Customary Law Without Custom
Customary Law Without Custom
Customary Law Without Custom
2007
Recommended Citation
Petersen, Niles. "Customary Law Without Custom? Rules, Principles, and the Role of State Practice in International Norm Creation."
American University International Law Review 23, no.2 (2007): 275-310.
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Washington College of Law Journals & Law Reviews at Digital Commons @ American
University Washington College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in American University International Law Review by an authorized
administrator of Digital Commons @ American University Washington College of Law. For more information, please contact
fbrown@wcl.american.edu.
CUSTOMARY LAW WITHOUT CUSTOM?
RULES, PRINCIPLES, AND THE ROLE OF
STATE PRACTICE IN INTERNATIONAL NORM
CREATION
NIELS PETERSEN*
275
276 AM. U. INT'L L. REV. [23:275
1. Statute of the International Court of Justice art. 38 para. 1, June 26, 1945,
59 Stat. 1055, 1060, 3 Bevans 1153, 1187.
2. See Holger Hestermeyer, Access to Medication as a Human Right, in 8
MAX PLANCK YEARBOOK OF UNITED NATIONS LAW 101, 159 (Armin von
2008] CUSTOMARYLA W WITHOUT CUSTOM?
Bogdandy & Riidiger Wolfrum eds., 2004) (noting the lack of definite rules for
recognizing customary international law).
3. See ANTHONY A. D'AMATO, THE CONCEPT OF CUSTOM IN INTERNATIONAL
LAW 58 (1971) (noting that there is no consensus as to how much time a practice
must be maintained to evidence the existence of a custom); G. I. Tunkin, Remarks
On the JuridicalNature of Customary Norms of International Law, 49 CAL. L.
REV. 419, 420 (1961) (arguing that the element of time is not dispositive as to
whether a customary law exists).
4. See KAROL WOLFKE, CUSTOM IN PRESENT INTERNATIONAL LAW 81 (1964)
(acknowledging that factors such as wealth, power, and size play a role in the
formation of international custom); Michael Byers, Introduction: Power,
Obligation, and Customary InternationalLaw, 11 DUKE J. COMP. & INT'L L. 81,
84 (2001) (suggesting that an emphasis on state practice in the formation of
customary international law has the inequitable result that international legal norms
will disproportionately favor wealthier states).
5. See Hestermeyer, supra note 2, at 158 (arguing that uncertainty in the area
of customary international law is growing); Onuma Yasuaki, A Transcivilization
Perspective on Global Legal Order in the Twenty-first Century: A Way to
Overcome West-centric and Judiciary-centric Deficits in International Legal
Thoughts, inTOWARDS WORLD CONSTITUTIONALISM: ISSUES IN THE LEGAL
ORDERING OF THE WORLD COMMUNITY 151, 179 (Ronald S.J. Macdonald &
Douglas M. Johnston eds., 2005) (criticizing the manner in which western scholars
identify state practice).
278 AM. U INT'L L. REv. [23:275
17. See Bin Cheng, United Nations Resolutions on Outer Space. "Instant"
InternationalCustomary Law?, 5 INDIAN J. INT'L L. 23, 35-40 (1965).
18. See G.A. Res. 1721, U.N. GAOR, 16th Sess., Supp. No. 17, U.N. Doc.
A/5100 (Dec. 20, 1961); G.A. Res. 1962, U.N. GAOR, 18th Sess., Supp. No. 15,
U.N. Doc. A/5515 (Dec. 13, 1963).
19. See Bin Cheng, On the Nature and Sources of International Law, in
INTERNATIONAL LAW, TEACHING, AND PRACTICE 201, 222-29 (Bin Cheng ed.,
1982) (arguing that usage is not necessary when there is unanimity among states
regarding a rule of international law).
20. See Guzman, supra note 8, at 122 (defining the rational choice approach as
one that looks to the incentives for states to behave in a particular manner).
