Sperber Wilson Relevance 1996 PDF
Sperber Wilson Relevance 1996 PDF
Sperber Wilson Relevance 1996 PDF
DEIRDRE WILS0N'
I]
BLACI<WELL
Oxford UK &- Cambridge USA
Contents
1 Communication
The code model and the semiotic approach to communication
Decoding and inference in verbal comprehension
The mutual-knowledge hypothesis
Grice's approach to 'meaning' and communication
Should the code model and the inferential model be amalgamated?
Problems of definition
Problems of explanation: Grice's theory of conversation
Cognitive environments and mutual manifestness
Relevance and ostension
Ostensive-inferential communication
11 The informative intention
12 The communicative intention
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
2 Inference
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
3 Relevance
1 Conditions for relevance
2 Degrees of relevance: effect and effort
3 Is the context given or chosen?
vu
IX
1
3
9
15
21
24
28
31
38
46
50
54
60
65
65
71
75
83
93
103
108
118
118
123
132
Contents
VI
4
5
6
7
8
A choice of contexts
Relevance to an individual
The relevance of phenomena and stimuli
The principle of relevance
How relevance theory explains ostensive-inferential
communication
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
137
142
151
155
163
172
172
176
183
193
202
217
224
231
237
243
Postface
255
281
293
Notes to Postface
295
Bibliography
299
Index
321
In this book, first published nine years ago, we present a new approach
to the study of human communication. This approach (outlined in
chapter 1) is grounded in a general view of human cognition (developed
in chapters 2 and 3). Human cognitive processes, we argue, are geared
to achieving the greatest possible cognitive effect for the smallest possible
processing effort. To achieve this, individuals must focus their attention
on what seems to them to be the most relevant information available.
To communicate is to claim an individual's attention: hence to communicate is to imply that the information communicated is relevant. This
fundamental idea (developed in chapter 3), that communicated information comes with a guarantee of relevance, is what in the First Edition
we called the principle of relevance and what we would now call the
Second, or Communicative Principle of Relevance (see the Postface to
this Second Edition). We argue that this principle of relevance is essential
to explaining human communication, and show (in chapter 4) how it is
enough on its own to account for the interaction of linguistic meaning
and contextual factors in utterance interpretation.
Here is how this book came about. In 1975, Deirdre Wilson published
Presuppositions and Non-Truth-Conditional Semantics and Dan Sperber
published 'Rudiments de rhetorique cognitive', a sequel to his Rethinking Symbolism. In these works, we were both turning to pragmatics the study of contextual factors in verbal communication - but from
different perspectives: Deirdre Wilson was showing how a number of
apparently semantic problems could be better solved at a pragmatic
level; Dan Sperber was arguing for a view of figures of speech rooted in
pragmatics. We then formed the project of writing, in a few months, a
joint essay which would cover, at least programmatically, the ground
between our two vantage points and show the continuities and discontinUlt1es between semantics, pragmatics and rhetoric. Work did not
proceed according to plan. We got involved in carrying out the
VUl
List of symbols
P, Q
U
A
C
I
P
1,2
a, b
individual assumptions
an utterance
a set of assumptions made manifest by an utterance
a set of contextual assumptions
a set of assumptions the communicator intended to make manifest
a set of newly presented assumptions
notes to First Edition
notes to Second Edition
1
Communication
Communication
The code model and the inferential model are not incompatible; they
can be combined in various ways. The work of pragmatists, philosophers
of language and psycholinguists over the past twenty years has shown that
verbal communication involves both coding and inferential processes.
Thus both the code model and the inferential model can contribute to the
study of verbal communication. However, it is usually assumed that one
of the two models must provide the right overall framework for the study
of communication in general. Most authors take for granted that a proper
theory of communication should be based on the familiar code model; a
few philosophers seem tempted to develop the inferential model into an
inferential theory of communication.
Against these reductionist views, we maintain that communication can
be achieved in ways which are as different from one another as walking is
from plane flight. In particular, communication can be achieved by coding
and decoding messages, and it can be achieved by providing evidence for
an intended inference. The code model and the inferential model are each
adequate to a different mode of communication; hence upgrading either to
the status of a general theory of communication is a mistake. Both coded
communication and inferential communication are subject to general
constraints which apply to all forms of information processing, but these
are too general to constitute a theory of communication either.
Some modes of locomotion involve the interaction of quite different
mechanisms: bicycle riding, for instance, involves both physiology and
engineering. Similarly, verbal communication involves both code and
inferential mechanisms. In trying to construct an adequate description of
these two types of mechanism and their interaction, it is important to
realise that they are intrinsically independent of one another, and that
communication in general is independent of either.
In sections 1 to 3 of this chapter we will discuss the code theory, and in
sections 4 to 7, the inferential theory. In discussing the views of code and
inferential theorists, our aim is to contrast two extreme approaches so as to
map out the full range of available choices; it is not to do justice to those
who have defended subtly qualified, or cautiously vague, versions of
either. In sections 8 to 12 of this chapter and in chapters 2 and 3, we will
propose what we hope is an improved inferential model. However, we do
not regard this model as the basis for a general theory of communication.
In chapter 4, we will show instead how it can be combined with a code
model to provide an explanatory account of verbal communication.
1 The code model and the semiotic approach to communication
A code, as we will use the term, is a system which pairs messages with
signals, enabling two information-processing devices (organisms or
Communication
received
signal
I
I
nOIse
Figure 1
This diagram shows how a message originating in an information source
can be duplicated at a destination as the result of a communication process.
For instance, the source and the destination could be telecommunications
employees, the encoder and the decoder telex machines, the channel an
electric wire, the message a text, i.e. a series of letters, and the signal a series
of electrical impulses. The message is typed by the source on the encoder's
keyboard. The encoder contains a code which associates each letter to a
distinct pattern of electrical impulses. The encoder sends these impulses
through the channel to the decoder. The decoder contains a duplicate of
the encoder's code, and uses it to deliver to the destination the series of
letters and signs associated by the code to the electrical impulses it has
received.
Communication is achieved by encoding a message, which cannot
travel, into a signal, which can, and by decoding this signal at the receiving
end. Noise along the channel (electrical disturbances in our example) can
destroy or distort the signal. Otherwise, as long as the devices are in order
and the codes are identical at both ends, successful communication is
guaranteed.
In this example, the communicating devices are neither the telecommunications employees nor the telex machines but the man-machine pairs
5
on both sides. This apparent complication is, in fact, illuminating. It
shows what the relevant internal structure of any device capable of coded
communication would have to be. Consider the case of honey bees. Von
Frisch (1967) has shown that bees can encode into flight patterns (their
'dance') what they have learnt about the location of nectar, so that other
bees can decode the information and find the nectar in their turn. To
account for this communicative ability, bees must be seen as containing
two information-processing sub-devices: a memory (which constitutes
the 'source' on the one side and the 'destination' on the other) in which
plans for flying to~ards a. supp.ly of nectar can. b.e store~, and an
encoder-decoder devIce whlCh paIrs messages conslstmg of flIght plans
with signals consisting of dances.
It may seem that a similar model could be proposed for human. verbal
communication, as shown in figure 2:
thought
~---.
I ,------,
central
I
thought
linguistic
encoder
processes
received
acoustic
signal
acoustic
signal
f--f---+I
air
SPEAKER
I
I
I
received
thought
I
~--~I~--~
I central
thought
processes
HEARER
nOIse
Figure 2
Here the source and the destination are central thought processes, the
encoder and the decoder are linguistic abilities, the message is a thought,
and the channel is air which carries an acoustic signal. There are two
assumptions underlying this proposal: the first is that human languages,
such as Swahili or English, are codes; the second is that these codes
associate thoughts to sounds.
While Shannon and Weaver's diagram is inspired by telecommunications technology, the basic idea is quite old, and was originally proposed
as an account of verbal communication. To give just two examples:
Aristotle claimed that 'spoken sounds are symbols of affections in the
soul', which are themselves 'likenesses of actual things' (Aristotle, De
Interpretatione: 43). In our terms, he claimed that utterances encode
assumptions. Arnauld and Lancelot in their famous Grammaire de
Port-Royal describe language as
Communication
the marvellous invention of composing out of 25 or 30 sounds that
infinite variety of words, which tho' they have no natural resemblance to the operations of the mind, are yet the means of unfolding
all its secrets, and of disclosing unto those, who cannot see into our
hearts, the variety of our thoughts, and our sentiments upon all
manner of subjects.
Words therefore may be defined, distinct and articulate sounds,
made use of by men as signs, to express their thoughts. (Arnauld and
Lancelot, Grammaire de Port-Royal: 22)
Communication
alone applied to linguistics. After the publication in 1957 of Noam
Chomsky's Syntactic Structures, linguistics took a new turn and did
undergo remarkable developments;4 but these owed nothing to semiotics.
As the structure of language became better understood, its sui generis
nature became more and more striking. The assumption that all systems of
signs should have similar structural properties became more and more
untenable. Without this assumption, however, the semiotic programme
makes little sense.
.
Saussure made a further prediction:
8
We will try to show that this line of argument is invalid. It is true that a
language is a code which pairs phonetic and semantic representations of
sentences. However, there is a gap between the semantic representations
of sentences and the thoughts actually communicated by utterances. This
gap is filled not by more coding, but by inference. Moreover, there is an
alternative to the code model of communication. Communication has
been described as a process of inferential recognition of the communicator's intentions. We will try to show how this description can be improved
and made explanatory.5
10
Communication
12
Communication
provided by the grammar. Much recent work in pragmatics has assumed,
largely without question, that this can be done. Pragmatics has been
treated, on the analogy of phonology, syntax and semantics, as a code-like
mental device, underlying a distinct level of linguistic ability. It is widely
accepted that there are rules of pragmatic interpretation much as there are
rules of semantic interpretation, and that these rules form a system which
is a supplement to a grammar as traditionally understood.
There are certainly pragmatic phenomena which lend themselves to this
sort of approach. For example, a pragmatic device might contain rules of
interpretation such as (8) and (9):
(8) Substitute for 'I' a reference to the speaker.
(9) Substitute for 'tomorrow' a reference to the day after the utterance.
Imagine a hearer equipped with such rules and able to recognise that the
speaker of (1) is Ann and the date of utterance is 30 November. He could
automatically interpret utterance (1) as conveying the thought in (10):
(1) I'll come tomorrow.
(10) Ann will come on 1 December.
13
premises. A decoding pr?ces~ starts. from a sigr;tal and results in the
recovery of a message whICh IS assocIated to the sIgnal by an underlying
code. In general, conclusions are not associated to their premises by a
code, and signals do not warrant the messages they convey.
To illustrate the difference between coding and inferential processes,
consider (13)-(15):
(13) (a) Either Mary is early or Bob is late.
(b) Bob is never late.
(14) [m;;)ri: IZ3 :li:]
(15) Mary is early.
That Mary is early, i.e. (15), can be either inferred from the premises in
(13) or decoded from the phonetic signal in (14), but the converse is not
true: (15) can be neither decoded from (13) nor inferred from (14). It
cannot be decoded from (13) because there is no code identifying (13) as a
signal and (15) as its associated message. It cannot be inferred from (14)
because signals do not by themselves warrant the messages they encode
(otherwise any absurdity could be transformed into a warranted assumption merely by uttering it).
The view that utterance interpretation is a largely inferential process
squares well with ordinary experience. Consider (16)-(18), for instance:
(16) Jones has bought the Times.
(17) Jones has bought a copy of the Times.
(18) Jones has bought the press enterprise which publishes the Times.
14
Communication
They can use the standard inference rule (21) as a decoding rule, treat
utterances (22) and (23) as signals, and thus convey by use of these signals
messages (24) and (25) respectively:
15
16
Communication
eses or religious beliefs, anecdotal memories, general cultural assump~ions, beliefs about the mental state of the speaker, may all play a, role in
mterpretation.
While it is clear that members of the same linguistic community
converge on the same language, and plausible that they converge on the
same inferential abilities, the same is not true of their assumptions about
the world. True, all humans are constrained by their species-specific
cognitive abilities in developing their representation of the world, and all
members of the same cultural group share a number of experiences,
teachings and views. However, beyond this common framework, individuals tend to be highly idiosyncratic. Differences in life history
necessarily lead to differences in memorised information. Moreover, it has
been repeatedly shown that two people witnessing the same event - even a
salient and highly memorable event like a car accident - may construct
dramatically different representations of it, disagreeing not just on their
interpretation of it, but in their memory of the basic physical facts. 8 While
grammars neutralise the differences between dissimilar experiences,
cognition and memory superimpose differences even on common experiences.
Grammars and inferential abilities stabilise after a learning period and
remain unchanged from one utterance or inference to the next. By
contrast, each new experience adds to the range of potential contexts. It
does so crucially in utterance interpretation, since the context used in
interpreting a given utterance generally contains information derived
from immediately preceding utterances. Each new utterance, while
drawing on the same grammar and the same inferential abilities as previous
utterances, requires a rather different context. A central problem for
pragmatic theory is to describe how, for any given utterance, the hearer
finds a context which enables him to understand it adequately.
A speaker who intends an utterance to be interpreted in a particular way
must also expect the hearer to be able to supply a context which allows that
interpretation to be recovered. A mismatch between the context envisaged
by the speaker and the one actually used by the hearer may result in a
misunderstanding. Suppose, for example, that the speaker of (7) wants to
stay awake, and therefore wants to accept his host's offer of coffee,
whereas the host assumes that the speaker does not want to stay awake,
and thus interprets (7) as a refusal:
(7) Coffee would keep me awake.
Clearly, this difference between actual and envisaged contexts will lead to
a misunderstanding. Of course such misunderstandings do occur. They
are not attributable to noise in the acoustic channel. The question is
whether they happen because the mechanisms of verbal communication
17
18
Communication
19
Communication
certain, or else it does not exist; and since it can never be certain it can
never eXIst.
The apparent fallback position for the code theorist would be to replace
the requirement of mutual knowledge by that of mutual probabilistic
assumptions. This more realistic proposal raises an obvious problem. In
general, the higher the order of the assumptions involved in such a scheme,
the less likely they are to be true. Bob may know for a fact that Monkey
Business is the film playing tonight; in the absence of compelling evidence,
he should feel less certain that Ann assumes that he knows it, and even less
certain that she assumes that he assumes that she assumes that he knows it,
and so on. The assumption of mutuality itself, which is the highest ordered
one, will have the weakest probability. How, then, could restricting the
context to mutual assumptions ensure the identity or near-identity of
premises which the code model requires?
Another problem with the mutual-knowledge hypothesis is that even if
it defines a class of potential contexts for use in utterance interpretation, it
says nothing about how an actual context is selected, nor about the role of
context in comprehension. Take the following utterance:
20
21
This analysis can be developed in two ways. Grice himself used it as the
point of departure for a theory of 'meaning', trying to go from the analysis
of 'speaker's meaning' towards such traditional semantic concerns as the
analysis of 'sentence meaning' and 'word meaning'. For reasons which
should become apparent, we doubt that very much can be achieved in this
direction. However, Grice's analysis can also be used as the point of
departure for an inferential model of communication, and this is how we
propose to take it. In the rest of this section we will show how this analysis
applies to the description of communication. In the next three sections we
will consider some of the objections and reformulations which have been
proposed. Finally, in the last five sections of this chapter, we will develop
our own model.
There are situations in which the mere fact that an intention is
recognised may lead to its fulfilment. Suppose that Mary intends to please
22
Communication
Peter. If Peter becomes aware of her intention to please him, this may in
itself be enough to please him. Similarly, when the inmates of a prison
recognise their warder's intention to make them fear him, this may be
enough in itself to make them fear him. There is one type of intention for
which this possibility, rather than being exceptional, is regularly exploited: intentions to inform are quite generally fulfilled by being made
recognisable.
Suppose that Mary intends to inform Peter of the fact that she has a sore
throat. All she has to do is let him hear her hoarse voice, thus providing
him with salient and conclusive evidence that she has a sore throat. Here,
Mary's intention can be fulfilled whether or not Peter is aware of it: he
could realise that she has a sore throat without also realising that she
intends him to realise that she has one. Suppose now that Mary intends, on
2 June, to inform Peter (truly or falsely) that she had a sore throat on the
previous Christmas Eve. This time she is unlikely to be able to produce
direct evidence of her past sore throat. What she can do, though, is give
him direct evidence, not of her past sore throat, but of her present
intention to inform him of it. How can she do this, and what good will it
do? One way she can do it is by uttering (28), and the good it will do is to
give Peter indirect, but nevertheless strong, evidence that she had a sore
throat on the previous Christmas Eve:
(28) I had a sore throat on Christmas Eve.
In our first example, Mary's hoarse voice is most likely to have been
caused by her sore throat. The fact that she has spoken hoarsely is thus
direct evidence for the assumption that she has a sore throat. Mary's
utterance of (28) on 2 June is not directly caused by her having had a sore
throat on the previous Christmas Eve. Hence her utterance is not direct
evidence for the assumption that she had a sore throat on the previous
Christmas Eve. However, her utterance is directly caused by her present
intentions. Although she might have had various intentions in uttering
(28), it is most likely that she intended to inform Peter that she had a sore
throat on the previous Christmas Eve. This makes Mary's utterance direct
evidence of her present intention to inform Peter of her past sore throat.
Suppose now that Peter assumes that Mary is sincere and is likely to
know whether or not she had a sore throat on the previous Christmas Eve.
Then for Peter, the fact that Mary intends to inform him that she had a sore
throat on that date provides conclusive evidence that she had. In these
quite ordinary conditions, Mary's intention to inform Peter of her past
sore throat can be fulfilled by making Peter recognise her intention. This is
not an exceptional way of fulfilling an intention to inform an audience. Let
us assume that it is precisely how Mary intends to have her intention
23
fulfilled. Then she does have all three sub-intentions of the GriceStraws on definition (27), as shown in (29):
(29) Mary intends
(a) her utterance (28) to produce in Peter the belief that she had a sore
throat the previous Christmas Eve;
(b) Peter to recognize her intention (a);
(c) Peter's recognition of her intention (a) to function as at least part
of his reason for his belief.
24
Communication
cognition and interaction. Humans typically conceptualise human and
animal behaviour, not in terms of its physical features, but in terms of its
underlying intentions. For instance, an ordinary-language concept such as
give, take, attack or defend applies to various forms of behaviour which
do not fall under any characteristic physical description, and have in
common only the kind of intention which governs them. Human
interaction is largely determined by the conceptualisation of behaviour in
intentional rather than physical terms. The idea that communication
exploits this ability of humans to attribute intentions to each other should
be quite intelligible, and even appealing, to cognitive and social psychologists.
So it seems that we all know - semioticians included - that communication involves the publication and recognition of intentions. Yet until
Grice, the significance of this truism was generally ignored;12 attempts to
describe and explain communication continued to be based on one form
or another of the code model. Grice's original idea, as presented in his
1957 paper, can thus be seen as an attempt to rehabilitate a commonsense
view of communication and spell it out in theoretically acceptable terms.
However, the elaboration of this idea in the work of Grice himself,
Strawson, Searle, Schiffer and others has often taken the form of a move
away from common sense, away from psychological plausibility, and
back to the code model. This unfortunate development resulted from the
discovery of part spurious, part genuine problems with Grice's original
formulation.
5 Should the code model and the inferential model be amalgamated?
25
Grice's analysis. John Searle at least takes the trouble to justify this
reaction. i4 He claims that Grice's analysis
fails to account for the extent to which meaning can be a matter of
rules and conventions. This account of meaning does not show the
connection between one's meaning something by what one says, and
what that which one says actually means in the language. (Searlt;
1969: 43)
Searle wants to improve on Grice's account by showing the connection
between speaker's meaning and -linguistic meaning. His first step is to
restrict the application of this account to the domain of 'literal meaning'.
This he defines in terms of the speaker's intentions, including the intention
to have her intentions recognised, but adds a rider: the speaker should
intend the hearer to recognise her intentions 'in virtue of his knowledge of
the rules for the sentence uttered' (Searle 1969: 48). In other words, the
speaker should intend the hearer to understand her by decoding her
utterance.
This reduces Grice's analysis to a commonsense amendment of the code
model. The code model is reintroduced as the basic explanation of
communication, but in the case of human communication, the message
th~t is encoded and decoded is regarded as a communicator's intention. If
Searle's revision is justified, then Grice's analysis is not a genuine
alternative to the code model after all.
Grice's greatest originality was not to suggest that human communication involves the recognition of intentions. That much, as already pointed
out, is common sense. It was to suggest that this characterisation is
sufficient: as long as there is some way of recognising the communicator's
intentions, then communication is possible. Recognition of intentions is
an ordinary human cognitive endeavour. If Grice is right, the inferential
abilities that humans ordinarily use in attributing intentions to each other
should make communication possible even in the absence of a code. And
of course it is possible.
For example, Peter asks Mary,
(30) How are you feeling today?
Mary responds by pulling a bottle of aspirin out of her bag and showing it
to him. Her behaviour is not coded: there is no rule or convention which
says that displaying a bottle of aspirin means that one is not feeling well.
Similarly, her behaviour affords only the weakest kind of direct evidence
about her feelings: maybe she always carries a bottle of aspirin in her bag.
On the other hand, it is strong direct evidence of her intention to inform
26
Communication
Peter that she does not feel well. Because her behaviour enables Peter to
recognise her intention, Mary successfully communicates with him, and
does so without the use of any code. 15
Even Searle does not deny the existence of purely inferential communication. However, he insists that it is rare, and that most human
communication crucially involves the use of a language or code:
Some very simple sorts of illocutionary acts can indeed be performed
apart from any use of conventional devices at all, simply by getting
the audience to recognize certain of one's ip.tentions in behaving in a
certain way ... One can in certain special circumstances 'request'
someone to leave the room without employing any conventions, but
unless one has a language one cannot request of someone that he,
e.g., undertake a research project on the problem of diagnosing and
treating mononucleosis in undergraduates in American universities.
(Searle 1969: 38)
27
28
Communication
as a result, they can produce much subtler and stronger evidence about
their intentions than they could in the absence of a shared code. They are
unlikely, then, to go to the trouble of communicating inferentially
without these powerful tools, just as modern humans are unlikely to go to
the trouble of making fire without matches or lighters. Still, just as no one
would want to define fire as necessarily produced by the use of matches or
lighters, it would be unreasonable to define communication as necessarily
achieved by the use of codes.
The reduction of Grice's analysis to an amendment of the code model
destroys not just its originality, but also many of i~s empirical implications
and justifications. The elevation of the inferential model into a general
theory of communication ignores the diversity of forms of communication, and the psychological evidence that much decoding is noninferential (to be discussed in chapter 4).
6 Problems of definition
Most discussions of Grice's 1957 article have had to do with the definition
of 'meaning' or 'communication' and have been highly philosophical. In
this section, we will single out two genuinely empirical issues for
discussion. Our aim is simply to highlight these relevant issues, not to .
write a history or an evaluation of the surrounding debates.
Grice characterises 'meaning' in terms of a communicator's intentions.
Conversely, an act of communication (in an appropriately restricted sense
of the term) might be characterised as one that fulfils these Gricean
intentions. However, as Searle (1969: 46-8; 1971: 8-9) points out, a
communicator can mean something, and successfully communicate it,
without all these Gricean intentions being fulfilled. Recall Strawson's
reformulation (27) of Grice's analysis. To mean something by an utterance
x, an individual S must intend
(27) (a) S's utterance of x to produce a certain response r in a certain
audience A;
(b) A to recognise S's intention (a);
(c) A's recognition of S's intention (a) to function as at least part of A's
reason for A's response r.
Now it is easy to see that once intention (b) is fulfilled, the
communicator has succeeded in communicating what she meant, whether
or not intentions (a) and (c) are also fulfilled. For example, when Mary
utters (28), her specific intention (29a) is to produce in Peter the belief that
she had a sore throat on the previous Christmas Eve. Suppose Peter
recognises this intention, but does not believe Mary. Then only her
Problems of definition
29
intention (29b) is fulfilled; intentions (29a) and (29c) are not. Nonetheless,
although Mary has failed to convince Peter, she. has succeeded in
communicating to him what she meant.
Since communication can succeed without intention (27a) being
fulfilled, intention (27a) is not an intention to communicate at all. It is
better described as an intention to inform, or as we will call it, an
informative intentionY The. true communicative intention is intention
(27b): that is, the intention to have one's informative intention recognised.
What about intention (27c): that the recognition by the audience of the
communicator's intention (27a) shall function as at least part of the
audience's reason for fulfilling intention (27a)? By definition, intention
(27c) cannot be fulfilled when the informative intention (27a) is not. Since
the fulfilment of (27a) is not necessary for successful communication, the
fulfilment of (27c) cannot be necessary either. What Grice has convincingly shown is that the recognition of an informative intention can lead to its
fulfilment. Very often, it is because this possibility exists that the
communicator engages in communication at all. However to turn this
possibility into a definitional necessity requires some justification. For the
time being, we will drop intention (27c) from the characterisation of
inferential communication without further discussion, and re-examine
Grice's motivations on this point in section 10. 18
We are now almost ready to propose a modified version of Grice's
analysis, highlighting the difference between the informative and communicative intentions. However, we must first get rid of a confusing
terminological idiosyncrasy. Grice and Strawson use the term 'utterance'
to refer not just to linguistic utterances, or even to coded utterances, but to
any modification of the physical environment designed by a communicator to be perceived by an audience and used as evidence of the
communicator's intentions. This usage seems to us to introduce a bias into
the identification of communicative behaviour. It encourages the view
that utterances in the usual linguistic sense can be taken as the paradigm of
communicative behaviour in general. Psychologists use the term 'stimulus' for any modification of the physical environment designed to be
perceived. We will do the same. An utterance in the usual sense is, of
course, a special case of a stimulus. Let us say, then, that communication
involves producing a certain stimulus intending theFeby
(31) Informative intention: to inform the audience of something;
Communicative intention: to inform the audience of one's
informative intention.
Note that the communicative intention is itself a second-order informative intention: the communicative intention is fulfilled once the first-order
informative intention is recognised. In ordinary situations, if all goes well,
30
Communication
Problems of explanation
31
be constructed where the third-order meta-communicative intention is
present but hidden from the audience, and the resulting interaction lacks
the required overtness. Adding a fourth-order meta-meta-communicative
intention that the third-order meta-communicative intention should itself
be recognised by the audience may not be enough either: in principle, for
any nth-order intention of this type, you need an n+ lth-order intention
to the effect that the nth-order intention be recognised. In other words
you need an infinity of such intentions to explicate the intuitive notion of
overtness along those lines.
There are ways of making logical sense of an infinity of intentions, and
of analysing speaker's meaning or communication in terms of such an
infinityY But the results have little psychological plausibility. Fr?m the
psychological point of view, intentions are mental representations capable
of being realised in the form of actions. No psychologist would want to
analyse an utterance as the realisation of an infinity of intentions so
understood. 20
The intuitive idea that communicative intentions must be overt can be
worked out in another way, using the notion of mutual knowledge. This
solution, proposed by Schiffer (1972), essentially involves the assumption
that a true communicative intention is not just an intention to inform the
audience of the communicator's informative intention, but an intention to
make the informative intention mutually known to the communicator and
the audience. By this criterion, the counterexample of Mary trying to get
Peter to repair her hair-drier without openly asking him is not a case of
true communication. Although Mary wants Peter to recognise her
informative intention, she does not want this informative intention to
become mutually known to both of them. More complex examples built
on the same pattern would similarly be ruled out by this mutualknowledge requirement. 21
We have already argued (in section 3) that the appeal to 'mutual
knowledge' lacks psychological plausibility. Hence to rely on it in
explicating the notion of overtness is to turn one's back on psychology
once more. Thus, all the solutions to the overtness problem proposed so
far replace vagueness by one inadequate formalism or another. What we
believe is a satisfactory solution will be proposed in section 8 and
developed in section 12. In the meantime, we turn to further problems
with Grice's analysis, problems this time not of definition but of
explanation.
32
Communication
Problems of explanation
33
Maxims of quantity
1 Make your contribution as informative as is required (for the current
purposes of the exchange).
2 Do not make your contribution more informative than is required.
Maxims of quality
Supermaxim: Try to make your contribution one that is true.
1 Do not say what you believe to be false.
2 Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence.
Maxim of relation
Be relevant.
34
Communication
Maxims of manner
Supermaxim: Be perspicuous.
1 Avoid obscurity of expression.
2 Avoid ambiguity.
3 Be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity).
4 Be orderly.
This account of the general standards governing verbal communication
makes it possible to explain how the utterance of a sentence, which
provides only an incomplete and ambiguous representation of a thought,
can nevertheless express a complete and unaml?iguous thought. 24 Of the
various thoughts which the sentence uttered could be taken to represent,
the hearer can eliminate any that are incompatible with the assumption
that the speaker is obeying the co-operative principle and maxims. If only
one thought is left, then the hearer can infer that it is this thought that the
speaker is trying to communicate. Thus, to communicate efficiently, all
the speaker has to do is utter a sentence only one interpretation of which is
compatible with the assumption that she is obeying the co-operative
principle and maxims.
Recall, for instance, our example (16)-(18):
(16) Jones has bought the Times.
(17) Jones has bought a copy of the Times.
(18) Jones has bought the press enterprise which publishes the Times.
Problems of explanation
35
In just the same way, if Peter is aware of (35), he could infer conclusion
(36):
(35) Mary's eyes remain open when she is awake.
(36) Coffee would cause Mary's eyes to remain open.
Now in ordinary circumstances, Mary would have wanted to communicate (34) but not (36), although both are inferable in the same way from the
thought she has explicitly expressed. This is easily explained on the
assumption that Mary obeys Grice's maxims. The explicit content of her
utterance does not directly answer Peter's question; it is therefore not
relevant as it stands. If Mary has obeyed the maxim 'be relevant', it must be
assumed that she intended to give Peter an answer. Since he can obtain just
the expected answer by inferring (34) from what she said, she must have
intended him to draw precisely this conclusion. There is no parallel reason
to think that she intended Peter to infer (36). Hence, just as the Gricean
maxims help the hearer choose, from among the senses of an ambiguous
sentence, the one which was intended by the speaker, so they help him
choose, from among the implications of the explicit content of an
utterance, the ones which are implicitly conveyed.
Suppose now that the exchange in (32) takes place in the same
circumstances as before, except that Peter has no particu'iar reason
beforehand to assume that Mary does not want to stay awake. Without
this assumption, no answer to his question is derivable from Mary's
utterance, and the relevance of this utterance is not immediately apparent.
One of Grice's main contributions to pragmatics was to show how, in the
event of such an apparent violation of the co-operative principle and
maxims, hearers are expected to make any additional assumptions needed
to dispose of the violation. Here Peter might first adopt (33) as a specific
assumption jointly suggested by the utterance, his knowledge of Mary,
and the general assumption that Mary is trying to be relevant. He might
then infer, as in the previous example, that she does not want any coffee.
