Renaissance Thought and Its Sources
Renaissance Thought and Its Sources
Renaissance Thought and Its Sources
&
Since 1821
SN A/S
Renaissance Thought
and its Sources
Founded in 1821 by Christian Tnder Sbye, Herman H.J. Lynge & Sn is the oldest
antiquarian book shop in Scandinavia. We are specialized in rare and important works within
History of Ideas, with a main focus on Science, Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, of all
periods.
Preface
The present catalogue is devoted to the thought of the Renaissance and its sources. In this context, sources
should be taken in a twofold sense. It means both the ancient sources of learning upon which the original
thought of the Renaissance is based and the sources upon which our knowledge of Renaissance thought is
based, the classics of the historiography of Renaissance thought (see Section II).
By Renaissance thought, we mean primarily Renaissance philosophy, albeit in a broad sense, including
the Humanist movement, the Aristotelian tradition, and Renaissance Platonism. The label of Renaissance
philosophy also covers fields that we would not categorize as philosophy today, such as science, medicine,
politics, linguistics, and sociology.
We have, however, not included any books solely relating to the fields of Religion, Art, Poetry, Natural History,
and Cartography, of which we have several important Renaissance printings in stock (see www.lynge.com).
The focus of this present catalogue is on works that have been determinative for the formation and development
of the philosophical thought that is peculiar to the Renaissance.
The present catalogue is obviously not an exhaustive list of works and editions formative for Renaissance
thought, but we believe that it reflects the intellectual wealth and diversity of the Renaissance period. It also
reflects our main fields of interest: important books within Science, Philosophy, and the History of Ideas.
Of all the books in the present catalogue, it is true that they are highly important editions of works that have
been of seminal importance to the development of Renaissance thought and to our understanding of this
previously neglected period in which the formats of modern culture, modern thought, and modern man were
cast.
Maria Girsel
Herman H.J.Lynge & Sn A/S
November 2012
Section I
commentators became completely available in Latin between the late fifteenth and the end of the sixteenth
centuries and were more and more used to balance the interpretations of the medieval Arabic and Latin
commentators. The Middle Ages had known their works only in a very limited selection or through quotations in
Averroes. Ermolao Barbaros complete translation of Themistius and Girolamo Donatos version of Alexanders
De Anima were among the most important ones in a long line of others. When modern historians speak of
Alexandrism as a current within Renaissance Aristotelianism that was opposed to Averroism, they are justified
in part by the fact that the Greek commentators, that is Alexander and also Themistius, Simplicius, and many
others, were increasingly drawn upon for the exposition of Aristotle. In a more particular sense, Alexanders
specific notion that the human soul was mortal received more attention from the Aristotelian philosophers.
(Kristeller, Renaissance Thought and its sources, 1979, p. 45).
The group of innovating Alexandrists who appear at the end of the century derive their name from
Alexander of Aphrodisias, the best of the Greek commentators on Aristotle, whom they studied and cited;
but the Averroists had likewise cited Alexander; his views they found discussed by the commentator himself.
And we find strong Humanistic interests. Whereas before the Physica had been the center of attention,
now it is the De Anima and the interpretation of human nature that awaken controversy. Like the Platonists,
the Aristotelians began discussing God, freedom, and immortality in relation to the individual soul, but, unlike
them, they arrived through Aristotle at naturalistic conclusions. (Randall in: Cassirer, Kristeller and Randall,
The Renaissance Philosophy of Man, 1956, p. 260).
Of his (Alexanders) interpretations of Aristotle (either in formal commentaries or in other writings), two
are particularly famous Alexander interprets a most difficult aspect of Aristotles psychology in his On
the Soul, Book III, chapters 4 and 5 The most conspicuous result of this theory is the denial of any kind of
personal immortality The assertion or the denial of the correctness of Alexanders interpretation of Aristotle
and, even more, the correctness of the doctrine (denial of personal immortality) became one of the great
controversies of the Middle Ages and early modern times. (D.S.B. I: pp. 11718).
The Christian commentators of Aristotles On the Soul naturally expounded an interpretation of the
question of the immortality of the soul that coincided with the religious Christian doctrines of the periods.
Meanwhile, in the second century CE, Alexander of Aphrodisias wrote commentaries on De anima that
were to conflict with Christian teaching on the soul, and, in the twelfth century, Averroes proposed another
line of interpretation that was equally offensive. Beginning in the thirteenth century, scholastic philosophers
and theologians in Paris and elsewhere debated this question hotly and often After the early fourteenth
century the controversy simmered, but then it boiled over again at Padua in the late fifteenth century, when
Pomponazzi was a student. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, Renaissance Philosophy, 1992, pp. 1067).
Alexander provided a mean between the purely material and the abstract intellect, and he made a place for
reason and intellect. With the aid of Alexanderreading the exact edition that we have here, namely the
very first printed version of the groundbreaking work, Pomponazzi, The last Scholastic and the first man
of the Enlightenment, was the one to solve the main problem of the Renaissance. He agreed that Aquinas
had sufficiently refuted Averros doctrine of the unity of all intellect, but he did not agree that there was a
plurality of intellects, rather that the human soul was mortal,also the rational faculty,a doctrine that of
course greatly disturbed the Church. For this interpretation he appealed to Alexander of Aphrodisias, who
identifies the active mortal intellect with the divine mind and declares the individual reason of each man to
be mortal. (Note 1: Pomponazzi, who was ignorant of Greek (as were many of the most important scholars of
the Renaissance), doubtless used the translation of Alexander peri psyches, by Girolamo Donato of Venice
(Breschia, 1495) ). To escape from the imputation of heterodoxy, he distinguished between two orders of truth,
the philosophical and the theological (Sandy II:p. 110).
It is a curious but generally accepted conception that with the rise of the Renaissance came the fall of Aristotle.
Weather this is actually true can be disputed, but it is a fact that with the recovery of many lost works of
ancient literature, the widening of the range of classical studies and the renewed interest in Plato, Aristotle
was no longer the sole authority on a huge number of fields. That this should mean a total ignorance of the
teachings of Aristotle must be considered somewhat of a myth (though a very frequently repeated one), and in
fact with the grand humanists of the late 15th and early 16th century, the study of Aristotle fits perfectly with
the broader comprehension of scholarship. The great humanists like Ficino, Pico and Pomponazzi had not
forgotten about Aristotle, and the revival of learning did not mean the neglect of the prince of philosophers.
On the contrary, with the appreciation of the knowledge of Greek and the invention of the printing, works
were being translated and printed like never before, which meant that the greatest of the humanists, many
of whom did not themselves know Greek, could be acquainted with the Greek texts of Aristotle and the
Greek commentaries of The Commentator, Alexander, in Latin translation. And thus this first printing of
the interpretation of the greatest of all commentators of one of the most influential works in the history of
philosophy comes to live and comes to influence an entire generation of philosophers, humanists and thinkers.
The De Anima became one of the most studied texts of all times, and it hugely influenced late 15th and early
16th century philosophy, theology and thought in general. Although the ancient commentators on Aristotle
left a much larger literature than that surviving from Aristotle himself, only a few of their commentaries were
known to the medieval West. In the four decades after 1490, the interpretations of Alexander, Themistius,
Ammonius, Philoponus, Simplicius, and other Greek commentators were added to the familiar views of
Averroes, Albert and Thomas, thus stimulating new solutions to Aristotelian problems.
Equally important for the continued growth of the Peripatetic synthesis was the recovery and diffusion of the
Greek commentaries on Aristotle. These treatises, about ten times longer than the works they discuss, were
written by pagans and Christians, Platonists and Peripatetics in late antiquity, between the second and seventh
centuries in the Greek world of the Eastern Mediterranean, and then again in twelfth-century Byzantium.
The most important of the two dozen commentators were Alexander of Aphrodisias, Ammonius, Simplicius,
Themistius and John Philoponus. Of these five, only Alexander and Themistius were Aristotelians
(Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 68).
Alexandre dAphrodisias peut tre considr comme le premier auteur de limmense importance que la
thorie du troisime livre de lAme acquit dans les dernieres sicles de la philosophie grecque, et Durant tout
le moyen ge. (Renan, p. 99).
Graesse I: 69: Cette traduction, qui diffre de la prcdente, a t rimprime plusieurs fois, p. ex.: s. l. 1500.
in-fol. Venet. 1502. 1514. 1538. in 8vo. Basil. 1535. in 8vo.
10
11
No incunable-edition of the work of Archimedes appeared, and the present edition is only preceded by small
Latin selections from his works in 1503 and 1543.
Archimedes, by Plinius called the God of mathematics, is arguably the greatest mathematician, physicist
and engineer of ancient times and one of the greatest geniuses of all times. There is no one individual whose
work epitomizes the character of the Alexandrian age so well as Archimedes (287212 B.C), the greatest
mathematician in antiquity. (Morris Kline). He gave birth to the calculus of the infinite conceived and
brought to perfection successively by Kepler, Cavalieri, Fermat, Leibnitz, and Newton. (Chasles).
With the commentaries of Eutocius, Renaissance thinkers read and understood the works of the Great
Archimedes, and one dare say that these commentaries influenced the Renaissance as much as Archimedes
work itself. Had it not been for Eutocius commentaries, we might not have extant all that we have of Aristotle,
and it is no coincidence that these commentaries have followed almost all editions of Archimedes ever since
their first appearance in print, in 1544.
The accompanying commentaries by Eutocius, still extant, had an effect on the history of mathematics. They
contain not only cross-references to Greek geometry, but also exhaustive comments on Archimedes calculation
of circles. It was these that opened an early door to Archimedes work and then, centuries later, influenced
the work of Western scholars such as Niclas of Cusa, Leonardo da Vinci, the Abbot Francesco Maurolico and
Niccol Tartaglia. (Grattan-Guinness p. 181).
Eutocius commentaries are of seminal importance to the history of mathematics, his examples of long
multiplication in his commentary on the Measurement of a Circle are the best available evidence of the
way in which the Greek handled such operations, and he preserves solutions of mathematical problems by
the earlier Greek geometers that are sometimes the sole evidence for their existence and are therefore of major
importance for the historian of mathematics.
It is through Eutocius that we have a valuable collection of solutions by Greek geometers of the problem of
finding two mean proportions to two given straight lines (D.S.B. IV:489).
All the books by Archimedes on which Eutocius commented have survived, and his elucidations may have
contributed to their survival. [] His commentaries on Archimedes were translated into Latin along with the
parent works of William of Moerbeke in 1269. The commentaries have usually been printed with the editions
of Archimedes and Apollonius and have never been printed separately. (D.S.B. IV:491).
The influence of Archimedes work can hardly be over-estimated. He was the first to formulate what can
genuinely be called physical laws: Law of the Lever and Law of floating bodies.in fact, from all of physics
before Simon Stevin (15481650), the only basic achievements which have textbook status nowadays are
the two laws by Archimedes. (Salomon Bochner).
In Mechanics, he worked out the principles of the subject, and he was the first to apply geometry to physical
science. In geometry, his works consist in the main of original investigations, beginning where Euclid left off. In
fact, he performed what is equivalent to integration, in finding the area of a parabolic segment, and of a spiral,
the surface and volume of a sphere and a segment etc. He also invented the whole science of Hydrastatics.
This represents a sum of mathematical achievements unsurpassed by any man in the worlds history
(Thomas Heath)There was hardly a field of mathematics (including approximation mathematics and
numerical analysis) to which he did not contribute something exceptionally ingenious and original. His work
in higher mathematics was almost two thousand years ahead of his time and was fully appreciated only in the
nineteenth century. (Cornelius Lanczos).
12
Among the 7 works contained in the Archimedian Princeps we have also the famous Sand Reckoner
(Psammites, Arenarius) dedicated to King Gelon, in which an extremely large number is introduced in
arithmetic. How many grains of sand could the whole universe hold?a work which also contains THE FIRST
PRINTED STATEMENT of the Heliocentric world picture, the COPERNICAN THEORY OF THE UNIVERSE
with the sun in the centre and the planets and the earth revolving around it, a theory first put forward by
Aristarchus in a lost work and here (in the Sand Reckoner) referred to by Archimedes: Aristarchus brought
out a book consisting of certain hypotheses, wherein it appears, as a consequence of the assumptions made,
that the universe is many times greater than the universe just mentioned (the common conception). His
hypotheses are that the fixed stars and the sun remain unmoved, that the earth revolves about the sun in the
circumference of a circle, the sun lying in the middle of the orbit, and that the fixed stars, situated about the
same centre as the sun, is so great that the circle in which he supposes the earth to revolve bears a proportion
to the distance of the fixed stars as the centre of the sphere bears to its surface (Heaths translation).The
Sand Reckoner (De arenae numero, Psammites, Arenarius) had also not been printed before.
Smith, Rara Arithmetica p. 227Dibner, Heralds..No 137Printing and the Mind of Man No 72Sparrow,
Milestones of Science No 9Adams A1531Stillwell No 140 (both Greek and Latin translation).
13
14
Paris, Chez Ambroise Drouart, 1600. Folio. Bound in one contemporary full limp vellum binding with a bit of
spotting and soiling. Contemporary owners name torn out of top margin of first title-page. Faint damp stain
to two first leaves and a light dampstain to last ab. 40 leaves of the Plato, getting heavier on the last five indexleaves. A bit of occasional minor light brownspotting. All in all a very attractive copy, with good margins.
Roman and Italic letter, and some Greek. Title-pages printed in red and black and with large woodcut printers
devices. Woodcut head- and tail-pieces and numerous beautiful woodcut initials. (24), 499, (41, -tables) pp. +
(8), 420, (10, -table) pp.
DKK 40,000.00 / EURO 5,400.00
Extremely scarce first editions of the important first complete French translations of the Politics of Aristotle
and the Republic of Plato. We have not been able to locate any earlier printings of the two works in any
bibliographies, nor have we been able to find any in the library databases, but it seems that Bibliothque
nationale du France owns a copy of at least the Aristotle with a title-page stating 1599, also Paris by Drouart.
We thus assume that this is the same printing, but with a variant title-page.
Both of these monumental works are translated by Louis Le Roy (or Leroy), the great classical scholar, and have
his learned an important commentaries, including additions and amendments by Louis Morel, who published
the work with Drouart. For many many years this first complete translation in to French was considered by far
the best and it exercised a tremendous influence on 17th century French thought.
Louis Le Roy (ab.15101577) was a famous French humanist
scholar and professor of Greek at the Collge Royal in 1572.
He used his own magnificent translations of Plato and
Aristotle in his voluminous political and historical writings;
his masterwork De la vicissitude ou varit des choses en
lunivers, 1576, is considered a pioneering work on cyclical
change in cultural history. He had previously published
parts of his translation of both Aristotles Politics and Platos
Republic, before his death, but only smaller sections. In
the dedication in Aristotle, dated 1576, Le Roy states his
intention of completing his translation of Platos Republic
and, provided that his health holds, to add a commentary that
would help the understanding of the text. When he died, he
left a number of finished works behind that had never been
printed, among them his monumental full translations of
Aristotles Politics and Platos Republic, which the scholarly
printer Frederic Morel completed. It took more that 20 years,
however, to bring the printing of them to fruition. The
Republic is augmented with a translation of Platos Phaedon.
Aristotle: BM STC Fr. C16, p.28; Brunet: I, 469; Cranz-Schmitt.
Plato: BM STC Fr. C16, p. 354; Brunet: IV, 702; Adams: P1467.
15
16
the decades that produces the first humanist Latin translations of Greek texts in print, and with his opposition
to the classical Latin medieval translations and outspoken Ciceronian style, he is one of the most radically
humanist translators of the Aristotelian texts.
Prions style is eminently exemplified in the translation of the title which he has chosen for the present work,
the elegant and stylish De ortu et interitu instead of the more clumsy but perfectly correct De generatione
et corruptione.
Nicolas de Grouchy (15101572), who later got into a feud with Prion, served as the corrector and reviser of
the present translation of Aristotles important treatise on substantial change, in which he introduces his four
causes and four elements and thus his atomic theory. De Grouchy was the controversial private tutor to the
young Montaigne at the Collge du Guyenne, and his corrections are of great importance, especially because
he did not fully approve of Prions strictly Cicerionian approach to the translations of Aristotle.
17
18
standard presentation of this tree is that of Pace in the present edition, on p. 9. It is that rendering of it, with
occasional slight alterations, which has remained standard ever since 1584.
That which we ever since Antiquity have called the Organon comprises the logical works of Aristotle:
1. Categories, 2. On Interpretation, 3. Prior Analytics, 4. Posterior Analytics, 5. Topics, 6. On Sophistical
Refutationswhich ever since late Antiquity/early Middle Ages have been accompanied by Porphyrios
(233/34-ca. 310) Isagoge, his introduction to Aristotles Categories. During the Renaissance, all editions
of Aristotles Organon also comprised Porphyrios Isagoge, which was seen as necessary for the
understanding of Aristotles logic.
Aristotles logic has played a seminal role in the history of Western thought. No other collection of writings has
had an impact on the history of philosophy that comes close to the Organon, an impact that remains pivotal
to this day. Aristotles logic, especially his theory of the syllogism, has had an unparalleled influence on the
history of Western thought. (SEP).
From Antiquity, the earlier middle ages had inherited Boethius translation of the two first treatises of Aristotles
Organon, along with Porphyrios Isagoge. These works formed the basis for logical study and teaching
until the end of the 11th century. Only during the 12th and 13th centuries, were Aristotles writingsalong
with those of the Arabic and some of the Greek commentatorstranslated into Latin. When the medieval
universities reached their full development during the thirteenth century, Aristotles works were adapted
as the standard textbooks for all philosophical disciplinesthus modern terms for many philosophical and
scientific disciplines correspond to the titles of Aristotles works (e.g. Ethics, Physics, Metaphysics). Through
Aristotles works, the West thus acquired, not only the specific problems and ideas that were being dealt with
at the universities, but also the terminology used to describe and discuss them and the systematic framework
within which all relevant problems should and could be treated. But come the Renaissance, we see a clear
change in the use of Aristotles works. We here witness something other than a mere continuation of the
late medieval Aristotelianism. The Humanists began supplying new translations of Aristotles works and
translated all the Greek commentators of Aristotle, many of them for the first time. And thus, a tendency to
emphasize the original Greek Aristotle developed, a tendency that became pivotal for the development of
modern thoughtthe development of modern science and modern philosophy is inextricably linked with
the Renaissance Humanist editions of Aristotles works in Greek (with Latin parallel-text). The Organon,
Aristotles seminal logical writings, occupies a central position within the Aristotelian body of writing and
thus within the development of Western thought. Certain Humanist versions of the Greek text and the
Latin translations, as well as the interpretations of them, thus came to play a seminal role in the trajectory
of Renaissance and modern though, Paces Organon-edition presumably being THE most important and
influential edition ever to have appeared.
The medieval traditions of logical writing survived well into the sixteenth century particularly at Paris and
at the Spanish universities, though with considerable internal changes. Treatises on sophisms and on proofs of
terms ceased to be written; whereas there was a sudden flurry of activity concerned with the various divisions
of terms and with the opposition of propositions, i.e. the logical relations between different kinds of categorical
proposition. These internal changes were not, however, sufficient to keep the tradition alive, and after about
1530 not only did new writing on the specifically medieval contributions to logic cease, but the publication of
medieval logicians virtually ceased. The main exceptions were the logical commentaries by (or attributed to)
such authors as Thomas Aquinas and John Duns Scotus, which found a place in their Opera Omnia, and
which benefited from a revived interest in the great medieval metaphysicians.