21. See id. at 139-40.
22. See id. at 148-49.
23. See id. at 149 (noting that state practice can serve as a tool for discerning
opiniojuris by identifying a state's intent to be bound by a norm). However, the
majority of the rational choice approaches still consider state practice to be a
constituent element of custom. See Edward T. Swaine, Rational Custom, 52 DuKE
L.J. 559, 567-68 (2002) (asserting that opinio juris without practice is "nothing
more than rhetoric"); George Norman & Joel P. Trachtman, The Customary
International Law Game, 99 AM. J. INT'L L. 541, 541 (2005) (rejecting the
Goldsmith-Posner model of rational choice theory, arguing that their model
remains unsupported). Still others deny the legal quality of international law. See
generally JACK L. GOLDSMITH & ERIC A. POSNER, THE LIMITS OF INTERNATIONAL
LAW 3 (2005) (reasoning that international law evolves as a result of states acting
282 AM. U. INT'L L. RE V. [23:275
30. Statute of the International Court of Justice, supra note 1, art. 38, para. 1
(emphasis added).
31. See, e.g., Christiana Ochoa, The Individual and Customary International
Law Formation, 48 VA. J. INT'L L. 119, 132 (2007) (discussing the practice and
behavior of states as a widely accepted element of customary international law
under both Article 38(l)(b) and the Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law
102).
32. See Frederic L. Kirgis, Jr., Custom on a Sliding Scale, 81 AM. J. INT'L L.
146, 149 (1987) (describing the trade off between state practice and opinio juris
and illustrating the relationship graphically); John Tasioulas, In Defence of
Relative Normativity: Communitarian Values and the Nicaragua Case, 16 OXFORD
J. LEGAL STUD. 85, 109 (1996) (analyzing various arguments that place more
emphasis on either state practice or opinio juris and concluding that custom must
be derived on a case by case basis from some combination of the two); Anthea E.
Roberts, Traditionaland Modern Approaches to Customary InternationalLaw: A
Reconciliation, 95 AM. J. INT'L L. 757, 774 (2001) (advocating an approach to
custom that reflects both state practice and opinio juris in equilibrium, and
critiquing the sliding scale approach due to its tendency to overemphasize one
component at the expense of the other).
33. See Kirgis, Jr., supra note 32, at 149 (describing the sliding scale approach
and explaining that an affirmative showing of one component may substitute for
the other, particularly in cases of "morally distasteful" or "destabilizing" activity).
34. See Tasioulas, supra note 32, at 113 (arguing that the sliding scale
approach is a particularly appropriate interpretation of norm identification in cases
where the norm at issue expresses an important moral value, such as peaceful co-
AM. U INT'L L. RE V. [23:275
B. GENERAL PRINCIPLES
The most promising proposal has been brought forward by Bruno
Simma and Philip Alston in a seminal article on the sources of
human rights law.38 After a thorough analysis of the present theory of
customary international law, they propose to use general principles in
existence); Roberts, supra note 32, at 790 (explaining that occasional state practice
in breach of a custom with high moral content will not detract from the custom's
general character).
35. See supra notes 28-31 and accompanying text (discussing state practice as
a component of customary law by definition).
36. Martti Koskenniemi, The Pull of the Mainstream, 88 MICH. L. REv. 1946,
1952 (1990) (emphasis added).
37. See id. at 1962 (arguing that technical definitions of human rights best
serve arguments in support of denying rights).
38. See generally Simma & Alston, supra note 16.
2008] CUSTOMAR YLA W WITHOUT CUSTOM?
39. Statute of the International Court of Justice, supra note 1, art. 38, para.
1(c).
40. See Simma & Alston, supra note 16, at 102-06. Cf Albert Bleckmann, Zur
origindren Entstehung gewohnheitsrechtlicher Menschenrechtsnormen [The
Original Formation of Customary Human Rights Norms], in
MENSCHENRECHTSSCHUTZ DURCH GEWOHNHEITSRECHT [HUMAN RIGHTS
PROTECTION THROUGH CUSTOMARY LAW] 29, 42-43 (Eckart Klein ed., 2002);
Oscar Schachter, New Custom: Power, Opinio Juris and Contrary Practice, in
THEORY OF INTERNATIONAL LAW AT THE THRESHOLD OF THE 21ST CENTURY 531,
539 (Jerzy Makarczyk ed., 1996) (discussing and approving the theory advanced
by Simma and Alston). But see Robert B. Lillich, The Growing Importance of
Customary InternationalHuman Rights Law, 25 GA. J. INT'L & COMP. L. 1, 16
(1995) (critiquing the argument that general principles may serve as independent
rules of international law).