To eliminate the apparent violation of the maxims, Peter would have to
assume that Mary had intended him to reason just as he did: that is, that
she was intending to convey implicitly both assumption (33) and
conclusion (34).
Grice calls additional assumptions and conclusions such as (33) and
(34), supplied to preserve the application of the co-operative principle and
maxims, implicatures. Like his ideas on meaning, Grice's ideas on
implicature can be seen as an attempt to build on a commonsense view of
verbal communication by making it more explicit and exploring its
implications. In his William James Lectures, Grice took one crucial step
away from this commonsense view towards theoretical sophistication;
36
Communication
but of course one step is not enough. Grice's account retains much of the
vagueness of the commonsense view. Essential concepts mentioned in the
maxims are left entirely undefined. This is true of relevance, for instance:
hence appeals to the 'maxim of relation' are no more than dressed-up
appeals to intuition. Thus, everybody would agree that, in ordinary
circumstances, adding (33) and (34) to the interpretation of Mary's answer
in (32) makes it relevant, whereas adding (35) and (36) does not. However,
this fact has itself to be explained before it can be used in a genuine
explanation of how Mary's answer is understood.
Grice's view of implicature raises even more b~sic questions. What is
the rationale behind the co-operative principle and maxims? Are there just
the nine maxims Grice mentioned, or might others be needed, as he
suggested himself? It might be tempting to add a maxim every time a
regularity has to be accounted for. 25 However, this would be entirely ad
hoc. What criteria, then, do individual maxims have to meet? Could the
number of maxims be not expanded but reduced ?26
How are the maxims to be used in inference? Grice himself seems to
think that the hearer uses the assumption that the speaker has observed the
maxims as a premise in inference. Others have tried to reinterpret the
maxims as 'conversational postulates' (Gordon and Lakoff 1975), or even
as code-like rules which take semantic representations of sentences and
descriptions of context as input, and yield pragmatic representations of
utterances as output (Gazdar 1979). The flavour of such proposals can be
seen from the following remarks:
The tactic adopted here is to examine some of the data that would, or
should be, covered by Grice's quantity maxim and then propose a
relatively simple formal solution to the problem of describing the
behaviour of that data. This solution may be seen as a special case of
Grice's quantity maxim, or as an alternative to it, or as merely a
conventional rule for assigning one class of conversational meanings
to one class of utterance. (Gazdar 1979: 49)
The pragmatic phenomena amenable to this sort of treatment are rather
limited: they essentially arise when the utterance of a certain sentence is so
regularly correlated with a certain pragmatic interpretation that it makes
sense to set up a rule linking the one to the other. For example, the
~t~erance of (37) regularly suggests (38), the main exception being when
It IS already assumed that (38) is, or might be, false:
(37) Some of the arguments are convincing.
(38) Not all of the arguments are convincing.
The proposal is to deal with this by setting up a general rule associating
Problems of explanation
37
(37) wit~ t~e pragmatic interI?r~tation (38), and eff:ctively. blocking its
application III contexts where It IS assumed that (38) IS, or mIght be, false
(Gazdar 1979: 55-9). However, in most cases of implicature, as for
instance in example (32)-(34), the context does much more than filter out
inappropriate interpretations: it provides premises without which the
implicature cannot be inferred at all. The translation of Grice's maxims
into code-like rules would thus reduce them to dealing with a narrow set
of interesting but quite untypical examples of implicature.
What, then, are the forms of inference involved in the J:.1ormal operation
of the maxims? If, as seems plausible, non-demonstrative (i.e. nondeductive) inference is involved, how does it operate? Without pursuing
these questions in any depth, most pragmatists have adopted one form or
another of the Gricean approach to implicatures, and are otherwise
content to explain the explicit core of verbal communication in terms of
the code model. The results are as can be expected. Although based on an
insight which seems quite correct, and although somewhat more explicit
and systematic than the intuitive reconstructions supplied by unsophisticated speakers, the analyses of implicature which have been proposed by
pragmatists have shared with these intuitive reconstructions the defect of
being almost entirely ex post facto.
.
Given that an utterance in context was found to carry particular
implicatures, what both the hearer and the pragmatic theorist can do, the
latter in a slightly more sophisticated way, is to show how in very intuitive
terms there was an argument based on the context, the utterance and
general expectations about the behaviour of speakers, that would justify
the particular interpretation chosen. What they fail to show is that on the
same basis, an equally convincing justification could not have been given
for some other interpretation that was not in fact chosen. There may be a
whole variety of interpretations that would meet whatever standards of
truthfulness, informativeness, relevance and clarity have been proposed or
envisaged so far. The theory needs improving at a fundamental level
before it can be fruitfully applied to particular cases.
In his William James Lectures, Grice put forward an idea of fundamental importance: that the very act of communicating creates
expectations which it then exploits. Grice himself first applied this idea
and its elaboration in terms of the maxims to a rather limited problem of
linguistic philosophy: do logical connectives ('and', 'or', 'if ... then') have
the same meaning in natural languages as they do in logic? He argued that
the richer meaning these connectives seem to have in natural languages can
be explained in terms not of word meaning but of implicature. He then
suggested that this approach could have wider applications: that the task
of linguistic semantics could be considerably simplified by treating a large
array of problems in terms of implicatures. And indeed, the study of
38
Communication
39
parallel case. O?~ hu~an cogn~tive ability i~ sight. With respec~ to sight,
each individual IS m a vIsual enVIronment whIch can be charactensed as the
set of all phenomena visible to him. What is visible to him is a function
both of his physical environment and of his visual abilities.
In studying communication, we are interested in conceptual cognitive
abilities. We want to suggest that what visible phenomena are for visual
cognition, manifest facts are for conceptual cognition. Let us define:
(39) A fact is manifest to an individual.at a .given time if and only ~f he. is
capable at that time of representmg It mentally and acceptmg Its
representation as true or probably true.
(40) A cognitive environment of an individual is a set of facts) that are
manifest to him.
40
Communication
41
Communication
cognitive environment, for every manifest assumption, the fact that it is
manifest to the people who share this environment is itself manifest. In
other words, in a mutual cognitive environment, every manifest assumption is what we will call mutually manifest.
Consider, for example, a cognitive environment E shared by Peter and
Mary, in which (41) and (42) are manifest:
42
The more complex assumptions of type (43)-(45) get, the less likely they
are actually to be made. However, in such a series, assumption n does not
have to be actually made by the individuals it mentions for assumption
n+ 1 to be true. There is therefore no cut-off point beyond which these
assumptions are likely to be false rather than true; they remain manifest
throughout, even though their degree of manifestness tends asymptotically toward zero. (41 )-( 45) and all the assumptions in E are not only
manifest to Peter and Mary; they are mutually manifest.
The notion of a mutually manifest assumption is clearly weaker than
that of a mutual assumption (and a fortiori than that of mutual
knowledge). Consider assumptions (46)-(48) and all the further assumptions that can be built on the same pattern:
(46) Peter and Mary assume that the phone is ringing.
(47) Peter and Mary assume that Peter and Mary assume that the phone is
rIngmg.
(48) Peter and Mary assume that Peter and Mary assume that Peter and
Mary assume that the phone is ringing.
As before, the more complex assumptions of type (46)-(48) get, the less
likely they are actually to be made. In this case, however, assumption n
does have to be made by Peter and Mary for assumption n + 1 to be true.
Moreover, there is sure to be some point - quite soon actually - at which
Mary does not assume that Peter assumes that she assumes that he assumes,
etc. At this point and beyond, all the assumptions in this series are false, and
mutuality of assumptions is not achieved. Another way of seeing that mutuality of assumptions is stronger than mutual manifestness is to notice that
43
(43) may be true when (46) is not, (44) may be true when (47) is not, (45)
may be true when (48) is not, and so on, while the converse is not possible.
Mutual manifestness is not merely weaker than mutual knowledge or
mutual assumption; it is weaker in just the right way. On the one hand, it
is not open to the same psychological objections, since the claim that an
assumption is mutually manifest is a claim about cognitive environments
rather than mental states or processes. On the other hand, as we will show
in section 12, the notion of mutual manifestness is strong enough to give a
precise and interesting content to the notion of overtness discussed in
section 6. However, by rejecting the notion of mutual knowledge and
adopting the weaker notion ?f ~utual manifestness, we 1ep:ive ourselves
of a certain type of explanatIOn III the study of commUnICatIOn.
Communication requires some degree of co-ordination between communicator and audience on the choice of a code and a context. The notion
of mutual knowledge is used to explain how this co-ordination can be
achieved: given enough mutual knowledge, communicator and audience
can make symmetrical choices of code and context. A realistic notion of
mutual manifestness, on the other hand, is not strong enough to explain
such symmetrical co-ordination. However, before concluding that
mutual manifestness is too weak after all, ask yourself what are the
grounds for assuming that responsibility for co-ordination is equally
shared between communicator and audience, and that both must worry,
symmetrically, about what the other is thinking. Asymmetrical coordination is often easier to achieve, and communication is an asymmetrical process anyhow.
Consider what would happen in ballroom dancing if the responsibility
for choosing steps was left equally to both partners (and how little help the
mutual-knowledge framework would be for solving the resulting coordination problems in real time). Co-ordination problems are avoided,
or considerably reduced, in dancing, by leaving the responsibility to one
partner who leads, while the other has merely to follow. We assume that
the same goes for communication. It is left to the communicator to make
correct assumptions about the codes and contextual information that the
audience will have accessible and be likely to use in the comprehension
process. The responsibility for avoiding misunderstandings also lies with
the speaker, so that all the hearer has to do is go ahead and use whatever
code and contextual information come most easily to hand.
Suppose Mary and Peter are looking at a landscape where she has
noticed a distant church. She says to him,
(49) I've been inside that church.
She does not stop to ask herself whether he has noticed the building, and
whether he assumes she has noticed, and assumes she has noticed he has
Communication
noticed, and so on, or whether he has assumed it is a church, and assumes
she assumes it is, and so on. All she needs is reasonable confidence that he
will be able to identify the building as a church when required to: in other
words, that a certain assumption will be manifest in his cognitive
environment at the right time. He need not have accessed this assumption
before she spoke. In fact, until she spoke he might have thought the
building was a castle: it might be only on the strength of her utterance that
it becomes manifest to him that the building is a church.
Inspired by the landscape, Mary says,
44
(50) It's the sort of scene that would have made Marianne Dashwood
swoon.
This is an allusion to Jane Austen's Sense and Sensibility, a book she
knows Peter has read. She does not stop to think whether he knows she
has read it too and knows she knows he has read it, and so on. Nor is she
unaware of the fact that they may well have reacted to the book in different
ways and remember it differently. Her remark is based on assumptions
that she does not mention and that he need never have made himself before
she spoke. What she expects, rightly, is that her utterance will act as a
prompt, making him recall parts of the book that he had previously
forgotten, and construct the assumptions needed to understand the
allusion.
In both these examples Mary makes assumptions about what assumptions are, or will be, manifest to Peter. Peter trusts that the assumptions he
spontaneously makes about the church and about Sense and Sensibility,
which help him understand Mary's utterances, are those she expected him
to make. To communicate successfully, Mary had to have some knowledge of Peter's cognitive environment. As a result of their successful
communication, their mutual cognitive environment is enlarged. Note
that symmetrical co-ordination and mutual knowledge do not enter into
the picture at all.
The most fundamental reason for adopting the mutual-knowledge
framework, as for adopting the code model, is the desire to show how
successful communication can be guaranteed, how there is some failsafe
algorithm by which the hearer can reconstruct the speaker's exact
meaning. Within this framework the fact that communication often fails is
explained in one of two ways: either the code mechanism has been
imperfectly implemented, or there has been some disruption due to
'noise'. A noiseless, well-implemented code mechanism should guarantee
perfect communication.
In rejecting the mutual-knowledge framework, we abandon the
possibility of using a failsafe algorithm as a model of human communication. But since it is obvious that the communication process takes place at
45
46
Communication
47
48
Communication
abilities always have plenty of unfinished business. The key problem for
efficient short-term information processing is thus to achieve an optimal
allocation of central processing resources. Resources have to be allocated
to the processing of information which is likely to bring about the greatest
contribution to the mind's general cognitive goals at the smallest
processing cost.
Some information is old: it is already present in the individual's
representation of the world. Unless it is needed for the performance of a
particular cognitive task, and is easier to access from the environment than
from memory, such information is not wortp. processing at all. Other
information is not only new but entirely unconnected with anything in the
individual's representation of the world. It can only be added to this
representation as isolated bits and pieces, and this usually means too much
processing cost for too little benefit. Still other information is new but
connected with old information. When these interconnected new and old
items of information are used together as premises in an inference process,
further new information can be derived: information which could not
have been inferred without this combination of old and new premises.
When the processing of new information gives rise to such a multiplication effect, we call it relevant. The greater the multiplication effect, the
greater the relevance.
Consider an example. Mary and Peter are sitting on a park bench. He
leans back, which alters her view. By leaning back, he modifies her
cognitive environment; he reveals to her certain phenomena, which she
may look at or not, and describe to herself in different ways. Why should
she pay attention to one phenomenon rather than another, or describe it to
herself in one way rather than another? In other words, why should she
mentally process any of the assumptions which have become manifest or
more manifest to her as a result of the change in her environment? Our
answer is that she should process those assumptions that are most relevant
to her at the time.
Imagine, for instance, that as a result of Peter's leaning back she can see,
among other things, three people: an ice-cream vendor who she had
noticed before when she sat down on the bench, an ordinary stroller who
she has never seen before, and her acquaintance William, who is coming
towards them and is a dreadful bore. Many assumptions about each of
these characters are more or less manifest to her. She may already have
considered the implications of the presence of the ice-cream vendor when
she first noticed him; if so, it would be a waste of processing resources to
pay further attention to him now. The presence of the unknown stroller is
new information to her, but little or nothing follows from it; so there
again, what she can perceive and infer about him is not likely to be of much
relevance to her. By contrast, from the fact that William is coming her
49
way, she can draw many conclusions from which many more conclusions
will follow. This, then, is the one truly relevant change in her cognitive
environment; this is the particular phenomenon she should pay attention
to. She should do so, that is, if she is aiming at cognitive efficiency.
Our claim is that all human beings automatically aim at the most
efficient information processing possible. This is so whether they are
conscious of it or not; in fact, the very diverse and shifting conscious
interests of individuals result from the pursuit of this permanent aim in
changing conditions. In other words, an individual's particular cognitive
goal at a given moment is always an instance- of a more general goal:
maximising the relevance of the information processed. We will show that
this is a crucial factor in human interaction.
Among the facts made manifest to Mary by Peter's behaviour is the very
fact that he has behaved in a certain way. Suppose now that she pays
attention to this behaviour, and comes to the conclusion that it must have
been deliberate: perhaps he is leaning back more rigidly than if he were
merely trying to find a more comfortable position. She might then ask
herself why he is doing it. There may be many possible answers; suppose
that the most plausible one she can find is that he is leaning back in order to
attract her attention to some particular phenomenon. Then Peter's
behaviour has made it manifest to Mary that he intends to make some
particular assumptions manifest to her. We will call such behaviour behaviour which makes manifest an intention to make something manifest
- ostensive behaviour or simply ostension. Showing someone something is
a case of ostension. So too, we will argue, is human intentional
communication.
The existence of ostension is beyond doubt. What is puzzling is how it
works. Any perceptible behaviour makes manifest indefinitely many
assumptions. How is the audience of an act of ostension to discover which
of them have been intentionally made manifest? For instance, how is Mary
to discover which of the phenomena which have become manifest to her as
a result of Peter's behaviour are the ones he intended her to pay attention
to?
Information processing involves effort; it will only be undertaken in the
expectation of some reward. There is thus no point in drawing someone's
attention to a phenomenon unless it will seem relevant enough to him to
be worth his attention. By requesting Mary's attention, Peter suggests that
he has reason to think that by paying attention, she will gain some relevant
information. He may, of course, be mistaken, or trying to distract her
attention from relevant information elsewhere, as the maker of an
assertion may be mistaken or lying; but just as an assertion comes with a
tacit guarantee of truth, so ostension comes with a tacit guarantee of
relevance~
50
Communication
10 Ostensive-inferential communication
Ostension provides two layers of information to be picked up: first, there
is the information which has been, so to speak, pointed out; second, there
is the information that the first layer of information has been intentionally
pointed out. One can imagine the first layer being recovered without the
second. For example, as a result of Peter's leaning back, Mary might notice
William coming their way, even if she paid no attention to Peter's
intentions. And as for Peter, he might not care much whether Mary
recognises his intention, as long as she notices William.
In general, however, recognising the intention behind the ostension is
necessary for efficient information processing: someone who fails to
recognise this intention may fail to notice relevant information. Let us
Ostensive-inferential communication
51
modify our example slightly and suppose that William is in the distance,
barely visible in a crowd. If Mary pays no attention to the fact that Peter's
behaviour is ostensive, she might well look in the right direction and yet
not notice William. If she pays attention to the ostension, she will be
inclined to take a closer look and find out what information Peter thought
might be relevant to her.
In our modified example, what Peter's ostension mostly does is make
much more manifest some information which would have been manifest
anyhow, though very weakly so. Sometimes, however, part of the basic
information will not be manifest at all unless the intention behind the
ostension is taken into account. Suppose a girl is travelling in a foreign
country. She comes out of the inn wearing light summer clothes,
manifestly intending to take a stroll. An old man sitting on a bench n~earby
looks ostensively up at the sky. When the girl looks up, she sees a few tiny
clouds, which she might have noticed for herself, but which she would
normally have paid no further attention to: given her knowledge - or lack
of knowledge - of the local weather, the presence of these tiny clouds is
not relevant to her. Now, however, the old man is drawing her attention to
the clouds in a manifestly intentional way, thus guaranteeing that there is
some relevant information to be obtained.
The old man's ostensive behaviour opens up for the girl a whole new
strategy of processing. If she accepts his guarantee of relevance, she has to
find out what makes him think that the presence of the clouds would be
relevant to her. Knowing the area and its weather better than she does, he
might have reason to think that the clouds are going to get worse and turn
to rain. Such an assumption is of a very standard sort and would probably
be the first to come to mind. The old man can thus be reasonably confident
that, prompted by his behaviour, she will have no difficulty in deciding
that this is what he believes. If it were not manifest to the old man that it
was going to rain, it would be hard to explain his behaviour at all. The girl
thus has reason to think that in drawing her attention to the clouds, he
intended to make manifest to her that he believed it was going to rain. As a
result of this act of ostension, she now has some information that was not
available to her before: that he thinks it is going to rain, and hence that
there is a genuine risk of rain.
In this example, the state of affairs that the old man drew the girl's
attention to had been partly manifest to her, and partly not. The presence
of the clouds and the fact that clouds may always turn to rain had been
manifest and merely became more so. However, until that moment she
had regarded the fact that the weather was beautiful as strong evidence that
it would not rain. The risk of rain in that particular situation was not
manifest to her at all. In other words, the clouds were already evidence of
52
Communication
oncoming rain, but evidence that was much too weak. The old man made
that evidence much stronger by pointing it out; as his intentions became
manifest, the assumption that it would rain became manifest too.
Sometimes, all the evidence displayed in an act of ostension bears
directly on the agent's intentions. In these cases, only by discovering the
agent's intentions can the audience also discover, indirectly, the basic
information that the agent intended to make manifest. The relation
between the evidence produced and the basic information conveyed is
arbitrary. The same piece of evidence can be used, on different occasions,
to make manifest different assumptions, even qmtually inconsistent
assumptions, as long as it makes manifest the intention behind the
ostension.
Here is an example. Two prisoners, from different tribes with no
common language, are put in a quarry to work back to back breaking
rocks. Suddenly, prisoner A starts putting some distinct rhythm into the.
sound of his hammer - one-two-three, one-two, one-two-three, onetwo - a rhythm that is both arbitrary and noticeable enough to attract the
attention of prisoner B. This arbitrary pattern in the way the rocks are
being broken has no direct relevance for B. However, there are grounds
for thinking that it has been intentionally produced, and B might ask
himself what A's intentions were in producing it. One plausible assumption is that this is a piece of ostensive behaviour: that is, that A intended B
to notice the pattern. This would in turn make manifest A's desire to
interact with B, which in the circumstances would be relevant enough.
Here is a more substantial example. Prisoners A and B are at work in
their quarry, each with a guard at his shoulder, when suddenly the
attention of the guards is distracted. Both prisoners realise that they have a
good chance of escaping, but only if they can co-ordinate their attack and
overpower their guards simultaneously. Here, it is clear what information
would be relevant: each wants to know when the other will start the
attack. Prisoner A suddenly whistles, the prisoners overpower their
guards and escape. Again, there is no need for a pre-existing code
correlating a whistle with the information that now is the moment t9
attack. The information is obvious enough: it is the only information that
A could conceivably have intended to make manifest in the circumstances.
Could not the repetition of such a situation lead to the development of a
code? Imagine that the two prisoners, caught again, find themselves in the
same predicament: again a whistle, again an escape, and again they are
caught. The next time, prisoner B, who has not realised that both guards
are distracted, hears prisoner A whistle: this time, fortunately, B does not
have to infer what the whistle is intended to make manifest: he knows. The
whistle has become a signal associated by an underlying code to the
message 'Let us overpower our guards now!'
Ostensive-inferential communication
53
54
Communication
55
56
Communication
57
to intend Peter to share. Yet there is more to her utterance than its explicit
content: she manifestly intends Peter to draw some conclusions from
what she said, and not just any conclusions. Quite ordinary cases such as
(51) are never discussed in the pragmatic literature.
Pragmatists tend to take for granted that a meaning is a proposition
combined with a propositional attitude, though they may diverge
considerably in the way they present and develop this view. In other
words, they treat the communicator's informative intention as an
intention to induce in an audience certain attitudes to certain propositions.
With assertions, often taken to be the most basic case, the informative
intention is treated as an intention to induce in an audience the belief that a
certain propositIOn is true.
There is a very good reason for anyone concerned with the role of
inference in communication to assume that what is communicated is
propositional: it is relatively easy to say what propositions are, and how
inference might operate over propositions. No one has any clear idea how
inference might operate over non-propositional objects: say, over images,
impressions or emotions. Propositional contents and attitudes thus seem
to provide the only relatively solid ground on which to base a partly or
wholly inferential approach to communication. Too bad if much of what
is communicated does not fit the propositional mould.
At first sight, it might look as if semioticians had a more comprehensive
view. They have an a priori account of how any kind of representation,
propositional or not, might be conveyed: namely, by means of a code.
However, studies by semioticians of what they call 'connotation', i.e. the
vaguer aspect of what is communicated, are highly programmatic and do
not offer the beginnings of a psychologically adequate account of the type
of mental representation involved.}! The semiotic approach is more
comprehensive only by being more superficial.
The only people who have been quite consistently concerned with the
vaguer aspects of communication are the Romantics, from the Schlegel
brothers and Coleridge to 1. A. Richards, and their many acknowledged
or unacknowledged followers, including many semioticians such as
Roman Jakobson in some of his writings, Victor Turner, or Roland
Barthes. However, they have all dealt with vagueness in vague terms, with
metaphors in metaphorical terms, and used the term 'meaning' so broadly
that it becomes quite meaningless.
We see it as a major challenge for any account of human communication
to give a precise description and explanation of its vaguer effects.
Distinguishing meaning from communication, accepting that something can
be communicated without being strictly speaking meant by the communicator or the communicator's behaviour, is a first essential step - a step
away from the traditional approach to communication and most modern
58
Communication
60
Communication
course, a continuum of cases in between. In the case of strong communication, the communicator can have fairly precise expectations about some
of the thoughts that the audience will actually entertain. With weaker
forms of communication, the communicator can merely expect to steer
the thoughts of the audience in a certain direction. Often, in human
interaction, weak communication is found sufficient or even preferable
to the stronger forms.
Non-verbal communication tends to be relatively weak. One of the
advantages of verbal communication is that it gives rise to the strongest
possible form of communication; it enables the pearer to pin down the
speaker's intentions about the explicit content of her utterance to a single,
strongly manifest candidate, with no alternative worth considering at all.
On the other hand, what is implicit in verbal communication is generally
weakly communicated: the hearer can often fulfil part of the speaker's
informative intention by forming any of several roughly similar but not
identical assumptions. Because all communication has been seen as strong
communication, descriptions of non-verbal communication have been
marred by spurious attributions of 'meaning'; in the case of verbal
communication, the difference between explicit content and implicit
import has been seen as a difference not in what gets communicated but
merely in the means by which it is communicated, and the vagueness of
implicatures and non-literal forms of expression has been idealised away.
Our account of informative intentions in terms of manifestness of
assumptions corrects these distortions without introducing either ad hoc
machinery or vagueness of description.
61
Communication
62
possibilities of interaction (and, in particular, m their possibilities of
further communication).
Recall, for instance, the case of Peter leaning back to let Mary see
William coming their way. If, as a result of his behaviour, it becomes
mutually manifest to them that William is coming, that they are in danger
of being bored by his conversation, ete., then they are in a position to act
efficiently: i.e. promptly. All Mary may have to do is say, 'Let's go!'; she
can feel confident that Peter will understand her reasons, and, if he shares
them, will be ready to act without question or delay.
In the case of the broken hair-drier, if Mary had made mutually
manifest her wish that Peter would mend it, one of two things would have
happened. Either he would have mended it, thus granting her wish and
possibly putting her in his debt; or he would have failed to mend it, which
would have amounted to a refusal or rejection. Mary avoids putting
herself in his debt or meeting with a refusal by avoiding any modification
of their mutual cognitive environment. If Peter mends the hair-drier, he is
being kind on his own initiative, and she does not owe him anything. If
Peter decides not to mend the hair-drier, he might reason as follows: she
doesn't know I know she intended to inform me of her wish, so if I ignore
it, she will attribute this to her failure to inform me; she may find me
stupid, but not unkind. As for Mary, she may have intentionally left this
line of reasoning open to Peter. If he does not mend her hair-drier, she will
find him unkind, but not hostile. His failure to grant her wish will not be
in the nature of a rebuff. They will stand in exactly the same social
-relationship to each other as before. This shows how ostensive communication may have social implications that other forms of information
transmission do not.
By making her informative intention mutually manifest, the communicator creates the following situation: it becomes mutually manifest that
the fulfilment of her informative intention is, so to speak, in the hands of
the audience. If the assumptions that she intends to make manifest to the
audience become manifest, then she is successful; if the audience refuses to
accept these assumptions as true or probably true, then she has failed in
her informative intention. Suppose - we will soon see how this may
happen - that the audience's behaviour makes it mutually manifest that the
informative intention is fulfilled. Then the set of assumptions I that the
communicator intended to make manifest to the audience becomes, at
least apparently, mutually manifest. We say 'at least apparently' because,
if the communicator is not sincere and some of the assumptions in I are
not manifest to her, then by our definition of mutual manifestness, these
assumptions cannot be mutually manifest to her and others. 32
A communicator is normally interested in knowing whether or not she
has succeeded in fulfilling her informative intention, and this interest is
63
mutually manifest to her and her audience. In face-to-face communication, the audience is generally expected to respond to this interest in fairly
conventional ways. Often, for instance, the audience is expected to
communicate its refusal to accept the information communicated, or else
it becomes mutually manifest that the communicator's informative
intention is fulfilled.
Where communication is non-reciprocal, there are various possible
situations to be taken into account. The communicator may be in a
position of such authority over her audience that the success of her
informative intention is mutually manifest in advance. Journalists,
professors, religious or political leaders assume, alas often on good
grounds, that what they communicate automatically becomes mutually
manifest. When the communicator lacks that kind of authority, but still
wants to establish a mutual cognitive environment with her audience, all
she has to do is adapt her informative intentions to her credibility. For
instance, in writing this book we merely intend to make mutually manifest
that we have developed certain hypotheses and have done so on certain
grounds. That is, we take it as mutually manifest that you will accept our
authority on what we actually think. The mutual cognitive environment
thus created is enough for us to go on to communicate further thoughts
which we would otherwise have been unable to communicate. (Of course
we would also like to convince you, but we hope to do this by the force of
our arguments, and not by making you recognise our informative
intentions. )
We began this chapter by asking how human beings communicate with
one another. Our answer is that they use two quite different modes of
communication: coded communication and ostensive-inferential communication. However, the two modes of communication are used in
fundamentally different ways. Whereas ostensive-inferential communication can be used on its own, and sometimes is, coded communication is
only used as a means of strengthening ostensive-inferential communication. This is how language is used in verbal communication, as we will
argue in chapter 4.
Ostensive-inferential communication can be defined as follows:
64
Communication
2
Inference
1 Non-demonstrative inference
In the last chapter, we outlined a model of ostensive-inferential communication, looking more closely at the ostensive nature of the communicator's behaviour than at the inferential nature of comprehension. In this
chapter, we will outline a model of the inferential abilities involved in
comprehension. Here, we have already made two broad hypotheses on
which we hope to build. First, we implicitly assumed that the process of
inferential comprehension is non-demonstrative: even under the best of
circumstances, we argued, communication may fail. The addressee can
neither decode nor deduce the communicator's communicative intention.
The best he can do is construct an assumption on the basis of the evidence
provided by the communicator's ostensive behaviour. For such an
assumption, there may be confirmation but no proof.
Second, we explicitly assumed that any conceptually represented
information available to the addressee can be used as a premise in this
inference process. In other words, we assumed that the process of
inferential comprehension is 'global' as opposed to 'local': where a local
process (e.g. deductive reasoning from fixed premises or auditory
perception) is either context-free or sensitive only to contextual information from some set domain, and a global process (e.g. empirical scientific
reasoning) has free access to all conceptual information in memory.
A non-demonstrative inference process with free access to conceptual
memory: this sounds, appropriately enough, like an ordinary central
thought process. A distinction between 'central' processes and 'input',
'perceptual' or 'peripheral' processes is assumed in much of current
cognitive psychology. Roughly speaking, input processes are relatively
specialised decoding processes, whereas central processes are relatively
unspecialised inferential processes. The distinction will be discussed and
illustrated below.
66
Inference
Non-demonstrative inference
67
Inference
68
inference is to be found in a system of inductive logic is open to question.
Inference is the process by which an assumption is accepted as true Or
probably true on the strength of the truth or probable truth of other
assumptions. It is thus a form of fixation of belief. There are other forms:
perception, for instance, is a process by which an assumption is accepted
as true or probably true on the strength of a non-conceptual cognitive
experience. Demonstrative inference, the only form of inference that is
well understood, consists in the application of deductive rules to an initial
set of premises. There is thus a temptation to think of non-demonstrative
inference as the application of non-deductive infere11fe rules. However,
this temptation is based on analogy rather than argument. In fact, there is
reason to doubt that spontaneous non-demonstrative inference, as
performed by humans, involves the use of non-deductive inference rules.
Deductive inference rules generate all the interesting conclusions
logically implied by a set of premises. 1 It is generally recognised that
non-demonstrative inference rules cannot be expected to generate all the
interesting conclusions non-demonstratively supported by a set of
premises. For instance, the theory of relativity could not have been
generated by applying inference rules to the results of Eddington's
experiment. Instead, the process of reaching valid non-demonstrative
conclusions is generally broken down into two distinct stages: hypothesis
formation and hypothesis confirmation. Eddington's experiment provided the first empirical confirmation of Einstein's theory, but did not in
any sense imply it. Hypothesis formation, it is argued, is a matter of
creative imagination; hypothesis confirmation, on the other hand, can be
seen as a purely logical process governed by inference rules.
The function of inference rules is to guarantee the logical validity of the
inferences they govern. In a valid demonstrative inference, the application
of deductive rules to tr,ue premises guarantees the truth of the conclusions.
Similarly, iljl a valid non-demonstrative inference, hypothesis confirmation could be seen as governed by logical rules. These confirmation rules
might apply jointly to the premises, or 'evidence', and the tentative
conclusions, or 'assumptions', and assign a degree of confirmation to the
assumptions on the basis of the evidence. It is tempting to move from these
logical considerations to psychological speculation.
Humans are rather good at non-demonstrative reasoning; otherwise the
species would be extinct. This might be because they have logical rules
which constrain the confirmation of assumptions in the way just
described. However, this is not much of an explanation, since we have no
clear idea of what these rules might be. Also, at this level of vagueness,
other explanations are possible. For all we know, human inferential
successes might be attributable not so much to logical constraints on
confirmation as to cognitive constraints on hypothesis formation.
Non-demonstrative inference
69
70
Inference
71
72
Inference
73
-74
Inference
Strength of assumptions
75
play a cognitive role only via factual assumptions of the form It is dubious
that P, I regret that P, I am afraid that P, and so on.
A representation of the world, then, may be regarded without too much
oversimplification as a stock of factual assumptions, some basic, others
expressing attitudes to embedded propositional or non-propositional
representations. Factual assumptions are the domain par excellence of
spontaneous non-demonstrative inference processes. Each newly
acquired factual assumption is combined with a stock of existing
assumptions to undergo inference processes whose aim, we have suggested, is to modify and improve the individual's overall representation of
the world. 7
When a representation is stored not as a basic factual assumption but by
being embedded under an expression of attitude, it is often processed in a
self-conscious, non-spontaneous way. This is true of representations used
in problem-solving tasks of the kind familiar from experimental psychology. It is true of speculatively held opinions, religious beliefs, or scientific
hypotheses. The largely conscious reasoning processes which these
indirectly held representations undergo are of great intrinsic interest, but
we see it as a mistake to extrapolate from them to the spontaneous and
essentially unconscious inference processes used in most ordinary thinking, and in particular in ordinary verbal comprehension.
The model of inferential communication and the notion of relevance we
are developing are not tied to any particular form of inference. We assume,
for instance, that the lengthy and highly self-conscious processes of
textual interpretation that religious or literary scholars engage in are
governed just as much by considerations of relevance as is spontaneous
utterance comprehension. However, in this book we want to focus on the
latter. Spontaneous inference plays a role even in scholarly interpretation,
whereas scholarly thinking is a rather exceptional human endeavour, even
for scholars. The study 'of spontaneous inference is thus a necessary
prerequisite to a proper investigation of all forms of human inference,
including inferential communication.
3 Strength of assumptions
Factual assumptions are entertained with greater or lesser confidence; we
think of them as more or less likely to be true. We do so consciously in two
main types of situation. First, we may have to choose between contradictory assumptions, as when I assumed that Bob would be out of town, and
now I assume that I am seeing him walking down the street: of the two
assumptions, the one I regard as more likely to be true will displace the
other. Second, we may have to choose between different courses of action,
76
Inference
as when I want to buy some petrol, and I assume that both the petrol
station up the street and the one down the street are open: if I regard the
assumption that the station down the stt:eet is open as more likely to be
true, that is where I will go.
When our more confident assumptions are those which are in fact more
likely to be true, we tend to make the right choices of assumptions and
courses of action. In other words, the adequacy of our representation of
the world depends not only on which assumptions we hold, but also on
our degree of confidence in them: an adequate representation is one in
which there is a good match between the assumRtions we regard as well
confirmed and those that actually are well confirmed. Improvements in
our representation of the world can be achieved not only by adding
justified new assumptions to it, but also by appropriately raising or
lowering our degree of confidence in them, the degree to which we take
them to be confirmed.
'Confirmation' is a term taken from a relatively undeveloped branch of
logic (which itself took it from commonsense psychology). How should it
be adapted for use in cognitive psychology? Two very different answers
can be given. On one approach, the logical concept of confirmation makes
a good psychological concept as it stands; the logician's system is, on the
whole, an -adequate psychological model. All that is needed is to replace
the objective notion of confirmation with some subjective analogue: for
example, a system assigning subjective probability values to representations. Call this the logical view.
On another approach, the logical concept of confirmation should be not
adapted but rejected. The ability to judge an assumption as more or less
likely to be true is to be explained not in terms of a system which assigns
subjective probability values to assumptions, but in terms of a non-logical
property of assumptions: what, metaphorically, we will call their strength.
Call this the non-logical, or functional, view. This is the approach that we
would like to pursue.
According to the logical view, every factual assumption consists of two
representations. The first is a representation of a state of affairs - for
instance (7a); the second is a representation of the confirmation value of
the first representation - for instance (7b):
(7) (a) Jane likes caviar.
(b) The confirmation value of (a) is 0.95.
How are these two representations arrived at? The first, so the story goes,
is the output of a non-logical cognitive process of assumption formation.
The second is the output of a process of logical computation which takes
as input the assumption to be confirmed, on the one hand, and the
available evidence, on the other. When new evidence becomes available, a
Strength of assumptions
77
78
Inference
the confirmation value of (7a). The strength of (7a) is established and
varies as a by-product of other processes, and need not be represented at
all in order to exist and vary.
However, this is not the whole story. Functional properties of
representations, such as accessibility or strength, need not be represented
in the mind in order to exist, vary and affect cognitive processes, but they
can be represented. People have intuitions about the accessibility of
different assumptions; we appealed to such intuitions about example
(8)-(9) above. Similarly, people have intuitions about the strength of their
assumptions. They may express these intuition~ in different ways. They
may say such things as
(10) I am quite certain that Jane likes caviar.
(11) I firmly believe that J ane likes caviar.
(12) What I have seen confirms my assumption thatJane likes caviar.
(13) It seems more probable to me that Jane likes caviar than that she likes
oysters.
Behind these forms of expression lies a tacit hypothesis. We take for
granted that there is a good match between the strength of our
assumptions and the likelihood that they are true. That is, we trust our
cognitive mechanisms to strengthen or weaken our assumptions in a way
that is epistemologically sound: we trust our representation of the world
to be adequate in this respect, as in others. As a result, intuitions about the
strength of our assumptions are expressed as intuitions about their degree
of confirmation. Such intuitions are assumptions about assumptions, and
can be processed as such. More often than not, they are assumptions about
changes in the strength of a single assumption, as in (12), or about the
relative strength of pairs of assumptions, as in (13). In some cases, it seems
plausible that such assumptions play a genuine cognitive role: for instance,
in conscious attempts to resolve a contradiction by working out which of
the contradictory assumptions is the more likely to be true.
According to the logical view, the soundness of our assumptions
depends on our ability to carry out a computational check on the
confirmation value of each assumption. According to the functional view,
the soundness of our assumptions - to the extent that they are sound depends on our having cognitive mechanisms so attuned to the world we
live in that the strength of our assumptions tends to match the likelihood
that they are true. On the logical view, a representation of the confirmation value of an assumption is an aspect of that assumption; it is the
outcome of a logical process which every assumption undergoes. On the
functional view, a representation of the degree of confirmation of an
assumption is another assumption; it is generally the product of an
intuition about one of the effects of the processing history of that
Strength of assumptions
79
In
Someone who quite strongly believes (14) and (15) might find it difficult
or impossible to answer the question, 'Do you think it is more likely that
Jane likes caviar than that there are more Indian restaurants than Chinese
restaurants in Chelsea?'
It seems to us implausible that humans might have a system for
computing and representing the strength of assumptions which is both
wholly unconscious and radically more sophisticated than anything that is
reflected in their conscious intuitions. We therefore reject the possibility
that an individual might unconsciously assess cpnfirmation values
through the kind of numerical computations suggested by logicians, when
he is incapable of doing so consciously. 8 We conclude, more generally,
that the strength of an assumption cannot be quantitatively assessed: in the
terms of Carnap (1950), it is a comparative rather than a quantitative value.
In his 1950 treatise on subjective probability (another term for
estimated degree of confirmation), Carnap contrasts classificatory, comparative and quantitative concepts along the following lines.
A classificatory concept sets up a necessary and sufficient condition for
class membership. For example, an integer either is prime (if it can be
evenly divided by no other whole number than itself and 1), or it is not.
80
Inference
A comparative concept is one that figures in comparative judgements.
For example, some things feel warmer than others, some sounds seem
louder than others, some foods taste nicer than others, and so on. Some
classificatory concepts have comparative counterparts, but not all of them
do. Caffeinated is both a classificatory concept (a substance either does or
does not contain caffeine) and a comparative one (some substances contain
more caffeine than others). On the other hand, prime does not have a
comparative interpretation: numbers cannot be more or less prime.
Carnap's third type of concept, the quantitative concept, is one that
figures in numerical comparisons. For example: distance is a quantitative
concept because we can not only say that London is further from
Edinburgh than it is from Oxford, but also measure the distance in miles
or kilometres, and hence say how much further London is from
Edinburgh than it is from Oxford. However, as Carnap points out, not
every comparative concept has a quantitative counterpart. Though we
might know that one food tastes better than another, there is no obvious
way of measuring how good a food tastes, and therefore of measuring how
much better one food tastes than another.
The existence of an objective numerical scale makes it easy to formulate
precise absolute judgements and to compare unlike objects: say the ages of
a child and a car, or the distance from Trafalgar Square to Buckingham
Palace and from the foot of Mount Everest to the top. Where no numerical
scale exists, absolute judgements become gross, and comparison of unlike
objects becomes much harder. For example, someone might be able to say
that one champagne tastes better than another, or that one caviar tastes
better than another, but be quite unable to say whether or not a certain
champagne tastes better than a certain caviar.
Even where an objective numerical scale exists, it does not follow that
some internal analogue of it is used in mental comparison. For example,
when a suitcase feels heavier the longer it is carried, this feeling is
presumably not based on any assumption that the suitcase is actually
gaining ounces or pounds as the journey proceeds. Similarly, comparisons
of the warmth of unlike objects, such as a liquid with a solid, or a solid
with a gas, are much harder than comparisons of the warmth of like
objects. This strongly suggests that ordinary judgements of warmth are
not based on an internal analogue of a temperature scale.
Difficulties in comparing unlike objects are hard to explain on the
assumption that a numerical scale is being used. Where such difficulties
arise, it seems more reasonable to assume that what is being used is not a
numerical scale but rather a heuristic (based for instance on matching
procedures), which applies only to like objects: comparing, for example,
the taste of several samples of caviar, the warmth of various liquids, the
strength of several assump_tions of related content.
Strength of assumptions
81
82
Inference
[alha:vJhedelk]
I have a headache.
Peter has a headache at time t.
Peter says that - - .
Peter says that Peter has a headache at time t.
(24)
(25)
(26)
(27)
83
84
Inference
Nor is there any reason why there should be from the purely logical point
85
86
Inference
Concepts, like the logical forms that contain them, are psychological
objects considered at a fairly abstract level. Formally, we assume that each
concept consists of a label, or address, which performs two different and
complementary functions. First, it appears as an address in memory, a
heading under which various types of information can be stored and
retrieved. Second, it may appear as a constituent of a logical form, to
whose presence the deductive rules may be sensitive. These functions are
complementary in the following sense: when the address of a certain
concept appears in a logical form being processed, access is given to the
various types of information stored in memory at that address.
The information that may be stored in memory- at a certain conceptual
address falls into three distinct types: logical, encyclopaedic and lexical.
The logical entry for a concept consists of a set of deductive rules which
apply to logical forms of which that concept is a constituent. The
encyclopaedic entry contains information about the extension and/or
denotation of the concept: that is, about the objects, events and/or
properties which instantiate it. The lexical entry contains information
about the natural-language counterpart of the concept: the word or phrase
of natural language which expresses it. On this approach, a conceptual
address is thus a point of access to the logical, encyclopaedic and linguistic
information which may be needed in the processing of logical forms
containing that address. We consider each type of entry in turn.
A logical entry consists of a set of deductive rules, each formally
describing a set of input and output assumptions: that is, a set of premises
and conclusions. Our first substantive claim is that the only deductive
rules which can appear in the logical entry of a given concept ate
elimination rules for that concept. That is, they apply only to sets of
premises in which there is a specified occurrence of that concept, and yield
only conclusions from which that occurrence has been removed.
Standard logics invariably contain such rules. For example, the standard
logical rule of and-elimination takes as input a single conjoined premise
and yields as output one of its constituent conjuncts:
(46) And-elimination
(a) Input: (P and Q)
Output: P
(b) Input: (P and Q)
Output: Q
That is, it applies only to premises containing a designated occurrence of
the concept and, and yields conclusions from which that occurrence has
been removed. The standard rule of modus ponendo ponens takes as input
a pair of premises, one a conditional and the other the antecedent of that
conditional, and yields as output the consequent of the conditional:
87
88
Inference
entries, the relations between the various types of assumption contained in
them, and the relations among the entries themselves. Many of the models
that have been proposed incorporate such notions as schema, frame,
prototype or script. 14
,
The idea behind these notions is that humans are disposed to develop
stereotypical assumptions and expectations about frequently encountered
objects and events. For example, I have an idea of a typical pet, which
includes dogs and cats but excludes elephants and spiders. It is thought
that these schematic assumptions and expectations are stored and accessed
as a unit or 'chunk', that they are highly accessi~le, and that they will be
used in default of any more specific information in processing utteran~es
about the associated objects or events. Thus, when I hear that my
.neighbour has bought a pet, I will assume that it is something like a dog or
a cat rather than an elephant or a spider, unless given specific information
to the contrary. We do not want to argue for or against any particular one
of these models. We share the basic hypothesis which is common to all of
them: in our terms, that encyclopaedic information contains not only
factual assumptions but also assumption schemas which an appropriate
context may convert into full-fledged assumptions.
Intuitively, there are clear-enough differences between encyclopaedic
and logical entries. Encyclopaedic entries typically vary across speakers
and times: We do not all have the same assumptions about Napoleon or
about cats. They are open-ended: new information is being added to them
all the time. There is no point at which an encyclopaedic entry can be said
to be complete, and no essential minimum without which one would not
say that its associated concept had been mastered at all. Logical entries, by
contrast, are small, finite and relatively constant across speakers and times.
There is a point at which the logical entry for a concept is complete, and
before which one would not say that the concept had been mastered at all.
Suppose, for example, that a child has not yet realised that X knows that P
implies P, and so uses know interchangeably with believe. We would say
that he had not yet mastered the concept. On the other hand, if he has
grasped this logical point but is unable to think of a single instance of
something he is prepared to call knowledge, we would regard this as a
failure of memory or experience (or a mark of philosophical potential)
rather than of understanding.
The distinction between logical and encyclopaedic entries corresponds
in many ways to the traditional distinction between analytic and synthetic
truths, which has been a notorious subject of dispute. However, our claim
is not so much that there is a fundamental difference between two types of
truth, two types of information content, as that information must be
representable in two different forms, and function in two different ways, if
89
90
Inference
to us remotely plausible. However, it is primarily a formal and functional
distinction, and does not necessarily imply that there are two fundamentally different kinds of truth.
The third type of entry for a concept, its lexical ,entry, contains
information about the natural-language lexical item used to express it. We
assume that this entry includes the sort of syntactic and phonological
information that would be contained in the lexical entry for that item in a
generative grammar: information about its syntactic category membership and co-occurrence possibilities, phonological structure, and so
(j
,
on.
The fact that concepts have both logical and lexical entries provides a
point of contact between input and central processes, between the
linguistic input system and the deductive rules of the central conceptual
system. Recovery of the content of an utterance involves the ability to
identify the individual words it contains, to recover the associated
concepts, and to apply the deductive rules attached to their logical entries.
We assume, then, that the 'meaning' of a word is provided by the
associated concept (or, in the case of an ambiguous word, concepts). This
allows us to maintain a somewhat ecumenical view of lexical semantics.
Most theories of lexical semantics assume that all words, with the possible
exception of proper names, have meanings of the same format. They then
differ as to what this universal format is. We recognise the possibility that
different words may have meanings of different formats.
A classical view is that the meaning of a word is provided by a definition
which expresses the individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for the word to apply. For instance, the definition of 'mother' could'
be female parent. If this is so, it can be represented by assignit;lg 'mother' as
the lexical entry for the concept female parent, or by associating with the
concept mother the elimination rule in (50) (where X and Y stand for
possibly empty strings of constituents):
(50) Mother-elimination rule
Input: (X - mother - Y)
Output: (X - female parent - Y)
On this classical view, proper names, for which necessary and sufficient
conditions of application cannot be given, are radically different from
other words: they have reference but no meaning. 'Homer', for instance,
cannot be defined as the author of the Iliad and the Odyssey, since there is
no inconsistency in denying that he is their author; he cannot be defined as
a Greek man (a grossly incomplete definition anyhow), since there is no
inconsistency in denying that he was Greek or that he was a man, and so
on. If that is so, if there are words which have reference but no logical
92
Inference
Input: (X - yellow - Y)
Output: (X - colour of a certain hue - Y)
Our framework allows for empty logical entries, logical entries which
amount to a proper definition of the concept, and logical entries which fall
anywhere between these two extremes: that is, which provide some logical
specification of the concept without fully defining it. We assume that this
range of possibilities actually exists in the human mind; how exactly it is
exploited, to what extent actual concepts are logically specified, we see as a
matter for empirical research. What is at issue in the case of each concept
is: what deductive inferences are made possible by its presence in an
assumption ?19
In this section we have argued that the rules used in spontaneous
deductive inference are elimination rules attached to concepts. We have
treated concepts as triples of entries, logical, lexical and encylopaedic, filed
at an address. In one sense, the distinction between address and entry is a
distinction between form and content, the address being what actually
appears in logical forms, and the various entries spelling out its logical,
lexical and encyclopaedic content. In another sense, though, everything
discussed in this section has been purely formal. Logical entries are sets of
deductive rules: that is, formal operations on logical forms; encyclopaedic
entries are sets of assumptions: that is, representations with logical forms;
and lexical entries are representations with linguistic forms. All three
types of entry are thus available for use in a computational account of
comprehension.
Occasionally, an entry for a particular concept may be empty or
lacking. For example, a concept such as and, which has no extension, may
lack an encylopaedic entry. We saw that proper names and other concepts
could be seen as having an empty logical entry. Finally, there may be
concepts which have encyclopaedic and logical entries and play a role in
cognitive processes, but which are not lexicalised and which therefore
have an empty lexical entry. For example, it seems reasonable to assume
that corresponding to the general concept lexicalised as 'the military' or
93
94
Inference
95
to read, write and erase logical forms, compare their formal properties,
store them in memory, and access the deductive rules contained in the
logical entries for concepts. Deductions proceed as follows. A set of \,.
assumptions 20 which will constitute the axioms, or initial theses, of the
deduction are placed in the memory of the device. It reads each of these
assumptions, accesses the logical entries of each of its constituent
concepts, applies any rule whose structural description is satisfied by that
assumption, and writes the resulting assumption down in its memory as a
derived thesis. Where a rule provides descriptions of two input assumptions, the device checks to see whether it has in memory an appropriate
pair of assumptions; if so, it writes the output assumption down in its
memory as a derived thesis. The process applies to all initial and derived
theses until no further deductions are possible.
The system monitors for redundancies and contradictions in its
derivations in the following way. Before writing an assumption down in
its memory, it checks to see whether that assumption or its negation is
already there. If the assumption itself is there, the device refrains from
writing it down again, and marks the theses and deductive rules used in
deriving it so that the derivation will not be repeated. If the negation of the
assumption is already there, the device halts, and the deductive process is
suspended until the ~ontradiction is resolved; a method of resolving
contradictions will be considered below. Subject to these constraints, the
device continues to operate until no new theses can be derived.
The move to formal systems raises questions about the capacity of the
deductive device which are sometimes overlooked when informal systems
are proposed. Most informal systems - at least those invented by logicians
- aim at completeness: that is, they aim to provide deductive rules which
will derive as logical implications all the entailments (or all those that hinge
on the logical properties of and, or, etc.) of a given set of assumptions. It is
easy to show that this set of entailments is infinite for any finite set of
premises. For example, a single arbitrary assumption P entails each of the
following conclusions:
(54) (a) (P and P)
(b) (P or Q)
(c) (not (not P))
(d) (If (not P) then Q)
(e) (If Q then P)
These are all entailments of P in the sense that there are no conceivable
states of affairs in which P would be true and any of (54a-e) false.
Logicians aiming at completeness will therefore set up deductive rules
enabling each of (54a-e) to be derived as logical implications of P. (54a) is
standardly derived by the rule of and-introduction, which takes two
96
Inference.
arbitrary assumptions, in this case P and P, as premises, and derives their
conjunction as conclusion:
(55) And-introduction
Input: (i) P
(ii) Q
Output: (P and Q)
(54b) is standardly derived by the rule of or-introduction, which takes an
arbitrary assumption as premise, and derives its disjunction with any
other arbitrary assumption as conclusion:
(56) Or-introduction
Input: P
Output: (P or Q)
(54c) is standardly derived by the rule of double negation, which takes an
arbitrary assumption as premise and derives the negation of its negation as
conclusion:
98
Inference
99
(63) (a) If the boiler needs repairing or the electricity has been cut off, the
house will be uninhabitable. [Premise].
(b) The boiler needs repairing. [Premise]
(c) The boiler needs repairing or the electricity has been cut off. [By
or-introduction from (b)]
(64) The house will be uninhabitable. [By modus ponens from (a) and (c)]
These rules, like modus ponens itself, are elimination rules, and as will be
seen below, there is good reason to think that they play a role in the
spontaneous deductive processing of information. We assume that some
version of rule (65) is attached to the logical entry for and, and some
version of rule (66) is attached to the logical entry for or.
Rules (65) and (66) make it possible to derive (62) from (61) and (64)
from (63) without the use of introduction rules. The derivation of (62)
from (61) would go as in (61') below, with a step of conjunctive modus
ponens at (b'), followed by a step of regular modus ponens:
(61') (a) If the trains are on strike and the car has broken down, there is no
way of getting to work. [Premise]
100
Inference
(b) The trains are on strike. [Premise]
(b') If the car has broken down, there is no way of getting to work.
[From (a) and (b) by conjunctive modus ponens]
(c) The car has broken down. [Premise]
(62) There is no way of getting to work. [From (b') and (c) by modus
ponens]
The derivation of (64) from (63) would go as in (63') below, with a step of
disjunctive modus ponens deriving the conclusiqn directly from the
premIses:
(63') (a) If the boiler needs repairing or the electricity has been cut off, the
house will be uninhabitable. [Premise]
(b) The boiler needs repairing. [Premise]
(64) The house will be uninhabitable. [From (a) and (b) by disjunctive
modus ponens]
There is thus no question that alternative derivations exist.
The psychological plausibility of these derivations depends on the
psychological plausibility of rules (65) and (66) themselves. Rips (1983)
has experimental evidence that rule (66), the rule of disjunctive modus
ponens, is 'not only psychologically real but is one of the most highly
accessible rules, more accessible than the rule of modus ponens itself. His
evidence also shows that the rule of or-introduction is one of the least
accessible rules, and is indeed rejected by many subjects. The fact that
derivations such as (63)-(64) are regularly and easily performed strongly
suggests that no step of or-introduction is involved.
We know of no experimental evidence on rule (65), the rule of
conjunctive modus ponens. However, in a relevance-based framework,
both conjunctive and disjunctive modus ponens would be highly valued
for the following reason. When some item of information is presented in
the form of a complex conditional with a conjunctive or disjunctive
antecedent, the chances of finding the whole conjunctive or disjunctive
antecedent ready-stored in memory are clearly much smaller than those of
finding just one of its constituent conjuncts or disjuncts. What the rules of
conjunctive and disjunctive modus ponens do is allow inferences to be
drawn on the basis of a single conjunct or disjunct, rather than requiring
the whole conjunctive or disjunctive antecedent to be supplied. They thus
increase the chances of the presented information interacting with the
individual's existing representation of the world to enable new conclusions to be drawn. For an organism interested in improving its representa-
102
Inference
derivable by the rules of the deductive device; (67)-(68) and (69)-(70) are
cases in point. We would therefore expect the deductive device to be
complemented with some non-deductive, or not directly deductive,
procedures for checking validity whenever the deductive machinery-is
insufficient. And in that case, from the fact that subjects make correct
judgements of validity, it does not follow that these judgements have been
arrived at by direct derivation.
OUr deductive device offers such an indirect procedure based on the fact
that it monitors contradictions. One way of showing that an argument is
valid is to show that it is inconsistent to assert the prquises while denying
the conclusion. For instance, if (67a-b) and the negation of (68), or (69)
and the negation of (70), were the initial theses of a derivation, the
deductive device would reveal the inconsistencies involved, and thus
establish that (67a-b) entails (68) and that (69) entails (70).
We therefore reject two extreme views of the human deductIve ability.
We do not believe that all deductive inference must be accounted for
purely in terms of deductive rules (the position tacitly adopted in Rips
1983). On the other hand, we do believe that a deductive rule system is an
extremely efficient device for reducing the number of assumptions that
have to be separately stored in memory, for accessing the conclusions of
arguments, for drawing out the implications of newly acquired conceptual
information, and for increasing the impact of this information on a stored
conceptual representation of the world. We therefore reject the claim
made by Johnson-Laird (1982b, 1983) that there are no mentally
represented deductive rules at all:
The crux of the matter is that a system of inference may perform in an
entirely logical way even though it does not employ rules of
inference, inferential schemata, meaning postulates, or any other
sort of machinery conventionally employed in a logical calculus.
Oohnson-Laird 1982b: 20)
It seems reasonable to assume, with Johnson-Laird, that subjects use
various heuristics that are not directly derivational in performing certain
types of reasoning tasks; but it does not follow that there are n~ mentally
represented deductive rules at all, any more than it follows from the fact
that subjects perform correctly on certain reasoning tasks that they must
be using deductive rules.
We are suggesting, then, a mixed view of human deductive abilities. Our
hypothesis is that when presented with a set of assumptions, subject to the
usual limitations of memory and attention,23 the device should directly and
automatically compute the full set of non-trivial implications defined by
its deductive rules, as part of its regular working procedure. Trivial
103
Inference
assumptions with some internal organisation. We would now like to
suggest that the improvements brought by new information to an existing
representation of the world can be traced via the workings of the deductive
device.
When a set of assumptions is placed in the memory of the deductive
device, all the deductive rules in the logical entries attached to their
constituent concepts are accessed. As can be seen from the examples given
above, these rules are of two formally distinct types, which we will call
analytic and synthetic. An analytic rule takes only a single assumption as
input; a synthetic rule takes two separate assul\lptions as input. For
example, and-elimination (rules (46a-b) above), which takes a single,
conjoined assumption as input, is an analytic rule, and modus ponendo
ponens (rule (47) above), which takes a conditional assumption and its
antecedent as input, is a synthetic rule.
Let us say that any conclusion obtained from an initial set of
assumptions by a derivation in which only analytic rules are used is
analytically implied by that set of assumptions:
104
105
106
Inference
Someone who accepted (75a-c) but denied any of (78a-f) would be guilty
of a failure not of logic but of understanding. Ori the other hand, someone
could quite well understand (75a-c) without having computed the
synthetic implications (76a-c). Suppose you acquired each of these
assumptions at a different time and in different circumstances, so that you
never happened to bring them together and compute. their synthetic
implications (76a-c). This omission would not mean that you had
understood each individual assumption any the less. We all have hundreds
of thousands of assumptions stored in memory, from which hundreds of
thousands of synthetic implications could be computfd if only they could
all be brought together in the memory of the deductive device. The fact
that they never have been, and indeed never will be, does not mean that
each individual assumption has not been properly understood.
Notice that what makes a synthetic implication synthetic is not the form
in which its premises are presented but the nature of the rules used in
deriving it. There is no reason why a single complex assumption should
not have synthetic implications. For example, the conjoined assumption
in (79) synthetically implies (76a), just as the separate assumptions (75a)
and (75b) do:
(79) The ticket is in the wallet and the wallet is in the suitcase.
(75) (a) The ticket is in the wallet.
(b) The wallet is in the suitcase.
(76) (a) The ticket is in the suitcase.
The only difference in the way this implication is derived frorp. (75a-b) on
the one hand and from (79) on the other is that (79) must undergo
and-elimination before rule (77) can apply. Otherwise the derivations are
identical, and what is a synthetic implication in one case remains a
synthetic implication in the other.
We have now reached the point where a single assumption can have
three types of logical implication: trivial implications, which are not
directly computed by our device; analytic implications, which are
necessary and sufficient for understanding it; and synthetic implications,
which have to do not so much with grasping the information being offered
as with exploiting this information to the full. Our framework thus sheds
some light on the rather hazy pretheoretical distinction between 'semantic' and 'logical' implication, between intrinsic meaning and wider import.
The distinction between analytic and synthetic implications has an
important practical consequence. The analytic implications of a given
assumption are intrinsic to it: they are recoverable as long as the
assumption itself is recoverable, simply by reprocessing it through the
deductive device. Synthetic implications, by contrast, are not intrinsic to
any single member of the set of assumptions from which they are derived
107
108
Inference
(iii) C does not non-trivially imply Q.
Contextual effects
109
110
Inference
least as high as that of (83), which entails it. It could not be lower, since this
would mean that conceivably (83) might be true and (82) false, and this is
ruled out by the fact that (83) entails (82). On the other hand, if there is any
possibility that the party was a success without Peter, or Paul, or Mary
being there, then the confirmation value of (82) should be even higher than
that of (83).
From a logical point of view, then, there is a lower limit to the
confirmation value of a conclusion: it cannot be less than the confirmation
value of the conjunction of the premises. From a cognitive point of view,
the question now becomes: how can the deductive de.vice assess that lower
limit, given that (as we are assuming) it can neither derive the conjunction
of the premises nor compute its confirmation value? Further logical
considerations must be taken into account before this cognitive question
can be answered.
We are considering, then, how the confirmation value of the conjunction (83) might be assessed. The confirmation value of a conjunction of
assumptions depends on the values of its conjuncts. From a logical point
of view, it cannot be higher than the value of the weakest, i.e. least
confirmed, conjunct. Suppose it is certain that Peter and Paul came to the
party, but doubtful that Mary did. It is equally doubtful, then, that Peter,
Paul and Mary all came to the party. On the other hand, the confirmation
value of a conjunction can be lower than that of its weakest conjunct.
Suppose that (81 b-d) are are all strongly confirmed, but less than certain.
Generally, the likelihood of all three assumptions being true is less than
the likelihood of any single one of them being true. The confirmation
value of a conjunction should therefore be lower than thatof any of its
individual conjuncts. In fact, the greater the number of conjuncts, and the
lower their confirmation values, the lower the confirmation value of the
conjunction.
There is thus an upper limit to the confirmation value of the conjunction
of premises used in a deduction, and this can be assessed without either
deriving that conjunction or computing its confirmation value. The upper
limit of the confirmation value of a conjunction is the confirmation value
of its weakest conjunct; to assess that, no computation is required.
Notice that in a single deduction, different conclusions may be derived
on the basis of different premises. Only those premises actually used in
the derivation of a particular conclusion should affect its confirmation
value. For instance, let us add to (81) one further premise (81e):
(81) (e) If Paul and Mary came to the party, Roger left early.
Now, from the set of premises (81a-e), another conclusion follows:
(84) Roger left early.
Contextual effects
111
112
Inference
Contextual effects
113
114
Inference
(86) (a) Either Bob came to the party or Mary came to the party.
(b) Bob did not come to the party.
(86a-b) logically implies (87):
(87) Mary came to the party.
This leads to an independent strengthening of (81d), which is identical in
content to (87). Since (81d) is also an argument for (82) in the context of
(81a-c), (82) is in turn dependently strengthened by (81d). The contextualisation of (86) in (81) thus strengthens both ~81d) and (82).
We have so far considered two types of contextual effect: the addition of
contextual implications and the strengthening of previously held assumptions. But a significant improvement of one's representation of the world
can also result from the elimination of false assumptions. This highly
significant contextual effect may be brought about when there is a
contradiction between new and old information.
In our account of the working of the deductive device, we said that
when it encounters a contradiction, it halts until the contradiction is
resolved. Suppose, for example, that (88a-b) is contextualised in (89):
(88) (a) If Jennifer came, the party was a success.
(b) Jennifer came.
(89) (a) If Bill came, the party was not a success.
(b) Bill came.
(c) The party was not a success.
(d) If the party was not a success, we won't have another party.
(e) We won't have another party.
(88a-b) logically implies (90), the negation of (89c):
(90) The party was a success.
Ort deriving (90), we said, the device will attempt to resolve this
contradiction. In resolving a contradiction, the strength of the two
contradictory assumptions must be taken into account.
The deductive device has the power not only to read and write
assumptions in its memory, but also to erase them. Let us assume that
when two assumptions are found to contradict each other, if it is possible
to compare their strengths, and if one is found to be stronger than the
other, then the device automatically erases the weaker assumption. When
an assumption is erased, the device also erases any assumption which
analytically implies it, and the weaker of any pair of assumptions which
synthetically imply it; this procedure applies recursively until no more
erasures can take place. When such a procedure is possible, the contradiction is eliminated at the root, and the deductive process can be resumed.
Contextual effects
115
116
Inference
Contextual effects
117
3
Relevance
119
120
Relevance
gical models which make use of it, and, in particular, on the value of the
theory of verbal comprehension that it allows us to formulate. Intuitions
o.f relevance are not the only kinds of intuition involved in comprehenSIOn.
121
would have no contextual effect in the present context, and this is why it is
intuitively felt to be irrelevant.
'
There are thus t~!'~j~es of case in which. an assumption may lack
contextual effects, and be irrelevant, in a context>In the first, illustrated by
(1), the assumption may contribute new information; but this information
does not connect up with any information present in the context. In the
second, illustrated by (2), the assumption is already present in the context
and its strength is unaffected by the newly presented information; this
newly presented information is therefore entirely uninformative and, a
fortiori, irrelevant. In the third type of case, illustrated by (3), the
assumption is inconsistent with the context and is too weak to upset it;
processing the assumption thus leaves the context unchanged.
It should be stressed that in all these examples it is only the assumption
explicitly expressed by the utterance that lacks contextual effects and is
irrelevant: the fact that someone chooses to express an irrelevant
assumption may itself be highly relevant. For instance, it may be a way of
making manifest a desire to change the subject, and this desire may well be
relevant. Or, to take an actual example, we have expressed the irrelevant
assumptions (1)-(3) in an attempt to make what we hope were relevant
remarks. Relevance may be achieved by expressing irrelevant assumptions, as long as this expressive behaviour is itself relevant.
On the basis of these examples, we want to claim that an assumption
which has no contextual effect in a given context is irrelevant in that
context. In other words, having some contextual effect in a context is a
necessary condition for relevance.
.
The next question seems to be whether having contextual effects might
be not only a necessary condition for relevance but also sufficient. There is
a certain amount of evidence that it is. For example, consider the following
(attested) exchange:
(4) Flag-seller: Would you like to buy a flag for the Royal National
Lifeboat Institution?
Passer-by: No thanks, I always spend my holidays with my sister in
Birmingham.
To see the relevance of the passer-by's response, the hearer must be able to
supply something like the premises in (5), and derive something like the
contextual implication in (6):
(5) (a)
(b)
(c)
(d)
Birmingham is inland.
The Royal National Lifeboat Institution is a charity.
Buying a flag is one way of subscribing to a charity.
Someone who spends his holidays inland has no need of the
services of the Royal National Lifeboat Institution.
122
Relevance
Degrees of relevance
123
124
Relevance
(9) Flexibility
Extent condition 1: an object is flexible to the extent that it is easy to
bend.
Extent condition 2: an object is flexible to the extent that the shape it
can be bent into differs from its initial shape.
If an object can be bent at all, then conditions 1 and 2 are satisfied to some
extent, and conversely. These two extent conditions, therefore, logically
imply a necessary and sufficient condition: an object is flexible if and only
if it can be bent. Since this necessary and sufficient condition is implied by
definition (9), it need not be stated independently.
Definition (9) makes comparisons possible only in some cases: other
things being equal, if object Ais easier to bend than object B, then it is
Degrees of relevance
125
more flexible; or, other things being equal, if object A can be bent further
than object B, then it is more flexible. But if A is easy to bend into a not
very different shape and impossible to bend any further, and B can be bent
only with difficulty but can then be bent much further, definition (9) does
not allow a comparative judgement to be made; and this seems to reflect
the limitations of ordinary usage. Incidentally, if we wanted to give an
adequate representation of the logical entry of the ordinary language
concept of flexibility, we would reformulate the extent conditions of
definition (9) as inference rules, which could be done in several different
ways. But our reason for discussing degrees of flexibility is not to shed
light on ordinary comparative concepts; it is to illustrate the form that a
theoretical comparative concept might take.
We are trying to develop a theoretical concept of relevance, for use in
the study of communication and cognition. We expect this theoretical
concept to help predict people's intuitions, but not necessarily their use of
the word 'relevance' or of similar ordinary language terms. We can
improve on definition (7) of relevance by adopting an extent-conditions
format of the type just illustrated:
(10) Relevance
Extent condition 1: an assumption is relevant in a context to the extent
that its contextual effects in this context are large.
Extent condition 2: an assumption is relevant in a context to the extent
that the effort required to process it in this context is small.
This definition implies the necessary and sufficient condition of definition
(7), which therefore need not be stated independently.
The assessment of relevance, like the assessment of productivity, is a
matter of balancing output against input: here contextual effects against
processing effort. Definition (10) of relevance, like definition (9) of
flexibility, makes clear comparisons possible only in some cases: other
things being equal, an assumption with greater contextual effects is more
relevant; and, other things being equal, an assumption requiring a smaller
processing effort is more relevant.
Let us now illustrate this comparative notion of relevance with a few
artificial examples; artificial in particular in the sense that the contexts we
are using are much smaller and more arbitrary: than contexts used in reallife comprehension. Readers should try to resist the natural tendency to
supply much richer and more appropriate contexts, a tendency which will
be discussed at length later on.
Consider a context consisting of assumptions (l1a-c):
(11) (a) People who are getting married should consult a doctor about
126
Relevance
(b) Two people both of whom have thalassemia should be warned
against having children.
(c) Susan has thalassemia.
Consider the effects that assumptions (12) and (13), both by hypothesis
equally strong, would have in this context:
(12) Susan, who has thalassemia, is getting married to Bill.
(13) Bill, who has thalassemia, is getting married to Susan.
Both (12) and (13) have some contextual effects in context (11), and are
therefore relevant by definition (10). In particular, both (12) and (13) carry
the contextual implication (14):
(14) Susan and Bill should consult a doctor about possible hereditary risks
to their children.
Def!.rees of relevance
127
(17)(a)
(b)
(c)
(d)
(e)
[certain]
[certain]
[certain]
[certain]
[strong]
[very weak]
[strong]
Suppose that a hearer who has context (17a-g) in mind takes everything
the speaker says as certain. Suppose that the speaker is in a position to
assert either (18) or (19):
(18) Sue is richer than Jim.
(19) Sue is richer than Peter.
Intuitively, the assumption expressed by (19) is the more relevant, and is
128
Relevance
the one which, other things being equal, the speaker should choose to
express.
This is easily accounted for in terms of our definition of relevance.
Assumption (18) has only two contextual effects in the context (17a-g):
first, it raises the strength of (17f) from very weak to certain, since it is
identical in content to (17f) and is itself certain; second, it raises the
strength of (17g) from strong to certain, since (17g) is synthetically implied
by (17d) and (17), which are now both certain.
Assumption (19) has five contextual effects. It contextually implies (20)
and (21):
(20) Sue is richer than Sam.
(21) Sue is richer than Bill.
[certain]
[certain]
Degrees of relevance
129
130
Relevance
contextual implications. Contextual effects involving changes in confirmation value could also be measured, as long as these values too were
quantitative, i.e. of the kind favpured by logicians.
Suppose further that all the operations of our automaton can be
analysed as combinations of equally simple elementary operations; in this
case the processing effort needed for a certain ta~k, e.g. achieving certain
contextual effects, could be measured by counting the elementary
operations involved. Or, if the automaton were implemented in the form
of a computer program, processing effort could be measured in terms of
the time taken to achieve particular effects. Then it would just be a matter
of deciding, in a principled or arbitrary way, h'ow contextual effects and
processing effort should be weighted against one another, and relevance
for this automaton could be quantitatively defined.
Things go differently when it comes to assessing contextual effects
achieved by human minds, and the processing effort needed to achieve
them. On the contextual-effects side, we have argued that nonquantitative confirmation values are involved. If so, then these effects
cannot be measured. On the processing-effort side, the prospects for
quantitative assessment are no better. For example, we do not know what
elementary operations complex thought processes reduce to. We do know
that the duration of a mental process is not an adequate indicator of its cost
for the organism: time spent in high mental concentration involves greater
effort than equal time spent in relaxed daydreaming.
The problems involved in measuring contextual effects and processing
effort are, of course, by no means specific to relevance theory or to
pragmatics. They affect psychology as a whole. However, for relevance
theory these problems take on a more specific form. Within relevance
theory, the problem is not so much to assess contextual effects and
processing effort from the outside, but to describe how the mind assesses
its own achievements and efforts from the inside, and decides as a result to
pursue its efforts or reallocate them in different directions.
Here is one line of possible speculation: contextual effects and mental
effort, just like bodily movements and muscular effort, must cause some
symptomatic physico-chemical changes. We might assume that the mind
assesses its own efforts and their effects by monitoring these changes.
Although we have nothing to say on the neuro-physics or neurochemistry involved, this is not an empty assumption. It contrasts with
another conceivable view/ on which contextual effects would beFassessed
by actually counting contextual implications, and processing effort by
actually counting inferential steps. There are many reasons for rejecting
this view: counting each step means adding one operation at each step,
which should considerably increase the effort involved in every mental
process. This in turn would be paradoxical, since presumably the point 6f
Degrees of relevance
131
132
Relevance
for them than for duller people. Speakers who are not aware of their
hearers' disposition in the matter risk asking them for too much effort or
providing them with too few effects;
Mental effects and effort are non-representational properties of mental
processes. Relevance, which is a function of effect and effort, is a
non-representational property too. That is, relevance is a property which
need not be represented, let alone computed, in order to be achieved.
When it is represented, it is represented in terms of comparative
judgements and gross absolute judgements, (e.g. 'irrelevant', 'weakly
relevant', 'very relevant'), but not in terms of fipe absolute judgements, i.e.
quantitative ones.
Since we are interested in relevance as a psychological property, we have
no reason to aim for a quantitative definition of relevance. What we have
to do is add empirical substance to our comparative definition by
considering how relevance is sought and achieved in mental processes, and
particularly in processes of verbal comprehension. Our first task is to
move from a purely formal characterisation of a context to a more
empirical one, and to consider the implications of such a move.
We have suggested that the context used to process new assumptions is,
essentially, a subset of the individual's old assumptions, with which the
new assumptions combine to yield a variety of contextual effects. We have
also proposed two criteria for comparing the relevance of different
assumptions in a given context. However, we still have to face the serious
problem of how the context is determined: how some particular subset of
the individual's assumptions is selected. For ease of exposition, we will
discuss this problem with reference to a particular case: that of a hearer
processing an assumption explicitly asserted by a speaker. In section 6, we
will generalise our account to deal with the assumptions made manifest by
any kind of stimulus.
In this section, we will look at various approaches which take for
granted that, at any given moment, there is only one context available to
the individual, and try to show that they fail precisely because of this
underlying hypothesis. In the next section we will suggest an alternative
approach.
In much of the literature, it is explicitly or implicitly assumed that the
context for the comprehension of a given utterance is not a matter of
choice; at any given point in a verbal exchange, the context is seen as
uniquely determined, as given. 4 Moreover, it is generally assumed that the
context is determined in advance of the comprehension process. The
133
134
Relevance
135
136
Relevance
initial remark. So, according to our fourth hypothesis, (35) is not part of
the context for the interpretation of (36b).
This might lead us, if we still had the stamina, to formulate a fifth
hypothesis: the context for the comprehension of an utterance consists of
the assumptions expressed and implicated by preceding utterances, plus
the encyclopaedic entries attached to any concepts used in these assumptions and in the utterance itself, plus the encyclopaedic entries attached to
any concepts used in the assumptions contained in the encyclopaedic
entries already added to the context. With our fourth hypothesis, one
layer of encyclopaedic entries was added to the context. With our fifth
hypothesis, two layers are added.
The defects of this line of speculation are becoming blatant. With the
last two hypotheses, we have already assumed that the context is
automatically filled with a huge amount of encyclopaedic information,
most - and sometimes all- of which fails to increase the contextual effects
of the new information being processed. Since each expansion of the
context means an increase in processing effort, this method of context
formation would lead to a general loss of relevance. Imagine the following
dialogue, for instance:
(37) (a) Peter: Where does John live?
(b) Mary: John lives next to the Capri restaurant.
A choice of contexts
137
4 A choice of contexts
.)
138,
Relevance
A choice of contexts
139
140
Relevance
To understand Mary's concluding remark that she will make 'it' herself,
Peter needs information provided by her opening remark that she would
like to eat an osso-bucco. However, his interpretation of this opening
remark will in the meantime have been transferred from the memory of his
deductive device to his general short-term memory, if our above
hypotheses are correct. This interpretation must therefore be transferred
back to the memory of the deductive device, thus extending the
immediately given context (which consists of what is left in the memory of
Peter's deductive device after he has interpreted Mary's penultimate
remark that she is sorry to hear that he has had a bad day).
A second way of extending the context is to add to it the encyclopaedic
entries (or possibly smaller chunks of encyclopaedic information, taken
from these entries) of concepts already present either in the context or in
the assumption being processed. We have shown the need for such
extensions with examples (31 )-(38) above. We have also shown that the
assumption that such encyclopaedic extensions are automatically made
for every concept and in every case leads to absurdities; we used this as an
A choice of contexts
141
argument against the view that the context is uniquely determined. On the
other hand, once the determination of a context is seen as a matter of
choice and as part of the interpretation process itself, it seems reasonable
to assume that such extensions take place when they appear to be neededand only then.
A third way of extending the context is to add to it information about
the immediately observable environment. People constantly monitor the
physical environment while carrying out conceptual tasks which may be
partly or totally unrelated to that environment. Where is this subattentively monitored information stored? Again, we do not know, but
we can speculate: all this information is very briefly retained in specialised
short-term perceptual memory stores, from which some of it can be
transferred to the general short-term conceptual memory store and to the
memory of the deductive device. This happens, in particular, when the
interpretation of an utterance leads the hearer to pick up some environmental information and add it to the context. For example, suppose that
Mary, holding up a piece of veal, says to Peter,
(40) If you're tired, I'll cook this.
Peter will have to add to the context some description of the object Mary is
holding. The very form of Mary' s utterance provides an incentive to do so:
just as anaphoric pronouns, such as 'it' in (39), suggest going back in
discourse, deictic pronouns, such as 'this' in (40), suggest adding
environmental information to the context.
We have so far suggested that the choice of a context for inferential
processes in general, and for comprehension in particular, is partly
determined at any given time by the contents ef the memory of the
, deductive device, those of the general-purpose short-term memory store,
,;' and those of the encyclopaedia, and by the information that can be
immediately picked up from the physical environment. These factors
determine not a single context but a range of possible contexts. What
determines the selection of a particular context out of that range? Our
answer is that the selection of a particular context is determined by the
search for relevance.
In much of the pragmatic literature, events are assumed to take place in
the following order: first the context is determined, then the interpretation process takes place, then relevance is assessed. In other words,
relevance is seen as a variable to be assessed in function of a predetermined context. However, from a psychological point of view, this is
a highly implausible model of comprehension. Humans are not in the
business of simply assessing the relevance of new information. They try to
process information as productively as possible; that is, they try to obtain
from each new item of information as great a contextual effect as possible
142
Relevance
5 Relevance to an individual
At the end of each deductive process, the individual has at his disposal a
particular set of accessible contexts. This set is partly ordereg:each
conte:l(t(aE~rt fr0E!_th~j_nitiaISQ.ntextj-contains one or more smaller
contexts:~anleac1i context
from the maximafcohtexts Yiscontained
in orie-or-moreIarg/!~contexts. The set of accessible contexts is thus partly
ordered by the inclusion-relation. This formal relation has a psychological
counterpart: order of inclusion corresponds to order of accessibility. The
initial, minimal context is immediately given; contexts which include only
the initial context as a sub-part can be accessed in (one step and are
therefore the most accessible contexts; contexts which include the initial
context and a one-step extension as sub-parts can be accessed in two steps
and are therefore the next most accessible contexts, and so on. Notice a
point of crucial importance for relevance theory: just as processing an item
of information in a context involves some effort, so accessing a context
involves some effort. The less accessible a context, the greater the effort
involved in accessing it, and conversely.
Consider a new assumption A. This may be relevant in some, all or none
of the contexts accessible to an individual at a given time, depending on
whether some, all or none of these contexts already contain or imply a
(apart
Relevance to an individual
143
token of A, and on the relativ,e strength of old and new tokens. Six
situations can be distinguished (the list is not exhaustive, but is representative enough for our present purposes):
(41)(a) A is already contained in (or implied by) the initial context, at
maximal strength. Then the new token of A is irrelevant in this
context, and in all the other accessible contexts too, since all these
contexts include the initial context. 1'0. this situation there is no
point in searching for relevance beyond the initial context, since
the search will be unproductive.
(b) A is contained in (or implied by) none of the accessible contexts;
however A has no contextual effect in any of them either. Then
again, A is irrelevant in all the accessible contexts, and there is no
point in extending the initial context in the search for relevance.
(c) A is contained in (or implied by) the initial context and all
accessible contexts, at less than maximal strength. Then an
independent strengthening of A by the new token will ensure its
relevance in all the accessible contexts. In this situation an
extension of the context will be justified as long as A has more
contextual effects in the extended context than in the initial
context, and the gain in contextual effects is not outweighed by
the greater effort needed to process A in the extended context.
(d) A is contained in (or implied by) none of the accessible contexts,
and has some contextual implications in the initial context. Then
A is relevant in all the accessible contexts in which it retains these
contextual implications. Here again an extension of the context
will be justified as long as it yields greater contextual effects, and
the increase in contextual effects is not outweighed by the increase
in processing effort required.
(e) A is contained in (or implied by) none of the contexts; it has no
contextual effect in the initial context but has some contextual
effect in some extensions of the initial context. Then A is relevant
in some of the accessible contexts. In this situation, no relevance
will be achieved unless the context is extended. Extensions should
follow the pattern laid down in (c) and (d).
(f) A is not contained in (nor implied by) the initial context, but is
contained (at maximal strength) in some of the larger accessible
contexts; A has contextualeffects in some of the contexts in which
it is not contained (which mayor may not include the initial
context). Then A is relevant in some of the accessible contexts, and
its relevance will be that of a reminder. A reminder is relevant only
in contexts which do not contain the information in question: its
144
Relevance
function is to make this information accessible at a smaller
pro~essing cost than would De needed to obtain it by successive
extensions of the contexC
Relevance to an individual
145
(43) Relevance to an individual (comparative)
Extent condition 1: an assumption is relevant to an individual to the
extent that the contextual effects achieved when it is optimally
processed are large.
Extent condition 2: an assumption is relevant to an individual to the
extent that the effort required to process it optimally is small.
As with definition (10) (the comparative definition of relevance in a
context), this definition of relevance to an individual does not make
comparisons possible in all cases. Take two unrelated assumptions, each
relevant to a different individual at a different time: is assumption A 1 more
relevant to Bill at time tl than assumption A2 is to Joan at time t2? Our
definition does not normally make it possible to answer such a question,
nor, from a psychological point of view, is there any reason why it should.
The only comparisons of relevance that play a psychological role are those
which are subservient to the goal of maximising relevance: relevance to
oneself, or, from the point of view of a communicator, relevance to an
audience.
Let us illustrate this definition of relevance to an individual with an
example somewhat less fragmentary than previous ones (although it still
does not come near the complexities of real-life information processing).
Suppose that the following exchange has so far taken place:
146
Chunk 1.
Chunk 2.
Chunk 3.
Chunk 4.
Chunk 5.
Relevance
Encyclopaedic information about Peter, including the
assumption, Peter isa surgeon.
Encyclopaedic information about Mary.
Encyclopaedic information about making dinner, including a
scenario of looking in the refrigerator to see what is available,
and the assumption, A dinner consists of at least a main course
and a dessert.
.
Information about the currently monitored physical environment.
Assumptions processed at earlier. stages in the exchange,
including: Mary would like to eat an osso-bucco.
Chunks 1-5 are accessible in one step from the initial context. Each of
these potential extensions makes further extensions. accessible in turn. For
instance, the information that Peter is a surgeon makes chunk 6 accessible:
Chunk 6.
Chunk 7.
Chunk 8.
Chunk 9.
Chunk 10. Encyclopaedic information about chocolate mousse, including the assumption, A chocolate mousse is a dessert.
Of course, further levels of extension and many more extensions at each
level are possible, but we will stop here and consider what effect various
Relevance to an individual
147
continuations of the dialogue between Peter and Mary might have on
context selection.
Case A. Suppose first that Peter stops after saying, 'I'm tired'. Mary might
then have a thought which is relevant to her in the context (45). She may
for instance decide to make the dinner herself, which contextually implies
that she will do what Peter wishes. This contextual implication makes her
decision relevant not only to her but also to Peter, so she might decide to
inform him of it aqd say,
Case B. Suppose that the dialogue (repeated for convenience with the new
development italicised) continues as in (47):
148
Relevance
Chunk 11. Encyclopaedic information about the Capri restaurant, {ncluding the assumption, The speciality of the Capri restaurant
is osso-bucco.
Now clearly, some possible extensions of the context would diminish
overall relevance: for instance there would be no gain in contextual effects
from the addition of chunk 6 (information about surgery), and the extra
processing costs would lead to a loss of relevance. Other extensions,
however, would increase relevance. Suppose, for instance, that chunk 2
contains the assumption (50):
(50) Mary is tired.
With (50) added to the context, Peter's last remark contextually implies
(51):
(51) Peter would like them to go to the Capri restaurant.
Adding chunk 5, and in particular the information that Mary would like to
eat an osso-bucco, and chunk 11 (information about the Capri restaurant)
yields another contextual implication:
(52) Peter would like them to go to a restaurant the speciality of which is
what Mary would like to eat.
149
This leads in turn to many more contextual implications and strengthenings in a context containing information about Mary and .Peter (and about
osso-bucco ).
Case D. Suppose that the dialogue continues as in (53):
(53) Mary: What I would like to eat tonight is an osso-bucco.
Peter: I had a long day. I'm tired. I've just done a coronary bypass.
Peter's last remark is not relevant in the initial context (45a-c). However,
it is relevant in a context extended to include chunk 9 (information about
coronary bypass, including the assumption that performing a coronary
bypass is exhausting). This extension, which was accessible in three steps
from the initial context, has now become accessible in one step thanks to
the presence of the concept of a coronary bypass in Peter's utterance. In a
context so extended, the assumption that Peter has just done a coronary
bypass contextually strengthens (45a) (Peter is tired), and achieves
relevance thereby. This, then, is an illustration of situation (41e).
Case E. Suppose that the dialogue continues as in (54):
(54) Mary: What I would like to eat tonight is an osso-bucco.
Peter: I had a long day. I'm tired. I wish you would make the dinner
tonight, and, by the way, there's a dessert, a chocolate mousse, in the
refrigerator.
)
The first part of Peter's last remark ('I wish you would make the dinner
tonight') is relevant as described in the discussion of Case B.1t should lead
to the addition of chunk 3 (and in particular the assumption that a dinner
consists of at least a main course and a dessert) to the context, as described
in the discussion of Case A. This one-step extension makes chunk 7
(which contains the information that there is a chocolate mousse in the
refrigerator) accessible in one further step, which, in a third step, makes
accessible chunk 10 (which contains the information that a chocolate
mousse is a dessert).
From the assumptions that would be available in the memory of Mary's
deductive device if she carried out this three-step extension of the initial
context (45a-c), she would be able to deduce that all she has to do to make
the dinner is make a main course. The second part of Peter's last remark
('There's a dessert, a chocolate mousse, in the refrigerator') makes the
same conclusion available without her having to extend the context
beyond adding chunk 3. It also makes chunk 10 (information about
chocolate mousse) accessible in one step, without her having to go
through chunk 7 (the contents of the refrigerator).
Case E illustrates situation (41), and shows how a reminder may be
relevant: the effort needed to retrieve some relevant information from
150
Relevance
memory may be greater than the effort needed to get the same information
from the interpretation of an utterance. In these-circumstances, a reminder
is relevant: the contextual effects it produces could have been produced
otherwise, but more slowly and at a greater processing cost. On the other
hand, when a reminder comes after the context has been extended to
include the very information that the speaker is trying to bring to the
hearer's attention, then the extra effort needed to process an utterance
which carries no new contextual effects is wasted, and redundancy rather
than relevance is the result.
The five cases discussed above show how the ratker abstract notion of
relevance in a context can help with the construction of a psychologically
more significant notion of relevance to an individual. They also show the
crucial importance of the organisation of encyclopaedic memory in the
pursuit of relevance. In fact, the relation between memory and relevance is
so close that relevance theory might well shed new light on the
organisation of memory itself. For instance, the way in which information
is chunked may in principle help or hinder the search for relevance;
plausibly, forms of chunking which are a help rather than a hindrance tend
to predominate. Conversely, the pursuit of relevance may lead to the
faster building and enrichment of chunks of a certain form.
In this section we have characterised and illustrated a notion of
relevance to an individual. We have done this in an attempt to come closer
to a psychologically adequate notion of relevance, for use in describing
and explaining verbal comprehension and other cognitive processes. So
far, we have treated relevance as a property of assumptions. In particular,
we have equated the relevance of an utterance with the relevance of the
assumption it explicitly expresses. Yet hearers do not simply pick up the
assumption expressed by an utterance. More generally, individuals do not
simply pick up assumptions from their environment. In either case, a
complex cognitive process requiring mental effort is involved.
Conversely, a communicator cannot directly present an audience with
an assumption. All a speaker or any other type of communicator can do is
present a stimulus, hoping that its perception by members of the audience
will lead to a modification of their. cognitive environment and trigger
some cognitive processes. To the audience, a stimulus is initially just one
phenomenon among others: that is, just one perceptible feature of the
physical environment. It becomes identifiable as a stimulus only when it is
recognised as a phenomenon designed to achieve cognitive effects.
Which phenomena does the individual pay attention to? How does he
go about processing the information they make manifest? We want to
claim that he tends to pay attention to relevant phenomena, and to process
them so as to maximise relevance. However, to do this we have to
characterise relevance not just as a property of assumptions in the mind,
151
Why does he make some assumptions and not others? First, there are
certain assumptions he cannot avoid making in a given cognitive
environment. Take auditory perception. The faculty of auditory perception handles a great number and variety of noises, few of which reach the
level of attention: that is, lead to the construction and manipulation of
conceptual representations by the central thought processes. The mechanisms of auditory perception act as a filter, processing and filtering out most
acoustic information at a sub-attentive level. These sub-attentively
processed phenomena may come to the individual's attention, but only
when central thought processes turn to the perceptual mechanisms for
information about them.
However, some acoustic phenomena automatically pre-empt attention,
automatically give rise to assumptions and inferences at a conceptual level.
The perceptual mechanisms are organised so as to let certain types of
phenomena impinge on central thought processes. Some of these favoured
types of phenomena are probably innately determined: for instance~ the
152
Relevance
automatic attention paid to all sudden loud noises has contributed to the
survival of the species and is presumably an outcome of natural selection.
Other types of phenomena pre-empt attentio Il as a result of some form
of learning. The crying of a particular baby, even if barely audible,
pre-empts the attention of the parents. A smell of gas pre-empts the
attention of gas-users. Once the individual has smelled the gas, he cannot
help but make assumption (55), the assumption that there is such a smell.
The automatic filtering out of some phenomena and the automatic
pre-empting of attention by others can be seen as a heuristic device aimed
at maximising cognitive efficiency: in general, it is the phenomena which
are least likely to be relevant which get filtered out, and those most likely
to be relevant which pre-empt attention. In other words, the perceptual
mechanisms - and perceptual salience itself - are relevance-oriented.
Assumption (56), the assumption that there is a gas leak, is a contextual
implication of assumption (55) in a context containing ordinary encyclopaedic information about household uses of gas. We want to suggest that
assumption (56) is made in an attempt to maximise the relevance of
assumption (55); indeed it is particularly useful in this respect, since it
gives easy access to many other contextual effects. Precisely because the
processing of (55) is governed by the search for relevance, assumption (57)
is unlikely to be made: the processing effort needed to derive (57) is greater
than the effort needed to derive (56), and moreover (57) does not lead to
rich contextual effects achievable at a low processing cost.
A phenomenon can be more or less efficiently processed depending on
which, if any, of the assumptions it makes manifest are actually
constructed. For some phenomena, the best course is to filter them out at a
perceptual level. For others, it is to represent them conceptually and
process them in a rich encyclopaedic context. The notion of relevance can
thus be extended to phenomena in a straightforward way:
(58) Relevance of a phenomenon (classificatory)
A phenomenon is relevant to an individual if and only if one or more
of the assumptions it makes manifest is relevant to him.
A comparative definition is similarly straightforward. As always, we
will characterise the comparative notion of relevance in terms of effect and
effort. Here, what has to be taken into account on the effort side is not
only the effort needed to access a context and process an assumption in
that context, but also the effort needed to construct that assumption. The
construction and processing of different assumptions will involve different effects and amounts of effort, and hence different degrees of relevance.
For reasons discussed in the last section, we will characterise the relevance of
a phenomenon to an individual as the relevance achieved when it is
optimally processed. 8
153
We now define:
154
Relevance
the attention of the audience on the communicator's intentions. That is,
the assumption that the stimulus is ostensive must be both manifest
enough and relevant enough to lead tooptimal~processing. This condition
is generally met by stimuli which both pre-empt the attention and are
irrelevant unless treated as ostensive stimuli. This is clearly true of coded
signals used in ostensive communication, linguistic utterances in particular, which, unless treated as ostensive stimuli, are mere irrelevant noises or
marks on paper. It is also true of non-coded ostensive stimuli.
A non-coded ostensive stimulus may be an ordinary bodily movement,
with little intrinsic relevance, made with artificial- and attention-arresting
- rigidity: as when Peter leans back ostensivety to let Mary see William
coming (see chapter 1, section 9). It may be a piece of mimicry: for
instance, Mary might mimic the act of driving to communicate to Peter
that she wants to leave the party. Most of what such performances make
manifest is of little or no relevance. Someone has made some quite
ordinary bodily movement: so what? The only relevant assumptions
made manifest by such behaviour are assumptions about the individual's
informative intention.
The best ostensive stimuli are entirely irrelevant unless they are treated
as ostensive. Consider a case where an intrinsically highly relevant
stimulus is used - or misused - ostensively: say, somebody who is believed
to have her arms paralysed mimics the act of driving. Here, the fact that
she can move her arms would be so much more relevant than anything she
might have wanted to communicate that her informative intention might
well go unnoticed. Or to take a political example, acts of terrorism
designed to publicise a cause have so many important implications
irrespective of the terrorists' informative intention that they are much
better at attracting public attention than at conveying the intended
message.
However, it is not enough for the ostensive stimulus to attract attention
and focus it on the communicator's intentions. It must also reveal the
communicator's intentions. How can it do this? We will argue that what is
crucial here is that an ostensive stimulus comes with the communicator's
guarantee of relevance. b In general, there is no guarantee that a phenomenon will turn out to be relevant. Some phenomena are not relevant at
all, and are therefore not worth processing at a conceptual level; others
may be highly relevant, and may set off a whole train of thought. There
can be no a priori expectation of relevance for phenomena in general.
In the special case of ostensive stimuli, the situation is quite different.
By producing an utterance, the speaker requests her hearer's attention. By
requesting his attention, she suggests that her utterance is relevant enough
to be worth his attention. This applies not just to speech but to all forms of
ostensive communication. Ostensive stimuli arouse definite expectations
155
The principle of relevance
of relevance, of relevance achievable once the communicator's informative
intention is recognised. In the next section, we will develop this idea and
formalise it as a principle of relevance. Then, in the last section of this
chapter, we will show how the principle of relevance explains ostensiveinferential comunication.
As we said, this definition does not explain how ostension works: how the
ostensive stimulus makes manifest the communicator's informative
intention. We suggested that an answer to this question was to be sought
in a principle of relevance, but that such a principle would not be truly
explanatory until the notion of relevance had itself been explicitly
characterised. Having done this, we can now return to the principle of
relevance.
To achieve its effect, an act of ostensive communication must attract
the audience's attention. In that sense,9 an act of ostension is a request
for attention. Someone who asks you to behave in a certain way, either
physically or cognitively, suggests that he has good reason to think it
might be in your own interests, as well as his, to comply with his request.
This suggestion may be ill founded or made in bad faith, but it cannot be
wholly cancelled. If a request has been made at all, the requester must have
assumed that the requestee would have some motive for complying with
it. Even a blackmailer has to make it look preferable for his victim to
co-operate rather than to refuse; similarly, when a drowning man calls for
help, his only chance is that some passer-by will find it morally preferable,
however physically inconvenient, to help him.
Less dramatically, the host who asks his guests to eat automatically
suggests that what he is offering them is edible, and indeed worth eating.
Just as feeding someone normally requires the participation of the
recipient in the form of appropriate bodily behaviour, ostensive communlcation requires the participation of the recipient in the form of
appropriate cognitive behaviour, and in particular of attention. If Mary
requests Peter's attention by pointing to something in the landscape, or
holding something up for him to see, or talking to him, he is entitled to
156
Relevance
assume that the stimulus being drawn to his attention is relevant to him,
or at least that she has reason to think it is; if she gives him something to
think about, she must believe that he will find it good food for thought.
There is thus a substantial difference between the frame of mind in
which the individual may approach an ostensive stimulus directed at him
and the frame of mind in which he approaches other phenomena. When
attending to other phenomena, he may have hopes of relevance: if such
hopes were totally unwarranted, there would be no point in attending to
them at all. However, whether these hopes turn out to be justified depends
on a variety of factors, most of which are beyond \he individual's control,
and which he may not even be aware of. What makes these hopes
reasonable is that humans have a number of heuristics, some of them
innate, others developed through experience, aimed at picking out
relevant phenomena. Even so, hopes of relevance sometimes turn out to be
unjustified, and when they are justified, they are justified to a greater or
lesser extent: there can be no general expectation of a steady and
satisfactory level of relevance.
With an ostensive stimulus, however, the addressee can have not only
hopes, but also fairly precise expectations of relevance. It is manifest that
an act of ostensive communication cannot achieve its effect unless the
audience pays attention to the ostensive stimulus. It is manifest that people
will pay attention to a phenomenon only if it seems relevant to them. It
is manifest, then, that a communicator who produces an ostensive stimulus
must intend it to seem relevant to her audience: that is, must intend to
make it manifest to the audience that the stimulus is relevant. Adding a
layer of mutuality to this account, let us suppose that it is not merely
manifest but mutually manifest to communicator and audience that an
ostensive stimulus is being produced. Then it is not merely manifest but
mutually manifest that the communicator must intend the stimulus to
seem relevant to the audience: that is, must intend it to be manifest to the
audience that the stimulus is relevant. By our definition of ostensiveinferential communication, this amounts to saying that an ostensive communicator necessarily communicates that the stimulus she uses is relevant
to the audience. In other words, an act of ostensive communication
automatically communicates a presumption of relevance.
What is the exact content of the presumption of relevance communicated by an act of ostensive communication? As we have said, what is
communicated is that to the best of the communicator's knowledge, the
ostensive stimulus is relevant enough to be worth the audience's attention.
No weaker guarantee would do. But the presumption of relevance is more
specific than this. The relevance of a stimulus is determined by two
factors: the effort needed to process it optimally, and the cognitive effects
157
158
Relevance
159
160
Relevance
being put on display in the local bookshop, it would be reasonable for her
to say to Peter,
(63) Iris Murdoch's new book is in the bookshops.
It may turn out that Peter already has this information, in which case
utterance (63) will in fact be irrelevant to him. However, it would still have
been perfectly appropriate, and the presumption of relevance would have
been communicated in good faith, because Mary has at least tried to be
optimally relevant. Moreover, the risk she took was reasonable: it was
worth taking because of the hope, if she had succeeded, of achieving a high
degree of relevance to Peter.
How much effort the addressee can expect the communicator to put
into being relevant varies with the circumstances, the communicator, and
the relationship between communicator and addressee. Lecturers are
expected to try very hard to be relevant; students are allowed, and
sometimes even encouraged, to communicate without being hampered by
the fear of being irrelevant. A master talking to his servant may say
whatever he wishes and merely assume that it will be relevant enough; a
servant addressing his master is expected to have made quite sure that he
has something relevant to say.
161
162
Relevance
this is very often true, particularly in conversation. lO In a talk exchange,
a seminar or a book, there may well be a mutually manifest purpose or
direction. However, this does not follow from the principle of relevance,
and is not automatically conveyed by every ostensive stimulus. Knowledge of such a common purpose, when it exists, is one contextual factor
among others, and it is only as such that it can play a role in
comprehension. cl
Achieving optimal relevance, then, is less demanding than obeying the
Gricean maxims. In particular, it is possible to be optimally relevant
without being 'as informative as is required' by die current purposes of the
exchange (Grice's first maxim of quantity): for instance by keeping secret
something that it would be relevant to the audience to know. It seems to us
to be a matter of common experience that the degree of co-operation
described by Grice is not automatically expected of communicators.
Peo~le who don't give us all the information we wish they would, and
don't answer our questions as well as they could, are no doubt much to
blame, but not for violating principles of communication.
A more radical difference between Grice's approach and relevance
theory is this. Grice's principle and maxims are norms which communicators and audience must know in order to communicate adequately.
Communicators generally keep to the norms, but may also violate them to
achieve particular effects; and the audience uses its knowledge of the
norms in interpreting communicative behaviour.
The principle of relevance, by contrast, is a generalisation about
ostensive-inferential communication. Communicators and audience need
no more know the principle of relevance to communicate than they need
to know the principles of genetics to reproduce. Communicators do not
'follow' the principle of relevance; and they could not violate it even if
they wanted to. The principle of relevance applies without exception:
every act of ostensive communication communicates a presumption of
relevance. It is not the general principle, but the fact that a particular
presumption of relevance has been communicated by and about a
particular act of communication, that the audience uses in inferential
comprehension. ll
However, the most important difference between Grice's approach and
ours has to do with the explanation of communication. Grice's account of
conversation starts from a distinction between what is explicitly said and
what is implicated. No explanation of explicit communication is given;
essentially, the code model, with a code understood as a set of
conventions, is assumed to apply. Implicatures are explained as assumptions that the audience must make to preserve the idea that the speaker has
obeyed the maxims, or at least the co-operative principle. The principle of
Ostensive-inferential communication
163
164
Relevance
communicator's informative intention reduces, then, to the problem of
identifying the set of assumptions I.
What the principle of relevance does is identify one member of I:
namely, the presumption of relevance. The presumption of relevance
is not just a member of I, it is also about I. As a result, it can be
confirmed or disconfirmed by the contents of I. The possibilities of
confirmation and disconfirmatIOn are different for the two different parts
(61a) and (61b) of the presumption of relevance, repeated here for
(61) Presumption of optimal relevance
(a) The set of assumptions I which the communicator intends to
make manifest to the addressee is relevant enough to make it
worth the addressee's while to process the ostensive stimulus.
(b) The ostensive stimulus is the most relevant one the communicator
could have used to communicate I.
For the addressee, every assumption about the contents of I either
verifies (61a) - I is relevant enough - or else falsifies it. There may be
borderline cases, sets of assumptions on the margin of being relevant
enough. However, there cannot be cases for which there is insufficient
evidence, sets of assumptions whose relevance cannot be assessed by the
addressee: in processing I, he automatically discovers how relevant it is.
With the second part of the presumption of relevance, (61b), things need
not be so clear-cut. Given an assumption about the contents of I, it may
be manifest that the communicator could have used a more relevant
stimulus, and this will falsify (61b). However, (61b) may be neither
falsified nor verified: after all, in ordinary conditions, the addressee does
not know exactly what range of stimuli the communicator had at her
disposal, and hence cannot be sure that she has used the most relevant one
to communicate I. The presumption of relevance as a whole, then,
should either be clearly falsified (in the case where either (61a) or (61b) is
falsified), or be merely confirmed, but not verified (in the case where (61a)
is verified and (61b) is not falsified).
For some assumptions in I, all the evidence the communicator gives
the addressee is indirect: the addressee's only reason for accepting them is
the communicator's mutually manifest intention that he should. For other
assumptions in I, the communicator also provides direct evidence, as
when Peter ostensively leans back to let Mary see who is coming. The
status of the presumption of relevance is altered by the comprehension
process itself. At the start of the comprehension process, the initial
evidence for the presumption of relevance is entirely indirect; it is entirely
based on the communicator's guarantee that her stimulus is optimally
relevant to the addressee. However, by processing the stimulus, the
Ostensive-inferential communication
165
166
Relevance
there, the search stops; otherwise, he will search a second place, and so on.
These two strategies, listing and ranking hypotheses, or searching for
hypotheses and testing them one by one, are suited to different types of
tasks. The first strategy is ill suited to tasks where it would be impossible
or inconvenient to list all possible hypotheses. For instance, if the task is to
find a pupil who is neither the tallest nor the shortest in the school, it
would be a waste of effort to rank all the pupils by height. The second
strategy is ill suited to tasks where there is no decisive criterion that can b
applied to isolated hypotheses. For instance, it would be impossible to
find out which is the tallest pupil in a school without taking all the pupils
mto account.
For other tasks, neither the list-and-rank strategy nor the item-by-item
testing strategy is appropriate on its own. The search for a true scientific
theory cannot be based on an examination of all possible theories, since we
do not know what these are; nor can it be based on a criterion which could
be used to decide whether an isolated theory is true. The strategy of
scientific discovery is much more complex, and involves both comparison
and individual testing; its results are, in principle at least, never final. As
we have pointed out, in this respect comprehension is unlike scientific
discovery: it yields final results almost immediately, which suggests that a
rather simple strategy must be involved.
Could comprehension be achieved by listing and ranking all possible
hypotheses about the communicator's informative intention? The idea
may seem attractive if comprehension is seen as a simple matter of
decoding a signal into a small set of possible messages and then choosing
among them. It must be rejected, however, because neither the possible
figurative interpretations of a coded message, nor its possible implicatures,
are enumerable. We will argue that this is true even when unambiguously
coded signals are used as stimuli. Moreover, even if it were possible to list
all the possible interpretations of an ostensive stimulus, it would still be
absurdly inconvenient. As we have seen, one of the factors which makes
one interpretation more relevant than others is that it requires less
processing effort. If the only way of finding the right interpretation were
to list and rank all possible interpretations, then all possible interpretations would require the same amount of effort: namely, the effort needed
to construct and compare them. It is hard to think of any ostensive
stimulus that would be worth such an absurd amount of effort.
Could comprehension be achieved, then, by constructing an initial
hypothesis, testing it, and moving on to a second one if the first is not
adequate? At first sight it might seem that here again the answer must be
no. Let us say that an interpretation is consistent with the principle of
relevance if and only if a rational communicator might have expected it to
be optimally relevant to the addressee.e Suppose now that the addressee
Ostensive-inferential communication
167
168
Relevance
maximise cognitive efficiency, will test hypotheses in order of accessibility. Suppose he arrives at a hypothesis which is consistent ~ith the
principle of relevance. Should he stop there, or go on and test the next
hypothesis on the ground that it might be consistent with the principle of
relevance too? It is easy to show that he should stop there. Suppose he
does go on, and finds another hypothesis which verifies the first part of the
presumption of relevance: the putative set I is relevant enough. In these
circumstances, the second part of the presumption of relevance is almost
invariably falsified. If it was at all possible, the communicator should have
used a stimulus which would have saved the addressee the effort of first
accessing two hypotheses consistent with the principle of relevance, and
then having to choose between them.
Consider the following utterance, for instance:
(65) George has a big cat.
Ostensive-inferential communication
169
170
Relevance
Ostensive-inferential communication
171
4
Aspects of verbal
. .
communicatIon
173
174
175
176
177
178
B's first reply communicates that the treatment worked well, not by
saying so, but by producing direct evidence that it did. Properly speaking,
this is not a case of verbal communication, and it falls outside the scope of
pragmatics. Verbal communication proper begins when an utterance, such
as B's second reply, is manifestly chosen by the speaker for its semantic
propertIes.
In other words, verbal communication proper begins when the speaker
is recognised not just as talking, not even just as communicating by
talking, but as saying something to someone. Most utterances do this, of
course, and an adequate account of verbal communication must explain
why. One way of explaining it is to assume that people learn, or are
innately equipped with, more or less ad hoc pragmatic rules to the effect
that utterances should be used for communication only in virtue of their
semantic properties. 2 However, this leaves exceptions such as (6) to be
explained.
A simpler explanation follows from the principle of relevance. According to relevance theory, the correct interpretation of an ostensive stimulus
is the first accessible interpretation consistent with the principle of
relevance. For most utterances, this will be an interpretation based on
semantic properties: the other properties of the utterance are generally not
relevant enough to yield an interpretation consistent with the principle of
relevance. In odd cases such as (6), the semantic properties of the
utterance do not yield an appropriate interpretation and other properties
(in this case acoustic properties) do. The principle of relevance thus
explains both the usual, semantically based cases of utterance interpretation and the occasional exceptions.
Suppose that Mary's behaviour is an ordinary case of verbal communication - that is, that it makes manifest assumption (7):
(7) Mary has said to Peter 'It will get cold.'
(8):
179
180
might help.3 Moreover, the complexity of the task is generally underestimated: it is seen as simply a matter of choosing a single sense and reference
from a limited set of alternatives. The fact that logical forms must often be
enriched is generally ignored; no explanation is given of how such
enrichment can be achieved.
Suppose Peter has decided that 'It' refers to the dinner, that 'will' refers
to the immediate future, and that 'cold' means inducing cold. In other
words, he has decided that the propositional form expressed by Mary's
utterance is (lad):
(10) (d) The dinner will get cold very soon.
However, a hearer can recover (lab) but still not know what propositional
attitude Mary intended to communicate; and without knowing this, he
will be unable to decide what she intended to communicate apart from
(lab) itself. In particular, even though Mary has said that the dinner will
get cold very soon, she need not be asserting that the dinner will get cold
very soon. Asserting that P involves communicating that one believes that
P. However, in the weak sense of 'saying that' which corresponds to the
declarative mood, one can say that P without communicating that one
believes that P. For example, in saying that the dinner will get cold very
soon, Mary might be speaking metaphorically or ironically, in which case
she would not communicate that she believes that the dinner will get cold
very soon.
181
182
183
The main problem with Grice's distinction has to do not with the
characterisation of implicatures, but with the characterisation of the
explicit. First, he does not envisage the kind of enrichment of logical form
involved, for instance, in interpreting 'will' as will very soon; he treats
comparable cases, for instance the interpretation of 'and' as and then in
some contexts, as cases of implicature. Most Gricean pragmatists assume
without question that any pragmatically determined aspect of utterance
interpretation apart from disambiguation and reference assignment is
necessarily an implicature. In fact, recent work has shown that a number
of problems with classical implicature analyses are resolved when the
'implicatures' are re analysed as pragmatically determined aspects of
explicit content. 4
Second, Grice says very little about how propositional attitudes are
communicated, and it is unclear what he would regard as 'explicit' and
what 'implicit' here. Third, he has no notion of degrees of explicitness.
Generally speaking, we see the explicit side of communication as richer,
more inferential, and hence more worthy of pragmatic investigation than
do most pragmatists in the Gricean tradition.
In the next two sections, we show how relevance theory accounts for
the recovery of the propositional form of an utterance (section 3) and its
implicatures (section 4)~ For simplicity of exposition, we will look only at
ordinary assertions, i.e. utterances which communicate their propositional forms. In the final sections of this chapter we will generalise our
treatment to other types of utterance.
184
185
use to identify propositional forms which meet this criterion? Here again,
the outline of an answer is strongly suggested by the principle of
relevance. At every stage in disambiguation, reference assignment and
enrichment, the hearer should choose the solution involving the least
effort, and should abandon this solution only if it fails to yield an
interpretation consistent with the principle of relevance.
We will now look separately at the three sub-tasks involved in the
identification of propositional form: disambiguation, reference assignment and enrichment. One problem we immediately encounter is that we
cannot avoid the use of artificial examples. When an artificial example is
produced, say as part of a theoretical discussion or in an experimental
situation, it is processed and understood in isolation from any natural
context. This is not to say that it is processed and understood in isolation
from any context. In the first place, it gives access to encyclopaedic
information about the objects and events referred to, and hence to a range
of potential contexts of the usual type; in the second place, the author or
experimenter may provide some elements of a natural context by
describing a setting, asking the individual to imagine a previous utterance,
and so on.
Even so, artificial examples tend to favour considerations of effort over
considerations of effect in the assessment of relevance. In the absence of
real-life contextual constraints, or constraints specially set up by the
experimenter, hearers automatically construct a context which yields the
least effort-consuming conceivable interpretation. It would thus be easy,
on the basis of artificial examples, to conclude that the identification of
propositional form is entirely determined by a principle of least effort.
The existence of garden-path utterances such as (13) should prevent us
from making such a mistake.
Though effort is only one of the two factors involved in the assessment
of relevance, it is a factor well worth studying, and here there is an
advantage in the fact that it is to some extent isolated by artificial examples.
We are assuming that the identification of propositional form involves
two mental mechanisms: a linguistic input module and a central inferential
ability. How are the two mechanisms related, and how does the effort
made by each affect the overall processing effort? More specifically, does
the linguistic input module construct all the possible semantic representations of a sentence, one of which is then selected by centtal processes? Or
are the semantic representations of a sentence more or less effortconsuming for the input module to construct, so that the easiest one is
constructed first, a second representation being constructed only if the
first is rejected, and so on? In other words, how are the 'wrong'
interpretations filtered out?
These questions are not going to be answered at the purely speculative
186
187
constituent which are linguistically compatible with the selected interpretation of the first constituent, and so on. With the interaction of input
module and central mechanisms so conceived, it remains true that ~the
module has no access to encyclopaedic contextual information; however,
contextual factors may affect its processes in a purely inhibitory way.
For example, when (17), the first part of (13), has been decoded, the
central mechanism is in a position to choose between an interpretation on
which 'that' is a demonstrative determiner, and one on which it is a
complementiser:
(17) I saw that ...
(13) I saw that gasoline can explode.
188
189
The identification of propositional form
by disambiguation and reference assignment. Quite often, semantlC
representations must also be enriched. This task is, of course, an
inferential one. Consider (23):
190
191
192
193
In the last section we showed how the principle of relevance guides the
identification of propositional form. In section 10, we will discuss the
identification of the speaker's propositional attitude. From the context,
the propositional form of the utterance and the propositional attitude
expressed, all the explicatures of the utterance can be inferred. For the time
being, we will continue to look only at ordinary assertions, where the
propositional form is itself an explicature, and indeed the explicature on
which most of the contextual effects of the utterance, and therefore most
of its relevance, depend. In this section, we will show how the principle of
194
195
196
It follows from the principle of relevance that in giving the indirect answer
in (33b), she must have expected to achieve some additional contextual
197
effects not obtainable from (36), which would offset the additional effort
needed to process (33b), supply premise (34) and deduce (35) as an
implicated conclusion. More generally, it follows from the principle of
relevance that the surplus of information given in an indirect answer must
achieve some relevance in its own right.
It does not follow, though, that there is any specific implicature, apart
from (34) and (35), which Mary must have expected Peter to recover. An
act of communication merely makes manifest which assumptions the
communicator intends to make manifest, or, equivalently, it merely makes
these assumptions manifest on the further assumption that the communicator is trustworthy. It does not necessarily make the audience actually
entertain all the assumptions communicated. This is true of implicatures
too. Implicatures are merely made manifest by the act of communication
(again, on the further assumption that the speaker is trustworthy). Some
implicatures are made so strongly manifest that the hearer can scarcely
avoid recovering them. Others are made less strongly manifest. It is
enough that the hearer should pay attention to some of these weaker
implicatures for the relevance of the intended interpretation to become
manifest.
As we have seen, utterance (33b) gives Peter access to his encyclopaedic
information about expensive cars. One 'obvious line of interpretation
would be to retrieve the names of other expensive cars, and derive the
conclusion that Mary would not drive them. It is a stereotypical - and
hence highly accessible - item of general knowledge that a Rolls Royce
and a Cadillac are expensive cars. Hence it would be reasonable for Peter
to add premises (37) and (38) to the context, derive conclusions (39) and
(40), and investigate their contextual effects:
(37)
(38)
(39)
(40)
198
199
200
Aspects of verbal communication
conclusions strongly encourages the hearer to use some subset of these
premises or conclusions, and to regard some subset of them - not
necessarily the same subset - as part of the speaker's beliefs. An utterance
with a wide range of weakly implicated premises or conclusions again
encourages the hearer to use some subset of these assumptions, and to
regard some subset of them - again not necessarily the same - as part of the
speaker's beliefs. Clearly, the weaker the implicatures, the less confidence
the hearer can have that the particular premises or conclusions he supplies
will reflect the speaker's thoughts, and this is where the indeterminacy
lies. However, people may entertain different thoughts and come to have
different beliefs on the basis of the same cognitive environment. The aim
of communication in general is to increase the mutuality of cognitive
environments rather than guarantee an impossible duplication of
thoughts.
To conclude this section, we want to contrast our approach with other
approaches to implicature. First, in our framework, there is no connection
between conveying an implicature and violating a pragmatic principle or
maxim. Gricean implicatures fall into two classes: those where there is no
violation or where the violation is only apparent, and those where the
violation is genuine and even the recovery of an implicature does not
restore the assumption that the maxims have been observed. For us, this
second class of examples must be reanalysed.
In the second place, we have taken seriously Grice's requirement that
implicatures should be calculable: that is, recoverable by an inference
process. In Grice's framework, and the framework of most pragmatists,
some sort of ex post facto justification for the identification of an
implicature can be given, but the argument could have worked equally
well for quite different assumptions which happen not to be implicated at
all. This is particularly true of the second class of implicatures, those
resulting from deliberate violation of the maxims; they tend to violate the
calculability requirement in a particularly blatant way.
Consider Grice's analysis of irony, for example. Mary says (49), and in
doing so patently violates the first maxim of quality (truthfulness):
(49) Jim is a fine friend.
Peter, assuming that Mary must have been trying to convey some true
information, looks around for some true assumption related to (49),
which she might have wanted to convey. He decides that she must have
wanted to convey the opposite of what she has said:
(50) Jim is not a fine friend.
201
However, 'looking around for some related assumption which the speaker
might have wanted to convey' does not count as an inference process:
such a process is virtually free of rational constraints. Why, for instance,
should Peter not decide that (49) is to be interpreted as conveying the
closely related (51), as long as (51) is something that Mary might have
wanted to convey?10
(51) Bill is a fine friend.
Relevance theory does not sanction the analysis of (49) as meaning (50)
- unless (49) is recognisably a slip of the tongue - if only because a speaker
who merely wanted to convey (50) could have spared her hearer some
unnecessary processing effort by asserting it directly. In section 9 we will
propose an alternative account.
The reason why standard accounts of implicature do not always satisfy
the calculability requirement on implicatures is that the calculation of
implicatures is a matter of non-demonstrative inference. It involves a
partly non-logical process of assumption formation; then the assumption
has to be confirmed. Standard accounts impose few if any constraints on
the formation of assumptions. In practice, they just take what is the
intuitively correct assumption and show that it is consistent with Gricean
maxims or with some other principles, constraints or rules of the same
kind. Intuitively wrong assumptions, such as the assumption that the
speaker of (49) means (51) are, alas, just as easy to 'confirm' in this way.
Relevance theory solves this problem by looking not just at the
cognitive effects of an assumption, but also at the processing effort it
requires. The psychological processes by which assumptions are formed
determine their accessibility, which affects their relevance, which affects
their plausibility. Different assumptions are thus predicted to differ in
plausibility before any confirmation process takes place. When an initially
more plausible interpretation is found to be consistent with the principle
of relevance, then it is uniquely confirmed, and all less initially plausible
interpretations are disconfirmed.
Another important point to have emerged from this section has to do
with the scope of pragmatics. The idea that pragmatics should be
concerned purely with the recovery of an enumerable set of assumptions,
some explicitly expressed, others implicitly conveyed, but all individually
intended by the speaker, seems to us to be a mistake. We have argued that
there is a continuum of cases, from implicatures which the hearer was
specifically intended to recover to implicatures which were merely
intended to be made manifest, and to further modifications of the mutual
cognitive environment of speaker and hearer that the speaker only
intended in the sense that she intended her utterance to be relevant, and
hence to have rich and not entirely foreseeable cognitive effects. Pragmat-
202
ists and semioticians who look only at the strongest forms of implicature
have a badly distorted image of verbal communication. They miss, or at
least fail to explain, the subtler effects achieved by much implicit
communication. We will return to the role of weak implicatures when we
discuss style and tropes in sections 6 and 7. But first we want to consider
some of the ways in which linguistic form affects pragmatic interpretation.
203
204
205
VP
NP
John
NP
invited
Lucy
206
(58)
someone
John
did something
invited
someone
Lucy
A propositional representation of the fact that John invited Lucy would
then carry, via the labels on the nodes of its tree structure, the information
that someone invited someone, that someone invited Lucy, that John
invited someone, that John did something, and so on.
On this approach, there is a clear sense in which the logical category
labels correspond to, and are indeed semantic interpretations of, syntactic
category labels of natural language (though there need not be a one-one
correspondence). As a result, a hearer who has made the anticipatory
syntactic hypothesis that, say, the words 'John invited' will be followed
by an NP, can by semantically interpreting this anticipatory syntactic
hypothesis derive the anticipatory logical hypothesis that John invited
someone. We see such hypotheses as playing a crucial role in disambiguation and reference assignment.
Let us assume that when he hears the word 'Jennifer' in (59), the hearer
accesses a range of possible referents for 'Jennifer' - that is, a set of
conceptual addresses with the word 'Jennifer' as part of their lexical entry
- and gains access in turn to a range of associated encylopaedic entries:
(59) Jennifer admitted STEALING.
On assigning 'Jennifer' to the syntactic category NP, he makes the
anticipatory syntactic hypothesis that it will be followed by a VP, which
yields by variable-substitution the anticipatory logical hypothesis (60):
(60) Jennifer did something.
Let us assume that he knows a Jennifer Smith and a Jennifer O'Hara. Our
hypothesis is that he now proceeds to make a tentative assignment of
reference to the expression 'Jennifer' by considering whether the information that Jennifer Smith did something or the information that Jennifer
O'Hara did something might be relevant to him in some context he
currently has accessible.
207
If so, then he should provisionally accept that interpretation and retain the
context for further processing.
208
209 .
210
care too much about where the cut-off point between foreground and
background will come. That is, she need have no specific intention about
which of the implications of her utterance are foreground and which
background (which are given and which new), contrary to what is
normally accepted in the literature.
We can also shed some light on the intuition that there is a gradient of
given and new information. Wherever the cut-off point between foreground and background comes, there is a clear sense in which (64b), for
example, simultaneously acts as a foreground implication in relation to
(64a), giving a partial answer to the question it:raises, and as a background
implication in relation to (64c), raising a question to which (64c) gives at
least a partial answer. As we have seen, even (64c), which is necessarily a
foreground implication, may simultaneously raise a background question
which some subsequent utterance (or a continuation of the same
utterance) will answer. Our distinction between foreground and background, like our notion of focus itself, is thus a purely functional one, and
should play no role in the linguistic description of sentences.
Different stress assignments induce different focal scales If the focally
stressed constituent were 'Jennifer', the focal scale for (59) would be (65):
(65) (a) Someone confessed to stealing/
Who confessed to stealing?
(b) J ennifer confessed to stealing.
If the focally stressed constituent were the verb 'admitted', the focal scale
would be (66):
(66) (a) Jennifer did something/
What did J ennifer do?
(b) J ennifer did something regarding stealing/
What did Jennifer do regarding stealing?
(c) J ennifer confessed to stealing.
(65) and (66) have the same logical properties as (64): each consists of a
series of logically related members, each member analytically implying the
immediately preceding member and being analytically implied by the
immediately following member. Moreover, each is obtainable by the same
general procedure: take the full propositional form of the utterance and
replace by a logical variable, first the interpretation of the focally stressed
constituent, then the interpretation of the next smallest syntactic constituent which contains the focally stressed constituent, and so on until there
are no more inclusive constituents to be replaced.
However, there is an important difference between (64) on the one hand
and (65) and (66) on the other, linked to the fact that, in the two latter
cases, the focal stress is not on the last word of the sentence. As a result, the
211
Peter:
Mary:
Mary:
Mary:
212
213
)
)
s
e
c
cs
le
re
is
214
215
between foreground and background implications. The strongest presuppositional effects are carried by analytic implications of background
implications. Thus, if the focus in (73a) is 'the Exhibition', or 'visited the
Exhibition', and the background is The King of France did something, or
The King of France visited something, the information that there is a King
of France will be analytically implied by the background, and a hearer
who rejects it will be unable to access a context in which the utterance
would be relevant at all. By contrast, if the focus in (73 b) is 'the King of
France', or 'was visited by the King of France', and the background is The
Exhibition had some property, or The Exhibition was visited by someone,
then at least the hearer will be able to access the appropriate context and
see what sort of contextual effects the speaker must have had in mind.
Hence the intuition that in this case the consequences of reference failure
are less dramatic.
Turning to examples (53a-c), triples of this type are often seen as
showing the need for two separate distinctions, one based on left-right
word order and the other on intonational prominence:
(53)(a) It rained on MONDAY.
(b) On Monday it RAINED.
(c) On MONDAY it rained.
Thus Halliday (1967-8) distinguishes thematic or textual structure, based
on left-right word order, from informational structure, based on intonational prominence. He defines the theme as the leftmost syntactic
constituent in the sentence and the rheme as everything that follows. The
theme-rheme distinction, like the focus-presupposition distinction, is
often seen as genuinely linguistic: thus Brown and Yule (1983: 133) claim
that 'theme is a formal category in the analysis of sentences'. In our
framework the differences between (53a), (53 b) and (53c) can be
accounted for without introducing theme as a formal category at all.
We have seen that (53a) has a range of possible foci: 'Monday', 'on
Monday' and the sentence as a whole. It is thus construable as an answer to
the questions, 'On what day did it rain?', 'When did it rain?' and 'What
happened?' The effect of (53 b) and (53c) is to modify this range of possible
interpretations. By the time the hearer of (53 b) has processed the words
'On Monday', he knows that there is some question about what happened
on Monday which the speaker thinks is relevant to him. In other words,
the effect of fronting the unstressed constituent 'On Monday' is to force it
into the background. By the same token, by the time the hearer of (53c)
has processed the words 'On Monday', he should know that they give the
answer to some question which he should at this point be able to access for
himself. In other words, the effect of fronting the stressed constituent 'On
Monday' is to select it as focus. Sentences such as (53b) and (53c) may
216
involve slightly greater processing costs than (53a); if so, this would be the
price paid for fixing an adverbial expression in the background while
retaining utterance-final stress, or of pinpointing the focus more precisely
than its normal syntactic position would permit. However, the special
effects of such structures arise simply from the interaction between
syntax, stress assignment and the principle of relevance. While the
theme-rheme distinction may be a valuable way of highlighting intuitions,
it has no place in the technical descriptive vocabulary of either linguistics
or pragmatics.
The classic paper on the topic-comment distinction is Reinhart (1981).
She defines the 'sentence topic' as a syntactic constituent, explicitly
present in the sentence, whose referent the sentence is about; many
authors also appeal to a vaguer notion of 'discourse topic'. In general,
sentence topics will be both unstressed and early in the word order. Thus
in (54a) the sentence topic is John-Paul the Second, in (54b) it is the present
Pope:
(54)(a) John-Paul the Second is the present POPE.
(b) The present Pope is John-Paul the SECOND.
(c) It is John-Paul the SECOND who is the present Pope.
As regards the pragmatic role of topics, there is a general agreement that
their function is to provide access to what in our terms would be
contextual information crucial to the comprehension process. Thus the
classic discourse topics are titles and picture captions, whose role is
precisely to give access to encyclopaedic information crucial to the
comprehension of the accompanying texts or pictures; by the same token,
sentence topics are generally unstressed syntactic constituents occurring
early in the utterance, whose function in our framework is to give access to
encyclopaedic information which the speaker regards as crucial to the
interpretation process.
One reason for looking seriously at the literature on topics is that it is
often claimed that the most basic notion of relevance, the one it is most
important to define, is that of relevance to a topic. Thus Brown and Yule
(1983: 68) comment that though the notion of topic is 'very difficult to pin
down' it is nonetheless 'essential to concepts such as relevance and
coherence'. Given the role of topics in providing access to contexts, these
comments are not too surprising. To the extent that an utterance is
relevant (in our sense) in a homogeneous context derivable from a single
encyclopaedic entry, it will be topic relevant (in a derivative sense), the
topic being simply the conceptual address associated with that encyclopaedic entry. However, in our framework an utterance may also be
relevant in a non-homogeneous context - that is, a context derived from a
variety of encyclopaedic and environmental sources - in which it should
217
218
219
In circumstances that are easy to imagine, (76) might convey that there are
two red socks; (77) that the speaker went for a very long walk; (78) that
there were a great many houses, (79) that the speaker will definitely never
smoke again, (80) that the speaker was excited about the fox in the garden;
and (81) that she was moved by the disappearance of her childhood days.
Thus the 'emphatic' effects of repetition are worked out in different ways
for different examples. In particular, they may be reflected in the
propositional content of the utterance, as in (76)-(78), in the speaker's
degree of commitment to that propositional content, as in (79), or in some
other expression of the speaker's attitude, as in (80) and (81).
221
hearer would otherwise have thought. Realising that her utterance will be
sceptically received, she repeats the word 'never', the likely target of the
scepticism, to convince the hearer that she means what she says. In other
words, 'never, never' is here similar in import to 'definitely never', and
reflects the speaker's degree of commitment to the assumption expressed.
This strengthens the explicature and all its contextual implications,
thereby increasing the contextual effects of the utterance.
With (80) and (81), none of the above interpretations works well. No
increase in effect is likely to be achieved either by enriching the
propositional form, or by strengthening the implicatures. We want to
suggest that in these cases, the repetition should yield an increase in
contextual effects by encouraging the hearer to extend the context and
thereby add further implicatures. The repetition in (80) cannot be
accounted for by assuming that there are several foxes in the garden, or by
strengthening the assumption that there is a fox. Instead, the hearer of (80)
is being encouraged to dig deeper into his encyclopaedic entry for fox,
with a guarantee that the extra processing effort will be outweighed by a
gain in contextual effects: the fact that there's a fox in the garden is
presented as more relevant than the hearer would have spontaneously
realised.
Similarly, the repetition in (81) cannot be accounted for by assuming
that the speaker's childhood days are longer gone, or more definitely
gone, than might otherwise have been assumed, so if the presumption of
relevance is to be confirmed, then the repetition of 'gone' must be
interpreted as an encouragement to expand the context. There is a
difference between (80) and (81), though. Paying attention to the fact that
there is a fox in the garden, and making the effort to remember basic facts
about foxes, is likely to yield some strong and predictable contextual
implications, such as 'The chickens are in danger'. These strong implications are likely to be interpreted as strong implicatures of the utterance. In
the case of (81), the extra relevance is more likely to be achieved by a more
diversified expansion of the context and by a wider array of weaker
implicatures. In other words, the hearer is encouraged to be imaginative
and to take a large share of responsibility in imagining what it may be for
the speaker to be way past her youth.
Compare the interpretation of (81) and (82):
(81) My childhood days are gone, gone.
(82) My childhood days are gone.
222
(83) Mary went on holiday to the mountains, Joan to the sea, and Lily to
the country.
(84) Mary lives in Oxford, J oan in York, and Lily in a skyscraper.
(85) Mary came with Peter, Joan with Bob, and Lily with a sad smile on
her face.
In each of these examples there are clear syntactic, semantic and
phonological parallelisms. These reinforce the hearer's natural tendency
to reduce processing effort by looking for matching parallelisms in
propositional form and implicatures. In (83), for instance, the missing VP
in the second and third clause can safely be assumed to be 'went on
holiday'. Moreover, the same easily accessible context - scenarios of
typical holidays - enables the three clauses to yield parallel contextual
effects, with some conclusions true of Mary, Joan and Lily, and others
contrasting their respective holidays on fairly standard dimensions of
comparison. A speaker aiming at optimal relevance would deliberately
introduce such linguistic parallelisms only if she expected them to lead to a
reduction in the hearer's processing effort, and in particular, if she thought
that the search for parallel contexts and contextual effects would be
223
224
spell out along a whole variety of lines. In this way the required
parallelisms of context and contextual effects could be maintained. The
result would be a wide range of fairly weak implicatures.
In (83), (84) and (85), because of the form of the utterance, the search
for an interpretation consistent with the principle of relevance induces a
certain processing strategy; in the case of (83) this strategy yields an
unremarkable interpretation; the contribution to relevance made by the
form of the utterance is merely to reduce processing effort. In the case of
(84), and even more so of (85), this strategy takes the hearer beyond
standard contexts and premises, and yields typical poetic effects.
How do poetic effects affect the mutual cognitive environment of
speaker and hearer? They do not add entirely new assumptions which are
strongly manifest in this environment. Instead, they marginally increase
the manifestness of a great many weakly manifest assumptions. In other
words, poetic effects create common impressions rather than common
knowledge. Utterances with poetic effects can be used precisely to create
this sense of apparently affective rather than cognitive mutuality. What we
are suggesting is that, if you look at these affective effects through the
microscope of relevance theory, you see a wide array of minute cognitive
effects.
Poetic effects, we claim, result from the accessing of a large array of very
weak implicatures in the otherwise ordinary pursuit of relevance. Stylistic
differences are just differences in the way relevance is achieved. One way
in which styles may differ is in their greater or lesser reliance on poetic
effects, just as they may differ in their greater or lesser reliance on
implicature and in the way they exploit the backgrounding and foregrounding of information in their explicatures.
225
IS
not an
226
227
eating, that the information you are communicating is worth his attention,
that the stimulus you use is economical, that you are therefore not
gratuitously making him entertain the mental representation of a dog
biting, and that the first inferable interpretation consistent with these
assumptions should be the right one.
In appropriate conditions, any natural or artificial phenomenon in the
world can be used as a representation of some other phenomenon which it
resembles in some respects. Having climbed the walls of the villa, the first
thief silently imitates a dog biting to warn her accomplice at the foot of the
wall. You ask me what is the shape of Brazil, and for answer I point to an
appropriately shaped cloud in the sky. Mary wants to communicate to
Peter that she would like to leave the party, and she mimics the act of
driving.
Utterances can be used as representations in another way, too: not in
virtue of resembling some phenomenon, but in virtue of having a
propositional form which is true of some actual or conceivable state of
affairs. In the case of an assertion, for instance, the propositional form of
the utterance is used to represent some state of affairs in the real world; in
the case of a request, the propositional form of the utterance is used to
represent a desirable state of affairs. However, utterances are also
phenomena, and like all phenomena they can be used to represent
something they resemble. This possibility is often overlooked by
theorists, and even when it is not, we want to argue that the role it plays in
verbal communication is grossly underestimated.
Consider the following dialogue:
(98) Peter: What language did you speak to the inn-keeper?
Mary: Bonjour, comment allez-vous, bien, merci, et vous?
228
229
to
(104) There is a prime number greater than 8,364,357 and smaller than
8,366,445.
How plausible does it sound to you? Well, never mind. The point is that
we have just used an utterance interpretively, to represent an assumption,
without attributing this assumption to anyone: that is, without reporting
it. We have already done so many times in this book: many of our
numbered examples are used to represent utterances, assumptions or
intentions which we did not attribute to anybody, not even to fictitious
characters, and which we put forward to illustrate some abstract point.
In speculative thinking, thoughts are often entertained as approximate
representations of assumptions one would like to be able to formulate
better. This is true of trivial speculation: I don't remember when the party
at the Jones's is supposed to be; I tryout on myself, 'It's on Tuesday', 'It's
on Wednesday', 'It's on Thursday', ete., hoping that when I hit on the
right date, I will somehow recognise it. I entertain these successive
thoughts as attempts at representing the relevant piece of information in
my memory, and this is what makes my hope not entirely unreasonable: a
230
231
232
is
an interpretation of
a mental representation
of the speaker
which can be
entertained as
a description of
an interpretion of
an actual
(e.g. attributed)
representation
a desirable
(e.g. relevant)
representation
an actual
state of affai rs
a desirable
state of affairs
(a)
(b)
(c)
(d)
Figure 3
233
relevance, we do not feel too dismayed. Moreover, for the time being we
are concerned only with resemblances of a very restricted type: logical
resemblances among propositional forms (where two propositional forms
resemble each other if and only if they share logical properties ). We will
show that the identification of these resemblances, like every other aspect
of comprehension, is guided by the principle of relevance.
Let us say that an utterance, in its role as an interpretive expression of a
speaker's thought, is strictly literal if it has the same propositional form as
that thought. To say that an utterance is less than strictly literal is to say
that its propositional form shares some, but not all, of its logical properties
with the propositional form of the thought it is being used to interpret.
From the standpoint of relevance theory, there is no reason to think that
the optimally relevant interpretive expression of a thought is always the
most literal one. The speaker is presumed to aim at optimal relevance, not
at literal truth. The optimal interpretive expression of a thought should
give the hearer information about that thought which is relevant enough
to be worth processing, and should require as little processing effort as
possible. There are many quite ordinary situations where a literal
utterance is not optimally relevant: for example, where the effort needed
to process it is not offset by the gain in information conveyed. There are
thus many situations where a speaker aiming at optimal relevance should
not give a literal interpretation of her thought, and where the hearer
should not treat her utterance as literal.
For example, suppose I earn 797.32 pence a month. You, a friend I
have not seen for some years, ask me over a drink how much I am earning
now. If I remember the exact figure, I can choose between the strictly
literal and truthful answer in (1 OSa), and the less than literal (1 OSb), which
I know to he strictly speaking false:
(105) (a) I earn 797.32 pence a month.
(h) I earn 800 a month.
In the circumstances, there is no reason to think you need an exact figure.
From either reply you will be able to derive exactly the same conclusions
about my status, standard of living, purchasing power, life style, and
whatever else you are planning to use my salary as an indicator of. Aiming
at optimal relevance, I should therefore choose the reply which will
convey these conclusions as economically as possible. In other words, I
should choose the false hut economical (1 OSh) rather than the complex but
strictly literal and truthful (10Sa), and expect you to recognise that I am
offering something less than a strictly literal interpretation of my
thoughts.
To take a rather more abstract example, suppose I have a complex
thought P, which makes manifest to me a set of assumptions I, and I
235
236
237
The result is a quite complex picture, for which the hearer has to take a
large part of the responsibility, but the discovery of which has been
triggered by the writer. The surprise or beauty of a successful creative
metaphor lies in this condensation, in the fact that a single expression
which has itself been loosely used will determine a very wide range of
acceptable weak implicatures.
Take, for example, Flaubert's comment on the poet Leconte de Lisle:
(108) His ink is pale. (Son encre est pale.)
238
Aspects of verbal communication
meiosis, litotes) fall together with a range of cases which would not
normally be regarded as figurative at all. What unites these cases is the fact
that the thought of the speaker which is interpreted by the utterance is
itself an interpretation. It is an interpretation of a thought of someone
other than the speaker (or of the speaker in the past). That is, these
utterances are second-degree interpretations of someone else's thought, as
illustrated by path (a) in figure 3 above. If we are right, then the same is
true of irony as is true of metaphor: whatever abilities and procedures are
needed to understand it are independently needed for the interpretation of
quite ordinary non-figurative utterances. 25
We have already considered, in section 7, the case of utterances used to
interpret someone else's speech or thought. They are always (at least)
second-degree interpretations: like all utterances, they first interpret a
thought of the speaker, and it is only because this thought is itself an
interpretation of someone else's thought that the utterance ultimately
represents someone else's thought. Another way of making the same point
is to say that an utterance used as an interpretation of someone else's
thought is always, in the first place, an interpretation of one's understanding of that other person's thought. When we talk of utterances used to
interpret someone else's thought, it should be clear, then, that we are
always talking of second-degree interpretations.
How do interpretations of someone else's thought achieve relevance? In
the best-known case, that of 'reported speech', they achieve relevance by
informing the hearer of the fact that so-and-so has said something or
thinks something. In other cases, these interpretations achieve relevance
by informing the hearer of the fact that the speaker has in mind what
so-and-so said, and has a certain attitude to it: the speaker's interpretation
of so-and-so's thought is relevant in itself. When interpretations achieve
relevance in this way, we will say that they are echoic, and we will argue
that ironical utterances are cases of echoic interpretation.
Here is a simple case of an echoic utterance:
(109) Peter: The Joneses aren't coming to the party.
Mary: They aren't coming, hum. If that's true, we might invite the
Smiths.
Mary's first sentence echoes what Peter has just said. It achieves relevance
not, of course, by reporting to Peter what he has just said, but by giving
evidence that Mary has paid attention to his utterance and is weighing up
its reliability and implications.
An echoic utterance need not interpret a precisely attributable thought:
it may echo the thought of a certain kind of person, or of people in general.
Suppose you tell me to hurry up and I reply as follows:
239
240
Aspects of verbal communication
has been unsound, that they should never have set out, that it was his fault
that their day has been ruined, and so on. The recovery of these
implicatures depends, first, on a recognition of the utterance as echoic;
second, on an identification of the source of the opinion echoed; and third,
on a recognition that the speaker's attitude to the opinion echoed is one of
rejection or dissociation. We would argue that these are common factors
in the interpretation of all ironical utterances.
As regards the particular range of rejecting or dissociative attitudes
conveyed by verbal irony, there is no need to look for a clear-cut answer.
Are anger, outrage and irritation among the ~ttitudes that the ironist can
convey? This question, it seems to us, should be of interest only to
lexicographers. From the pragmatic point of view, what is important is
that a speaker can use an echoic utterance to convey a whole range of
attitudes and emotions, ranging from outright acceptance and endorsement
to outright rejection and dissociation, and that the recognition of these
attitudes and emotions may be crucial to the interpretation process. We
doubt very much that there is either a well-defined subset of ironical
attitudes or a well-defined subset of ironical utterances which express
them. Rather, what exists is a continuum, with different blends of attitude
and emotion giving rise to a whole range of borderline cases which do not
fit neatly into any existing scheme. Irony is not a natural kind.
Let us briefly compare this account with the classical account of irony as
saying one thing and meaning, or implicating, the opposite. The most
obvious problem with the classical account- and with its modern variant,
the Gricean account - is that it does not explain why a speaker who could,
by hypothesis, have expressed her intended message directly should
decide instead to say the opposite of what she meant. It cannot be too
strongly emphasised what a bizarre practice this would be. Suppose we are
out for a drive and you stop to look both ways before joining the main
road. The road is clear, but as you are about to drive on I say quietly,
(113) There's something coming.
You slam on your brakes and look both ways, but the road is as clear as
before. When you ask me what on earth I was doing, I explain gently that I
was merely trying to reassure you that the road was clear. My utterance
satisfies the classical definition of irony. I have said something which is
patently false, and there is a logically related assumption, namely (114),
which I could truthfully have expressed:
(114) There's nothing coming.
Why do you not instantly leap to the conclusion that this is what I was
trying to convey?
The classical account of irony notably fails to explain what distinguishes
241
242
his audience to believe, that at least one of them is false. However, there is
no need to come to the stronger conclusion that there is some determinate
assumption which means the opposite of what has been explicitly said, and
which Voltaire wanted to endorse.
In fact (l1Sa), like many of the best examples of irony, is a garden-path
utterance, likely to cause the reader momentary processing difficulties
later offset by appropriate rewards. One at first reads it as an ordinary
assertion, is led to the absurd conclusion that both sides won, and only
then reinterprets echoically. By leaving the echo implicit when the
addition of some explicit material would have:immediately put the reader
on the right track, the author opens up a whole new line of interpretation.
What sort of hearer would have needed no explicit push towards the
echoic interpretation? One who would automatically assume that after a
battle both sides invariably claim victory, that this behaviour is always
absurd, that the author and reader are not the sort of people to be fooled,
and so on. Thus, by leaving the echo implicit, the author manages to
suggest that he shares with his readers a whole cynical vision which is
absent from the explicitly interpretive version in (llSd):
(115) (d) When the battle was over and the rival kings were doing what
they described as celebrating their victory with Te Deums in
their respective camps ...
Example (86) in section 7 fits quite straightforwardly into this
framework.
(86) Peter is quite well-read. He's even heard of Shakespeare.
To believe (86), one would also have to believe that anyone who has heard
of Shakespeare is quite well-read - a patently ludicrous opinion. The
speaker of (86) thus makes fun of the idea that Peter is well-read, and
strongly implicates that he is not well-read at all. However, the irony
would fall flat if, manifestly, neither Peter himself nor anyone else had
ever entertained the thought that Peter was well-read: in this case there
would be no one to echo.
Our accounts of metaphor and irony share two essential features. First,
we are arguing that the possibility of expressing oneself metaphorically or
ironically and being understood as doing so follows from very general
mechanisms of verbal communication rather than from some extra level of
competence. 26 Second, we are arguing that there is a continuum of cases
rather than a dividing line between metaphorical and literal utterances on
the one hand, between ironical utterances and other echoic utterances on
the other; we are arguing, in other words, that metaphor and irony involve
no departure from a norm, no transgression of a rule, convention or
maXim.
Speech acts
243
If our account is correct, there are two conclusions to be drawn: first,
metaphor and irony are not essentially different from other types of
'non-figurative' utterances; and second, they are not essentially similar to
one another. Metaphor plays on the relationship between the propositional form of an utterance and the speaker's thought; irony plays on the
relationship between the speaker's thought and a thought of someone
other than the speaker. This suggests that the notion of a trope, which
covers metaphor and irony and radically distinguishes them from
'non-figurative' utterances, should be abandoned altogether: it groups
together phenomena which are not closely related and fails to group
together phenomena which are.
10 Speech acts
Perhaps the single most uncontroversial assumption of modern pragmatics is that any adequate account of utterance comprehension must include
some version of speech-act theory. As Levinson (1983: 226) says,
speech acts remain, along with presupposition and implicature in
particular, one of the central phenomena that any general pragmatic
theory must account for.
We would like to question this assumption. The vast range of data that
speech-act theorists have been concerned with is of no special interest to
pragmatics. What is of interest is their attempt to deal with the
interpretation of non-declarative (e.g. interrogative and imperative)
sentences, which must indeed be accounted for in any complete pragmatic
theory. In this section we will look first at speech-act theory as a general
pragmatic programme, and then at the analysis of non-declaratives, for
which we will sketch some proposals of our own.
Speech-act theory grew out of a reaction to what was seen as an
excessively narrow concentration on the informative use of language.
Language can be used to perform actions - speech acts: for example, to
create and discharge obligations, to influence the thoughts and actions of
others, and more generally, to create new states of affairs and new social
relationships. A better understanding of the nature of language, argued
Austin (1962), must involve a better understanding of how language is
embedded in social institutions, and of the various actions that it can be
used to perform.
Speech-act theorists have been much concerned with descriptive
questions: how many types of speech act are there, and how should they
be grouped together ?27 Searle (1979a) distinguishes assertives (e.g. state-
Speech acts
245
order to perform this speech act, the speaker must ostensively communicate, by linguistic means, via an utterance such as (119a), or by inference,
via an utterance such as (119b), an assumption of the form in (120):
(119) (a) I bid two no trumps.
(b) Two no trumps.
(120) The speaker is bidding two no trumps.
However, the study of bidding is part of the study of bridge, not of verbal
communication. Generally speaking, the study of institutional speech acts
such as bidding, or declaring war, belongs to the study of institutions.
Many other speech acts, by contrast, can be successfully performed
without being identified as such either by the speaker or by the hearer.
Take predicting, for example. What makes an utterance a prediction is not
the fact that the speaker ostensively communicates that she is making a
prediction; it is that she ostensively communicates an assumption with a
certain property: that of being about a future event at least partly beyond
her control. Thus, (121) could be a prediction without the speaker's ever
intending to communicate, or the hearer's ever recovering, the information in (122):
(121) The weather will be warmer tomorrow.
(122) The speaker is predicting that the weather will be warmer tomorrow.
This is not to say that it would never be desirable for the speaker of (121)
simultaneously to communicate assumption (122), or that it would never
be relevant for the hearer of (121) to recognise it as a prediction. The fact
that a prediction is being made is a fact like any other, and as such may be
made manifest by a speaker, or recognised by a hearer, in the usual way.
Our claim is simply that even where (122) is manifestly true, its recovery is
not essential to the comprehension of an utterance such as (121), as the
recovery of (120) is essential to the comprehension of an utterance such as
(119b) above.
Many speech acts which have been regarded as quite central to
pragmatics fall into one or other of these two categories. Promising and
thanking, for example, fall into the first category: they are institutional
acts, which can be performed only in a society with the requisite
institutions, and which must be recognised as such in order to be
successfully performed. 28 By contrast, asserting, hypothesising, suggesting, claiming, denying, entreating, demanding, warning and threatening
(to the extent that they are speech acts at all) fall into the second category:
they are acts which do not need to be identified as such in order to be
successfully performed, and which, like predicting, can be identified in
terms of some condition on their explicit content or implicatures. In
246
Speech acts
247
form of her utterance; but as we have seen, not all declarative utterances
are assertive in this sense: for example, metaphors and ironies are not. The
problem is quite general. If a directive is an attempt to get the hearer to
perform the action explicitly described, then the ironical imperative (126)
is not a directive:
(126) Go ahead and ruin my carpet.
It is not a genuine attempt to get the hearer to go ahead and ruin the
speaker's carpet. Similarly, the rhetorical question (127) is not a genuine
request for information:
(127) What monster would dare to harm a sleeping child?
Thus, the correlation between syntactic sentence types and generic speech
acts cannot be maintained unless a whole range of utterance types such as
(126) and (127) are excluded as 'insincere' or 'defective', or the traditional
typology of speech-act types is abandoned.
Even the claim that there is a well-defined range of mutually exclusive
syntactic sentence types is open to question. Is (128), which can be used
with either assertive or directive force, a declarative or an imperative?
(128) You are to leave tomorrow.
Is (129), said with rising intonation, a declarative or an interrogative?
(129) You won't be needing the car?
Is (130) a declarative or an exclamative?
(130) This book is so interesting.
e
a
Ll
248
Speech acts
249
In this case the utterance would be the result of choosing path (a) on figure
3 above.
As, ,:,e ~av~ seen, ~ome acts of saying that P ~chieve relevance not by
prov1dlllg llldIrect eVIdence for P but by expresslllg the speaker's attitude
to P. For example, the speaker of (131) above, in reporting the bus driver's
words, may tacitly dissociate herself from them. In this case, (132) might
achieve relevance by providing the hearer with evidence for (140) and, if he
trusts the speaker enough, for (141) and (142):
(140) The speaker believes it is ridiculous to say that the bus is leaving.
(141) It is ridiculous to say that the bus is leaving.
(142) The bus is not leaving.
Or, to consider a final case, suppose there has been an argument about
when the bus would leave, with the speaker of (131) maintaining that it
will not leave for ten minutes and the hearer insisting that it will leave
immediately. When the bus moves off and the speaker says (131), the
assumption expressed by her utterance will be irrelevant to the hearer,
who is already aware that the bus is moving off. In these circumstances,
the description in (132) would achieve relevance not by providing the
hearer with indirect evidence for the assumption expressed, but by
providing him with evidence for such higher-level descriptions as
(143 )-(144):
(143) The speaker acknowledges that the bus is leaving.
(144) The speaker admits that she was wrong.
.t
:r
:r
,,.
There are thus a variety of ways in which a description such as (132) can
be relevant; some will have the effect of an ordinary assertion, others the
effect of a report of speech or thought, others the effect of an irony or
dissociation, others the effect of a speech-act classification and so on. A
speaker who wants to achieve some particular effect should give whatever
linguistic cues are needed to ensure that the interpretation consistent with
the principle of relevance is the one she intended to convey. Thus, when
an utterance is interpreted as an ordinary assertion, this is not a result of
the operation of some maxim of quality or convention of truthfulness,
but simply of an interaction between the form of the utterance, the hearer's
accessible assumptions and the principle of relevance. 3D
It is tempting to assume that there is an exactly parallel account of
imperatives to the one just proposed for declaratives, replacing the terms
'declarative form', 'saying that' and 'belief' by 'imperative form', 'telling
to' and 'desire', respectively. On this approach, an imperative utterance
such as (145) would be integrated into a description such as (146), which
250
Aspects
of verbal communication
Speech acts
251
desirable from the speaker's point of view, whereas an advisory speech act
is one that represents a certain state of affairs as desirable from the hearer's
point of view. What makes (148) above intuitively requestive is the fact
that the speaker is representing as desirable from her own point of view a
state of affairs in which the traffic warden pretends he did not see her;
what makes (150b) above intuitively advisory is the fact that the speaker is
representing as desirable from the hearer's point of view a state of affairs in
which the hearer turns right and keeps straight on. What is essential to the
comprehension of these utterances is not their assignment to the class of
advisory or requestive speech acts, but a recognition that the state of
affairs described is being represented as desirable from the speaker's point
of view in the first case, and the hearer's in the second.
If we are right, then the interpretation of imperative and declarative
utterances might proceed along broadly parallel lines. The hearer, on
recovering the propositional form P of an imperative utterance would integrate it into a description of the form The speaker is telling the hearer to P.
Telling the hearer to P might be analysed as communicating that the thought
that P interprets is entertained as a description of a desirable state of affairs.
Who entertains this thought in this way: the speaker or someone whose
thought the speaker is interpreting? From whose point of view is the state
of affairs described desirable? The hearer has to answer these questions
inferentially. As usual, the first interpretation consistent with the
principle of relevance will be selected, and a speaker who wants to be
correctly understood must make sure that the interpretation she intends to
convey is the first one consistent with the principle of relevance. We
believe that along these lines a satisfactory account of imperative
utterances might be constructed. On this account, the most basic, literal,
non-attributive imperatives would be the result of choosing path (d) in
figure 3 above and producing an utterance which was a literal interpretation of the speaker's thought. Metaphorical but non-attributive imperatives would be the result of choosing the same path but producing an
utterance which was a less than fully literal interpretation of the speaker's
thought. Attributive imperatives would be the result of choosing path (a).
Speech-act theorists tend to analyse interrogative utterances as a special
sub-type of directive speech act: specifically, as requests for information
(see Searle 1969: 69; Bach and Harnish 1979: 48). However, exam
questions such as (152), rhetorical questions such as (153), expository
questions such as (154), self-addressed questions such as (155) and indirect
questions such as (156) all present problems for this approach:
(152) What were the causes of the First World War?
(153) When did you say you were going to give up smoking?
(154) What are the main objections to this approach? First ...
252
When an examiner asks (152) above, it is not because she wants to know
the answer, but because she wants to evaluate the candidate's attempt at an
answer. A speaker who asks the rhetorical question (153) would not
normally be expecting any verbal response at all. A standard expository
device of many writers is to ask a question, such as (154), which they then
proceed to answer themselves. Many questjons, such as (155), are
produced in the absence of any audience, as pure intellectual speculations
or musings. Indirect questions such as (156) also resist speech -act analysis.
It is hard to see what request for information is being made, or even
alluded to, in (156): (156) could be true without it ever having occurred to
Peter to wonder, let alone ask, who his neighbour is. The standard
speech-act approach thus rules out any possibility of a unitary account of
direct and indirect questions.
We would like to suggest that an account of interrogative utterances can
be built around the notion of an interpretive use introduced in section 7.
Our hypothesis is that the hearer of an interrogative utterance recovers its
logical form and integrates it into a description of the form The speaker is
asking Wh-P, where Wh-P is an indirect question. Let us distinguish
between yes-no questions, which have not only a logical but also a fully
propositional form, and Wh-questions, which have a logical form but no
fully propositional form. Then we want to analyse asking Wh-P, where
Wh-P is a yes-no question and P is the propositional form of the
utterance, as communicating that the thought interpreted by P would be
relevant if true. We want to analyse asking Wh-P, where Wh-P is a
Wh-question and P is the less-than-propositional logical form of the
utterance, as communicating that there is some completion of the thought
interpreted by P into a fully propositional thought which would be
relevant if true. In other words, interrogative utterances are interpretations of answers that the speaker would regard as relevant if true.
Relevance, like desirability, is a two-place relation: what is relevant to
one person may not be relevant to another. Thus, in interpreting a
question, the hearer must always make some assumption about who the
speaker thinks its answer would be relevant to. Different assumptions
yield different types of question. For example, rhetorical questions such as
(153) above ('When did you say you were going to give up smoking?') are often
reminders, designed to prompt the retrieval of information the speaker
regards as relevant to the hearer. Similarly, expository questions such as
(154) above (,What are the main objections to this approach? First .. .'),
and more generally offers of information, are analysable as questions
whose answers the speaker regards as relevant to the hearer. Regular
requests for information, by contrast, are analysable as questions whose
Speech acts
253
254
Postface
1 Introduction
In the nine years since Relevance was first published, the theory of
communication it proposes has been widely accepted, widely criticised
and widely misunderstood. The book has been translated into several
languages;! its implications for pragmatic theory have been explored in
a growing number of books and articles; it has inspired work in
neighbouring disciplines, including linguistics, literary studies, psychology and philosophy. In section 2 of this postface, we review briefly the
main developments that have taken place since the first edition was
published. 2
Many commentators, to whom we are very grateful, have raised a wide
variety of objections to the theory.3 We have had the opportunity to
answer most of them in a series of publications to which interested
readers are referred. 4 These criticisms have helped us correct some mistakes in the book; they have also made us aware of the difficulties in
comprehension and the many possibilities of misunderstanding it presents. Either because we are dense, or because we have had more time
than our commentators to think about these issues, we find that the most
serious problems with our theory are those we have discovered ourselves.
In section 3 of this Postface, we outline these problems, and propose
several significant changes both of formulation and of substance.
2 Developments
There is now a substantial body of work expounding and evaluating the
basic ideas of relevance theory. This includes a precis of Relevance,s two
textbooks and large sections of an encyclopaedia of pragmatics,6 expository articles designed for non-specialist audiences/ and several lengthy
256
Postface
critiques. s The implications of the theory have been explored in monographs and dissertations,9 there are edited collections including papers in
relevance theory,IO there is an e-mail network for exchange of ideas, and
a bibliography for classroom useY Several research projects have been
undertaken; informal workshops are held each year in London, and
more formal conferences and lecture series have been held around the
world. We will not attempt here a survey of this very diverse literature,
but merely point out some of the directions in which we feel that
particularly interesting and fruitful work is being done.
Postface
257
258
Postface
Post/ace
259
0/ language use
260
Postface
3 Revisions
Postface
261
when our book was read and interpreted - as we wanted - in the context
of wider cognitive concerns, this use of the term 'principle' would seem
rather arbitrary, cause unnecessary effort, and hence (as we should have
predicted on relevance-theoretic grounds) lead to misinterpretation.
We have decided to remedy the situation by talking in future of two
Principles of Relevance: the First (or Cognitive) Principle is given in (1),
and the Second (or Communicative) Principle is given in (2). Throughout this book, the term 'Principle of Relevance' refers to the Second,
Communicative Principle. The change is, of course, expository and not
substantive, but it is worth spelling out what we hope to highlight by
this reformulation.
3.2 The First Principle of Relevance
The First Principle of Relevance is less subtle than the Second Principle,
but it is still controversial and in need of justification. As stated, it is
also too vague, and in need of elaboration.
Relevance is not a commodity; it is a property. What is it a property
of? By our definition, it is a property of inputs to cognitive processes. It
can be a property of stimuli, for example, which are inputs to perceptual
processes, or of assumptions, which are inputs to inferential processes.
Stimuli, and more generally phenomena, are found in the environment
external to the organism; assumptions, which are the output of cognitive
processes of perception, recall, imagination or inference, are internal to
the organism. When we claim that human cognition tends to be geared
to the maximisation of relevance, we mean that cognitive resources tend
to be allocated to the processing of the most relevant inputs available,
whether from internal or external sources. In other words, human
cognition tends to be geared to the maximisation of the cumulative
relevance of the inputs it processes. It does this not by pursuing a longterm policy based on computation of the cumulative relevance achieved
over time, but by local arbitrations, aimed at incremental gains, between
simultaneously available inputs competing for immediately available
resources.
Why assume that human cognition tends to be geared to the maximisation of relevance? The answer comes in two stages, one to do with the
design of biological mechanisms in general, the other with efficiency 'in
cognitive mechanisms.
We start from the assumption that cognition is a biological function,
and that cognitive mechanisms are, in general, adaptations. As such,
they are the result of a process of Darwinian natural selection (although
other evolutionary forces may have helped to shape them). We assume,
then, that cognitive mechanisms have evolved in small incremental steps,
262
Postface
Pastface
263
3.2.1 The First Principle of Relevance and truth Our definition of the
relevance of an assumption in a context takes no account of the objective
truth or falsity of the assumption itself, or of the conclusions that may
be derived from it in the context. Thus, a false assumption that
contextually implies many false conclusions, or a true assumption that
combines with a false contextual premise to imply many false conclusions, is, by our definition, as relevant as a true assumption that
implies many true conclusions. On the other hand, our rationale for
introducing this notion of relevance has to do with considerations of
cognitive efficiency, and the notion of cognitive efficiency cannot be
divorced from that of truth. The function of a cognitive system is to
deliver knowledge, not false beliefs. Does this mean there is something
missing from our definition of relevance? Definitely, and it is in need of
revision. Note, though, that for most of our purposes our incomplete
definition is good enough.
When we use the notion of relevance to help describe how a cognitive
system allocates its resources, there is no harm in leaving objective truth
or falsity out of account. The system has no other way of distinguishing
true from false assumptions than via its own inputs and internal
processes. Basically, if an assumption is caused by the environment in
the appropriate way (e.g. through perception), the system accepts it; if
an assumption is inferentially derived by the system~s own computational mechanisms from accepted premises, it again accepts it. When the
system is a reflective one, e.g. a human being, it may be aware that it
wants real knowledge and not false beliefs; it may be aware of the risk
of accepting false assumptions; it may develop some procedures to
double-check the outcome of other procedures; but all it can do in the
end is trust the sum of its own procedures to deliver knowledge. So the
system will take the output of its own mechanisms as cognitively
warranted, and will assess relevance in terms of all contextual effects
achieved, even though, unbeknownst to it, some of its conclusions may
turn out to be false. From this solipsistic point of view (in the sense of
Fodor 1980), truth can safely be ignored.
However, this is not the only point of view that needs to be taken
into account. A reflective cognitive system may be aware that some of
its beliefs are likely to be false, even if it cannot tell which, and it may
regard information leading to false beliefs as worse than irrelevant.
264
Postface
In (4), Peter's assumption that Mary was talking to a man was true, and
led to rich contextual effects. However, these effects were false beliefs.
Was Peter's assumption relevant? We would rather say that it seemed
relevant, but in fact was not. In (5), by contrast, Peter's assumption that
Mary was talking to a man was false, but it led to many true beliefs, so
that here we would be willing to say that it was genuinely relevant
Post/ace
265
266
Postface
extent that the effort required to achieve these positive cognitive
effects is small.
Postface
267
268
Post/ace
goal that goes beyond merely understanding and being understood, and
are expected to provide whatever information would best further this
common goal. What is to be expected is not just relevance enough, but
maximal relevance to achieving the common goal. 30
We have expressed disagreement with this view. It may be true that in
most verbal exchanges the participants share a purpose that goes beyond
merely understanding one another, but it need not always be the case.
Conflictual or non-reciprocal communication, for example, involve no
such purpose. It is also true that understanding is made easier by the
presence of a common goal. We can accountcfor by this pointing out
that a common goal creates a number of mutually manifest contextual
assumptions on which the interlocutors can draw. The existence of a
common conversational goal need not be built into pragmatic principles.
We still believe this is correct.
However, we ourselves have stressed that interlocutors always share
at least one common goal, that of understanding and being understood.
It is in the communicator's manifest interest both to do her best and to
appear to be doing her best to achieve this common goal. This provides
a second reason for crediting her with the intention to convey a
presumption of relevance, and is reflected in clause (b) of the presumption as stated above. In its current version, however, clause (b) is wholly
about effort. The intended effect is treated as given, and clause (b) says
that the stimulus used to achieve this effect is the one that requires least
effort from the addressee.
The presumption of minimal effort expressed by (b) is at best too
vague and at worst too strong. A communicator may well be willing to
try to minimise the addressee's effort, since this will make him more
likely to attend to her ostensive stimulus and succeed in understanding
it. Still, for all sorts of reasons, the particular stimulus she produces may
not be the one that would absolutely minimise the addressee's effort. In
the first place, there is the communicator's own effort to consider. As
speakers, we are prepared to make only so much effort in formulating
our thoughts, and as hearers, we know better than to expect flawlessly
crafted utterances. Then there may be rules of etiquette or standards of
ideological correctness that rule out the utterance that would be easiest
to process (which would also be likely to convey unwanted weak
implicatures). As speakers, we avoid what we see as objectionable
formulations, and as hearers, we expect such restraint.
Clause (b) of the presumption of optimal relevance should in any case
have allowed for the speaker's right to be lazy or prudish, i.e. to have
her own preferences and take them into account. 31 In later publications
or oral presentations, we amended this effort clause to say that no
unjustified or gratuitous effort was to be demanded. In other words,
Post/ace
269
from a range of possible stimuli which were equally capable of communicating the intended interpretation and equally acceptable to the
communicator (given both her desire to minimise her own effort and
her own moral, prudential, or aesthetic preferences), the communicator
should prefer, and appear to prefer, the stimulus that would minimise
the addressee's effort.
However, this line of reasoning, which was based on considerations
of effort, applies equally to the effect side. Suppose that, from the
communicator's point of view, her goals would be equally well served
by a number of utterances (or other stimuli), all of which would cause
the intended contextual effects, but some of which would cause further
contextual effects, and be (or seem) more relevant to the addressee as a
result. Which should she choose? She should choose the utterance that
would be (or seem) most relevant to the addressee, for just the reasons
given above in discussing the minimisation of effort.
Here is an illustration. Mary wants to make it quite manifest to Peter
that she will be out from 4 o'clock to 6 o'clock. She might inform him
of this by saying any of (lOa-c):
(10) (a) I'll be out from 4 to 6.
(b) I'll be out at the Jones's from 4 to 6.
(c) I'll be out at the J ones's from 4 to 6 to discuss the next meeting.
Suppose she assumes that any of these utterances would be relevant
enough to Peter. Suppose it doesn't matter to her whether she tells him
where she is going and why. Suppose the amount of effort needed to
produce any of these utterances makes no difference to her. Then it
would be rational enough to utter any of (lOa-c), since each would
achieve her goal at an equally acceptable cost to her. However, it would
be most rational to produce the utterance most relevant to Peter, since
this would make it most likely that he would attend to her communication, remember it, and so on: in other words, it would maximise the
manifestness to Peter of the information that Mary wants him to have.
Since (lOc) would demand more effort from Peter than (lOb), and (lOb)
than (lOa), Mary should choose one of these longer utterances if and
only if the extra information conveyed yields enough effect to make it
more relevant to Peter. If he doesn't care where she is going, she should
choose (lOa). If he cares where she is going, but not why, she should
choose (lOb). If he cares both where and why, she should choose (lOc).
These choices are rational even if Mary doesn't particularly want to be
helpful to Peter by telling him what he may want to know. They are
rational as ways of maximising the chances that she will succeed in
making manifest to him the one thing she does want to make manifest:
that she will be away from 4 o'clock to 6 o'clock.
270
Postface
This says that the addressee is entitled to expect a level of relevance high
enough to warrant his attending to the stimulus, and which is, moreover,
Postface
271
272
Postface
(13) You remember I bought that lottery ticket? Well, guess what? I
won 10,000!
Mary's statement, taken literally, may well be not only relevant enough
to be worth Peter's attention, but much more relevant than he would
have expected, given the unrevised presumption of relevance. Still, if this
is the first accessible interpretation that is relevant enough (and unless it
conflicts with other of his contextual assumptions), he will accept it as
the one intended. This, at least, is what an analysis based on the
unrevised presumption of relevance would (correctly) predict.
Compare this with the case where Mary says to Peter:
(14) You remember I bought that lottery ticket? Well, guess what? I
won a prize!
Here, the first accessible interpretation that is relevant enough will
probably represent Mary's prize as just big enough to be worth talking
about. If just knowing that she won a prize is relevant enough, then the
Postface
273
value of the prize may not be seen as relevant at all. Here again, an
analysis based on the unrevised presumption of relevance is adequate.
The revised presumption of relevance yields the same analysis of these
and similar examples. In interpreting (13), Peter assumes that Mary had
the ability - in this case the knowledge - to say something more than
minimally relevant (namely that she had won 10,000), and that she gave
this information in the absence of contrary preferences. In interpreting
(14), let us assume that Peter accepts clause (b) of the presumption of
relevance and expects Mary's utterance to be the most relevant one
compatible with her abilities and preferences. Still, he has no reason to
think she has a more relevant piece of information that she is reluctant
to share with him; so he will assume that the prize is merely big enough
to be worth mentioning. Quite often, the lower limit mentioned in
clause (a) of the (revised) presumption of relevance will coincide with
the higher limit mentioned in clause (b). The speaker has something just
relevant enough to be worth saying, and says it.
In some cases, though, the revised presumption yields different, and
better, analyses. Here we will consider two. The first is adapted from
Grice (1989: 32). Peter and Mary are planning a holiday in France. Peter
has just said that it would be nice to visit their old acquaintance Gerard
if it would not take them too far out of their way. The dialogue
continues:
(15) (a) Peter: Where does Gerard live?
(b) Mary: Somewhere in the South of France.
As Grice notes, Mary's answer implicates (16):
(16) Mary does not know where in the South of France Gerard lives
This implicature is easily explained in terms of Grice's maxims. Mary's
answer is less informative than the first maxim of Quantity ('Make your
contribution as informative as is required') would suggest. 'This
infringement [... ] can be explained only by the supposition that [Mary]
is aware that to be more informative would be to say something that
infringed the second maxim of Quality, "Don't say what you lack
evidence for'" (Grice 1989: 32-33).
In the unrevised version of relevance theory, we would have to explain
this implicature by noting that, in the situation described, it would
generally be mutually manifest that Mary is expected and willing to
co-operate in planning the holiday in France. From this assumption, together with the fact that her reply is not relevant enough to
answer Peter's question, it can be inferred that she does not know
exactly where Gerard lives. Then not only is (16) manifest but, given
274
Postface
Postface
275
276
Postface
Post/ace
277
(24) (a) Henry: If you or some of your neighbours have pets, you
shouldn't use this pesticide in your garden.
(b) Mary: Thanks. We don't have pets, but some of our neighbours certainly do.
Here, it seems to us, the fact that at lea~t some of Mary's neighbours
have pets is relevant enough, and there is no reason to assume she meant
that not all of them do (or that she doesn't know whether all of them
do). Griceans who treat the inference from 'some' to 'not all' as a
generalised implicature would have to claim that Mary's utterance does
have this implicature, or that the hearer of (24b) would first make this
inference and then (for what reason?) cancel it. Neither hypothesis
seems plausible to us.
However, in some cases the predictions of the unrevised presumption
of relevance are not obviously correct. This happens when the basic
interpretation of 'some' (where 'some' is compatible with 'all') is relevant
enough to be worth the hearer's attention, but when it would clearly be
more relevant to the hearer to know whether 'not all' is the case too. An
example is (25):
(25) (a) Henry: Do all, or at least some, of your neighbours have pets?
(b) Mary: Some of them do.
Here, Henry has made manifest that it would be relevant to him to
know not only whether some of Mary's neighbours have pets, but
whether all of them do. An unrevised relevance model, applied mechanically to this case, would predict that Henry should stop at the first
interpretation that is relevant enough; this is clearly the one on which
Mary is taken to communicate that she has at least some neighbours
who have pets, and nothing more. This prediction is manifestly wrong.
Mary's answer would normally be taken to convey that not all of her
neighbours have pets.
It would, of course, be easy enough to apply the relevance model
flexibly: one might argue, for instance, that someone who asks a
question automatically makes it manifest that what he would consider
relevant enough is nothing less than a full answer to his question, or an
utterance at least as relevant as that. In that case, Mary's answer in (25b),
understood as conveying only that she has at least some neighbours who
have pets, would not be relevant enough. Standard relevance considerations would cause it to be interpreted as implicating34 that not all her
neighbours have pets, thereby satisfying Peter's expectation of adequate
relevance.
However, we much prefer a model that can be applied mechanically.
Isn't this what taking cognitive science seriously is all about? The revised
278
Postface
There are many other aspects of relevance theory that we would like to
see developed, and that we or others have begun working on in articles
and unpublished lectures. Many involve local revisions of the version of
the theory presented in this book. Some open new perspectives that may
turn out to be more important in the general balance of the theory than
the present revisions.
Experimental studies testing relevance-theoretic hypotheses have just
begun, and we hope that they will lead to revisions, new insights, and,
perhaps more important, new problems to investigate. Interesting applications of the theory to literary studies suggest that it might be of some
relevance, more generally, in the study of various cultural productions.
Postface
279
Novel insights and new problems should come from the formal modelling of the theory, possibly with the use of spreading activation models
which seem particularly well suited to representing, on the one hand
the role of accessibility, and, on the other, the way the system'~
computations can be guided on line by monitoring its efforts and effects.
Two important and related domains have hardly been explored at all
from a relevance-theoretic perspective: the theory has been developed
from the point of view of the audience of communicative acts, and
without taking into account the complex sociological factors richly
studied by sociolinguistics. The cognitive processes at work in the
communicator, and the social character and context of communication
are, of course, essential to the wider picture, to the study of which we
hope relevance theory can contribute, and from which it stands greatly
to benefit.
We ourselves have been working on a revised and more detailed
description of inferential comprehension, integrating in particular the
processes involved in enrichment and the comprehension of loose talk
or metaphor. This work will be presented in our forthcoming Relevance
and Meaning.
CHAPTER
COMMUNICATION
282
283
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
284
29
30
31
32
validation before being accepted by the individual as facts. If this were so,
being perceptible would not be a sufficient condition for being manifest. The
best evidence for this claim is the fact that one can mistrust one's senses, and
hence perceive and yet not believe. However, one can also infer and not
believe, as when a validly inferred conclusion contradicts a strongly held
belief. It seems to us that the output of perception, just like that of inference,
requires no validation in order to be accepted as true. On the other hand, the
output of perception (like the output of inference) can be inferentially
invalidated. To be more precise, therefore, we might say that to be manifest is
to be capable of being perceived or inferred without being immediately
invalidated.'
What, for instance, Lewis (1969: 56) calls a basis for common (i.e. mutual)
knowledge is roughly equivalent to our mutual manifestness. We part
company with him when he goes on to state, as a mere matter of definition,
that the existence of such a basis is a sufficient condition for the existence of
common knowledge itself. See also Clark and Marshall1981.
It would be unfair not to mention that inferential theorists generally resist the
temptation. Grice (1982: 237), who develops an inferential account of how
language could have originated, calls it 'a myth'. See also Lewis 1975/1983:
181.
See Catherine Kerbrat-Orecchioni 1977 for a survey.
This is why we did not analyse the informative intention as an intention to
make I mutually manifest. This would not be adequate in the cases where
the communicator does not herself believe the information she is trying to
communicate. There is another way of handling this problem, though:
ostensive communication could be described as an attempt to create a
genuinely mutual cognitive environment between social personae. When the
communicator is sincere (and so is the audience in manifesting its acceptance of
the information communicated), then the actual individuals and their social
personae coincide, and otherwise they don't. This formulation, which is a
notational variant rather than a substantive alternative to the one we follow
here, might be more appealing from a sociological point of view.
CHAPTER
INFERENCE
285
If the paradox is not more blatant, it is, we fear, because of the general haziness
with which these issues are usually discussed.
3 Here we assume only token identity between brain states and mental states.
See Fodor 1974.
4 For the role of incomplete logical forms in speculative thinking, see Sperber
1985: chapter 2.
5 Or storage format: the important point being that all representations stored in
that store or format are retrievable and processable in the same way, and
differently from representations stored otherwise.
6 See Sperber (1985: chapter 2) for elaboration and discussion of this distinction.
7 Because logical forms, propositional forms and factual assumptions are not
directly observable, we will have to use natural-language sentences to
represent them, despite the lack of any one-to-one correspondence between
sentences on the one hand and logical forms, propositional forms and factual
assumptions on the other. In practice, this should present no more problem
than it does in everyday communication, when hearers or readers normally
have no difficulty in identifying the assumptioI1-a given utterance was intended
to express. We do not mean to imply that natural language reflects the
structure of the language of thought more closely than is required by the fact
that both are formal objects with semantic properties, and that the one can be
successfully used to communicate the other.
8 And, for that matter, even when he is capable of doing so consciously, as
evidenced by the work of Kahneman and Tversky.
9 See Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky 1982: especially chapters 1, 34 and 35.
10 In what format are assumption schemas stored in the mind? They could be
embedded in factual assumptions which state that some completion of the
schema is or might be true. Or they could be stored as fully propositional
factual assumptions, but with very weak empirical import, which achieve
relevance only when strengthened by the addition of new constituents. For
instance, assumption schema (29) below could be stored as (i) or as (ii):
. (29) The outside temperature is - - degrees centigrade.
(i) For some number n, 'the outside temperature is n degrees centigrade'
is true.
(ii) The outside temperature is some number of degrees centigrade.
11
12
13
14
286
287
RELEVANCE
288
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
289
along the lines suggested here could be worked out, a more general
consequence would be that there would be no need for a notion of focus in
generative grammar. The issues are complicated and have been the subject of
some sophisticated syntactic argumentation. What is worrying about this
argumentation is that for all its complex machinery it often ends in appeals to
pragmatic notions whose nature is left unspecified. We have simply tried to
sketch in the lines of a pragmatic account which should serve at least as a
supplement to the linguistic notion of focus, and at best as a replacement for it.
For discussion, see Wilson 1975; Kempson 1975; Gazdar 1979; J. D. Fodor
1979; and Soames 1979.
In the same way, it can be shown that cohesion and coherence are derivative
categories, ultimately derivable from relevance. For detailed arguments for
this position, see Blass 1986, 1990.
Note also a technical difference of some consequence: while new or focused
information has invariably been treated as non-propositional, or of less than
propositional size, foreground information is, by our definition, propositional: a foreground implication is an analytic implication, not an NP or VP, or an
NP intension or a VP intension.
This is not to say, however, that no arbitrary linkages between linguistic form
and pragmatic interpretation exist. It used to be suggested in the presuppositionalliterature (e.g. in Stalnaker 1974: 212) that there were certain linguistic
structures whose function was to impose constraints on the contexts in which
utterances containing those structures could occur. Pending an account of the
role of context in utterance interpretation, it was hard to see why such
structures should exist. Some years ago, however, Diane Blakemore suggested
that in a relevance-based framework they might have a significant advantage
from a processing point of view. As we have seen, the speaker can use the
linguistic form of an utterance to guide the interpretation process. Blakemore's idea was that, just as the natural links between intonational structure
and pragmatic interpretation may become grammaticalised, so a language
might develop certain structures whose sole function was to guide the
interpretation process by stipulating certain properties of context and
contextual effects. Clearly, in a relevance-based framework the use of such
structures might be highly cost-efficient. This approach appears to shed light
on a wide range of apparently disparate phenomena on the borderlines
of grammar and pragmatics, and seems to us a particularly promising area
for future research. For a detailed development of this approach, see
Brockway 1981,1983; Blakemore 1985, 1987, 1988a. For further interesting
work along these lines see MacLaran 1982; Kempson 1984; Smith 1983; and
Blass 1990.
The distinction between descriptions and interpretations was developed in
another context in Sperber 1985: chapter 2.
See Searle 1969: chapter 3; Lewis 1975; Bach and Harnish 1979: 10-12,
127-13 I.
Or in some other given world, in the case of fiction for instance.
In an earlier paper (Sperber and Wilson 1981), we analysed irony and free
indirect speech as varieties of mention. We distinguished direct speech,
290
26
27
28
29
30
291
anything less than certain of her own name would normally be inconsistent
with manifest assumptions, with (ii), by contrast, an educated guess would be
quite relevant enough
CHAPTER I
COMMUNICATION
INFERENCE
a We would not now assume such asharp distinction between input (specialised) and central (unspecialised) systems. In the last ten years, there has been
growing evidence that so-called central systems should be analysed in
modular terms. See Sperber 1994b for discussion.
b For reservations about the treatment of 'central' systems in the Fodorian
framework, see note a above.
c It is worth emphasising that the deductive system presented in this chapter is
designed to do no more than illustrate one way in which deductive inferences
294
might be performed. We are a long way from having the sort of evidence that
would choose between the huge range of conceivable methods of performing
deductive inference.
d It is sometimes suggested that we have overlooked a fourth type of contextual
effect, namely weakening of existing assumptions. Weakenings are allowed
for in our formal definition of the conditions under which a contextualisation
has contextual effects (chapter 2, note 26). We assume, though, that weakening is always a by-product of a more basic contextual effect: for example,
contradiction and elimination of an existing assumption weakens all contextual implications which depended on that assumption for some support.
CHAPTER
RELEVANCE
a This definition is too strong as it stands. It should be modified to accommodate the fact that someone who says, for example, 'I tell you that P', or 'P
despite Q', can explicitly communicate P.
b That is, given the particular instantiation of the principle of relevance
communicated on that occasion.
c In preparing the French translation of Relevance, we discovered that, in fact,
this classic example of irony (discussed by Booth 1974: 10) is not the work of
Voltaire but of his English translator. A closer (and duller) translation of the
French original would go: 'Finally, while the two kings had Te Deums sung
in their respective camps .. .'.
Notes to Postface
4
5
6
7
296
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
297
forthcoming; Haegeman 1987, 1989; Hirst 1987; Horn 1992; Kandolf 1993'
Klinge 1:93; Moeschler 1993b; Recanati 1994, forthcoming; Scancarelli
1986; Stamton 1993, 1994; Taylor 1993; and references in note 16.
See, for example, Blakemore 1987; Carston 1988a.
See Grice 1989: 121-2,361-3.
For survey and discussion of early work on non-truth-conditional semantics
see Wilson 1975. For important work outside the relevance-theor~tic frame~
work, see Ducrot 1980b, 1983, 1984, Ducrot et al. 1980.
For procedural accounts of discourse connectives, see Ariel1988; Blakemore
1988a, b, 1990, 1993; Blass 1990, 1993; Ducrot 1984, Ducrot et al. 1980;
Gutt 1988; Haegeman 1993; Higashimori 1992a, b, 1994; Itani 1995; Jucker
1993; Luscher 1994; Moeschler 1989a, b, 1993a; Smith and Smith 1988;
Unger 1994; Vandepitte 1993; Wilson and Sperber 1993. For related accounts
of procedural semantics, see Gabbay and Kempson 1991; Jiang 1994;
Kempson forthcoming.
Relevance-theoretic accounts of mood indicators are developed in Clark
1991, 1993a, b; Lunn 1989; Rouchota 1994a, b, c; Wilson and Sperber
1988a, b, 1993. For discussion of various aspects of the relevance-theoretic
approach to speech acts, see Bird 1994; Clark 1991; Groefsema 1992b;
Harnish 1994; Moeschler 1991; Reboul 1990b, 1994b; Recanati 1987; see
also Kasher 1994.
On mood indicators, see note 22. On discourse particles and adverbials, see
Blass 1989, 1990; Espinal1991; Ifantidou 1994; Ifantidou-Trouki 1993; Itani
1995; Konig 1991a, b; N0lke 1990; Watts 1988; Wilson and Sperber 1993;
Yoshimura 1993b. On parentheticals, see Blakemore 1990/1; Espinal 1991;
Ifantidou 1994; Wilson and Sperber 1993. On tense and aspect, see Moeschler 1993b; Smith 1993; Zegarac 1991, 1993.
For development and applications of the relevance-theoretic accounts of
metaphor and irony, see Forceville 1994a, b; Hymes 1987; Pilkington 1992,
1994; Reboul 1990a, 1992a; Song forthcoming; Sperber and Wilson 1985/6,
1990b; Wilson and Sperber 1988b, 1992; Vicente 1992; Yoshimura 1993a.
For discussion, see Gibbs 1994; Goatly 1994; Hamamoto forthcoming;
Kreuz and Glucksberg 1989; Martin 1992; Perrin forthcoming; Recanati
forthcoming; Seto forthcoming.
See Gutt 1990, 1991, 1992; Tirkkonen-Condit 1992; Winckler and van der
Merwe 1993.
On echo questions, see Blakemore 1994b; on reformulations, see Blakemore
1993; on pseudo-imperatives, see Clark 1991, 1993a; on hearsay particles,
see Blass 1989, 1990, Ifantidou 1994, Itani 1995; on metalinguistic negation,
see Carston forthcoming a, Moeschler 1992; see also Burton-Roberts
1989a, b; Fretheim forthcoming b; Yoshimura 1993b. For interesting application of the related notion of 'polyphonie', see for example Ducrot 1983.
The implications of relevance theory for literature are discussed in Durant
and Fabb 1990; Fabb forthcoming, in preparation; Green 1993; Kiparsky
1987; Pilkington 1991, 1992, 1994; Reboul 1990a, 1992a; Richards 1985;
Sperber and Wilson 1987b: 751; Trotter 1992; Uchida forthcoming.
On humour, see Ferrar 1993, Jodlowiec 1991; on politeness, see Austin
298
29
30
31
32
33
34
Bibliography
300
Bibliography
Bibliography
301
302
Bibliography
Bibliography
303
304
Bibliography
Bibliography
305
306
Bibliography
Bibliography
307
308
Bibliography
Bibliography
309
Kempson, R. (1975), Presupposition and the delimitation of semantics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Kempson, R. (1984), 'Anaphora, the compositionality requirement and the
semantics-pragmatics distinction'. Proceedings of the North-Eastern Linguistics Society XIV, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, MA.
Kempson, R. (1986), 'Ambiguity and the semantics-pragmatics distinction', in
Travis 1986: 77-103.
Kempson, R. (ed.) (1988a), Mental representations: The interface between
language and reality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Kempson, R. (1988b), 'Grammar and conversational principles', in Newmeyer
1988, vol. 11: 139-63.
Kempson, R. (1988c), 'Logical form: The grammar-cognition interface'. Journal
of Linguistics 24.2: 393-431.
Kempson, R. (forthcoming), 'Semantics, pragmatics and natural-language interpretation' . To appear in Lappin forthcoming.
Kerbrat-Orecchioni, C. (1977), La connotation. Presses Universitaires de Lyon,
Lyon.
Kerbrat-Orecchioni, C. (1981), 'L'ironie comme trope'. Poetique 41: 108-27.
Khalfa, J. (ed.) (1994), What is intelligence? Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Kiparsky, P. (1987), 'On theory and interpretation', in Fabb, Attridge, Durant
and McCabe 1987: 185-98.
Kirschner, C. and de Cesaris, J. (eds) (1989), Studies in Romance linguistics.
John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Kleiber, G. (1990), 'Marqueurs referentiels et processus interpretatifs: pour une
approche "plus semantique'''. Cahiers de linguistique franr;aise 11: 241-58.
Kleiber, G. (1992), 'Article defini: unicite et pertinence'. Revue roumane 27.1:
61-89.
Klinge, A. (1993), 'The English modal auxiliaries: From lexical semantics to
utterance interpretation'. Journal of Linguistics 29: 315-57.
Konig, E. (1991a), 'A relevance-theoretic approach to the analysis of modal
particles in German'. Multilingua 10. 112: 63-77.
Konig, E. (1991b), The meaning of focus particles: A comparative perspective.
Routledge, London.
Kreuz, R. and Glucksberg, S. (1989), 'How to be sarcastic: The echoic reminder
theory of verbal irony' . Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 118:
374-86.
Kripke, S. (1972), 'Naming and necessity', in Davidson and Harman 1972:
253-355. Reprinted as Naming and necessity. Blackwell, Oxford (1980).
Lappin, S. (ed.) (forthcoming), Handbook of contemporary semantics. Blackwell,
Oxford.
Leach, E. (1976), Culture and communication. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Leech, G. (1983), Principles of pragmatics. Longman, London.
Leech, G. and Thomas, J. (1990), 'Language, meaning and context: Pragmatics',
in Collinge 1990: 173-205.
Lemmon, E. (1965), Beginning logic. Nelson, London.
310
Bibliography
Bibliography
311
Mey, J. (ed.) (1986), Language and discourse: Text and protest. John Benjamins,
Amsterdam.
Mey, J. and Talbot, M. (1988), 'Computation and the soul'. Journal of
Pragmatics 12: 743-89.
Miller, G. and Johnson-Laird, P. (1976), Language and perception. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Minsky, M. (1977), 'Frame system theory', in Johnson-Laird and Wason 1977:
355-76.
Mitsunobu, M. (1993), 'A relevance theory bibliography'. Department of
English, Tokyo Metropolitan University.
Moeschler, J. (1989a), 'Pragmatic connectives, argumentative coherence and
relevance'. Argumentation 3.3: 321-39.
Moeschler, J. (1989b), Modelisation du dialogue. Representation de l'inference
argumentative. Hermes, Paris.
Moeschler, J. (ed.) (1989c), Argumentation, relevance and discourse. Argumentation 3.3. Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Moeschler, J. (1991), 'The pragmatic aspects of linguistic negation: Speech acts,
argumentation and pragmatic inference'. Argumentation 6: 51-75.
Moeschler, J. (1992), 'Une, deux ou trois negations?' Langue franr;;aise 94: 8-25.
Moeschler, J. (1993a), 'Relevance and conversation'. Lingua 90. 112: 149-71.
Moeschler, J. (1993b), 'Aspects pragmatiques de la reference temporelle: indetermination, ordre temporel et inference'. Langages 112: 39-54.
Moeschler, J. and Reboul, A. (1994), Dictionnaire encyclopedique de pragmatique. Seuil, Paris.
Moeschler, J., Reboul, A., Luscher, J.-M. and Jayez, J. (1994), Langage et
pertinence: Reference temporelle, anaphore, connecteurs et metaphore. Presses
Universitaires de Nancy, Nancy.
Morgan, J. (1979), 'Observations on the pragmatics of metaphor', in Ortony
1979: 136-47.
Morris, C. (1938), 'Foundations of the theory of signs', in Neurath, Carnap and
Morris 1938: 77-138. Reprinted in Morris 1971.
Morris, C. (1971), Writings on the general theory of signs. Mouton, The Hague.
Muller, J. (ed.) (1994), Towards a pragmatics of the audiovisual. NODUS,
Munster.
Munitz, M. and Unger, P. (eds) (1974), Semantics and philosophy: Studies in
contemporary philosophy. New York University Press, New York.
Nasta, D. (1991), Meaning in film: Relevant structures in soundtrack and
narrative. Peter Lang, Bern.
N eale, S. (1992), 'Paul Grice and the philosophy of language'. Linguistics and
Philosophy 15.5: 509-59.
Nebeska, I. (1991), 'Muze byt relevance postacujicim principem komunikace?'
Slovo a Slovesnost 52.2: 104-8.
Neisser, U. (ed.) (1982), Memory observed: Remembering in natural contexts.
W. H. Freeman, San Francisco, CA.
Neurath, 0., Carnap, R. and Morris, C. (eds) (1938), International encyclopaedia of unified science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
312
Bibliography
Newmeyer, F. (1988), Linguistics: The Cambridge Survey, vols I-IV. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Nishiyama, Y. (1992), 'Hatsuwa-kaishaku to Ninchi: on Kanrensei-riron nitsuite (Utterance interpretation and cognition: On Relevance Theory)', in
Anzai et al. 1992: 466-76.
Nishiyama, Y. (1993), 'Kontekusuto-kouka to Kanrensei: Kanrensei-riron no
Mondai-ten (Contextual effects and relevance: Some problems of relevance
theory)'. Eigo Seinen 139.5: 14-16.
Nishiyama, Y. (1995), 'Gengai no Imi wo Toraeru (How to read between the
lines)'. Gengo 24.4: 30-9.
N0lke, H. (1990), 'Pertinence et modalisateurs d'nonciation'. Cahiers de
linguistique fram;aise 11.
Oh, c.- K. and Dinneen, D. (eds) (1979), Syntax and semantics 11: Presupposition. Academic Press, New York.
O'Neill, J. (1988), 'Relevance and pragmatic inference'. Theoretical Linguistics
15: 241-61.
Ortony, A. (ed.) (1979), Metaphor and thought. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Parret, H. (ed.) (1994), Pretending to communicate. WaIter de Gruyter, Berlin.
Parret, H., Sbisa, M. and Verschueren, J. (1981), Possibilities and limitations of
pragmatics. John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Pateman, T. (1986), 'Relevance, contextual effects and least effort'. Poetics
Today 7.4: 745-54.
Patton, T. and Stampe, D. (1969), 'The rudiments of meaning: Ziff on Grice'.
Foundations of Language 5.1: 2-16.
Perrin, L. (forthcoming), L'ironie mise en trope, du sens litteral au sens figure.
University of Geneva, doctoral dissertation, to be published by Editions
Kime.
Philippaki-Warburton, I., Nicolaides, K. and Sifianou, M. (eds) (1994), Themes
in Greek linguistics. Papers from the 1st international conference on Greek
Linguistics (Reading 1993). John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Pilkington, A. (1991), 'The literary reading process: A relevance theory perspective', in Ibsch, Schram and Steen 1991: 117-23.
Pilkington, A. (1992), 'Poetic effects'. Lingua 87. 112: 29-51.
Pilkington, A. (1994), Poetic thoughts and poetic effects. University of London,
Ph.D. thesis.
Pike, K. (1967), Language in relation to a unified theory of the structure of
human behavior. Mouton, The Hague.
Politzer, G. (1990), 'Characterizing spontaneous inferences'. The Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 13.1: 177-8.
Politzer, G. (1993), La psychologie du raisonnement: Lois de la pragmatique et
de la logique formelle. These de Doctorat d'Etat, University of Paris VIII.
Posnanski, V. (1992), A relevance-based utterance processing system. Cambridge
University, Ph.D. thesis, University of Cambridge Laboratory, Technical
report, No. 246.
Prince, E. (1981), 'Towards a taxonomy of given-new information', in Cole
1981: 223-56.
Bibliography
313
Pulman, S. (1983), Word meaning and belief Croom Helm, London.
Putnam, H. (1975a), 'The meaning of "meaning''', in Gunderson 1975: 131-93.
Reprinted in Putnam 1975b: 215-7l.
Putnam, H. (1975b), Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers II.
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
'
Quine, W. (1960), Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Reboul, A. (1990a), Analyse de la metaphore et de la fiction. University of
Geneva, Ph.D. thesis.
Reboul, A. (1990b), 'The logical status of fictional discourse: What Searle's
speaker can't say to his hearer', in Burkhardt 1990: 336-63.
Reboul, A. (1992a), Rhetorique et stylistique de la fiction. Presses Universitaires
de Nancy, Nancy.
Reboul, A. (1992b), 'How much am I I and how much is she I?' Lingua 87:
169-202.
Reboul, A. (1994a), 'L'anaphore pronominale: le probleme de l'attribution des
referents', in Moeschler et al. 1994: 105-73.
Reboul, A. (1994b), 'The description of lies in speech-act theory', in Parret
1994: 292-8.
Reboul, A. (forthcoming), 'What (if anything) is accessibility? A relevanceoriented criticism of Ariel's Accessibility Theory of referring expressions'. To
appear in Acts of the 6th international conference on functional grammar
(York, 1994).
Recanati, F. (1979), La transparence et l'enonciation. Seuil, Paris.
Recanati, F. (1987), Meaning and force. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Recanati, F. (1989), 'The pragmatics of what is said'. Mind and Language 4.4:
295-329. Reprinted in Davis 1991: 97-120.
Recanati, F. (1993), Direct reference: From language to thought. Blackwell,
Oxford.
Recanati, F. (1994), 'Contextualism and anti-contextualism in the philosophy of
language', in Tsohatzidis 1994: 156-66.
Recanati, F. (forthcoming), 'The alleged priority of literal interpretation'. To
appear in Cognitive Science.
Reddy, M. (1979), 'The conduit metaphor - a case of frame conflict in our
language about language', in Ortony 1979: 284-324.
Reinhart, T. (1981), 'Pragmatics and linguistics: An analysis of sentence topics'.
Philosophica 27: 53-94.
Richards, C. (1985), 'Inferential pragmatics and the literary text'. Journal of
Pragmatics 9: 261-85.
Rips, L. (1983), 'Cognitive processes in propositional reasoning'. Psychological
Review 90.1: 38-7l.
Roberts, L. (1991), 'Relevance as an explanation of communication'. Linguistics
and Philosophy 14.4: 453-72.
Rochemont, M. (1986), Focus in generative grammar. John Benjamins,
Amsterdam.
Rouchota, V. (1992), 'On the referential-attributive distinction'. Lingua 87.112:
137-67.
314
Bibliography
Bibliography
315
316
Bibliography
Bibliography
317
2.
Trotter, D. (1992), 'Analysing literary prose: The relevance of relevance theory'.
Lingua 87.112: 11-27.
Tsohatzidis, S. (1994), Foundations of speech act theory: Philosophical and
linguistic perspectives. Routledge, London.
Tyler, L. and Marslen-Wilson, W. (1977), 'The on-line effect of semantic
context on syntactic processing'. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior 16.6: 683-92.
Uchida, S. (forthcoming), 'Text and relevance'. To appear in Carston, Uchida
and Song forthcoming.
Unger, C. (1994), 'The scope of discourse connectives and its relation to the
utterance in which it occurs'. University College London, M.A. dissertation,
to appear in Journal of Linguistics.
Vandepitte, S. (1989), 'A pragmatic function of intonation'. Lingua 79: 265-97.
Vandepitte, S. (1993), A pragmatic study of the expression and the interpretation
of causality: Conjuncts and conjunctions in modern spoken British English.
Koninklijke Academie voor Wetenschappen, Letteren en Schone Kunsten van
Belgie, Brussels.
Verschueren, J. and Bertuccelli-Papi, M. (eds) (1987), The pragmatic perspective.
John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Verschueren, J., Ostman, J.-O. and Blommaert, J. (forthcoming), Handbook of
Pragmatics: Manual. John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Vicente, B. (1992), 'Metaphor, meaning and comprehension'. Pragmatics 2:
49-62.
Vygotsky, L. (1962), Thought and language, translated from the Russian (1934).
MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Walker, R. (1975), 'Conversational implicatures', in Blackburn 1975: 133-81.
Walker, R. (1989), 'Review of Relevance'. Mind and Language 4.112: 151-9.
Watson, R. (1995), 'Relevance and definition'. Journal of Child Language 22:
211-22.
318
Bibliography
Bibliography
319
Wolf, G. (ed.) (1992), New departures in linguistics. Garland, New York.
W right, R. (1975), 'MeaningNN and conversational implicature', in Cole and
Morgan 1975: 363-82.
Yoshimura, A. (1993a), 'Explicature and implicature formation in the modeling
of metaphor and metonymy'. Osaka University Papers in English Linguistics
I: 175-84.
Yoshimura, A. (1993b), 'Pragmatic and cognitive aspects of negative polarity'.
Osaka University Papers in English Linguistics I: l41-73.
Yu, P. (1979), 'On the Gricean program about meaning'. Linguistics and
Philosophy 3.2: 273-88.
Zegarac, V. (1991), Tense, aspect and relevance. University of London, Ph.D.
thesis.
Zegarac, V. (1993), 'Some observations on the pragmatics of the progressive'.
Lingua 90.1/2: 201-20.
Ziff, P. (1967), 'On H. P. Grice's account of meaning'. Analysis 28: 1-8.
Reprinted in Steinberg and Jakobovits 1971: 60-5.
Ziv, y. (1988), 'On the rationality of "Relevance" and the relevance of
"Rationality"'.Journal of Pragmatics 12.5/6: 535-45.
Index
Blass, R., 289 nnl9, 21, 295 n9, 296 n15, 297 nn21;
23,26
Booth, W., 294 n4c
Brockway, D., 289 n21
Brown, G., 70,216-17,287 n4, 288 n12
Burton-Roberts, N., 295 n8, 297 n26
Cairns, H., 288 n6
Cameron, D., 295 n8
Campbell, J., 296 n9, 298 n28
Cara, F., 260
Carlson, T., 283 n22
Carnap, R., 79-80
Carston, R., 257-8, 286 nnl6, 19,288 n4, 295 n7,
296 nnlO, 16,297 nnl8, 26, 298 nn32, 33, 34
categories, logical and syntactic, 205-6
central thought processes, 47-8, 65-7, 71-5, 83-5,
90,151-5,165-6,185-7,293 nn2a, 2b
Chafe, W., 288 n12
Chametzky, R., 295 n8
Charolles, M., 295 n8
Chiappe, D., 295 n3
Chomsky, N., 8,94,196
Clark, B., 296 n9, 297 nn22, 26
Clark, H., 17-20, 283 n22, 284 n29, 288 nn9, 12,
290 n25, 296 nU
code, 3-15,24-8, 36-8, 43, 52-3, 63, 65, 166, 167,
169-70,172-6,177,191-3,282 n16
code model of communication, 2-21, 32, 44-6, 58,
166,169-70,174,196,230-1
cognitive effect, 263-6
cognitive environment, 38-46, 58-60, 62-4,151,
197,198,200,201,217-18,224,284 n32
coherence, 289 n 19
cohesion, 289 n19
Coleridge, S., 57
common knowledge, see mutual knowledge
communication
explicit, 11,37,55-60,162-3,174-6,182-93,
217-24,248,249,256-8,298 n34
implicit, 11, 12,34-7,55-60,162-3,174-5,
322
Index
182-3,193-202,217-24,235-7,239-42,
272-8, 298 nn30, 34
overt, 30-1, 60-4, 282 n20
strong, 59-60, 174-6
weak, 59-60, 212
see also code model of communication;
ostensive-inferential communication
concept, 85-93, 204
classificatory, 79, 124, 144, 152, 182
comparative, 79-81, 124-9, 144-5, 152-3, 182
quantitative, 79-81, 129-32
theoretical, 119-20, 125
conceptual-procedural distinction, 258, 297 n21;
see also constraints on relevance; semantics,
procedural confirmation, 65-6, 68-9, 75-82,
109-17, 164-72,201,211
see also strengthening
connectives, logical, 37, 84-103, 183,288 n4
constraints on relevance, 258-9, 289 n21, 297 nn22,
23
context, 12, 15-21, 36-7, 67, 89, 103, 118-23, 125,
129,132-51,163 n21, 167, 185-7,209,216-17,
221-2,223,236-7,287 n7
contextual effect, 108-37, 142-51, 156-7,202,204,
209-10,233-7,263-6,269-70,286 n26, 294
n2d
contextualisation, 107, 108, 113-16,286 n16
contradiction, 95, 114-15, 120-1, 148, 294 n2d
convention 25-7,52-3,217,226,230-1,249,282
n16
co-operative principle, 33, 35, 36, 161-2, 256, 260,
267-8, 273-4, 294 n3d, 296 n 14
Cormack, A., 288 n4
Cruttenden, A., 288 n12
Culpeper, J., 295 n8
Cunningham, c., 295 n8
Davidson, D., 281 nil
Davies, M., 281 nil
Davis, S., 296 nl0
de B"eaugrande, R., 70
declarative, 246-7
see also mood
deductive device, 93-108, 110-17,126,137-40,
145, 286 n20, 287 n7, 293 n2b
description, 224-31, 232, 247-8, 289 n22
descriptive use, 224-31, 232, 247-8, 259, 289 n22
Dinneen, D., 288 n12
disambiguation, 12, 13,34, 168-9, 175, 179,183-7,
190-1,204-8,256-7,288 n6, 296 n14
discourse markers, 258-9, 297 n22
Dressier, W., 70
Dretske, F., 2
Ducrot, 0., 281 n7, 297 nn20, 21, 26
Durant, A., 297 n27
echoic interpretation, 238-9, 259, 297 n26
effability, principle of, 191-2
efficiency, 46-9, 152, 167-8,204,263-6,289 n21
elimination rule, 86-93, 97-103
and-elimination, 86
conjunctive modus ponens, 99, 100
disjunctive modus ponens, 99, 100
modus ponendo ponens, 87,98-9,100,105
Index
of communication, 161-2,267-8
Goatly, A., 297 n24
Good, D., 287 n3
Goodman, N., 69
Gorayska, B., 295 n8
Gordon, D., 36
grammar, generative, 8, 9-15, 94, 172-6,212-13
Green, G., 203, 288 n9, 294 n3d
Green, K., 297 n27
Grice, H.P., 2, 14,21-38,53-4,61,64, 161-3,
182-3,195-6,200-1,240-1,256,267-8,273,
281 nn7, 11,282 nn14, 17, 19,283 nn23, 24,
284 n30, 287 n10, 296 n12, 297 n19
see also maxims of communication; speaker's
meaning
Grimshaw, J., 253
Groefsema, M., 296 nn9, 17,297 n22
Grundy, P., 295 n8
guessing, 290 n30
Guijarro Morales,J.-L., 296 n10
Gundel, J., 296 n15
Gussenhoven, C, 288 n17
Gutt, E.-A, 259, 295 n7, 296 ng, 297 nn21, 22
Haegeman, L., 296 n17, 297 n21
hair-drier example, 30, 31, 61, 62-3
Halliday, M., 288 n12
Hamamoto, H., 297 n24
Happe, F., 260, 296 n9
Harman, G., 281 n11
Harnish, R.M., 17,20,69-70,251-2,281 nn7, 11,
283 n27, 287 n2, 288 nn3, 10,289 n23, 290
n27, 296 n14, 297 n22, 298 n32
Haviland, S., 283 n22, 288 n12, 296 n13
Hawkins, J., 296 n15
Higashimori, 1., 297 n21
Hinkelman, E., 293 n1a
Hirst, D., 295 n3, 296 n17
Hjelmslev, L., 7
Hobbs, J. 287 n6
Hogaboam, T., 288 n6
Horn, L., 296 n17, 298 nn30, 32
Hugly, P., 288 n10
humour, 297 n28
Hymes, D., 297 n24
hyperbole, 235-6
Ifantidou, E., 296 n9, 297 nn23, 26
illocutionary force, 10-11,226,243-54
imperative, 243, 246-7, 249-51, 254;
see also mood
implication
analytic, 104-8,204,215
background,209-11,214-17
contextual, 107-8, 112, 120, 126, 137, 143, 147,
148,204,221-2,233-5,275-6
foreground, 209-11, 214-17, 289 n20
logical,84
non-trivial,97-103
synthetic, 104-8, 112, 113, 137, 139
323
324
Index
179-80,200-1,230-1,249,271,273-8,283
nn24, 26, 287 n2, 296 n14, 298 n30
Mayher, J., 298 n28
meiosis, 238
mental model, 285 nIl, 286 n24, 287 n2
mention, 289 n25
metaphor, 180,224-5,231-7,242-3,248,251,259,
279, 283 n27, 290 n26, 297 n24
metonymy, 237
Mey, J., 295 n3
Miller, G., 286 n18, 164 n25
Minsky, Mo, 285 n14
Mitsonobu, M., 296 nIl
modularity, 65-7,71-2,83,177-8,260,293 nn2a, 2b
Moeschler,J., 295 nn6, 7,296 nn9, 10,297 nnl7,
21, 22, 23, 26, 298 n28
mood, 73, 180,247,297 nn22, 26
imperative, 73, 247, 254, 297 n25
indicative, 73, 180,247,254,297 n26
subjunctive, 247
Morgan, J., 288 n9, 294 n3d
Morris, c., 281 n6
mutual knowledge, 15-21, 38-46, 179-80,281 nl0,
283 n21, 284 nn29, 2, 293 nla
see also mutual manifestness
Nasta, D., 296 n9, 298 n28
Neale, 5., 296 nnl2, 16
Nebeska, 1., 295 n8
Neisser, U., 281 n8
Nishiyama, y., 295 n8
N"lke, H., 297 n23
Oh, C.-Ko, 288 n12
O'Neill, J., 295 n8
optimal processing, 144, 152-3, 154, 156-7
ostension, 49-54, 71, 155
ostensive-inferential communication, 23, 49, 50-4,
60-4,65-6,153-72,174,176,226-31,244-5,
271-2,275
see also inferential model of communication
parallelism, 213, 222-4
Parkes, c., 285 n13, 286 n18
parsing, 204-8
Pateman, T., 295 n3
Patton, T., 281 nIl
Peirce, c., 6
perceptual processes, see input processes
Perfetti, c., 288 n6
Pemer, J., 293 nla, 295 n3
Perrin, L., 296 n9, 297 n24
phenomena, 40,151-5,160-1
Pike, K., 7
Pilkington, A., 296 n9, 297 nn24, 27
poetic effects, 196,217-24,235-7
politeness, 297 n28
Politzer, G., 260, 295 n3, 296 n9
Posnanski, V., 296 n9, 298 n29
pragmatics, 10-15,20-1,36-8,56-60,69-71,
Index
141-2,179-80,182-3,194-6,201-2,217,
230-1,243-7,281 nn6, 7, 289 n21
Gricean, 21-38, 60-4, 161-3, 182-3, 195-6,
200-1,240-1,256,267-8,273-8,296 n13
predictions, 245
presumption of relevance, 156-9, 161, 164-72,234,
266-78,287 nIl, 294 n3c, 298 n31
presupposition, 202, 203, 213-15, 217, 283 n27, 287
n6, 289 nnl8, 21
Prince, E., 288 n12
principle of relevance, 50,158-63,166-72,178,
184-5,195,196-7,201,220-2,229,231,
233-5,248,249,251,253,254,262-78,287
nIl, 293 nlc, 294 n3d, 294 n4b
processing effort, 46-50,124-32,136-7,142,
149-50,156-7,166-8,185,190-1,196-7,204,
213,216,220-2,223,233-6,268-9
promises, 245, 246, 290 n28
propositional form, 72-5,179-93,228,231-7,
252-3
see also assumption; logical form
prototype, 88,91-2, 138
see also encyclopaedia
Pulman, S., 286 n16
Pumam, H., 91, 286 n15
questions, 194,251-3
indirect, 251-2
relevant, 203, 207-8, 214, 215
rhetorical, 247, 251-2
Wh-, 203, 207-8, 252-3
yes-no, 225, 252-3
Quine, W., 288 n8
quotation, 227-8
see also echoic interpretation; mention
Reboul, A., 295 nn6, 7, 296 nn9, 15,297 nn22, 24,
27
Recanati, .,281 n11, 282 n19, 290 n27, 296 nnl5,
16,297 nnl7, 22, 24
Reddy, R., 281 nl
reference assignment, 10, 12, 17-21, 91, 175, 179,
183-4,187-8,190-4,204-8,214-15,256-7,
288 n7, 296 nn13, 14, 15
Reinhart, T., 288 n12
relevance, 36, 38, 46-50, 51-2, 70-1, 75, 103, 117,
. 118-72,209-10,238,252-3,260-78,298 n30
m a context, 123-132, 142, 265
and evolution, 261-3
to an individual, 142-51,265-6,294 n3a
maximal, 261-3, 293 nlc, 298 n30
optimal, 157-60, 194, 196,204,208,214,218,
222,234,266-72,287 nIl
of phenomena, 151-5,261-3,287 n8, 294 n3a
of stimuli, 153-5
to a topic, 216-17
and truth, 263-6, 293, nIb
see also principle of relevance
reminders, 137, 143, 149-50,211
repetition, 219-22
325
326
Index
Smith, N., 260, 281 n4, 289 n21, 295 n7, 296 nl0,
297 nn21, 23
Soames, S., 289 n18
social factors in communication, 30-1, 60-64, 279,
297 n28
Song, N.-S., 297 n24
speaker's meaning, 21-38, 53-4, 56-7, 281 nll
speech acts, 10-11,224-6,243-54,258,259,290
nn27, 28, 297 nn 22, 25
assertive, 243-4, 246-7
directive, 244, 246-7, 251-2
indirect, 244, 283 n27
see also assertions; promises; questions;
reminders; saying; telling; thanking; threats;
warnings
Sperber, D., 258, 260, 281 nn3, 4, 10, 283 nn24, 26,
285 nn4, 6, 288 nl0, 289 nn22, 25, 293 nnla,
2a, 294 nn3d, 3e, 295 nn4, 5, 7, 296 nn13, 16,
297 nn21, 22, 23, 24, 27
Stainton, R., 296 n9, 297 n17
Stalnaker, R., 283 n27, 287 n6, 289 n21
Stampe, D., 281 nIl
Stenning, K., 287 n6
stimuli, 2, 29,58,61,63,67,81,132,160,163,164,
177
ostensive, 153-61, 166, 168-9, 174...:.5, 189,
226-7,254
relevance of, 153-5
Strawson, P., 21, 23, 24, 28-30, 60-1, 214-15, 281
nll, 283 n21
strengthening, 120, 147-8
dependent, 112, 114
independent, 112-14, 143
retroactive, 115-17, 190-1
see also assumption; confirmation
stress, 202-3, 209-17, 288 nB
contrastive, 212-3, 288 nnll, 16
stylistic effects of, 196, 202-24
Sun, y., 295 n8
Swinney, D., 288 n6
symbolism, 281 n5
synecdoche, 237
Taglicht, J., 288 n12
Talbot, M., 295 n3
Tanaka, K., 296 n9, 297 n28
Tanenhaus, M., 288 n6
Taylor, J., 297 n17
Taylor, T., 295 n8
telling, 246-7, 249-51, 294 n4a
thanking, 245, 246, 290 n28
theme, 202, 215-16
Thomas, J., 295 n7
Thomason, R" 93
thoughts, 29,9,10,149,191-3,200,229-31,233-5,
238-9, 252-4, 288 n8
see also central thought processes
threats, 245
Tirkkonen-Condit, S., 297 0.25
Todorov, T., 6
Toolan, M., 295 n8
topic, 202, 216-17
translation, 228, 259, 297 n25
Travis, c., 288 n4, 295 n3
tropes, 224-43, 259, 297 n24
Trotter, D., 297 n27
truth conditions, 214, 227, 296 n14
see also description
truth and relevance, 263-6
Tsimpli, 1., 260
Tversky, A., 285 nn8, 9
Tyler, L., 288 n6
Uchida, S., 297 n27
Unger, c., 297 n21
van der Merwe, c., 297 n25
Vandepitte,S., 296 n9, 297 n21
Vicente, B., 297 n24
Voltaire, 241, 294 n4c
Vygotsky, 1., 6
Walker, E., 285 n13, 286 n18, 295 n3
Walker, R., 283 n24, 288 nl0
warnings, 245
Watson, R., 260
Watts, R., 297 n23
Weaver, W., 4, 5
Wilks, Y., 295 n8
Wilson, D., 258, 281 nn4, 10,283 nn24, 26, 27, 288
nl0, 289 nn18, 25, 293 nla, 294 n3d, 295 nn4,
5,7,296 nnto, 13, 15, 16,297 nn20, 21, 22, 23,
24,27
Wilson, J., 298 n28
Winckler, W., 295 n6, 297 n25
Winograd, T., 285 n14, 288 n5
word meaning, 90-3
Wright, R., 281 nll
Yoshimura, A., 297 nn23, 24, 26
Yu, P., 281 nIl
Yule, G., 70, 216-17, 287 n4, 288 n12
Zegarac, V., 296 n9, 297 n23
zeugma, see gapping
Ziff, P., 281 nll
Ziv, Y., 295 n8
Zwicky, A., 290 n29