The main changes in the teaching and writing of logic during the sixteenth century were due to the impact of
humanism. First, commentaries on Aristotle came to display a totally new style of writing. One reason for this
19
was the influence of new translations of Aristotle, and new attitudes to the Greek text. Another reason was the
publication of the Greek commentators on Aristotles logic, Alexander, Themistius, Ammonius, Philoponus
and Simplicius. A third reason was the new emphasis on Averroes, which expressed itself in the great AristotleAverroes edition of 15501552. The effects of these new factors can be seen in the commentaries on individual
works of the Organon by such Italians as Agostino Nifo (14731546) and Jacopo Zabarella (15331589),
the latter of whom offered a particularly influential account of scientific method. They can also be seen in the
Organon edition of Giulio Pace (15501635), which was first published in 1584 and contained the Greek
text side-by-side with a new translation which was designed not only to read well but also to capture the
philosophical significance of Aristotles words. (Raul Corazzon, History of Renaissance and Modern Logic
from 1400 to Stuart Mill).
No editor better understood the nature of this Treatise of Aristotle than Julius Pacius, who was the preceptor
of Casaubon, and profoundedly skilled in all the arcane of the Peripatetic philosophy, in both the Greek and
Latin tongues. (Dibdin I: 318)
Giulio Pace of Beriga (or Julius Pace/Pacius) (15501635) was a famous Italian Aristotelian scholar and jurist.
He was born in Vicenza and studied law and philosophy in Padua. He was inspired by the Reformation
and put on trial by the Inquisition. Therefore he had to flee Italy and escaped, first to Geneva, thereafter to
Germany. While in Heidelberg, he converted to Protestantism. He was highly respected as an academic and
was widely known for his deep knowledge and understanding of Aristotle, whom he became famous for
translating. He was elected public professor in Geneva, where he taught for ten years (15751585). The next
ten years he spent teaching law at the University of Heidelberg (where he got into different conflicts, especially
with the philosophical faculty for giving private tuition in the controversial Ramist logic). After Heidelberg,
he taught at different universities throughout Europe, including Hungary, where he was also well known,
especially for his 1584-edition of Aristotles Organon, which played a definitive role in Aristotle-scholarship
and philosophy in general throughout all of Europe.
Pace may have met Thomas Balasz during his stay in Hungary.
The presentation-inscription (in Latin) is from the Hungarian citizen, who is presumably a Bishop: Thomas
Balassz transylvanus Clauoiopolita-/nus, natione Hungarus, suo Dno benevuolo-/ uti fratri dilectissimo
suffisicationum/ grati animi scribebat, Erasmo Fabricio/ Rectori Schola Cassouiensis, professor mor
suauitatem [].
Fabrizio is the Humanist Latinizasion of Schmied/Schmidt, thus, Erasmo Frabrizio is the Latin Humanist
version of Erasmus Schmidt.
THE GERMAN RENAISSANCE HUMANIST PHILOLOGIST, MATHEMATICIAN, AND PHILOSOPHER
ERASMUS SCHMIDT (15701637) was famous as a learned scholar with an immense understanding of
Greek philosophical and scientific literature. He was one of the last of the German Hellinists, who learned
the Greek language and literature after the Melanchtonian model and spirit. He wrote a number of noted
treatises and works, most famously a carefully commented edition of Pindars poems and fragments with a
Latin translation. He also made an edition of the poems of Hesiod that turned out to be very influential and
was used as the standard version for many years. He wrote a large number of influential works of classical
philology, and he played an important role, not only in the interpretation of classical and post-classical texts,
but also in the exposition and interpretation of grammar and language.
Erasmus Schmidt was born in Delitzsch and died in Wittenberg, where he was rector of the Wittenberg
Academy at two times in his life. After having been taught in the public school, at the age of 14 or 15, he was
sent to the Landesgymnasium in Schulpforrta, where he was taught by, among others, Sethus Calvisius. He
20
was so skilled that he received an electorial stipend and in 1590 enrolled at the University of Wittenberg. Here
he studied philosophy and graduated in 1593, after which time he gave private tuition in Greek language
and mathematics, earning a great reputation, which caused him to be put forth as the successor for the
professorship of Petrus Otto. Jstel himself, however, was given the professorship, and due to this rejection, he
left Germany and went to Hungary, where he became an educator (paedagoge). It is here that he was given the
present, wonderfully bound copy of Paces Organon-edition, which he seems to have annotated extensively
and devoted a lot of attention. Erasmus Schmidt stayed in Hungary until 1597, which fits perfectly with the
last owners inscription to the pasted-down back end-paper, which is dated 1st of April 1597. Schmidt got a
position as assistant professor at the philosophical faculty in Wittenberg from the 1st of May 1597, and has
presumably left Hungary about a month earlier, at which time Alberto Grawerg has presumably been given
the present copy.
Dibdin I:318; Adams A:1866.
21
22
23
DEFINING SOVEREIGNTY
BODIN, JEAN
Les six livres de la rpublique.
Paris, Chez Iacques du Puys, 1577. Folio. Bound in a nice 18th century half calf with marbled
paper over boards. Single gilt lines and gilt title to spine. Top corner of front board bumped and
a small tear to upper front hinge and lower back hinge, otherwise very nice. Repair to one leaf
(a ii), otherwise Internally very nice and clean. Old owners inscription to title-page. Large titlewoodcut. Woodcut initials and vignettes. (8), (765paginated 1-519 + 552-797pp. 519 and 552
being recto and verso of the same leaf, i.e. nothing missing), (1), (54,Table des matieres) pp.
DKK 48,000.00 / EURO 6,500.00
The rare second edition of Bodins seminal main work, in which sovereignty is defined and treated
extensively for the first time. Bodins statement of sovereignty is the first systematic one in modern
European philosophy, and thus deserves a landmark status. (SEP). The work is also the first to coin the term
Political Science; it occupies a central place in European political thought and immensely influenced all
thinkers on the subject throughout centuries. for the next three centuries the political thought of the West
will be preoccupied with these ideas, with a new theory of the State and with the concept of Sovereignty.
(Catlin, A History of the Political Philosophers, 1950, p. 207).
The extremely scarce first edition, first issue of the Six Books of the Republic appeared in 1576 and bears
this date on the title-page, a second issue of the first edition also appeared, like this second edition bearing
the year 1577 on the title-page. All three appeared in Paris and were published by Du Puys. The work
immediately became very popular, and numerous editions appeared already in the 16th century. Later in
1577 an unauthorized edition of the work appeared, printed in Geneva; in 1583 seven editions seem to have
appeared. The early folio-editions are all scarce.
The French lawyer and political philosopher, Jean Bodin (15301596) wrote his main work, Les six livres de
la rpublique during the French Wars of Religion, when French Catholics and Protestants were fighting each
other. He sees that the only real way to hold a community together and solve conflicts like the ones going on
at the time is by establishing a supreme authority. There must be a ruling power which is unrestricted, but at
the same time, it cannot be a power that is free to disregard all laws. Inspired by Aristotles Politics, Bodin
now solves the problem of order though the definition of a concept that unites the rulers and the ruled in one
body politic, one unitary political society, that is placed above any other human law and that defines human
law; he can now define the concept of sovereignty without having to allow a ruler to neglect otherwise present
laws and regulations. The sovereign body is necessarily unrestricted; it is bound by natural and divine law,
but no human law can touch it or contest it; within its territory, it is the single authority. Bodins Sovereign also
has the power to legislate, and thus, he not only overrules the common law that had been prevailing in most
sovereign states, he has also created a theoretical foundation for monarchy.
With this seminal work, the single most important political work of the French Renaissance, the work that
came to influence all Western political thought for centuries, Bodin had earned himself the reputation of being
the founder of the science of the state.
The Six Books of the Republic went through many editions in the authors lifetime and after, and had an
immense influence all over Europe. It is, in effect, the first modern attempt to create a complete system of
24
political science. Its basis was the Politics of Aristotle, and it was through Bodin that Aristotles work came
to exercise influence on modern political thinking which has made him the father of modern democracy. Bodin
was not content merely to reproduce his master, however; he added considerably from his own experience.
Although like most sixteenth-century writers he approved of absolute government, he demanded its control
by constitutional laws, in which respect he foreshadowed the development during the seventeenth century
of the social contract. Thus Bodin was the first to set out clearly the argument round which most political
discussion centred in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, that law is merely an expression of the
sovereign will, but that where this reposes in an absolute monarch, it must be mitigated by a customary or
natural law. When the lawgivers law becomes unjust, it ceases to be valid and must be resisted. (Printing
and the Mind of Man p. 58).
Adams B2234; Brunet I:1025; Graesse I:460; PMM 94(a) (first issue, 1576).
25
26
27
of selling books that could be controlled by the regime, and he was to submit a bound copy of every work that
came off his press for censorship. []. (Zanr, p. 23).
Torrentino played a fundamental role in the programme of the cultural development and promotion of the
Tuscan language that was instituted by the Academy with the full support of Cosimo I. The success of this
policy can be seen in the considerable number of volumes written in the volgare that were published by
the ducal printer. Not surprisingly, given the exclusive nature of his employment, Torrentino was more or
less restricted to producing works that were penned by members of the Fiorentina; in the course of fifteen
years, he published Sixty-one titles associated with them. Of these, thirty-nine were no more than simple
transcriptions of academic lectures. [] Bartolis vernacular translations of Albertis De Re Aedificatoria
(1550) and Boethius De Consolatione Philosophiae (1552) also came off Torrentinos presses.
The texts that have been cited so far reflect the specific mission of the Academy to promote lingua volgare,
by producing works written in contemporary Tuscan and by translating Latin and Greek classics into the
vernacular. The Fiorentinas economic dimension was recalled in the many historical biographies published
by Torrentino. (Zanr, pp. 2325).
As a philosopher Boethius (480ca. 525) stands tall in the middle between Antiquity and the Middle Ages.
Time-wise he clearly belongs to late Antiquity, but he is a Christian and he writes in Latin. Still being a
Christian, he also comes to represent the actual centre of a tradition that goes directly back to Plotinus and
thereby indirectly back to Plato and Aristotle.
Boethius was imprisoned and later executed, accused of treason against the gothic regime as well as of sorcery,
though he himself claims that it was caused by his political activity, where he as a court official defended the
weak; caused by his uprightness, his enemies were too many. The most plausible explanation is that Theoderic
doubted the loyalty of the Roman aristocracy and thereby especially the frank Boethius.
While in prison, Boethius wrote this his main work, which is without a doubt the most widely read, commented
and influential of his works. The work is atypical for the time and is written as a philosophical conversation
between Boethius himself and the goddess of Philosophy. Though always a Christian, in this work he is first
and foremost a philosopher, which is why there are many allusions to pagan neo-platonism, however during
the Middle Ages all passages of this work were very popularly interpreted in accordance with Christianity. Few
people have been of so seminal character to Medieval and Reniassance philosophy and religion as Boethius;
perhaps only Aristotle himself and Augustine were more influential and important. Few books were so widely
read during the Middle Ages as the Consolation of Philosophy, and virtually no book has been as major a
source of ancient philosophy in the early Middle Ages and consequently the Renaissance as this one. As well
of being of great textbook value this work has inspired and influenced numerous religious, philosophical
and literary writers. For some writers, such as the Middle English poet, Chauser, the Consolation seems
to have provided a model for writing about serious issues in a way which presupposes no commitment to
Christianity, a philosophical precedent for the use of pagan setting in a literary fiction. (John Marenbon,
Medieval Philosophy, 1998, p. 24).
With the death of Boethius came also the end of ancient tradition of philosophy in the Latin West, though
through his writings, the influence of this philosophical tradition was preserved during the Middle Ages and
through to the Renaissance and early modern times.
Judith Bryce, Cosimo Bartoli (15031572): The Career of a Florentine Polymath), 1983.
Domenico Zanr, Cultural Non-Conformity in Early Modern Florence , 2004.
Adams: B-2299.
28
29
Minimo, La Croce only had the book De Immenso et Innumerabilibus in front of him, or at least he only
provides excerpts from this [also not in translation], as Heumann does only from the Physical Theorems
[also small fragments, not in translation]; (pp. (VII)-VIIIown translation from the German).
Brunos most representative work, Spaccio de la bestia trionfante (The Expulsion of the Triumphant Beast),
published in an atmosphere of secrecy in 1584 and never referred to as anything but blasphemous for more
than a century, was singled out by the church tribunal at the summation of his final trial. That is hardly
surprising because the book is a daring indictment of the corruption of the social and religious institutions
of his day. The triumphant beast signifies the reign of multifarious vices. Cast in the form of allegorical
dialogues, Brunos work presents the deliberations of the Greek gods who have assembled to banish from the
heavens the constellations that remind them of their evil deeds. The crisis facing Jove, the aging father of the
gods, is symbolic of the crisis in a Renaissance world profoundly disturbed by new religious, philosophical,
and scientific ideas. (From Arthur D. Imertis 1964 translation of the work into English).
Bruno, who had already used geometric diagrams and philosophical terms to present n infinite universe, now
wrote a dialogue in which he transformed the cosmos by transforming its imagery. He called it The Triumphant
Beast, a phrase that brought to mind the book of Revelation [] Unlike most of his contemporaries, who
30
gave the universe about six thousand years of existence since creation, the Nolan philosopher had already
proclaimed that it was infinitely old; in The Expulsion of the Triumphant Beast, he insists that the universe
holds cultures and memories that have come and gone and will come and go again. (Rowland, pp. 164-65).
Giordano Bruno was born in Nola in Southern Italy in 1548, and entered the Dominical order in Naples at
the age of 18. While pursuing theological studies, he also thoroughly studied the ancient philosophers and
began doubting some of the teachings of the Catholic Church. When he was in Rome in 1576, these doubts
became known to the authorities of his order, and an indictment for heresy was prepared against him. Before
he could be arrested, he escaped and began a long journey which took him to many European countries,
among these England, where his most important works are published, until in 1592 he was denounced to the
Inquisition and arrested. In 1593 he was taken to Rome, imprisoned, and subjected to a 6 year long trial. He
firmly refused to recant his philosophical opinions, and in 1600 he was condemned for heresy, sentenced to
death, and burned alive.
Bruno burned for philosophy; he was killed for moral, physical, and metaphysical views that terrified and
angered authorities. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 315).
Salvestrini: 112
Copenhaver & Schmitt: Renaissance Philosophy, 1992.
Ingrid D. Rowland: Girodano Bruno. Philosopher/Heretic, 2008.
See also:
Cassirer: Das Erkenntnisproblem, 1922 Bd. 1; An Essay on Man, 1944. Garin: Italian Humanism,
1965. Paterson: The Infinite Worlds of Giordano Bruno, 1970. Kristeller: Eight Philosophers of the Italian
Renaissance, 1964. Copenhaver & Schmitt: Renaissance Philosophy, 1992. W. Boulting, Giordano Bruno.
31
32
In the sense of unifying Europe under one currency, Budelius seperates himself from not only Medieval
monetary thinkers, but from his contemporary mercantilists as well: The medieval literature on money is
characterized by nascent nationalism, with the imagery of the body applied to the kingdom, and of money
as the blood moving through its parts. Nicole Oresmes De Moneta pointed out that if money is accumulated
in the kings treasury and withdrawn from circulation, it constitutes an abscess in the body. (Cambridge
Companion to Economic Thought).
His comments represent the synthesis of two traditions, one uncovering the theoretical possibility of fiat money,
the other uncovering its practical usefulness, as means of raising revenues in emergencies, from examples
taken from history. Budelius cites examples of copper petty coinage in Germany and the Low countries, and
gives examples of siege money. From Maastricht in 1579 (copper), Vienna in 1529 (lead), tin in Neuss, and even
paper siege money in Leyden in 1574. He then writes: I hold this to be indubitable, as I recall a little earlier,
that a Prince in the midst of costly wars, and therefore in great necessity, can order that money be made out of
leather, bark, salt, or any material he wants, if he is careful to repair the loss inflicted thereby on the community
with good and better money. The insights of Budel about token money were to be tested by some experiments
in the coming years and were carried further by important theorists in the Renaissance and later.
Budelius (153091), was a practitioner, a jurist by training, who worked as diplomat for the archbishop of
Cologne, and later as mint-master in Westphalia for the duke of Bavaria. This is reflected in his practical and
empirical approach to the economic challenges the Renaissance society was subjected to, unlike the more often
seen theoretical and moral approach.
Goldsmith 254; Mattioli 451; Einaudi 737; Adams 3153.
33
34
It is through his great enclyclopaedic endeavors that many of da Vincis unpublished ideas are passed on
to the likes of Stevin, Galilei and Descartes, but Cardanus not only reported and collected, he himself made
important contributions in the fields of mathematics and algebra, mechanics (where he developed and went
beyond Leonardo da Vincis ideas on the balance and virtual velocities), in chemistry, astronomy, mineralogy,
hydrodynamics, etc.
In fact, it seems that there is hardly a scientific field to which Cardanus encyclopedic work did not make
the most important contributions. As an example, Stillwell lists the De subtilitate under no less than three
different chapters (Medicine, Natural Science, Physics): [w]ritten in a popular style and treating a wide
range of subjects. Includes a description of a touch-system not unlike Braille, as an aid to the blind, and
a suggestion regarding a sign-language for the deaf. According to Garrison, Cardanos biological concepts
tended toward evolution. (III: 329). A philosophical discussion of method, tending toward evolution in
its biologic concepts. Wightman speaks of Cardanos heat as having a modern character. The author
was a scientist of advanced ideas and varied interests, his writing relating to medicine, physics, natural
science, and in particular to mathematics. (IV:609). Cardano refers to the electro-magnetic powers of the
lodestone, magnetic declination, and electrification by friction. He describes pumps, siphons, the water-screw
of Archimedes, and machinery for raising sunken vessels. His concepts regarding heat and various other
matters veered towards the modern. (V:745).
Wellcome I:1302.Ferguson No. 2483. Dibner No. 139 (Latin edition).Graesse II:45.
35
could not enjoy the privileges of Paris university students. Rasmus appealed first to the assembly of regents
of Philosophy and later to the Parliament of Paris. Before the Parliament Ramus outlined a programme of
study in which grammar, rhetoric, and dialectic led first to natural and moral philosophy and later theology
or law. He argued that his method of teaching avoided wasting time on scholastic technicalities and produced
graduates who were better prepared for practical life. The effectiveness of this speech and the support of his
patron helped him to avoid censure and obtain a royal lectureship. (Mack, A History of Renaissance Rhetoric
13801620, Pp. 153-4).
by 1565 he was leading opposition to the naming of Jacques Charpentier (no relation), a long-time adversary,
to the royal chair of mathematics. Charpentier, who had by then succeeded Ramus as the Cardinal de Lorraines
protg and who enjoyed Jesuit support, kept his chair; and Ramus, ever more threatened, in 1567 again fled
Paris, taking refuge with the Prince de Cond. (DSB).
37
38
Scarce first edition thus, being the first (and until 1989 only) edition with the important and influential
commentaries by Bernardino Daniello, one of the most important Dante-commentators of the Renaissance.
The work is rare and much sought after both due to the excellent commentaries of Daniello and the beautifully
executed printing of the work.
Bernardino Daniello da Lucca (ca. 15001565) was a famous Renaissance-commentator, who contributed
decisively to the reception of several important classic and Medieval texts. Not only do his Dante-commentaries
constitute the best and most important of his own works, they are also considered among the most important
Dante-commentaries of the Renaissance overall. It is not until recently that the full scope of Daniellos
importance to the Dante-commentary-tradition has been understood, but with the new 1989-edition of the
present work, the extent of his influence on the Dante-reception has properly come to light. While there are a
number of late 19th- and early 20th-century editions of Dantes Trecento and Quattrocento commentaries, the
Renaissance commentaries have generally only been available in a few rare book collections. Until now, of the
four major Renaissance commentators, only Castelvetros 1579 work was available in a more recent edition.
(Deborah Parker, Bernardino Daniello and the Commentary Tradition, in: Dante Studies, No. 106, 1988).
