. An implication of
this is that stock returns are negatively correlated at long horizons, a feature
documented by empirical research such as (Fama and French 1988), (Poterba
and Summers 1988), and (Richards 1997).
The Barberis, Huang, and Santos model is one with a single type of representative individual who suers from psychological biases. The next model that
we consider assumes that their are two types of representative individuals, ones
with rational beliefs and others with irrational beliefs regarding the economys
fundamentals.
15.2
The Kogan, Ross, Wang, and Westerfield model is based on the following assumptions.
15.2.1
Assumptions
The model is a simplified endowment economy with two dierent types of representative individuals, where one type of the individuals suers from irrational
optimism or pessimism regarding risky asset returns. Both types of individuals
maximize utility of consumption at a single, future date.10
A.1 Technology:
There is a risky asset that represents a claim on a single, risky dividend
payment made at the future date T > 0. The value of this dividend payment is
denoted DT , and it is the date T realization of the geometric Brownian motion
process
dDt /Dt = dt + dz
(15.27)
where and are constants, > 0, and D0 = 1. Note that while the process
in equation (15.27) is observed at each date t [0, T ], only its realization at
date T determines the risky assets single dividend payment, DT .
As with
442
date T . This bond is assumed to be in zero net supply, that is, the aggregate
net amount of risk-free lending or borrowing is zero. However, because there
are heterogeneous groups of individuals in the economy, some individuals may
borrow while others will lend.
A.2 Preferences:
All individuals in the economy have identical constant relative risk-aversion
utility defined over their consumption at date T .
dierent groups of representative individuals.
are rational traders who have a date 0 endowment equal to one-half of the risky
asset and maximize the expected utility function
E0
"
Cr,T
(15.28)
where Cr,T is the date T consumption of the rational traders and < 1. The
second group of individuals are irrational traders. They also possess a date 0
endowment of one-half of the risky asset but incorrectly believe that the probability measure is dierent from the actual one. Rather than thinking that the
aggregate dividend process is given by (15.27), the irrational traders incorrectly
perceive the dividend process is
z
dDt /Dt = + 2 dt + db
(15.29)
Therefore, an irrational
b0
E
"
Cn,T
(15.30)
15.2.2
Solution Technique
b0 [xT ] = E0 [ T xT ]/ 0
E
(15.31)
"
Cn,T
= E0
"
Cn,T
T
(15.32)
444
(15.33)
T = t e 2
2 2
(T t)+(zT zt )
(15.34)
From (15.32) and (15.34) we see that the objective function of the irrational
trader is observationally equivalent to that of a rational trader whose utility is
state dependent. The state variable aecting utility, the Brownian motion zt , is
the same source of uncertainty determining the risky assets dividend payment.
representative individuals, we can solve for an equilibrium where the representative individuals act competitively, taking the price of the risky asset and the
risk-free borrowing or lending rate as given. In addition, because there is only
a single source of uncertainty, that being the risky assets payo, the economy
is dynamically complete.
Given market completeness, let us apply the martingale pricing method introduced in Chapter 13. Each individuals lifetime utility function can be interpreted as of the form (12.54) but with interim utility of consumption equalling
zero and only a utility of terminal bequest being non-zero.
Hence, based on
equation (12.56), the result of each individuals static optimization is that his
= r MT
(15.35)
1
T Cn,T
= n MT
(15.36)
where r and n are the Lagrange multipliers for the rational and irrational
individuals, respectively. Substituting out for MT , we can write
1
Cr,T = ( T ) 1 Cn,T
(15.37)
where we define r /n . Also note that the individuals terminal consumption must sum to the risky assets dividend payment
Cr,T + Cn,T = DT
(15.38)
Equations (15.37) and (15.38) allow us to write each individuals terminal consumption as
Cr,T =
1
1
1 + ( T ) 1
DT
(15.39)
DT
(15.40)
Cn,T =
( T ) 1
1
1 + ( T ) 1
Similar to what was done in Chapter 13, the parameter = r /n is determined by the individuals initial endowments of wealth.
Each individuals
initial wealth is an asset that pays a dividend equal to the individuals terminal
consumption.
446
the date t price of the zero coupon bond that pays 1 at date T > t is given by
(15.41)
In what follows, we deflate all asset prices, including the individuals initial
wealths, by this zero coupon bond price. This is done for analytical convenience,
though it should be noted that using the zero coupon bond as the numeraire is
somewhat dierent from using the value of a money market investment as the
numeraire, as was done in Chapter 10. While the return on the zero coupon
bond over its remaining time to maturity is risk-free, its instantaneous return
will not, in general, be risk-free.
Let us define Wr,0 and Wn,0 as the initial wealths, deflated by the zero coupon
bond price, of the rational and irrational individuals, respectively. They equal
Wr,0
E0 [Cr,T MT ]
E0 [Cr,T MT /M0 ]
=
E0 [MT /M0 ]
E0 [MT ]
h
i
h
i
1
E0 Cr,T
E0 Cr,T Cr,T
/r
h
i =
h
i
1
1
E0 Cr,T
/r
E0 Cr,T
h
i
1
DT
E0 1 + ( T ) 1
h
i1
1
E0 1 + ( T ) 1
DT1
(15.42)
where in the second line of (15.42) we used (15.35) to substitute for MT and then
in the third line we used (15.39) to substitute for Cr,T . A similar derivation
that uses (15.36) and (15.40) leads to
Wn,0
h
i
1
1
DT
E0 ( T ) 1 1 + ( T ) 1
h
=
i1
1
1
1
E0 1 + ( T )
DT
(15.43)
Because it was assumed that the rational and irrational individuals are each
(15.44)
(15.45)
Given this value of , we have now determined the form of the pricing kernel
Define St as the
and can solve for the equilibrium price of the risky asset.
date t < T price of the risky asset deflated by the price of the zero coupon
bond.
T 12 2 2 (T t)+(zT zt )
Et [DT MT /Mt ]
=
St =
Et [MT /Mt ]
Et
Et
"
1
1
1 + T,t
"
1
1
1 + T,t
DT
DT1
(15.46)
While it is not possible to characterize in closed form the rational and irrational
individuals portfolio policies, we can still derive insights regarding equilibrium
asset pricing.13
15.2.3
12 Recall that it was assumed that D = 1. Note also that powers of / and D , such
0
T
T
0
as DT
, are also lognormally distributed.
13 Kogan, Ross, Wang, and Westerfield show that the individuals demand for the risky
asset, , satisfies the bound || 1 + || (2 ) / (1 ).
448
For the limiting case of there being only rational individuals, that is, = 0,
then T,t = t = 1 and from (15.46) the deflated stock price, Sr,t , is
Sr,t
2
2
Et [DT ]
h
i = Dt e[ ](T t)+ (T t)
1
Et DT
(15.47)
2
2
1
= e[(1) ]T +[(1) 2 ] t+(zt z0 )
A simple application of Its lemma shows that equation (15.47) implies that
the risky assets price follows geometric Brownian motion:
dSr,t /Sr,t = (1 ) 2 dt + dz
(15.48)
Similarly, when all individuals are irrational, the deflated stock price, Sn,t , is
2
2
2(T t)
1
Sn,t = e[(1) ]T +[(1) 2 ] t+(zt z0 ) = Sr,t e
(15.49)
dSn,t /Sn,t = (1 ) 2 dt + dz
Note that in (15.49) and (15.50) the eect of is similar to .
(15.50)
When all
greater demand raises the deflated stock price relative to that in an economy
with all rational individuals while equation (15.50) indicates that it also lowers
the stocks equilibrium expected rate of return.
It is also interesting to note that (15.48) and (15.50) indicate that when the
economy is populated by only one type of individual, the volatility of the risky
populate the economy, the risky assets volatility, S,t , always exceeds . Applying Its lemma to (15.46), Kogan, Ross, Wang, and Westerfield prove that
the risky assets volatility satisfies the following bounds14
S,t (1 + ||)
(15.51)
The conclusion is that a diversity of beliefs has the eect of raising the equilibrium volatility of the risky asset.
For the special case in which rational and irrational individuals have logarithmic utility, that is, = 0, then (15.46) simplifies to
St
1 + Et [ T ]
Et (1 + T ) DT1
2
= Dt e[ ](T t)
(15.52)
1 + t
1 + t e2 (T t)
1 2
1 2
= e[ 2 ]T 2 (T t)+(zt z0 )
1 + t
1 + t e2 (T t)
For this particular case, the risky assets expected rate of return and variance,
as a function of the distribution of wealth between the rational and irrational
individuals, can be derived explicitly. Define
Wr,t
Wr,t
=
Wr,t + Wn,t
St
(15.53)
as the proportion of total wealth own by the rational individuals. Using (15.42)
and (15.46), we see that when = 0 this ratio equals
14 The proof is given in Appendix B of (Kogan, Ross, Wang, and Westerfield 2006). Below,
we show that this bound is satisfied for the case of individuals with logarithmic utility.
450
t =
"
#
1
1
DT
1 + T,t
Et
Et
"
1
1
1 + T,t
DT
#=
1
1
=
1 + Et [ T ]
1 + t
(15.54)
S,t = +
and
"
t
1 + e2 (T t) 1
t 1
(15.55)
(15.56)
traders should control most of the economys wealth and asset prices should
reflect these rational individuals (correct) beliefs. The implication is that even
when some individuals are irrational, markets should evolve toward long-run
eciency because irrational individuals will be driven to "extinction."
Cn,T
T Cr,T
= 0 a.s.
(15.57)
Cn,T
T Cr,T
> equals
and an individual is said to survive relatively in the long run if relative extinction
does not occur.16
For the case of individuals having logarithmic utility, irrational individuals
always suer relative extinction. The proof of this is as follows. Rearranging
(15.37), we have
1
Cn,T
= ( T ) 1
Cr,T
(15.58)
= T
(15.59)
1
= e 2
2 2
T +(zT z0 )
Based on the strong Law of Large Numbers for Brownian motions, it can be
15 In
could also define the absolute extinction of the irrational individual. This would
occur if lim Cn,T = 0 almost surely, and an individual is said to survive absolutely in the long
T
run if absolute extinction does not occur. Relative survival is sucient for absolute survival,
but the converse is not true. Similarly, absolute extinction implies relative extinction, but
the converse is not true.
452
0 a<0
=
a>0
(15.60)
(15.61)
Et
1
1
ln (Wr,T /Wr,t ) =
[Et [ln (Wr,T )] ln (Wr,t )]
T t
T t
(15.62)
since Wr,t is known at date t and T t > 0. Equivalently from (15.62) the rational log utility individual follows a portfolio policy that maximizes Et [d ln Wr,t ]
at each point in time. The selected portfolio policy is referred to as the "growthoptimum portfolio," because it maximizes the (continuously-compounded) return on wealth.18 Now given that in the model economy there is a single source
of uncertainty aecting portfolio returns, dz, the processes for the rational and
17 See
dWr,t /Wr,t
= r,t dt + r,t dz
(15.63)
dWn,t /Wn,t
= n,t dt + n,t dz
(15.64)
where, in general, the expected rates of returns and volatilities, r,t , n,t , r,t ,
and n,t , are time varying. Applying Its lemma, it is straightforward to show
that the process followed by the log of the ratio of the individuals wealth is
d ln
Wn,t
Wr,t
1
1
n,t 2n,t r,t 2r,t dt + (n,t r,t ) dz
2
2
(15.65)
Given that the irrational individual chooses a portfolio policy that deviates from
the maximum growth portfolio, we know that Et [d ln Wn,t ] Et [d ln Wr,t ] < 0,
and thus Et [d ln (Wn,t /Wr,t )] < 0, making d ln (Wn,t /Wr,t ) a non-stationary
process whose limit as t is . Hence, the limiting value of Wn,t /Wr,t is
zero, which verifies Friedmans conjecture that irrational individuals lose wealth
to rational ones in the long run.
454
= ( T ) 1
(15.66)
2
1 2
= e[+ 2 ] 1 T + 1 (zT z0 )
Thus, we see that the limiting behavior of Cn,T /Cr,T is determined by the sign
Cn,T
lim
T Cr,T
0
<0
=
0 < < 2
0
2 <
(15.67)
conjecture.
The intuition for these results comes from our previous discussion of a log
utility investors choice of the growth optimal portfolio.
viduals are more risk-averse than log utility ( < 0), their demand for the risky
asset is less than would be chosen by a log utility investor.19 Certeris paribus,
the wealth of these < 0 investors would tend to grow slower than that of
someone with log utility. When < 0, irrationally pessimistic investors would
demand even less of the risky asset than their rational counterparts, which would
move them even further away from the growth optimal portfolio. Hence, in this
case, a rational individuals wealth would tend to grow faster than the wealth
19 For example, recall from Chapter 12s analysis of the standard consumption-portfolio
choice problem when investment opportunities are constant that equation (12.35), =
r
, implies that the demand for the risky asset decreases as risk aversion increases.
(1)2
(0 < < 2), her portfolio demand is closer to the growth optimal portfolio
than is the portfolio demanded by the rational individual. Therefore, in this
case the moderately optimistic individuals wealth grows faster than that of the
rational individual, so that the rational individual suers relative extinction in
the long run. In contrast, when the irrational individual is strongly optimistic
( > 2), her demand for the risky asset is so great that her portfolio choice is
further from the growth optimal portfolio than is the rational individual. For
this case the irrational individuals wealth tends to grow relatively slowly and,
as the pessimistic case, she does not survive in the long run.
The model outlined in this section is clearly a simplification of reality in
that it assumes that individuals gain utility from only terminal, not interim,
consumption.
