The University of Chicago Law Review The University of Chicago Law Review
The University of Chicago Law Review The University of Chicago Law Review
The University of Chicago Law Review The University of Chicago Law Review
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/1600567?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
The University of Chicago Law Review is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The University of Chicago Law Review
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism
Adrian Vermeulet
t Professor of Law, The University of Chicago. Thanks to David Currie, Jack Goldsmith,
Don Herzog, Eric Posner, David Strauss, Cass Sunstein, and participants at a University of Vir-
ginia workshop for helpful comments, to Eric Truett for excellent research assistance, and to the
Russell J. Parsons Research Fund for financial support. Special thanks to Yun Soo Vermeule.
1 David Hume, Of the Independency of Parliament, in David Hume, Essays: Moral, Politi-
cal, and Literary 42 (Liberty Fund 1985) (Eugene F Miller, ed). For works associating Hume with
the knavery principle, see Lewis A. Kornhauser, Virtue and Self-Interest in the Design of Constitu-
tional Institutions, 3 Theor Inq in L 15-16 (2002); Franklin A. Kalinowski, David Hume on the
Philosophic Underpinnings of Interest Group Politics, 25 Polity 355, 369-74 (1993); David M.
Kirkham, European Sources of American Constitutional Thought before 1787,3 USAFA J Legal
Stud 1, 22 (1992). For other versions of the knavery principle, see John Stuart Mill, Considera-
tions on Representative Government, in 19 Collected Works of John Stuart Mill: Essays on Politics
and Society 371, 505 (Toronto 1977) (J.M. Robson, ed); Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace 29-30
(Bobbs-Merrill 1957) (Lewis White Beck, ed).
421
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
422 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
2 See, for example, Morton White, Philosophy, The Federalist, and the Constitution 13-22
(Oxford 1987); Douglass Adair, "That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science": David Hume,
James, Madison, and the Tenth Federalist, 20 Huntington Library Q 343,348-57 (1957) (describ-
ing the influence of Hume on Madison's writings on factions).
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 423
The initial puzzle is why anyone might endorse the knavery prin-
ciple as a master principle of constitutional design. As Hume puts it,
"[I]t appears somewhat strange, that a maxim should be true in poli-
tics, which is false in fact."3 It is not true that public officials, or for that
matter people generally, always pursue rational self-interest, except in
the tautological sense that reduces altruistic behavior and morally-
motivated behavior to interdependent utility functions4 and a "taste
for fairness,"'5 respectively. In Hamilton's words, the "assumption of
universal venality in human nature is little less an error in political
reasoning, than the supposition of universal rectitude."6 But the em-
pirical question turns out to be a distraction. The standard defense of
the principle, stemming from work in the economics of constitutional
choice, casts it as a methodological commitment rather than an em-
pirical claim. The knavery principle is factually erroneous, yet (on this
view) represents the best postulate by which to assess constitutional-
design proposals.
The methodological defense of the principle rests on four claims.7
First is a claim from symmetry or parsimony: If people are best mod-
eled as rational maximizers of self-interest in explicit markets, the
same model should be applied to implicit political markets. By itself
the appeal to symmetry does not, of course, tell us whether rational
self-interest is the correct uniform assumption to use, but the implicit
claim is that explicit markets can't sensibly be modeled on any other
assumption. Second is a kind of maximin argument, or more loosely
an argument based on avoiding the worst-case scenario: If the harms
from self-interested official behavior are greater than the benefits of
public-spirited official behavior-if knaves do more harm than
knights do good -then constitutional rules should be designed on pes-
simistic assumptions to minimize the worst possible outcomes rather
than to maximize the best possible outcomes. Third is a selection
claim: Just as non-profit-maximizing behavior is driven out of explicit
markets by the bankruptcy of non-profit-maximizing firms, so too
public-regarding behavior will be driven out of political markets be-
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
424 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
8 See Albert 0. Hirschman, Against Parsimony: Three Easy Ways of Complicating Some
Categories of Economic Discourse, 1 Econ & Phil 7,8-9,20 (1985).
9 See Kornhauser, 3 Theor Inq in L at 18-19 (cited in note 1).
10 See Bruno S. Frey, A Constitution for Knaves Crowds Out Civic Virtues, 107 Econ J 1043,
1044-45 (1997).
11 See Richard Titmuss, The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy 223
(Pantheon 1971).
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 425
12 Uri Gneezy and Aldo Rustichini, A Fine is a Price, 29 J Legal Stud 1, 14 (2000) (finding
that the number of late parents at day care increased after a fine for lateness was implemented,
and concluding that "[n]o guilt or shame ... can be attached to the act of buying a commodity at
will").
13 See Brennan and Hamlin, Democratic Devices and Desires at 87-97 (cited in note 7);
Geoffrey Brennan, Selection and the Currency of Reward, in Robert E. Goodin, ed, The Theory
of Institutional Design 256,258 (Cambridge 1996).
14 For examples of this frustration, see Philip K. Howard, The Lost Art of Drawing the
Line: How Fairness Went Too Far 129-31 (Random House 2001).
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
426 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 427
18 Id.
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
428 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
23 Id at 45.
24 David Hume, Whether the British Government Inclines More to Absolute Monarchy, or to
a Republic, in Hume, Essays 47,47-48 (cited in note 1).
25 For modem accounts of the collective action problems involved in vote-buying, see Saul
Levmore, Voting with Intensity, 53 Stan L Rev 111, 122-41 (2000); Russell Hardin, Morality
within the Limits of Reason 93 (Chicago 1988).