Even if Daniellos Dante-commentaries primarily relate those of his teacher, the highly esteemed Renaissance
scholar Trifon Gabriele, there is no doubt as to the importance of these commentaries, be they plagiarized
or not. Gabrieles commentaries and his Dante-teachings have never been published (and are only extant in
manuscript-version), and his foundational thoughts on Dante are thus only available through the present
edition of Dante, with Daniellos frequently repeated, quoted, and highly esteemed commentaries.
On recherche cette dition cause du commentaire, qui est fort estim. Il y manque pourtant les vers 105 118
du sixime chant du Purgatoire, omis par la faute de limprimeur. (Brunet II:504). Le commentaire est aussi
attribu Gabriello Trifone. (Graesse II:930).
Adams D:104, Brunet II:504, Graesse II:930.
39
40
The scarce first edition thus, being the most important edition of the text before the appearance of the Greek
editio princeps (1533). The present edition is the first Euclid-edition printed in France, the first printed outside
of Italy and the first to contain both Campanuss and Zambertis translations. It was edited by the famous
founder of the French humanistic School, Jacques Lefvre (Jakob Faber Stagulensis), who, in this edition,
solved many of the editorial problems of the previously printed editions.
This beautifully printed edition, with the diagrams presented in the margins of the text, became the standard
for many following editions.
The work also comprises the proofs of Theon of Alexandria. During the Middle Ages it was thought that the
proofs were made by Theon alone and that Euclid himself only formulated the propositions. The most notable
of Theons editions is that of Euclids Elements, which was so influential that it consigned the original text
to near oblivion. (D.S.B. XIII:322).
The most famous source of Greek geometry is the monumental work of Euclid of Alexandria, called the
Elements (around 300 B.C). No other book of science had a comparable influence on the intellectual
development of mankind. It was a treatise of geometry in thirteen books which included all the fundamental
results of scientific geometry up to his time. Euclid did not claim for himself any particular discovery, he
was merely a compiler. Yet, in view of the systematic arrangement of the subject matter and the exact logical
procedure followed, we cannot doubt that he himself provided a large body of specific formulations and
specific auxiliary theorems in his deductions. It is no longer possible to pass judgment on the authorship of
much of this material; his book was meant as a textbook of geometry which paid attention to the material,
while questions of priority did not enter the discussion. (Cornelius Lanczos in Space through the Ages).
Adams E 982Riccardi 1516 (4)Thomas-Stanford No. 6.Max Steck III.14.
41
42
Yet the value of the matter it contains regarding the foundations of mathematics and geometry in particular
is even greater, though less widely recognized. (Morrow, p. XXXII).
Proclus here explains the meaning of Element in geometry, he states the theoretical and pedagogical purposes
of an elementary treatise, and offers a striking evaluation of the excellence of Euclids own work. Futhermore,
he famously defends pure mathematics, and geometry in particular, against its critics, and includes an
important interpretation of the attitude of Plato, who was often used by these critics, against mathematics.
Proclus furthermore raises questions that are absolutely fundamental to the understanding of both Plato and
the science of Euclid, namely what the nature of the objects of mathematic enquiry is, and what the validity
of the procedures used to handling them are. Posing these absolutely fundamental problems for the first time
makes Proclus the first real philosopher of mathematics. Proclus treatise is the only systematic treatise that
has come down to us from antiquity dealing with these questions. (Marrow, p. XXXIII).
Proclus commentary, which takes up the second part of the book, pp. 1115, is also known as the Herwagiana,
named after the printer. Apart from the above-mentioned elements of the commentary, it also constitutes the
first criticism of Euclid to question the Parallel-axiom,hereby paving the road to NON-EUCLIDEAN
GEOMETRY. Proclus was the first commentator to be very explicit about his objection to the Parallel axiom,
as he refused to count it among the postulates. To justify his opinion he remarks that the converse (the sum
of two angles is less than that of two right angles), is one of the theorems proved by Euclid (Book I. Prop.
17), and he thinks it impossible that a theorem, the converse of which can be proved, is not itself capable of
proof. He says: This (postulate) ought even to be struck out of the postulates altogether; for it is a theorem
involving many difficulties, which Ptolemy, in a certain book, set himself to solve, and it requires for the
demonstration of it a number of definitions as well as theorems, and the converse of it is actually proved by
43
44
45
classics, and only occasionally , as in the case of Fracastoros poem, reprinting the work of a contemporary. In
1532 he issued the first edition of Machiavellis Il Principe, and in 1549 he became official printer to the Papal
See (Baumgartner & Fulton, p. 39).
Girolamo Fracastoro (14841553), a Veronese of thick-set, hirsute appearance and jovial mien, who practiced
in the Lago di Garda region, was at once a physician, poet, physicist, geologist, astronomer, and pathologist,
and shares with Leonardo da Vinci the honour of being the first geologist to see fossil remains in the true light
(1530). He was also the first scientist to refer to the magnetic poles of the earth (1543). His medical fame rests
upon that most celebrated of medical poems, Syphilis sive Moribus Gallicus (Venice, 1530), which sums up
the contemporary dietetic and therapeutic knowledge of the time, recognizes a venereal cause, and gave the
disease its present name (Garrison, History of Medicine, p. 233).
The magnificent medical poem is about the main character, a young shepherd called Syphilis, who induces
the people to forsake the Sun God, who in return bestows upon man a new, horrible plague, which Fracastoro
names after the shepherd. It epitomized contemporary knowledge of syphilis, gave to it its present name, and
recognized a venereal cause. Fracastorius refers to mercury as a remedy. (Garrison and Morton).
The work must be described as seminal, and its great influence and importance has continued throughout
centuries. As stated in the bibliography by Baumgartner and Fulton, which is devoted exclusively to the poem,
[t]he full extent of the influence exerted by a work which has received such wide recognition cannot be
adequately estimated without searching bibliographical analysis, and thus they have traced 100 editions of
46
Fracastoros Syphilis-poem, including translations into six languages. 18 of these appeared in the 16th century,
but it is curious to see, how the work continues to resurface up until the 20th century. Almost 200 years after
the work originally appeared, Italy witnessed a great revival of Fracastoro and his poem, and the first Italian
translation appeared in 1731, with a preface by the great Enlightenment philosopher Giambattista Vico, and
by 1739 five Italian editions had appeared. Another revival of the work took place as late as the 20th century,
with four new English translations appearing between 1928 and 1935.
Le pome de Fracastor sur la Syphilis restera toujours un chef-doeuvre, parce que le pinceau est large,
limagination hardie, la versification harmonieuse, et que le pote agrandit son sujet ingrat en remontant aux
cases celestas, en montant la main des Dieux sappersantissant pour punir la terre; la fiction, surtout, quil
a imagine pour retrace la dcouverte du mercure, est un tableau digne des plus grands matres. Achille
Chreau, Le Parnasse medical francais, 1874, p. xv).
Baumgartner & Fulton, A Bibliography of the Poem of Syphilis sive Moribus Gallicus by Girolamo Fracastoro
of Verona: no. 2 (our copy follows exactly the collation given hereand also has the final blank leaf mentioned
but not found in any of the examined copies).
Garrison and Morton: 2364.
There is every reason to believe that the first edition of 1530 was personally supervised by Fracastoro as
it was passing through the press. The printer, however, omitted two verses in the first book, which have
been inserted in manuscript, apparently by Fracastoro himself, in the copy on vellum now preserved in the
Bibliothque Nationale. As these two lines are included in the Rome edition of the following year, it is likely
that Fracastoro also supervised this, the second edition, and that this should be regarded as the authoritative
text, since there is no evidence of textual changes in seven subsequent editions during his life.
47
48
49
50
Very rare Froben-edition of the first work by the Renaissance-historian Paolo Giovio. All early editions of this
work are very rare.
Giovio was a gifted philosopher, medic and historian. He was born in 1483 in Come (Lombard) and was as
controversial a person as he was an author. He died in 1552 in Florence, and this particular edition is thus
printed in his lifetime. Three other editions appeared in his lifetime, all printed in Rome, in 1524, 1527, 1528,
but the 1531-edition is the only one by as prominent a printer as Froben.
Giovio was very strategic and succeeded in connecting himself with the Medici-family, especially Giulio
Medici, who was later elected Pope (Clement VIII); when he became Pope, Giovio was assigned chambers in
the Vatican and in 1528 he was announced Bishop of Nocera. Giovio wrote historical and biographical works
and essays; these works are said not to be taken as authorities, but in their entirety and with proper reservation
they do have real value, especially because he gives a rich and lively picture of Italy in his own time. He gives
indispensable accounts of the manners and lives of the people of Renaissance Italy. As a writer and clergy he
played quite a big role in Renaissance Italy.
This his first work is a rarity and plays a special part in his body of writing, as it is neither historical nor
biographical. It deals with the types of fish that Romans eat and tells how to prepare them, it is thus of great
importance to anyone interested in the lives and customs of the time, and it is sometimes counted among the
earliest of cook books. It also provides names of the fish and details of where they can be found, and where the
best of each species is most easily found, making it of real value to the ichthyologist; this work is also said to
contain the first reference in history to American fish.
The work was translated into Italian in 1560, eight years after the death of Giovio.
Not in Simon. BMC (NH) only mentions the 1561 edition and the 1560 translation. Wood p. 359: a very early
treatise on Roman ichthyology (the rare 1524 first edition).
51
52
of him, or at least he only provides excerpts from this [also not in translation], as Heumann does only from
the Physical Theorems [also small fragments, not in translation]; also Bayle had, of Brunos metaphysical
works, himself also merely read this work, of which I here provide an excerpt. (Vorrede, pp. (VII)-VIIIown
translation from the German).
Jacobi continues by stating that although everyone complains about the obscurity of Brunos teachings and
thoughts, some of the greatest thinkers, such as Gassendi, Descartes, and our own Leibnitz (p. IX) have taken
important parts of their theorems and teachings from him. I will not discuss this further, and will merely state
as to the great obscurity (grossen Dunkelheit) of which people accuse Bruno, that I have found this in neither
his book de la Causa nor in De lInfinito Universo et Mondi, of which I will speak implicitly on another
occasion. As to the first book, my readers will be able to judge for themselves from the sample (Probe) that I
here present. My excerpt can have become a bit more comprehensible due to the fact that I have only presented
the System of Bruno himself, the Philosophia Nolana which he himself calls it, in its continuity My main
purpose with this excerpt is, by uniting Bruno with Spinoza, at the same time to show and explain the Summa
of Philosophy (Summa der Philosophie) of En kai Pan [in Greek charactersmeaning One and All].
It is very difficult to outline Pantheism in its broader sense more purely and more beautifully than Bruno
has done. (Vorrede pp. IX-XIown translation from the German).
So not only does Jacobi here provide this groundbreaking piece of Brunos philosophy in the first translation
ever, and not only does he provide one of the most important interpretations of Spinozas philosophy and
establishes the importance of Bruno to much of modern thought, he also presents Bruno as the primary
exponent of pantheism, thereby using Bruno to change the trajectory of modern thought and influencing all
philosophy of the decades to come. After the second edition of Jacobis Ueber die Lehre des Spinoza, no selfrespecting thinker could neglect the teachings of Bruno; he could no longer be written off as having obscure
and insignificant teachings, and one could no longer read Spinoza nor Leibnitz without thinking of Bruno. It
is with this edition that the world rediscovers Bruno, never to forget him again.
WITH THE FIRST EDITION OF UEBER DIE LEHRE DES SPINOZA (1785), JACOBI BEGINS THE FAMOUS
PATHEISMUSSTREIT, which focused attention on the apparent conflict between human freedom and any
systematic, philosophical interpretation of reality.
53
In 1780, Jacobi (17431819), famous for coining the term nihilism, advocating belief and revelation instead
of speculative reason, thereby anticipating much of present-day literature, and for his critique of the Sturmund-Drang-era, had a conversation with Lessing, in which Lessing stated that the only true philosophy was
Spinozism. This led Jacobi to a protracted and serious study of Spinozas works. After Lessings death, in 1783
Jacobi began a lengthy letter-correspondende with Mendelssohn, a close friend of Lessing, on the philosophy
of Spinoza. These letters, with commentaries by Jacobi, are what constitute the first edition of Ueber die
lehre des Spinoza, as well as the first part of the second edition. The second edition is of much greater
importance, however, due to greatly influential Appendices. The work caused great furor and the enmity of
the Enlightenment thinkers. Jacobi was ridiculed by his contemporaries for attempting to reintroduce into
philosophy belief instead of reason, was seen as an enemy of reason and Enlightenment, as a pietist, and as a
Jesuit.
But the publication of the work not only caused great furor in wider philosophical circles, there was also a
personal side to the scandal which has made it one of the most debated books of the period:
Mendelssohn enjoyed, as noted at the outset, a lifelong friendship with G. E. Lessing Along with
Mendelssohn, Lessing embraced the idea of a purely rational religion and would endorse Mendelssohns
declaration: My religion recognizes no obligation to resolve doubt other than through rational means; and it
commands no mere faith in eternal truths (Gesammelte Schriften, Volume 3/2, p. 205). To pietists of the day,
such declarations were scandalous subterfuges of an Enlightenment project of assimilating religion to natural
reason While Mendelssohn skillfully avoided that confrontation, he found himself reluctantly unable to
remain silent when, after Lessings death, F. H. Jacobi contended that Lessing embraced Spinozas pantheism
and thus exemplified the Enlightenments supposedly inevitable descent into irreligion.
Following private correspondence with Jacobi on the issue and an extended period when Jacobi (in personal
straits at the time) did not respond to his objections, Mendelssohn attempted to set the record straight about
Lessings Spinozism in Morning Hours. Learning of Mendelssohns plans incensed Jacobi who expected
to be consulted first and who accordingly responded by publishing, without Mendelssohns consent, their
correspondenceOn the Teaching of Spinoza in Letters to Mr. Moses Mendelssohna month before the
publication of Morning Hours. Distressed on personal as well as intellectual levels by the controversy over
his departed friends pantheism, Mendelssohn countered with a hastily composed piece, To the Friends of
Lessing: an Appendix to Mr. Jacobis Correspondence on the Teaching of Spinoza. According to legend, so
anxious was Mendelssohn to get the manuscript to the publisher that, forgetting his overcoat on a bitterly
cold New Years eve, he delivered the manuscript on foot to the publisher. That night he came down with
a cold from which he died four days later, prompting his friends to charge Jacobi with responsibility for
Mendelssohns death.
The sensationalist character of the controversy should not obscure the substance and importance of
Mendelssohns debate with Jacobi. Jacobi had contended that Spinozism is the only consistent position for a
metaphysics based upon reason alone and that the only solution to this metaphysics so detrimental to religion
and morality is a leap of faith, that salto mortale that poor Lessing famously refused to make. Mendelssohn
counters Jacobis first contention by attempting to demonstrate the metaphysical inconsistency of Spinozism.
He takes aim at Jacobis second contention by demonstrating how the purified Spinozism or refined
pantheism embraced by Lessing is, in the end, only nominally different from theism and thus a threat neither
to religion nor to morality. (SEP).
The Beylagen, which are not included in the 1785 first edition and only appear with the 1789 second edition,
include: I. Auszug aus Jordan Bruno von Nola. Von der Ursache, dem Princip und dem Einen (p. 261-306) II.
Diokles an Diotime ber den Atheismus (p. 307-327) translation of Lettre sur lAthisme by F. Hemsterhuis.
54
55
The present work also contributed greatly to what later was to become known as Christian Kabbalah. Living
in a region where the Catholic Church was dominant, where a large part of the land was still under heavy
influence from Moslem Arabs, and where the Jews made important contributions to the culture, Lull sought
to unify all three religions by developing a (natural) philosophy incorporating elements common to all. These
rather unorthodox, and to some extent heretical, thoughts were later taken up by the Italian Renaissance
philosopher Pico della Mirandola (146394). He and many of his contemporaries believed to have discovered
in Kabbalah a lost divine revelation that could give the key to understanding both the teachings of Pythagoras,
Plato, and the Orphics, as well as the inner secrets of Catholic Christianity.
Pico della Mirandola had a considerable amount of Kabbalistic literature translated into Latin by the convert
Samuel ben Nissim Abulfaraj.
Raymond Lull (ab. 12321315), Majorcan writer, philosopher, memorycian (he was later to become a great
source of inspiration for Giordano Bruno), logician, and a Franciscan tertiary. He wrote the first major work
of Catalan literature. Recently-surfaced manuscripts show him to have anticipated by several centuries
prominent work on elections theory. He is sometimes considered a pioneer of computation theory, especially
given his influence on Gottfried Leibniz. He is also well known also as a glossator of Roman Law.
Lull taught himself Arabic with the help from a slave. As a result, he wrote his Ars Magna, which was
intended to show the necessary reasons for the Christian faith. To promote his theory and test its effectiveness,
he went to Algiers and Tunis.
At the age of 82, in 1314, Lull traveled again to North Africa, where an angry crowd of Muslims stoned him
in the city of Bougie. Genoese merchants took him back to Mallorca, where he died at home in Palma the
following year.
Despite the fact that a large corpus of the printed works by Lull are erroneously ascribed to him: On the whole,
we get the impression that the Testament, De secretis naturae seu de quinta essential, and Lapidarius
are probably the oldest members of the Lullian alchemical collections (Thorndyke)
The present Ryff-edition became very popular and later appeared numerous times. It was reprinted already
the following year in Venice, 1542, and editions followed in Nrnberg, 1546, Basel, 1561, Kln, 1567, etc. etc.
Freilich: 372
Adams: L, 1703
Honeyman: v, 2064A
Wellcome: 3897
56
sovereignty, contrary to the view of Aquinas that the consent required of the governed causes them to lose
sovereignty. Marsilio moved closer than Thomas both to the political theories that were to accompany vast
changes in practical politics during the renaissance and also to Aristotles older conception of the polis as
a human artifact, unprotected by the divine mandate that Augustine saw hovering over the city of man. Jean
Gerson and other conciliarists who advocated the solutions worked out at Constance were less radical than
Marsilio, whose ideas remained to incite not only the transformations of church government that came with
the Reformation but also the greater novelties of political philosophy that emerged from new Renaissance
statecraft.(Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 45).
Almost from the beginning, the book provoked outrage, contributing to its prolonged influence of both politics
and theology. In 1343 Clement VI categorized it as the worst case of heresy he had ever come across. John
XXIIs response to the Defensor pacis suggests that this was not extravagant hyperbole, but a dispassionate
assessment of the perceived threat to the papacy posed by the author. (Garnett, p. 17).
Marsilius Of Padua, Italian Marsilio Da Padova (born c. 1280, Padua, Kingdom of Italy-died c. 1343, Munich),
Italian political philosopher whose work Defensor pacis (Defender of the Peace), one of the most original
treatises on political theory produced during the Middle Ages, significantly influenced the modern idea of the
state. He has been variously considered a forerunner of the Protestant Reformation and an architect both of the
Machiavellian state and of modern democracy.(Encycl. Britt.).
58
Although the relevance to the course of the Protestant Reformation is obvious and profound, this is not the
only great importance that the book possesses. Even in the august company of Dante and William of Ockham,
there appears to be scholarly consensus on Marsiliuss pre-eminence. [] With Marslius, he [i.e. Figgis] wrote
elsewhere, it is the omnicompetent, universal, all absorbing modern state, the great Leviathan of later teachers
not power divided, but power concentrated and unified.
This estimate of Marsiliuss significance is also a common one. In 1920 Ephraim Emerton wrote that Marsilius
is the herald of a new world, the prophet of a new social order, acutely conscious of his modernness and not
afraid to confess it. According to one of his modern editiors, C.W. Previt-Orton: The glimmer of modernity,
often to be seen elsewhere c. 1300, has suddenly given way [in the Defensor pacis] to a transitory daylight.
Like the unfinished statues of Michelangelo, the state [Marsilius] conceives withdraws itself alive from the
marble, and seems rather cloaked than shaped by the mass of medieval speculation from which it is hewn.
