Modernism Polarity and The Rule of Law
Modernism Polarity and The Rule of Law
Modernism Polarity and The Rule of Law
5-8-2013
Recommended Citation
Manderson, Desmond (2012) "Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law," Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities: Vol. 24: Iss. 2, Article
1.
Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Yale
Journal of Law & the Humanities by an authorized administrator of Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please
contact julian.aiken@yale.edu.
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
Articles
Desmond Manderson
* Future Fellow, College of Law / Research School of Humanities and the Arts, The Australian
National University, Canberra.
475
the rule of law. But by paying attention to the historical moment when
these two traditions most dramatically collided, there is much we can
learn. Not only does the historical context sharpen and intensify the issues
at stake, but it also reveals a third alternative that ignores neither the
critique of positivism nor the rule of law. In this Article, I will call this
alternative "polarity," and I want to show where and why it arises from
the historical context of modernism and what implications it might have
for a post-positivist rule of law. History therefore teaches us not only why
the problems with the rule of law have been so long-lasting, but what we
might do about it. Perhaps, after all, the peril to the rule of law might be
averted not by ignoring the critique of positivism but by embracing it.
In Part I, I show how the basic assumptions of positivism parallel those
of the rule of law such that the intellectual critique leveled at the former
causes acute problems for the latter. Yet, those who have attempted to
engage with the critique from the point of view of the rule of law have
merely avoided the issue. I illustrate that avoidance by looking at recent
work by Brian Tamanaha in particular.
In Part II, I show that missed opportunities and circular debates around
this critical issue go back many years. It is only by going back to the
historical and interdisciplinary origins of the conflict between the rule of
law and legal critique that we can see it properly and respond to it
adequately. History, I will argue, affords us insight, perspective, and new
opportunities. The challenge to the rule of law crystallized and was indeed
at its most intense at the height of the movement of modernism in the
fraught years following World War I. Right across Europe and in
America, the "crisis of modernity" unleashed by that cataclysm
profoundly undermined the faith of the West in its systems, mechanisms,
structures, and institutions. That led in many quarters to a reactionary
romanticism, a kind of anti-positivism of which, in relation to law and
politics, Carl Schmitt is emblematic. The force of Schmitt's argument
against the very possibility of rule-constrained decisionmaking has not
diminished. Powerful traces of transcendentalism or romanticism, which
would throw out the baby of the rule of law with the bathwater of
positivism, can still be found across many aspects of contemporary legal
theory.
Returning to the roots of the problem sharpens what is at stake in this
debate and demonstrates how closely the legal and political issue is tied to
a literary, aesthetic, philosophical and cultural context-modernism. In
Part III, I argue that while post-war modernism dramatizes the standoff
between positivism and romanticism, it also contains the resources to
move beyond it-resources which, like modernism itself, legal theory
keeps forgetting. The language and ideas of "polarity" articulated by D.H.
Lawrence in the early 1920s is one such resource. Polarity expresses
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 2
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
A. Orthodoxy
The rule of law seems to depend upon positivist assumptions about the
1. H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation ofLaw and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593, 614-15
(1958).
2. Owen Dixon, Address upon Taking the Oath of Office (Apr. 21, 1952) (transcript available in
85 CLR xiv-xv) (Austl.).
3. See generally RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY (1978).
4. The Declaration of Delhi provided an expansive statement of the rule of law which went well
beyond merely formal or procedural guarantees. It treated the rule of law as "a dynamic concept ...
which should be employed not only to safeguard and advance the civil and political rights of the
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 4
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
expanding circle of expectations implicit in the rule of law," but these add
to, rather than subtract from, its central features, most notably a
commitment to protecting values of predictability and certainty in the law.
This much was evident as far back as Aristotle, who famously
distinguished rule by "the best men" from rule by "the best laws."' As the
rule of law took its modem shape it came to express other concerns too:
the tripartite division of powers, habeas corpus, and law's equal
application to all persons.' But it never lost its principal commitment to a
theory of interpretation and certainty. As Friedrich Hayek put it in his
conservative manifesto, The Road to Serfdom, the rule of law does not
ensure justice. Rather, it ensures certainty and clarity in the application of
government power, which for Hayek is itself a moral principle:
"[G]overnment in all its actions is bound by rules fixed and announced
beforehand-rules which make it possible to foresee with fair certainty
how the authority will use its coercive powers in given circumstances, and
to plan one's individual affairs on the basis of this knowledge."' Thus,
positivist theories of interpretation seem to form the necessary condition
of what it means to do justice "according to law."
B. Critique
Yet critiques of this claim for a rational, abstract, and certain objectivity
have only multiplied with the passing years, from legal realists and
Marxists to feminists in the 1970s, race theorists and critical legal studies
in the 1980s, and post-structural theorists in the 1990s. Thus, according to
Derrida, justice embodies two opposed impulses: equal treatment and
singular respect. Justice expresses an aspiration towards "law or right,
legitimacy or legality, stabilisable and statutory, calculable, a system of
regulated and coded prescriptions"' and at the same time wishes to find a
unique and singular response to the particular situation and person before
us. Justice is both general and unique; it involves treating everybody the
same and treating everybody differently.9 If we could divorce justice from
law, then this would not present a problem. We could apply the law in
court and talk about justice over lunch. But this response will not work.