In
general, an individuals portfolio choice, which aects his growth of wealth and
survivability, is determined by risk aversion as well as beliefs. Hence, systematic dierences between rational and irrational investors risk aversions could
influence the models conclusions. In addition, one might expect that irrational
individuals might learn over time of their mistakes since the historical distribution of the dividend process will tend to dier from their beliefs. The eect of
such learning may be that irrationality could diminish with age.20 Lastly, the
20 However, there is empirical psychological evidence (Lord, Ross, and Lepper 1979) showing
that individuals tend to persist too strongly in their initial beliefs after being exposed to
456
Yet, the main conclusions of the model, that irrational investors may
have a significant impact on asset prices and that they may not necessarily
become extinct, are likely to remain robust.
15.3
Summary
tempted to present two of the relatively few general equilibrium models that
incorporate psychological biases or irrationality.
can be solved using essentially the same techniques that previously were used
to derive models of rational, expected utility maximizing individuals.
Both
models embed rationality as a special case, which makes it easy to see how their
behavioral assumptions specifically aect the models results.
As of yet, there appears to be no consensus among financial economists regarding the importance of incorporating aspects of behavioral finance into asset
pricing theories. It is especially unclear whether a behavioral paradigm will be
universally successful in supplanting asset pricing theories built on expected utility. However, it is likely that research exploring the asset pricing implications
of behavioral biases will grow in coming years.
contrary information.
21 Recent models incorporating various forms of irrationality, (Barberis, Shleifer, and Vishny
1998), (Daniel, Hirshleifer, and Subrahmanyam 1998), and (Hong and Stein 1999), have been
constructed to explain the empirical phenomena that stock returns display short run positive
serial correlation (momentum) and the long run negative serial correlation (reversals or mean
reversion).
15.4. EXERCISES
15.4
457
Exercises
1. In the Barberis, Huang, and Santos model, verify that the first order
conditions (15.16) and (15.17) lead to the envelope condition (15.18).
2. In the Barberis, Huang, and Santos model, solve for the price - dividend
ratio, Pt /Dt , for Economy II when utility is standard constant relative
risk aversion, that is,
E0
"
t Ct
t=0
"
1
Cr,T
1
"
2
Cn,T
2
price of the risky asset deflated by the discount bond maturing at date T .
Chapter 16
16.1
The model by Sanford Grossman (Grossman 1976) that we consider in this section examines how an investors private information about a risky assets future
payo aects her demand for that asset and, in turn, the assets equilibrium
price. In addition, it takes account of the idea that a rational individual can
learn about others private information from the risky assets price, a concept
known as "price discovery." The model is based on the following assumptions.
1 More in-depth coverage of topics in this chapter include books by Maureen OHara
(OHara 1995) and Markus Brunnermeier (Brunnermeier 2001).
16.1.1
461
A.1 Assets
This is a single-period portfolio choice problem. At the beginning of the
period, traders can choose between a risk-free asset, which pays a known endof-period return (one plus the interest rate) of Rf , or a risky asset that has
a beginning-of-period price of P0 per share and has an end-of-period random
payo (price) of Pe1 per share. The unconditional distribution of Pe1 is assumed
to be normally distributed as N(m, 2 ). The aggregate supply of shares of the
but the risk-free asset is in perfectly elastic supply.
risky asset is fixed at X,
(16.1)
(16.2)
16.1.2
Let Xf i be the amount invested in the risk-free asset and Xi be the number of
shares of the risky asset chosen by the ith trader at the beginning of the period.
Thus,
W0i = Xf i + P 0 Xi .
(16.3)
i
P1 Rf P 0 Xi .
(16.4)
Denote Ii as the information available to the ith trader at the beginning of the
period. The traders maximization problem is then
i
h
h
1i ) | Ii = max E eai (Rf W0i
max E Ui (W
Xi
Xi
i
[ P1 Rf P 0 ]Xi ) | Ii . (16.5)
(16.6)
or
h
i
i
h
1
2
max Xi E P1 | Ii Rf P0 ai Xi Var P1 | Ii
.
Xi
2
(16.7)
The first-order condition with respect to Xi then gives us the optimal number
463
(16.8)
Equation (16.8) indicates that the demand for the risky asset is increasing in
its expected excess return but declining in its price variance and the investors
risk aversion. Note that the CARA utility assumption results in the investors
demand for the risky asset being independent of wealth.
16.1.3
A Competitive Equilibrium
Now consider an equilibrium in which each trader uses his knowledge of the
unconditional distribution of P1 along with the conditioning information from
his private signal, yi , so that Ii = {yi }. Then using Bayes rule and the fact
that P1 and yi are jointly normally distributed with a squared correlation 2i
2
, the ith traders conditional expected value and variance of P1 are2
2
+ 2i
i
h
E P1 | Ii
Var P1 | Ii
m + 2i (yi m)
(16.9)
2 (1 2i ).
Xi =
2 Note
m + 2i (yi m) Rf P0
.
ai 2 (1 2i )
1 , y
cov (P
i )
P y
i
1
(16.10)
t
2 + 2
i
= i .
n
X
m + 2 (yi m) Rf P0
(16.11)
# ," n
" n
#
X
1 X m + 2i (yi m)
1
X
=
.
Rf i=1 ai 2 (1 2i )
a 2 (1 2i )
i=1 i
(16.12)
=
=
ai 2 (1 2i )
i=1
X
n
n
X
m + 2i (yi m)
Rf P0
ai 2 (1 2i )
ai 2 (1 2i )
i=1
i=1
or
P0
From (16.12) we see that the price reflects a weighted average of the traders
conditional expectations of the payo of the risky asset. For example the weight
on the ith traders conditional expectation, m + 2i (yi m), is
1
ai 2 (1 2i )
,"
n
X
i=1
1
ai 2 (1 2i )
(16.13)
The more precise (higher i ) is trader is signal or the lower is his risk aversion
(more aggressively he trades), the more that the equilibrium price reflects his
expectations.
16.1.4
The solution for the price, P0 , in equation (16.12) can be interpreted as a competitive equilibrium: each trader uses information on his own signal and, in
465
equilibrium, takes the price of the risky asset as given in deciding on how much
to demand of the risky asset. However, this equilibrium neglects the possibility of individual traders obtaining information about other traders signals
from the equilibrium price itself, what practitioners call price discovery. In
this sense, the previous equilibrium is not a rational expectations equilibrium.
Why?
tion (16.10), using only information about their own signals, and the price in
(16.12) results.
would have the incentive to change his or her demand from that initially formulated in (16.10). This implies that equation (16.12) would not be the rational
expectations equilibrium price.
In equilibrium, the aggregate demand for the shares of the risky asset must
equal the aggregate supply, implying
i
h
n
E P1 | yi , P0 (y) Rf P0 (y)
X
=
.
h
i
X
ai Var P1 | yi , P0 (y)
i=1
(16.14)
Now one can show that a rational expectations equilibrium exists for the case
of the
i s
for i = 1, ..., n.
m + 2 (
2 (1 2 ) X
y m)
=
Rf
Rf
," n
#
X 1
a
i=1 i
(16.15)
where y
1X
2
yi and 2
2 .
n i=1
2 + n
2
n .
Now if individual traders demands are given by equation (16.10) but where
yi is replaced with y and i is replaced with , then by aggregating these de as in equation (16.11), we end up with
mands and setting them equal to X
the solution in equation (16.15), which is consistent with our initial assumption
that traders can invert P0 (y) to find y. Hence, P0 (y) in equation (16.15) is the
rational expectations equilibrium price of the risky asset.
Note that the information, y, reflected in the equilibrium price is superior to
any single traders private signal, yi . In fact, since y is a sucient statistic for
all traders information, it makes knowledge of any single signal, yi , redundant.
The equilibrium would be the same if all traders received the same signal, y
N (0,
2
n )
3 See
467
esting features in that it shows that prices can aggregate relevant information
to help agents make more ecient investment decisions than would be the case
if they relied solely on their private information and did not attempt to obtain
information from the equilibrium price itself.
However, as shown by Sanford Grossman and Joseph Stiglitz (Grossman
and Stiglitz 1980), this fully revealing equilibrium is not robust to some small
changes in assumptions. Real-world markets are unlikely to be perfectly ecient. For example, suppose each trader needed to pay a tiny cost, c, to obtain
his private signal, yi . With any finite cost of obtaining information, the equilibrium would not exist because each individual receives no additional benefit
from knowing yi given that they can observe y from the price. In other words,
a given individual does not personally benefit from having private (inside) information in a fully-revealing equilibrium. In order for individuals to benefit
from obtaining (costly) information, we need an equilibrium where the price is
only partially revealing. For this to happen, there needs to be one or more additional sources of uncertainty that add noise to individuals signals, so that
other agents cannot infer them perfectly. We now turn to an example of a noisy
rational expectations equilibrium.
16.1.5
Let us make the following changes to the Grossman models assumptions along
the lines of a model proposed by Bruce Grundy and Maureen McNichols (Grundy
4 This can be compared to semi-strong form market eciency where asset prices need only
reflect all public information.
the problem, we assume that the number of traders is very large. If we define
e as the per capita supply of the risky asset and let n go to infinity, then by the
X
e becomes zero, so
that in the limit as n , the correlation between e
i and X
Next, let us modify the type of signal received by each trader to allow for a
e + i
yi = P1 +
(16.16)
where
e N (0, 2 ) is the common error independent of P1 and, as before, the
e . Because of
idiosyncratic error i N(0, 2 ) and is independent of P1 and
the infinite number of traders, it is realistic to allow for a common error so that
traders, collectively, would not know the true payo of the risky asset.
Recall from the Grossman model that the rational expectations equilibrium
price in (16.15) was a linear function of y and X. In the current model, the
aggregate supply of the risky asset is not fixed, but random.
However, this
e
P0 = 0 + 1 y + 2 X
(16.17)
Pn
i
469
yi /n = P1 +
e.
Although some assumptions dier, trader is demand for the risky asset continues to be of the form (16.8).
equilibrium, investor is information set includes not only her private information but also the equilibrium price: Ii = {yi , P0 }. Given the assumed structure
e and yi , then investor
in (16.17) and the assumed normal distribution for Pe1 , X,
(16.18)
where
2
2
2 2
1
1 + + 2 X
=
1 2 + 2
2
1
1 2 + 2 21 2
2 + 2 + 2
2
= m 1 (0 1 m 2 X ) 2 m
(16.19)
0 + ( 1 Rf ) P0 + 2 y
h
i
aVar P1 | Ii )
(16.20)
1 Rf
0
i+
h
i P0 +
h 2
iy
aVar P1 | Ii )
aVar P1 | Ii )
aVar P1 | Ii )
h
where a 1/ limn
1
n
Pn
1
i ai
X=
0
1
1
+
P0
y
2 2
2
(16.21)
h 2
i
=
2
aVar P1 | Ii )
(16.22)
1
2X
i
= h
2
a 2X (2 + 2 ) + (1 /2 )2 2 2
(16.23)
Xi =
a
ai
1
X i
2
(16.24)
From (16.24) one sees that if there were no information dierences, each investor
would demand a share of the average supply of the risky asset, X, in proportion
to the ratio of the harmonic average of risk aversions to his own risk aversion.
However, unlike the fully revealing equilibrium of the previous section, the individual investor cannot perfectly invert the equilibrium price to find the average
471
signal in (16.17) due to the uncertain aggregate supply shift, X. Hence, individual demands do respond to private information as reflected by i . The ratio
1 /2 reflects the simultaneous equation problem faced by the investor in trying
to sort out a shift in supply, X, from a shift in aggregate demand generated by
y. From (16.23) we see that as 2 or 2 , so that investors private
signals become uninformative, then 1 /2 0 and private information has no
eect on demands or the equilibrium price. If, instead, 2 = 0, so that there
is no common error, then (16.23) simplifies to
1
1
=
2
a2
(16.25)
1
a
X
i
ai
ai 2
(16.26)
so that an individuals demand responds to her private signal in direct proportion to the signals precision and indirect proportion to her risk aversion.
16.2
Let us now consider another model with private information that is pertinent
to a security market organized by a market maker. This market maker, who
might be thought of as a specialist on a stock exchange or a security dealer in an
over-the-counter market, sets a risky assets price with the recognition that he
may be trading at that price with a possibly better-informed individual. Albert
"Pete" Kyle (Kyle 1985) developed this model, and it has been widely applied
to study market micro-structure issues. The model is similar to the previous
one in that the equilibrium security price partially reveals the better-informed
16.2.1
agents trade in an asset that has a random end of period liquidation value of
N p0 , 2v .
A.2 Liquidity Traders
Noise traders have needs to trade that are exogenous to the model. It is
assumed that they, as a group, submit a market order to buy u shares of
473
cannot distinguish what part of this total order consists of orders made by noise
traders and what part consists of the order of the insider.
anonymous.) The market maker sets the market price, p, and then takes the
position (e
u+x
e) to clear the market. It is assumed that market making is
a perfectly competitive profession, so that the market maker sets the price p
such that, given the total order submitted, his profit at the end of the period is
expected to be zero.
16.2.2
Since the noise traders order is exogenous, we need only consider the optimal
actions of the market maker and the insider.
The market maker observes only the total order flow, u + x. Given this
information, he must then set the equilibrium market price p that gives him
zero expected profits. Since his end of period profits are (
p) (u + x), this
implies that the price set by the market maker satisfies
p = E [
| u + x]
(16.27)
The information on the total order size is important to the market maker. The
more positive is the total order size, the more likely it is that x is large due to
the insider knowing that is greater than p0 . Thus, the market maker would
7 This assumption can be weakened to the case of the insider having uncertainty over
but having more information on than the other traders. One can also allow the insider to
submit limit orders, that is, orders that are a function of the equilibrium market price (a
demand schedule), as in another model by Pete Kyle (Kyle 1989).
lower than otherwise. Thus, the pricing rule of the market maker is a function
of x + u, that is, P (x + u).
Since the insider sets x, it is an endogenous variable that depends on .