41. See Simma & Alston, supra note 16, at 102 (emphasizing that the general
principles do not derive from speculation, but instead from states' acceptance and
recognition).
42. See id. at 104 (arguing that customary law should be based on the express
articulation of general principles by states).
43. See Balakrishnan Rajagopal, The Allure of Normativity, 11 HARV. HUM
RTS. J. 363, 363 (1998) (reviewing PHILIP ALSTON, HUMAN RIGHTS LAW (1996))
(discussing the tendency within the international human rights community to
deemphasize pragmatic issues and instead focus on establishing moral certainties
as binding principles).
44. See Simma & Alston, supra note 16, at 99 (distinguishing human rights
obligations from other customary law which can be derived from examining
patterns of state interaction).
286 AM. U. INT'L L. RE V. [23:275
45. See id. (inquiring why human rights obligations could be recognized at all
under traditional theories of customary international law when there is generally a
total lack of state interaction in the performance of human rights obligations and
thus a general absence of the traditional state practice element of customary law).
46. ROBERT ALEXY, A THEORY OF CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS 47-48 (Julian
Rivers trans., 2002) (defining principles as norms that can be satisfied to varying
degrees and rules as norms that are either satisfied or unsatisfied).
47. This thesis refers to and tries to modify a proposal of Stefan Kadelbach &
Thomas Kleinlein. See Stefan Kadelbach & Thomas Kleinlein, (berstaatliches
Verfassungsrecht [Supranational Constitutional Law], 44 ARCHIV DES
VOLKERRECHTS [ARCHIVE OF INTERNATIONAL LAW] 235, 255-65 (2006). It is
important not to confuse terminology. Alexy's principles are not the same as
general principles of international law although the employed expressions are very
similar. In this article, I will use the term "principle" or "legal principle" when
referring to Alexy's differentiation. When I want to address the source of
international law described in Article 38(l)(c) of the ICJ Statute, I will use the
term "general principles."
48. See, e.g., D.W. Greig, The Underlying Principles of International
HumanitarianLaw, 9 AUSTL. Y.B. INT'L L. 46, 65 (1985); Vaughan Lowe, The
Politics of Law-Making: Are the Method and Character of Norm Creation
Changing?, in THE ROLE OF LAW IN INTERNATIONAL POLITICS 207, 213-19
2008] CUSTOMA R Y LA W WITHOUT CUSTOM?
(Michael Byers ed., 2000) (analyzing the relationship between principles and rules,
and their role in judicial decision-making); Robert Kolb, Principlesas Sources of
InternationalLaw, 53 NETH. INT'L L. REV. 1, 26 (2006) (distinguishing general
principles of law from the detailed rules developed through the application of
general principles).
49. See generally ALEXY, supra note 46, at 45-47.
50. Compare Joseph Raz, Legal Principlesand the Limits of Law, 81 YALE L.J.
823, 838 (1972) (describing the difference between rules and principles as one of
degree and commenting that rules prescribe specific acts, while principles
prescribe more general actions), with George C. Christie, The Model of Principles,
1968 DUKE L.J. 649, 669 (arguing that principles are simply vague extensions of
rules).
51. See Christie, supra note 50, at 669 (asserting that under the current legal
universe of rules and principles, judges may resort to an ever more vague
description of the norm to support a number of possible decisions in a case).
52. See ALEXY, supra note 46, at 47-48; see also RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING
RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 26-27 (1977) (noting that conflicting principles may be
balanced against one another while conflicting rules cannot). Dworkin's
conception differs in some respects, however, as he conceives rights more as a
"trump card" than as something which may be weighed against the achievement of
public goals. Id. at 266-72.