The rule of law tells us to follow the rules, but every legal decision
individual in a free society, but also to establish social, economic, educational and cultural conditions
under which his legitimate aspirations and dignity may be realized." INTERNATIONAL COMMISSION OF
JURISTS, THE RULE OF LAW IN A FREE SOCIETY: A REPORT ON THE INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS OF
JURISTS 2 (1959).
5. ARISTOTLE, POLITICS 1286a (Harris Rackham trans., 1932).
6. A.V. DICEY, INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF THE LAW OF THE CONSTITUTION 203 (1902).
7. FRIEDRICH HAYEK, THE ROAD TO SERFDOM 54 (1944).
8. Jacques Derrida, Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority, II CARDOZO L. REV.
919, 959 (1990).
9. Id. at 961.
C Response
Many scholars thus reject such critiques of legal interpretation on
purely normative grounds, dismissing them just because the rule of law
10. RICHARD BEARDSWORTH, DERRIDA AND THE POLITICAL 110 (1996) (arguing that the aporia
of law is nothing but the aporia of time); see also id. at 37, 98-121.
11. See Lon Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to ProfessorHart, 71 HARV. L. REV.
630, 661-69 (1958).
12. H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 121 (1961).
13. Brian Langille, Revolution Without Foundation: The Grammar of Scepticism and Law, 33
MCGILL L.J. 451, 455 (1988).
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 6
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
14. BRIAN TAMANAHA, LAW AS A MEANS TO AN END: THREAT TO THE RULE OF LAW (2006)
[hereinafter TAMANAHA, LAW AS A MEANS TO AN END]; BRIAN TAMANAHA, ON THE RULE OF LAW:
HISTORY, POLITICS, THEORY (2004); see also TREVOR ALLAN, CONSTITUTIONAL JUSTICE: A LIBERAL
THEORY OF THE RULE OF LAW (2001); WILLIAM SCHEUERMAN, CARL SCHMITT: THE END OF LAW
(1999); John Gardner, The Legality ofthe Law, 17 RATIO JURIS 168 (2004); Andrei Marmor, The Rule
ofLaw and Its Limits, 23 LAW & PHIL. I (2004); Jeremy Waldron, Is the Rule ofLaw an Essentially
Contested Phenomenon?, 21 LAW & PHIL. 137 (2002).
15. TAMANAHA, LAW AS A MEANS TO AN END, supra note 14, at 236.
16. Id.
17. Id. at 237-44.
18. Id. at 227-29.
that would be the death of the rule of law. But the real question seems to
me how to face the critique and not how to ignore it. If law does involve
"madness"-an unavoidable "moment of undecidability"l 9 in which the
judge merely intuits what justice requires-what then? Must we ignore
the critique or forget the rule of law?
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 8
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
24. See RICHARD MURPHY, COLLINGWOOD AND THE CRISIS OF WESTERN CIVILIZATION: ART,
METAPHYSICS AND DIALECTIC 105, 142, 233 (2008).
25. M.H. ABRAMS, NATURAL SUPERNATURALISM 181 (1971).
26. Id.at220-21.
27. Max Weber, Science as Vocation, Speech at Munich University (1918), reprinted in FROM
MAX WEBER: ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGY 129, 155 (H.H. Gcrth & C. Wright Mills trans. and eds.,1946);
see also RICHARD SVEDBERG, THE MAX WEBER DICTIONARY: KEY WORDS AND CENTRAL CONCEPTS
63 (2005); MAX WEBER, THE PROTESTANT ETHIC AND THE SPIRIT OF CAPITALISM (Talcott Parsons
trans., Routledge 1992) (1904).
28. See, e.g., OTTO DIX, DER KREIG (1924); JAMES JOYCE, ULYSSES (1922); RICHARD MURPHY,
COLLINGWOOD AND THE CRISIS OF WESTERN CIVILIZATION (2008); VIRGINIA WOOLF, TO THE
LIGHTHOUSE (1928).
29. See, e.g., PETER FITZPATRICK, MODERNISM AND THE GROUNDS OF LAW (2001).
30. JEFFREY HERF, REACTIONARY MODERNISM (1984).
31. CARL SCHMITT, POLITICAL ROMANTICISM (Guy Oakes trans., The MIT Press 1986) (1919).
32. CHARLES FERRALL, MODERNIST WRITING AND REACTIONARY POLITICS (2004); see also
HERF, supra note 30.
33. CARL SCHMITT, POLITICAL THEOLOGY: FOUR CHAPTERS ON THE CONCEPT OF SOVEREIGNTY
6-13 (George Schwab trans., MIT Press 1985) (1922).
34. This was essentially the argument made by Kelsen in his work on sovereignty at the same
time as Schmitt. See HANS KELSEN, DAS PROBLEM DER SOUVERANITAAT UND DIE THEORIE DES
VOLKERRECHTS (IDC 1986) (1920). It was also made by H.L.A. Hart, still more explicitly, in his
discussion of the "penumbra" of legal interpretation in his debate with Lon Fuller. See H.L.A. Hart,
Positivism and the SeparationofLaw and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593, 614-15 (1958).