The insider chooses x to maximize his expected end of period profits,
, given
knowledge of and the way that the market maker behaves in setting the
equilibrium price:
| ] = maxE [( P (x + u)) x | ]
maxE [
x
(16.28)
)) x | ] = maxE [( (x + u
)) x | ] (16.29)
maxE [( P (x + u
x
= max ( x) x, since E [
u] = 0
x
475
x = +
and =
where = 2
1
2 .
(16.30)
setting rule, the optimal trading strategy for the insider is a linear trading rule.
Next, let us return to the market makers problem of choosing the market price
that, conditional on knowing the total order flow, results in a competitive (zero)
expected profit. Given the assumption that market making is a perfectly competitive profession, a market maker needs to choose the best possible estimate
of E [
| u + x] in setting the price p = E [
| u + x]. What estimate of the mean
of is best? The maximum likelihood estimate of E [
| u + x] is best in the
sense that it attains maximum eciency and is also the minimum variance unbiased estimate.
Note that if the insider follows the optimal trading strategy, which according
to equation (16.30) is x = +
, then from the point of view of the market
maker, and y u
+x = u
+ +
are jointly normally distributed. Because
and y are jointly normal, the maximum likelihood estimate of the mean of
conditional on y is linear in y, that is, E [
| y] is linear in y when they are
jointly normally distributed. Hence, the previously assumed linear pricing rule
is, in fact, optimal in equilibrium. Therefore, the market maker should use the
maximum likelihood estimator, which in the case of and y being normally
distributed is equivalent to the least squares estimator. This is the one that
minimizes
i
h
i
h
y)2
E (
P (y))2 = E (
h
i
= E (
(
u + +
))2
(16.31)
(16.32)
i
h
Recalling the assumptions E [] = p0 , E ( p0 )2 = 2v , E [u] = 0, E u2 =
2 2
v
min (1 )
,
+ p20 + ( + )2 + 2 2u 2 ( + ) (1 ) p0 (16.33)
= + p0 (1 )
(16.34)
0 = 2 (1 ) 2v + p20 + 2 ( + ) + 2 2u
2p0 [ ( + ) + (1 )]
(16.35)
2v
2 2v + 2u
and =
Substituting in for the definitions = 2
(16.36)
1
2
477
we have
= p0
1
2
v
u
(16.37)
(16.38)
p = p0 +
1
2
v
(
u + x)
u
(16.39)
x=
16.2.3
u
(
p0 )
v
(16.40)
From (16.40), we see that the greater is the volatility (amount) of noise trading,
u , the larger is the magnitude of the order submitted by the insider for a given
deviation of from its unconditional mean. Hence, the insider trades more
actively on his private information the greater is the camouflage provided by
noise trading.
maker to extract the signal of insider trading from the noise. Note that if
equation (16.40) is substituted into (16.39), one obtains
v
+ 12 (
p0 )
p = p0 + 12 u
u
v
u + p0 +
= 12
u
(16.41)
1
2
reflected in the equilibrium price, so that the price is not fully revealing.8
, is
To
E [
] = E [x ( p)] = E
u
(
p0 ) 12
v
v
u
p0
u
(16.42)
E [
| ] =
1
2
u
( p0 )2
v
(16.43)
Hence, the larger is s deviation from p0 , the larger the expected profit. Unconditional on knowing , that is, before the start of the period, the insider
expects a profit of
E [
] =
1
2
i
u h
E (
p0 )2 = 12 u v
v
(16.44)
which is proportional to the standard deviations of noise traders order and the
end of period value of .
Since, by assumption, the market maker sets the security price in a way that
gives him zero expected profits, the expected profits of the insider equals the
expected losses of the noise traders. In other words, it is the noise traders, not
the market maker, that lose, on average, from the presence of the insider.
From equation (16.39), we see that =
8A
1 v
2 u
16.3. SUMMARY
479
maker raises the price when the total order flow, (u + x), goes up by 1 unit.9
This can be thought of as relating to the securitys bid-ask spread, that is, the
dierence the price for sell orders versus buy orders, though here sell and buy
prices are not fixed but are a function of the order size since the pricing rule is
linear. Moreover, since the amount of order flow necessary to raise the price
by $1 equals 1/ = 2 uv , the model provides a measure of the depth of the
market or market liquidity. The higher is the proportion of noise trading to
the value of insider information,
u
v ,
Intuitively, the more noise traders relative to the value of insider information,
the less the market maker needs to adjust the price in response to a given
order, since the likelihood of the order being that of a noise trader, rather
than an insider, is greater. While the greater is the number of noise traders
(that is, the greater is u ), the greater is the expected profits of the insider
(see equation (16.44)) and the greater is the total expected losses of the noise
traders. However, the expected loss per individual noise trader falls with the
greater level of noise trading.10
16.3
Summary
The models considered in this chapter analyze the degree to which private information about an assets future payo or value is reflected in the assets current
price. An investors private information aects an assets price by determining
the investors desired demand (long or short position) for the asset, though the
investors demand also is tempered by risk-aversion. More subtly, we saw that a
rational investor can also learn about the private information of other investors
through the assets price itself, and this price discovery aects the investors
9 It is now common in the market microstructure literature to refer to this measure of order
flow and liquidity as "Kyles lambda."
10 Gary Gorton and George Pennacchi (Gorton and Pennacchi 1993) derive this result by
modeling individual liquidity traders.
16.4
Exercises
1. Show that the maximization problem in (16.7) is equivalent to the maximization problem in (16.5).
2. Show that the results in (16.9) can be derived from Bayes Rule and the
assumption that P1 and yi are normally distributed.
3. Consider a special case of the Grossman model. Traders can choose between holding a risk-free asset, which pays an end-of-period return of Rf ,
or a risky asset that has a beginning of period price of P0 per share and
has an end-of-period payo (price) of Pe1 per share. The unconditional dis
16.4. EXERCISES
481
There are two dierent traders who maximize expected utility over end-off1i , i = 1, 2. The form of the ith traders utility function
period wealth, W
is
i1i
f1i = eai W
Ui W
, ai > 0.
At the beginning of the period, the ith trader observes yi which is a noisy
signal of the end-of-period value of the risky asset
where
i N
yi = Pe1 + ei
1 2]
=0.
3.a Suppose each trader does not attempt to infer the other traders information from the equilibrium price, P0 . Solve for each of the traders demands
for the risky asset and the equilibrium price, P0 .
3.b Now suppose each trader does attempt to infer the others signal from the
equilibrium price, P0 . What will be the rational expectations equilibrium
price in this situation? What will be each of the traders equilibrium
demands for the risky asset?
4. In the Kyle (1985) model, replace the original assumption A.3 with the
following new one:
A.3 Better-Informed Traders
The single risk-neutral insider is assumed have better information than
the other agents. He observes a signal of the assets end-of-period value
equal to
s = ve + e
is distributed independently of u
where e
~N 0, 2s , 0 < 2s < 2v , and e
and . The insider does not observe u
, but chooses to submit a market
order of size x that maximizes his expected end-of-period profits.
4.a Suppose that the market makers optimal price setting rule is a linear
function of the order flow
p = + (u + x) .
Write down the expression for the insiders expected profits given this
pricing rule.
4.b Take the first order condition with respect to x and solve for the insiders
optimal trading strategy as a function of the signal and the parameters of
the market makers pricing rule.
Chapter 17
466
are the models "output." The second section covers models that value fixedincome derivatives, such as interest rate caps and swaptions, in terms a given set
of bond prices. In contrast, these models take the term structure of observed
bond prices as the input and have derivative values as the models output.
17.1
Equilibrium term structure models describe the prices (or, equivalently, the
yields) of dierent maturity bonds as functions of one or more state variables or
"factors." The Vasicek (Vasicek 1977) model, introduced in Chapter 9 (see equation 9.28), and the Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985b)
model, presented in Chapter 13 (see equation 13.51) were examples of singlefactor models. The single factor in the Vasicek model was the instantaneous
maturity interest rate, denoted r (t), which was assumed to follow the OrnsteinUhlenbeck process (9.17). In Cox, Ingersoll, and Rosss one-factor model, the
factor determined the expected returns of the economys production processes,
and, in equilibrium, the instantaneous maturity interest rate was proportional
to this factor and inherited its dynamics. This interest rate followed the square
root process in equation (13.49).
Let us generalize the pricing relationships for default-free zero-coupon bonds
by considering a situation where multiple factors determine their prices. The
derivation of these bond values will utilize our results from earlier chapters. We
start by assuming that there are n state variables, xi , i = 1, ..., n, that follow
the multi-variate diusion process
dx = a (t, x) dt + b (t, x) dz
(17.1)
where x = (x1 ...xn )0 , a (t, x) is a nx1 vector, b (t, x) is a nxn matrix, and
467
(17.2)
where
0
0
p (t, T, x) = a (t, x) Px + Pt + 12 Trace b (t, x) b (t, x) Pxx /P (t, T, x)
(17.3)
(17.4)
and where Px is an n 1 vector whose ith element equals the partial derivative
Pxi , Pxx is an nxn matrix whose i, j th element is second order partial derivative
Pxi xj , and Trace[A] is the sum of the diagonal elements of a square matrix A.
Similar to the Black-Scholes hedging argument discussed in Chapter 9 and
applied to derive the Vasicek model, we can form a hedge portfolio of n+1 bonds
having distinctly dierent maturities. By appropriately choosing the portfolio
weights for these n + 1 bonds, the n sources of risk can be hedged so that the
portfolio generates a riskless return. In the absence of arbitrage, this portfolios
return must equal the riskless rate, r (t, x). Making this no-arbitrage restriction
produces the implication that each bonds expected rate of return must satisfy
1 As discussed in Chapter 10, the independence assumption is not important. If there are
correlated sources of risk (Brownian motions), they can be re-defined by a linear transformation to be represented by n orthogonal risk sources.
468
(17.5)
1
2 Trace
0
0
b (t, x) b (t, x) Pxx + [a (t, x) b (t, x) ] Px rP + Pt = 0 (17.6)
Given functional forms for a (t, x), b (t, x), (t, x), r (t, x), this PDE can be
solved subject to the boundary condition P (T, T, x) = 1. Note that equation
(17.6) depends on the expected changes in the factors under the risk-neutral
measure Q, a (t, x) b (t, x) , rather than the factors expected changes under
the physical measure P , a (t, x).
specify only the factors risk-neutral processes.2 This insight is not surprising
because we saw in Chapter 10 that the Feynman-Kac solution to this PDE is
the risk-neutral pricing equation (10.58).
h R
i
bt e tT r(s,x)ds 1
P (t, T, x) = E
(17.7)
In addition to the pricing relations (17.6) and (17.7), we saw that a third pricing
approach can be based on the pricing kernel that follows the process
(17.8)
In this case, pricing can be accomplished under the physical measure based on
2 However, if the factors are observative variables for which data are available, it may be
necessary to specify their physical processes if empirical implementations of the model require
estimates for a (x, t) and b (x, t).
M (T )
P (t, T, x) = Et 1
M (t)
469
(17.9)
Thus far, we have placed few restrictions on the factors and their relationship
to the short rate, r (t, x), other than to assume that the factors follow the Markov
diusion processes (17.1). Let us next consider some popular parametric forms.
17.1.1
Ane Models
We start with models in which the yields of zero coupon bonds are linear
or "ane" functions of state variables.
of Vasicek (Vasicek 1977) and Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross (Cox, Ingersoll, and
Ross 1985b).
formulae that are relatively easy to compute and because the parameters of the
state variable processes can often be estimated using relatively straightforward
econometric techniques.
Recall that a zero-coupon bonds continuously compounded yield, Y (t, T, x),
is defined from its price by the relation
P (t, T, x) = eY (t,T,x)(T t)
(17.10)
One popular class of models assumes that zero-coupon bonds continuouslycompounded yields are ane functions of the factors. Defining the time until
maturity as T t, this assumption can be written as
0
Y (t, T, x) = A ( ) + B ( ) x
(17.11)
470
of (17.11) is that the short rate is also ane in the factors since
A ( ) + B ( )0 x
0
(17.12)
0
1
2 B ( )
)
+ A(
+
B( )0
x
= + 0 x
(17.13)
Darrell Due and Rui Kan (Due and Kan 1996) characterize sucient conditions for a solution to equation (17.13).
are that the factors risk-neutral instantaneous expected changes and variances
are ane in x.
variances are ane in the state variables, so will the equilibrium bond price
yields. These conditions can be written as
(17.14)
p
b (t, x) = s (x)
(17.15)
(17.16)
471
where soi is a scalar constant and s1i is an nx1 vector of constants. Now, because the state variables covariance matrix equals b (t, x) b (t, x)0 = s (x) 0 ,
additional conditions are needed to ensure that this covariance matrix remains
positive definite for all possible realizations of the state variable, x. Qiang Dai
and Kenneth Singleton (Dai and Singleton 2000) and Darrell Due, Damir Filipovic, and Walter Schachermayer (Due, Filipovic, and Schachermayer 2002)
derive these conditions.3
Given (17.14), (17.15), and (17.16), the partial dierential equation in (17.13)
can be re-written as
0
0
1
2 B ( ) s (x) B ()
[ (xx)]0 B () +
A ( ) B ( )0
+
x
= + 0 x
(17.17)
Note that this equation is linear in the state variables, x. For the equation to
hold for all values of x, the constant terms in the equation must sum to zero
and the terms multiplying each element of x must also sum to zero.
These
conditions imply
A ( )
B ( )
= + (x)0 B ( )
= 0 B ()
1
2
1
2
n
P
i=1
n
P
[0 B ( )]i s0i
(17.18)
[0 B ()]i s1i
(17.19)
i=1
where [0 B ()]i is the ith element of the nx1 vector 0 B ( ). Equations (17.18)
and (17.19) are a system of first order ordinary dierential equations that can
3 These conditions can have important consequences regarding the correlation between the
state variables. For example, if the state variables follow a multivariate Ornstein Uhlenbeck
process, so that the model is a multifactor version of the Vasicek model given in (9.28), (9.29),
and (9.30), then any general correlation structure between the state variables is permitted.
