Anarchy and Pragmatism
Anarchy and Pragmatism
Anarchy and Pragmatism
Anti-Copyright
Wayne Price
Anarchism and the Philosophy of Pragmatism
originally May 2014. Updated for Utopian Magazine
Retrieved on February 16th, 2015 from http://
www.utopianmag.com/files/in/1000000144/7_Pragmatism.pdf
theanarchistlibrary.org
Stikkers, Kenneth W. (2009). Dewey, economic democracy, and the Mondragon cooperatives. European Journal of
Pragmatism and American Philosophy. Pp. 185-198. http://
lnx.journalofpragmatism.eu/wpcontent/uploads/2012/01/EJPAP_2011 _III_2.pdf
Tabor, Ronald D. (2013). The Tyranny of Theory: A Contribution
to the Anarchist Critique of Marxism. Edmonton Alberta Canada:
Black Cat Press.
Trotsky, Leon (1966). Their morals and ours. Their Morals and
Ours: Marxist versus Liberal Views on Morality (ed. George Novack). NY: Merit Publishers. Pp. 13-43.
West, Cornell (1989). The American Evasion of Philosophy; A Geneology of Pragmatism. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Westbrook, Robert B. (1991). John Dewey and American Democracy. Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press.
Westbrook, Robert B. (2005). Democratic Hope: Pragmatism and
the Politics of Truth. Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press.
Wieck, David (1978). Anarchist justice. In Anarchism (ed. J. R.
Pennock & J. W. Chapman). NOMOS XIX. NY: New York University
Press. Pp. 215-236.
*original version published on www.Anarkismo.net
31
McKenna, Erin (2001). The Task of Utopia: A Pragmatist and Feminist Perspective. Lanham MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Manicas, Peter T. (1974). The Death of the State. NY: Capricorn
Books/ G.P. Putnams Sons.
Manicas, Peter T. (Spring 1982). John Dewey: Anarchism and
the political state. Transactions of the Charles S. Pierce Society.
Vol. 18, no. 2. Pp. 133-158.
Manicas, Peter T. (2008). Philosophy and politics: A historical
approach to Marx and Dewey. http://www2.hawaii.edu/-manicas/
pdf_files/chap10web.pdf
Marx, Karl (1938). Theses on Feuerbach, 1938 translation.
Source: Marx-Engels Collected Works
May, Todd (1994). The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism. University Park PA: Pennsylvania State University
Press.
Pereira, Irene (2009). Proudhon, pragmatist. (trans. V. Cisney
& N. Morar). New Perspectives on Anarchism.(ed. Nathan J. Jun
& Shane Wahl). Lanham MD: Lexington Books. Pp. 227-240. http:/
/pages.uoregon.edu/nmorar/Nicolae_Morar/Publications_files/
ProudhonPragmatist.pdf
Phelps, Christopher (1997). Young Sidney Hook: Marxist and
Pragmatist. Ithaca NY/London: Cornell University Press.
Price, Wayne (2009). The two main trends in anarchism.
Anarkismo.
http://anarkismo.net/article/
13536?search_text=Wayne+Price
Price, Wayne (2010), Paul Goodmans anarchism. Anarchism
and Socialism: Reformism or Revolution? Edmonton, Alberta,
Canada: thoughtcrime ink. Pp. 118-132.
Price, Wayne (2013). The Value of Radical Theory: An Anarchist
Introduction to Marxs Critique of Political Economy. Oakland CA:
AK Press.
Ryan, Alan (1997). John Dewey and the High Tide of American
Liberalism. NY/London: W.W. Norton.
30
Contents
What is Pragmatism? . . . . . . . . . . .
Pragmatism, Democracy, and Anarchism
Pragmatism, Reformism, and Revolution .
Reformism or Revolution? . . . . . . . . .
In Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
6
11
17
21
26
28
tive self-determination through discussion, intelligence, and collective problem-solving. Pragmatists have usually rejected the need
for a social revolution, but there have been some who have seen
its necessity.
It is possible to be a pragmatist in philosophy and a revolutionary anarchist, or so I believe. I think this combination provides the
best tools for consistent revolutionary praxis. It is at least worth
exploring.
References
Bartenberger, Martin (2014). John Dewey and David Graeber: Elements of radical democracy in pragmatist and anarchist thinking.
Paper prepared for the Fourth Annual Radical Democracy Conference at The New School, NYC, and presented on 15th March 2014.
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2408571
Bernstein, Richard J. (2010). The Pragmatic Turn. Cambridge UK/
Malden MA: Polity Press.
Bookchin, Murray (1996). The Philosophy of Social Ecology: Essays on Dialectical Naturalism. Montreal/NY: Black Rose Books.
