The document discusses key objections that have been made to the ontological argument for God's existence. It identifies three main areas of debate: 1) objections based on the definition of "God", 2) objections that "existence" is not a predicate of God, and 3) objections that existential claims cannot be derived from definitions alone. It provides examples of objections in each category and notes that full analysis of each is required to receive full marks.
The document discusses key objections that have been made to the ontological argument for God's existence. It identifies three main areas of debate: 1) objections based on the definition of "God", 2) objections that "existence" is not a predicate of God, and 3) objections that existential claims cannot be derived from definitions alone. It provides examples of objections in each category and notes that full analysis of each is required to receive full marks.
The document discusses key objections that have been made to the ontological argument for God's existence. It identifies three main areas of debate: 1) objections based on the definition of "God", 2) objections that "existence" is not a predicate of God, and 3) objections that existential claims cannot be derived from definitions alone. It provides examples of objections in each category and notes that full analysis of each is required to receive full marks.
The document discusses key objections that have been made to the ontological argument for God's existence. It identifies three main areas of debate: 1) objections based on the definition of "God", 2) objections that "existence" is not a predicate of God, and 3) objections that existential claims cannot be derived from definitions alone. It provides examples of objections in each category and notes that full analysis of each is required to receive full marks.
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 4
Ontological argument and the relationship
between reason and faith
0 1 Analyse key objections that have been made to the
ontological argument. The Specification identifies three areas for debate and full marks are available for a full analysis of each one. In each case the fault with the argument should be clear.
Those based on the definition of God
This is not what all understand to be God, (e.g. following Aquinas); definition not coherent what Anselm means by greater can be explored here, (e.g. Norman Malcolm describes the idea that it is greater to exist in reality than in the mind alone as remarkably queer); definition not informative / lacks features of God of classical theism.
Those based on the idea that existence is a predicate of God.
Analysis of the concept of existence or of what it means to exist and the demonstration that in normal discourse, existence is not a property or predicate of an object. Expect reference to the established debate, e.g. from Kant.
Those based on the possibility of deriving existential claims from
definition. Some conflation with the above is likely but expect an analysis of the idea of an existential claim as the claim that there is something corresponding to a particular definition in the real world so even if I have the idea in mind of God whose non -existence is impossible, I may still ask if there is something in the real world that should correctly be called God. Russells argument is of particular value here. (30 marks) AO1
0 2 To what extent would the success or failure of the ontological
argument have any significance for religious faith?
A well-informed discussion must deal with the likely consequences of both
success and failure. It may assume or analyse one or more concepts of faith and consider what success or failure would actually be. Some of the following points may be raised: Proof negates / would negate faith, so failure as proof neither looked for nor relevant. The argument starts from faith rather than ending with it its success is giving understanding to faith and would be significant for faith. Success in challenging the fools concept of God would be valuable. The greatest conceivable being (the God of philosophy) is not the God of (theistic) faith so argument is irrelevant. For an answer which discusses only the significance of one of success or failure maximum Level 5. (20 marks) AO2
Question 2 Religious language
03 Explain what it means to say that religious language is: non-cognitive symbolic. Candidates should show understanding of both the non-cognitive theory of religious language and the idea that religious language is symbolic, with appropriate use of examples and reference to scholarly views. There is an overlap between non-cognitive and symbolic, so apply suggestions below flexibly. Key idea: language not used literally but represents something other than itself. Non-cognitive: not intended to convey information e.g. Braithwaite and the idea of religious language as moral discourse expressing attitudes and intentions. Religious language as evocative e.g. intended to evoke a sense of the presence of God rather than to inform the intellect about God. Symbolic: Note analogical use of language may, but need not, be included here. Symbolic language participates in the reality it relates to (Tillich) so opening up that reality to human understanding. The power of symbols changes over time and their interpretation may vary. Use of symbolism in (e.g.) religious poetry, myth, scripture, prayer. Answers that deal with only one of non-cognitive or symbolic, max level 5. (30 marks) AO1
04 It is not possible to talk meaningfully about God. Evaluate
this claim. This can be approached in a variety of ways from both atheist and faith perspectives. The verification/ falsification debate may be, but need not be, used. In support (e.g.) Verification / falsification debate; Impossible to talk meaningfully when there is no shared experience; All words take their meaning from empirical world; God, since he is transcendent, not in the same category, so words do not apply; Contrary to claim (e.g.) Refutation of verification / falsification principles God, through scripture, provides the words that may be used; God guides human beings to a true understanding, the words are a medium of religious experience; God as a term has rules for its use that is its meaning e.g., God is omnipotent and God is omniscient, are analytical statements and true by definition. (20 marks) AO2
Question 4 The problem of evil
07 Explain the free will defence and examine its purpose. Explain: The free will defence is presented in a variety of ways, and markers must expect a variety of different, but equally acceptable, approaches to this question. Creation as it left the creator was both perfect and free traditionally understood to mean that Angels and Man were free to act as they chose. Free will is an essential part of developing as a spiritual being, in a freely chosen loving relationship with God, which is the greatest good. Denying human beings this free choice, and the possibility of this greatest good, would not have been good / loving. All evil is the consequence of the abuse of free will. It is not the fault of God. God will not intervene to remove the consequences of free will because this would make the use of free will valueless. Human beings have to appreciate the value and significance of free will; extending this, some argue that free will can only be meaningfully exercised in a world like this in which what we call natural evil occurs. In this way the free will defence may explain the existence of natural evil, but many presentations of it simply do not tackle the issue of natural evil at all. Purpose: to answer the challenge to faith posed by evil; to construct a theodicy which shows that the existence of evil and of an all-loving and all powerful God is possible; to defend the justice of God in the face of evil. There is not expected to be any balance between the two parts of the answer. Max level 5 if only one tackled. (30 marks) AO1 08 How far is free will a satisfactory explanation for the existence of evil in a world created by God? This may, but need not, include a debate about whether free will actually exists. The following points do not form an exhaustive list, nor is it expected that candidates should refer to all of them. Finitely perfect beings choosing to act against Gods will is that a contradiction? Did suffering, and therefore evil, predate the first moral evil? How can moral evil explain natural evil? Where did the temptation to do evil come from if evil only existed after the decision was made? The claim that God had the choice between creating robots controlled by God and beings who would freely choose to do wrong is a false one. God could, and should, have created beings who always freely chose to do good. Gods foreknowledge must mean that he knew the choices humanity would make, and the consequences of those choices, before they happened. Knowing this was Gods action in creating such beings a loving one? (20 marks) AO2