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 10
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
35. SCHEUERMAN, supra note 14, at 585; CARL SCHMITT, DIE DIKTATUR 585 (6th ed. 1994)
(1921).
36. DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND
HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR 42 (1997).
37. SCHMITT, supra note 31, at 13.
38. SCHEUERMAN, supra note 14; CARL SCHMITT, GESETZ UND URTEIL. EINE UNTERSUCHUNG
ZUM PROBLEM DER RECHTSPRAXIS [LAW AND JUDGMENT: AN INVESTIGATION INTO THE PROBLEM OF
LEGAL PRACTICE] (MIinchen Beck 1969) (1912).
39. William Scheuerman, Legal Indeterminacy and the OriginsofNazi Legal Thought, 17 HIST.
POL. THOUGHT 571, 587 (1996).
40. SCHMITT, supra note 31, at 54-55; Carl Schmitt, Der Fiihrerschitzt das Recht [The Leader
Protects the Law], 39 DEUTSCHE JURISTEN-ZEITUNG, 945-50 (1934).
41. The miraculous might be defined as a fact or reality which emerges despite its physical
impossibility-that is, "against the law." The analogy draws our attention to the relationship between
Schmitt's jurisprudence and his arch-conservative Catholicism. The connection is made explicit in
SCHMITT, supra note 31, and is discussed in GIORGIO AGAMBEN, STATE OF EXCEPTION 80-85 (Kevin
Attell trans., 2005). See also CARL SCHMITT, ROMAN CATHOLICISM AND POLITICAL FORM (G.L.
Ulmen trans., 1996) (1923).
C. A Continuing Romanticism
Right after World War I, the crisis of modernity raised the stakes and
sharpened the distinction between positivism's fetishization of certainty
and romanticism's appeal to a transcendent justice unassimilable to legal
rules. But the romantic turn has not died. It can still be heard in Lon Fuller
and Philippe Nonet; 44 in a revival of interest in Schmitt and Heidegger
wherein we find prominently these appeals to the palpable yet ineffable
power of this idea of justice;4 5 and in the transcendentalism of some
recent scholars of Derrida and law.46 Gillian Rose for example, accuses
Derrida, Levinas, and their followers of advocating a kind of "messianic
justice" which surrenders all reason and knowledge in favor of a "new
ethics" with no justification or relation to either.4 7 Meanwhile, as I have
argued elsewhere, the belief in the natural, anomic, and healing power of
literature still influences a great deal of writing in law and literature. 4 8
Neither is that all. An elegiac sense of loss and betrayal colors almost
all of the work of critical legal studies (CLS) from the 1980s. Juxtaposed
against its general nihilism, the almost routine gestures towards love or
politics or community in Peter Gabel or Duncan Kennedy or Mark
42. F.R. Cristi, Hayek and Schmitt on the Rule of Law, 17 CANADIAN J. POL. SC. 521, 529
(1984); see also ELLEN KENNEDY, CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE: CARL SCHMITT IN WEIMAR 24 (2004)
(describing Schmitt's concern that Rcchstaat theory subordinated the substantive content of the state
to procedure).
43. Heiner Biclefcldt, Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism: Systematic Reconstruction and
Counter-criticism,in LAW AS POLITICS: CARL SCHMITT'S CRITIQUE OF LIBERALISM 23, 25-27 (David
Dyzcnhaus ed., 1998) [hereinafter LAW AS POLITICS]; Robert Howse, From Legitimacy to
Dictatorship-AndBack Again: Leo Strauss 's Critiqueof the Anti-Liberalism of CarlSchmitt, in LAW
AS POLITICS, supra, at 56, 61-63.
44. Philippe Nonet, Antigone's Law, 2 LAW, CULTURE & HUMAN. 314 (2006); Philippe Nonet,
What is Positive Law?, 100 YALE L.J. 667 (1990).
45. See, e.g., MARIANNE CONSTABLE, JUST SILENCES: THE LIMITS AND POSSIBILITIES OF
MODERN LAW (2007); MARIANNE CONSTABLE, THE LAW OF THE OTHER: THE MIXED JURY AND
CHANGING CONCEPTIONS OF CITIZENSHIP, LAW, AND KNOWLEDGE (1994).
46. See, e.g., MARINOS DIAMANTIDES, LEVINAS, LAW, POLITICS (2007); SUSANNA LINDROOS-
HOVINHEIMO, JUSTICE AND THE ETHICS OF LEGAL INTERPRETATION (2012); DESMOND MANDERSON,
PROXIMITY, LEVINAS, AND THE SOUL OF LAW (2006); see also GILLIAN ROSE, JUDAISM AND
MODERNITY (1993); GILLIAN ROSE, THE BROKEN MIDDLE (1992); Jack Balkin, Deconstruction's
Legal Career, 27 CARDOZO L. REV. 719-40 (2005); Jack Balkin, TranscendentalDeconstruction,
TranscendentalJustice,92 MICH. L. REV. 1131 (1994).
47. See ROSE, JUDAISM AND MODERNITY, supra note 46, at 6; ROSE, THE BROKEN MIDDLE,
supra note 46, at 310.
48. Desmond Manderson, The Irony ofLaw and Literature,35 AUSTL. FEMINIST L.J. 107 (2011).
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 12
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
49. See, e.g., Peter Gabel, Phenomenology of Rights-Consciousness and the Pact of the
Withdrawn Selves, 62 TEX. L. REV. 1563 (1984) (discussing community as the salvation of law);
Mark Kelman, Trashing, 36 STAN. L. REV. 293 (1984) (defending nihilism as method); Duncan
Kennedy, Freedom & Constraint in Adjudication: A CriticalPhenomenology, 36 J. LEGAL EDUC. 518
(1986) (discussing politics as the salvation of law); Arthur Leff, Unspeakable Ethics, UnnaturalLaw,
1979 DUKE L.J. 1229, 1249 (discussing the possibility of God as the salvation of law); Joseph Singer,
The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory, 100 YALE L.J. 94 (1984) (describing the
nihilistic streak of CLS); Mark Tushnet, An Essay on Rights, 62 TEX. L. REV. 1363 (1984) (discussing
politics as the salvation of law).
50. ROBERTO UNGER, KNOWLEDGE AND POLITICS (1975); ROBERTO UNGER, PASSION: AN
ESSAY ON PERSONALITY (1986); ROBERTO UNGER, POLITICS: A WORK IN CONSTRUCTIVE SOCIAL
THEORY (1987); see also Drucilla Cornell, Beyond Tragedy and Complacency, 81 Nw. U. L. REV. 693
(1987); Martin Stone, The Placement ofPolitics in Roberto Unger's Politics, in LAW AND THE ORDER
OF CULTURE 78 (Robert Post ed., 1991).
51. Compare UNGER, KNOWLEDGE AND POLITICS, supra note 50, at 295, with Leff, supra note
49, at 1249 (concluding, similarly but ironically, "Sez who? God help us.").
52. TAMANAHA, LAW AS A MEANS TO AN END, supra note 14, at 23.
53. HART, supra note 12; JOSEPH RAZ, AUTHORITY OF LAW (1979); Michael Giudice, Existence
andJustification ConditionsofLaw, 16 CANADIAN J.L. & JURISPRUDENCE 23 (2003).
54. Joseph Raz, The Rule ofLaw and its Virtue, 93 L.Q. REV. 195 (1977).
55. TAMANAHA, LAW AS A MEANS TO AN END, supra note 14, at 23.
In different ways, then, these modes of legal theory all seek some
transcendent balm-sometimes literature, sometimes politics, sometimes
ethics, sometimes God, sometimes wisdom-capable of overcoming the
limitations of legal judgment. Roger Berkowitz is a good example of the
new romantics. He argues that "the gift of science" is a poisoned chalice.
Indeed, the plea to re-forge the relationship between law and justice runs
through The Gift of Science from the first sentence: "Justice has fled our
world." 56 This justice is presented throughout as "transcendent."57 Modern
law's promise of scientific objectivity suppresses precisely "the legal idea
of justice ... in its connection with transcendence . .. the beautiful dream
of transcendence."5 Justice as law's underlying "ethical unity" appears to
transcend individual or conflicting interests in favor of the unification of
the community. Berkowitz argues:
Active thinking . . . is irreducible to rules or laws. . . . Similarly,
justice demands that man think and in thinking transcend the
limits of his unique self and enter into an ethical community with
others. The dream of justice, in other words, is the dream of
transcendence. 5 9
Ultimately, "the natural connection with the divine" underpins
Berkowitz's argument. Our "incalculable yet manifest sense of divine and
human justice" girds this authority, provides this insight, ordains this
inhuman unity, and grants this transcendence.o
According to Berkowitz, "the impulse to think deeply and critically
about whom we have become need not and should not be confused with
the romantic longing for a return to a glorified past."6 ' But this disclaimer
is not convincing. Berkowitz is an advocate "striving to rejuvenate an idea
of justice." 62 Nothing could be clearer, it seems to me, than that the very
ideas of insight, nature, and transcendence that mark legal romanticism
are the foundation of Berkowitz's approach. Just as in the influential work
of Philippe Nonet, Berkowitz displays "a mourning, or, rather,
melancholic longing for a lost utopia, a world without the things the law
decides." Judgment becomes a game played with invisible trumps, in
which one just leaps over the gap between rules and particulars, between
then and now, by reference to some inarticulable thing above and beyond
56. ROGER BERKOWITZ, THE GIFT OF SCIENCE: LEIBNIZ AND THE MODERN LEGAL TRADITION, at
ix (2005).
57. Id. at x, xiii, xv, 90, 139.
58. Id. at 159-60.
59. Id. at x.
60. Id. at 159, 24.
61. Id. at xiv.
62. Id.
63. Andrew Norris, Heideggerian Law Beyond Law? Technique, Recht, and Phusis, 2 LAW,
CULTURE & HUMAN. 341, 348 (2006).
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 14
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
64. JACQUES DERRIDA, SPECTRES OF MARX: THE STATE OF THE DEBT, THE WORK OF MOURNING
& THE NEW INTERNATIONAL 28 (Peggy Kamuf trans., 1994).
65. PETER F]AGESUND, THE APOCALYPTIC WORLD OF D.H. LAWRENCE (1991).
66. D.H. LAWRENCE, PHOENIX: THE POSTHUMOUS PAPERS OF D.H. LAWRENCE (E.D. McDonald
ed., 1936).