(Garnett, pp. 2-3).
OCLC lists merely two copies outside of Germany (7) and Denmark (1): Yale and Ohio State. The 1522 Latin
edition is much more common in library holdings world-wide, and the English edition, of 1535, slightly more
so, with 13 copies listed on OCLC.
George Garnett: Marsilius of Padua & The Truth of History, 2006.
J.N. Figgis: Studies in the History of Political Thought from Gerson to Grotius, 2nd ed., 1916.
J.A. Watt: Spiritual and Temporal Powers, in: The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c. 3501450, 1988.
Brian P. Copenhaver & Charles B. Schmitt: Renaissance Philosophy, 1992.
59
60
The work is in two separate parts, and a second edition of volume two appeared in 1580.
The first volume deals mainly with astronomy and geometry, comprising seven tracts 1. De Sphaera liber
unus. 2. Computus Ecclesiasticus in summam collectus. 3. Tractatus Instrumentatorum Astronomicarum. 4.
Tractatus de Lineis horarijs. 5. Euclidis propositiones elementorum, libri Tredecimi solidorum tertij, regularium
corporum primi. 6. Musicae traditiones. 7. De lineis horarijs libri tres. The second volume is devoted entirely to
arithmetic and contains, among other things, some notable research on the theory of numbers. This includes,
in particular, a treatment of polygonal numbers that is more complete than that of Diophantus, to which
Maurolico added a number of simple and ingenious proofs. (DSB IX:191).
Among the topics related to mathematics in the Opuscula are chronology (the treatise Computus
ecclesiasticus) and gnomonics (in two treatises, both entitled De lineis horariis, one of which also discusses
conics). The work also contains writing on Euclids Elements (for which see also the unpublished Bibliothque
Nationale, Paris, manuscript Fonds Latin 7463). Of particular interest, too, is a passage on a correlation between
regular polyhedrons, which was commented upon by J.H.T. Mller, and later by Moritz Cantor. []
Maurolicos work in astronomy includes the first treatise collected in the Opuscula, De sphaera liber unus,
in which he criticized Copernicus. In another item of the collection, De instrumentis astronomicis, Maurolico
described the principal astronomical instruments and discussed their theory, use, and history. (DSB IX:191).
Adams M 919.Riccardi VIII:38.Smith Rara Arithmetica, pp. 348-50.Augustus de Morgan Arithmetical
Books, p. 24 On the properties of numbers and the doctrine of incommensurables (listing only volume two);
a superior work to the mass of those which then treated of similar subjects.
61
62
Giovanni Francesco [Gianfranceso] Pico della Mirandola (14701533), not to be confused with his uncle
Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (14631494) was a highly important Renaissance thinker and philosopher,
who was strongly influenced by the Neoplatonic tradition, but even more so by the preaching of Girolamo
Savonarola, whose thought he defended throughout his life.
The first of the two treatises printed here De morte Christi & propria cogitanda is the first work that Pico
dedicates to Savonarola, the year before his condemnation, and it marks his lifelong devotion to the prophetic
Renaissance preacher. As Schill points out, this important treatise was finished at the most three years after
Columbus discovery of America became known. It is the first treatise in which Pico mentions and treats the
seminal discovery, an interest that he was to maintain throughout all of his later writings. Gianfr. Pico was
very well connected, not least through the merits of his uncle, and he keeps appearing in close connection
with the most important and famous early scholars, historians, publicizers and popularizers of the discovery
of America. For instance, he was a close friend and correspondent of Matthaeus Ringmann, the man who
gave to America its name. As such, Pico played an important role in the earliest history of the discovery of
America, both due to his influential connections and due to his insightful reflections upon this discovery and
the meaning it would have and had on man, his relationship to Christ, God, and the Universe.
The work deals with the discovery in the most interesting way, enrolling it in mans relation to the universe
and to God. It is a religious-moral treatise on the duty of man to remember Christs death and his own. Gianfr.
Pico establishes an inner connection in man with the human nature of Christ and uses the discovery of this
new part of the world to express the limitless inner connection of man with Christ.
The effect that the Columbus Letter (1493) had upon the people of the Renaissancethe wondrous astonishment
that this discovery affected, although at the time it was merely thought to be a discovery of a continent that had
been known since Antiquity, namely Asiacan only properly be understood when reading the earliest sources
of this discovery. Pico was among the very first to describe what this discovery meant to man, and his work
is an invaluable source to the early history of the discovery of America. He inscribed Columbus discovery in
Christianity and in mans inner relation to Christ. He explains how, through unceasing pious contemplation
and a true, inner, heartfelt urge, it will be possible for man to obtain an inner connection with Christ. And
it does not even require great effort. It is not about reaching India; not to explore the erithrean shores [] On
the contrary, we are drawn to him by a natural force. (De morte Christi). And thus, the younger Pico here
appears from the very beginning as a diverse and stimulating character, who does not refrain from weaving
in to his pious or learned discussions experiences of daily life and contemporary history as examples and
comparisons, and which due to this very fact also becomes an unerring mirror for the true, inner participation
of the intellectual upper class of Europe in such events that concern us here. (Own translation from the
German of Schill, p. 20).
Shill provides many further examples of Pico mentioning and using Columbus discovery in this his first
work and the importance the work thus comes to have on our knowledge of the earliest understanding of the
consequences of the discovery. Even where he doesnt directly mention the discoveries, suddenly allusions
to them appear woven into a biblical or otherwise spiritual quotation, be it involuntary, or be it intentionally,
providing a special emotional momentum. (Own translation from the German of Schill, p. 22).
Just like his uncle, Gianfr. Pico devoted his life to philosophy, but being a follower of Savonarola and having
a Christian mission, he made it subject to the Bible. He even depreciated the authority of the philosophers,
above all of Aristotle.
His [i.e. Gianfrancesco Pico] uncle and his uncles circle of Florentine friends were important influences on
the younger Pico, who also continued the older philosophers devotion to Savonarola, even after Florence
63
tired of him in 1498. Gianfrancesco lived longer than his uncle, from 1469 to 1533, but he spent much of his
time fighting his relatives to keep the little princedom that he bought from Giovanni in 1491, so his published
output of more than thirty works, about a third of them philosophical, is remarkable. Savonarola taught him
to exclude reason from religion and to distrust philosophers as infidels, and Gianfrancesco modified the friars
views mainly by reinforcing them with his greater learning. As early as 1496 [written in 1496, printed in
1497], in one of his first works, On the Study of Divine and Human Philosophy, he distinguished divine
philosophy, rooted in scripture, from human philosophy based on reason; he denied that Christians need
human wisdom, which is as likely to hinder as to help the quest for salvation. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 245).
This seminal treatise, one of his very first productions, and the earliest philosophical one that he wrote, sharply
differentiated human philosophy, based on reason, from divine philosophy, based on scripture, and dismissed
human and rational philosophy as useless, and perhaps even harmful. It is to those means that Gianfr. Pico,
as the first thinker since Antiquity, uses the teachings of Sextus Empiricus. Even the violent condemnation,
hanging, and burning of Savonarola in the main square of Florence in 1498 did not prevent Pico from spreading
his radical views.
At the very beginning of the 16th century [recte end of the 15th], Gian Francesco Pico, the nephew of Pico
della Mirandola, had predicted the final failure of all attempts at reconciliation of the different philosophical
movements. Gian Francesco Pico was a thinker of very considerable stature and a follower of Savonarola.
There was a touch of tragedy about his personality. For his life was suspended, as it were, between the scaffold
of Savonarola and incessant family feudsin the course of one of which he was finally killed. No wonder that
he borrowed from the scepticism of Sextus Empiricus in order to destroy philosophy to make more room for
religion. (Garin, p. 133).
64
As the only Greek Pyrrhonian sceptic whose works survived, he [Sextus Empiricus] came to have a dramatic
role in the formation of modern thought. The historical accident of the rediscovery of his works at precisely
the moment when the sceptical problem of the criterion had been raised gave the ideas of Sextus a sudden and
greater prominence than they had ever before or were ever to have again. Thus, Sextus, a recently discovered
oddity, metamorphosed into le divin Sexte, who, by the end of the seventeenth century, was regarded as
the father of modern philosophy. Moreover, in the late sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the effect of his
thoughts upon the problem of the criterion stimulated a quest for certainty that gave rise to the new rationalism
of Ren Descartes and the constructive skepticism of Pierre Gassendi and Martin Mersenne. (Popkin, p. 18).
The revival of ancient philosophy was particularly dramatic in the case of scepticism. This critical and antidogmatic way of thinking was quite important in Antiquity, but in the Middle Ages its influence faded []
when the works of Sextus and Diogenes were recovered and read alongside texts as familiar as Ciceros
Academia, a new energy stirred in philosophy; by Montaignes time, scepticism was powerful enough to
become a major force in the Renaissance heritage prepared for Descartes and his successors. (Copenhaver &
Schmitt, pp. 17-18).
But not only in being the first serious attempt that we have of reviving the Scepticism of Sextus Empiricus, was
Gianfr. Picos work on divine and human philosophy of great importance to the development of Renaissance
thought. The entire foundation upon which the work is baseda sharp differentiation between human
philosophy (reason) and divine philosophy (scripture)comes to play a dominant role in the development of
16th century Renaissance thought.
The work, dedicated to Alberto Pio of Carpi, shows certain indications of Savonarolas influence and gives
us the first glimpse of Picos unfavourable attitude toward secular philosophy, a viewpoint which will be
developed in greater detail in his Examen Vanitatis, published in 1520. (Schmitt, p. 50).
Throughout the early modern period, from Ficino and Pico to Newton and Leibniz, such convictions [of the
unity of truth) supported a pattern of historiography that could never have emerged without the humanists,
even though it did not preserve their fame for modern times. Other myths of classicism and Christianity
outlived the fable of ancient theology because they conflicted less flagrantly with the findings of history.
The purpose of the ancient theology was to sanctify learning by connecting it with a still more ancient source
of gentile wisdom that reinforces sacred revelation. Rather than baptize the heathens as Ficono or the older
Pico wished, some early modern critics damned them, and one of the most aggressive thinkers of this school
was the younger Pico. He saw an impassable gulf between Christian and pagan belief where his uncle had
tried to build bridges. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 337).
BMC VI:843; Goff: P644;
See:
Schill, Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola und die Entdeckung Amerikas, 1929; Popkin: The History of
Scepticism. From Savonarola to Bayle, 2003; Schmitt: Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola (14691533)
and his critique of Aristotle, 1967; Copenhaver & Schmitt: Renaissance Philosophy, 1992; Garin: Italian
Humanism, 1965.
66
67
Gianfr. Pico, a learned scholar and apt reader of classical texts, was the first Renaissance thinker that we know
to have seriously studied and used the works of Sextus Empiricus, which were not printed until the 1560ies,
causing a revolution in Renaissance thinking. No discovery of the Renaissance remains livelier in modern
philosophy than scepticism. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 338). The revived skepticism of Sextus Empiricus
was the strongest single agent of disbelief. (ibid., p. 346).
The printing of Sextus in the 1560s opened a new era in the history of scepticism, which had begun in the late
fourth century BCE with the teachings of Pyrrho of Elis. [] Before the Estienne and Hervet editions, Sextus
seems to have had only two serious students, Gianfrancesco Pico at the turn of the century and Francesco
Robortello about fifty years later. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, pp. 240-41).
No significant use of Pyrrhonian ideas prior to the printing of Sextus Hypotyposes [in the 1560ies] has
turned up, except for that of Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola. (Popkin, p. 19).
Giovanni Francesco [Gianfranceso] Pico della Mirandola (14701533), not to be confused with his uncle
Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (14631494) was a highly important Renaissance thinker and philosopher,
who was strongly influenced by the Neoplatonic tradition, but even more so by the preaching of Girolamo
Savonarola, whose thought he defended throughout his life.
Just like his uncle, Gianfr. Pico devoted his life to philosophy, but being a follower of Savonarola and having
a Christian mission, he made it subject to the Bible. He even depreciated the authority of the philosophers,
above all of Aristotle.
It is in the Examen, Gianfr. Picos main work, that his sceptical arguments are developed to their fullest
extent, and it is here that he not only discusses at length Pyrrhonism, based on Sextus Hypotyposes( which
were only published more than 40 years later), and deals in detail with Sextus Adversus Mathematicos
(also only published more than 40 years later), propounding his own ideas and attacking Aristotle, he also
provides lengthy summaries of Sextus texts, which seem more like actual translations than interpretations
or paraphrases.
As Charles Schmitt also shows, the younger Pico must have read Sextus in a Greek manuscript, as the texts
of Sextus were not printed before the 1560ies, when the Hervet- and the Estienne-editions appear, causing
what we would call The Sceptical Revolution of the Renaissance, a turning point in the history of modern
thought. Apparently, Gianfr. Pico used a codex that belonged to Giorgio Antonio Vespucci. It was during an
enforced exile around 1510 that Gianfr. Pico set to work on his Examen Vanitatis Doctrinae Gentium, which
was published for the first time in 1520 and dedicated to Pope Leo X. The work was printed in a small edition
by an obscure press in his own little principality at Mirandola, which explains its scarcity.
In the Examen Pico introduced the actual sceptical arguments of Sextus Empiricus, plus some newer
additions, in order to demolish all philosophical views, especially those of Aristotle, and to show that only
Christian knowledge, as stated in the Scriptures, is true and certain. (Popkin, pp. 20-21). But although he here
carefully set forth the ancient sceptical criticisms of sensory knowledge claims and of the rational criteria that
let us judge what is true and false, it is important to remember that he did not as such advocate scepticism,
rather, he used it for his own means. Using the ancient sceptical arguments as ammunition to undermine the
confidence in natural knowledge, his aim was to lead people to see that the only real and reliable knowledge
is revealed knowledge. He denounces all pagan philosophical claims, attacks Aristotles theory of knowledge
with the arguments of Sextus, all the time regarding Christianity as immune to sceptical infection, because it
does not depend upon the dogmatic philosophies that Sextus had refuted.
68
In his use of Sceptical arguments, Gianfr. Pico was not only doing something completely new in a Renaissance
setting (i.e. reviving and using sceptical arguments at all), he was doing something completely new as such. The
original Pyrrhonian formulations were primarily directed against Stoic and Epicurean theories of knowledge,
and traditionally they were not directed towards the all-overshadowing dominating theories of Aristotle. As
such, Gianfr. Pico makes Aristotelianism more of an empirical theory than it was traditionally viewed, and
also in this did the Examen come to have groundbreaking influence. He furthermore introduces several
critiques of Aristotelianism that were not generally known at the time, such as that of Hasdai Crecas (15th
century Jewish Spanish thinker), whose work had not yet been published and which only existed in Jewish
manuscript, as well as that of the late Hellenistic commentator John Philoponous, who later came to play an
important role in Renaissance readings of Aristotle.
As early as 1496 [originally printed 1497], in one of his first works, On the Study of Divine and Human
Philosophy, he distinguished divine philosophy, rooted in scripture, from human philosophy based on reason;
he denied that Christians need human wisdom, which is as likely to hinder as to help the quest for salvation.
By 1514 he had completed a longer and sterner work, The Weighing of Empty Pagan Learning against True
Christian Doctrine, Divided into Six Books, of Which Three Oppose the whole Sect of Philosophers in General,
while the Others Attack the Aristotelian Sect Particularly, and with Aristotelian Weapons, but Christian
Teaching is Asserted and Celebrated throughout the Whole. As its title suggests, the Examen, published in
1520, hardened Picos hostility to pagan philosophy. Just when Luther was making the Bible the sole rule of
faith, Pico discredited every source of knowledge except scripture and condemned all attempts to find truth
elsewhere as vanitas, emptiness; profane knowledge is at best a distraction from the work of salvation, as some
of the greatest Fathers had taught. Picos purpose was sincerely religious and only incidentally philosophical;
much of Renaissance scepticism remained true to his pious motives, though they were not fully appreciated
for forty years after he wrote. By demolishing secular thought, Pico hoped to empty the human mind of reason
and make a clear channel for Gods grace; mans only intellectual security lay in church authority. Convinced
69
of Christianitys unique value, he turned his uncles eirenic learning to contrary purposes, working skillfully
with Greek manuscripts to make his humanism a potent weapon against religious error. [].
Pico devoted most of his first three books to reproducing the arguments of Sextus Empiricus against the
various schools of ancient philosophy; in Books IV and V he turned scepticism against Aristotle. His extensive
borrowings from Sextus often come closer to translation than paraphrase or analysis, and his choices are
therapeutic rather than theoretical. Aristotle had to go because he was the chief source of secular contagion
among the faithful, and Sextus was the best medicine available. Pico regarded Christianity itself as immune
to sceptical infection because it does not depend on the dogmatic philosophies that Sextus had refuted. [].
(Copenhaver & Schmitt, pp. 245-46).
The Examen marks a turning-point in the history of Renaissance thought and the development of modern
philosophy. The importance of the revival of scepticism can hardly be over-estimated, and Gianfr. Picos use of
the sceptical arguments which he utilizes in the Examen would prove to be highly important and influential.
But the revival that Gianfr. Pico is thus responsible for, not only comes to serve his own purpose, as history
will prove, the sword is two-edged.
Claiming in the Examen that the works assigned to Aristotle were doubtfully authentic; his sense-based
epistemology could not produce reliable data; his doctrines, often presented with deliberate obscurity, had
been disputed by opponents and followers alike and had been criticized by Christian theologians; even
Aristotle himself was uncertain about some of them. Aristotelian philosophy, the pinnacle of human wisdom,
was therefore shown to be constructed on the shakiest of foundations. Christian dogma, by contrast, was built
on the bedrock of divine authority and therefore could not be undermined by the sceptical critique. Or so he
believed, unaware that scepticism, which he had revived as an ally of Christianity, would eventually become
a powerful weapon in the hands of its enemies. (Jill Kraye: Two Cultures: Scholasticism and Humanism in
the Early Renaissance, in: The Philosophy of the Italian Renaissance).
Defended by ancient philosophers such as Sextus Empiricus, refuted by Augustine (De civitate dei (11,26):
Even if I am mistaken, I exist; a clear anticipation of Descartes cogito), Scepticism was revived in the Middle
Ages by Nicholas of Autrecourt (whose works were burned by papal order in 1347). By the Renaissance, this
tendency came to be linked with fideism (Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola, Erasmus, Montaigne, Gassendi,
Daniel Huet, and Pierre Bayle, to name but a few), leading, in one way or another, to its modern culmination in
Hume. (Black Swans, the Brain, and Philosophy as a Way of Life : Pierre Hadot and Nassim Taleb on Ancient
Scepticism).
Gianfrancescos most important philosophical work, probably written sometime after 1510 and published
in 1520, was Examen vanitatis doctrinae gentium, which is especially important because it marks the first
serious attempt to adapt the Pyrrhonist (radically skeptical) philosophical ideas of the Hellenistic philosopher
Sextus Empiricus to contemporary intellectual discourse. (Charles G. Nauert: Historical Dictionary of
Renaissance, 2004).
See: Popkin: The History of Scepticism. From Savonarola to Bayle, 2003; Schmitt: Gianfrancesco Pico della
Mirandola (14691533) and his critique of Aristotle, 1967; Copenhaver & Schmitt: Renaissance Philosophy,
1992; Garin: Italian Humanism, 1965.
Adams P:1156.
70
71
During the Renaissance a profound interest in the teachings of Neoplatonism emerged, centered and focusing
on Plotinus and his Enneads. Neoplatonism came to hugely influence Renaissance philosophy, science,
humanism, and theology, and much Renaissance thought stemmed directly from the reading of Plotinus,
making the editio princeps of this text one of the foundational works for the development of modern thought.