However, if the state variables follow a multivariate square-root process, so that the model
is a multifactor version of the Cox, Ingersoll and Ross model given in (13.51), (13.52), and
(13.53), then the correlation between the state variables must be non-negative.
472
(17.20)
(Dai and Singleton 2000) study the "completely ane" case where both the
physical and risk-neutral drifts are ane, while Gregory Duee (Duee 2002)
and Jeerson Duarte (Duarte 2004) consider extensions of the physical drifts
that permit nonlinearities.4 Because the means, volatilities, and risk premia of
bond prices estimated from time series data depend on the physical moments
of the state variables, the flexibility in choosing the parametric form for can
allow the model to better fit historical bond price data.
p
and Singleton analyze = s (x) 1 where 1 is an nx1 vector of constants. Duffee considersqthe "essentially ane" modeling of the market price of risk of the form =
p
s (x) 1 + s (x) 2 x, where s (x) is an nxn diagonal matrix whose ith element equals
soi + s01i x
if inf soi + s01i x > 0, zero otherwise, and 2 is an nxn matrix of constants.
This specification allows time variation in the market prices of risk for Gaussian state variables (such as state variables that follow Ornstein-Uhlenbeck processes), allowing their signs
to switch over time. Duarte extend Duees modeling to add a square
q root term. This "semi
p
ane square-root" model takes the form = 1 0 + s (x) 1 + s (x) 2 x where 2 is
an nx1 vector of constants. See, also, work by Patrick Cheridito, Damir Filipovic, and Robert
Kimmel (Cheridito, Filipovic, and Kimmel 2003) for extensions in modeling the market price
of risk for ane models.
4 Dai
17.1.2
473
Quadratic-Gaussian Models
Another class of models assumes that the yields of zero coupon bonds are
quadratic functions of state variables.
Y (t, T, x) = A () + B ( )0 x + x0 C ( ) x
(17.21)
0
exp A ( ) B () x x0 C ( ) x into the general partial dierential equation
(17.6), we obtain
[a (t, x) b (t, x) ]0 [B ( ) + 2C ( ) x]
A () B ()0
C ( )
+
x+ x0
x
= + 0 x + x0 x
(17.22)
474
(17.23)
b (t, x) =
(17.24)
Substituting these assumptions into the partial dierential equation (17.22), one
obtains
1
2
[B ( ) + 2C ( ) x]0 0 [B () + 2C () x]
Trace [0 C ( ) ] [ (xx)]0 [B ( ) + 2C ( ) x]
+
A ( ) B ( )0
C ()
+
x+ x0
x
= + 0 x + x0 x
(17.25)
For this equation to hold for all values of x, it must be the case that the sums of
the equations constant terms, the terms proportional to the elements of x, and
the terms that are products of the elements of x must each equal zero. This
leads to the system of first order ordinary dierential equations
A ( )
= + (x)0 B ( ) 12 B ( )0 0 B () + Trace [0 C ( ) ]
(17.26)
B ( )
C ( )
= 0 B ( ) 2C ( )0 0 B () + 2C ()0 x
(17.27)
= 20 C () 2C ()0 0 C ( )
(17.28)
475
Gallant (Ahn, Dittmar, and Gallant 2002) show that the models of Francis
Longsta (Longsta 1989), David Beaglehole and Mark Tenney (Beaglehole
and Tenney 1992), and George Constantinides (Constantinides 1992) are special cases of quadratic-gaussian models.
For
fectively allows one to observe the individual state variables from the observed
yields.
example, if n = 1, there are two state variable roots of the quadratic yield equation.
476
17.1.3
Term structure models have been modified to allow state variable processes to
dier from strict diusions. Such models can no longer rely on the Black-Scholes
hedging argument to identify market prices of risk and a risk-neutral pricing
measure.
these models need to make additional assumptions regarding the market prices
of risks that cannot be hedged.
A number of researchers, including Chang-Mo Ahn and Howard Thompson (Ahn and Thompson 1988), Sanjiv Das and Silverio Foresi (Das and Foresi
1996), Darrell Due, Jun Pan, and Kenneth Singleton (Due, Pan, and Singleton
2000), Sanjiv Das (Das 2002), and George Chacko and Sanjiv Das (Chacko and
Das 2002), have extended equilibrium models to allow state variables to follow
jump-diusion processes. An interesting application of a model with jumps in
a short-term interest rate is presented by Monika Piazzesi (Piazzesi 2005) who
studies changes in the federal funds rate made by the Federal Reserve.
Other ane equilibrium models have been set in discrete-time, where the
assumed existence of a discrete-time pricing kernel allows one to find solutions
for equilibrium bond prices that have a recursive structure. Examples of models
of this type include work by Tong-Sheng Sun (Sun 1992), David Backus and
Stanley Zin (Backus and Zin 1994), and V. Cvsa and Peter Ritchken (Cvsa and
Ritchken 2001). Term structure models also have been generalized to include
discrete regime shifts in the processes followed by state variables. See work by
Vasant Naik and Moon Hoe Lee (Naik and Lee 1997) and Ravi Bansal and Hao
Zhou (Bansal and Zhou 2002) for models of this type.
Let us now turn to term structure models whose primary purpose is not
to determine the term structure of zero coupon bond prices as a function of
477
17.2
Models for valuing bonds and bond derivatives have dierent uses. The equilibrium models of the previous section can provide insights as to the nature
of term structure movements. They allow us to predict how factor dynamics
will aect the prices of bonds of dierent maturities. Equilibrium models may
also be of practical use to bond traders who wish to identify bonds of particular
maturities whose market valuations appear to be over- or under-priced based on
their predicted model prices. Such information could suggest profitable bond
trading strategies.
However, bond prices are modeled for other objectives, such as the pricing
of derivatives whose payos depend on the future prices of bonds or yields.
Equilibrium models may be less than satisfactory for this purpose because it is
bond derivatives, not the underlying bond prices themselves, that one wishes to
value. In this context, one would like to use observed market prices for bonds
as an input into the valuation formulas for derivatives, not model the value of
the underlying bonds themselves.
would like the model to "fit," or be consistent with, the market prices of the
underlying bonds.
In a discrete-time, binomial model setting, Thomas Ho and Sang Bin Lee
((Ho and Lee 1986)) first introduced the concept of pricing fixed-income derivatives by taking the initial term structure of bond prices as given and then
making assumptions regarding the risk-neutral distribution of future interest
478
rates. This binomial approach was modified for dierent risk-neutral interest
rate distributions by Fischer Black, Emanuel Derman, and William Toy (Black,
Derman, and Toy 1990) and Fischer Black and Piotr Karasinski (Black and
Karasinski 1991). While these binomial models are not covered in this chapter,
we will discuss a similar approach that is set in continuous time. It shares the
characteristics of fitting the currently observed market prices of bonds and of
making particular assumptions regarding the risk-neutral distribution of future
interest rates.
17.2.1
Heath-Jarrow-Morton Models
The approach by David Heath, Robert Jarrow, and Andrew Morton ((Heath,
Jarrow, and Morton 1992)), hereafter referred to as HJM, diers from the previous equilibrium term structure models because it does not begin by specifying
a set of state variables, x, that determines the current term structure of bond
prices. Rather, their approach takes the initial term structure of bond prices as
given (observed) and then specifies how this term structure evolves in the future
in order to value derivatives whose payos depend on future term structures.
Because models of this type do not derive the term structure from more basic
state variables, they cannot provide insights regarding how economic fundamentals determine the maturity structure of zero-coupon bond prices. Instead,
HJM models are used to value fixed-income derivative securities: securities such
as bond and interest rate options whose payos depend on future bond prices
or yields.
An analogy to the HJM approach can be drawn from the risk-neutral valuation of equity options. Recall that in Chapter 10 equation (10.47), we assumed
that the risk-neutral process for the price of a stock, S (t), was geometric Brownian motion, making this price lognormally distributed under the risk-neutral
479
measure. From this assumption, and given the initial price of the stock, S (t),
the Black-Scholes formula for the value of a call option written on this stock
was derived in equations (10.51) and (10.52). Note that we did not attempt to
determine the initial value of the stock in terms of some fundamental state variables, say S (t, x). Rather, the initial stock price, S (t), was taken as given and
an assumption about this stock prices volatility, namely that it was constant
over time, was made.
The HJM approach to valuing fixed-income derivatives is similar but slightly
more complex because it takes as given the entire initial term structure of bond
prices, P (t, T ) T 1, not just a single asset price.
neutral processes for how this initial set of bond prices change over time and
does not attempt to derive these initial prices in terms of state variables, say
P (t, T, x).
bond prices is somewhat indirect. They begin by specifying processes for bond
forward rates. A fundamental result of the HJM analysis is to show that, in the
absence of arbitrage, there must be a particular relationship between the drift
and volatility parameters of forward rate processes and that only an assumption
regarding the form of forward rate volatilities is needed for pricing derivatives.
Let us start by defining forward rates. Recall from Chapter 7 that a forward
contract is an agreement between two parties where the long (short) party agrees
to purchase (deliver) an underlying asset in return for paying (receiving) the
forward price.
480
the value of these two cashflows at date t must sum to zero, implying
(17.29)
so that the equilibrium forward price equals the ratio of the bond prices maturing
at dates T + and T , F (t, T, ) = P (t, T + ) /P (t, T ).
ef(t,T, ) F (t, T, ) =
P (t, T + )
P (t, T )
(17.30)
forward contract where the underlying bond matures very shortly (e.g., the next
day or instant) after the maturity of the forward contract. This permits us to
define an instantaneous forward rate as
ln [P (t, T )]
ln [P (t, T + )] ln [P (t, T )]
=
T
(17.31)
P (t, T ) = e
RT
t
f (t,s)ds
(17.32)
481
(17.33)
prices, P (t, T ), implied by the forward rate processes. Note that since ln [P (t, T )]
RT
= t f (t, s) ds, if we dierentiate with respect date t, we find that the process
RT
d ln [P (t, T )] = f (t, t) dt t df (t, s) ds
(17.34)
RT
d ln [P (t, T )] = r (t) dt
RT
t
(t, s) dsdt
RT
t
RT
t
482
RT
t
t. Using Its lemma we can derive the bonds rate of return process from the
log process in (17.35).
1
dP (t, T )
= r (t) I (t, T ) + I (t, T )0 I (t, T ) dt I (t, T )0 dz (17.36)
P (t, T )
2
Now recall from (17.5) that the absence of arbitrage requires that the bonds
expected rate of return equal the instantaneous risk-free return plus the product
of the bonds volatilities and the market prices of risk. This is written as
1
r (t) I (t, T ) + I (t, T )0 I (t, T ) = r (t) (t) 0 I (t, T )
2
(17.37)
or
1
0
I (t, T ) = I (t, T ) I (t, T ) + (t) 0 I (t, T )
2
(17.38)
Equation (17.36) and (17.38) shows that the bond price process depends only
on the instantaneous risk-free rate, the volatilities of the forward rates, and the
market prices of risk.
df (t, T ) =
0
0
(t, T ) (t, T ) (t) dt + (t, T ) db
z
=
b (t, T ) dt + (t, T )0 db
z
(17.39)
where
b (t, T ) (t, T ) (t, T )0 (t) is the risk-neutral drift observed at
RT
b (t, s) ds as the
date t for the forward rate at date T . Define
b I (t, T ) t
integral over the drifts of all forward rates from date t to date T . Then using
483
(17.38) we have
b I (t, T ) =
RT
t
b (t, s) ds =
RT
t
(t, s) ds
or
RT
t
b (t, s) ds =
RT
1
I (t, T )0 I (t, T ) + (t) 0 I (t, T ) (t) 0 I (t, T )
2
1
I (t, T )0 I (t, T )
(17.40)
2
1
2
R
T
t
0 R
T
(t, s) ds
(t,
s)
ds
.
t
absence of arbitrage, the risk-neutral drifts of forward rates are completely determined by their volatilities.
Indeed, if we dierentiate
b I (t, T ) with respect
to T to recover
b (t, T ) we obtain
0
0
z
df (t, T ) = (t, T ) I (t, T ) dt + (t, T ) db
R
T
=
(t, T )0 t (t, s) ds dt + (t, T )0 db
z
(17.41)
One can also use (17.41) to derive the risk-neutral dynamics of the
instantaneous maturity interest rate, r (t) = f (t, t), which is required for discounting risk-neutral payos. Suppose dates are ordered such that 0 t T .
In integrated form (17.41) becomes
f (t, T ) = f (0, T ) +
Rt
(u, T )0 I (u, T ) du +
Rt
(u, T )0 db
z (u)
(17.42)
484
r (t) = f (0, t) +
Rt
0
0 (u, t) I
(u, t) du +
Rt
0 (u, t)
db
z (u)
(17.43)
Rt
f (0, t)
(u, t)0
0
=
dt + 0 (u, t) (u, t) +
I (u, t) dudt
t
t
R t (u, t)0
db
z (u) dt + (t, t)0 db
z
(17.44)
+ 0
t
dr (t) =
where we have used the fact that I (t, t) = 0 and I (u, t) /t = (u, t).
With these results, one can now value fixed-income derivatives.
As an
forward rate curve (equivalently, the term structure of bond prices or yields)
at date T , which we write as C (T, f (T, T + )) where 0. The contingent
claims risk-neutral valuation equation is
h R
i
bt e tT r(s)ds C (T, f (T, T + )) | f (t, t + ) , 0
C (t, f (t, t + )) = E
(17.45)
that the dynamics of dr are more complicated than simply setting T = t in equation
(17.41) because both arguments of f (t, t) = r (t) are varying simultaneously. Equation (17.44)
(t,u)
is equivalent to dr = df (t, t) + fu
|ut dt.