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 16
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
B. Polarity in Lawrence
Polarity for Lawrence is most emphatically not a reconciliation or a
fusion, but an oscillation. Take the magnet as a model. Here we have two
opposite poles, positive and negative, but what at first glance appears to
be an irreconcilable dualism is in fact the source of its energy. The two
opposite poles that wage war within a man or an idea or an institution
remain necessary to one another. Its forces form the electrical circuit that
drives us on. Lawrence wrote, "I know I am compounded of two waves. I
am framed in the struggle and embrace of the two opposite waves of
darkness and of light."76 Likewise, polarized light does not mix or meld. It
has been separated into its distinct component parts. In Psychoanalysis
and the Unconscious, Lawrence writes of "the polarity of the dynamic
consciousness . . . the sharp clash of opposition . . . and no possibility of
creative development without this polarity from the beginning of life."
He even attempts to map these polarities onto the body, the contrast
between upper and lower bodies, front and back, man and woman-even
73. D.H. LAWRENCE, The Crown, in REFLECTIONS ON THE DEATH OF A PORCUPINE AND OTHER
ESSAYS 251-306 (Michael Herbert ed., 1988) (1915).
74. D.H. LAWRENCE, THE RAINBOW 317-18 (M. Kinkead-Weekes ed., 1989) (1915).
75. D.H. LAWRENCE, TWILIGHT IN ITALY AND OTHER ESSAYS 252 (Paul Eggert ed., 1994)
(1916).
76. MONTGOMERY, supra note 69, at 15.
77. D.H. LAWRENCE, PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THE UNCONSCIOUS 65-66 (1923).
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 18
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
written in 1922, the same year that both T.S. Eliot's The Waste Land and
James Joyce's Ulysses were published, one of the most characteristic if
unsung works of modernism.
In Kangaroo, the abiding metaphor for polarity is the Australian surf:
Then, when [the waves] fell, the fore-flush in a great soft swing
with incredible speed up the shore, on the darkness soft-lighted
with moon, like a rush of white serpents, then slipping back with a
hiss that fell into silence for a second, leaving the sand of
granulated silver . . . . A huge but a cold passion swinging back
and forth. Great waves of radium swooping with a down-curve
and rushing up the shore. Then calling themselves back again,
retreating to the mass. Then rushing with venomous radium-
burning speed into the body of the land. Then recoiling with a low
swish, leaving the flushed sand naked."
The oscillation of the waves evokes Somers's own polarity, towards
and away from the romance of ecstatic belonging, and presents it not as a
conflict or a problem, but as part of him. Although they "seem to sunder
life into an irreconcilable dualism [they] are in fact polar opposites ....
We can distinguish them but we cannot divide them."84
Polarity is thus not synthesis, not balance, not transcendence, and
categorically not harmony-it is opposition. Polarity describes forces that
cannot be compromised since we are committed too much to both.
Lawrence articulates "antitheses, contraries, contradictions." 85 He
advocates a metaphysics of modernist energy, not romantic peace.
Jung, of course, where the dark and the light exist simultaneously within
us;88 and in Freud's concept of "ambivalence," which is not treated as a
feeling of indifference but rather as a desire that pulls us with equal force
in two quite contradictory directions.89 One might even detect the trace of
polarity in Erwin Schrodinger's "superposition," the strange suspension of
matter in simultaneously contradictory states. 90
No discussion of this period or these ideas would be complete, certainly
in the context of law and politics, without reflecting on the work of
Walter Benjamin. In the period immediately following the Great War,
Benjamin was pondering the very same questions as Carl Schmitt and the
great German positivist Hans Kelsen. Kelsen's monograph on sovereignty
was published in 1920, Benjamin's Critique of Violence in 1921.91
Schmitt's Political Theology appeared in 1922 as a riposte to both.9 2 In
1928, Benjamin returned the favor with the publication of The Origin of
German Tragic Drama, which was likewise addressed to the relationship
between exception, decision, and sovereignty. 93 Complications arise,
however, because of the enigmatic and inimitable quality of Benjamin's
thought. Throughout his work there is undoubtedly a messianic and
utopian strain. 94 In Critique of Violence, he agrees with Schmitt that the
ungovernable "decision" is a necessary implication of "the curious and at
first discouraging experience of the ultimate undecidability of all legal
problems." Of course, this is the very problem with which we began our
reflections about the crisis facing the rule of law. The violence of a free
decision, not the passive application of a prior norm, becomes the
necessary predicate of all law. But Benjamin attempts to distinguish
between different modes of violence: law-preserving violence and law-
making violence in the first place, two forms of human power, and then a
pure or divine violence outside of the law which deposes it and thus
89. SIGMUND FREUD, TOTEM AND TABOO (A. A. Brill trans., Moffat, Yard & Co. 1918) (1913).
90. Erwin Schrddingcr, Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be
Considered Complete?, 47 PHYSICS REV. 777 (1935). 1 do not intend to square the circle by claiming
the mantle of scientific truth for the philosophical or legal notions of polarity, although I think it is
fair to say that they recognize a truth-in-contradiction from an unexpected source. What I do wish to
claim is that all ideas are born of a particular cultural context or zeitgeist, and the emergence of
cognate ideas at the same time demonstrates clearly the potency of the particular historical moment to
call forth a particular constellation of insights. Every era formulates its own set of problems and
perspectives, and these multiple connections across very different fields demonstrate their fecundity
and their continuing relevance.