The Renaissance recognized no deep divide between Platos teachings and those of the Neoplatonists. This
blurring of categories was particularly momentous for the fifteenth century when an immense Neoplatonic
literatureseveral times the size of the Platonic corpusalso became known. A primary task of translation
for Ficino was the Enneads of Plotinus, one of the subtlest and most penetrating philosophical works of late
antiquity and one that played a major role in the destiny of Renaissance Platonism. (Copenhaver & Schmitt,
Renaissance Philosophy, p. 15).
Plotinus (204270) may justly be regarded as the true founder of Neo-Platonism, in so far as he perpetuated
its principles in a written form (Sandys, I:343). In the class-room of Plotinus a new and original approach was
taken to the interpretations of the later Platonic and Aristotelian commentators; these groundbreaking new
ideas and interpretations have been preserved as the Enneads, the magnum opus of Neoplatonism, divided
in to six groups of nine books. It is Plotinus student, Porphyry (ca. 233-301-5) that we have to thank for the
preservation of these founding books of Neoplatonism.
Neoplatonism is a term invented in the 18th century for a school of religious and mystical philosophy, which
was founded in the third century and which dominated down to the end of Antiquity in the sixth century,
when the Emperor Justinian closed the Neoplatonic Academy (529). Neoplatonic teaching revolved around
a renewed study of the teachings of Plato that were now combined with the doctrines of other schools of
Greek philosophy. The school called itself Platonic, but modern historians named it Neoplatonic in order to
emphasize its differences from Plato. Platos dialogues were the main philosophical authority, but Plotinus,
Ammnius and the other Neoplatonists attempted to fit all of Platos scattered doctrines into a coherent system
and to incorporate other Stoic and Aristotelian ideas into this, thus creating a comprehensive synthesis of Greek
thought. As such, Neoplatonism came to dominate the final phase of ancient philosophy and bequeathed
its heritage to subsequent ages. Neoplatonism must be considered the only really original product of Greek
philosophy in the third century, and after having been neglected during the Middle Ages, this original
philosophical direction was re-discovered in the Renaissance, the philosophy of which came to be hugely
dominated by it.
As the actual founder of Neoplatonism, Plotinus, in his Enneads, added to the genuine Platonic elements
a more explicit emphasis on a hierarchical universe, which consists of several levels, beginning with the
transcendental One. Plotinus original idea of the supreme One that is totally transcendent, which contains
no division, multiplicity or distinction and which is prior to and different from everything that exists came to
bridge the gap between progressive Christian and Gnostic ideas and traditional Platonic philosophy. Ficino
himself had tried to Christianize the original doctrines of Plato, but in spite of this it was obvious that Plotinus
Enneads, with the hypostases of the One, Soul and Mind, posed a better resolution to the problems of
Trinitarian theology. The common grounds of the Christians and the Neoplatonists meant that Plotinus work
may be said to have influenced 16th century thought more profoundly than the actual writings of Plato himself.
Plato in the Neoplatonic version was perfectly suited for 16th and 17th century Europe.
With much of Renaissance Platonism thus rendered through Plotinus, the Enneads came to profoundly
influence not only Renaissance philosophy and theology, but also art and science of the 16th and 17th centuries;
Of even greater interest is the impact of Renaissance Platonism upon sciences in medicine, astrological and
alchemical theories exercised a good deal of influence during that time yet the main impact of Platonism, as
might be expected, was felt in mathematical sciences, which had been most cultivated and respected by Plato
72
and his followers. (Kristeller, Renaissance Thought and its Sources, pp. 62-63). Much knowledge of Plato
in the Renaissance was rendered through especially Plotinus and Ficino, and the publication of this editio
princeps of the Greek text of Plotinus incorporating Ficinos translation of it must be said to have been of the
utmost importance to the development of late Renaissance thought, philosophy and science.
Platonism had of course also earlier played an enormous rle in philosophy and thought in general, but with
the publication of the original Platonic texts and the translations of them, the intellectual world changed, and
the influence of the availability of the original texts must not be overlooked.
The scarce edition princeps was based upon four anuscripts. Brunet calls determines it very rare: Premire
dition, assez rare.
Sandys II:105; Graesse 5:352 ; Brunet IV:727 ; Adams P:1597
73
74
Pomponazzis conclusion [in the De Incantationibus] results from a dramatic change in method which in turn
is based on a profoundly new attitude toward philosophical inquiry. Medieval theologians and philosophers
as well as most Renaissance thinkers were content to limit the role of reason in nature because they sincerely
believed that the Christian God intervened in the natural order to create miraculous occurrences. As we have
seen, this belief prevented their scientific convictions from destroying Christian doctrine by exempting central
Biblical miracles from natural process. Even those who held that Christian revelation and Aristotelian science
were irreconcilable maintained a sincere fideism which allowed each universe to remain intact, each standing
separate from the other. But once Pomponazzi applied the critical method of Aristotelian science to all religious
phenomena, Christian miracles were engulfed by the processes of nature. Absorbed by the usual course of
nature, the miracle could no longer be the product of divine fiat. Indeed Christianity itself became merely
another historical event, taking its place within the recurring cycles of nature, and destined to have a temporal
career within the eternal flow of time. (Pine, p. 273).
De Incantationibus constitutes one of the single most important works of the Renaissance. Bringing everything
in the world under the general laws of nature, the history of religion as well as all other facts in experience,
De Incantationibus gives us, for the first time in the history of philosophy an outline of a philosophy of
nature and of religion, an outline that came to be seminal in the history of philosophy and science throughout
the following centuries. With the main aim of the work being to determine the fact that there is no such
thing as supernatural, no magic, no omens, no witchcraft, no divine intervention, no apparitions, etc., etc.
all marvelous events and powers observed in experience or recorded in history have their natural, scientific
explanation, they are all within the scope of principles common to all nature, it is no wonder that it was
placed on the index of forbidden books immediately upon its publication, as the only of Pomponazzis works
ever. The analysis of the history of religions and the theory of the nature and use of prayer that Pomponazzi
here develops is hugely interesting and so far ahead of its time that one hardly believes it. E.g. the notion
that religious doctrines all aim, through fables and myths (which he disproves), to preserve the social order
rather than to discover the truth, is not something you will find in any other work of the Middle Ages or the
Renaissance. [H]e brings the whole phenomena of religious historythe changes of religious belief, and
the phases of thaumaturgic powerunder certain universal laws of nature. Of these facts as of all others, he
suggests, there is a natural and a rational explanation; in them the powers that are at work in all nature are still
operative; and they are subject to the laws and conditions that govern nature generallythe laws of change,
of development, of growth and decay, and transformation in decay. (Douglas, p. 299).
In regard to the religious issue, I have tried to show that he makes a claim for the absolute truth of philosophy
and relegates religion to the purely practical function of controlling the masses. Religious doctrines contain a
kind of truth because they can persuade men to act so as to preserve the social order. But religious doctrine has
social value rather than speculative veracity. [] rational truth is the only truth. It is really compatible only
with complete disbelief. And I think that this is the statement that Pomponazzi makes. The only doctrines
that he accepts are those of philosophy. Philosophy rejects the personal Christian God acting within history
and eliminates the miracles of religion. Philosophy reduces to the absurd the notion of a life after death. And
finally philosophy destroys revelation itself by viewing it as the product of heavenly forces rather than the act
of divine will. (Pine, pp. 34-35).
The work was originally written in 1520, but was not published in Pomponazzis life-time. It circulated in
manuscript form, however, and was also as such widely noted. In 1552, 27 years after Pomponazzis death, the
manuscript was brought to Basel by Pomponazzis student Guglielmo Gratarolo, who had had to flee Italy due
to his anti-religious views. Here, in Basel, he had the book printed for the first time, with a foreword written
by himself, in 1556. This was the very first time that the book was published, as it had also not been included
in the standard edition of Pomponazzis collected works, published at Venice the year after his death, 1525
presumably due to its dangerous and revolutionary views.
75
In his preface, Gratarolo expresses fear that someone may think him either over curious or less Christian
for publishing this book. He furthermore explains that he had purchased the manuscript 20 years earlier
and brought it with him North when leaving Italy 6 years previously. Granting, however, that there may
be something in the work which does not entirely square with Christianity, Gratarolo thinks that it should
not be suppressed or withheld from the scholarly public, since it contains more solid physics and abstruse
philosophy than do many huge commentaries of certain authors taken together. (Thorndyke, V, p. 99-100).
Come the Renaissance, the idea of eliminating demons and angels and attempts at a showdown with magical
transformations and the like were not completely novel in themselves. Much scientific thinking of the Middle
Ages and the Renaissance carried such beliefs that had in some form or other been current for a long time.
But up until Pomponazzis treatise, these ideas had always been surrounded by hesitance and a clear aim at
still protecting the miraculous nature of Christianity itself, not leading the theories forward and not letting
them bear any relevance. Let us pause here a moment to estimate the place of this radical treatise [i.e. De
Incantationibus] in the history of European rationalism. [] It was Pomponazzis achievement to go beyond
these earlier hesitations and qualifications, particularly in regard to the astrological determination of religious
belief. By dramatic shifts of emphasis and the extension of certain ideas to their logical limits, Pomponazzi
utterly transformed the context in which these earlier views occurred. In their newly radicalized form, they
challenged the supremacy of revelation by elevating philosophy to a position hitherto unattained in the Latin
West. (Pine, p. 268).
[] Even this brief sketch makes clear that Pomponazzi came at the end of a long scientific tradition which
had absorbed, and to some degree, subordinated Aristotelian-Arabic science and astrology to the Christian
universe. But if we look at each strand of this tradition, we can see how Pomponazzi carried these concepts to
their furthest limits. (Pine, pp. 268-72).
Pomponazzi clearly sought to explain all miraculous cures, events, etc. through natural powers. All sequences
and concoctions which could seem magical or supernatural are within the same framework as other observed
sequences and concoctions in nature. We may not be able to explain all of them (although Pomponazzi does
attempt in the treatise to provide specific and elaborate natural, physical explanations of a large number of
magical and supernatural events), but that is merely a lack in our intellect or understanding and by no
means because these occurrences or events are not governed by nature and the physical laws of nature.
This whole mode of explanation of the marvelous in nature and history is constantly pitted against the
orthodox theory which attributed magic and miracles to the agency of angels or demons. The book De
naturalium Effectuum Causis is a uniform polemic against that theory, as essentially a vulgar superstition.
It is the tendency of the vulgar mind, he says, always to ascribe to diabolic or angelic agency events whose
causes it does not understand. (Douglas, p. 275).
These fictions are designed to lead us to truth and to instruct the common people who must be led to the
good life and turned away from evil just like children, that is to say, by the hope of reward and the fear of
punishment; and it is by these vulgar motives that they are led to spiritual knowledge, just as children pass
from delicate nourishment to more solid nourishment. Hence it is not far from my concept or from the truth
that Plato taught the existence of angels and demons not because he believed in them but because it was his
aim to instruct the ignorant. (Pomponazzi, De Incantationibus, 10, pp. 201-202).
In order to understand the monumental accomplishment of Pomponazzis De Incantationibus, one must
realize which tradition he is inscribed in, namely that of Italian Aristotelianism (as opposed mainly to the
Renaissance Platonism). It is within this long tradition that he effects a revolution. In the Italian schools alone
the emerging science of nature did not mean a sharp break with reigning theological interests. To them it
76
came rather as the natural outcome of a sustained and co-operative criticism of Aristotelian ideas. Indeed, that
mathematical and mechanical development which by the end of the sixteenth century produced Galileo owes
very little to the Platonic revival but received powerful stimulus from the critical Aristotelianism of the Italian
universities. (Ren. Phil. of Man, p. 12).
Pomponazzi stood at a crossroad in the history of Aristotelianism. He still studied the great logicians and
natural philosophers of the 14th century, which his Italian humanistic colleagues had given up (focusing
instead on man and his place in the universe), but at the same time he had a highly original approach to
the teachings of Aristotle and a unique uninhibited approach to the nature of the universe, and he responded
philosophically to the achievements of humanism, always seeking the truth and the naturalist explanation.
Of that critical Aristotelianism which sought to find the true meaning of the works of Aristotle, lay them
bare, and develop them further to find the true nature of the universe, to explain how the world functions
without any preconceived notions (like the belief in Christ, etc.), Pomponazzi was a forerunner. With his
De Incantationibus, this last scholastic and the first man of the Enlightenment paved the way for the
Enlightenment of the centuries to come, for rational free thinking. His quest against the theologians and his
scorn for all comfortable and compromising modernism in religion, and his sober vision of the natural destiny
of man (Randall, p. 268) combined with his refusal to leave the bounds of the Aristotelian tradition, his
meticulous use of the medieval method of refutation, and his thorough rationalism, enabled him to revolutionize
the Aristotelianism of the 16th centuryand indeed the entire trajectory of philosophy of the ages to come
and invoke the period of scientific free-thinking that breaks free of Christian doctrines and which later comes
to be the Enlightenment. Against Picos denial of astrology as incompatible with human freedom, he tried to
77
make an orderly and rational science of the stars, opposed to all superstitionthe naturalists answer to the
Humanist. (Randall, p. 277).
During the twelve decades or so between Pomponazzis arrival (1484) and Galileos departure in 1610, the
learned community that Shakespeare called fair Padua, nursery of arts, achieved a distinction in scientific
and medical studies unmatched elsewhere in Europe. Thus, Pomponazzis career in northern Italy brought
him close to the most exciting advances of his time in science and medicine. In keeping with the nature of his
university appointments, he approached Aristotle from a perspective quite distant from Brunis humanism or
Lefvres theologizing. [] Pomponazzis Aristotelianism developed entirely within the framework of natural
philosophy. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 105).
With this final explanation, Pomponazzi has discovered natural causes for all miraculous events and hence
has eliminated the miracle as a category for understanding the process of nature. [] As we have seen,
Pomponazzis theory offers three fundamental natural explanations of events which Christianity ascribes to
the miraculous intervention of angels and demons. [] Here Pomponazzis method takes its most radical turn.
Biblical miracles are now also found to have natural causes. Moses, we learn, performed his task by natural
means. The dead revived by the prophets were not really dead. And the acts of Christ and the Apostles can
be explained within natural limits. (Pine, pp. 254-56).
The histories of other religions record miracles similar to those of Christianity, and Pomponazzi justifies his
frequent citation of historians in a philosophical work as authorities for past natural events of rare occurrence.
Such is the most detailed and carefully worked out, the most plausible and at the same time most sweeping
expression of the doctrine of astrological control over the history and development of religions that I have seen
in any Latin author. (Thorndyke V, pp. 108-9).
Adams: P-1827; Wellcome: I:5153; DSB: XI:71-74.
A.H. Douglas: The Philosophy and Psychology of Pietro Pomponazzi, 1910.
M.L. Pine: Pietro Pomponazzi: Radical Philosoper of the Renaissance, 1986.
Thorndyke: A History of Magic and Experimental Science, Vol. V, 1966 (4th printing)
P.O. Kristeller: Eight Philosophers of the Italian Renaissance, 1965.
J.H. Randall, in: The Renaissance Philosophy of Man, 1956 (4th impression).
B.P. Copenhaver & C.B. Schmitt: Renaissance Philosophy, 1992.
E. Cassirer: Individuum und Kosmos in der Philosophie der renaissance, 1969 (3. Aufl.orig. 1927).
See also: Kristeller: Renaissance Thought and its Sources; Medieval Aspects of Renaissance Learning;
Renaissance Thought II, Papers on Humanism and the Arts.
FULLER DESCRIPTION AVAILABLE UPON REQUEST-
78
RENAISSANCE PHYSIOGNOMY
PORTA, GIOVANNI BATTISTA DELLA
De Humana PhysiognomoniaLibri IIII: Qvi ab extimis, qu in hominum corporibus
conspiciuntur signis, ita eorum naturas, mores & consilia (egregiis ad viuum expressis
Iconibus) demonstrant, vt intimos animi recessus penetrare videantur. Nunc ab innumeris
mendis, quibus passim Neopolitana scatebat editio, emendati, primumq; in Germania
lucem editi.
Hanovi (Hannover), G. Antonium, impensis Petri Fischeri Fr.( Frankfurt), 1593. 8vo. (17x12 cm.).
Contemporary full vellum. Title with woodcut printers device. (16), 534, (55) pp. 2 large woodcut
portraits (verso of title-page and verso of last leaf in first quire) and numerous woodcuts in the text,
depicting human and animal physiognomies. Title-page a bit soiled and a cut in lower right corner
(no loss). 3 leaves in Index repaired in lower right corners with loss of a few letters. Otherwise a
fine and well-preserved copy.
DKK 18,500.00 / EURO 2,500.00
The rare second edition (being the first edition printed in Germany) of Portas seminal work, the richly and
well-illustrated Physiognomia, which is considered the founding work on Physiognomy.
Giambattista della Porta was an immensely influential Renaissance thinker, scientist and writer, who
contributed greatly to the intellectual era of the Renaissance. His groundbreaking work on physiognomies
79
was originally printed in Italy in 1586 and was planned to appear in a second edition in Italy in 1593, but his
work had attracted the attention of the Inquisition, and the printing of the work was prohibited. Thus the rare
second edition appeared in Germany in 1593, and after 1600, numerous more editions of the work began to
appear. He published his last work in 1610.
Porta played a seminal role in the development of the academies of the late Renaissance, and he himself
established the Accademia dei Segreti (Academia Secretorum Naturae) some time prior to 1580. It met in
Portas house in Naples, and it was devoted to discussion and study of the secrets of nature. It is thus no
surprise that he was examined by the Inquisitionthis was probably not only due to his astonishing work
on the correspondence between the external form of the body and the internal character of the person (the
Physignomonia), but also because of the dangerous activities of his academy. The academy was thus
closed by the Inquisition, and in 1592 all further publication of his works was prohibited. This ban was not
lifted until 1598.
His academy was a forerunner of the important Academia dei Lincei which was founded in Rome by
Federico Cesi in 1603, and which Porta himself joined in 1610. Apart from the founder Cesi, Porta was the
most influential member, at least until Galilei joined it in 1611.
In his seminal De Humana Physiognomia, Porta sets out to establish a link, in accordance with the
prevailing theories of correspondences, between the external form of bodies and the expressions of faces and
the psychology of persons by comparing with animal trades. In numerous expressive woodcuts throughout
the work, human characters are depicted in comparison with animal counterparts (mammals, birds, etc.).
Though credited with having priority in inventing the telescope (due to book XVII, on refraction, of his
Magiae Naturalis, 1589, and his work on concave and convex lenses, De Refractione, 1593), Portas world
image was fundamentally a magical one, as was typical of many Renaissance scientists and thinkers (e.g. Pico
della Mirandola). His system of spiritualistic metaphysics led him to draw interesting and later influential
analogies between plants, animals and men, and he saw the same shapes, humours etc. in organisms that at
a first glance are not related. This created the foundation of his main physiognomic work, and in it he draws
interesting parallels between human and animal shapes and physiognomies, throughout documenting this
with illustrations.
This could perhaps sound as a fanciful work, but in fact he presents a striking and convincing system which
should and would not be dismissed.
Portas studies in physiognomy became a main inspiration for Johann Kaspar Lavater in the 18th century.
Della Porta preceeded Lavater in attempting to estimate human characters by the features. He was the
founder of physiognomy, and this is one of the earliest works on the subject. (Garrison & Morton).
Giovanni Battista Della Porta, as he was also known, was born around 1535 and died in 1615, which dates him
amidst The Scientific Revolution and Reformation. He was an Italian scholar, scientist, natural philosopher
and playwright from Naples, who came to influence Renaissance thought in a number of ways.
His devotion to experiment and his study of mathematics brought him in the 1580s to the verge of greatness,
but he was soon overwhelmed again by the lure of the occult and the marvelous. Perhaps Portas most
compelling virtue and weakness was this youthful enthusiasm for the things of nature. There is a joy in his
studies that not even the fatigue of working on the telescope and parabolic mirrors could diminish. (DSB
XI:98).