53. See, e.g., ALEXY, supra note 46, at 48-50 (defining a norm collision as an
instance where two norms lead to two mutually incompatible legal judgments).
The dichotomic differentiation between rules and principles has often been
criticized for analytical and normative reasons. I do not want to address these
criticisms in this contribution because other scholars have already dealt extensively
with them. See, e.g., id. at 61-66; Mattias Kumm, Constitutional Rights as
Principles: On the Structure and Domain of Constitutional Justice, 2 INT'L J.
CONST. L. 574, 589-93 (2004) (reviewing ROBERT ALEXY, A THEORY OF
CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS (Julian Rivers trans., 2002)).
54. See ALEXY, supra note 46, at 49.
288 AM. U. INT'L L. REv. [23:275
55. See id. at 48 (describing the difference between competing principles and
conflicts of rules as the most defining distinction between the two).
56. See Robert Alexy, Zum Begriff des Rechtsprinzips [The Concept of Legal
Principles], in ARGUMENTATION UND HERMENEUTIK IN DER JURISPURDENZ
[ARGUMENTATION AND HERMENEUTICS IN JURISPRUDENCE] 59, 64 (Werner
Krawietz et al. eds., 1979) (F.R.G.).
57. See ALEXY, supra note 46, at 54-55 (noting that the balancing of competing
principles is controlled by the idea of "conditional relation of precedence").
58. See DWORKIN, supra note 52, at 26 (discussing the importance of the
"weight" of a principle and noting that court rulings based upon a balancing will
often result in a controversial decision).
59. See Mattias Kumm, Liberale Gerechtigkeitstheorien und die Struktur der
Grundrechte [Liberal Theories of Justice and the Structure of Fundamental
Rights], in JURISTISCHE GRUNDLAGENFORSCHUNG [LEGAL RESEARCH] 218, 220
(Robert Alexy ed., 2005).
2008] CUSTOMARY LA W WITHOUT CUSTOM? 289
60. See Neil MacCormick, "Principles"of Law, 19 JURIDICAL REV. 217, 222
(1974) (Scot.) (describing variations upon liability rules as examples of a broader
liability principle that has been applied to a specific circumstance).
61. See Nico Krisch, Review Essay, Legality, Morality, and the Dilemma of
HumanitarianIntervention after Kosovo, 13 EUR. J. INT'L L. 323, 331 (2002).
62. See, e.g., Julie Mertus, Reconsidering the Legality of Humanitarian
Intervention: Lessons from Kosovo, 41 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1743, 1763, 1771
(2000) (arguing that while the parameters for the use of force are not totally clear,
it is likely that the U.N. Charter implicitly permits humanitarian intervention).
63. See, e.g., Richard B. Lillich, ForcibleSelf-Help by States to Protect Human
Rights, 53 IOWA L. REV. 325, 347-51 (1967) (asserting that where a test attempts to
balance competing principles, such test must be informed by the standards of the
legal system from which the principles derive-in this case, the international legal
order); see also Richard B. Lillich, HumanitarianIntervention through the United
Nations: Towards the Development of Criteria, 53 ZEITSCHRIFT FUR
AUSLANDISCHES OFFENTLICHES RECHT UND VOLKERRECHT [HEIDELBERG
JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW] 557, 562-63 (1993) (F.R.G.) (reviewing the
twelve criteria set forth by the International Law Association for assessing the
legality under international law of humanitarian interventions); John Norton
Moore, The Control of Foreign Intervention in Internal Conflict, 9 VA. J. INT'L L.
205, 262 (1969) (concluding that the U.N. Charter contains complementary
policies restricting unilateral force, yet urging action to protect human rights).