485
assured of fitting the current term structure of interest rates, since the forward
rate curve, f (t, t + ), is an input. Only for special cases regarding the type of
contingent claim and the assumed forward rate volatilities can the expectation
in (17.45) be computed analytically. In general, it can be computed by a Monte
Carlo simulation of a discrete-time analogue to the continuous-time risk-neutral
forward rate and instantaneous interest rate processes in (17.41) and (17.44).9
Valuing American-type contingent claims using the HJM approach can be
more complicated because, in general, one needs to discretize forward rates to
produce a lattice (e.g., binomial tree) and check the nodes of the lattice to see
if early exercise is optimal.10 However, HJM forward rates will not necessarily
follow Markov processes. From (17.41) and (17.44), one see that if the forward
rate volatility functions are specified to depend on the level of forward rates
themselves, (t, s, f (t, s)), then the evolution of f (t, T ) and r (t) depends on
the entire history of forward rates between two dates such as 0 and t. It will
not be possible to express forward rates as f (0, T, x (0)) and f (t, T, x (t)) where
x (t) is a set of finite state variables.11 Non-Markov processes lead to lattice
structures where the nodes do not re-combine.
486
forward rate volatilities are deterministic and lead to a Markov process for the
instantaneous interest rate.
Consider the value of a European option maturing at date T where the underlying asset is a zero coupon bond maturing at date T + . It is assumed that
n = 1 and the forward rates volatilities decline exponentially with their time
horizons:
(t, T ) = r e(T t)
(17.46)
where r and are positive constants. From (17.36), this implies that the rate
of return volatility of a zero-coupon bond equals
I (t, T )
RT
t
(t, s) ds =
RT
t
r e(st) ds =
r
1 e(T t)
(17.47)
Note that this volatility function is the same as the Vasicek model of the
term structure given in (9.31).
R t 2r (tu)
Rt
e
e2(tu) du+ 0 r e(tu) db
z (u) (17.48)
0
done in Chapter 9 in equation (9.27). For conditions on forward rate volatilities that lead
to Markov structures, see the work of Andrew Carverhill (Carverhill 1994), Peter Ritchken
and L. Sankarasubramanian (Ritchken and Sankarasubramanian 1995), and Koji Inui and
Masaaki Kimima (Inui and Kijima 1998).
487
i
Rt h
f (0, t)
dt + 0 2r e2(tu) 2r e(tu) e2(tu) dudt
t
Rt
0 r e(tu) db
z (u) dt + r db
z
(17.49)
dr
Rt
f (0, t)
dt + 0 2r e2(tu) dudt + [f (0, t) r (t)] dt + r db
z
2
1 f (0, t)
+ f (0, t) + r2 1 e2t r (t) dt + r db
=
z
t
= [r (t) r (t)] dt + r db
z
where r (t)
1
f
(17.50)
aecting its future distribution is the current level of r (t). However, it diers
from the standard Vasicek model which assumes that the risk-neutral process for
r (t) has a long run mean that is constant.13 By making the central tendency,
r (t), to be a deterministic function of the currently observed forward rate curve,
f (0, t) t 0, the models implied date 0 price of a zero coupon bond, P (0, T ),
will coincide exactly with observed prices.14 This model was proposed by John
Hull and Alan White ((Hull and White 1990), (Hull and White 1993)), and is
referred to as the "Extended Vasicek" model.15
Since, as with the standard Vasicek model, the extended Vasicek model has
13 Recall from equation (10.63) that the unconditional mean of the risk-neutral interest rate
is r + q r /, where r is the mean of the physical process and q is the market price of interest
rate risk.
1
14 It is left as an exercise to verify that when r (t)
f (0, t) /t + f (0, t) +
h
R
i
R
2
T
2
2t
b exp
/ , then P (0, T ) = E
r
(s)
ds
=
exp
T
r 1 e
0
0 f (0, s) ds .
15 Hull and White show that, besides r (t), the parameters (t) and (t) can also be
r
extended to be deterministic functions of time. With these extensions, r (t) remains normally
distributed and analytic solutions to options on discount bonds can be obtained. Making
(t) and r (t) to be time varying allows one to fit other aspects of the term structure, such
as observed volatilities of forward rates.
488
where d1 =
(17.51)
i
h
ln [P (t, T + ) / (P (t, T ) X)] + 12 v (t, T )2 /v (t, T ), d2 = d1
2
2r
2(T t)
1
e
1 e
3
2
(17.52)
This solution illustrates a general principle of the HJM approach, namely, that
formulas can be derived whose inputs match the initial term structure of bond
prices (P (t, T ) and P (t, T + )) or, equivalently, the initial forward rate curve
(f (t, s) s t).
17.2.2
Market Models
16 Note that when applying Mertons derivation to the case of the underlying asset being a
bond, then , the return correlation between bonds maturing at dates T and T + , equals 1.
This is because there is a single Brownian motion determining the stochastic component of
returns.
489
As shown in the previous section, HJM models begin with a particular specification for instantaneous-maturity, continuously-compounded, forward rates,
and then derivative values are calculated based on these initial forward rates.
However, instantaneous-maturity forward rates are not directly observable, and
in many applications they must be approximated from data on bond yields or
discrete-maturity forward or futures rates that are unavailable at every maturity. A class of models that is a variation on the HJM approach can sometimes
avoid this approximation error and may lead to more simple, analytic solutions
for particular types of derivatives. These models are known as "Market Models"
and are designed to price derivatives whose payos are a function of a discrete
maturity, rather than instantaneous maturity, forward interest rate. Examples
of such derivatives include interest rate caps and floors and swaptions. Let us
illustrate the market model approach by way of these examples.
(17.53)
17 The convention for LIBOR is to set the compounding interval equal to the underlying
instruments maturity. For example, if = 14 years, then three-month LIBOR is quarterlycompounded. If = 12 years, then six-month LIBOR is semi-annually compounded.
490
(17.54)
that is, the option payo at date T + depends on the -period spot LIBOR
at date T .19 Because uncertainty regarding the LIBOR rate is resolved at date
T , which is periods prior to the caplets settlement (payment) date, we can
also write
1
1 X, 0
= P (T, T + ) max
P (T, T + )
1 + X
1 + X
= max 1
, 0 = max 1
,0
P (T, T + )
1 + L (T, T, )
which illustrates that a caplet maturing at date T + is equivalent to a put
option that matures at date T , has an exercise price of 1, and is written on a
zero coupon bond that has a payo of 1 + X at its maturity date of T + .
Similarly, a floorlet, whose date T + payo equals max [X L (T, T, ) , 0],
can be shown to be equivalent to a call option on a zero coupon bond.20
To value a caplet using a market model approach, let us first analyze the
18 This
modeling assumes that LIBOR is the yield on a default-free discount bond. However,
LIBOR is not a fully default-free interest rate, such as a Treasury security rate. It represents
the borrowing rate of a large, generally high credit quality, bank. Typically, the relatively
small amount of default risk is ignored when applying market models to derivatives based on
LIBOR.
19 Caplets are based on a notional principal amount, which here is assumed to be $1. The
value of a caplet having a notional principal of $N is simply N times the value of a caplet
with a notional principal of $1, that is, is payo is N max [L (T, T, ) X, 0].
20 Therefore, the HJM - extended Vasicek solution in (17.51) to (17.52) is a one method for
valuing a floorlet. A straightforward modification of this formula could also value a caplet.
491
L (t, T, ) =
P (t, T )
1
P (t, T + )
(17.56)
We can derive the stochastic process followed by this forward rate in terms of
the bond prices risk neutral process. Note that from (?? along with dz = db
z
z.
(t) dt, we have dP (t, T ) /P (t, T ) = r (t) dt I (t, T )0 db
Applying Its
(17.57)
(17.58)
RT
bt e t
E
processes.
r(s)ds
if c (t, L (t, T, ))
is the contingent claims value, it could be calculated as
c (T, L (T, T, )) where r (t) and L (t, T, ) are assumed to follow risk-neutral
492
prices are deflated by the value of the money market account which follows the
process dB (t) = r (t) B (t) dt.
Not only does L (t, T, ) follow a martingale under the forward measure, but
so does the value of all other securities. To see this, let the date t price of a
contingent claim be given by c (t). In the absence of arbitrage, its price process
is of the form
dc
= [r (t) + (t) 0 c (t)] dt + c (t)0 dz
c
(17.59)
Now define the deflated contingent claims price as C (t) = c (t) /P (t, T + ).
Applying Its lemma gives
dC
C
(17.60)
+ [c (t) + I (t, T + )] 0 dz
(17.61)
et [C (t + )] 0, where E
et [] is the date t expectation under
so that C (t) = E
the forward measure. Now, to show why this transformation can be convenient,
suppose that this contingent claim is the caplet described earlier. This deflated
493
max [L (T, T, ) X, 0]
e
= Et
P (T + , T + )
(17.62)
(17.63)
Noting that
L (t, T, ) also has a zero drift, leads to a similar formula first proposed by
Fischer Black (Black 1976) for valuing options on commodity futures:
(17.64)
i
h
where d1 = ln (L (t, T, ) /X) + 12 v (t, T )2 /v (t, T ), d2 = d1 v (t, T ), and
v (t, T )2 =
RT
t
|I (s, T + ) I (s, T )| ds
(17.65)
494
portfolio in the manner described above, where the caplet maturing at date Tj
is priced using the date Tj + forward measure.
by issuers of floating-rate bonds whose bond payments coincide with the caplet
maturity dates.
Since a floating
rate bonds coupon rate payable at date T + is most commonly tied to the period LIBOR at date T , caplet payos follow this same structure. Analogous
to a cap, an interest rate floor is a portfolio of floorlets, and can be valued using
the same technique described in this section.
Example: A Swaption
Frequently, a market model approach is applied to value another common interest rate derivative, a swaption. A swaption is an option to become a party
in an interest rate swap at a given future maturity date and at a pre-specified
swap rate.
Let us, then, define the interest rate swap underlying this swap-
495
opposite.24
Note that the swaps series of floating rate payments plus an additional $1
at date Tn+1 can be replicated by starting with $1 at time T0 = T1 and
repeatedly investing this $1 in -maturity LIBOR deposits.25
same cashflows that one would obtain by investing $1 in a floating rate bond at
date T0 . Similarly, the swaps series of fixed rate payments plus an additional
$1 at date Tn+1 can be replicated by buying a fixed-coupon bond that pays
coupons of K at each swap date and pays a principal of $1 at its maturity
date of Tn+1 . Based on this insight, one can see that the value of a swap to the
floating rate payer is the dierence between a fixed coupon bond having coupon
rate K, and a floating coupon bond having coupons tied to -period LIBOR.
Thus, if t T0 = T1 , then the date t value of the swap to the floating rate
payer is26
K
n+1
P
j=1
(17.66)
24 Recall
496
one obtains
s0,n (t) =
=
Pn+1
j=1
(17.67)
(17.68)
497
ing the swap. By normalizing all security prices by B1,n (t), we will value the
swaption using the so-called "forward swap measure."
Similar to valuation under the risk-neutral or forward measure of the previous section, let us define C (t) = c (t) /B1,n (t). Also define dz = dz+
(t) + B1,n (t) dt where B1,n (t) is the date t vector of instantaneous volatil-
ities of the zero coupon bond portfolios value, B1,n (t). Similar to the derivation
in equations (17.59) to (17.61), we have
dC
= c (t) + B1,n (t, T + ) 0 dz
C
(17.69)
so that all deflated asset prices under the forward swap measure follow martingale processes. Thus,
C (t) = E t [C (T0 )]
(17.70)
Re-written in terms of the undeflated swaptions current value, c (t) = C (t) B1,n (t),
(17.70) becomes
(17.71)
so that the expected payo under the forward swap measure is discounted by
the current value of a portfolio of zero coupon bonds that mature at the times
of the swaps exchanges.
Importantly, note that s0,n (t) = [P (t, T0 ) P (t, Tn+1 )] /B1,n (T0 ) is the
ratio of the dierence between two security prices deflated by B1,n (t). In the
absence of arbitrage, it must also follow a martingale process under the forward
498
swap measure.
forward swap rate is lognormally distributed under the forward swap measure:
ds0,n (t)
= s0,n (t) 0 dz
s0,n (t)
(17.72)
so that S0,n (t) is a vector of deterministic functions of time that can be calibrated to match observed forward swap volatilities or zero coupon bond volatilities.28 This assumption results in (17.71) taking a Black-Scholes-type form
(17.73)
i
h
where d1 = ln (s0,n (t) /X) + 12 v (t, T0 )2 /v (t, T0 ), d2 = d1 v (t, T0 ), and
v2 (t, T0 ) =
17.2.3
R T0
t
(17.74)
The term structure models that we have studied thus far have specified a finite
number of Brownian motion processes as the source of uncertainty determining
the evolution of bond prices or forward rates.
499
(17.75)
Moreover, the Black-Scholes hedge, by making the market dynamically complete and by identifying a unique (t) associated with dz, allows us to perform
risk-neutral valuation by the transformation db
z = dz + (t) dt or valuation
using the pricing kernel dM/M = r (t) dt (t)0 dz.
However, the elegance of these models comes with an empirical downside.
The fact that all bond prices depend on the same n 1 vector dz places restrictions on the covariance of bonds rates of return. For example, when n = 1,
the rates of return on all bonds are instantaneously perfectly correlated. While
in these models, the correlation can be made less perfect by increasing n, doing
so introduces more parameters that require estimation.
A related empirical implication of (17.75) or (17.33) is that it restricts the
possible future term structures of bond prices or forward rates. In other words,
starting from the current date t set of bond prices P (t, T ) T > t, an arbitrary
future term structure, P (t + dt, T ) T > t + dt, cannot always be achieved by
any realization of dz.
infinite number of bond prices (each of a dierent maturity), but the finiteness
of dz allows matching this future term structure at only a finite number of
maturity horizons.29 Hence, models based on a finite dz are almost certainly
inconsistent with future observed bond prices and forward rates.
Because of
this, empiricists must assume that data on bond prices (or yields) are observed
with "noise" or that, in the case of HJM-type models, parameters (that the
model assumes to be constant) must be re-calibrated at each observation date
29 For example, consider n = 1. In this case, all bond prices must either rise or fall with a
given realization of dz. This model would not permit a situation where short maturity bond
prices fell but long maturity bond prices rose. The model could produce a realization of dz
that matches long maturity bond prices or short maturity bond prices, but not both.
500
zT
dP (t, T ) /P (t, T ) = r (t) dt + p (t, T ) db
T > t
(17.76)
where db
zT (t) is a single Brownian motion process (under the risk-neutral measure) that is unique to the bond that matures at date T .30 The set of Brownian
motions for all zero coupon bonds { zbT (t) }T >t comprise a Brownian "field" or
db
zT1 (t) db
zT2 (t) = (t, T1, T2 ) dt
(17.77)
(t,T1 ,T2 )
|T1 =T2
T1
|T1 T2 |
where
is a positive constant.
One can also model the physical process for bond prices corresponding to
30 An alternative way of specifying a random field model is to assume that the
risk-neutral
processes for instantaneous
forward rates are of the form df (t, T ) =
i
h
R
(t,
s)
c
(t,
T,
s)
ds
dt
+
(t,
T
)
dz
(t, T ) T
T where dzT1 dzT2 = c (t, T1 , T2 ) dt. This spect
ification extends the HJM equation (17.41) to a random field driving forward rates.
501
T > t
(17.78)
with dzT (t), T > t satisfying the same correlation function as in (17.77). Analogous to the finite-factor pricing kernel process in (17.8), a pricing kernel for
this random field model would be
dM/M = r (t) dt
R
t
(17.79)
so that an integral of the products of market prices of risk and Brownian motions
replaces the usual sum of these products that occur for the finite factor case.31
The benefit of a model like (17.76) and (17.77) is that a realization of the
Brownian field can generate any future term structure of bond prices or forward rates and, hence, be consistent with empirical observation and not require
model re-calibration.
dom field models can provide a flexible covariance structure among dierent
maturity bonds.
HJM models, the covariance matrix of dierent maturity bond returns or forward rates will always be non-singular no matter how many bonds are included.
This could be important when valuing particular fixed-income derivatives where
the underlying is a portfolio of zero coupon bonds, and the correlation between
these bonds aects the overall portfolio volatility.
31 Note, however, that a random field model is not the same as a standard finite factor model
extended to an infinite number of factors. As shown in (17.78), a random field model has
a single Brownian motion driving each bond price or forward rate. A factor model, such as
(17.2) or (17.36), extended to infinite factors would have the same infinite set of Brownian
motions driving each bond price.
502
However, this rich covariance structure requires stronger theoretical assumptions for valuing derivatives compared to finite-dimensional diusion models. A
given bonds return can no longer be perfectly replicated by a portfolio of other
bonds, and, thus, a Black-Scholes hedging argument cannot be used to identify
a unique market price of risk associated with each dzT (t).32
fixed-income securities is no longer dynamically complete. Hence, one must assume, perhaps due to an underlying preference-based general equilibrium model,
that there exists particular T (t) associated with each dzT (t), or, equivalently,
that a risk-neutral pricing exists.
Random field models can be parameterized by assuming particular functions for bond price or forward rate volatilities.
(17.80)
where db
z is a Brownian motion (under the risk-neutral measure) that is assumed to be independent of the Brownian field {db
zT } T > t.
Based on
this parameterization, which is similar to a one factor ane model, they derive
solutions for various interest rate derivatives.33
32 Robert Goldstein (Goldstein 2000) characterizes random field models of the term structure
as being analogous to the APT model ((Ross 1976)). As discussed in Chapter 3, the APT
assumes that a given assets return depends on the risk from a finite number of factors along
with the assets own idiosyncratic risk. Thus, the asset is imperfectly correlated with any
portfolio containing a finite number of other assets. Similarly, in a random field model, a
given bonds return is imperfectly correlated with any portfolio containing a finite number of
other bonds. Taking the analogy a step further, perhaps market prices of risk in a random
field model can be characterized using the notion of asymptotic arbitrage, rather than exact
arbitrage.
33 Robert Kimmel ((Kimmel 2004)) also derives models with stochastic volatility driven by
multiple factors.
503
If, similar to David Kennedy (Kennedy 1994), one makes the more simple
assumption that p (t, T ) and (17.76) and (t, T1, T2 ) in (17.77) are deterministic
functions, then options on bonds, such as caplets and floorets, have a BlackScholes-type valuation formula. For example, suppose as in the HJM-extended
Vasicek case of (17.51) to (17.52) that we value a European call option that
matures at date T , is written on a zero coupon bond that matures at date
T + , and has an exercise price of X.
(17.81)
where p (t, T + ) P (t, T + ) /P (t, T ) is the deflated price of the bond that
matures at date T + . Applying Its lemma to the risk-neutral process for
bond prices in (17.76), we obtain:
dp (t, T + )
p (t, T + )
(17.82)
q
zT + 1 (t, T, T + )2 db
zU,T where
We can re-write db
zT + = (t, T, T + ) db
34 This re-writing puts the risk-neutral process for p (t, T + ) in the form of our prior analysis
in which the vector of Brownian motions, db
z, was assumed to have independent elements.
This allows us to make the transformation to the forward measure in the same manner as was
done earlier.
504
p (t, T + ) becomes
dp (t, T + )
p (t, T + )
= p (t, T + )
q
1 (t, T, T + )2 db
zU,T
(17.83)
where
(t, T, )2 p (t, T + )2 + p (t, T )2 2 (t, T, T + ) p (t, T + ) p (t, T )
(17.84)
Thus, p (t, T + ) is lognormally distributed under the forward rate measure, so
that (17.81) has the Black-Scholes-Merton-type solution
(17.85)
RT
t
(u, T, )2 du
(17.86)
and (u, T, ) is defined in (17.84). While this formula is similar to the Vasicekbased ones in (9.45) and (17.51), the volatility function in (17.84) may permit
a relatively more flexible form for matching observed data.
17.3
Summary
This chapter has briefly surveyed some of the important theoretical developments in modeling bond yield curves and valuing fixed income securities. The
17.4. EXERCISES
505
chapters presentation has been in the context of continuous time models and,
to keep its length manageable, many similar models set in discrete time have
been left out.35 Moreover, questions regarding numerical implementation and
parameter estimation for specific models could not be answered in the short
presentations given here.
There is a continuing search for improved ways of describing the term structure of bond prices and of valuing fixed income derivatives.
Researchers in
this field have dierent objectives, and the models that we presented reflect this
diversity.
17.4
Exercises
506
d (t) = [ (t)] dt + dz
where dzr dz = dt and > 0, r , > 0, > 0, , and are constants.
In addition, define the constant market prices of risk associated with dzr
and dz to be r and .
notation used in this chapter and solve for the equilibrium price of a zero
coupon bond, P (t, T ).
2. Consider the following one-factor quadratic-gaussian model. The single
state variable, x (t), follows the risk-neutral process
z
dx (t) = [x x (t)] dt + x db
and the instantaneous-maturity interest rate is given by r (t, x) = +
x (t) + x (t)2 . Assume , x, , and are positive constants, and that
14 2 / 0 where is also a constant. Solve for the equilibrium price
of a zero coupon bond, P (t, T ).
3. Show that for the extended Vasicek model when r (t) 1 f (0, t) /t +
h
R
i
b exp T r (s) ds
=
f (0, t) + 2r 1 e2t /2 , then P (0, T ) = E
0
R
T
exp 0 f (0, s) ds .
4. Determine the value of an n payment interest rate floor using the LIBOR
market model.
Chapter 18
507
508
This method views the exogenously specified default process as the reducedform of a more complicated and complex model of a firms assets and capital
structure. Examples of this approach include work by Robert Jarrow, David
Lando, and Stuart Turnbull (Jarrow, Lando, and Turnbull 1997), Dilip Madan
and Haluk Unal (Madan and Unal 1998), and Darrell Due and Kenneth Singleton (Due and Singleton 1999). This chapter provides an introduction to
the main features of these two methods of modeling default.
18.1
This section considers a model similar to that by Robert Merton (Merton 1974).
It specifies the assets, debt, and shareholders equity of a particular firm. Let
A(t) denote the date t value of a firms assets. The firm is assumed to have a
very simple capital structure. In addition to shareholders equity, it has issued
a single zero-coupon bond that promises to pay an amount B at date T > t.
Also let T t be the time until this debt matures. The firm is assumed to
pay dividends to its shareholders at the continuous rate A(t)dt, where is the
firms constant proportion of assets paid in dividends per unit time. The value
of the firms assets are assumed to follow the process
dA/A = ( ) dt + dz
(18.1)
where denotes the instantaneous expected rate of return on the firms assets
and is the constant standard deviation of return on firm assets. Now let
D(t, T ) be the date t market value of the firms debt that is promised the
payment of B at date T . It is assumed that when the debt matures, the firm
pays the promised amount to the debtholders if there is sucient asset value to
do so. If not, the firm defaults (bankruptcy occurs) and the debtholders take
509
ownership of all of the firms assets. Hence, the payo to debtholders at date T
can be written as
(18.2)
= B max [0, B A (T )]
From the second line in equation (18.2), we see that the payo to the debtholders
equals the promised payment, B, less the payo on a European put option
written on the firms assets and having exercise price equal to B. Hence, if
we make the usual frictionless market assumptions, then the current market
value of the debt can be derived to equal the present value of the promised
payment less the value of a put option on the dividend-paying assets.2
If we
let P (t, T ) be the current date t price of a default-free zero-coupon bond that
pays $1 at date T and assume that the default-free term structure satisfies the
Vasicek model as specified earlier in (9.28) to (9.30), then using Chapter 9s
results on the pricing of options when interest rates are random, we obtain:
(18.3)
yield to maturity on the firms debt, denoted R (t, T ), can be calculated from
(18.3) as R (t, T ) =
as R (t, T )
2 One
needs to assume that the risk of the firms assets, as determined by the dz process, is
a tradeable risk, so that a Black-Scholes hedge involving the firms debt can be constructed.
510
Based on this result, one can also solve for the market value of the firms
shareholders equity, which we denote as E (t). In the absence of taxes and other
transactions costs, the value of investors claims on the firms assets, D (t, T ) +
E (t) must equal the total value of the firms assets, A (t). This allows us to
write
(18.4)
511
In response,
some research has taken a dierent tack by assuming that when the firms assets
hits a lower boundary, default is triggered. This default boundary is presumed
to bear a monotonic relation to the firms total outstanding debt.
With the
initial value of the firms assets exceeding this boundary, determining future
default amounts to computing the first passage time of the assets through this
boundary.
Francis Longsta and Eduardo Schwartz (Longsta and Schwartz 1995) develop such a model following the earlier work of Fischer Black and John Cox
(Black and Cox 1976). They assume a default boundary that is constant over
time and, when assets sink to the level of this boundary, bondholders are assumed to recover an exogenously given proportion of their bonds face values.
This contrasts with the Merton model where, in the case of default, bondholders
recover A (T ), the stochastic value of firm assets at the bonds maturity date,
which results in a loss of B A (T ). In the Longsta-Schwartz model, possible
default occurs at a stochastic date, say , defined by the first (passage) time
that A ( ) = k, where k is the pre-determined default boundary. Bondholders
are assumed to recover P ( , T ) B, where < 1 is the recovery rate equaling
a proportion of the market value of an otherwise equivalent default-free bond,
3 For a description of the KMV application of the Merton model for forecasting defaults,
see (Crosbie and Bohn 2002). Alan Marcus and Israel Shaked (Marcus and Shaked 1984)
apply the Merton model to analyzing the default risk of commercial banks.
4 A study by Edward Jones, Scott Mason, and Eric Rosenfeld (Jones, Mason, and Rosenfeld
1984) is an example.
512
P ( , T ) B.5
While these "first passage time" models seek to provide more real-
ism than the more simple Merton model, they come at the cost of requiring
numerical, rather than closed-form, solutions.7
For firms with complicated debt structures, these first passage time models
simplify the determination of default by assuming it occurs when a firms assets
sink to a specified boundary. The interaction between default and the level and
timing of particular promised bond payments are not directly modeled, except
in so far as they aect the specification of the default boundary. In the next
section, we consider the reduced form approach which goes a step further by
not directly modeling either the firms assets or its overall debt level.
5 P ( , T ) B is the market value of a zero-coupon bond paying the face value of B at date
T . However, Longsta and Schwartz do not limit their analysis to defaultable zero coupon
bonds. Indeed, they value both fixed and floating coupon bonds assuming a Vasicek model
of the term structure. Hence, in general, recovery equals a fixed proportion, , of the market
value of an otherwise equivalent default-free (fixed or floating rate) bond.
6 More precisely, they assume that the risk-neutral process for the log of the ratio of firm
debt to assets, say l (t) = ln [k (t) /A (t)], follows an Ornstein-Uhlenbeck process. For an
example of a model displaying mean-reverting leverage in the context of commercial bank
defaults, see (Pennacchi 2005).
7 An exception is the closed-form solutions obtained by Stijn Claessens and George Pennacchi (Claessens and Pennacchi 1996) who model default-risky sovereign debt such as Brady
bonds.
18.2
513
With the reduced form method, default need not be tied directly to the dynamics
of a firms assets and liabilities.
However, because
514
default during the interval (t, t + dt) is denoted (t) dt where (t) is the physical
default intensity or hazard rate and is assumed to be non-negative.9
Note
from this definition, the physical probability of the firm not defaulting (that is,
surviving) over the time interval from t to , where t < T , is
R
Et e t (u)du
18.2.1
(18.5)
A Zero-Recovery Bond
To determine D (t, T ), an assumption must be made regarding the payo received by bondholders should the bond default.
bondholders recover nothing should the bond default and, later, we generalize
this assumption to permit a possible non-zero recovery value. With zero recovery, the bondholders date T payo is either D (T, T ) = B if there is no default
or D (T, T ) = 0 if default has occurred over the interval from t to T .
Ap-
plying risk-neutral pricing, the date t value of the zero-recovery bond, denoted
DZ (t, T ), can be written as
h R
i
bt e tT r(u)du D (T, T )
DZ (t, T ) = E
(18.6)
bt [] is the
where r (t) is the date t instantaneous default-free interest rate, and E
intensity will account for the market price risk associated with the Poisson
9 Recall that in Chapter 11 we modeled jumps in asset prices as following a Poisson process
with jump intensity . Here, a one-time default follows a Poisson process, and its intensity
is explicitly time-varying.
515
dx = a (t, x) dt + b (t, x) dz
(18.7)
0
where x = (x1 ...xn ) , a (t, x) is a nx1 vector, b (t, x) is a nxn matrix, and
0
dz = (dz1 ...dzn ) is an n 1 vector of independent Brownian motion processes
so that dzi dzj = 0 for i 6= j. As in the previous chapter, x (t) includes macroeconomic factors that aect the default-free term structure, but it now also
includes firm-specific factors that aect the likelihood of default for the particular firm. Similar to (17.8), the stochastic discount factor for pricing the firms
default risky bond will be of the form
(18.8)
where (t, x) is an nx1 vector of the market prices of risk associated with
the elements of dz and (t, x) is the market price of risk associated with the
actual default event which occurs when the Poisson process q (t) jumps from
0 (the no default state) to 1 (the absorbing default state) at which time dq =
1.11
10 For concreteness our presentation assumes an equilibrium Markov state variable environment. However, much of our results on reduced form pricing of defaultable bonds carry over
to a non-Markov, no-arbitrage context, such as the Heath-Jarrow-Morton framework. See
(Due and Singleton 1999).
11 Recall from the discussion in Chapter 11 that jumps in an assets value, as would occur
when a bond defaults, cannot always be hedged. Thus, in general it may not be possible to
determine (t, x) based on a no arbitrage restriction. This market price of default risk may
need to be determined from an equilibrium model of investor preferences.
516
Hence, default risk reflects two types of risk-premia, (t, x) and (t, x).
Based on the calculation of survival probability in (18.5), the value of the
zero-recovery defaultable bond is
R
RT
h R
i
b
b
tT r(u)du t (u)du
]du B (18.9)
b
bt e tT [r(u)+(u)
DZ (t, T ) = Et e
e
B =E
Equation (18.9) shows that valuing this zero-recovery defaultable bond is similar
b (u)
to valuing a default free bond except that we use the discount rate of r (u)+
b (t, x), and
rather than just r (u). Given specific functional forms for r (t, x),
the risk-neutral state variable process (specifications of (18.7) and (t, x)), the
expression in (18.9) can be computed.
18.2.2
The value of a bond that has a possibly non-negative recovery value in the
event of default equals the value in (18.9) plus the present value of the amount
recovered in default. Suppose that if the bond defaults at date where t <
T , bondholders recover an amount w (, x) at date . Now note the the
risk-neutral probability density of defaulting at time is
e
R
t
b
(u)du
b
( )
(18.10)
h R
i
b ( ) is discounted by exp
b (u) du because default at date
In (18.10),
t
517
T:
bt
DR (t, T ) = E
bt
= E
"Z
"Z
r(u)du
w () e
R
t
b
[r(u)+(u)
]du b
b
(u)du
b
( ) d
( ) w ( ) d
#
(18.11)
Putting this together with (18.9) gives the bonds total value, D (t, T ) =
DZ (t, T ) + DR (t, T ), as
"
Z
R
b ]ds
tT [r(s)+(s)
b
D (t, T ) = Et e
B+
R
t
b
[r(s)+(s)
]ds
b ( ) w ( ) d
(18.12)
One assumption
k (t, ) d
(18.13)
h R
i
b
]du
b ()
bt e t [r(u)+(u)
k (t, ) E
(18.14)
and the vector x in (18.7) has a risk-neutral process that is also ane.13 In this
case, the recovery value in (18.13) can be computed by numerical integration of
12 Work by Darrell Due ((Due 1998)), David Lando((Langer 1998)), and Dilip Madan and
Haluk Unal((Madan and Unal 1998)) make this assumption. As reported by Gregory Duee
(Duee 1999), the recovery rate, , estimated by Moodys for senior unsecured bondholders
is approxmately 44 percent.
13 This is shown in (Due, Pan, and Singleton 2000).
518
(18.11) becomes
bt
DR (t, T ) = E
bt
= E
"Z
"Z
"
bt e
= E
RT
t
b
[r(u)+(u)
]du
b ( ) ( , x) e
b
(u)du
b
r(u)du
( ) ( , x) e
R
t
b
(u)du
b
RT
t
RT
r(u)du
r(u)du
Bd
#
Bd
( ) ( , x) d B
(18.15)
probability of default for the period from date t to the maturity date T . Therei
h R
T b
(u) du , that is, one minus the probability of
fore it must equal 1 exp t
surviving over the same period. Making this substitution and using (18.9) we
have
R
RT
b
(u)du
tT r(u)du
b
t
1e
B
DR (t, T ) = Et e
h RT
i
RT
b
]du B
bt e t r(u)du e t [r(u)+(u)
= E
= BP (t, T ) DZ (t, T )
(18.16)
14 This specification has been studied by Robert Jarrow and Stuart Turnbull ((Jarrow and
Turnbull 1995)) and David Lando ((Langer 1998)).
519
(18.17)
Hence, this recovery assumption amounts to requiring only a solution for the
value of a zero-recovery bond.
Recovery Proportional to Market Value
Let us consider one additional recovery assumption analyzed by Darrell Due
and Kenneth Singleton (Due and Singleton 1999).
bondholders are assumed to recover a proportion of what was the bonds market
value just prior to default.
D + , T = w ( , x) = D , T [1 L ( , x)]
(18.18)
(18.19)
where D and the nx1 vector D are given by the usual Its lemma expressions
similar to (11.8) and (11.9).
520
b (t, x) L
b (t, x) dq (18.20)
b (t, x) dt + 0D db
zL
dD (t, T ) /D (t, T ) = r (t, x) +
b (t, x), when the bond does not default it must earn an
fault (dq = 1) is
b (t, x) L
b (t, x) to make its unconditional risk-neutral
excess expected return of
expected return equal r (t). Based on a derivation similar to that used to obtain
(11.16) and (17.6), one can show that the defaultable bonds value satisfies the
equilibrium partial dierential equation
1
2 Trace
(18.21)
where Dx denotes the nx1 vector of first derivatives of D (t, x) with respect to
each of the factors and, similarly, Dxx is the nxn matrix of second order mixed
partial derivatives. In addition, b
a (t, x) = a (t, x) b (t, x) is the risk-neutral
b (t, x) L
b (t, x) is the
drift of the factor process (18.7) and R (t, x) r (t, x) +
defaultable bonds risk-neutral drift in the process (18.20). Now note that should
521
the bond reach the maturity date, T , without defaulting, then D (T, T ) = B
which determines the boundary condition for (18.21).
in the form of a PDE for a standard contingent claim except that R (t, x) has
replaced r (t, x) in the standard PDE. This insight allows us to write the PDEs
Feynman-Kac solution as:16
h R
i
bt e tT R(u,x)du B
D (t, T ) = E
(18.22)
b (t, x) L
b (t, x) can be viewed as the "default-adjusted"
where R (t, x) r (t, x)+
discount rate.
b (t, x) L
b (t, x) has the interpretation
The product s (t, x)
b (t, x) and L
b (t, x) are not individually identified in (18.22), when implementing
this formula we can simply specify a single functional form for s (t, x).
18.2.3
Examples
Because default intensities and/or credit spreads must be non-negative, a popular stochastic process for modeling these variables is the mean-reverting, squareroot process used in the term structure model of John Cox, Jonathan Ingersoll,
and Stephen Ross (Cox, Ingersoll, and Ross 1985b).
a (t, x) =
example, suppose that x = (x1 x2 ) is a two-dimensional vector, b
0
(1 (x1 x1 ) 2 (x2 x2 )) , and b (t, x) is a diagonal matrix with first and
b (t, x) = x2 (t), this has the implication that the defaultr (t, x) = x1 (t) and
free term structure and the risk-neutral default intensity are independent. Arguably, this is unrealistic since empirical work has found a negative correlation
16 Recall from Chapter 10 that (10.14) was shown to be the Feynman-Kac solution to the
Black-Scholes PDE (10.7). See Darell Due and Kenneth Singleton (Due and Singleton
1999) for an alternative derivation of (18.22) that does not involve specification of factors or
the bonds PDE.
522
Hence,
With r (t, x) = x1 (t) and denoting x1 = r, we obtain the Cox, Ingersoll, and
Ross formula for the value of a default-free discount bond:19
(18.23)
where
21 e(1 +1 ) 2
A1 ( )
(1 + 1 ) (e1 1) + 21
B1 ()
and 1
p
21 + 2 21 .
21 r/21
2 e1 1
(1 + 1 ) (e1 1) + 2 1
(18.24)
(18.25)
17 This evidence is presented in work by Gregory Duee ((Duee 1999)) and Pierre CollinDufresne and Bruno Solnik ((Collin-Dufresne and Solnik 2001)).
18 For models with more flexible correlation structures that require numerical solutions, see
examples given by Darrell Due and Kenneth Singleton (Due and Singleton 1999). Some
b (t) (or s (t) =
b (t) L (t)) be positive by
research has dropped the restriction that r (t) and
assuming these variables follow multi-variate ane Gaussian processes. This permits general
correlation between default-free interest rates and default intensities as well as closed-form
solutions for defaultable bonds. The model in work by C.V.N. Krishnan, Peter Ritchken, and
James Thomson ((Krishnan, Ritchken, and Thomson 2004)) is an example of this.
19 The formula in (18.23) to (18.25) is the same as (13.51) to (13.53) except that it is written
in terms of the parameters of the risk-neutral, rather than physical, process for r (t). Hence,
relative to
our earlier notation, 1 = + where the market price of interest rate risk equals
(t) = r/ 1 .
523
(18.26)
where
b
(18.27)
1 DZ (t, T ) + BP (t, T )
= + 1 V (t, T ) P (t, T ) B
D (t, T ) =
(18.28)
524
(18.29)
(18.30)
= P (t, T ) S (t, T ) B
where
default-free bond except that the instantaneous maturity interest rate, R (t) =
r (t) + s (t) is now the sum of two non-negative square root processes. Hence
the defaultable bond is inversely related to s (t) and can be strictly less than
the default-free bond as s (t) can always be positive when 22 s 22 .
Valuing the defaultable coupon bond of a particular issuer (e.g., corporation) is straightforward given the preceding analysis of defaultable zero-coupon
bonds. Suppose that the issuers coupon bond promises n cashflows, with the
ith promised cashflow being equal to ci and being paid at date Ti > t. Then
the value of this coupon bond in terms of our zero-coupon bond formulas is
n
P
i=1
D (t, Ti )
ci
B
(18.31)
Our results can also be applied to valuing credit derivatives. A credit default
swap is a popular credit derivative that typically has the following structure.
One party, the protection buyer, makes periodic payments until the contracts
maturity date as long as a particular issuer, bond, or loan does not default.
525
The other party, the protection seller, receives these payments in return for
paying the dierence between the bond or loans par value and its recovery
value if default occurs prior to the maturity of the swap contract. At the initial
agreement date of this swap contract, the periodic payments are set such that
the initial contract has a zero market value.
We can use our previous analysis to value each side of this swap. Let the
contract specify equal period payments of c at future dates t + , t + 2, ...,
t + n.20 Then recognizing that these payments are contingent on default not
occurring and that they have zero value following a possible default event, their
market value equals
n
c P
DZ (t, t + i)
B i=1
(18.32)
If we
let w (, x) be the recovery value of the defaultable bond (or loan) underlying
the swap contract, then assuming this bonds maturity date is T t + n, the
value of the swap protection can be computed similar to (18.11) as
bt
E
"Z
t+n
R
t
b
[r(u)+(u)
]du
b () [B w ( )] d
(18.33)
B 1
t+n
k (t, ) d
(18.34)
where k (t, ) is defined in (18.14). For given assumptions regarding the funcb (t, x), and w (t, x), and the state variables x, the value
tion forms of r (t, x),
20 A period of = one-half year is common since these payments often coincide with an
underlying coupon bond making semi-annual payments.
526
might be inferred by setting the actual market prices of one or more of an issuers
b (t),
bonds to their theoretical formulas. Then, based on the implied values of
s (t), or w (t), one can determine whether a given bond of the same issuer is overor under-priced relative to other bonds.
variables could be used to set the price of a new bond of the same issuer or a
credit derivative (such as a default swap) written on the issuers bonds.
18.3
Summary
Research on credit risk has grown significantly in recent years, generating and
generated by greater interest in credit risk management and credit derivatives.
This chapter introduced the two main branches of modeling defaultable bond
values.
In contrast,
the reduced form method abstracts from specific aspects of a firms financial
structure, but it can permit a more flexible modeling of default probabilities
and may provide a better fit to the prices of an issuers bonds.
