BRENNAN (Stoic Souls in Stoic Corpses)
BRENNAN (Stoic Souls in Stoic Corpses)
BRENNAN (Stoic Souls in Stoic Corpses)
Tad Brennan
What did the Stoics think about the relation between soul and body?
What did they think about the relation between any particular individual, e. g. you or I or Socrates, and the souls and bodies that in some sense
belong to us? Did they think that you and I and Socrates are simply
bodies? Simply souls? Did they think that we are a combination of
body and soul? Or did they have some more complicated view?
The texts that would have directly answered these questions are unfortunately lost. Few relevant scraps remain, and those are not obviously
consistent. So in this paper, I try to employ an indirect strategy: I try to
infer the answers to our questions about anthropology and metaphysics
from Stoic views about ethics and the final end.
Heres the thought: when the Stoics (or any other ancient school)
instruct you to pursue some telos or end, they do so as part of an account
of what is good for you. But an account of what is good for you for
you, rather than the cosmos or a community or a cow must involve an
account of what you, in fact, are. To put it somewhat awkwardly, you
are the thing for which the things-that-are-good-for-you, are good. If
we can figure out how to characterize the beneficiary of these benefits
what is the you for whom these things are good then we can figure
out what you are. And then the nature of the goods, and the way in
which they are good for you, may give us further detail about what exactly you are. So by starting from ethical evidence, we may be able to
This is a revised version of a talk that I gave at the Zweiter Kongress der Gesellschaft fr antike Philosophie in Hamburg, Germany in 2007. I am grateful to
Dorothea Frede for her organization of the event and for the invitation to speak
there. This paper incorporates and extends a line of thought I began in my book
The Stoic Life (2005), particularly chapter 8, and arrives at a determinate conclusion concerning some issues I left unresolved there. I received useful comments
from members of the Hamburg audience, particularly Tony Long, Brad Inwood, Keimpe Algra, Brad Inwood, Chris Gill, and Jula Wildberg. My revisions benefited from the advice of Charles Brittain and Jacob Klein. And as always, my deepest thanks go to Liz Karns.
390
Tad Brennan
I. Epictetus
This papers title comes from one of the few pieces of direct evidence, a
saying of Epictetus, that Marcus Aurelius reports to us: As Epictetus
used to say, you are a little soul, dragging around a corpse. (4.41.1)
This saying is extraordinary for a number of reasons. To begin with,
it identifies the human being with the soul alone, to the exclusion of the
body. It does not say that you are a living body, or a body that is animated by a soul, or a body together with a soul, or a combination of
body and soul. You are simply a soul.
This is reinforced by the striking word that is used of the souls relation to the body, that it bastazei. This verb bastazein, which in English we might translate as to drag or to lug, and in German as perhaps
schleppen, emphasizes the effort, discomfort, and unnaturalness of the
activity. When the Epicurean Lucretius wants to explain how the earth
can remain at rest on its underpinnings, he compares the earth to our
own heads, which, he says, rest so naturally and effortlessly on our
necks that we never notice their weight (5.541 further proof that Lucretius died young). He thinks the earth can do this because it is not an
alien burden resting on an alien support; the earth and its supporting air
grew together naturally from the start. Here, by contrast, Epictetus is
making the body a burden, an encumbrance, an alien weight constantly
perceived as impeding the souls freedom. Instead of saying that the soul
associates with a body or works in conjunction with a body or manifests
its psychic capacities through it, Epictetus says that it drags it.
Finally, the very word that Epictetus uses for the body makes a startling point: he calls it, not a body (sma), but a corpse (nekros) (not
Krper, but Leichnam). Socrates refers to his own body as a corpse,
in a striking passage in the Phaedo, probably the most body-hating of the
dialogues. He says towards the end (115a) that he will step off and have a
bath, in order to save the women the trouble of washing the corpse, referring to his own body. Socrates own cold-bloodedness in viewing his
body in these terms is consistent with his earlier condemnations of the
body for its role in causing all mortal evils and misfortunes. But he has at
least the excuse that his body will have become a corpse by the time he
refers to, i. e. by the time when the women would otherwise have to
391
wash it. Aristotle is even more brutal in a passage from the Protrepticus, in
which he compares our souls attachment to our body to the fate of captives who are tortured by being tied face-to-face and point-to-point
with corpses.2 On this picture we are the captives: that is, we are the
soul alone, and our bodies are loathsome and repellent corpses, things
we are unnaturally and inorganically bound to, things whose very proximity to us is a form of torture.
This picture of the body as something alien, extraneous, burdensome and noxious to the real human being, the soul, fits well with Socrates views in the Phaedo about both anthropology and ethics. A human
being is simply a soul, not a combination of soul and body, and the body
is a sort of prison (62b). Given that this is the sort of thing a human
being is, theres no mystery why the goods of the body should be no
part of our human good. It also fits with Socrates metaphysics. Soul
and body are of completely different types: the soul is an incorporeal,
partless, and immortal being, whereas the body is a corporeal, divisible,
and perishable being.
The ethical view of the body and its goods that we find in the Phaedo is very close to the view that we find in Stoic ethics, both in Epictetus
and elsewhere. The Stoics, too, thought that the body and the goods of
the body such as food, health, and wealth are indifferent to our own
happiness.
Of course, the official Stoic position is that there is no such thing as
a good of the body. Things that other philosophers and non-philosophers might call goods of the body really are not goods at all: they refuse to use the word good (agathon) of such things, or bad (kakon) of
their absences and opposites, reserving those appellations for virtue and
vice alone. This stance runs counter to ordinary usage (as the Stoics
were aware) 3 ; it also runs counter to a very natural argument, parts of
which they should be reluctant to reject. In outline, this argument familiar from, e. g., Socrates argument in Republic I4 would say that anything that has a function has a virtue, and anything that advances and
increases a things virtue is good for it. If sharpness is the virtue of knives, then being sharpened is good for them, and sharpening stones are
among the goods for knives. Thus it is very natural to say that food
is, at least in this sense, a good for the body; it helps the body to perform
2
3
4
392
Tad Brennan
its function. Why, then, do the Stoics insist that something that is a good
for my body in this sense cannot be a good for me, i. e. contribute to my
happiness?
And how well does this picture of the bodys ethical status fit with
Stoic anthropology? The Stoics certainly did not have the metaphysical
picture of the Phaedo, in which bodies are of a completely different
order and nature from the immaterial, imperishable souls. The Stoics insisted that souls, too, are corporeal, and that at least some souls are perishable.5 And turning from metaphysics to anthropology, I think it is
hard to find evidence from the Early Stoa that a human being was identified with the soul alone, rather than some combination of soul and
body. If, as seems possible from the evidence, they thought that a
human being is a compound of both soul and body, how could they
think that the good of one part of the human being, the good of the
body, is no part of the good of the whole human being?
The question I want to explore in this paper, then, is primarily a
question about Stoic anthropology in relation to Stoic ethics: what
did the Stoics think about the relation between the human body and
the human soul, and how does this fit with their views on the structure
and content of the human good?
Corporeality: Nemesius 81, 6 10 = SVF 2.790 = LS 45. Perishability: Eusebius, PE 15.20.6 = SVF 2.809 = LS 53W.
393
Antiochus maintained the view that the schools of Plato and Aristotle his so-called Old Academy6 had been in near-total agreement
on ethics, and that Stoic philosophy was either stolen from them, where
it was correct, or wrong when it was original. Or sometimes stolen, but
given a specious appearance of originality by pointless neologisms. The
view that Antiochus attributed to the Academics and Peripatetics is that
the good for human beings is a combination of virtue along with moderate physical advantages, i. e. some minimum of health, wealth, and the
other things the Stoics classify as promoted but not good. Virtue is by
far the most important of the goods in the view of Antiochus Old
Academy, and it is necessary for happiness no one can lead a good
and satisfying life who is not virtuous. This fact alone, Antiochus thinks,
will ensure that a rational agent will always have reason to do what is
virtuous, instead of pursuing some physical advantage in a way contrary
to virtue. But he denied that virtue is sufficient for happiness; crushing
pain or grinding poverty really are bad things that prevent their victims
from being happy, no matter how virtuous they may be. And accordingly, the goods of the body food and health, and the wealth that is
instrumental to their provision really are goods, goods for us.
The Stoic claim that such things make no difference to the agents
happiness is not at first sight very plausible, but it is at least bracing
and impressive. It degenerates into a laughable evasion when the Stoics
proceed to say that agents should select (eklegesthai) health because it is
promoted (progmenon) and avoid poverty because it is demoted (apoprogmenon).7 Antiochus complains that this relabeling will not change
the agents outlook. Let Zeno show me how I will be better prepared
to despise money if I classify it among the promoteds than if I call it a
good, or more courageous in enduring pain if I label it contrary to nature than if I call it bad.8
Before introducing his criticisms of the Stoics, Ciceros Antiochean
spokesman starts by listing some points on which he thinks the Stoics
will agree with him:
6
7
8
Cicero uses this term at Fin. 5.7 8; Antiochus included in it Platos disciples
Xenocrates, Speusippus, Polemo and Crantor, as well as Aristotle and his successor Theophrastus (see 4.3, 5.7).
As at e. g. Stobaeus 2.84 85 = SVF 3.128 = LS 58E. Long & Sedley translate
these terms as preferred and dispreferred. Promoted things were thought to
be in agreement with nature, and demoted things contrary to nature.
Cic. Fin. 4.72.
394
Tad Brennan
Let it be granted to begin with, that we have an affection for ourselves, and
that the earliest impulse bestowed upon us by nature is a desire for self-preservation.9 On this we are agreed [sc. Antiochus and the Stoics]; and the implication is that we must study what we ourselves are, in order to keep ourselves true to our proper character. We are, then, human beings, consisting
of a soul and body of a certain kind; and these are the things we ought to
esteem,10 as the first instincts of nature demand, and it is from these that we
must construct our End, our Chief and Ultimate Good.11
Thus Antiochus argued that, since our nature includes both body and
soul, so too our telos must include goods of the body as well as goods
of the soul; and since he takes it that the Stoics agree with him that
human nature is compounded of body as well as soul, he then asks
them how they can consistently reject goods of the body:
By what means, or at what point did you suddenly discard the body, and all
those things which are in accordance with nature but out of our control,
and lastly duty itself ? 12 My question then is, how comes it that so many
things that Nature strongly recommends have been suddenly abandoned
by Wisdom? Even if we were not seeking the telos of human beings, but
of some living creature that consisted solely of a mind (let us allow ourselves
to imagine such a creature, in order to facilitate our discovery of the truth),
even so that mind would not accept this telos of yours. For such a being
would ask for health, and freedom from pain, and would also desire its
own preservation, and security for the goods just specified; and it would
set up as its telos to live according to nature, which means, as I said, to possess [sc. not merely pursue] either all or most and the most important of the
things which are in accordance with nature. In fact, you may construct a
9 These are references to the theory of oikeisis, which we will examine more
fully below.
10 Its important to note that esteeming (diligere) my body and soul is not an act of
valuing them, either in the sense of judging them to be good or to be promoted. Rather, it is a matter of judging them to be the beneficiaries of the
other valued things. Its not a matter of the summum bonum, as I have put it elsewhere, but of the cui bono.
11 Cic. Fin. 4.25, tr. Rackham in Loeb edition.
12 This last reference to duty (see below on befitting actions) is extremely compressed. Of course the Stoics did not discard duty in the sense of denying
that certain actions are befitting, but Cicero is claiming that their rejection of
goods of the body will implicitly commit them to that denial. Antiochus is
here attacking the Stoics with one of their own arguments, developed later
at Fin. 4.46 (and cf. Off. 1.6) which says that a theory that makes health and
the like indifferent will be unable to provide a coherent account of befitting actions. This style of argument was crafted by Chrysippus to combat Aristos
more extreme assertion of the indifference of indifferents; see Fin. 3.50 (though
this contains no explicit reference to the befitting).
395
living creature of any sort you like, but even if it be devoid of a body, as is
our imaginary being, nevertheless its mind will be bound to possess certain
attributes analogous to those of the body, and consequently it will be impossible to set up for it a telos on any other line than those which I have laid
down. Now Chrysippus, in his survey of the differences between living
things, says that some of them excel by the body, and others excel by
the soul, while still others are equally endowed in respect of both; and
then he proceeds to discuss what constitutes the ultimate good proper to
each species. However, while he placed human beings in the genus that
excel in the soul, he then went on to define their summum bonum in
such a way that they seem not merely to excel by their souls, but actually
to be nothing beyond their souls. But the only case in which it would be
correct to place the summum bonum in virtue alone is if there existed a creature consisting solely of pure intellect, with the further proviso that this intellect possessed nothing of its own that was in accordance with nature, as
bodily health is. But it is impossible even to imagine a self-consistent picture of what such a creature would look like.13
We can see from this passage that Chrysippus wrote a book in which he
first talked about the nature of various species of living things, i. e. made
a survey of the differences between living things, and then for each
species derived from the account of its nature an account of its telos,
i. e. he proceeds to discuss what constitutes the ultimate good proper
to each species.14 That this was the direction and order of argumentation in Chrysippus book is secured, not only by the comment then he
proceeds to discuss, but also by the whole structure of Antiochus criticism here.
It is extremely interesting, I think, that Chrysippus adopted this
method. He seems to have operated with the principle that in the
case of anything that can be said to have a telos, that thing will have
that telos in virtue of its nature. He applied this principle in the case
of a variety of different living things, discussing the differences in
their natures and the differences in their ends that flowed from them.
And he applied the same principle in the same way to the case of
human beings. Diogenes Laertius (7.85) tells us that in the first book
of his treatise On Ends (Peri teln), Chrysippus said that self-preservation
is the first appropriate thing for every living thing, panti zi, and then
Diogenes tells us how animals differ from plants by using impulse to
13 Fin. 4.26 29, translation modified from Rackham.
14 The introduction of the purely psychic creature is not obviously Antiochus innovation; Chrysippus may have introduced hypothetical creatures of this sort
for his own purposes in developing his survey.
396
Tad Brennan
397
398
Tad Brennan
399
the telos of each species, and in particular the human telos, from a
specification of its nature; indeed, it was exactly because Antiochus
was convinced that this remained Chrysippus strategy that he continued to feel that Chrysippus was guilty of an inconsistency.
What we cannot derive from this passage, I am afraid, is any very clear
account of how Chrysippus thought the human soul is related to the
body. For instance, what exactly did he mean by saying that human beings excel by their souls, animo excellere? I myself would be pleased
even to figure out what Greek word he used (not that it seems to
have helped Antiochus very much). And would Chrysippus have agreed
with Epictetus that you are a little soul, lugging around a corpse?
They certainly agreed that the end for human beings is virtue and virtue
alone, and they certainly agreed that bodily health and wealth and what
we ordinarily call goods are not goods at all. But did they agree on the
underlying account of human nature? Was it, as I have suggested, exactly in virtue of their account of human nature that they denied that
the things are goods? Was their denial that bodily goods are good simpliciter derived from a view that human beings are not bodily creatures?
I believe that it was, and I shall argue for this claim in the rest of the
paper.
400
Tad Brennan
instance I have found of the claim that a human being is composed out
of soul and body. From its role in the context defending the consistency of Zenos definition with other parts of Stoic doctrine I have
some confidence that it is a genuinely Stoic claim rather than a piece
of skeptical mischief.
Somewhat similar is a line from Hierocles Elements,18 in which he
says that the living thing (to zion) is a composite of both soul and
body (syntheton ex amphotern, ek smatos kai psychs). The claim is not
specifically about a human being, but it is generically about living
things, and to the extent that it supports the Sextus passage, it is starting
to look as though Epictetus is in disagreement with his predecessors in
claiming that a human being is merely a soul.
There are also places where the cosmos is said to be composed of
soul and body, and this claim is used in order to argue that the cosmos
is an animal for that reason. Dio Chrysostom19 tells us that the constitution of the cosmos is very similar to that of the other living things, inasmuch as it is composed of soul and body (tote d malista proseoiks ti tn
alln systasei zin, kath hoson ek psychs kai smatos synestanai), and Plutarch20 gives us a direct quotation from Chrysippus treatise On Providence, in which he says that the kosmos is composed of soul and body
(synestanai ek psychs kai smatos).
These passages make it look as though Antiochus is right to think
that Stoic axiology is inconsistent with Stoic anthropology: the Stoics
do seem to say that living things in general, and human beings in particular, are a compound, composed of soul and body.
On the other hand, there are passages that make it look as though a
human being is the soul only even outside of the Epictetus fragment
we began with. Consider the following rather odd passage that Galen
quotes.21 Its a text in which Chrysippus is arguing that the commanding-faculty is located in the chest, by examining what happens when we
say the Greek word for I, i. e. the first person singular personal pronoun eg:
Here is what Chrysippus wrote about the word eg in the first of his books
On the Soul, in a discussion of the commanding faculty: This is also how
we say eg, pointing at ourselves (heautous), in the place in which we de18
19
20
21
401
clare the intellect (dianoia) to be, since the pointing-gesture is carried there
naturally and appropriately. And even without a pointing-gesture of this
sort using our hands, we incline towards ourselves (heautous) when we
say eg, both because that is the immediate effect of the sound eg,
and because of the accompanying pointing-gesture that Im about to describe. For we utter the first syllable of eg by drawing down the lower
lip, gesturing at ourselves (heautous). And following on the motion of the
chin and the inclination towards the chest and that kind of pointing-gesture, the next syllable remains adjacent and does not suggest something
at a distance, as happens with ekeinos [i.e. that man].
Chrysippus wants to prove that the rational soul is in the heart, while
Galen holds that it is in the brain. Let us not dwell, as Galen does, on
the spectacle of lunatic phonology in the service of crackpot anatomy.
We should focus only on the repeated insistence that three things are
collocated in the chest: the commanding faculty, i. e. rational soul or dianoia, the referent of ego, and the self or heautous. Three times we are
told that pointing towards the chest means pointing towards ourselves,
and that this is evidence that our soul must be in our chest. Consider the
inference; would the collocation of our self and our chest tell us anything about where our soul is, if the body were part of the self ? If
my body were part of me, then of course I would be pointing at myself
when I point at my chest and this would remain true no matter where
my soul might reside. This seems to me pretty good evidence that
Chrysippus agrees with Epictetus on the central point: myself, what I
refer to when I say I, is the same as my soul, in particular my dianoia
or hgemonikon.
Well what are we to make of all of this? I think that we can get a
clear picture of the Stoic doctrine, and also explain the source of Antiochus confusion, if we look at the word systasis. This is a noun derived
from the verb we have seen above, synestanai, and it means something
like constitution or composition. As usual, nominalizations like this
manifest a process/product ambiguity: is a systasis the process of putting
some components together, or is it the compound that results from this
process? In the case of Stoicism, I think it is actually a third thing, something like a principle of composition, a cause of the compounding, or a
rationale for the structure of the compound. (The word constitution
itself, as used in political philosophy, works exactly this way; the constitution of a government is neither the act of constituting the government, nor the government itself that is the product of that process, but
rather the principle and rationale for the structure of the government,
402
Tad Brennan
e. g. the principles that make it a parliamentary system, give it a bicameral legislation, and so on.)
I already mentioned the passage from Chrysippus On Ends, in which
he said that self-preservation is the first appropriate thing for every living
thing.22 But what he said more precisely is that the first appropriate or
oikeion thing for each animal is its systasis.
They say that the first impulse an animal has is towards preserving itself
(hauto), since nature made it appropriate/familiar to itself from the very beginning, as Chrysippus says in the first book of the treatise On Ends, where
he says that the first thing that is appropriate/familiar to each animal is its
own systasis and its awareness of this.
Notice how this passage says both that the first appropriated thing is the
systasis, and also that nature from the very beginning makes the animal
appropriate or familiar to itself, heauto. It is not impossible that this describes two, simultaneous acts of oikeisis of two distinct things, but it
looks to me more likely that it is describing one act of oikeisis,
whose object can be described indifferently as the systasis, or heauto.
This reading is supported by a passage of Alexander of Aphrodisias23
in which he says:
Now the Stoics (though not all of them) say that the first thing that is oikeion to an animal is itself (hauti) (for each animal, as soon as it is born, is
made oikeion to itself and hence the human being, too). But the Stoics
who seem a bit more sophisticated and careful about the matter say that
as soon as we are born what is made appropriate to us is our systasis and
its preservation.
Here too, the systasis is put in parallel with the animal itself, or made to
be a more accurate characterization of the animals self. What we mean
by referring to itself, if we consider the matter carefully, is the animals
systasis.
Seneca24 tells us that the constitutio (a natural Latin rendering of systasis) is the commanding-faculty in a certain state relative to the body
(principale animi quodammodo se habens erga corpus).25 He then tells us
22
23
24
25
D.L. 7.85.
De An. Mant. 150.25 = SVF 3.183.
Sen. Ep. 121.
This verbal formulation seems to fit the pattern for an item in the fourth Stoic
genus, i. e. the pros ti ps echon. Fourth-genus predications are those whose
nature it is to become and cease to be a property of something without any internal change or qualitative alteration For son and man on the right, in
order to be there, need certain external things. Hence without any internal
403
that the first thing made familiar to every animal is its constitutio, but that
the constitution of a human being is a rational one, and thus a human
being is made familiar to itself not qua animal, but qua rational.
These passages are enough, I think, to solve our problem. When
Seneca says that our constitutio, our systasis, is the commanding-faculty
in a certain relation to the body, he is not saying that our systasis is a
compound of soul and body. Quite the contrary: the systasis simply is
the hgemonikon, though it is the hgemonikon described in a certain
way, in relation to a certain object. Just as one and the same body
can be both a hand and also a fist, when so disposed, so too our soul
is also our virtue, when so disposed, or our knowledge, when otherwise
disposed. Here we learn that our hgemonikon, that very portion of pneuma, is also our systasis, when disposed in a certain way in relation to the
body. And this is our self. Not the soul and the body, but rather the soul
as a principle of composition for the soul-body compound.
Now we can see why the more sophisticated Stoics mentioned by
Alexander said that our ethical grounding comes, not from an appropriation to the animal, but from an appropriation to the systasis. And this is
the same systasis that was put in parallel by Diogenes Laertius with the
change, a father could cease to be a father on the death of his son, and the man
on the right could cease to be the man on his right if his neighbor changed position. (Simplicius, in Cat. 166.15 29 = SVF 2.403 = LS 29C; tr. from LS
29C). I believe this applies to the systasis as well; if the body perishes, then
the systasis is not a systasis any longer. But of course it does not follow that
the underlying substance is destroyed; when the father ceases to be a father,
the man who was a father does not thereby die, and the soul-like entity that
was a systasis need not perish either. Nor should we infer from the fact that
the substance receives the fourth-genus predication in virtue of a Cambridgechange like relation, that it cannot exercise robust causal powers towards the
object it is related to. It is true that the Stoics deny that the father has some inherent differentiation (diaphora) that entitles the man to be called a father;
this depends entirely on the existence of the external relatum, sc. the offspring.
However, the father can still interact causally with his offspring in a variety of
robust ways. Some of the possibilities for robust causal interaction arise from the
fact that the father is still a substance and a qualified thing, so, e. g. the father can
fall on his offspring qua massive, or warm them qua heated. But some of these
robust causal interactions involve the father acting on his offspring qua father,
beginning with the very begetting of them. So from the fact that the systasis
seems to be a fourth-category item, nothing follows about its ability to exercise
robust causal powers of organizing, governing, shaping, and so on, the body
that it is relative to. I hope that something like this will answer a question
that David Sedley put to me in Hamburg.
404
Tad Brennan
heauto of the animal. It is not the same as the animal, which is a compound, but it is the same as the animals self.
And here you can see why Antiochus will have been confused. For
Chrysippus is quite happy to say that every animal is a compound of soul
and body, and that human beings, too, are a compound of soul and
body. He never denies that human beings are composed of body and
soul. But if we ask who I am, or who Chrysippus is, then the answer
is that I am not a soul-body compound. Rather, we, ourselves, are
the principle of composition, the systasis, which is only a name for
the hgemonikon playing a particular role.
This explains why Chrysippus was not inconsistent in giving us an
end that is suitable for a purely psychic creature. Although as an animal,
human beings are composed of soul and body, when we ask who we
are, what our selves are, then the answer is that we are a purely psychic
thing, the systasis or hgemonikon.
In one way, my proposal that the systasis is a principle of composition rather than the composite makes it like an Aristotelian form, especially an Aristotelian soul. I dont mind that comparison, but I think in
fact that the Stoic soul is even more loosely bound to the body than the
Aristotelian soul is. Unlike the Aristotelians, the Stoics seem to have argued that at least in certain cases, the souls of certain individuals can survive the separation of soul and body, and persist as unified portions of
pneuma without bodies, in which case they are called daimones or sometimes hres.26 I think this makes all the more sense when we think of
the Stoic souls relation to the body as just one of the jobs it can do.
True, while the soul is incorporated, it plays the role of organizing
the soul-body compound that is the animal, and that is when we call
it a systasis. But that is to describe it as relatively disposed towards
something else, not to say what it is in its essence.
After all, Socrates in the Phaedo also thinks that, during life, his soul
is involved in some sort of compound with a body. That is why he defines death as the separation of the soul from the body; they must be
somehow combined if they need to be separated. But even though
he concedes that there is a soul-body compound during life, he does
not think of that compound as himself; the real Socrates, the one
who is talking and arranging all of his words, is only a soul, not a compound. The relation to the body is not essential to Socrates in any way;
it is just an accidental episode in his biography.
26 S.E. M. 9.71 = SVF 2.812; D.L. 7.151 = SVF 2.1102.
405
406
Tad Brennan
come a nature, an irrational soul, and finally a rational soul. And at each
stage of his life, that same thing could be called the systasis of that stage.
Furthermore, when we look at a variety of living things e.g. a tree and
a fish and Socrates we may say that each one is the same as its systasis,
where that refers in the first case to a nature that is somehow relatively
disposed to some woody-stuff, in the second case to an irrational soul
that is somehow relatively disposed to some fishy flesh, and in the
third case to a hgemonikon that is somehow disposed towards a
human body.
Thus systasis acts as a convenient covering term, in two ways: it
can refer indifferently to a variety of soul-like entities in a variety of distinct life-forms (tree, fish, man), picking out their roles in organizing
that life-form; and it can refer indifferently to the same soul-like entity
in the course of one individuals development from embryo to rational
adult, even though that soul-like entity undergoes important qualitative
changes that take it from being a physis to being a hgemonikon in the
space of fifteen years. Each age of life, Seneca tells us, has its constitution: one for the infant, one for the boy, one for the adolescent, one
for the old man.29 Characterized in relation to the kind of life-form
that the systasis is constituting, and the kind of soul-like entity that anchors the systasis, the systasis is different at each age: when Socrates is in
utero, his systasis is a physis, disposed in a certain way towards the body of
a plant, whereas when he is a toddler, his systasis is an irrational soul, disposed in a certain way towards the body of an irrational animal, and
when he is an adult, his systasis is a rational soul, a hgemonikon, disposed
in a certain way towards the body of a rational human being. But of
course, viewed as one diachronic individual, we can say that one and
the same thing was Socrates self at every stage, and that at every
stage it was his systasis.
You can see that many of the same problems are going to arise for
the Stoics that arise for the Platonists. The relation between the soul and
the body is fairly clear, but now we would like to hear more about the
relation between myself and the human being. I am not a compound of
soul and body, but there is such a compound, a human being, and its
not altogether clear how I am related to it. In particular, it is not altogether clear why I should take the ethical and desiderative attitude towards it that the Stoics urge me to take. I should be indifferent to my
body, because it is no part of the real me, which is my hgemonikon
29 Sen. Ep. 121 = LS 57B.
407
ISBN 978-3-11-020236-6
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Gesellschaft fr antike Philosophie. Kongress (2nd : 2007 : University of
Hamburg)
Body and soul in ancient philosophy / edited by Dorothea Frede and
Burkhard Reis.
p. cm.
This volume contains a collection of papers presented at the Second
International Conference of the Gesellschaft fr antike Philosophie e.V.
(GANPH) at the University of Hamburg from 18 to 21 July 2007 - Pref.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-3-11-020236-6 (hardcover : alk. paper)
1. Mind and body - Congresses. 2. Soul - Congresses. 3. Ancient philosophy - Congresses.
I. Frede, Dorothea, 1941- II. Reis,
Burkhard. III. Title.
B105.M53G47 2007
1281.1093-dc22
2009027593
Preface
This volume contains a collection of papers presented at the Second International Conference of the Gesellschaft fr antike Philosophie e.V.
(GANPH) at the University of Hamburg from 18 to 21 July 2007.
The relationship between the body and soul was chosen as the theme
for this conference because this issue was a key topic in the debates
among philosophers from the Archaic period to the beginnings of
early Christianity, and has not ceased to be of interest since antiquity.
In recent decades, however, discussion of the so-called mind-body
problem has intensified enormously due to the rapid progress of the
neurosciences, which has led to a more differentiated understanding
of the connections and relationship between physiological and cognitive
processes. The question of the unity or duality of mind and brain has
therefore become one of the most controversial topics within and between the fields of philosophy, psychology, neurophysiology, and related disciplines. Even if the philosophers in antiquity had no conception
of the complex processes underlying neurophysiology, they did anticipate key questions that are still at the center of attention nowadays.
The conference was made possible thanks to the financial contributions of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft, the University of Hamburg, the ZEIT-Stiftung, and of the Hamburgische Stiftung fr Wissenschaften, Entwicklung und Kultur Helmut und Hannelore Greve. The
staff of the office of the Gesellschaft fr antike Philosophie provided organizational and planning assistance in preparing for the conference.
The fact that the conference itself progressed not only without a
break-down, but also to the participants expressed satisfaction, is due
to the careful planning and supervision of Dr. Burkhard Reis at all
stages, and also to the initiative and untiring support provided by the
conference assistants on the spot. Profound thanks are extended to all
organisations and persons who contributed to the success of the conference, not least to the speakers and to the faithful and attentive audience.
Regrettably, due to page limitations, not all of the presentations delivered at the conference could be included in this volume. The necessary limitations did not permit the inclusion of contributions by the fifteen younger scholars who were selected as speakers via a call for papers. Since the omitted presentations constituted valuable additions to
VI
Preface
Dorothea Frede
Contents
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
I. Presocratics
Carl Huffman
The Pythagorean conception of the soul from Pythagoras to
Philolaus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
21
Christian Schfer
Das Pythagorasfragment des Xenophanes und die Frage nach der
Kritik der Metempsychosenlehre . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
45
Brad Inwood
Empedocles and metempsychsis: The critique of Diogenes of
Oenoanda . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
71
Anthony A. Long
Heraclitus on measure and the explicit emergence of rationality
87
Georg Rechenauer
Demokrits Seelenmodell und die Prinzipien der atomistischen
Physik . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
111
II. Plato
David Sedley
Three kinds of Platonic immortality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
145
Michael Erler
Denn mit Menschen sprechen wir und nicht mit Gttern.
Platonische und epikureische epimeleia ts psychs . . . . . . . . . . .
163
Gyburg Radke-Uhlmann
Die energeia des Philosophen zur Einheit von literarischem
Dialog und philosophischer Argumentation in Platons Phaidon .
179
VIII
Contents
Jan Szaif
Die aret des Leibes: Die Stellung der Gesundheit in Platons
Gterlehre . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
205
III. Aristotle
Gnther Patzig
Krper und Geist bei Aristoteles
zum Problem des Funktionalismus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
249
Christopher Shields
The priority of soul in Aristotles De anima: Mistaking
categories? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
267
David Charles
Aristotle on desire and action . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
291
Friedemann Buddensiek
Aristoteles Zirbeldrse? Zum Verhltnis von Seele und pneuma
in Aristoteles Theorie der Ortsbewegung der Lebewesen . . . .
309
Ursula Wolf
Aporien in der aristotelischen Konzeption des Beherrschten und
des Schlechten . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
331
IV. Academy
John Dillon
How does the soul direct the body, after all? Traces of a dispute
on mind-body relations in the Old Academy . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
349
V. Hellenism
Keimpe Algra
Stoics on souls and demons: Reconstructing Stoic demonology
359
Tad Brennan
Stoic souls in Stoic corpses . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
389
Contents
IX
Christopher Gill
Galen and the Stoics: What each could learn from the other
about embodied psychology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
409
Martha C. Nussbaum
Philosophical norms and political attachments: Cicero and
Seneca . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
425
447
Therese Fuhrer
Der Geist im vollkommenen Krper. Ein Gedankenexperiment
in Augustins De civitate dei 22 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
465
Theo Kobusch
Die Auferstehung des Leibes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
493
Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
511