Graesse V: p.417. Adams P:1925.Brunet IV:826.Garrison & Morton No. 150 (1586-edition).
80
81
The very rare first, and perhaps only, edition of this work, consisting in extracts of Proclos philosophical
works in Latin, namely those on Plato, composed by Raphal Mambla.
Renaissance printings of the philosophical works of the great Greek Neoplatonist Proclos (410-85) (often
considered the last great Neoplatonist) are of the utmost scarcity. His greatest contribution lies in his
commentaries on Platos works, as well as his Theological Elements. He developed one of the most elaborate,
precise and convincing systems of Neoplatonism, and his influence on Medieval, and later also Renaissance,
thought was immense.
Neoplatonism is a term invented in the 18th century for a school of religious and mystical philosophy,
which was founded in the third century and dominated down to the end of Antiquity in the sixth century,
when the Emperor Justinian closed the Neoplatonic Academy (529). Neoplatonic teaching revolved around
a renewed study of the teachings of Plato that were now combined with the doctrines of other schools of
Greek philosophy. The school called itself Platonic, but modern historians named it Neoplatonic in order to
emphasize its differences from Plato. Platos dialogues were the main philosophical authority, but Plotinus,
Ammnius, Proclus, and the other Noeplatonists attempted to fit all of Platos scattered doctrines into a
coherent system and to incorporate other Stoic and Aristotelian ideas into this, thus creating a comprehensive
synthesis of Greek thought. As such Neoplatonism came to dominate the final phase of ancient philosophy
and bequeathed its heritage to subsequent ages. Neoplatonism must be considered the only really original
product of Greek philosophy in the third century, and after having been neglected during the Middle Ages,
this original philosophical direction was re-discovered in the Renaissance, the philosophy of which came to be
hugely dominated by it.
In Proclus, one of the last heads of the Athenian school, Neoplatonism attains its most systematic and even
schematic perfection. In his Elements of Theology and Platonic Theology all things and their mutual
relations are neatly defined and deduced in their proper place and order; and the concepts of Aristotles logic
and metaphysics, divested of their specific and concrete reference, are used as elements of a highly abstract
and comprehensive ontology. As a commentator, Proclus applied this neat and scholastic system to some of
Platos dialogues, just as other members of the school applied it to Aristotle. And as the leading philosophy
of the period, Neoplatonism supplied practically all later Greek Church Fathers and theologians with their
philosophical terms and concepts (Kristeller, Renaissance Thought and its Sources, p. 53).
During the Renaissance a special and profound interest in the teachings of Neoplatonism emerged, and the 15th
and 16th century Latin translations and editions of the works of Plato and of the Neoplatonists, which made
the texts available to Western readers, are of immense importance to the history of Platonism, Neoplatonism,
and Western thought in general.
Not in Adams, not in Graesse, not in Brunet.
82
83
Of Ptolemys genuine works the most germane to and significant for our investigation is his Tetrabiblos,
Quadripartium, or four books on the control of human life by the stars In the Tetrabiblos the art of
astrology receives sanction and exposition from perhaps the ablest mathematician and closest scientific
observer of the day or at least from one who seemed so for succeeding generations. Hence from that time on
astrology was able to take shelter from any criticism under the aegis of his authority (Thorndike I:111).
As opposed to the Karpos, almost all research points to the fact that the Tetrabiblon must genuinely be by
Ptolemy, and as such, it is to be considered of the greatest importance, not only to astrology, the history and
impact of the science, but also to astronomy and to the understanding of the man who wrote one of the most
important astronomical works of all times. In the Tetrabiblos Ptolemy first discusses the validity of the art
of judicial astrology, and the introductory chapters are devoted to defending astrology against charges that
it is uncertain and useless. According to Ptolemy, the laws of astronomy are beyond dispute, but the art of
predicting human affairs from the movement of the stars should be attacked using more reason than that, and
his main argument is that one should not reject the art itself merely because it can be abused, and frequently
is, by impostors, or because it is an art not yet fully developed and may be difficult to handle properly. In
book I Ptolemy goes on to explain the technical concepts of astrology, in book II, the influences on the earth in
general, and in books II and IV, the influences on human life. Although often dependent on earlier authorities,
Ptolemy often develops his own dogma. The discussion in books III and IV is confined to what can be deduced
from a mans horoscope (D.S.B. XI:198).
The great influence of the Tetrabiblos is shown not only in medieval Arabic commentaries and Latin
translations, but more immediately in the astrological writings of the declining Roman Empire, when such
astrologers as Hephaestion of Thebes, Paul of Alexandria, and Julius Firmicus Maternus cite it as a leading
authoritative work. Only the opponents of astrology appear to have remained ignorant of the Tetrabiblos,
84
continuing to make criticisms of the art which do not apply to Ptolemys presentation of it or which had been
specifically answered by him. (Thorndike I: 115-16).
Camerariuss translation of the Tetrabiblon, here printed for the first time, is probably the most important
and influential of the many Latin versions of the text. It is considered the best, most widely used, and most
important for the spreading of Ptolemaean astrology in the Renaissance, where this came to play a great role
at the universities and beyond. Melanchton never doubted the scientific accuracy of astrology. For instance,
in 1535 Joachim Camerarius edition of Ptolemys Tetrabiblos was warmly received by Melanchton; in the
same year he began lecturing on Ptolemys work at Wittenberg and stressed the scientific character of the
work in his opening address. And in the following year he commented on the second book, beginning with an
exhortation to appreciate the philosophical arguments of the first book (Stefano Caroti in: Paolo Zambelli
edt., Astrologi hallucinati Stars and the End of the World in Luthers Time, 1986, p. 113).
It is widely accepted that it is the present first Greek/Latin-edition, i.e. the editio princeps of the Greek text
together with Camerarius Latin version of it, that has played the most dominant role in the spreading and
interpreting of Ptolemys astrology in the Renaissance. Astrology, as derived from Classical Antiquity, with
Ptolemy as the greatest exponent of them all, came to play a seminal role in Renaissance understanding
of both exact sciences and philosophy, and thus this period witnessed a huge number of discussions and
interpretations of astrology in general, but of the astrology of Ptolemys Tetrabiblion in particular. Many of
the main proponents of Ptolemys astrology in the Renaissance are known specifically to have owned or read
the present Greek/Latin edition and refer to Camerarius Latin version and to the original Greek text which
had now become available for the first time.
85
demonstrated in the preface to his book, On the excellence of mathematics, in which he shows the necessary
of mathematics to the learning of all liberal arts.
Ramelli was captain of engineers to the kings of France and Poland. His reputation grew and he eventually left
France to serve under the Duke of Anjou, later King Henry III.
Dibner, Heralds of Science No 173 (1588-edition); Wellcome No. 5324; Sotheran I: 3882; Klaus Jordan Nr. 3045.
87
RENAISSANCE ENLIGHTENMENTDEFENDING
ARISTOTLE AGAINST CARDANO
SCALIGER, JULIUS CAESAR.J.C. BORDONIUS
Exotericarum exercitationum liber quintus decimus de subtilitate, ad Hieronymum
Cardanum. In extremo duo sunt indices: priorbreuiusculus, continens sententias
nobiliores: alter opulentissimus, pen omnia complectens.
Lutetiae (Paris), Ex officina typographica Michaelis Vascosani, uia Iacobaea, ad insique Fontis,
1557. 4to. Lovely 17th century full calf binding with five raised bands and small gilt ornaments
to back. Boards with two blindstamped triple-line borders inside eachother, the inner one with
gilt corner-ornaments, gilt centre-pieces. Binding with some wear. Leather overall worn, corners
bumped, capitals worn, upper capital with a bit of loss of leather. Strip of about one cm. cut away
from top of t-p., no loss of text, old (near contemporary) scribbles and owners names crossed
out on t-p., near contemporary or a little later handwritten ex libris to top of title-page (Ex libris
Joannis Rebraut). Contemporary or a little later marginal annotations to some leaves and likewise
neat bibliographical inscription to pasted down front endpaper (7 lines, Hac Editio/ est
emendatissima et elegantissima.). Smaller marginal dampstaining to upper corner from leaf SSiii
onwards, not affecting text. Last about 15 leaves with very minor marginal loss, not affecting text.
Internally all in all nice and clean. Illustrated with woodcuts, about 19 larger and smaller woodcut
illustrations in the text, depicting diagrams of the earth, how water is created, moon, sun & earth,
etc. (8), 476, (1), (59, -indexes), (1, -Privilege du Roi), (1, -colophon, verso blank) pp.
DKK 20,000.00 / EURO 2,700.00
The beautiful and rare first edition of Scaligers devastating polemical attack on Cardanos main work, De
Subtilitate, which caused one of the most famous of Renaissance disputes and invoked a foundational
discussion of the nature of empirical approach to natural sciences and philosophy. The work presents us with
numerous interesting attempts at describing and explaining various (natural) phenomena and (philosophical)
dilemmas, and it became a highly famous and widely read book that exercised profound influence upon
later philosophers, scientists and natural historians. The Exotericarum exercitationum won a celebrity that
survived its authors death. Lipsius, Bacon, and Leibnitz were among its later admirers; and Kepler who read
it as a young man, accepted its Averroist doctrine of attributing the movement of each star to a particular
intelligence. (D.S.B. XII:136).
The title of the work indicates that this be the 15th book of Scaligers attack on Cardanus main work De
Subtilitatea rambling miscellany of natural philosophy which eventually grew to twenty-one books and
appeared in many reprints and revisions before and after Cardanos death in 1575polemically indicating
that there were enough problems with the work to fill another 14 volumes. 14 such volumes were never written,
nor planned. Seldom read but widely cited in its own time and the century following was the Fifteenth Book
of Exoteric Exercises on Subtlety by Julius Caesar Scaliger, a blast from an admirer of Aristotle bothered by
Cardanos prose as well as his originality and sloppiness; Scaligers title implied that there was enough wrong
with De subtilitate to have filled fourteen other volumes. At one point, Scaliger thought that his attach had
literally killed its victim, but it only helped enlarge his reputation, for better or for worse. (Copenhaver &
Schmitt, p. 308).
88
Just as Cardanos two grand encyclopaedic works, Scaligers Exotericarum deals with all parts of natural
philosophy, and thereby with all subjects that in the Renaissance were accepted as belonging to this
discipline, i.e. natural science in general. In astronomy Scaliger ridiculed Cardanos stress on the astrological
significance of comets; and he denied that the worlds decay is proven because the apse of the sun was thirtyone semidiameters nearer the earth than in Ptolemys time. Scaliger also rejected several of Cardanos beliefs
in natural history: that the swan sings at its death; that gems have occult virtues (a flea has more virtue than
all the gems); that there exist corporeal spirits that eat; that the peacock is ashamed of its ugly legs. (D.S.B.
XII:135).
Due to his realistic and empirical approach to natural sciences and philosophy, Scaliger considered it necessary
to attack the likes of Cardano. He considered himself an empirical Averroist, like e.g. Pomponazzi (by whom
he is said to have been taught), and like him also primarily based his research and work on experience and
observation. This search for truth was closely connected with his disputatious nature, which is what finally led
him to this elaborate criticism of Cardanos De subtilitate libri XXI, as it had lead him to attack Erasmus 26
years earlier. However, having received no answer from Cardano, Scaliger believed a false rumor that he had
died, and suddenly felt awful having attacked the allegedly dead man;he thus wrote him a funeral oration,
full of repent. Cardano had not died, as it turned out, and he published his reply two years after the death of
Scaliger.
Julius Caesar Scaliger (Bordonius) was born in Padua, Italy, in 1484, and died in Agen, France, in 1558. He
studied at the University of Padua, where he received the doctorate in artes in 1519, and where he was
appointed lecturer in logic the following year,a post he declined, perhaps in order to study medicine, the
doctorate in which he is believed to have obtained as well. In Padua he was taught philosophy by the most
prominent of philosophers: Pomponazzi, Marc Antonio, Zimara and Nifo. Scaliger himself later received a
great reputation throughout Europe, not only as a philosopher, but also as a physician and a natural scientist.
He befriended the likes of Ronsard and Rabelais (for a time), and was known by almost all learned Europeans
in the Renaissance. It was because of Scaliger that Nostradamus and Rabelais came to Agen. Due to the
empirically grounded research, many of the results of Scaligers work were considered controversial and
heretical;he was summoned before the Inquisition (but was acquitted), and some of his books were placed
on the Index of Prohibited Books.
89
90
of modern philosophy. Moreover, in the late sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the effect of his thoughts
upon the problem of the criterion stimulated a quest for certainty that gave rise to the new rationalism of Ren
Descartes and the constructive skepticism of Pierre Gassendi and Martin Mersenne. (Popkin, p. 18).
The printing of Sextus in the 1560s opened a new era in the history of scepticism, which had begun in the late
fourth century BCE with the teachings of Pyrrho of Elis. [] Before the Estienne and Hervet editions, Sextus
seems to have had only two serious students, Gianfrancesco Pico at the turn of the century and Francesco
Robortello about fifty years later. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, pp. 240-41).
Our knowledge of ancient scepticism comes from Sextus, which is introduced to the Renaissance with the first
printings of his works in 1562 and 1569, Hervets 1569-edition being by far the most important, not only due
to the fact that it is here that Sextus main work, Adversus Mathematicos appears for the first time, but also
due to the influence that Hervet, his interpretation, and his preface came to exercise on the use of skepticism
throughout more than a century.
The revival of ancient philosophy was particularly dramatic in the case of scepticism. This critical and antidogmatic way of thinking was quite important in Antiquity, but in the Middle Ages its influence faded []
when the works of Sextus and Diogenes were recovered and read alongside texts as familiar as Ciceros
Academia, a new energy stirred in philosophy; by Montaignes time, scepticism was powerful enough to
become a major force in the Renaissance heritage prepared for Descartes and his successors. (Copenhaver &
Schmitt, pp. 17-18).
Hervets seminal Sextus-edition was was printed in Paris by bookseller Martin Le Jeune, but part of the edition
was taken up by Christopher Plantin and issued in Antwerp under his imprint, explaining the two different
imprints of our copy.
91
The first printed edition was by Henri Estienne (Stephanus) in 1562 of Sextus Hypotyposes. A second
printed Latin edition of the Hypotyposes plus Adversus Mathematicos appeared in 1569. The text of the
Hypotyposes is that of Estienne, the translation of Adversus Methematicos was done by French counterreformer and theologian, Gentian Hervet, from a manuscript that belonged at the time to the Cardinal of
Lorraine. The Greek text was not published until 1621 by the Chouet brothers. (Popkin, p. 18).
Gentian Hervet (d. 1584) was a committed churchman, who after studies in the universities of Orleans and
Paris lived in the household of Reginald Pole, later to became Archbishop of Canterbury and Cardinal, at first
in England thenas Pole had, because of the Reformation, to leave Englandin Padua, Venice and Rome.
Hervet took part with Marcello Cervini (later Pope Marcellus II) in the first sessions of the Council of Trent. He
returned to France in 1555 as vicar general to the bishop of Noyon and wrote pamphlets against the Huguenots.
In 1561 he entered the service of the Cardinal of Lorraine, Charles de Guise, whom he accompanied to the third
period of the Council of Trent (1562-3). In 1564 he took part as canon of the cathedral in the provincial council
of Rheims, in which the cardinal published the decrees of the Council of Trent. About the time of his activity in
the Council of Trent the focal point of Hervets translations shifted. He translated not only the Greek Fathers
of the Church, but in addition, under the influence of academic scepticism as represented also by Reginal Pole,
Sextus Emopiricus Adversus Mathematicos (Paris, 1569). He had long been active as translator of works
connected with the Aristotelian philosophy. During an earlier sojurn in Rome, he published a number of
philosophical texts which concerned the controversies surrounding Pietro Pomponazzi. In 1544 he translated
into Latin Aristotles De anima, together with the commentary of Johannes Philoponus. There followed
translations of Alexander of Aphrodisiass De fato (1544) and Quaestiones naturales et morales (1548)
and of Zacharias Scholasticuss Ammonius: Dialogus quod mundus non sit Deo coaeternus (1546). In these
works Hervet described those who denied the immortality of the soul as atheists and as opponents of Aristotle
and his commentators. (Lohr, p. 36).
Hervets religious outlook came to be determinative for the use of scepticism throughout the following century.
He not only gave to the modern world the writings of Sextus, and the only proper knowledge we have of
ancient scepticism, he also outlined its importance and usage. During the 1560ies, Hervet fought intellectually
against the encroachments of Calvinism, challenging various Protestants to debate with him and publishing
many pamphlets against their views. He saw Sextus work as ideal for demolishing this new form of heretical
dogmatism, that of the Reformer. If nothing can be known, he insisted, Calvinism cannot be known either.
In the mid-sixteenth century, the Calvinist movement in France grew very rapidly, and within a few years,
France was embroiled in a civil war, both militarily and intellectually. In order to save the citadels of French
thought from falling into the hands of the Reformers, strong measures had to be taken. One of these measures
was to put Pyrrhonism to work in the service of the Church. The first step taken in this direction was the
publication in 1569 of the writing of Sextus Empiricus in Latin by a leading French Catholic, Gentian Hervet,
the secretary of the cardinal of Lorraine. As has been mentioned earlier, Hervet, in his preface, boldly wrote
that in this treasury of doubts was to be found an answer to the Calvinists. They were trying to theorize about
God. By destroying all human claims to rationality through skepticism, Hervet believed that the Calvinist
contentions would be destroyed as well. Once one realized the vanity of mans attempts to understand, the
fideistic message that God can only be known by faith, not by reason, would become clear.
The avowed aim by Hervet, to employ Pyrrhonism to undermine the Calvinist theory, and then to advocate
Catholicism on a fideistic basis, was to become the explicit or implicit view of many of the chief battlers
against the Reformation, in France. By adapting the pattern of argument of the sceptics of the issue at hand,
the Counter-Reformers constructed a new machine of war to reduce their opponents to forlorn scepticism
in which they could be sure of nothing. (Popkin, p. 67).
92
secretary of the Cardinal of Lorraine and participant at part of the Council of Trent, linked his work on
Sextus with what Gianfrancesco Pico had earlier done. He declared that just how useful Sextus Empiricus
commentary can be in upholding dogmas of the Christian religion against outside philosophers, Gianfrancesco
Pico della Mirandola has beautifully taught us in that book in which he upholds Christian philosophy against
the dogmas of outside philosophers. (Popkin, p. 36).
This leads us to the problem of what, if any, relation there is between the revival of interest in the writings of
Sextus Empiricus by Pico della Mirandola and the first Latin editions of the works of Sextus by Henri Estienne
and Gentian Hervet. No mention is made of Gianfrancesco in Estiennes preface to the first of Sextus works
to be printed in 1562, and there is no clear indication that he knew of Picos work. When the larger work
against the mathematicians was published seven years later, however, the translator, Gentian Hervet, has the
following to say in his preface:
Just how useful Sextus Empiricuss commentary can be in upholding dogmas of the Christian religion against
outside philosophers, Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola has beautifully taught us in that book in which he
upholds Christian philosophy against the dogmas of outside philosophers.
Here perhaps we have a clearer and more accurate evaluation of Pico and his endeavor than we have
hitherto encountered. Hervet seems to be one of the few who realized precisely what Pico was getting at.
He sees Gianfrancesco as one who has safeguarded the Christian religion against the onslaught of dogmatic
philosophers. Hervet believed, as Pico did, that a sceptical attitude toward the various polemics among
dogmatic schools of philosophy is the best safeguard for Christianity. (Schmitt, p. 169).
Since the Renaissance had to discover or rediscover the tools of philology and history needed for such
detective work, the pioneering labours of obscure humanist scholarsGentian Hervet, who translated sextus,
or William Canter, who first published a Greek text of the Eclogae of Stobaeuscertainly deserve our
memory and admiration. It was they who first edited, organized, translated, printed, and disseminated the
philosophical remains of antiquity that succeeding centuries have come to take for granted. If Thales and
his successors were the fathers of Western philosophy, the humanist scholars of the Renaissance were the
midwives of its rebirth in a classical form. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p. 18).
Kristeller: Renaissance Thought II. Papers on Humanism and the Arts, 1965.
Popkin: The History of Scepticism. From Savonarola to Bayle, 2003.
Lohr: Renaissance Latin translations on the Greek commentaries on Aristotle, in: Humanism and Early
Modern Philosophy, Edt. by Kraye and Stone, 2000.
Schmitt: Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola (14691533) and his critique of Aristotle, 1967.
Copenhaver & Schmitt: Renaissance Philosophy, 1992.
94
95
The collection of his orations in the first printing became highly influential in the late Renaissance and came
to determine the development of the art of writing speeches as well as a certain way of presenting philosophy
and moral thought to the people.
96
97
98
99
of early modern empiricism. He had a remarkable influence on Tommaso Campanella, Giordano Bruno, Pierre
Gassendi, Francis Bacon, Thomas Hobbes and authors of the clandestine Enlightenment like Guillaume Lamy
and Giulio Cesare Vanini. (SEP).
Telesio was born in Cosenza and in a sense he opens the long line of philosophers through which the South
of Italy has asserted its Greek heritage, a line that links him with Bruno and Campanella, with Vico in the
eighteenth century, and with Croce and Gentile in our own time. (Kristeller, Eight Philosophers, p. 97). He
was educated by his uncle, the humanist Antonio Telesio, in Milan and Rome, and he studied philosophy
and mathematics at the university of Padua, where he got his doctorate in 1535. He had a great respect for
the famous Aristotelian Vicenzo Maggi, with whom he discussed his magnum opus, obtaining his approval
before publishing the seminal second version of it in 1570. He was closely connected not only with Maggi, but
also with the other leaders of the most intelligent and official Aristotelianism of his age. But Telesio opposes
the Aristotelianism of both his own and earlier times, claiming that they all erected arbitrary systems that
consisted of a strange mixture of reason and experience. They created their systems without consulting nature,
and thus they merely obtained arbitrary ideas of the world.
What separates Telesio and his contemporaries from the great Renaissance thinkers that had gone ahead is
not merely the passing of a few decades, but the emergence of a completely different intellectual atmosphere.
The tradition of medieval thought, which was still felt very strongly in the fifteenth century and even at the
beginning of the sixteenth, began to recede into the more distant background, and it was now the tbroad thought
and learning of the early Renaissance itself which constituted the tradition by which the new generations
of thinkers were shaped, and against which their immediate reactions were directed. (Kristeller, Eight
Philosophers, p. 91). Telesio belongs to a group of thinkers that we call the Renaissance philosophers of nature.
They are considered a group by themselves, different from the humanists, Platonists, and Aristotelians that
we usually group other Renaissance thinkers into. What distinguished these philosophers of nature, however,
was not a different subject matter from that of the Aristotelians and the Platonists (of both contemporary and
earlier times), but their clear claim to explore the principles of nature in an original and independent way,
tearing themselves loose of an established tradition and authority that kept them in binds. They formulated
novel theories andfreed themselves from the ancient philosophical authorities, especially Aristotle, who had
dominated philosophical speculation, not least natural philosophy, for centuries.
Telesio, of course, did not stand alone in this group of bold, original thinkers that we call the Renaissance
philosophers of nature, and whose quest it was to make new discoveries and to attain knowledge unaccessible
to the ancients, it also included for instance Fracastoro, Cardano, Paracelsus, and Bruno. But Telesio in
particular protrudes, as his thought is distinguished by such clarity and coherence, and his ideas anticipate
important aspects of later philosophy and science.
His magnum opus, the extremely influential De Rerum Natura, is that which by far best expresses his novel
thoughts and that which most profoundly influenced the thought, philosophy, and science of the cnturies to
come.
[b]y 1547 his ideas seem to have been in public circulation, and within a few years he was at work on his
first treatise On the Nature of Things According to Their Own Principles, one of the more incisisve titles
in Renaissance philosophy and a clear allusion to Lucretius. [] Pressed by his followers, he published the
original two book version of De rerum natura [the title of this being De Natura iuxta propria principia
liber] in 1563 [recte: 1565], having previously testing the soundness of his arguments in conversations with
Vincenzo Maggi, a noted Paduan Peripatetic. Another edition followed in 1570; in 1575 Antonio Persio gave
public lectures on the Telesian system in Venice, Padua, Bologna, and the south; and in 1586 appeared the
100
definitive expansion to nine books. The author died two years later in Cosenza. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p.
310).
In the preface to the work, Telesio rejects Aristotles doctrine as being in conflict with the senses, with itself,
and with the Scriptures, and he claims that his own doctrine is free from these defects. As we have seen above,
in the introduction, or sub-title to the first book, he furthermore insists that unlike his predecessors, he has
followed nothing but sense perception and nature. He then proceeds to expound the principles of his natural
philosophy, positing heat and cold as the two active principles of all things, and matter as a third, passive,
principle. Having developed and applied these principles, he concludes the first work with a very interesting
treatment of space and time. After having set forth his own position, he examines and refutes the views of
earlier philosophers, expecially those of Aristotle, whom he considers superior to all others. So far as Telesios
relation to Aristotle is concerned, we must admit that he shows considerable independence, both in his own
theories and in his detailed criticism of Aristotles views, and this independence is more valuable since it is
based not on ignorance, but on a thorough knowledge of the Aristotelian writings, and is accompanied by a
genuine respect for the relative merits of Aristotelianism. (Eight Philosophers, pp. 101-2).
The only sources apart from Aristotle that Telesio quotes at length are medical, i.e. Hippocrates and Galen,
from which he got his notions of human physioglogy. He does, however, draw upon other sources, borrowing
notions, though not quotiong them (e.g. Fracastoco, the Epicureans, the Stoics, the Neoplatonists, Ficino).
These apparent borrowings from various sources should certainly not be overlooked, but ones final
impression is that in transforming and combining these ideas, and in formulating some important new ones,
Telesio was remarkably original. In his cosmology, the role assigned to heat, cold, and matter is chiefly of
historical interest, since it is one of the first serious attempts to replace Aristotles natual philosophy. We may
give him credit, too, for apparently doing away with the sharp disinction between celestial and terrestrial
phenomena, which was one of the chief weaknesses of the Aristotelian system. Of greater significance are
his theories of the void, and of space and time. His assertion of an empty space was in a sense a return to the
position of the ancient atomoists, which Aristotle had tried to refute; this position must have been known to
Telesio, from Lucretius and also from Aristotle himself, but the evidence on which he based himself was partly
new and, so to speak, experimental.
101
Still more important is his theory of space and time. Whereas Aristotle had defined time as the number or
measure of motion, thus making it dependent on motion, Telesio regards time as independent of, and prior to,
motion, like an empty spectacle. He thus moves a long step away from Aristotle in the direction of Newtons
absolute time.
In the case of space, the change in conception is even more interesting. The Greek term Topos, which we often
translate as space has the primary meaning of place, and Aristotles theory that the topos of the contained
body is the limit or border of its containing body makes much better sense when we translate topos as place
rather than space. Telesio seems to be aware of this ambiguity, for he uses not only the term locus, which had
been the standard Latin translation of Aristotles topos, but also spatium, which is much more appropriate
for his notion of an empty space in which all bodies are contained. Thus he again moves away from Aristotle
in the direction of Newtons absolute space; but, more than this, I am tempted to believe that it was Telesio
himself who gave terminological precision to the word spatium (space) and substituted it for locus, a
usage for which I do not know any earlier clear instances. (Kristeller, Eight Philosophers, pp. 103-4).
Telesios theories and entire world-view proved to be extremely influential, and his is considered a forerunner
directly as well as indirectlyof not only Newton and Locke, but also Descartes and Bacon, and a strong direct
influence on Bruno, Campanella, and Patrizi.
Telesio dedicated his whole life to establishing a new kind of natural philosophy, which can be described as
an early defense of empiricism bound together with a rigorous criticism of Aristotelian natural philosophy and
Galenic physiology. Telesio blamed both Aristotle and Galen for relying on elaborate reasoning rather than
sense perception and empirical research. His fervent attacks against the greatest authorities of the Western
philosophical and medical traditions led Francis Bacon to speak of him as the first of the moderns (Opera
omnia vol. III, 1963, p. 114). He was perhaps the most strident critic of metaphysics in late Renaissance times.
It was obviously due to his excellent relationships with popes and clerics that he was not persecuted and was
able during his own lifetime to publish his rather heterodox writings, which went on the index shortly after
his death. (SEP)
Giordano Bruno speaks of the giudiciosissimo Telesio in the third dialog of De la causa, whilst Francis
Bacon based his own speculative philosophy of nature on a blend of Telesian and Paracelsian conceptions
(Giachetti Assenza 1980; Rees 1977; 1984). Thomas Hobbes followed Telesio in the rejection of species
(Schuhmann 1990; Leijenhorst 1998, p. 116ff.) The physiology of Ren Descartes in De homine shows close
similarities to Telesios physiological theories as they are presented in De natura rerum (Hatfield 1992).
Telesio also had some influence on Gassendi and on libertine thinkers (Bianchi 1992). (SEP)
His sense of empirical science, which included progressive ideas on space, vacuum, and other physical topics,
grew out of a disenchanted world-view remarkable for its hard-headed clarity. (Copenhaver & Schmitt, p.
314).
Adams: T:292; Thorndyke: VI:370-71.
Paul Oskar Kristeller: Eight Philosophers of the Italian Renaissance, 1964; Renaissance Thought and its
Sources, 1979.
Eugenio Garin: Italian Humanism. Philosophy and Civic Life in the Renaissance, 1965
Copenhaver & Schimtt: Renaissance Philosophy, 1992.
Ernst Cassirer: Individuum und Kosmos in der Philosophie der renaissance, 1927.
D.S.B. XIII:277-80. (Telesio also introduced concepts of space and time that anticipated the absolute space and
time of Newtonian physics).
102
103
key text of the Renaissance, which opened a new period in the interpretation of the Greek philosopher [i.e.
Aristotle] (Lohr, p. 25). The work was partly responsible for the development of Renaissance Aristotelianism
and thus Renaissance thought in general. The combination of the fact that we here have the paraphrases by
one of the greatest ancient Greek commentators of the key texts of the most significant philosopher of all
times, rendered into Latin by perhaps the most significant translator of the period and printed at the most
crucial time for the development of early modern thought, makes this one of the most significant philosophical
publications of the Renaissance. There can be no doubt as to the influence that the present publication came to
have on the development Renaissance philosophy.
The publication of Barbaros translation of Themistius inaugurated a new period in the study of Aristotelian
philosophy. In his version of Themistius Paraphrases we encounter not simply a translation occasioned
by contemporary controversies, as was often the case in the Middle Ages. Rather, Barbaros version brings
together a corpus of the commentaries of Themistius on Aristotelian philosophy: the Posterior Analytis,
Physics, De anima and Parva naturalia. (Lohr, p. 26).
The first printing of the work appeared in 1480 (the same year stated at the end of each section in the present
edition), and in 1499 this second printing appeared. Both printings are of the utmost scarcity and almost
impossible to find. After these two incunable-editions, at least 9 new printings appeared before 1560, bearing
witness to the great impact of the text, and in 1570 Hieronymus Scotos printed a new edition.
With reference to those works of Aristotle which were and remained the center of instruction in logic and
natural philosophy [i.e. The Posterior Analytics, Physics, etc.], the most important changes derived from the
fact that the works of the ancient Greek commentators became completely available in Latin between the late
fifteenth and the end of the sixteenth centuries and were more and more used to balance the interpretations
of the medieval Arabic and Latin commentators. The Middle ages had known their works only in a very
limited selection or through quotations in Averroes. Ermolao Barbaros complete translation of Themistius
and Girolamo Donatos version of Alexanders De Anima were among the most important ones in a long
line of others. When modern historians speak of Alexandrism as a current within Renaissance Aristotelianism
that was opposed to Averroism, they are justified in part by the fact that the Greek commentators, that is,
Alexander and also Themistius, Simplicius, and many others, were increasingly drawn upon for the exposition
of Aristotle. (Kristeller, p. 45).
Equally important [as the recovery of Aristotles Mechanics and Poetics] for the continued growth of
the Peripatetic synthesis was the recovery and diffusion of the Greek commentaries on Aristotle The most
important of the two dozen commentators were Alexander of Aphrodisias, Ammonius, Simplicius, Themistius,
and John Philoponus. Of these five, only Alexander and Themistius were Aristotelians (Copenhaver &
Schmitt, p.68).
Already in the Middle Ages, scholars had been aware of and used commentaries on and paraphrases of the key
texts of Aristotle, but their knowledge of this was primarily based on some Latin translations and allusions,
fragments, and summaries in the writings of the Muslim philosophers, e.g. Averroes. But with the emergence
and translations into Latin of the ancient Greek commentators [Alexander and Themistios being the primary
ones] and their paraphrases of Aristotles texts, the Renaissance came to discover an Aristotle that would
influence almost all thought of the period. The ancient Greek commentators not only had a much more thorough
knowledge of classical Greek thought than would have been possible for a medieval writer, but they also had
access to works that were later lost and through these ancient commentators rediscovered in the Renaissance.
By the middle of the 16th century, almost all of these texts had been printed in both Greek and Latin, and these
publications were of the utmost importance to the development of almost all Renaissance thought. Their
recovery, publication, and translation took some time, but almost all circulated in Greek and Latin by the
104
105
107
108
Extremely scarce first edition thus, containing all of Theophrastus 23 characters in Greek and Latin, being the
first edition of Auberius excellent Latin translation and first edition with Lycios interesting commentaries.
This very rare edition, which presents us with the Greek text of H. Stephan (Stephanus), contains a new Latin
version by Claudius Auberius, who was scarcely twenty years of age when he composed it. The notes are
critical and historical; sometimes bold, but always erudite This version and these notes were republished in
Zuingers edition of Aristotles Ethics at Basil. fol. 1582. (Dibdin II:500).
This version of Theophrastus milestone work, the first recorded attempt at systematic character writing,
became hugely influential and is still referred to in modern editions of the text, as Auberius translation
is regarded as one of the best and most important interpretations of the text. Claude Aubery or Claudius
Auberius (ca. 15401596) was a noted philosopher and medical doctor, professor of Philosophy in Lausanne.
He translated several Greek texts into Latin, but is best remembered for his excellent version of Theophrastus
Characters, which was highly influential throughout the Renaissance and which was incorporated into later
Renaissance Aristotle-editions as the standard-version of Theophrastus text.
Theophrastus (ca. 371ca. 287 BC), Aristotles successor at the Lyceum, and probably the most famous
Aristotelian of all times, successfully presided over the Peripatetic School for 36 years and here wrote a number
of works. The most famous of them is arguably his great moral opus The Characters, which continues to
amaze readers to this day. It introduced the character sketch, which became the core of the Character as a
genre, and as such it influenced the entire literay tradition of the Western world.
The fabulous, very witty, astute, harsh, and insightful characteristics of type characters of the human race
have been formative for our understanding of moral virtues and vices and how they come to be expressed in
man, for our understanding of human nature in general. It is no wonder that the work became so popular and
widely read during the Renaissance, the era of man as the centre of the universe.
Le texte est le celui de Henri Estienne (insre dans ldition dAristote de 1557), mais dans la version il suit
pour la plupart ses propres conjectures (Graesse 7: 125).
Dibdin II:500, Graesse VII:125.
109
THE ALDUS-COIN
TITUS VESPASIAN
Roman coin. Denarius.
[Rome, AD 79-80]. 18 mm. diameter. Dolphin entwined around anchor on one side, and Draped
bust of Tutus, turning right on the other side. An excellent, near mint specimen. 3,05 g.
DKK 18,000.00 / EURO 2,400.00
Excellent specimen of the beautiful and rare coin that inspired Aldus Manutius famous printers device,
the dolphin-and-anchor, the most famous logo in the history of book printing and the trademark of the
Renaissance. The Aldus coin is the only bookor printingrelated ancient coin in existence.
Aldus Manutius, the most famous printer of all times, had been given a copy of the Titus coin, with the
dolphin-and-anchor logo on the verso, as a gift by Pietro Bembo. He was extremely taken by the magnificent
logo, that in Roman times, by Titus Vespasian, had been used to illustrate the proverb Festina lente (make
haste slowly), and was so inspired by it that he began using it as his printers device at the very beginning of
the 16th century. Before it appears as his printers device for the first time, he used it as an illustration in one
of his most magnificent books, Colonnas Hypnerotomachia Poliphili, 1499.
In his Adagiorum Collectanea, the collection of classical proverbs that he kept revising throughout his life,
Erasmus Roterodamus had composed a lengthy essay on the festina lente proverb, which intrigued him
immensely. Erasmus traced the motto back to the emperor Titus Vespasian, who had minted a coin with the
emblem (i.e. the present coin), and had the rare opportunity to inspect that very coinnamely that which
belonged to his printer, Aldus Manutius, who had been given it by the great Italian scholar Pietro Bembo. The
second edition of Erasmus Adagiorum Collectanea was published by Aldus in Venice in 1508, and Erasmus
subsequently praises his printer to the skies in the course of explaining festina lente.
Erasmus explains the motto as such: the circle as having neither beginning nor end represents eternity. The
anchor, which holds back and ties down the ship and binds it fast, indicates slowness. The dolphin, as the
fastest and in its motions most agile of living creatures, expresses speed. If then you skillfully connect these
three, they will make up some such principle as Ever hasten slowly, and adds that by claiming it as his
own (recognizable and marketable) emblem, Aldus gave fresh celebrity to the same device that was once
approved by Vespasian. Not only is it most familiar, it is highly popular among all those everywhere in the
world to whom sound learning is either familiar or dear. Erasmus seems to also suggest that the device had
perhaps become too popular: the city of Venice, with its many claims to distinction, has none the less become
distinguished through the Aldine press, so much so that any books shipped from Venice to foreign countries
immediately find a readier market merely because they bear that citys imprint.
110
And he might have been right. In fact, the Aldine press was so successful and renowned, and Aldus printers
device as taken from the Titus Vespatian coin, so incorporated a symbol of elegant, correct printing and higher
learning, that it was imitated by printers all over Europe. By using the dolphin-and-anchor device, other
printers, although much inferior, would benefit from the authority and prestige of the Aldine press. In spite
of Erasmus attempts to make the public aware of this by praising the efforts of Aldus and opposing them
to those common printers who reckon one pitiful gold coin in the way of profit worth more than the whole
realm of letters, publishers kept using the Aldus device for centuries.
The coin is rarely seen is such excellent condition as here.
111
112
published at Cologne in 1575, followed the traditional division of Averroes, but also gave the Greek division
of the text into chapters and had the third book begin according to Greek tradition. The authors upon whom
Toletus depended were the Latin commentators, especially Thomas, as well as the Greeks and Arabs, with
special attention given to Averroes. However rich his commentary, the major philosophical discussion is found
in the more than seventy quaestiones, which resemble a systematic treatise. (Schmitt, Skinner, Kessler, The
Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy, p. 511).
If one question is to be pointed out as the main philosophical one of the Renaissance, it is that of the souls
relation to reason or intelligence. Anima and Intellectus were then the watchwords of the schools: their
relation, or the nature of anima intellective, was the point round which discussion moved and on which was
invoked the authority of Averroes, Alexander or St Thomas. When the audiences in the Italian class-rooms
called out Quid de anima? this was the subject which they desired to hear treated. (Douglas, p. 74).
For Toletus, intellectual abstraction is simply a precision from accidents and a consideration of the substance
of anything. In his great De animacommentary, he allowed for a direct intellectual cognition of a singular
material thing. And although he thinks it more probable that an agent intellect is necessary, he regards it as
probable that there is no agent intellect or that the two intellects distinguished by Aristotle are one and the
same. Toletus followed a Thomistic line, but departed from Thomism in some details. He held that individuals
are directly apprehended by the intellect and that the agent intellect is the same power as the possible intellect.
He rejected the Thomistic doctrines of the real distinction between essence and existence and of individuation
by designated matter; for Toletus individuation results from form. (Cambr. Dict. of Phil.).
113
Having already stated that the basic psychological positions of the church were identical with those of true
philosophy, Toletus was less anxious in philosophical argument itself to adhere to the faith and more open
to strictly philosophical values. This applied particularly to the problem of immortality. Citing the volitional
aspects of the human soul as well as the intellectual ones, he argued that immortality could be demonstrated
by natural means, while admitting that Aristotle himself was unclear on the question. (Schmitt, Skinner,
Kessler, The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy, p. 511).
Toletus stands at the very centre of 16th century Spanish scholarship and counts as one of the most important
Aristotle scholars of this tradition. His works formed the basis of Jesuit teaching in logic until the end of the
1600s.
Only two copies in libraries world-wide (Berlin, Gotha) (and likewise only two of the first, 1575-edition). Not
in Adams, which only has the 1581, 1582, 1583, and 1594 editions.
114
Section II
115
116
117
This classic of Renaissance historiography is of the greatest importance to the development of the history of
the Renaissance and of history of art and culture in general. More specifically, Burckhardt here establishes the
fact that the Renaissance came first in developing the human individuality to the highest degree. He places
the earliest signs of the modern European Spirit in Florence, which was a great contributing factor to the
comprehension of this city as representing one of the highlights of European culture.
The Swiss historian of art and culture, Jacob Chrisoph Burckhardt (18181897), contributed seminally to
the historiography of these two fields. He is considered the discoverer of the Renaissance, and with his main
work he founded the study of thirteenth- to fifteenth-century Italy and thereby the historical study of the
Renaissance, the society of which he dealt with all aspects of.
In general, Burckhardts works all constitute an original historical approach to the study of art, culture, social
institutions etc.
As a highly respected scholar of Greek civilization, Burckhardt, with his original historiographical approach,
was highly admired by Nietzsche, who also attended his lectures. The two kept in contact and corresponded
frequently. Like Nietzsche, Burckhardt was a great admirer of Schopenhauer, and he greatly opposed the
Hegelian interpretations of history.
as in the case of other great historians such as Gibbon, Ranke, Macaulay, no criticism of details can detract
from the powerful spell which Burckhardts book has exercised upon such widely different writers as Ruskin,
Nietzsche and Gobineau, as well as upon innumerable lovers of the most magnificent period of European
history. (PMM).
Printing and the Mind of Man 347.
118
119
his fundamental insight, at that time completely novel, that in the Renaissance a new, dynamical Weltgefhl
emerges, a feeling which gave rise to a new systematic and uniform Philosophy of the individual. Cassirer
understands the Humanism of the Renaissance as a Humanism of Individuality, thus implicitly pointing to the
contextual dependence of the Renaissance on Enlightenment. The work is a cornerstone of Renaissance history
and is fundamental to students of the history of science and philosophy, political theory, and the history of
Reformation and Renaissance thought as such. Cassirers Individuum und Kosmos [s]hould be widely
used by students of the various literature of political theory. (John Herman Randall, Jr.).
This provocative volume, one of the most important interpretive works on the philosophical thought of the
Renaissance, has long been regarded as a classic in its field. Ernst Cassirer here examines the changes brewing
in the early stages of the Renaissance, tracing the interdependence of philosophy, language, art, and science;
the newfound recognition of individual consciousness; and the great thinkers of the periodfrom da Vinci
and Galileo to Pico della Mirandola and Giordano Bruno. The Individual and the Cosmos in Renaissance
Philosophy discusses the importance of fifteenth-century philosopher Nicholas Cusanus, the concepts of
freedom and necessity, and the subject-object problem in Renaissance thought. This fluent translation of a
scholarly and penetrating original leaves little impression of an attempt to show that a spirit of the age or
spiritual essence of the time unifies and expresses itself in all aspects of society or culture. (review of the
University of Chicago-edition of 2010).
120
HEIDEGGER ON HUMANISM
HEIDEGGER, MARTIN
ber den Humanismus.
Frankfurt am Main, Klostermann, (1949). 8vo. Original printed wrappers. Nice and clean copy. 47,
(1) pp.
DKK 750.00 / EURO 100.00
First separate edition of Heideggers important work on Humanism, expounding his controversial thoughts
on Humanism in general and Humanism as viewed in the Renaissance. The question posed is that of what
man is seen from a humanistic point of view.
The work was originally published in Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit and later in Wegmarken (1967).
Die vorliegene Schrift ist der fr die Verffentlichung durchgesehene und an einigen Stellen erweiterte text
eines Briefes, der im Herbst 1946 an Jean Beaufret (Paris) geschrieben wurde. (Verso of title-page).
The work is written in the form of a letter, answering Beaufrets question: How is it possible to ascribe meaning
to the word Humanism? Heideggers answer gives us the essence of his late philosophy. He wishes to show
that humanism itself is the cause of the problem that it considers itself the solution to.
121
122
and creating a new epoch, re-inventing and re-using the classical Greek and Roman values. Once again they
gave birth to the humanistic arts, literature, philosophy, painting, sculpting, etc. It is not a new invention of
later times to view this historical epoch as something new and still something different, something worthy
of the term Re-birth, acknowledging both the source from which inspiration was drawn as well as the
achievements of the new era.
Thus, Michelet is not the first to understand what went on in this period, but still he changed our concept of
it for everhe invented the term which has not only determined this perioed ever since, but which has also
been used to explain and understand all that went on in this most crucial period for modern man. It is in the
present work by Michelet that he uses for the first time the noun Renaissance for this epoch and lets it refer to
the discovery of world and of man in the 16th century. He not only lets the term refer to the artistic or scholarly
part of the period, he lets it refer to the entire complex of changes that were taking place in this period, and he
thus gives birth to the period as that of the mind and spirit of man, instead of just that of painting and learning.
Michelets work appeared at a time that allowed for it to exercise the greatest of influence. From the end of the
16th century until the middle of the 18th century, the history of the Renaissance was a field that barely existed.
Only with Voltaire was some focus put on this period that we ever since Michelet have called the Renaissance.
Only with Michelet are we given the vocabulary to sum up this period and to describe it properly and in detail.
When he publishes his work in 1855, historians and thinkers are ready to view this period as something in
itself and as something worth noticing. That which Michelet thus began is that which Burchardt takes up in
his Cultur der Renaissance in Italien (1860), in which Renaissance is finally characterized as the birth
of modern humanity. Both Michelet and Burckhardt believed that modern, secular man is a product of the
Renaissance.
The terms restauratio or resttitutio had been applied by fourteenth-century Italian humanists to the
revival of ancient languages and literatures, that of rinascita by Ghiberti and Vasari to the new blossoming
art and architecture. In the eighteenth century Voltaire and Gibbon first saw the Italian civilization of the
fourteenth to sixteenth centuries as an entity and as a determining factor in the whole course of European
history. Michelet (324) in 1855 first used the term renaissance for this period as an historical epoch in its own
right. Burckhardt, an admirer of both Voltaire and Gibbon, supplied the final synthesis. (Printing and the
Mind of Man, p. 211)
123
COINING HUMANISM
NIETHAMMER, F.I.
Der Streit des Philanthropinismus und Humanismus in der Theorie des ErziehungsUnterrichts unsrer Zeit.
Jena, Frommann, 1808. 8vo. Contemporary (original?) blue full paper binding with blindstamped
title-lable to spine. Occasional light brownspotting throughout. All in all a very nice and fine copy.
(6), 359, (1) pp.
DKK 9,500.00 / EURO 1,300.00
Scarce first edition of Niethammers seminal work, in which he introduces the term humanism for a
systematically worked out body of thought with its own value structure and becomes the first to apply the
word within a conceptual framework, thus profoundly influencing all later research on the humanistic period.
The term Humanismus was coined in 1808 by the German educator, F.J. Niethammer, to express the
emphasis on the Greek and Latin classics in secondary education as against the rising demands for a more
practical and more scientific training. In this sense, the word was applied by many historians of the nineteenth
century to the scholars of the Renaissance, who had also advocated and established the central role of the
classics in the curriculum (Kristeller, Renaissance Thought and its Sources, pp. 21-22).
Niethammers work not only came to determine how we have come to talk of the Renaissance and that
essential part of it which we now call humanism, it also illustrates how scholars framed the essential values
embodied in humanism at the time. It furthermore anticipated the 19th century age of -isms and ideology
and the attempts at developing more structured and systematic ways of organizing theories and ideas with the
purpose of influencing society and its culture.
124
125
Paduan Averroism (16th century) in this work meant that Renaissance philosophy was finally given a role
of its own in the history of philosophy,it is with this work that the philosophy of the Renaissance is taken
seriously in the study of philosophy.
Memoirs on semitic languages and on the study of Greek in the Middle Ages were crowned by the Acadmie
in 1848 and 1849 but do not seem to have been published. Renans first book, published in 1852, was, in
fact, Averroes et lAverrosme (see 24) which earned him a doctorate of letters. (PMM 352). Renan has
always been admired for his sharp mind, his great abilities and courage, but for the same reasons he was
feared by many. Ds 1852 il signalait dans la prface de son Averros comme le trait caractristique du dixneuvime sicle la substitution de la mthode historique dans toutes les tudes relatives lesprit humain.
Cette substitution est lgitime; mais elle serait dangereuse si elle allait jusqu proscrire la thologie et la
mtaphysique (N.B.G. (1862) 51:984).
Ernest Renan (18231892) was a French philologist, philosopher and historian. His father died when he was
aged five, and his mother wanted him to become a priest. Until he was about 16 years old, he was trained
by the Church, but due to his investigative and truth-seeking nature as well as his studies (e.g. Hebrew), he
was in doubt as to the historical truth of the Scriptures, and with the help of his sister he chose his own path
in life. He studied intensively the languages of the Bible and filled a number of minor academic positions,
frequently encountering difficulties because of the heterodoxy and outspokenness of his religious opinions.
(Printing and the Mind of Man 352). In 1840 he began studying philosophy and later philology, in 1847 he took
his degree as Agrg de Philosophie and became master at the Lyce of Vendome. After having returned from
a mission to Italy in the year 1850 where he gathered material for his historical-philosophical masterpiece,
Averros et lAverroisme, he was offered employment at the Bibliothque Nationale (at the manuscript
department). In 1861 he was chosen to become professor of Hebrew at the Collge de France, but because the
emperor refused to ratify the appointment (inspired by the Clerical party), he was not established in the chair
untill 1870. In 1878 he was elected for the Academy. Renan is considered a scolar of the greatest excellence and
an impressive writer.
126
Reference Works
Adams, H.M. (Comp.). Catalogue of Books Printed on the Continent of Europe , 1501-1600 in Cambridge Libraries.
1967.
Baumgartner, Leona and John F. Fulton. A Bibliography of the Poem Syphilis sive Morbus Gallicus by Girolamo
Fracastoro of Verona. New Haven, Yale University Press, 1935.
Bochner, Salomon. The role of mathematics in the rise of science. Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1966.
Bonola: Non-Euclidean Geometry. A Critical and Historical Study of its Development. H. S. Carslaw. New
York, Dover Publications, 1955 (1908).
Boulting, William. Giordano Bruno. His Life, Thought, and Martyrdom. London, K. Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1914.
British Encyclopaedia. www-version.
Brunet, Jacques-Charles. Manuel du Libraire et de lamateur de livres. Copenhague, Rosenkilde et Bagger, 1966
(1860).
Bryce, Judith: Cosimo Bartoli (1503-1572): The Career of a Florentine Polymath), Genve, Librairie Droz,
1983.
Cajori, Florian. A History of Mathematics. New York, Macmillan, 1901.
Cambridge Companion to Economic Thought. on-line-version.
Canney, Margaret and David Knott. Catalogue of the Goldsmiths Library of Economic Literature. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1970.
Caroti, Stefano, Melanchtons Astrology, in: Paolo Zambelli edt., Astrologi hallucinati Stars and the End of the
World in Luthers Time. Berlin, Walter de Gruyter, 1986.
Carter, John & Percy H. Muir. Printing and the Mind of Man. (PMM). Mnchen, Karl Pressler, 1983 (1967).
Cassirer, Ernst. An Essay on Man. An Introduction to a Philosophy of Human Culture. New Haven, Yale University
Press, 1944.
Cassirer, Ernst. Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit. Berlin, B. Cassirer,
1922.
Cassirer, Ernst. Individuum und Kosmos in der Philosophie der Renaissance. Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche
Gesellschaft, 1969 (1927).
Cassirer, Ernst. The Problem of Knowledge. Philosophy, Science, and History Since Hegel.Translated by William H.
Woglom and Charles W. Hendel. New Haven & London, Yale University Press, 1969 (1950).
Cassirer, Ernst; Paul Oskar Kristeller; John Herman Randall (Edts.). The Renaissance Philosophy of Man. Chicago,
University of Chicago Press, 1956 (1948).
Catlin, Sir George Edward Gordon. A History of the Political Philosophers. London, George Allen and Unwin,
1950 (1939).
Chasles, Michel. Aperu historique sur lorigine et le dveloppement des mthodes en gomtrie. Paris, GauthierVillars et fils, 1883 (1837).
Chreau, Achille: Le Parnasse medical francais. Paris, A. Delahaye, 1874.
Clanton, Dan W. The Good the Bold, and the Beautiful: The Story of Susanna and its Reniassance Interpretations. New
York, T & T Clark, 2006.
Copenhaver, Brian P. and Charles B. Schmitt. Renaissance Philosophy. Oxford & New York, Oxford University
Press, 1992.
Cranz, F. Edward and Charles B. Schmitt. A Bibliography of Aristotle Editions 1501-1600. (Cranz-Schmitt). BadenBaden, Valentin Krner, 1984.
Dibdin, Thomas Frognall. An Introduction to the Knowledge of Rare and Valuable Editions of the Greek and Latin
Classics. New York, Georg Olms Verlag, 1977 (1827).
127
Nussbaum, Arthur. A Note on the Idea of World Money, in: Political Science Quarterly (PSQ). on-line-version.
Parente, James A. Religious Drama and the Humanist Tradition. Leiden & New York, E.J. Brill, 1987.
Parker, Deborah: Bernardino Daniello and the Commentary Tradition, in: Dante Studies, No. 106, 1988. online-version.
Paterson, Antoinette Mann. The Infinite Worlds of Giordano Bruno. Springfield, Charles C. Thomas, 1970.
Pine, Martin L. Pietro Pomponazzi: Radical Philosoper of the Renaissance. Padova, Editrice Antenore, 1986.
Popkin, Richard. The History of Scepticism. From Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford & New York, Oxford University
Press, 2003.
Pozzo, Riccardo. The Impact of Aristotelianism on Modern Philosophy. Washington, D.C., Catholic University of
America Press, 2004.
Price, Paola Malpezzi. Moderata Fonte: Women and Life in Sixteenth Century Venice. Cranbury, NJ, Rosemont
Publishing & Printing Corp., 2003.
Renan, Ernst. Averroes et lAverrosme. Essai historique. Paris, Durand, 1852
Riccardi, Pietro. Saggio di una Bibliografia Euclidea. Hildesheim & New York, Georg Olms, 1887-93.
Ross, W.D. (Edt.). Aristotles Prior and Posterior Analytics. A revised Text with Introduction and Commentary.
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2001 (1949).
Ross, W.D. (Edt.). The Works of Aristotle Translated into English. Volume I. London, Oxford University Press, 1950
(1928).
Rowland, Ingrid D. Girodano Bruno. Philosopher/Heretic. New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2008.
Saintsbury George. The Earlier Renaissance. Edinburgh, London, W. Blackwood and Sons, 1901.
Salvestrini, Virgilio. Bibliografia di Giordano Bruno. Firenze, Sansoni Antiquariato, 1958.
Sandys, Sir John Edwin. A History of classical scholarship. Masnsfield Centre, Martino Publishing, 2003 (1903).
Schill, Adolf. Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola und die Entdeckung Amerikas. Berlin, Martin Breslauer, 1929.
Schmitt, Charles B. Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola (1469-1533) and his critique of Aristotle. The Hague,
Martinus Nijhoff, 1967.
Smith, (David Eugene). Rara Arithmetica. Boston & London, Ginn and Company, 1908.
Sparrow, Ruth A. Milestones of Science. Buffalo & New York, Buffalo Society of Natural Sciences, 1972.
Spinazzola, Dora Franceschi (edt.). Catalogo della Biblioteca di Luigi Einaudi. Torino, Fondazione Luigi Einaudi,
1981.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP). on-line-version
Steck, Max. Bibliographia Euclideana. Hildesheim, Gerstenberg Verlag, 1981.
Stillwell, Margaret Bingham. The Awakening Interest in Science during the First Century of Printing 1450-1550.
New York, Bibliographical Society of America, 1970.
Taleb, Nassim Nicholas. The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable. New York, Random House, 2007.
The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy
Thomas-Stanford, Charles. Early Editions of Euclids Elements. San Francisco, Alan Wofsy Fine Arts, 1977.
Thorndike, Linn. A History of Magic and Experimental Science. New York & London, Columbia University Press,
1923.
Tremolada, Carlo (Edt.). Catalogo della Biblioteca [di Raffaele Mattioli] (Mattioli). Milano, Fondazione Raffaele
Mattioli, 1906.
Watt, J.A. Spiritual and Temporal Powers, in: The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c. 350-1450. Edt.
By J.H. Burns. Cambridge & New York, Cambridge Uinversity Press, 1988.
[Wellcome]. A Catalogue of Printed Books in the Wellcome Historical Library. New York, Martino Publishing, 1996.
Wolf, A. A History of Science, Technology and Philosophy in the 16th and 17th Centuries. New York, Harper &
Brothers, 1959 (1950).
Wood, Casey A. An Introduction to the Literature of Vertebrate Zoology. London, Oxford University Press, 1931.
Yates, Frances Amelia. The Occult Philosophy in the Elizabethan Age. London & Boston, Routledge, 1979.
Zanr, Domenico. Cultural Non-Conformity in Early Modern Florence. Burlington, Ashgate, 2004.
129
History
Founded in 1821 by Christian Tnder Sbye, HermanH.J.Lynge&Sn is the
oldest antiquarian book shop in Scandinavia. Herman Henrik Julius Lynge was
a co-worker in the Sbyeske Boghandling, and when Sbye died in 1844,
Lynge became the manager. In 1853 he could finally afford to buy the book shop
himself, and he changed the name to H.H.J.Lynge (Sbyeske Boghandling).
A couple of years later, he changed the name again, to Herman H.J.Lynges
Boghandel, and when his son became his official partner in 1892, the book
shop was given the name that it still bears today, HermanH.J.Lynge&Sn.
As the first and greatest international antiquarian book shop in Scandinavia,
HermanH.J.Lynge (& Sn) has always played a great role in the antiquarian book
trade. The old book shop has always been situated at the heart of Copenhagen, as
it still is today. (For more details see the Wikipedia entry for HermanH.J.Lynge).
As international scientific booksellers, a large number of important collections have
been handled and sold by us throughout the years. Among these collections are several
of internationally known Danes, e.g: Sren Kierkegaard (Philosopy), J.J.A.Worsaae
(Archaeology), Otto Jespersen (Philology/Linguistics), Alf Ross (Law), Jon Helgason
(Old Norse).
Please visit our web-site, where you can search and browse more than 20.000 books:
www.lynge.com