While, due to space constraints, this chapter has been limited to models of
corporate defaults, the credit risk literature also encompasses additional topics
such as consumer credit risk and the credit risk of (securitized) portfolios of
loans and bonds.
18.4. EXERCISES
18.4
527
Exercises
1. Consider the example given in the structural approach to modeling default risk. Maintain the assumptions made in the chapter but now suppose
that a third party guarantees the firms debtholders that if the firm defaults, the debtholders will receive their promised payment of B. In other
words, this third-party guarantor will make a payment to the debtholders
equal to the dierence between the promised payment and the firms assets if default occurs. (Banks often provide such a guarantee in the form
of a letter of credit. Insurance companies often provide such a guarantee
in the form of bond insurance.)
What would be the fair value of this bond insurance at the initial date, t?
In other words, what would be the competitive bond insurance premium
to be charged at date t?
B1
if A (T ) B1
D1 (T ) =
A (T ) otherwise
528
B2
D2 (T ) =
A (T ) B1
if A (T ) B1 + B2
if B1 + B2 > A (T ) B1
otherwise
The firm is assumed to pay no dividends to its shareholders, and the value
of shareholders equity at date T , E (T ), is assumed to be
A (T ) (B1 + B2 ) if A (T ) B1 + B2
E (T ) =
0
otherwise
Assume that the value of the firms assets follows the process
dA/A = dt + dz
18.4. EXERCISES
529
their default intensities. Suppose that the maturity dates for the bonds
all exceed date T > t. Write down the expression for the probability that
none of the bonds in the portfolio defaults over the period from date t to
date T .
4. Consider the standard (plain vanilla) swap contract described in the previous chapter. In equation (17.67) it was shown that under the assumption
that each partys payments were default free, the equilibrium swap rate
agreed to at the initiation of the contract, date T0 , equals
s0,n (T0 ) =
1 P (T0 , Tn+1 )
P
n+1
j=1 P (T0 , Tj )
where for this contract fixed interest rate coupon payments are exchanged
for floating interest rate coupon payments at the dates T1 , T2 , ...,Tn+1 with
Tj+1 = Tj + and is the maturity of the LIBOR of the floating rate
coupon payments.
parties have credit risk. Suppose, instead, that they both have the same
credit risk, and it is equivalent to the credit risk reflected in LIBOR interest
rates.21 Moreover, assume a reduced form model of default with recovery
proportional to market value, so that the value of a LIBOR discount bond
promising $1 at maturity date Tj is given by (18.22):
RT
j
bT0 e T0 R(u,x)du
D (T0 , Tj ) = E
b (t, x) L
b (t, x) is assumed to be the same for both parties. Assume that if
default occurs at some date < Tn+1 , the counterparty whose position is
that LIBOR reflects the level of default risk for a large international bank.
530
s0,n (T0 ) =
1 D (T0 , Tn+1 )
P
n+1
j=1 D (T0 , Tj )
Bibliography
Abel, A. B. (1990): Asset Prices Under Habit Formation and Catching Up
with the Joneses, American Economic Review, 80, 3842.
Ahn, C.-M., and H. E. Thompson (1988): Jump-Diusion Processes and
the Term Structure of Interest Rates, Journal of Finance, 43, 155174.
Ahn, D.-H., R. F. Dittmar, and A. R. Gallant (2002): Quadratic Term
Structure Models: Theory and Evidence, Review of Financial Studies, 15,
243288.
Amin, K. I., and A. J. Morton (1994): Implied Volatility Functions in
Arbitrage-Free Term Structure Models, Journal of Financial Economics,
35, 141180.
Andersen, T. G., T. Bollerslev, F. X. Diebold, and H. Ebens (2001):
The Distribution of Realized Stock Return Volatility, Journal of Financial
Economics, 61, 4376.
Anderson, R. W., and J.-P. Danthine (1981): Cross Hedging, Journal
of Political Economy, 89(6), 11821196.
Ang, A., and M. Piazzesi (2003): A No-Arbitrage Vector Autoregression
of Term Structure Dynamics with Macroeconomic and Latent Variables,
Journal of Monetary Economics, 50(4), 745787.
567
568
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
569
570
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
571
Bollerslev, T., R. Y. Chou, and K. F. Kroner (1992): ARCH Modeling in Finance: A Review of Theory and Empirical Evidence, Journal of
Econometrics, 52, 559.
Brace, A., D. Gatarek, and M. Musiela (1997): The Market Model of
Interest Rate Dynamics, Mathematical Finance, 7(2), 127147.
Breeden, D. T. (1979): An Intertemporal Asset Pricing Model with Stochastic Consumption and Investment Opportunities, Journal of Financial
Economics, 7, 26596.
Brunnermeier, M. K. (2001): Asset Pricing under Asymmetric Information:
Bubbles, Crashes, Technical Analysis, and Herding. Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Campbell, J. (1999): Asset Prices, Consumption, and the Business Cycle,
in Handbook of Macroeconomics, ed. by J. B. Taylor, and M. Woodford. Amsterdam: North Holland.
Campbell, J. Y. (2000): Asset Pricing at the Millenium, Journal of Finance.
Campbell, J. Y., and J. H. Cochrane (1999): By Force of Habit: A Consumption Based Explanation of Aggregate Stock Market Behavior, Journal
of Political Economy, 107(2), 205251.
Campbell, J. Y., A. Lo, and C. MacKinlay (1997): The Econometrics of
Financial Markets. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Campbell, J. Y., and N. G. Mankiw (1989): Consumption, Income, and
Interest Rates: Reinterpreting the Time Series Evidence, in National Bureau
of Economic Research Macroeconomics Annual, ed. by O. J. Blanchard, and
S. Fischer, vol. 4. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
572
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
573
Constantinides, G. M. (1986): Capital Market Equilibrium with Transaction Costs, Journal of Political Economy, 94, 842862.
(1990): Habit Formation: A Resolution of the Equity Premium Puzzle, Journal of Political Economy, 98(3), 519543.
(1992): A Theory of the Nominal Term Structure of Interest Rates,
Review of Financial Studies, 5, 531552.
Coval, J. D., and T. Shumway (2003): Do Behavioral Biases Aect Prices?,
Journal of Finance, forthcoming.
574
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
575
576
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Duffie, D., D. Filipovic, and W. Schachermayer (2002):
577
Ane
578
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
579
580
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Ho, T., and S. B. Lee (1986): Term Structure Movements and Pricing Interest Rate Contingent Claims, Journal of Finance, 41, 10111028.
(2004): The Oxford Guide to Financial Modeling: Applications for
Capital Markets, Corporate Finance, Risk Management, and Financial Institutions. Oxford University Press, New York.
Hong, H., and J. C. Stein (1999): A Unified Theory of Underreaction,
Momentum Trading and Overreaction in Asset Markets, Journal of Finance,
54(6), 21432184.
Huang, J.-z., and M. Huang (2003): How Much of the Corporate-Treasury
Yield Spread Is Due to Credit Risk?, Penn State University, NYU, and
Stanford Business School Working Paper.
Huberman, G. (1982): A Simple Approach to Arbitrage Pricing Theory,
Journal of Economic Theory, 28, 183191.
Hull, J., and A. White (1990): Pricing Interest Rate Derivative Securities,
Review of Financial Studies, 3, 573592.
(1993): One-Factor Interest-Rate Models and the Valuation of
Interest-Rate Derivative Securities, Journal of Financial and Quantitative
Analysis, 28, 235254.
Hull, J. C. (2000): Options, Futures, and other Derivative Securities. PrenticeHall, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ, fourth edn.
Ingersoll, J. E. (1987): Theory of Financial Decision Making. Rowman &
Littlefield, Totowa, NJ.
Inui, K., and M. Kijima (1998): A Markovian Framework in Heath-JarrowMorton Models, Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 33, 423
440.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
581
582
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Jones, E., S. Mason, and E. Rosenfeld (1984): Contingent Claims Analysis of Corporate Capital Structures: An Empirical Investigation, Journal of
Finance, 39, 611627.
Jones, E. P. (1984): Option Arbitrage and Strategy with Large Price
Changes, Journal of Financial Economics, 13, 91113.
Judd, K. L. (1998): Numerical Methods in Economics. MIT Press, Cambridge,
MA.
Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky (1979): Prospect Theory: An analysis of
decision under risk, Econometrica, 47, 263291.
Karatzas, I., J. Lehoczky, and S. E. Shreve (1987): Optimal Portfolio
and Consumption Decisions for a "Small Investor" on a Finite Horizon,
SIAM Journal of Control and Optimization, 25, 15571586.
Karatzas, I., and S. E. Shreve (1991): Brownian Motion and Stochastic
Calculus. Springer-Verlag, New York.
Karlin, S., and H. M. Taylor (1975): A First Course in Stochastic
Processes. Academic Press, New York, NY.
(1981): A Second Course in Stochastic Processes. Academic Press,
New York, NY.
Kennedy, D. (1994): The Term Structure of Interest Rates as a Gaussian
Random Field, Mathematical Finance, 4, 247258.
(1997): Characterizing Gaussian Models of the Term Structure of
Interest Rates, Mathematical Finance, 7, 107118.
Kimmel, R. L. (2004): Modeling the Term Structure of Interest Rates: A
New Approach, Journal of Financial Economics, 72, 143183.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
583
584
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Leippold, M., and L. Wu (2002): Asset Pricing under the Quadratic Class,
Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 37(2), 271295.
Lettau, M., and S. Ludvigson (2001): Resurrecting the (C)CAPM: A
Cross-Sectional Test When Risk Premia Are Time-Varying, Journal of Political Economy, 109, 12381287.
Lettau, M., and H. Uhlig (2000): Can Habit Formation Be Reconciled with
Business Cycle Facts?, Review of Economic Dynamics, 3, 7999.
Lintner, J. (1965): The Valuation of Risky Assets and the Selection of Risky
Investments in Stock Portfolios and Capital Budgets, Review of Economics
and Statistics, 47, 1337.
Litterman, R., and J. Scheinkman (1988): Common Factors Aecting
Bond Returns, Journal of Fixed Income, 1, 5461.
Lo, A. W. (1988): Maximum Likelihood Estimation of Generalized Ito
Processes with Discretely Sampled Data, Econometric Theory, 4, 231247.
Longstaff, F. (1989): A Nonlinear General Equilibrium Model of the Term
Structure of Interest Rates, Journal of Financial Economics, 23, 195224.
Longstaff, F., and E. Schwartz (1995): A Simple Approach to Valuing
Risky Fixed and Floating Rate Debt, Journal of Finance, 50, 789819.
Lord, C. G., L. Ross, and M. R. Lepper (1979): Biased assimilation and
attitude polarization: the eects of prior theories on subsequently considered
evidence, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37(11), 20982109.
Lucas, R. E. (1972): Expectations and the Neutrality of Money, Journal of
Economic Theory, 4, 103124.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
585
586
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
587
588
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Piazzesi, M. (2005a): Ane Term Structure Models, in Handbook of Financial Econometrics, ed. by Y. Ait-Sahalia, and L. Hansen. Elsevier, Amsterdam.
(2005b): Bond Yields and the Federal Reserve, Journal of Political
Economy, 113, 311344.
Pliska, S. (1986): A Stochastic Calculus Model of Continuous Trading: Optimal Portfolios, Mathematics of Operations Research, 11, 371382.
Poterba, J. M., and L. H. Summers (1988): Mean Reversion in Stock
Returns: Evidence and Implications, Journal of Financial Economics, 22(1),
2759.
Pratt, J. W. (1964): Risk-Aversion in the Small and in the Large, Econometrica, 32(1), 12236.
Rabin, M., and R. H. Thaler (2001): Anomalies: Risk Aversion, Journal
of Economic Perspectives, 15(1), 219232.
Ramsey, F. P. (1928): A Mathematical Theory of Saving, Economic Journal, 38(4), 543559.
Rebonato, R. (2004): Interest-Rate Term Structure Pricing Models: A Review, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 460, 667728.
Richards, A. J. (1997): Winner-Loser Reversals in National Stock Market
Indices: Can They be Explained?, Journal of Finance, 52(5), 21292144.
Ritchken, P., and L. Sankarasubramanian (1995): Volatility Structures
of Forward Rates and the Dynamics of the Term Structure, Mathematical
Finance, 5, 5572.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
589
590
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
591
Thaler, R., and E. J. Johnson (1990): Gambling with the House Money
and Trying to Break Even: The Eects of Prior Outcomes on Risky Choice,
Management Science, 36, 643660.
Tirole, J. (1982): On the Possibility of Speculation Under Rational Expectations, Econometrica, 50(5), 11631181.
Tobin, J. (1958): Liquidity Preference as Behavior Towards Risk, Review of
Economic Studies, 67, 6586.
Treynor, J. L. (1961): Toward a Theory of Market Value of Risky Assets,
unpublished manuscript.
Tuckman, B. (2002): Fixed Income Securities: Tools for Todays Markets.
John Wiley and Sons, Inc., New York, second edn.
Varian, H. R. (1992): Microeconomic Analysis. W. W. Norton & Company,
third edn.
Vasicek, O. A. (1977): An Equilibrium Characterization of the Term Structure, Journal of Financial Economics, 5(2), 177188.
von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern (1944): Theory of Games and
Economic Behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Wachter, J. A. (2002): Portfolio and Consumption Decisions under MeanReverting Returns: An Exact Solution for Complete Markets, Journal of
Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 37(1), 6391.
Wang, J. (1993): A Model of Intertemporal Asset Prices Under Asymmetric
Information, Review of Economic Studies, 60, 249282.
Weil, P. (1989): The Equity Premium Puzzle and the Risk-Free Rate Puzzle,
Journal of Monetary Economics, 24, 401421.
592
BIBLIOGRAPHY