290 AM. U. INT'L L. REv. [23:275
64. See, e.g., Bruno Simma, NATO, the UN and the Use of Force: Legal
Aspects, 10 EUR. J. INT'L L. 1, 2-3 (1999) (emphasizing that Article 2(4) of the
U.N. Charter is a "watertight" prohibition against the use of force); see also
Marcello G. Kohen, L 'Emploi de la Force et la Crise du Kosovo: Vers un Nouveau
D~sordre JuridiqueInternational [The Use of Force and the Crisis in Kosovo:
Toward a New International Legal Disorder], 32 REVUE BELGE DE DROIT
INTERNATIONAL [BELGIAN INTERNATIONAL LAW REVIEW] 122, 134 (1999)
(rejecting the argument that the use of force to prevent a humanitarian crisis in
Kosovo was permissible); Nico Krisch, Unilateral Enforcement of the Collective
Will: Kosovo, Iraq, and the Security Council, in 3 MAX PLANCK YEARBOOK OF
UNITED NATIONS LAW 59, 59-60 (Jochen A. Frowein & Riidiger Wolfrum eds.,
1999) (reflecting on potential justifications for human rights-based military
intervention in Kosovo and Iraq, and arguing that the intervening states claimed
the right to enforce their collective will unilaterally); Micheal Byers & Simon
Chesterman, Changing the Rules about Rules? Unilateral Humanitarian
Intervention and the Future of International Law, in HUMANITARIAN
INTERVENTION 177, 178-79 (J.L. Holzgrefe & Robert 0. Keohane eds., 2003)
(offering an "exceptional illegality" approach for justifying humanitarian
intervention that would be "more consistent with the position of states, and in
keeping with the principles of international law").
65. See, e.g., Simma, supra note 64, at 5 (explaining that in the absence of U.N.
Security Council authorization of the use of force, military action in the form of
humanitarian intervention is necessarily a breach of Article 2(4) of the U.N.
Charter).
66. U.N. Charter art. 2, para. 4 (requiring that all members should refrain from
the threat or use of force).
67. See J.L. HOLZGREFE, The Humanitarian Intervention Debate, in
HUMANITARIAN INTERVENTION, supra note 64, at 15, 40 (arguing that the phrase,
"or in any other manner inconsistent with the purposes of the United Nations," in
Article 2, para. 4 of the U.N. Charter supplements the prohibition on the
unauthorized use of force, and does not provide a loophole as some critics have
suggested).
2008] CUSTOMAR Y LA W WITHOUT CUSTOM?
The two concepts that I have used for my argument are often
criticized, not without reason, for being a gateway into the legal
74. See, e.g., Stephen Hall, The Persistent Spectre: NaturalLaw, International
Order and the Limits of Legal Positivism, 12 EUR. J. INT'L L. 269, 293-95 (2001)
(describing the historical relationship between ius gentium and natural law and the
natural law-relation of general principles).
75. Statute of the International Court of Justice, supra note 1, art. 38, para. 1.
76. See, e.g., William C. Bradford, The Duty to Defend Them: A Natural Law
Justificationfor the Bush Doctrine of Preventive War, 79 NOTRE DAME L. REV.
1365, 1439 (2003) (citing Justice Kotaro Tanaka of the ICJ as stating that Article
38(l)(c) "extends the concept of the source of international law beyond the limit of
legal positivism according to which ... international law is nothing but the law of
the consent and auto-limitation of the state").
77. See, e.g., Hall, supra note 74, at 293.
78. See id. at 292 (reiterating that recognition is key to the idea of general
principles, not consent or enactment of measures on the international legal stage).
79. See ALFRED VERDROSS, DIE QUELLEN DES UNIVERSELLEN VOLKERRECHTS
[THE SOURCES OF UNIVERSAL INTERNATIONAL LAW] 128 (1973) (explaining that
principles can be recognized through implicit consensus).
80. See Simma & Alston, supra note 16, at 104.
2008] CUSTOMARY LA W WITHOUT CUSTOM?
81. See DWORKIN, supra note 52, at 28-45 (explaining that legal principles are
a conceptual predecessor to formal rules of law and as such form a basis on which
modem jurisprudence rests).
82. See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 259 (Peter Cane et al. eds., 2d ed.
1994) (1961) (responding to Dworkin's criticism of his work as portraying the
legal system as "all or nothing" rules, and admitting that legal principles have a
role, albeit small, to play in the understanding of the legal system as a whole).
83. See DWORKIN, supra note 52, at 22-45 (critically assessing Hart's concept
of legal positivism because legal principles, policies and rights are influential,
especially in cases of judicial discretion, yet defy traditional categorization as a
cohesive or formalized set of rules).
84. See id. at 43-45 (characterizing the view of legal positivists as being that
legal principles cannot be categorized or even listed as legal principles because
they are countless and constantly evolving).
85. See id. at 28-45 (explaining that legal rights, policies, and principles can
exist prior to formal rules of law, and form the theoretical basis upon which judges
can draw to express moral considerations and beliefs which may exist outside of
formal rules of law).
86. See SIECKMANN, supra note 73, at 247; Roger Cotterrell, Legality,
Liberalism's Empire: Reflections on Ronald Dworkin's Legal Philosophy, 1987
AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 509, 514 (1987) (stating that Dworkin views legal discourse
expansively and not in a narrow, easily catalogued system of rules and
regulations).
87. See Cotterrell, supra note 86, at 514 (explaining the central role and
inseparability of morality in both the development of jurisprudence and to the
lawyer and legal practice itself).
88. Statute of the International Court of Justice, supra note 1, art. 38, para. 1.
AM. U.INT'L L. REv. [23:275
2. Compliance Theories
97. Id. at 49; see also Anthony S. Winer, The CISG Convention and Thomas
Franck's Theory of Legitimacy, 19 N.W. J. INT'L L. & Bus. 1, 5 (1998) (explaining
how Franck's four properties can exert influence in the arena of international law
and particularly in the case of the acceptance and legitimacy of the CISG
Convention).
98. See FRANCK, supra note 95, at 49 (elucidating the indicators of legitimacy,
among which community practice is not a factor, as Franck stresses the importance
of viewing rules as dynamic sources and not staid practices of states).
99. See Guzman, supra note 8, at 163, 166-71, 173 (applying rational choice
analysis to treaty formation, persistent and subsequent objectors, and new states).
See generally Norman & Trachtman, supra note 23, at 541-42. (analyzing
rationalist theory under a "repeated multilateral prisoner's dilemma model" of
customary international law); Swaine, supra note 23, at 621 (using game theory to
demonstrate the shortcomings of traditional customary international law).
100. See Guzman, supra note 8, at 118 (stating that Guzman's theory of
customary international law still rests on the understanding that behavioral norms
create customary law among states); Norman & Trachtman, supra note 23, at 541-
42 (asserting that customary international law has the innate ability to affect state
behavior); Swaine, supra note 23, at 621 (suggesting that states may prefer the
flexibility of customary law because it allows them, if their behavior changes, to
abandon customary law with little economic fallout).
101. See Jack L. Goldsmith & Eric A. Posner, A Theory of Customary
International Law, 66 U. CHI. L. REv. 1113-77 (1999) (explaining their novel
presentation of the "norms" of customary international law and how they stem
from national self-interest rather than legal or moral obligations).
102. See id. at 1120.
20081 CUSTOMARY LA W WITHOUT CUSTOM? 297
c. Evaluation
110. See generally Anne van Aaken, Making International Human Rights
Protection More Effective: A Rational-ChoiceApproach to the Effectiveness of lus
Standi Provisions, 32 CONF. ON NEW POL. EcON. 29 (2006) (distinguishing
compliance with effectiveness of legal norms). The notion of compliance aims at
the simultaneity of state behavior and norm-content, while effectiveness considers
the reason why states comply with a norm. Even if states comply, a norm is only
effective if compliance is induced by content-independent reasons. See id. at 30-
32.
111. See Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 101, at 1132 (presenting the rational
choice perspective, which holds that a customary norm does not cause behavior,
but merely reflects behavior that is induced by states' self interest).
112. See Anne van Aaken, To Do Away With InternationalLaw? Some Limits to
"The Limits of International Law," 17 EUR. J. INT'L L. 289, 292 (2006)
(questioning methodology used by Goldsmith and Posner in their game theory
analysis).