Cohen, Jesse S. (2006). Anarchism and the Crisis of Representation; Hermeneutics, Aesthetics, Politics. Cranbury NJ: Selinsgrove:
Susquehanna University Press.
Coon, Deborah J. (June 1996). One moment in the worlds salvation: Anarchism and the radicalization of William James. The
Journal of American History. Vol. 83, no. 1. Pp. 70-99.
Cork, Jim (1950). John Dewey and Karl Marx. John Dewey:
Philosopher of Science and Freedom (ed. Sidney Hook). NY: Dial
Press. Pp. 331-350.
Dabrowski, Tomash, & Schmidt, Eric (2014). Anarchopragmatism: Deciding how to decide. Paper presented at the
annual meeting of the Southern Political Science Association, The
28
Pragmatism, in popular speech, is regarded as meaning a shallow opportunism. This is not its philosophical meaning. Philosophically, it means, literally, practicalism or praxis. William James
(who initiated the pragmatic movement) called much of his philosophy radical empiri- cism. John Dewey (who continued to develop
pragmatism) preferred the label instrumentalism or experimentalism. Some anarchists might protest that, far from being anarchists, almost all pragmatists are or have been liberals or social
democratic reformists. Certainly Dewey was.
This is essentially true, although not entirely true, as I will discuss.
What is Pragmatism?
Before giving my views on what pragmatism is, I must raise two
warnings. The first is that prag- matists disagree among themselves.
Dewey and James saw some things differently. They both had disagreements with Charles S. Pierce (who first used the term). The
most prominent philosopher in the revival of pragmatism in the
1980s and 90s was Richard Rorty. Yet many of his fellow neopragmatists argue that he has incorrectly rejected parts of Deweys heritage (Guignon & Hiley 2003; Kloppenberg 1996; Westbrook 2005).
The other caveat is that, while I am an anarchist (who has also
been influenced by aspects of Marxism), I am not a philosopher,
except at the most amateur level. This is my best understanding of
the philosophy of John Dewey and other pragmatists, as well as I
can explain it. For those interested, they should read further. Short
books which cover Deweys trend of thought include Hildebrand
(2008) and Hook (1995). A good selection of Deweys writings may
be found at McDermott (1981). Two fine biographies (which consider Deweys politics) are Ryan (1997) and Westbrook (1991).
Pragmatism is an experimental naturalism, which means it rejects all supernaturalism, without necessarily rejecting everything
6
ing to consider even the most radical ones. In the course of fighting
for better lives, the working people and others can educate themselves and transform themselves. They may make themselves into
self-governing members of a truly democratic society.
Richard Rorty himself has imagined his own pragmatist liberalism coming to pass after a national economic collapse, followed
by a military coup and its overturn. So Westbrook (2005; p. 169)
explains. Westbrook doubts this could happen, which, I think, expresses a limited understanding of the nature of the times we live
in. Given the economic, military, and ecological/ environmental
threats facing the human species, an anarchist-socialist revolution
would not only be a morally good thing, but may be a necessary thing for human survival. The alternatives are socialism or
barbarism (Luxemburg), anarchism or annihilation (Bookchin).
This is a very practical issue (Price 2013).
To return to my starting point: anarchists have believed in a wide
variety of philosophies (those who have thought about philosophy).
Pragmatists, followers of the philosophy I am recommending, such
as Bernstein (2010), find it valuable to be in dialogue with philosophers of different traditions. And pragmatists have believed in a
wide variety of politics. Most were liberals or social democrats, but
a few were conservatives. Some were Marxist socialists of various
sorts and some were anarchist socialists. Most believed in legal,
peaceful, reforms, but a few have been revolutionaries. William
James (1981) felt that the philosophies people adopted were influenced by their psychological temperaments. In any case, the connection between a set of philosophical beliefs and a specific political program is complex and affected by many factors.
Influenced by Hegel, Deweyan pragmatism has a holistic and
dynamic viewpoint. It includes some of the most positive aspects
of Marxs method, while rejecting its rigid determinism and teleology. It shares with anarchism a belief in radical, decentralized,
democracy, including in the industries of a socialized economy.
Like anarchism, it seeks to replace authoritarian rule by coopera27
By the end of the 1930s, Hook began to turn to the right. He felt
the pressures of the spread of Stalinist totalitarianism, of World
War II followed by the Cold War, and of the post-war prosperity in
the West. He devolved into an anti-communist cold-warrior, to the
right of Dewey. (The same was true of others, such as Max Eastman.
For a time he too was a student of John Dewey and a revolutionary
Marxist. He also moved far to the right.)
Christopher Phelps has sought to revive interest in Sidney Hooks revolutionary period (Phelps 1997). He argues that
Deweyan pragmatism is still consistent with a socialism which is
revolution- ary, democratic, and Marxist a socialism-from-below.
He rejects arguments that it was Hooks pragmatism which led
him to move to the right. However, Phelps Leninism (and Trotskyism) mar his efforts to make a radically-democratic case for
a pragmatic Marxism. Granted that Lenin was not Stalin, he and
Trotsky did establish a one-party police state which laid the basis
for Stalinism. Phelps does not consider the alternate approach for
a radically-democratic socialism-from-below revolutionary anarchism.
In Conclusion
Possibly the major argument against a revolutionary perspective is the current nonrevolutionaryif not outright reactionary
consciousness of most US people (whether we look at them as
workers or as citi- zens). Very, very, few are presently considering revolution. Yet there have been revolutions! A revolutionary
perspective is built on the possibility that most peoples consciousness may change. Our society is already facing economic crises,
dangers of war, and coming ecological, environmental, and energy
catastrophes. If the capitalist ruling class and its politicians are unable to deal with these issues (as they seem to be), then more and
more people may be looking around for answers. They may be will26
without a proslavery rebellion, to this peaceful and legal revolution (quoted on p. 292). This is a reference to the US Civil War,
which Marx had observed. Lincoln had gotten elected legally and
peacefully. Rather than accept the results, the slaveowners rose up,
took most of the nations officer corps, and tried to overturn the
government and break up the country in a bloody civil war. Hook
commented, As if it were not precisely the danger of a proslavery
rebelliona counterrevolution which demanded that the revolution everywhere assure its victory by a resort to force! (p. 292).
Hook believed that Marxs speculations of a peaceful, legal, revolution were unrealistic even at the time he made them, let alone a
century later. (This was a view anarchists had held in Marxs day.)
Westbrook (2005) criticizes the revolutionary Sidney Hook by
citing an article Hook wrote on workers democracy in 1934. In
this article, Hook had claimed that the rule of the workers would
include denying the former capitalists political rightsfreedom of
speech, assembly, and agitation (Hook quoted on p. 125). Westbrook rejects this political repression of a minority and raises questions about how democratic workers democracy would really be.
I agree that Hook was wrong to make political repression of the
bourgeoise, after a revolution, into an apparent principle. It should
be a matter of expediency, with as much freedom as possible for
everyone and political repression only if necessary (if they organize sabotage and armed counterrevolution). Making repression a
principle reflected Hooks Leninism.
However, Westbrook missed the real point. What the bourgeoisie
will resent about workers democracy is not really the possible
loss of their votesit is the loss of their capital, their industries,
their banks, their incomes, their mansions, their estates, their status. They will be furious about these being taken away from them
(even under Deweys program of socialization), much more than
about their right to circulate petitions. As far as they are concerned,
this expropriation is what makes the purest workers democracy
into a dictatorship.
25
olution. Not only anarchists, but, as can be seen, almost all of the
pragmatists who were influenced by Marx also adopted a nonrevolutionary, reformist perspective (see Cork 1950).
The most significant exception among Deweys followers was
the early Sidney Hook. Hook was a prominent student and explicator of Deweyan pragmatism. Yet in the 1920s and 30s he was
also the leading US Marxist scholar. He wrote two major books
explaining Marxs Marxism, one being Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx (Hook 2002). It was a critique of Marxs overall
views of politics and philosophy. At the time, Hook saw himself
as a follower of Lenin, whom he (incorrectly) interpreted as a radical democrat. This was based on Lenins apparent support of soviets (elected councils) of workers and peasants, rooted in factory
committees and village councils, replacing the bourgeois state. But
Hook was also influenced by Rosa Luxemburg and Karl Korsch,
who really were inspired by the humanistic, democratic, and libertarian aspects of Marxism.
Hooks main goal was to expound a revolutionary interpretation of Marx. In the course of his book, he answered most of the
arguments which had been and would be raised against revolution. Hook focused on Marxs theory of the state. It is Marxs
theory of the state which distinguishes the true Marxist from the
falseSince the acceptance of the class theory of the state is the
sine qua non of Marxism, to be a Marxist means to be a revolutionist (pp. 270, 273). He interprets Marx as saying that the state is an
organ of a ruling class; therefore the existing state cannot be used
to remove its own ruling class and to liberate its working class and
oppressed.
Dewey, Manicas, and others have noted that Marx and Engels
wrote, on several occasions, that it might be possible for the working class to take power by peaceful, electoral, means in Britain
or the United States. Hook refers to this. He quotes Engels that,
whenever Marx made such comme nts, He certainly never forgot
to add that he hardly expected the English ruling class to submit,
24
archist. Then she makes obvious arguments about how some of the
heritage of the past might be useful and, anyway, people cannot
complete ly change all their traits overnight. So, McKenna has the
opposite reaction to Bartenberger.
Neither of them realizes that anarchism has two main tendencies (Price 2009). Historically, the main one has been revolutionary,
from Bakunin onto Kropotkin, Goldman, Makhno, the anarchosyndicalists and the anarcho-communists. But there has also been
a reformist trend, believing in building producer and consumer
cooperatives, communes, and other alternative institutions. These
would grow, peacefully and gradually, until they replace the state
and the capitalist economy, with a minimum of direct combat. This
trend began with P.J. Proudhon and includes Graeber and possibly
the majority of current US anarchists. (I am generalizing; specific
individuals may not fit precisely into either tendency.) I think this
trend is unrealistic as a strategy because the capitalist class controls the marketplace even more than it does the state. It would
find ways to stop the alternate institutions from spreading beyond
the margins. Anyway, Bartenberger finds pragmatic liberalism to
be consistent with reformist anarchism, while McKenna finds it to
be in conflict with revolutionary anarchism.
Today, virtually allor allof the well-known pragmatic philosophers are liberals or reformist socialists (of those who mention
the topic anyway). This includes Richard Bernstein (2010), Richard
Rorty (Guignon & Hiley 2003), Robert Westbrook (2005), and Cornell West (1989; West has also been influenced by Marxism and the
African-American prophetic tradition).
Among pragmatists who were also anarchists or anarchistinfluenced, again almost all were reformist. This began with
William James, who Deborah Coon (1986) describes as believing in a pacifist, communitarian anarchism. Paul Goodman described himself as an anarchist-pacifist (as did David Wieck, who
I quoted earlier about Deweys pragmatism and anarchism). While
22
of Hegels views. This included Hegels holism and nondualism, his interactionism, and his dynamism. Jurgen Habermasremarked that American pragmatism should be seen as
the radical-democratic branch of Young Hegelianism, useful in
shoring up the democratic deficiencies of its other branches, not
least of all Marxism (Westbrook 2005; p. 124). But Dewey completely rejected Hegels determinism and teleology. (Teleology is
the belief that processes have inevitable ends built into themsuch
as the Marxist belief that socialism is inevitable). He saw the
world as still open, still being made. Perhaps he went too far in
rejecting historical determination, as I will argue.
Reformism or Revolution?
Martin Bartenberger (2014) argues that Deweys concept of radical democracy is compatible with anarchism because anarchism,
like pragmatism, rejects revolution, unlike the dogmatic Marxists. Bartenberger specifically cites the anarchist David Graeber as
a model. Bartenberger quotes him as seeing conflicts as processes
of problem solving rather than as a struggle between fixed interests (quoted on p. 8). Both Dewey and Graeber, he claims, reject
the idea of solving basic conflicts by revolutionary force. Instead
they supposedly advocate democratic means to reach democratic
ends (p. 9), by which he means using nonviolent discussion and
compromises.
On the other hand, Erin McKenna (2001) believes that Deweys
concept of democracy is incompatible with anarchism, because,
she says, anarchism, unlike pragmatism, advocates violent revolution! If the price is revolution, it may be too high (p. 53). Peculiarly, she asserts, Most anarchists see revolution as [requiring]a
total and complete change in peoples beliefs, values, and habits.
Furthermore, all vestiges of past institutions must be destroyed
(p. 53). Anarchist visions tend to endorse[an] immediate and
complete revolution (p. 65). She cites no evidence that anarchists
believe in such nonsense except an excerpt from Kropotkin about
how the French (bourgeois, not anarchist) revolution uprooted medieval and feudal institutions (which seems a good thing to me).
And she quotes Fanon, an important political writer but not an an21
employed to subdue and disarm the recalci- trant minority (p. 662).
This reduces the difference between force (revolution) and intelligence to a matter of immediate practice rather than of principle.
Even in this case, Dewey does not advocate preparing the workers and oppressed to be ready to resist and defeat the recalcitrant
minority. He does not advocate warning the people ahead of time
that this might happen. The whole of his influ- ence would be to
direct the authorized majority into legal and electoral channels.
This would disarm the working people in the face of what is not at
all an exception but is the most likely probability.
Dewey went over this argument again, in 1938, responding to
Leon Trotskys essay, Their Morals and Ours (Trotsky 1966). (To
an anarchist reader, Trotsky wrote some good things in the essay
as well as some very bad things, but that is not my topic.) Trotsky claimed that the class struggle was the major law of society,
from which revolutionary conclusions may be deduced. Dewey responded, One would expect, then, that with the idea of the liberation of mankind as the end-in-view, there would be an examination of all means that are likely to attain this end without any fixed
preconceptions as to what they must be, and that every suggested
means would be weighed and judged on the express ground of the
consequences it is likely to produce (Dewey 1966; p. 57). Since revolutionary socialists do not do this, he says, they are dogmatic and
unpragmatic.
This argument ignores the studies which Marxists and anarchists
have made, over generations, of the class nature of societies. It ignores the studies made of revolutions which have succeeded and
those which have failed, from the time of Marx and Bakunin to today. It treats each situation as a brand- new problem which has to
be analyzed from scratch. While it is correct to reject an inflexible
deter-minism, it is foolish to adopt this sort of indeterminism. It
seems to deny that anything can be learned from the past. Dewey
wrote this, after all, after the experiences of the Russian revolution and of the rise to power of Italian and German fascism. From
19
Bakunin, so tied his hands in the way that Dewey suggests (2008;
p. 16).
What is the meaning of this abstract appeal to intelligence?
Apparently it means to operate within the laws and institutions of
the existing state. Dewey claims to be arguing that radicals should
not commit themselves ahead of time, that they should examine
each situation by itself and intelligently decide if and when force
is needed or if public discussion and voting will be enough for those
thor- ough-going changes he wanted. But actually he is strongly
on the side of the legal, pacifistic, electoral, road to change, at least
in the USA.
Dewey recognized that our [political] institutions, democratic
in form, tend to favor in substance a privileged plutocracy (McDermott 2008; p. 661). However, he still argued that bourgeois politicians and institutions can be effected by changes in public opinion. Legislatures and congresses do not exist in a vacuumnot
even the judges on the benchThe assumption that it is possible
forlaw- making bodies to persist unchanged while society is undergoing great change is an exercise in verbal formal logicEven
as they now exist, the forms of representative bodies are potentially capable of expressing the public will (pp. 660-661). He did
not appreciate that there is a difference between some changes in
public opinion, such as changing laws about alcohol or marijuana,
and others, such as taking away the wealth of the entire privileged
plutocracy! The legislators, congressmen, and judges may bow to
some public pressures, but not to the call for the total expropriation
of the class to which they owe allegiance. It is the class to which
they mostly belong. (Talk about verbal formal logic!) They would
sooner cancel elections, organize fascist gangs, and try to make a
military coup.
Dewey admitted to one exceptionWhen society through an
authorized majority has entered upon the path ofgreat social
change, and a minority refuses by force to permit the method of
intelligent action to go into effect. Then force may be intelligently
18
that the promise of Deweys progressive education, industrial selfmanagement, and decentralized democracy had been thwarted (he
usually also cited Jefferson). Goodmans pragmatism was integral
to his anarchist critique of US politics, culture, and economy. (For
a review of Goodmans anarchism, see Price 2010.)
In the 1970s and 80s, a professional philosopher, Peter T. Manicas, made contributions to the study of the relation between pragmatism and anarchism (Manicas 1974; 1982). He proposed to take
a fresh look at [Deweys] writings from the vantage point of anarchism (1982; p. 134). He concluded, Deweys idea of democracyis anarchist contain[ing] a view of an ideal, noncoercive,
nonauthori- tarian society; [and] a criticism of existing society and
its institutions, based on this antiauthoritarian ideal (p. 136). Influenced by the anarchist Murray Bookchin, Manicas declared that
the democratic community presupposes radical decentralization
the dissolving of the dinosaur industrialized nation-state and the
disintegration of the monster institutional complexes of presentday societies (1974; p. 251). Pointing to ecological and other problems of oversized and overcentralized industrial societies, he advocated federations of integrated, collective, directly-democratic,
communities.
More recently, David Kadlec wrote, Little has been written of
the historical relationship between political anarchism and American pragmatism (2000; p. 22). While his book explores this to some
extent, it is mainly a discussion of how pragmatism and anarchism
influenced modernism in art and culture.
A few other authors have written one or two papers on the anarchist/pragmatist relationship, such as Bartenberger (2014), DeHaan (1965), and Pereira (2009). Dabrowsky & Schmidt have written, Anarchism and pragmatism have an essentially symbiotic
relationship; pragmatist principles bolster the anarchist case and
vice versa (2014; p. 1). (There are also a few people calling themselves anar- cho-pragmatists, who are pro-capitalist, false liber15