91. 1 Walter Benjamin, Critique of Violence, in WALTER BENJAMIN, SELECTED WRITINGS 1913-
26, at 236 (Marcus S.C. Bullock & Michael W. Jennings eds., 1996); Walter Benjamin, Zur Kritik der
Gewalt, 47 ARCHIV FOR SOZIALWISSENSCHAFT UND SOZIALPOLITIK 809 (1920/21).
92. SCHMITr, supra note 35.
93. WALTER BENJAMIN, THE ORIGIN OF GERMAN TRAGIC DRAMA (John Osborne trans., New
Left Bks. 1977) (1928); see also AGAMBEN, supra note 41; Samuel Weber, Taking Exception to
Decision: Walter Benjamin and Carl Schmitt, 22 DIACRITICS 5 (1992).
94. The point is fundamental, in different ways, to the argument made in the following: Catherine
Mills, Playing with Law: Agamben and Derrida on Postjuridical Justice, 107 S. ATLANTIC Q. 15
(2008); Michael Mack, Modernity as an Unfinished Project: Benjamin and Political Romanticism, in
WALTER BENJAMIN AND THE ARCHITECTURE OF MODERNITY 59 (Andrew Benjamin & Charles Rice
eds., 2009).
95. AGAMBEN,supra note 41, at 53.
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 20
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
makes real revolution possible.9 6 Clearly, this messianic justice, this pure
violence unsullied by calculation, expressive rather than teleological, and
coming from outside either present or projected legal structures, is closely
allied to a transcendental instinct and to the anti-modem hostility to
calculation and system.97 For Benjamin, this violence escapes the cycle of
instrumental politics because it is not a means to achieve an intended end
(as a strike is intended to raise wages or a revolution is intended to take
over the State). Divine violence is an end in itself. It is an expiation of the
past and provides the opportunity for an unimaginable and unpredictable
future. Like Lawrence's phoenix, it is the purifying fire from whose ashes
something new might rise. Benjamin writes, "But all mythic, law-making
violence, which we may call 'executive,' is pemicious. Pernicious, too, is
the law-preserving, 'administrative' violence that serves it. Divine
violence, which is the sign and seal but never the means of sacred
dispatch, may be called 'sovereign' violence."98
That last sentence is critical. It holds the key to where Benjamin and
Schmitt part company. In Benjamin, "sovereign" characterizes a force-it
is an attribute of a kind of violence itself. But in Schmitt, the word
"sovereign" shifts from being a subset of violence to being an agent,
indeed a personification, of it. In Benjamin, "sovereign" is an adjective;
for Schmitt, it is a noun. By concentrating the inevitable violence of
decisions beyond-the-rules onto a particular human person, Schmitt solves
the problem of rule-indeterminacy by subordinating everything to human
control and state interests. Benjamin's transcendence on the other hand
remains irreducible to human control and entirely outside the state.
Sovereign violence for Benjamin is radical and destabilizing; sovereignty
for Schmitt is reactionary and authoritarian. The Schmittian sovereign
tames the Benjaminian divine.
The difference between the two becomes even more apparent in The
Origin of German Tragic Drama, in which Benjamin explores the
baroque concept of sovereignty. Benjamin takes from the baroque the idea
of a transcendent figure (such as justice or the gods) that eludes the grasp
of the state and remains strictly unattainable. In direct response to
Schmitt, Benjamin argues that the role of the sovereign is not to seize
supreme executive power but rather to refuse it as one would a
temptation.99 Furthermore, in theatrical, artistic, and philosophical terms,
96. Id.; Benjamin, Critique of Violence, supra note 91, at 243, 250-52.
97. Anthony Aucrbach, Remarks to the After 1968 Seminar on Walter Benjamin's Critique of
Violence (Sept. 3, 2001); Antonis Balasopoulos, Crisis, Justice, Messianism: On Walter Benjamin's
Critique of Violence (July 9, 2011) (paper presented at Utopia/Crisis/Justice: Twelfth International
Conference of Utopian Studies Society).
98. Benjamin, Critiqueof Violence, supranote 91, at 252.
99. BENJAMIN, supra note 93.
A. DeconstructionandPolarity
These arguments closely parallel those of deconstruction. This is not so
surprising if we recall that Derrida's seminal article Force ofLaw takes as
its starting point a close reading of Benjamin's critique.'o' Derrida also
recognizes the power of the undecidable to contaminate legal judgment;
he also emphasizes the empty and unfillable space of transcendence, the
unattainability of perfection, and the inadequacy of human calculations. In
all these ways, he acknowledges Schmitt's critique of the rule of law, and
in some ways that is precisely what Force of Law is about. But Derrida's
principal contribution may lie in his eschewal of the messianic waiting for
justice that we find in Benjamin just because the urgency of the demand
for justice "does not wait."' 02 This was Schmitt's fundamental point too,
but Derrida's response to it is radically different. Schmitt, drawing on
Hobbes here, says the sovereign's decision is infallible because it is final.
Derrida says it is neither-and a good thing too. Thus, Derrida combines
Benjamin's normative openness with Schmitt's analytic realism.
100. Weber, supra note 93, at 17; see BENJAMIN, supra note 93, at 137.
101. See Derrida,supra note 8.
102. Mills, supra note 94, at 28-29.
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 22
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
103. Drucilla Cornell, The Violence of the Masquerade, II CARDOZO L. REV. 1047, 1057-58
(1990).
104. Derrida, supra note 8, at 959.
105. JACQUES DERRIDA, GIFT OF DEATH [DONNER LA MORT] (David Wills trans., 1996);
JACQUES DERRIDA, OF GRAMMATOLOGY (Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak trans., 1998).
106. JACQUES DERRIDA, ON COSMOPOLITANISM AND FORGIVENESS 34-35 (Mark Dooley &
Michael Hughes trans., 2002).
107. Id. at 44.
B. Beyond Transcendence
The vital distinction between polarity and transcendence (and therefore
between deconstruction and romanticism) has not always been
acknowledged. In a series of influential articles Jack Balkin, for example,
insisted that justice for Derrida is "transcendent" in just the sense of
appealing to an unreasoned and instinctive insight as a way to escape
from the paradox ofjustice."' So too for Gillian Rose, the "new ethics" of
"Messianic deconstruction" ultimately abandons justification in favor of
the sublime leap into the arms of a "sacralized polity."" 2 Although that
criticism might be correct about Heidegger or Levinas, I think it is quite
wrong about deconstruction." 3
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 24
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
MOSAIC 217-39 (Desmond Manderson ed., 2009); Nick Smith, Questions for a Reluctant
JurisprudenceofAlterity, in ESSAYS ON LEVINAS AND LAW: A MOSAIC, supra, at 55-75.
114. Barbara Johnson, The Surprise of Otherness: A Note on the Wartime Writings of Paul de
Man, in LITERARY THEORY TODAY 13, 18-21 (P. Collier & H. Geyer-Ryan eds., 1990).
115. See, e.g., BEARDSWORTH, supra note 10; SIMON CRITCHLEY, THE ETHICS OF
DECONSTRUCTION: DERRIDA AND LEVINAS (1992); Alletta Norval, Hegemony After Deconstruction:
The Consequencesof Undecidability,9 J. POL. IDEOLOGIES 139-57 (2004).
116. AGAMBEN, supra note 41, at 53.
unrepeatable, and spontaneous. That was exactly the logic that appealed
to Schmitt and appalled Tamanaha.
There is a second and countervailing element here. The Lawrentian
polarities that tug at us require a constant listening and correction of
received ideas. A "determinate oscillation" swings us between two
irreconcilable poles-general and particular, prior rules and new
circumstances-forcing us to rethink our rules, the meaning we give our
words, the imagined "essences" of those words, and the purposes that are
served by them. But in the end, the decision cannot wait-polarity,
opposition, and contradiction are never completely resolved. The pull of
singularity forces us to reflect on what the rule means and accomplishes
in this particular circumstance. We are forced to reconsider, to question,
to doubt. Our understanding of the rule is thus not static. The pull of
generality forces us to account for the implications of our decisions for
other circumstances. Our understanding of those circumstances is thus not
unconstrained. The decision that we make neither surrenders to the rules
nor abandons them; instead, it attempts to understandthem.
The decision that emerges-a legal judgment perhaps, or the practical
application of a rule-will always be an unstable and imperfect response
to these tensions. Unlike the romantics, however, we should never expect
our decision to transcend or heal them. The judgment we make endeavors
to reassess meaning and to question our assumptions, but the result,
whatever it may be, is provisional and open to reconsideration at every
moment. Our understanding of the rules may have been either shifted or
confirmed by our situation. Present circumstances may lead us to reflect
on the meaning of the rules we thought we knew, but on the other hand,
the pressure of the future may lead us to hold, despite everything, to our
previous interpretation. Either way, the new decision we make necessarily
attempts to impose and to justify a new stability and generality on the
swirling forces around us. Thus, we are constantly thrown from one pole
to the other, from the singularity of justice back to the (re-)construction of
rules. Of course, as soon as we are confronted with a new circumstance,
the previous interpretation must generate new tensions and a new polarity
pulling us in opposite directions again. Like the moon and the tides, the
experience of polarity, of the impossibility of our ever satisfying contrary
expectations, will always be felt as a tug and a repetition.
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 26
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
of necessity unsettled and partial, but in the doubt and the challenge that
comes before it and in the public discourse of reason-giving and argument
that comes after it. That the promise of science or objectivity as some new
and perfect ground to the rule of law is doomed to fail, I have no doubt.
But it does not follow that we should give up on reasons, now in the
plural, understood as an ongoing social process of transparency,
justification, and response. The arguments it resolves may be less
important for the rule of law than the conversations it allows. It is the
movement itself that matters, the irresolution rather than the resolution-
an endless polarity that ensures that we never stop deciding.
Derrida makes a similar point in a slightly different way. He describes
the "madness of decision" as that moment in which one is forced to
confront a polarity between the responsibility to "conserve the law and
destroy it or suspend it enough to have to reinvent it in each case."" 7 At
the same time, as we have seen, the polarity that tugs at justice from
contradictory directions and the gap that opens up between the abstract
rule and the unique circumstance that sheds light on it, mean that there is
a necessary imperfection or remainder to this process of inquiry. Due to
the critical and imperfect dimension inherent in the moment of judgment,
the obligation to decide is never severable from the obligation to
ruthlessly and publicly expose one's judgments, to explain, justify, and be
criticized for our imperfect decisions and interpretations. All decisions are
violent but not all violence is the same. The violence that sees itself as
such and attempts to think through and explain the choices that are made
is different from the violence that is ignorant of itself and pretends to have
escaped the dilemma.
Crucially for our understanding of the rule of law, then, this eternal
weaving of correction and change is not a private affair, but a public,
social event. It must be articulated, explained, and criticized. "There must
be resistance," wrote Lawrence. "We ought to pray to be resisted and
resisted to the bitter end . . . . There must be resistance in relationships. It
is the basis of strength, of balance, of unison."" 8 Without argument and
corrigibility, there can be for Lawrence no change. Thus, Lawrence sees a
moment of accountability, perhaps even of apology, as we confront
others. The Rainbow "deals in the soul's mistakes and self-retrieval, so
that the erring course is constantly under correction."" 9 Kangaroo is
riddled with the same public mea culpas:
"I am a fool," said Richard Lovatt, which was the most frequent
discovery he made. It came, moreover, every time with a new
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 28
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
CONCLUSION
The rule of law is not an arid technical exercise, which is the ethical
poverty of positivism. Neither is it an unanswerable and divine decree,
which is the ethical poverty of romanticism. It becomes instead the
framework for a social and human dialogue, which is as it should be. That
pluralism and that modernism Schmitt, for one, simply could not
fathom.' 2 6 But without the antiphonal response of reason-giving and
contingent justification, which Lawrence calls "call and answer," the law
would cease to offer us-all of us, whether citizens or lawyers or
judges-the possibility of learning something about ourselves and the
world.
This too, I think, reflects a crucial distinction in how we might think
about the rule of law. On the one hand, positivism does not conceive of
judges as learning something new. Judges, on the standard model, merely
apply what they already know: the answer is to be found in the rules
written down on the page in front of them. So the dialogue in a courtroom
125. RUTI TEITEL, TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE (2000); THE RULE OF LAW AFTER COMMUNISM:
PROBLEMS AND PROSPECTS IN EAST-CENTRAL EUROPE (Martin Krygier & Adam Czarnota eds.,
2007); Martin Krygicr, The Rule of Law: Legality, Teleology, Sociology, in RELOCATING THE RULE
OF LAw 49 (Gianluigi Palombella & Neil Walker eds., 2011).
126. The importance of the state and of a homogeneous society, and Schmitt's consequent
hostility to liberal pluralism, became increasingly clear in his writing. See CARL SCHMITT, THE
CONCEPT OF THE POLITICAL (G. Schwab trans., 1996) (1927); see also DYZENHAUS, supra note 36.
is all one-way. Only the parties to a dispute learn something: what the law
means and how to obey it. Such a model of legal judgment is resolutely
hierarchical.
But this will not do. Judgment-literary, personal, political, or legal, it
hardly matters-is a constant process of learning. There is no learning
without resistance and struggle. On this model, the judge listens and,
having heard something new (about the world, perhaps, or the people who
live in it) must correct his or her assumptions of what a proper application
of legal principles requires. Arrogance is the worst crime for any judge to
commit-and the most typical. A judge, like the rest of us, must be
prepared to make the frequent discovery that he or she is a fool. The rule
of law thereby cedes its mythical certainty, but by listening, deciding,
explaining, and listening again, law becomes better connected to its
community and able to develop, step by step, while always remaining
publicly answerable for its decisions. The rule of law facilitates a
structure of oscillation capable of learning from us rather than merely
instructing us.
On the other hand, the word "insight," the romantic foil to rule
following, appears equally to acknowledge no argument or struggle or
explanation. It is as hierarchical as its positivist counterpart. Justice
appears like a revelation, as the product of a purely inward process by
which one intuits the big picture. Every page of Berkowitz's The Gift of
Science exudes this static and non-discursive image of judgment. To
speak of law as a "natural or traditional insight" "that grows of its own
accord" implies that intuition arrives without need of any interrogation,
27
modification, or argument.1
But this will not do either. As Lawrence made so clear in all his work,
nothing in this world is free, natural, or manifest. What we learn about
justice-and, of course, this continually changes in a world of
bewildering complexity and endless polarity-we earn, precisely by
going through the ordeal of justification and reasons, and through the
resistance provided by others. Insight is not the opposite or transcendence
of reasons. On the contrary, like wisdom and foolishness, they are
productively related, the one chiseled out of us by the constant nagging of
the other. "Trial and error" is not an insult. It is the methodology of the
rule of law.
Understanding the rule of law through the lens of modernism, and in
particular through that of polarity, disturbs the hegemonic reason of
positivism and the hegemonic unreason of romanticism alike. Polarity's
backwards-and-forwards movement of constant correction, adjustment,
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 30
Manderson: Modernism, Polarity, and the Rule of Law
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol24/iss2/1 32