113. See Guzman, supra note 8, at 134.
114. See Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 101, at 1132 (insisting that payoffs,
and not customary international law, are the only factors determining state
behavior).
2008] CUSTOMARYLA W WITHOUT CUSTOM?
3. PositivistApproach
123. But see KELSEN, PRINCIPLES, supra note 7, at 558 (introducing the basic
norm (Grundnorm) as reason for the normativity of every legal system).
124. See HART, supra note 82, at 100.
125. Id. at 105.
126. But see Escorihuela, supra note 117, at 729 (deriding the sources doctrine
of ICJ Statute Article 38 as "sheer metaphysics" and suggesting its rejection in
favor of analysis of judicial decisions).
127. See Guzman, supra note 8, at 122 (denigrating state practice as having no
direct contribution to the existence of customary norms, while conceding that it
may influence state conduct).
128. See Oscar Schachter, International Law in Theory and Practice, in 178
RECUEIL DES COURS 9, 60 (1982) (Fr.) (noting the influence of Comte's
sociological positivism on legal thinkers).
129. AUGUSTE COMTE, DISCOURS SUR L'ESPRIT POSITIF [DISCOURSE ON THE
POSITIVE SPIRIT] (1844).
130. Id.
2008] CUSTOMAR Y LA W WITHOUT CUSTOM?
131. See Craig Haney, Psychological and Legal Change: On the Limits of a
Factual Jurisprudence, 4 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 147, 163 (1980) (distinguishing
between prescriptive and descriptive disciplines).
132. See id. at 148 (describing the emergence in the nineteenth century of a
concept of law whereby the law was viewed as an instrument for achieving
positive goals).
133. See Joost Pauwelyn, A Typology of Multilateral Treaty Obligations: Are
WTO Obligations Bilateralor Collective in Nature?, 14 EUR. J. INT'L L. 907, 908
(2003) (suggesting that multilateral, as contrasted with bilateral, obligations
presuppose a collective interest of states above and beyond the particular interests
of each state participating in the obligation).
134. See id. (introducing the concept of suspending obligations as a
countermeasure for breach).
135. See Kirgis, Jr., supra note 32, at 148-49 (discussing the relationship
between conduct, consistency, and state practice); see also Daniel Bodansky,
Customary (and Not so Customary) International Environmental Law, 3 IND. J.
GLOBAL LEGAL STUD. 105, 111 (1995) (discussing transboundary pollution and
claiming that consistent, uniform state practice is emphasized in traditional
customary law).
302 AM. U. INT'L L. RE V. [23:275
136. See Roberts, supra note 32, at 764 (2001) (discussing the legal spectrum
between facilitative and moral rules); see also HART, supra note 82, at 79-81
(explaining the distinction between primary and secondary rules which essentially
regulate moral and legal conduct, respectively).
137. Kadelbach & Kleinlein, supra note 47, at 262-63 (discussing the moral
underpinnings of principles and listing several moral values protected by
principles).
2008] CUSTOMA R Y LA W WITHO UT CUSTOM? 303
2. Principlesand FillingLacuna
159. Statute of the International Court of Justice, supra note 1,art. 38, para. 1.
160. See B~la Vitanyi, Les positions Doctrinales Concernant le sens de la
Notion de "PrincipesGndraux de Droit Reconnus par les Nations Civilisdes," 86
REVUE GENERALE DE DROIT INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC 48, 96-102 (1982) (Fr.)
(giving an overview of doctrinal approaches identifying general principles by
analogy to the forum domesticum).
161. See G. J. H. VAN HOOF, RETHINKING THE SOURCES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
139-46 (1983) (discussing the ICJ Statute drafters' dual view of general principles
of law, first as accepted by all nations, and second as natural law).
162. See Simma & Alston, supra note 16, at 102 (stating that the drafters of the
ICJ Statute did not want speculation to lead to the formation of general principles,
but rather general acceptance or recognition by states).
163. Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties art. 32, May 23, 1969, 1155
U.N.T.S. 331.
164. See M. Cherif Bassiouni, A FunctionalApproach to "General Principlesof
InternationalLaw," II MICH. J. INT'L L. 768, 776 (1990) (examining how general
principles are used to clarify and interpret international law); Johan G. Lammers,
General Principles of Law Recognized by Civilized Nations, in ESSAYS ON THE
DEVELOPMENT OF THE INTERNATIONAL LEGAL ORDER 53, 64 (Frits Kalshoven et
al. eds., 1980) (describing the use of general principles by arbitral tribunals prior to
the establishment of the PCIJ). See generally Alain Pellet, Article 38, in THE
STATUTE OF THE INTERNATIONAL COURT OF JUSTICE: A COMMENTARY 677
(Andreas Zimmerman et al. eds., 2006) (stating that although general principles of
law were relied upon occasionally prior to the establishment of the PCIJ, the
specific language of Article 38 encouraged reliance on general principles).
165. See Pellet, supra note 164, at 765 (noting that some drafters were
concerned that the use of general principles would lead to subjectivity by judges).
166. Statute of the International Court of Justice, supra note 1, art. 38, para. 1.
308 AM U. INT'L L. REV. [23:275
CONCLUSION
Even in times of an increasing institutionalization of international
law, unwritten international law counts-indeed, it may even gain
importance. This is so, in particular, if one accepts that international
regimes are not self-contained. It plays a considerable role in the
discussions on human rights, 17 3 democracy, 7 4 and accountability in
the context of international financial institutions, as well as in
attempts to introduce human rights'75 and environmental1 6
considerations into the scope of world trade law. Considering the
growing complexity of present international law, a rethinking of the
doctrine of sources becomes necessary. It is not without reason that
this issue has attracted much attention in recent international law
scholarship. This Article has attempted to reanimate the discussion of
general principles of law as a second primary source of unwritten
173. See generally John D. Ciorciari, The Lawful Scope of Human Rights
Criteria in World Bank Credit Decisions: An Interpretative Analysis of the IBRD
and IDA Articles of Agreement, 33 CORNELL INT'L L.J. 331 (2000) (examining
how one could interpret the World Bank Charter in light of universal human
rights); Genoveva Hernndez Uriz, To Lend or Not to Lend: Oil, Human Rights,
and the World Bank's Internal Contradictions, 14 HARV. HUM. RTS. J. 197 (2001)
(providing the human rights provisions incorporated into the World Bank's
Chad/Cameroon project loan as an example of effective application of a human
rights policy).
174. See STEFANIE KILLINGER, THE WORLD BANK'S NON-POLITICAL MANDATE
150-55 (2003); Adrian Leftwich, Governance, Democracy and Development in the
Third World, 14 THIRD WORLD Q. 605, 610-11 (243).
175. See JAN NEUMANN, DIE KOORDINATION DES WTO-RECHTS MIT ANDEREN
VOLKERRECHTLICHEN ORDNUNGEN [THE COORDINATION OF WTO LAW WITH
OTHER INTERNATIONAL LEGAL ORDERS] 288 (2002) (F.R.G.); Ernst-Ulrich
Petersmann, Human Rights and InternationalEconomic Law in the 21st Century:
The Need to Clarify Their Interrelationships,4 J. INT'L ECON. L. 3, 37-38 (2001)
(suggesting that the WTO use universal human rights when interpreting WTO
rules).
176. See Rao Geping, The Law Applied by World Trade Organization Panels,
17 TEMP. INT'L & COMP. L.J. 125, 130-31 (2003) (examining the Beef-Hormone
dispute as one based in environmental law and critiquing the Panel's holding that
customary international law did not override WTO provisions even if it was
considered a general principle because it was not clear how widely accepted it was
by the international community); Sarah Harrell, Beyond "Reach "? An Analysis of
the European Union's Chemical Regulation Program Under World Trade
Organization Agreements, 24 WIS. INT'L L.J. 471, 484 (2006) (arguing that the
precautionary principle of environmental law is so widely accepted, evidenced by
its inclusion in numerous environmental treaties, that it rises to the level of
customary international law and could have an effect on WTO decisions).
310 AM. U. INT'L L. REV. [23:275