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 429
B. Other Examples
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
430 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
26 David Hume, That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science, in Hume, Essays 14,18 (cited in
note 1).
27 Hume, First Principles at 36 (cited in note 17).
28 Id.
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 431
29 Hume, Whether the British Government Inclines toward Absolute Monarchy at 53 (cited
in note 24).
30 And perhaps inspired or influenced; this is a historical question that I lack competence
to answer.
31 See R.G. Lipsey and R.K. Lancaster, The General Theory of Second Best, 24 Rev Econ
Stud 11 (1956).
32 See, for example, Bruce Talbot Coram, Second Best Theories and the Implications for In-
stitutional Design, in Goodin, Theory of Institutional Design 91 (cited in note 13); Robert E.
Goodin, Political Ideals and Political Practice, 25 Brit J Polit Sci 37, 52-56 (1995).
33 See Avishai Margalit, Ideals and Second Bests, in Seymour Fox, ed, Philosophy for Edu-
cation 77,77 (Daf-Chen 1983).
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
432 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
34 See Gary Lawson, Delegation and Original Meaning, 88 Va L Rev 327, 333-34 (2002)
(asserting that the Constitution "does contain a discernible, textually grounded nondelegation
principle that is far removed from modern doctrine").
35 See David Schoenbrod, Power without Responsibility: How Congress Abuses the People
through Delegation 99-154 (Yale 1993) (arguing that delegation is both undesirable and unnec-
essary). For rejoinders to both the originalist and functionalist critiques of delegation, see Eric A.
Posner and Adrian Vermeule, Interring the Nondelegation Doctrine, 69 U Chi L Rev 1721,1733-
36,1743-54 (2002).
36 See, for example, Martin S. Flaherty, The Most Dangerous Branch, 105 Yale L Rev 1725,
1828-39 (1996); Abner S. Greene, Checks and Balances in an Era of Presidential Lawmaking, 61
U Chi L Rev 123,184-96 (1994).
37 See Lawrence Lessig and Cass R. Sunstein, The President and the Administration, 94
Colum L Rev 1,2-3 (1994).
38 For functional arguments in favor of the line-item veto, see Robert Justin Lipkin, The
New Majoritarianism, 69 U Cin L Rev 107,121-22 (2000); Steven G. Calabresi, Some Normative
Arguments for the Unitary Executive, 48 Ark L Rev 23,78-81 (1995).
39 See Calabresi, 48 Ark L Rev at 78-79 (cited in note 38) ("[T]he line-item veto would, if
everything else stayed the same, clearly lead to lower levels of district-targeted spending and
redistribution.").
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 433
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
434 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 435
any partial or transient benefit to which the use can at any time
yield.4
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
436 The University of Chicago Law Review [70:421
the global effects of judicial decisions as well? But there isn't really
any paradox. This view simply holds that judges can and should under-
stand what it is they do not understand, that they should know the
limits of their own knowledge. That second-best adjustments are de-
sirable does not entail that any particular institution or actor should
attempt to identify and implement them.
But the implications of this pragmatic critique for constitutional
adjudication are ambiguous. In the common-law setting the counsel
that judges should ignore second-best considerations is at least clear,
whatever its merit: The judges decide cases on strictly local grounds,
and the legislature may, if it chooses, overrule the judges after consid-
ering second-best effects. But this picture has no unique mapping onto
the constitutional setting, because constitutional decisions cannot be
overruled through ordinary lawmaking. If courts invalidate local struc-
tural innovations that, like the legislative veto, are impermissible
taken in isolation, they thereby ignore any appeals to the offsetting ef-
fects of the innovation along other margins -an approach that ob-
serves the injunction to ignore second-best considerations. Yet invali-
dation prevents the compensating adjustment from being made by any
institution, short of obtaining a constitutional amendment. If the law-
making process really is better suited than the judiciary to identify
necessary second-best adjustments, perhaps judges should simply de-
fer to politically-developed structural innovations in constitutional
cases, rather than invalidating them on the basis of a strictly local
analysis.
In my view, this ambiguity is irresolvable. Both systematic defer-
ence and systematic seriatim enforcement of local constitutional pro-
visions are compatible with the pragmatic critique. But this does not
mean that the critique is so spongy as to be worthless. What it does bar
is the ambitious idea that judges should evaluate global consequences
on a case-by-case basis,48 attempting to identify and uphold all and
only those structural innovations that will indeed compensate for
prior departures from the optimum. Despite its apparent modesty, that
procedure is a counsel of perfection, one that assumes a heroic judicial
capacity to identify the global effects of particular institutional inno-
vations (as opposed to the global effects of a general mode of judicial
decisionmaking). The case-by-case procedure is itself suspect on sec-
ond-best grounds: If the judges' information and computational ca-
pacities are far from the ideal, they ought not simply attempt to imi-
tate ideal judges to the best of their abilities; that is the approximation
'8 See INS v Chadha, 462 US 919,978 (1983) (White dissenting) (urging that the legislative
veto should be upheld to compensate for the demise of the nondelegation doctrine); Peter B.
McCutchen, Mistakes, Precedent, and the Rise of the Administrative State: Toward a Constitutional
Theory of the Second Best, 80 Cornell L Rev 1, 37-38 (1994) (elaborating White's claim).
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism 437
CONCLUSION
49 See Cass R. Sunstein and Edna Ullmann-Margalit, Second-Order Decisions, 110 Ethics
5,7 (1999).
This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Sun, 05 Jun 2016 19:38:51 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms