Idea Creativity
Idea Creativity
Idea Creativity
Philosophy of
History and Culture
Editor
Michael Krausz
Bryn Mawr College
Advisory Board
Annette Baier (University of Pittsburgh)
Purushottama Bilimoria (Deakin University, Australia)
Cora Diamond (University of Virginia)
William Dray (University of Ottawa)
Nancy Fraser (New School for Social Research)
Clifford Geertz† (Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton)
Peter Hacker (St. John’s College, Oxford)
Rom Harré (Linacre College, Oxford)
Bernard Harrison (University of Sussex)
Martha Nussbaum (University of Chicago)
Leon Pompa (University of Birmingham)
Joseph Raz (Balliol College, Oxford)
Amélie Rorty (Harvard University)
VOLUME 28
The Idea of Creativity
Edited by
Michael Krausz, Denis Dutton and Karen Bardsley
LEIDEN • BOSTON
2009
This book is printed on acid-free paper.
The idea of creativity / edited by Michael Krausz, Denis Dutton, and Karen Bardsley.
p. cm. -- (Philosophy of history and culture, ISSN 0922-6001 ; v. 28)
Includes index.
ISBN 978-90-04-17444-3 (hardback : alk. paper) 1. Creative ability. I. Krausz, Michael. II.
Dutton, Denis. III. Bardsley, Karen. IV. Title. V. Series.
BF408.I36 2009
153.3’5--dc22
2008055174
ISSN 0922-6001
ISBN 978 90 04 17444 3
Acknowledgments ....................................................................... ix
Contributors ................................................................................ xi
PART ONE
EXPLAINING CREATIVITY:
PERSONS, PROCESSES, AND PRODUCTS
PART TWO
PART THREE
Berys Gaut took the PhD from Princeton University in 1991 and is cur-
rently a Senior Lecturer in Moral Philosophy at University of St. Andrews
in Scotland. His research interests include aesthetics, especially its rela-
tion to ethics and to theories of creativity, philosophy of film and film
theory, moral theory, and Kant’s moral philosophy. He is author of Art,
Emotion, and Ethics (2007) and is currently completing A Philosophy of Cin-
ematic Art (forthcoming, 2009). Gaut is co-editor of The Routledge Compan-
ion to Aesthetics, and is Chairman of the Management Committee of The
Philosophical Quarterly.
Changed Our View of the World (1981); Personal Being: A Theory for Individual
Psychology (1984); Motives and Mechanisms: An Introduction to the Psychology of
Action (with David D. Clarke and Nicola De Carlo, 1985); Varieties of
Realism (1986); The Discursive Mind (1994); and One Thousand Years of Phi-
losophy: From Ramanuja to Wittgenstein (2000). His most recent book is Witt-
genstein and Psychology: A Practical Guide (with Michael A. Tissaw, 2005). In
1971, Harré, with Paul F. Secord, founded The Journal for the Theory of
Social Behaviour, with which he is still associated. Currently, he teaches at
Georgetown University in Washington, D.C. Harré is also the Director
of the Centre for the Natural and Social Sciences at the London School
of Economics.
and the Film (1987), and numerous other studies in sociology, philosophy,
and film history. Most recently, with Joseph Agassi he co-authored A
Critical Rationalist Aesthetics (2008).
Dean Keith Simonton took the PhD in Social Psychology from Harvard
University in 1975. He is currently Distinguished Professor of Psychology
at the University of California, Davis. His many publications examine
xvi contributors
Michael Krausz
This volume collects seventeen essays that address the question, What is
Creativity? This general question encompasses more specific ones that
the authors address in the three parts of the volume. Here, then, are
those specific questions along with abbreviated summaries of the essays
that answer them.
Part One
Explaining Creativity: Persons, Processes, and Products
Part One addresses these questions: What are the criteria for creativity?
Should we assign logical priority to creative persons, creative processes,
or creative products? Is creativity essentially mysterious? Can creativity
be explained? If creativity is explainable, can it be explained naturalisti-
cally? Is creativity unpredictable? Is creativity goal-directed? What role
does skill play in creativity? How does a creative product relate to
medium and work?
Carl Hausman offers the following four criteria of creativity. Cre-
ated outcomes have intelligible structures that are irreducible; created
outcomes are unpredictable; the structures of created outcomes are
inherently and usually instrumentally valuable; and the acts that lead
to created outcomes include an element of spontaneity. In emphasizing
the idea that the intelligibility of a creative outcome is discernible in a
structure that is unprecedented and unpredictable, Hausman resists a
determinism that excludes novelty or newness of intelligibility.
Larry Briskman asserts that, in contrast to creative persons and cre-
ative processes, the creativity of the product is what has logical priority.
We can only identify persons and processes as creative via our prior
identification of products as creative. A scientific or artistic product, for
example, is not creative because a creative person or a creative process
produced it. Instead, we deem persons to be creative persons and their
processes to be creative process only in light of the prior evaluation of
the product as a creative product. We deem the person involved and the
xviii introduction
Part Two
Creativity, Imagination, and Self
to our sense of place in the world? How does our knowledge of the
circumstances of creativity effect our appreciation of its products?
Paisley Livingston explores the conceptual space defined by two
extreme theses—the inspirationist idea that artistic creativity is a sud-
den, involuntary, and ultimately inexplicable event, and the rationalistic
counterthesis, which characterizes artistic creation as a deliberate selec-
tion from amongst an array of previously known options. Livingston
adduces Henri Poincaré’s surmisal that while unconscious mental pro-
cess blindly generates combinations, the aesthetic sensibility scans the
results. That sensibility singles out those results that are especially pleas-
ing, elegant, harmonious, or well proportioned. Livingston also suggests
that in moments of incubation, when artists or scientists have set aside
their work and have taken up some unrelated pastime, their minds are
not idle.
Michael Polanyi calls all thoughts of things that are not yet present,
acts of the imagination. In turn, intuition integrates those acts. The
final sanction of discovery lies in the recognition of a coherence that
intuition detects and accepts as real. Intuition informs the imagination,
which in its turn releases the powers of intuition. Accordingly, Polanyi
recognizes two kinds of awareness: awareness of the object at which we
are looking, and awareness of innumerable clues that we integrate to
the sight of the object. We have a subsidiary awareness of the clues that
bear upon the object of our focus. Intuitive powers integrate the largely
unspecifiable clues, and the process of integration is not fully definable.
Francis Sparshott suggests that poets develop a uniquely personal
way of finding themes and ways of working them. Poets are known
for their sustained habit of attention. As they scrutinize the world for
themes, they look ceaselessly for ways of proceeding. Their style is a
style of search, not a habit of acceptance. Their minds are restless scan-
ners. Though poets cannot describe it fully, they know nothing better
than their way of proceeding. They know what to do next. The style of
truly original and creative poets determines their way of changing and
developing. Innovators astonish us by the total development of their
practice, not by each work taken singly.
Michael Krausz outlines the personal program that motivates his
artistic production and self-transformation. His personal program val-
ues process over product, and accommodates nondualistic experiences
as benchmarks of his creative life journey. He regards self-transfor-
mation as a creative product. This program resists any sharp distinc-
tion between creative process and creative product. Creative persons,
xx introduction
Part Three
Forms and Domains of Creativity
EXPLAINING CREATIVITY:
PERSONS, PROCESSES, AND PRODUCTS
CHAPTER ONE
CRITERIA OF CREATIVITY1
Carl R. Hausman
1
The following discussion is a version of a paper presented at a session of The
Society for the Philosophy of Creativity, Pacific Division, in conjunction with the
American Philosophical Association meetings, Berkeley, California, 26 March 1976.
Reprinted from Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 40 (1979): 237–249.
2
Rollo May, The Courage to Create (New York: Norton, 1975).
3
Ibid., 39.
4 carl r. hausman
4
I have tried to take a step in this direction in A Discourse on Novelty and Creation (The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975). This book also develops at greater length, but with
different emphases, the criteria suggested in this paper.
criteria of creativity 5
II
and molecule is different from every other blade of grass, grain of sand,
and molecule. Likewise, what is unique may be a general or universal.
Angularity, the quality of hardness, or a law of nature—each has an
identity that is different from all other generals as well as distinctly
relative to its particular instances. And what is unique may be an actual
experience or activity or consciousness, each of which is different from
every other experience or act of consciousness.
The minimal condition of newness has been given priority, either
explicitly or implicitly, by some writers who claim that the world is
everywhere open to creative acts. Some philosophers—such as William
James, or those who adopt one aspect of a Whiteheadian view—suggest
that every activity or occasion is unique. Each experience, event, and
object is new in the sense of being a unique actualized integration of
components. As such, it is new in being different. And all things to this
extent exemplify creativity. Creativity, then, pervades all things.
It seems to me that universalizing creativity in this way makes the
meaning of creativity too broad. The price paid for this democratic
application is that we have no way to distinguish among creations. With
respect to uniqueness in the sense of being different, we do not have
even degrees of creativity. A stone exemplifies creativity as much as a
painting by Giotto. Except perhaps as a metaphysical category, this
universal meaning of creativity does not advance our understanding.
It does not help us understand what the creation of a more special
or striking kind is. The point that some condition other than unique-
ness in the sense of difference is needed can be seen if we notice that
‘uniqueness’ is a term that usually includes more than sheer difference.
There must be some merit in being different, and the attribution
of the term ‘unique’ implies that it is good to be different. However,
the value of being different still is insufficient to justify regarding a
valuable and different outcome of an act as a creation in any other
sense than the universal, thin sense. For one thing, many of the acts
and outcomes which, like all acts and outcomes which in this view are
unique, are different in certain ways that make them unacceptable
candidates as creative or as creations. If this were not so, then the
distinction between creative acts and imitation, routine processes, or
hackwork would be meaningless.
Now, the way singular is unique, which is to say, the way they are
different and therefore valuable, is the key to a second and more radi-
cal sense of newness. This point can be considered in terms of the way
in which what is unique may be regarded as intelligible.
criteria of creativity 7
III
The reason for examining the term new in the initial characterization
of creativity was to draw out and elaborate criteria of creativity. The
first criterion of creativity thus far suggested is that an instance of
creativity is found in an outcome that must exhibit a structure which
is different from all precedent structures. This formulation of the main
criterion has three consequences, consideration of which will indicate
further criteria.
First, with respect to the outcome, we should notice that since its
intelligibility is unprecedented, it is underived and is something that
was not predicted. But also, its intelligibility is discernible in a structure
that could not have been predicted. If the structure were predictable in
principle, it would be wholly dependent on prior intelligibility for its
own intelligibility. And the structure then would have precedence. It
would be derived and prefigured, traceable to antecedents and classified
as an instance of general and repeatable conceptualizable items. It
would have been known, anticipated, and describable, if sufficient
knowledge had been available. To interpret creations this way would
be to presuppose some form of determinism, and a determinism which
excludes Novelty Proper or newness of intelligibility from the intelli-
gible world. A creation in the radical sense, then, must exhibit structure
that is both unprecedented and unpredictable.
The second consequence of the requirement that a criterion must
exhibit a structure which is not derived from prior structures was sug-
gested earlier in the observation that those who find newness wherever
there is uniqueness seem to include value in their conception of what
it is to be unique. Uniqueness is considered good, good aesthetically,
morally, or in some ontological or metaphysical sense. What has been
said about the coherence that must be present in the ordering of com-
ponents of the creation similarly suggests value: an epistemological
value. Coherence contributes to making the creation recognizable and
knowable. It contributes to intelligibility, since it is the basis for the
definiteness required for recognizability.
However, the value of coherence pervades all intelligible things. Like
the value of uniqueness, this value is too broad. Something more than
epistemological value is at stake. If it were not, eccentricities would be
admitted as creations. For these exemplify what I am calling Novelty
Proper, possessing some coherence as recognizable structure. But as
merely eccentric, they do not merit being considered creations. Being
criteria of creativity 11
spontaneity in the act. We have simply shifted its locus. We still have
before us an act, now ‘internal,’ ‘in the mind,’ in which the rules con-
stituting it were introduced for the first time and in which an unprec-
edented structure came to be envisaged by the creator.
The creative act, then, is a transforming act. It proceeds in accord
with constraints that are given not only by the personality and environ-
ment of the creator and by the medium in which he works, but also
in the spontaneity of the act itself. The requirements of the developing
structure are themselves developed. The creator does not set out with
a pre-envisaged target. The creative artist does not know till he has
said it what he wants to say or how he will say it. He constitutes his
target as he discovers how to aim at it. Thus, the creative act is dis-
continuous. It includes at one or more of its stages a break with the
constraints that prior intelligibility imposed on the creator. Further, it
includes a break in continuities connecting intelligibilities, or structures
by which things are duplicable and known before creation takes place.
At the same time, the creative act is not wholly uncontrolled. If there
is serendipity, it is not sheer accident. The creator must not only exer-
cise critical judgment in deciding what to accept and reject when pos-
sibilities occur to him, but he must also form, refine, and integrate
these, even though he knows only with a degree of imprecision what
the final integration will be. And most important, he must assume
responsibility for what he brings into being. Even automatic writers
and the most romantic interpreters of their own creative acts must
accept responsibility for the outcome that they believe has its source
beyond them.
The responsibility indicates once more the role of value in the cre-
ation. For if creators bring their outcomes into being responsibly, they
are offered as what ought to be. Moreover, the responsibility of form-
ing an intelligibility which represents a repudiation of what was before
acceptable is conducive to the anguish frequently reported by artists.
It also confirms why writers like Rollo May speak of the need for cour-
age to create.
With the initial statement of the criteria of creativity and these
consequences in mind, the criteria can now be formulated: (1) a creation
must manifest what I have termed Novelty Proper, or a structure that
is different and un-derived from past structures and is thus unpredict-
able; (2) a creation must be inherently and often instrumentally valuable;
(3) the act that leads to the creation includes spontaneity as well as
directed control.
criteria of creativity 13
IV
gible. This is where they are discovered and created. On the other
hand, as identities, they must endure; they must have some constancy
so that they are not exhaustively bound by an instant of time and a
single place. They must be atemporal as well as temporal in their ini-
tial occurrences.
There is a second, related problem. The notion of Novelty Proper
is paradoxical. Novelty Proper is exemplified in outcomes that are
unfamiliar with respect to their intelligibility. Yet, as intelligible, they
must appear as if they were familiar. Moreover, what is both intelligible
and unfamiliar, though manifest as if it were familiar, is not convertible
into something already identifiable that makes the new intelligibility
predictable. If it were, newness would be denied in favor of deriving
the unfamiliar from what is prefigured.
Now, it should be pointed out that the paradox here is not peculiar
to the notion of Novelty Proper. The paradox is simply made evident
most sharply and dramatically in the case of creative acts which are
instances of Novelty Proper. All learning includes recognition of some-
thing not before familiar to the learner. One may insist that such learn-
ing is possible because what appears to be unfamiliar is learned because
it is referred to the familiar, to a fund of experience that was gradually
acquired. But this answer does not account for the first instance of
learning, or the encounter with what begins the fund of experience.
Something must initially be unfamiliar without a ready-made set of
familiar experiences to which it can be traced. Furthermore, the initial
recognition of the connection that holds between unfamiliar experience
to be learned and what is already acquired is itself a recognition of a
formerly unknown connection that must occur for the first time.
It should be noted, however, that creative experience is also like
learning experience, in that it concerns something unfamiliar initially
but which can grow familiar. Unless this was so, our vision of the intel-
ligible world could not grow; what is intelligible could never change.
The third problem to be mentioned centers on the consequence that
the criteria I have proposed seems to preclude the possibility of explain-
ing creativity. Creative acts cannot be explained in accord with the
traditional requirement that explanations show how things to be
explained are predictable. If explanation of creative acts is possible, it
must be of a different kind that meets different requirements.
The suggestion I have made elsewhere is that a different kind of
explanation is appropriate to creativity. I would call this other kind ‘an
account’ rather than ‘explanation,’ since the term account need not
16 carl r. hausman
Larry Briskman
I Introduction
In the past few decades, creativity has become rather like money:
everyone seems to want more of it. Just as we are living in monetarily
inflationary times, so too the notion of creativity has undergone a
wholesale devaluation. Soon we shall not only be carting away our
weekly salaries in wheelbarrows, but the very act of doing so shall come
to be called a creative one. Yet however lax popular standards may
become, there seems to me to be one aspect of creativity which will
remain constant, and that is that creativity is something valuable, and
that the notion of creativity is permeated with evaluation. To adjudge
something to be ‘creative,’ in other words, is to bestow upon it an
honorific title, to claim that it deserves to be highly valued for one
reason or another.2 Hence, without standards and values, creativity
ceases to exist, just as morality ceases to exist. But as with morality,
how high (or low) we set the standards is partially a matter for our
decision. In this essay, then, I shall adopt a fairly restrictive standard,
and in consequence limit the notion of creativity to Science and Art. I
hope that by doing so I do not prejudge any important issues, except
1
Revised and greatly expanded version of a paper first presented at seminars in
the Universities of Edinburgh and Leeds. I want to thank the participants in those
seminars, and especially Stanley Eveling, Leon Pompa, and Geoffrey Cantor, for their
critical comments and suggestions. In addition, I owe special thanks to Michael Krausz
for a series of stimulating discussions of issues related to this chapter. Reprinted from
Inquiry 23 (1980): 83–106 and The Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. D. Dutton
and M. Krausz (The Hague, Boston, London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1981),
129–155, all rights reserved.
2
A similar point has been made by Vincent Tomas in his article “Creativity in
Art,” reprinted in Creativity in the Arts, ed. V. Tomas (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall,
1964), 97–109.
18 larry briskman
For all our valuing of creativity, it appears to be, not least of all to
creative scientists and artists themselves, a kind of mystery, a kind of
miracle. Thus, Mozart writes of his best musical ideas: “Whence and
how they come I know not; nor can I force them.”3 In a similar vein,
Tchaikovsky writes that “the germ of a future composition comes sud-
denly and unexpectedly”;4 while Helmholtz reports that his ideas often
“arrived suddenly, without any effort on my part, like an inspiration.”5
Equally, Gauss, in referring to an arithmetical theorem which he had
for years tried unsuccessfully to prove, writes: “Finally, two days ago, I
succeeded, not on account of my painful efforts, but by the grace of
God. Like a sudden flash of lightning, the riddle happened to be solved.”6
Such quotations could, in fact, be multiplied almost indefinitely; so
consider finally, and more lightly, Desmond Morris’s recent report that
a journalist once asked Picasso: What is creativity? Picasso answered,
“I don’t know, and if I did I wouldn’t tell you.”7
Now I certainly do not want to claim to know more about creativity
than does Picasso, but it does seem to me that the mysteriousness and
miraculousness of creativity is, in effect, an important datum about it.
It is, I think, something from which we can learn, and which we should
try to explain. Yet if we do assume that creativity is a mysterious miracle,
then it becomes one of the most mysterious of all miracles—for it is
( pace Hume) a repeatable miracle. How, then, can we make rational sense
of this ‘miracle’? How, in other words, is creativity possible?
3
From a letter, reprinted in Creativity: Selected Readings, ed. P. E. Vernon (Harmond-
sworth: Penguin, 1970), 55 (Italics in the original).
4
Ibid., 57.
5
Quoted in R. S. Woodworth, Experimental Psychology (New York: Holt, 1938).
6
Quoted in Jacques Hadamard, The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1949), 15.
7
In H. A. Krebs and J. H. Shelly, eds., The Creative Process in Science and Medicine
(Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1975), 31. Morris also reports (58) that a journalist asked Picasso:
“What do you think of chimpanzee painting?” and Picasso bit him!
creative product and creative process in science and art 19
It is, I believe, crucial to see that the problem is to explain the pos-
sibility of creativity, not its necessity. For if we were to actually succeed
in explaining the necessity of creativity, or the necessity of specific
creative achievements, then in a sense we would have explained too
much. To see this, consider what would be involved in such an explana-
tion: take some specific creative scientific or artistic achievement C, and
assume that we had some general theory of creativity, or of the creative
process, T according to which C was necessary. This would mean that
given T, and a description of some relevant set of prior circumstances
or initial conditions P, we could actually deduce the attainment of C.
But this implies that anyone in possession of T, and given the descrip-
tion P, would have ipso facto been in a position to himself create C; and
would, moreover be able in principle to simulate the actual creative
process of the creator of C. Thus, a general theory of creativity, or of
the creative process, along the lines of T would provide a kind of
recipe for being creative; it would, in effect, provide a set of explicit
instructions for attaining creative achievements.
This possibility would, I maintain, have a number of untoward
consequences. First, T would rob the actual creator of C of any par-
ticular, or individual, claim to creativity, for on the assumption that
P was publicly available, T would provide a publicly available, quasi-
mechanical, means for creating C. Moreover, T would provide a means
for reaching innumerable creative achievements (C’, C”, . . .) effortlessly,
since all we would have to do would be to enumerate, one after another,
statements describing as yet unrealized sets of relevant initial conditions
(P’, P”, . . .) and then deduce what would be their resultant. By hypoth-
esis, these resultants (C’, C”, . . .) would have to be creative ones, for
otherwise T would not be the type of general theory of the creative
process (as opposed to some other kind of process) which we are here
envisaging. In other words, T would make creativity both too easy and
too cheap, since we could have creative achievements for the asking,
and this would mean that there would no longer be much point in
calling such achievements creative ones. Thirdly, T would turn every
creative achievement into something to be expected, given the relevant
prior conditions. But this means not only that there need be no surprises,
subjectively speaking, but also that there would be no objective novelty. For
the existence of T would entail that the achievement C was, so to speak,
already ‘contained within’ the prior conditions P, and this means that
relative to P, C was no novelty. Since, I take it, the novelty of C relative
20 larry briskman
8
I should point out here that, strictly speaking, C would lack novelty relative not
to P alone, but only relative to P together with T. But on the assumption either that
what T describes existed prior to C, or that T itself existed prior to C, if follows that,
since C is deducible from P plus T, C is no novelty relative to what preceded it, to
what existed prior to it.
creative product and creative process in science and art 21
I turn, in this section, away from the main problem to a more prosaic
aspect of creativity: namely, why have so many thinkers been interested
in it? Undoubtedly, different thinkers have different motivations, differ-
ent reasons for their interest. But it is, I think, instructive to investigate
a few typical reasons for this interest, as this will help to bring to the
surface some false hopes which, I believe, have been raised by research
into creativity. It will emerge, not unexpectedly perhaps, that the phi-
losophers have been on the side of the angels; while the social scientists,
and especially the psychologists, have been the villains of the piece.
Moreover, their very villainy will actually help us to zero in on our
initial problem.
On the whole then, contemporary philosophers have been concerned
with creativity as an aspect of the problem of human freedom. Popper,
for example, has argued10 that no scientific prediction (and hence,
no scientific explanation) of the growth of scientific knowledge is pos-
sible, on the grounds that we cannot come to know today what we
shall only come to know tomorrow. It follows that what Popper calls
the world of ‘objective mind’ (or of ‘theories, arguments, and prob-
lems-in-themselves’) is an essentially open world, in that it cannot
contain a theory which will predict the appearance in that world of
all future theories. But for Popper this world of objective mind (his
World 3) interacts both with the world of mental states (his World 2)
and with the world of physical states (his World 1)—the latter interac-
tion being mediated through the World 2.11 It follows that both the
mental world, and more importantly, the physical world, are also open;
and this both rules out a purely physical determinism and, in turn,
kicks open the door to the possibility of human freedom. In other
9
See J. Monod, Chance and Necessity (New York: Knopf, 1971), especially chap. 2.
10
In his “Indeterminism in Quantum Physics and in Classical Physics,” British Journal
for the Philosophy of Science 1 (1950), and elsewhere.
11
For Popper’s World 3 theory, see his Objective Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1972), especially chap. 3, 4, 6. I should say here that my approach in this chapter
has been greatly influenced by Popper’s “objectivist” epistemology.
22 larry briskman
12
From J. P. Sartre, Existentialism, trans. Bernard Frechtman (New York: The Philo-
sophical Library, 1947).
13
A propos of this, Popper writes, “At any moment we are prisoners caught in the
framework of our theories; our expectations; our past experiences; our language. But
we are prisoners in a Pickwickian sense: if we try, we can break out of our framework
at any time” (“Normal Science and its Dangers,” in Criticism and the Growth of Knowl-
edge, eds. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970),
56. Popper does, I think, tend to underemphasize the difficulty of such “breakouts.”
In fact, I believe that were such breakouts easy to achieve, we would no longer see
them as creative.
creative product and creative process in science and art 23
14
J. P. Guilford, “Traits of Creativity,” reprinted in Creativity, ed. P. E. Vernon,
167–188. Quote from 167.
15
N. E. Golovin, “The Creative Person in Science,” in C. W. Taylor and F. Barron,
eds., Scientific Creativity: Its Recognition and Development (New York: Wiley, 1963), 7–23
(Quote on 8). This volume consists of selected papers from three conferences on “The
Identification of Creative Scientific Talent” held at the University of Utah in 1954,
1957, and 1959, and supported by the U.S. National Science Foundation. This latter
fact, together with the fact that Golovin himself served for a time on the White House
staff, indicates both the degree of official U.S. support for the study of creativity and
the extent to which American psychologists encouraged the belief in the great practical
potentialities of their research.
16
T. A. Razik, “Psychometric Measurement of Creativity,” reprinted in Creativity,
ed. 155–166. The quote, with italics in the original, is from 156.
17
What, one wonders, is the reasoning behind such optimism? An instructive analogy
can be drawn between many twentieth century students of creativity and seventeenth
century students of methodology. For seventeenth century thinkers, like Bacon and
Descartes, scientific progress was to be guaranteed by “the man of method” whose
relentless application of the correct methodology would ensure continuous progress.
But we now live in a post-Einsteinian age (in art, a post-Picasso age) and our idea
of scientific (and artistic) progress is a more dramatic, revolutionary one. As a result,
I conjecture, many twentieth century thinkers have come to see ‘the man of creative
imagination’ as the new guarantor of scientific progress. Hence, the idea that creativ-
ity had to be something we could do something about; for otherwise scientific progress
becomes a contingent accident, a matter of fortuitous happenstance. The lesson, I suspect,
has yet to be learned that there is no guarantee of scientific progress, and that the
fact that we have any knowledge worthy of the name at all is itself a miraculously
improbable occurrence.
24 larry briskman
18
The main methodological tools of such studies were the so-called open-ended
tests of creativity. As Liam Hudson has pointed out in his book Contrary Imaginations
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1967), 126: “Open-ended tests are known throughout the
United States as creativity tests. Yet . . . there is scarcely a shred of factual support for
this.” For the severe problems involved in validating such tests (that is, in showing that
they are actually testing creativity!) see R. J. Shapiro’s, “Criterion Problem,” in Creativ-
ity, ed. P. E. Vernon, 257–269.
19
The notion of a ‘research program’ is due largely to the writings of Popper,
Agassi, and especially Lakatos. For a discussion of psychology’s dominant modern
metaphysical research program—behaviorism—and some suggested reasons for its
current demise, see my “Is a Kuhnian Analysis Applicable to Psychology?” Science
Studies 2 (1972): 87–97. For further reflections on behaviorism, see my “Skinnerism
and Pseudo-Science,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9 (1979): 81–103.
creative product and creative process in science and art 25
20
At this point, it will be useful to clear up two possible misunderstandings: First,
I am not here assuming that a critical interaction with prior products is the only way
26 larry briskman
The skeptic (in this instance, the psychologist) may still be unmoved,
for I have yet to give an argument for the thesis that the creativity of
the product has logical priority over the creativity of the person and
his (or her) psychological characteristics or processes. Nor have I suf-
ficiently argued the view that the creativity of the product cannot reside
in its psychological origins, but only in its objective relation to prior
products. Although these two theses seem to me to be almost obvious,
those who still harbor the hope that creativity must be fundamentally
a property of people and their psychology, and hence something which
we can (at least in part) control, foster, and predict, will rightly demand
an argument. I shall, therefore, have to oblige them.
A first, and crucial, argument seems to me to be this: in attempting
to deal with creativity “scientifically,” psychologists are obliged to assume
that creativity has the status of a fact—that it exists purely naturalisti-
cally, in the way that gravity exists, or the moon exists. Only against
such a background does it make sense to talk of the creative personal-
ity, or of creative “psychological processes,” as objects of scientific
investigation. Now even if there do exist, as facts, certain psychological
processes and personality traits related to creativity, that these are creative
psychological processes or traits of the creative personality is not itself
a fact but an evaluation. That is, although we can study certain per-
sonality traits and certain psychological processes as facts, we cannot
identify these personality traits or psychological processes as creative ones
independently of our standards and values. The reason for this is
simple. As I mentioned at the start of this essay, to adjudge some per-
son, process, or product to be creative is to bestow upon it an honorific
title, to claim that it deserves to be highly prized, highly valued, for one
reason or another. The question then is: what do we evaluate, to what
do our standards apply, in the first instance? Do we initially evaluate
people, processes, or products as creative?
As far as I can see, all we have to go on, initially, is a person’s output
(linguistic, scientific, artistic, etc.). For example, would we know anything
of the musical “genius” of a Beethoven, or the scientific “creativity” of
an Einstein, if both had been totally paralyzed, deaf, dumb mutes unable
to externalize that genius in objective scientific or artistic products? Clearly
not. What if Ludwig van Beethoven had written only uninspiring pastiche,
or Einstein had never contributed more to science than a best selling
high school physics textbook? Would they still be the creative giants we
now consider them to be? Again, the answer, I think, is clearly not. In
other words, what we evaluate as creative, that to which our standards
apply in the first instance, are a person’s products. But since creative
psychological processes and traits of the creative personality do not exist
as facts per se, but only as the result of an evaluation, and since our
evaluation must, in the first instance, be applied to a person’s products,
it follows that we cannot identify, independently of such products,
creative persons or creative psychological processes. Moreover, psy-
chologists, insofar as they study such processes and personality traits as
facts per se, independently of all evaluations (that is, insofar as they
study them “scientifically”), simply are not studying creativity. In other
words, a purely “scientific” study of creativity, and a fortiori a purely
psychological (or even sociological) study of creativity, is impossible.21
It is, I think, important to be clear about the above argument. I do
not deny (but nor, for that matter, do I assert) that there may be certain
independently identifiable psychological processes or personality traits
21
Incidentally, a similar argument can be used to show that a purely scientific
psychology or sociology of knowledge is equally impossible. For ‘knowledge,’ like cre-
ativity, is a normative or evaluative notion, which applies, in the first instance, to the
outcomes or products of research and not to the psychological processes or sociological
conditions involved in research. Thus, we cannot identify as facts per se any sociological
conditions of knowledge. In other words, far from replacing epistemology, there cannot
even be a sociology or psychology of knowledge in the absence of epistemology. For
in the absence of epistemology (or ‘the criteriological science of knowledge,’ to adopt
Collingwood’s terminology) there simply is no knowledge, and so clearly no psychology
or sociology of it. Pace H. V. O. Quine, epistemology cannot be naturalized. For some
rather disastrous consequences of ignoring the evaluative aspect of knowledge, and
of blurring the fact/value distinction, see my “Toulmin’s Evolutionary Epistemology,”
Philosophical Quarterly 24 (1974): 60–69.
28 larry briskman
22
The Japanese painter, Yasuo Kuniyoshi, reports (in The Creative Process: A Symposium,
ed. B. Ghiselin [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1952], 55) that this was, in
creative product and creative process in science and art 29
fact, an artistic problem which he tried to solve. The idea that the artist confronts
objective problems is well known to any reader of Gombrich’s brilliant Art and Illusion
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1960). I should mention that in my view an
artist’s subjective desire to express some idea, emotion, or vision itself constitutes an
objective artistic problem—namely, the problem of how to express it given the means
at his disposal. Such a problem may only be soluble if the artist invents or discovers
new means, not previously at his disposal. We might call this, paraphrasing Lakatos,
a ‘creative problem-shift.’
23
Ben Shahn, “The Biography of a Painting,” in Creativity in the Arts, ed. V. Tomas, 32.
30 larry briskman
24
It might here be objected that the fact that creative people talk of ‘inspiration,’
‘Divine Grace,’ ‘sudden and unexpected ideas,’ ‘bisociation,’ and so on when describ-
ing their own creative work invalidates my argument. I do not agree—such sudden
flashes of ‘illumination’ are invariably preceded by the production of unsuccessful
efforts which themselves help to shape the very illumination in question. Moreover, it
might be said that examples such as Coleridge’s composing of “Kubla Kahn” refutes
my suggestion, in that it seems to have emerged full-blown from Coleridge’s head
without the benefit of any interaction with intermediary products. Again, I am not so
sure—at the very least Coleridge had to critically interact with his ‘finished’ product
before accepting it as finished, and this means that before this conscious acceptance the
product can be thought of as an intermediary one even though it may be identical
to the finished one!
creative product and creative process in science and art 31
cation for any process which we will deem to be creative. That is, until
we have answered the question, “What aspects of artistic and scientific
products lead us to evaluate them as creative ones?” we cannot answer
the question “What kind of process could possibly result in such pro-
ducts?” and so cannot answer our primary question “How is creativity
possible?” For creativity is only possible insofar as it is possible to pro-
duce creative products. In this section, then, I shall have to concentrate
on the former question, and attempt to outline some aspects of creative
products. Only afterwards will we be in a position to tackle our main
question head on.
One of the most striking—and in way, paradoxical—features of great
creative advances is how often they appear to be, with hindsight, almost
obvious. Einstein puts the point nicely: “In the light of knowledge
attained, the happy achievement seems almost a matter of course, and
any intelligent student can grasp it without too much trouble. But the
years of anxious searching in the dark, with their intense longing, their
alternation of confidence and exhaustion, and the final emergence into
the light—only those who have themselves experienced it can under-
stand that.”25
But if creative achievements often seem obvious, “a matter of course,”
in retrospect, why are they so difficult to achieve? The answer lies,
naturally enough, in Einstein’s telling phrase about “the years of anx-
ious searching in the dark.” That is, great creative advances tend to shed
light where none has been shed before; one thus cannot approach one’s
target clearly, because until one has actually reached it, one cannot say
precisely what it is (or even if it exists).26 Popper makes substantially
the same point when he compares the quest for new knowledge with
the situation of “a blind man who searches in a dark room for a black
hat which is—perhaps—not there.”27 Small wonder, then, that creative
25
Quoted in Banesh Hoffmann and Helen Dukas, Albert Einstein: Creator and Rebel
(New York: Viking, 1972), 124.
26
This fact about creativity calls to mind what could be called ‘Plato’s Paradox’:
namely, that one cannot search for something unless one knows what one is searching
for. But plausibly one cannot know what one is searching for until one has actually found
it. Hence, one cannot search for something until one has found it. In other words, one
cannot search for something! This argument is not simply a sophism, for it indicates
that one must either have some imprecise idea of what one is looking for, or else some
recognitional criteria for saying that one has found what one is looking for. The importance
of such recognitional criteria for creative activity will be discussed in Section VII.
27
Karl Popper, “Replies to my Critics,” in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. P. Schilpp
(LaSalle: Open Court, 1974), vol. 2, 1061.
32 larry briskman
28
Interestingly, the idea that a creative product is a novel problem-solution enables
us to explain how even old ideas may qualify as creative products. For the required
novelty is no longer sheer temporal novelty; rather it is the novelty of a solution rela-
tive to a problem. An old idea, invoked in a new problem-situation, could constitute
a novel solution. We might, for example, construe Dalton’s creativity in this light, for
Dalton recognized in the old physical ideas of the atomists the potential solution to a
pressing chemical problem (that of explaining the law of constant proportions) and thus
built his ‘new system of chemical philosophy’ upon an atomistic basis. In other words,
Dalton did not create the idea of atoms, but he used that idea creatively.
29
I owe this way of seeing the thing to Stanley Eveling.
34 larry briskman
the creative process involves not only a searching in the dark but also,
as Einstein put it, an “anxious searching in the dark.”
We are now almost in a position to complete our characterization
of the creative product. Only one important aspect remains—that of
evaluation. For a creative product must not only incorporate a novel
problem-solution conflicting with the tradition out of which it emerged,
it must also be an acceptable problem-solution. That is, it must be
evaluated favorably; it must meet certain standards or certain criteria
of acceptability. Such standards will, of course, differ for different
endeavors, and those applicable in science will quite reasonably diverge
from those applicable to art (although there are, I think, more simi-
larities here than are often imagined). Nevertheless, the point remains
that before a novel problem-solution can be given the honorific title
creative, it must be evaluated positively as meeting certain standards.
Moreover, these standards will normally themselves be incorporated
into the background of prior products, in the tradition, against which
the problem-solution has emerged.30 In other words, from the point of
view of the background itself, the creative product surpasses that back-
ground in a positively evaluated way, in a way meeting certain stringent
requirements or standards already inherent in that background.
To sum up this section: a creative scientific, or artistic, product has,
I suggest, the following characteristics. First, relative to the background
of prior products, it is a novel product. Second, it puts this novelty to
a desirable purpose by solving a problem, such problems being themselves
relative to this background and emerging from it. Third, it does so in
such a way as to actually conflict with parts of this background, to neces-
sitate its partial modification, and to supplant and improve upon parts
of it. Finally, this novel, conflicting, problem-solution must be favorably
evaluated; it must meet certain exacting standards which are themselves
part of the background it partially supplants. I shall call any product,
30
It might be thought that this entails that creative contributions to ‘methodology’
or ‘criteriology’ (i.e., the theory of rational standards) is impossible. This is a mistake:
a novel methodological idea which solves an outstanding problem in our current meth-
odological theories may actually constitute an improvement from the point of view
of the older standards themselves. This, in effect, is how the rational improvement of
rational standards is itself possible. Agassi has christened this view ‘the bootstrap theory
of rationality’ and suggests that of a series of criteria of rationality each can constitute
‘an improvement on its predecessor by its predecessor’s own lights.’ See Joseph Agassi,
“Criteria for Plausible Arguments,” Mind 83 (1974): 406–416. For further elaboration of,
and suggested modifications to, Agassi’s idea of bootstrap rationality, see my “Historicist
Relativism and Bootstrap Rationality,” The Monist 60 (1977): 509–539.
creative product and creative process in science and art 35
31
The notion of transcendence here developed is not an absolute one—it admits of
degrees. For differing products may meet the four demands to a greater or lesser extent;
or a product may meet only some of the demands and not others. For example, it
might meet demands 1, 2, and 4, yet fail to meet demand 3 (i.e., it fails to necessitate
any alterations in the background). Thus, from the point of view of this chapter, it is
perfectly sensible to talk of degrees of creativity as well. This seems to me to be a crucially
valuable result. In fact, I would say that any theory, which made creativity into an
‘all-or-nothing’ thing (as Koestler’s ‘bisociative’ theory seems to do) should, for that
very reason, be rejected.
36 larry briskman
32
One can, I think, go even further and prove that no such problem-solving algo-
rithm (call it F ) can exist. For F would map problems into solutions (i.e., Solution=F
[Problem]). But problems are themselves functions of the background of prior products
(i.e., Problem=f [Background]). Combining these two we get that Solution=F( f [Back-
ground]). But solutions often contradict this background. How can a function map an
x into something inconsistent with x? Only, I suspect, by being itself inconsistent. So
no consistent problem-solving algorithm of the type envisaged can exist and an incon-
sistent one would be of no use whatsoever, since out of it we could get anything as a
solution to anything!
creative product and creative process in science and art 37
33
E. Vivas, “Naturalism and Creativity,” in Creativity in the Arts, ed. V. Tomas, 90.
34
Banesh Hoffmann and Helen Dukas, 119.
38 larry briskman
reject aspects of what he has done so far on the basis of his knowledge
of the problem he is trying to solve and of the standards which his
solution must meet. In other words, we can say that the creator is under
the “plastic” or “soft” control of his job specification—of the problem,
and of the standards required of a solution.35
We are, I think, finally in a position to outline a plausible answer to
our question. Basically, the answer rests upon the Darwinian idea of
blind variation and selective retention. As should be obvious, Darwin-
ism manages to transcend the limits of a strict mechanism (by recogniz-
ing the fertility of blind variation) while avoiding an out-and-out
teleology (since these variations are selected rather than directed). This
appears to be exactly what we are looking for—namely, a process
combining “blindness” with “control.” In other words, I am suggesting
that we may plausibly view the creative process on a Darwinian model,
as a case of the blind generation of variants coupled with the selective
retention of “successful” variants, all under the plastic control of the
creative job specification.36
To elaborate: we want a process which allows for the production of
novelty but which is not random, for we want to be able to explain the
appropriateness of the creative product. Moreover, we want a process in
which the final product does not itself direct its very production—that
is, we want a process which is blind. However, we also need a process
in which the question of production has, in effect, been controlled
(plastically) by those very factors which will enable the product to be
a transcendent one—in other words, the process, cannot be too blind.
The only way to satisfy all of these desiderata at once, I suggest, is to
see the creator as (1) critically interacting with prior products, with a
tradition, so as to put himself “in touch” with problems and standards
for acceptable solutions; (2) generating blindly, but not randomly, a hope-
fully potential solution or fragments of such a solution—blindly, because
these are generated without foreknowledge of success; not randomly,
35
The notion of plastic control is due to Popper. The reason that the control of
problems and standards is only plastic or soft (as opposed to ‘cast-iron’) is that these
can themselves be modified by the very attempts to solve them or satisfy them.
36
The psychologist Donald Campbell has already suggested a Darwinian model of
the creative process in his paper, “Blind Variation and Selective Retention in Creative
Thought as in Other Knowledge Processes,” Psychological Review 67 (1960): 380–400.
Where my account differs from his, however, is in seeing this Darwinian process as
under the plastic control of the creative job specification. In a sense, from my point
of view, Campbell’s process is just a bit too blind.
creative product and creative process in science and art 39
because the generation is itself already under the plastic control of the
relevant problem, the background of prior products, and the relevant
standards; (3) critically interacting with this initial, fragmentary product
so as to select or reject it, either in part or in its entirety, such a selec-
tion procedure being again under the plastic control of the problem,
the background, and the relevant standards; (4) generating blindly, but
not randomly, further hopefully potential solutions or fragments, this
time under the plastic control not only of the initial problem, the
background, and the relevant standards, but also under the plastic
control of what he has already done, of his initial effort; (5) repeat step
(3) (that is, critical selection); (6) repeat step (4) (that is, blind, but not
random, generation); etc. until, hopefully, one has managed to generate
or assemble a product which either meets the initial job specification
or else meets some improved job specification—this improved job
specification being itself the outcome of the above process.
It is essential to recognize that if the above schema is to work, the
control which the problem, the relevant standards, and especially the
background of prior products (the background “knowledge,” so to
speak) exercise over the creator must be a plastic control, not a “cast-
iron” one. For the problem, standards, or background knowledge may
themselves have to be modified during the very process itself. This
becomes particularly clear if we remember that often the way to a
solution to a problem is actually blocked by some of the background
knowledge, even though the problem owes its very existence to this
background knowledge. In this event, the creator will not be able to
solve his problem unless he generates a potential solution that actually
conflicts with this background knowledge; and this helps to explain why
our third requirement on transcendent products sometimes must be
fulfilled, if some of the other requirements are also to be fulfilled.
Naturally, however, since the above process is blind—that is, since there
is no foreknowledge of a solution—the creator cannot know (in advance)
that his way will be blocked by a particular aspect of the background.
But he might, through constant frustration, come to suspect that it is
being so blocked, and thus loosen the control that he will allow this
background to have over him; that is, he may be driven into becoming
a potential revolutionary! Equally, however, his frustration might lead
him to suspect that the very problem itself, which he is trying to solve,
is in need of radical reformulation, and in this case he will loosen the
control which his initial formulation has exercised over his generation
and selection of variants. Clearly, if the control of either the background
40 larry briskman
I have been arguing that creative products are what I have termed
transcendent products—that they transcend the tradition out of which
they spring. I have also been arguing that neither mechanism, nor pure
randomness, nor teleology will ever be able to satisfactorily account for
the emergence of such products, and so explain how creativity is pos-
sible. Rather, I have suggested, we must seek the explanation in a
Darwinian process of variation and selection, which is itself under the
plastic control, not of the yet-to-be realized transcendent product, but
of the already realized idea of such products. But I cannot conclude
without a brief mention of what I see to be the implications of all this
for the creator himself; for the person who is, after all, ultimately
responsible for the creative achievement he has produced.
It is well to remember that creative scientists and artists are as much
the inheritors of tradition as they is the transcenders of tradition. In
a sense, the scientist or artist is personally as much the product of a
creative product and creative process in science and art 41
37
Reported in Popper’s Objective Knowledge, 180. The idea of self-transcendence has
been beautifully explored in Gombrich’s paper, “Art and Self-Transcendence,” in The
Palace of Value in a World of Facts, eds. A. Tiselius and S. Nilsson (New York: Wiley
Interscience Division, 1970) 125–133.
CHAPTER THREE
I. C. Jarvie
I Introduction
My title links two abstract nouns that are usually set over against each
other, seen as contrasting, if not in opposition. The view that informs
this paper is that what can usefully be said about creativity is very
little, and rather trite; and that it is co-extensive with the rational ele-
ment in creativity. There may or may not be other than rational ele-
ments in creativity; confronted with them, my inclination would be for
the first time to invoke Wittgenstein: “whereof one cannot speak, thereof
one should be silent.” The little I think can be said about the rational-
ity of creativity will be confined to section five. The preceding sections
will offer a general critique of the literature, bringing out its poverty
and its irrationality.
Much of the growing literature on creativity,2 it seems to me, bypasses
several quite decisive arguments. Properly understood, these arguments
vitiate much of the debate in that literature. These arguments are the
following: the problem to be solved by studying creativity is not clearly
specified; creativity is treated as a psychological rather than a logical
issue; that to explain creativity is to explain it away; and, when we
create an explanation that explains creativity, it also, paradoxically, must
explain itself. To each of these arguments I shall devote a section.
1
Reprinted from The Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. D. Dutton and
M. Krausz (The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1981), 109–128,
all rights reserved.
2
See J. P. Guilford, “Creativity,” American Psychologist 5 (1950): 444–454; Arthur
Koestler, The Act of Creation (London: Hutchinson, 1964); P. E. Vernon, Creativity (Har-
mondsworth: Penguin, 1970); J. W. Getzels and P. W. Jackson, Creativity and Intelligence
(New York: Wiley, 1962); Anthony Storr, The Dynamics of Creation (New York: Atheneum,
1972); Journal of Creative Behaviour (1967).
44 i. c. jarvie
3
J. P. Guilford, “Creativity.”
the rationality of creativity 45
then, neither output nor urgency constitutes a good reason for investi-
gation. We need a third answer to the question ‘why research into
creativity at all,’ an answer that is not pragmatic, and that takes account
of works of art as well as cognition and technology. My suggestion
would be: the simple desire to explain the creative achievement, to
understand it better, to get at the truth about it. At the moment, cre-
ativity is in the virtus dormativa phase: ‘creativity’ is a property ascribed
to certain artistic and intellectual achievements by certain creators who
are said to possess the capacity to ‘create,’ as evidenced by the creativ-
ity of their work.
This is a parlous state of affairs indeed—provided only that an
explanation of creativity is possible (my skepticism on this score will
emerge presently). What, exactly, is in need of explanation; what is the
problem? What fact or facts clash with what beliefs, theories, or expec-
tations in the matter of creativity? I confess to not being sure. The
obvious explanation of such uncertainty is that different writers have
different problems, as we have already noted. There is, however, the
possibility that the problems are connected, and hence can be set out
in an orderly way. My suggestion for the status of most fundamental
problem of all, from which the others branch off, is this. Creative
achievements are unique events; explanatory progress is made only
with repeatable events. Hence there is something inexplicable about
creativity. Or, rather, to all new, interesting, novel, ingenious, pleasing,
inventive, gifted: and other cognitive, technological: and artistic acts
there is attributed a common property, something they all exemplify,
something that can thus be studied and explained: this is called creativ-
ity. Thus the inaccessible uniqueness of creation is made to yield to
the belief that nothing is mysterious, remote, inexplicable.
This fundamental problem is, I believe, absorbed during our elemen-
tary education. We are taught that artistic, cognitive, and technical
achievements are unique events, miracles, strokes of luck (or genius)
which we should mainly be concerned to welcome and study.4 This
fundamental epistemological pessimism seems to foreclose the problem:
creativity just is an inexplicable ‘gift.’ Our rationality is signaled to
the extent that we accept and make the best of this situation. That
same education, however, also indicates an epistemological optimism:
4
In the same way that chess masters record and study the grand masters and their
great games. No one seems to be trying to find out what makes a great game great
and thus deprive it of its mystique. Cf. Section III, below.
the rationality of creativity 47
5
Storr, The Dynamics of Creation, 61ff. Jean Cocteau somewhere compares being
creative to being pregnant. Salvador Dali expresses similar ideas in The Secret Life of
Salvador Dali (New York: Dial Press, 1961), as does the brilliant and tormented Brit-
ish painter Francis Bacon. See David Sylvester, Interviews With Francis Bacon (London:
Thames and Hudson, 1975).
48 i. c. jarvie
6
When I was first introduced to Rembrandt’s painting known as The Night Watch,
it was remarked that its bold, active, almost chiaroscuro style had shocked those who
commissioned it, and Rembrandt’s intransigent artistic temperament on this point
contributed to his financial downfall. The idea was that crass patrons always failed to
understand geniuses, who had to be tough to maintain their integrity. Later, I noticed
this story was declared a legend by contemporary historians, who claim that the picture
was always hung, that Rembrandt’s commissions did not dry up, and who attribute his
downfall to expensive living (especially the house). The theory that all creative artists
are misunderstood by hoi polloi is a widespread and pernicious one, since it can be
used to rebut all criticism, and even self-criticism and doubt.
the rationality of creativity 49
7
See J. Agassi, “The Function of Intellectual Rubbish,” Research in the Sociology of
Knowledge, Science, and Art 2 (1979): 209–227.
8
Charles Chaplin, My Autobiography (London: The Bodley Head, 1964; Penguin
ed., 1966), 154. Chaplin was amazed when Mack Sennett said to him, “We have no
scenario. We get an idea, then follow the natural sequence of events.” So different from
what he describes as the “rigid, non-deviating routine” of the theatre.
50 i. c. jarvie
Ibid., 175–179.
9
10
The most evocative account of Hollywood in the thirties and forties is by Charles
Higham and Joel Greenberg, Hollywood in the Forties (London: A. Zwemmer, 1968). The
the rationality of creativity 51
We can see then that there is some pattern to periods of great cre-
ativity. We cannot reproduce them at will. The fundamental strength
of public demand for movies cannot be recovered, especially since the
arrival of television. Hence, there have been long periods in which
filmmakers have been offered anything but encouragement and certainly
nothing like freedom. Recently a new phenomenon has appeared:
desperate experimentation in the face of bankruptcy. Several of the
major American movie companies have gone from success to collapse
in the last six or seven years. For a time, there were unrivalled oppor-
tunities for innovation and experiment. But that has passed, and a
pervading sense of insecurity co-exists with the most profitable year
since 1946.11
In this section, I have argued that the first weakness in studies of
creativity is poorly articulated aims. When the aims are articulated it
seldom looks as though any of them could sustain the kinds of explora-
tions of creativity that have been undertaken—practical or theoretical.
only book I know which attempts seriously to discuss the creative process in movies
without reference to individual genius, but rather to collective endeavor, is Lawrence
Alloway, Violent America: The Movies 1946–1964 (New York: Museum of Modern Art,
distributed by the New York Graphic Society, Greenwich, Conn., 1971).
11
See Pauline Kael, “On the Future of the Movies,” New Yorker (5 August 1974):
43–59.
52 i. c. jarvie
12
See J. Agassi, “The Role of Corroboration in Popper’s Methodology,” Australasian
Journal of Philosophy 39 (1961): 82–91; J. Agassi and I. C. Jarvie, “The Problem of the
Rationality of Magic,” British Journal of Sociology 18 (1967): 55–74.
the rationality of creativity 53
13
What I have in mind is Gombrich’s notion of art as “making and matching.” See
E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illusion (London: Phaidon Press, 1960).
14
Einstein is quoted to this effect in K. R. Popper, Objective Knowledge (Oxford: The
Clarendon Press, 1972), 225n.
54 i. c. jarvie
If we divert the entire budget of the U.S. Pentagon into research into
the causes of cancer, say, we can no more guarantee success (however
that is defined) than we can assure the gambler that his number will
come up (it will, but he could be dead before it does). No doubt, in
time, scientific research on this scale would yield the bureaucracy, jobs,
and contracting industry that the military budget does: and there are
unattractive as well as attractive aspects to there being so many men and
women in white coats. It is unlikely such expenditure and such waste
would ever be agreed to because, while the military has a task at which
it is very rarely tested, cancer research is tested every time a patient dies.
So much, then, for the question of what problems are being tackled
in the literature on creativity. Not only are these problems not often
formulated, formulating them inclines one to the conclusion that they
cannot be solved: not simply because they are difficult or intractable
but, much more seriously, because they reveal muddles that may vitiate
the enterprise. Creativity may not give rise to clear problems because
on no known theory is it presupposed as a definite property of the
physical world or the world of mind. To avoid concluding it is chime-
rical we shall have to seek it elsewhere.
15
I. C. Jarvie, “The Objectivity of Criticism of the Arts,” Ratio 9 (1967): 67–83.
Tovey comments that Bach’s art was neglected “as old-fashioned and crabbed” by his
younger contemporaries. We owe his rediscovery to Mendelssohn and Schumann. (See
“Bach, J. S.” in Encyclopedia Britannica, 11th ed.).
the rationality of creativity 55
With cognition, the question becomes more involved. For one thing,
there is a popular prejudice in favor of positive science being called
creative at the expense of negative science. Positive and negative are
connected with the simpleminded distinction between, say, a theory
(positive) and its criticism (negative). Sometimes, lord help us, a distinc-
tion is made between negative and constructive criticism. Hence,
Copernicus is creative for inventing heliocentrism, but the many critics
of Ptolemy are not even well-known. Along these lines one might as
well say Plato was creative and Aristotle was not: but this shows up the
absurdity. Aristotle created beautiful arguments against Plato which
were enormous creative achievements in themselves. Isaac Newton was
a creative genius, but so too was Berkeley, who picked holes in Newton’s
mathematics and metaphysics.
All this discussion is in the logical realm. Solving a problem is creative;
devising a criticism of a theory is creative. Creativeness cannot be
unpacked in any precise way, and indeed I have hinted earlier that it may
be a dispensable term. What I want to emphasize here is the different
point that whether or not an idea or a criticism is a creative one has
nothing to do with psychology, with whether an act of creation, inspira-
tion, or bisociation has occurred. Indeed, the extensive discussion of humor
by both Koestler and Freud demonstrates this. So far as this paper is
concerned, there is nothing creative about jokes. I find the expressions,
‘what a creative joke,’ or, ‘he’s a really creative comedian,’ very odd.
Odder, is the attention given to humor by those interested in creativity.
If there is rationality in creativity it is of course going to be located
in the public, objective, logical realm, and not in the psychological one.
Hence the importance of this distinction and the fact that it plays
haywire with the literature on creativity. On this view, creativity is a
cognate of ‘simple,’ ‘powerful,’ ‘unifying,’ ‘exciting,’ ‘trail-blazing,’ and
other sorts of adjectives that might be attached to new theories, new
criticisms, or new works of art. The rationality of creativity then con-
sists of it being successful action directed at solving an artistic or cog-
nitive problem. Calling something a ‘creative failure,’ might simply
indicate ingenuity. Degrees of creativity are also sometimes alluded to,
but I see no way of explicating these in any discussible manner.
Perhaps the notion of creativity, then, is that of a socially defined
event in the world of ideas or art, what Popper has called the world
of objective mind, or mind objectified, the third world or World 3.16
16
K. R. Popper, Objective Knowledge, chap. 3, 4.
56 i. c. jarvie
V To Explain Away
17
This may explain my total opposition (not to modern art but) to modernism in
art, the philosophy that traditions must be broken with. How someone trained as, or
pretending to be, an artist can even think of this is something of a mystery; it is a bit
like an English speaker deciding to utter only gibberish.
the rationality of creativity 57
VI Self-Reference
18
Albert Einstein, “Isaac Newton,” in his Out of My Later Years (New York: Philo-
sophical Library, 1950), 219–223, quote from 220.
58 i. c. jarvie
19
See I. C. Jarvie, Towards a Sociology of the Cinema (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1970), chap. 1–3.
20
In Bertrand Russell, Portraits from Memory (London: George Allen and Unwin,
1956), 194–197. Storr, The Dynamics of Creation, 42–43 attributes a similar idea to
Graham Wallas.
21
To show that Russell’s cool detachment has nothing to do with his endeavors being
logical and cognitive, one could cite the superb American painter Edward Hooper,
the rationality of creativity 59
who not only creates by “painting, scraping off, and repainting,” but also is dominated
by the objective logic of creation: “I find, in working, always the distracting intrusion
of elements not part of my most interested vision, and the inevitable obliteration and
replacement of this vision by the work itself as it proceeds. The struggle to prevent this
decay is, I think, the common lot of all painters to whom the invention of arbitrary
forms has lesser interest. I believe that the great painters, with their intellect as master
have attempted to force this unwitting medium of paint and canvas into a record of
their emotions. I find any disgression from this large aim leads me to boredom.” (Quoted
in Lloyd Goodrich, Edward Hoppper [New York: H. N. Abrams, 1971], 161.).
22
See the account in Erich Hertzmann, “Mozart’s Creative Process,” in The Creative
World of Mozart, ed. Paul Henry Lang (New York: W. W. Norton, 1963), 17–30.
23
Bertrand Russell, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, 1872–1914 (London: George
Allen and Unwin, 1967), 152–153.
60 i. c. jarvie
did not detract from Eliot’s stature as a creative innovator.24 The short
answer to that, I suppose, is that Eliot could have restored any cuts
Pound made had it been his judgment that they did not serve to solve
the poetic problem with which he was grappling. Furthermore, many
artists and intellectuals show their work to friends, wives, children,
professional peers, editors, publishers and the like long before it sees
the light of day. Academe has a tradition of acknowledging such help.
Because that tradition is not general does not at all imply the practice
is not.
It is not hard, then, to see the process of trial and error not only at
work, but consciously employed, in cognition and the individual arts.
A fortiori it is not going to be difficult to detect it in collective arts,
whether architecture or the cinema. Filmmaking not only employs trial
and error, but, to the extent possible, institutionalizes—even bureau-
cratizes—it. This is not necessarily all to the good, as, obviously, exces-
sive trial is a form of caution. Once Russell knew that earlier works he
had written contained mistakes, or did not sell, he might have been
justified in publishing nothing. Capable of error and yet wanting to
avoid it, the cautious policy is to do nothing.25 Capable of failure, yet
desperately trying to avoid it, cautious movie producers compromise—
that is to say, they interpret trial results too soon and too harshly. This
permeates the creative process in movies, which is an institutionalized
clash between art and commerce, each side with its own problems, its
own integrity, its own series of trials and errors to be avoided. Money
being the necessary, but by no means sufficient, condition of there ever
being any films made at all, commerce holds a powerful position. The
subtlety is not that the bureaucratic organization is split between com-
mercial people and creative people, but that commerce and creation
coexist in most film people. Hence, a script may be written and rewrit-
ten until it has shape and coherence; it then may be rewritten some
more to improve its commercial possibilities. The same will apply to
casting, to decisions on sets, costumes and locations, to editing the
picture, to the manner in which it is publicized. The writer, the direc-
24
T. S. Eliot, The Waste Land, a facsimile and transcript of the original drafts includ-
ing the annotations of Ezra Pound, ed. Valerie Eliot (New York: Harcourt, Brace,
Jovanovich, 1971).
25
In the movies, this becomes interesting in the political dimension. From time
to time Russia and China made it so difficult to avoid ideological error (because of
unpredictable shifts in the party line) that filmmaking shrank almost to zero.
the rationality of creativity 61
tor, the actor, the cameraman, the set designer, and the editor are all
simultaneously in search of a solution to their creative problems which
is also commercially viable. Some trials are creative (does that scene
cut well?), some commercial (does the preview audience like it?), many
are a mixture of both. For sure, the box office is neither physical nor
psychological; I suggest that the creative side similarly is a sort of objec-
tive matter.
In film, as in the other arts, but less so in philosophy and still less so
in science, there is a tedious avant-garde with a romantic view of cre-
ativity as mainly consisting in not interrupting while the Muse speaks
through the favored individual. Life is easier that way. Being rational
and self-critical is very hard and sometimes impossible. It is neverthe-
less the key to anything deserving the label creativity.
CHAPTER FOUR
I Introduction
1
Charles Darwin, On the Origin of the Species by Means of Natural Selection: Or, The
Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (London: J. Murray, 1859).
64 dean keith simonton
2
Dean Keith Simonton, “Creativity: Cognitive, Developmental, Personal, and Social
Aspects,” American Psychologist 55 (2000): 151–158.
3
William James, “Great Men, Great Thoughts, and the Environment,” Atlantic
Monthly 46 (1880): 441–459; quote from 448.
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 65
4
Ibid., 456.
5
Dean Keith Simonton, Origins of Genius: Darwinian Perspectives on Creativity (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1999).
6
Donal T. Campbell, “Blind Variation and Selective Retention in Creative Thought
as in other Knowledge Processes,” Psychological Review 67 (1960): 380–400.
7
Gary A. Cziko, “From Blind to Creative: In Defense of Donald Campbell’s Selec-
tionist Theory of Human Creativity.” Journal of Creative Behavior 32 (1998): 192–208.
66 dean keith simonton
8
Alexander Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, 3rd ed. (New York: Appleton, 1874); Paul
Souriau, Theorie de l’invention (Paris: Hachette, 1881); Ernst Mach, “On the Part Played
by Accident in Invention and Discovery,”Monist 6 (1896): 161–175; Henri Poincaré, The
Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, the Value of Science, Science and Method, trans.
George B. Halstead (New York: Science Press, 1921).
9
Jacques Hadamard, The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field (Princeton,
N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1945).
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 67
10
Donald T. Campbell, “Variation and Selective Retention in Socio-Cultural Evolu-
tion,” in Social Change in Developing Areas, eds. Herbert R. Barringer, George I. Blanksten,
and Raymond W. Mack (Cambridge, Mass.: Schenkman, 1965), 19–49; “Evolutionary
Epistemology,” in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. Paul A. Schlipp (La Salle, Ill.: Open
Court, 1974), 413–463.
11
Colin Martindale, The Clockwork Muse: The Predictability ofArtistic Styles (New York:
Basic Books, 1990); Barry M. Staw, “An Evolutionary Approach to Creativity and
Innovations,” in Innovation and Creativity at Work: Psychological and Organizational Strategies,
eds. Michael A. West and James L. Farr (New York: Wiley, 1990), 287–308; Aharon
Kantorovich, Scientific Discovery: Logic and Tinkering (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1993); Aharon Kantorovich and Yuval Ne’eman, “Serendipity as a Source
of Evolutionary Progress in Science,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 20 (1989):
505–529.
12
Dean Keith Simonton, Scientific Genius: A Psychology of Science (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press. 1988); “The Chance-Configuration Theory of Scientific
Creativity,” in The Psychology of Science: Contributions to Metascience, eds. Barry Gholson,
William R. Shadish, Jr., Robert A. Neimeyer, and Arthur C. Houts (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1989), 170–213.
13
Dean Keith Simonton, “Donald Campbell’s Model of the Creative Process: Cre-
ativity as Blind Variation and Selective Retention,” Journal of Creative Behavior 32 (1998):
153–158; “Creativity as Blind Variation and Selective Retention: Is the Creative Process
Darwinian?” Psychological Inquiry 10 (1999): 309–328; Origins of Genius.
68 dean keith simonton
A. Creative Process
Cognitive psychologists tend to view creativity as a special form of
problem solving.14 Although not all problems require creativity, acts of
creativity usually entail the solution of some given problem. Problem-
solving behavior can be ordered along a continuous dimension that
represents the amount of genuine creativity involved. At one extreme
are problems that require no creativity at all. Such problems can be
solved using well-defined ‘strong methods,’ such as algorithms.15 Arith-
metic and algebra problems are generally of this nature. With very
minor exceptions (for example, the introduction of trial values), these
problems cannot be said to require any form of BVSR process.
However, as problems become more novel and complex, with ill-
defined goals and indefinite means to attain those goals, some kind of
BVSR procedure becomes increasingly necessary. Domain-specific
strong methods must be replaced with more general ‘weak methods,’
such has problem-solving heuristics that cannot guarantee a solution.16
Besides some amount of blindness being involved in the application of
these heuristics—because we cannot always know in advance which
heuristic is optimal—one of the most commonplace heuristics is explic-
itly BVSR in operation, namely trial and error. In short, to the extent
that the problem requires a high degree of creativity, the more the
process must become Darwinian.17
Evidence for this conclusion comes from four sources: labora-
tory experiments, computer simulations, introspective reports, and
archival data.
Laboratory Experiments. Most empirical research on creative problem
solving uses laboratory experiments. This literature has amply docu-
mented the various processes that can contribute to the generation of
ideational variations that are to some degree blind.18 For instance,
experiments have indicated how the incubation period preceding a
14
Allan Newell and Herbert A. Simon, Human Problem Solving (Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1972).
15
David Klahr, Exploring Science: The Cognition and Development of Discovery Processes
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2000).
16
Klahr, Exploring Science.
17
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
18
Dean Keith Simonton, “Scientific Creativity as Constrained Stochastic Behavior:
The Integration of Product, Process, and Person Perspectives,” Psychological Bulletin 129
(2003): 475–494; Creativity in Science: Chance, Logic, Genius, and Zeitgeist (Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, 2004).
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 69
19
Colleen M. Seifert, David E. Meyer, Natalie Davidson, Andrea L. Patalano, and
Ilan Yaniv, “Demystification of Cognitive Insight: Opportunistic Assimilation and the
Prepared-Mind Perspective,” in The Nature of Insight, eds. Robert J. Sternberg and Jan-
net E. Davidson (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), 65–124.
20
Ron A. Finke, Thomas B. Ward, and Steve M. Smith, Creative Cognition: Theory,
Research, Applications (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992); R. A. Proctor, “Computer
Stimulated Associations,” Creativity Research Journal 6 (1993): 391–400; Albert Rothenberg,
Artistic Creation as Stimulated by Superimposed Versus Combined-Composite Visual
Images,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 50 (1986): 370–381; Robert S. Sobel
and Rothenberg, “Artistic Creation as Stimulated by Superimposed Versus Separated
Visual Images,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39 (1980): 953–961; Wendy
W. N. Wan and Chi-Yue Chiu, “Effects of Novel Conceptual Combination on Creativ-
ity,” Journal of Creative Behavior 36 (2000): 227–240.
21
Margaret A. Boden, The Creative Mind: Myths & Mechanisms (New York: Basic
Books, 1991).
22
John R. Koza, Genetic Programming: On the Programming of Computers by Means of Natural
Selection (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992); Genetic Programming II: Automatic Discovery
of Reusable Programs (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994); Koza, Forrest H. Bennett III,
David Andre, and Martin A. Keane, Genetic Programming III: Darwinian Invention and
Problem Solving (San Francisco, Calif.: Morgan Kaufmann, 1999).
23
Colin Martindale, “Creativity and Connectionism,” in The Creative Cognition
Approach, eds. Steve M. Smith, Thomas B. Ward, and Ron A. Finke (Cambridge Mass.:
MIT Press, 1995), 249–268.
70 dean keith simonton
24
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
25
Hermann von Helmholtz, “An Autobiographical Sketch,” in Popular Lectures on
Scientific Subjects, Second Series, trans. Edmund Atkinson (New York: Longmans, Green,
1898, orig. 1891), 266–291, quote from 282.
26
David N. Perkins, The Mind’s Best Work (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1981).
27
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 71
28
Rudolf Arnheim, Picasso’s Guernica: The Genesis of a Painting (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1962).
29
Dean Keith Simonton, “The Creative Process in Picasso’s Guernica: Monotonic
Improvements or Nonmonotonic Variants?” Creativity Research Journal (forthcoming).
30
Howard E. Gruber, Darwin on Man: A Psychological Study of Scientific Creativity (New
York: Dutton, 1974).
31
Simonton, Creativity in Science.
32
Howard E. Gruber, “Networks of Enterprise in Creative Scientific Work,” in The
Psychology of Science: Contributions to Metascience, eds. Barry Gholson, William R. Shad-
ish, Jr., Robert A. Neimeyer, and Arthur C. Houts (Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge
University Press, 1989), 246–265.
33
Dean Keith Simonton, Creativity in Science.
34
Poincaré, The Foundations of Science, 388.
72 dean keith simonton
Poincaré could not solve one problem without first solving another
problem that was seemingly unrelated to the earlier one.
B. Creative Personality
Researchers have made major headway in identifying the intellectual
and personality traits that correlate with individual differences in cre-
ativity.35 From our perspective, the most significant finding is that many
of these correlates involve traits that should facilitate engagement in
the hypothesized BVSR process.36 For instance, creativity is positively
correlated with the capacity to generate remote or unusual associations
and to generate a diversity of responses to a given stimulus.37 This
capacity would clearly augment the span of activation produced by
any set of stimuli.38 Creativity is also correlated with openness to expe-
rience, including wide interests and a sensitivity to new ideas.39 Con-
sequently, highly creative individuals are open systems subjected to a
variety of stimuli, thereby increasing the range of primed associations,
some of which lead to serendipitous connections between hitherto
unrelated ideas.
But perhaps the most telling correlate has to do with a person’s abil-
ity to filter out extraneous information. This ability is negatively asso-
ciated with both openness40 and creativity.41 Creative individuals are
35
Gregory J. Feist, “A Meta-Analysis of Personality in Scientific and Artistic Creativ-
ity,” Personality and Social Psychology Review 2 (1998): 290–309.
36
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
37
Harrison G. Gough, “Studying Creativity by Means of Word Association Tests,”
Journal of Applied Psychology 61 (1976): 348–353; J. P. Guilford, The Nature of Intelligence
(New York: McGraw-Hill); Sarnoff A. Mednick, “The Associative Basis of the Creative
Process,” Psychological Review 69 (1962): 220–232.
38
Martindale, “Creativity and Connectionism.”
39
Julie A. Harris, “Measured Intelligence, Achievement, Openness to Experience, and
Creativity,” Personality and Individual Differences 36 (2004): 913–929; Robert R. McCrae,
“Creativity, Divergent Thinking, and Openness to Experience,” Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology 52 (1987): 1258–1265.
40
Jordan B. Peterson and Shelley H. Carson, “Latent Inhibition and Openness to
Experience in a High-Achieving Student Population,” Personality and Individual Differ-
ences 28 (2000): 323–332; Peterson, Kathleen W. Smith, and Carson, “Openness and
Extraversion Are Associated with Reduced Latent Inhibition: Replication and Com-
mentary,” Personality and Individual Differences 33 (2002): 1137–1147.
41
Shelley H. Carson, Jordan B. Peterson, and Daniel M. Higgins, “Decreased
Latent Inhibition Is Associated with Increased Creative Achievement in High-Func-
tioning Individuals,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 85 (2003): 499–506; Hans
J. Eysenck, Genius: The Natural History of Creativity (Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press, 1995).
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 73
42
Ernst Mach, “On the Part Played by Accident in Invention and Discovery,” Monist
6 (1896): 161–175.
43
Hans J. Eysenck, “Creativity and Personality: Suggestions for a Theory,” Psycho-
logical Inquiry 4 (1993): 147–178; Genius.
44
Hans J. Eysenck, “Creativity and Personality: Word Association, Origence, and
Psychoticism,” Creativity Research Journal 7 (1994): 209–216.
45
Frank X. Barron, Creativity and Psychological Health: Origins of Personal Vitality and
Creative Freedom (Princeton, N.J.: Van Nostrand, 1963); Carson, Peterson, and Higgins,
“Decreased Latent Inhibition Is Associated with Increased Creative Achievement in
High-Functioning Individuals”; Eysenck, Genius.
46
Simonton, Origins of Genius; Creativity in Science.
74 dean keith simonton
DISPOSITION
more constrained, predictable, ← Cognitive processes → more unconstrained,
logical, conscious, deliberate, unpredictable, illogical,
simple, non-versatile intuitive, involuntary,
complex, versatile
more restricted, focused atten- ← Openness to experience → more unrestricted, defocused
tion, fewer interests, serendip- attention, many diverse inter-
ity rare ests, serendipity common
lower incidence rate, less severe ← Psychopathology → higher incidence rate, more
symptoms severe symptoms
DEVELOPMENT
more conventional, stable, ← Home environment → more unconventional, unstable,
homogeneous heterogeneous
more likely firstborn ← Birth order → more likely later born
superior grades, more ← Education and training → inferior grades, less formal
formal training, less training, more likely
likely marginal marginal
fewer, more homogeneous ← Mentors and role models → more numerous,
heterogeneous
more politically stable, ← Sociocultural Zeitgeist → more politically unstable,
culturally uniform culturally diverse
Figure 1. Domains of creativity are distinguished according to the extent to
which they involve the participation of blind-variation and selective-retention
processes. Placement along this dimension then determines the expected
dispositional traits and developmental experiences for creators active within
a given domain. Adapted from Dean Keith Simonton, Creativity in Science:
Chance, Logic, Genius, and Zeitgeist (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University
Press, 2004).
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 75
C. Creative Development
Research on this topic concentrates on two distinct phases of the life
span. In the first phase, the individual acquires the internal capacity
for creativity, whereas in the second the individual actualizes this capac-
ity into external products.
47
Arnold M. Ludwig, “Method and Madness in the Arts and Sciences,” Creativity
Research Journal 11 (1998): 93–101; Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, trans. Francis
Golffing (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1956; orig. 1872).
48
Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1970).
49
Dean Keith Simonton, “Psychology’s Status as a Scientific Discipline: Its Empirical
Placement within an Implicit Hierarchy of the Sciences,” Review of General Psychology
8 (2004): 59–67.
50
Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
51
Simonton, Creativity in Science.
52
Ibid.
53
Arnold M. Ludwig, The Price of Greatness: Resolving the Creativity and Madness Controversy
(New York: Guilford Press, 1995).
76 dean keith simonton
54
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
55
E.g., Kay R. Jamison, Touched with Fire: Manic-Depressive Illness and the Artistic Tem-
perament (New York: Free Press, 1993); J. I. Karlson, “Genetic Association of Giftedness
and Creativity with Schizophrenia,” Hereditas 66 (1970): 177–182.
56
Simonton, Origins of Genius; Creativity in Science.
57
Simonton, Creativity in Science.
58
Frank J. Sulloway, Born to Rebel: Birth Order, Family Dynamics, and Creative Lives (New
York: Pantheon, 1996).
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 77
IV Discussion
59
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
60
Simonton, Creativity in Science.
61
Subrata Dasgupta, “Is Creativity a Darwinian Process?” Creativity Research Journal 16
(2004): 403–413; Liane Gabora, “Creative Thought as a Non-Darwinian Evolutionary
Process,” Journal of Creative Behavior 39 (2005): 262–283; David N. Perkins, “Creativity:
78 dean keith simonton
66
Liane Gabora, “Creative Thought as a Non-Darwinian Evolutionary Process”;
“Why the Creative Process is Not Darwinian,” Creativity Research Journal (forthcoming).
67
Campbell “Blind Variation and Selective Retention in Creative Thought as in
Other Knowledge Processes.”
68
E.g., Gerald M. Edelman, Neural Darwinism: The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection
(New York: Basic Books, 1987); Thomas Söderqvist, “Darwinian Overtones: Niels
K. Jerne and the Origin of the Selection Theory of Antibody Formation,” Journal of
the History of Biology 27 (1994): 481–529.
69
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
70
Dean Keith Simonton, “Human Creativity: Two Darwinian Analyses,” in Animal
Innovation, eds. Simon M. Reader and Kevin N. Laland (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2003), 309–325.
80 dean keith simonton
but this need not be the only one. A classic example is Social Darwin-
ism, a theory predicated on Darwin’s concept of the struggle for exis-
tence—the title of Origin’s Chapter 3—and its involvement in weeding
out ‘inferior’ social groups. Briefly put, to say that something is Darwin-
ian means merely to claim that it has some characteristics analogous
to those witnessed in Darwin’s theory. To claim an analogy is not tan-
tamount to asserting an identity. It is perhaps for this reason that
scholars with established Darwinian credentials have not objected to
the application of this term to the phenomenon of human creativity.71
The analogical nature of the term is an asset insofar as it provides
a useful guide to theoretical and empirical research. On that score, I
maintain that a Darwinian theory of creativity has performed quite
well. Besides offering an integrative framework for coordinating all of
the diverse findings regarding the creative process, the creative person-
ality, and creative development, it has led to specific theoretical models
and empirical inquiries that otherwise would not have been pursued.72
For instance, the BVSR process provided the foundation for a combi-
natorial model that yields precise predictions regarding individual dif-
ferences and longitudinal changes in creative output.73 That model has
also led to quantitative predictions regarding certain primary attributes
of the multiples phenomenon, that is, the occasion when a given dis-
covery or invention is made by independent scientists.74 Furthermore,
the testing of Darwinian-inspired models has produced new and impor-
tant empirical results that would not have appeared otherwise. An
instance is the study of Picasso’s Guernica sketches mentioned earlier in
this chapter.75
Even so, it must be acknowledged that the term Darwinian can be
a liability as well as an asset. For some critics, it is an emotionally-
charged word associated with sociobiology and evolutionary psychology,
two intellectual movements that are sometimes seen as more political
and even religious rather than strictly scientific.76 One could, therefore,
argue that it might be better to find a more neutral word to designate
71
Michael Ruse, “Review of Origins of Genius: Darwinian Perspectives on Creativity by
Dean Keith Simonton,” Isis 92 (2001): 587–589.
72
Simonton, Origins of Genius.
73
Dean Keith Simonton, “Creative Productivity: A Predictive and Explanatory Model
of Career Trajectories and Landmarks,” Psychological Review 104 (1997): 66–89.
74
Simonton, “Psychology’s Status as a Scientific Discipline.”
75
Simonton, “The Creative Process in Picasso’s Guernica.”
76
Sternberg, “Cognitive Mechanisms in Human Creativity.”
creativity as a darwinian phenomenon 81
the set of ideas constituting the theory. For instance, rather than call
the creative process Darwinian or even BVSR, we might better refer
to it as a combinatorial or constrained stochastic process.77 After all, would
it be less valid if called by some other name?
My belief is that the benefits outweigh the costs. The study of cre-
ativity must be brought into the scientific mainstream. Rather than
representing some mysterious process, creativity should be examined
from a naturalistic perspective that links it with other phenomena of
the same kind. Of all natural phenomena, the evolution of life comes
closest to the creation of ideas. Notwithstanding the conspicuous
differences between the two processes, they both can be subsumed under
a generic BVSR mechanism. To the extent that Darwin can be credited
with introducing that particular mechanism into organic evolution, so
can he provide the eponym for the process underlying human creativ-
ity. That is just an act of giving credit where credit is due.
77
Simonton, “Scientific Creativity as Constrained Stochastic Behavior”; “Darwin
as a Straw Man.”
CHAPTER FIVE
Berys Gaut
I Introduction
II What Is Creativity?
We need first to get clear about what creativity is. The traditional
definition is two-part. The first part holds that a creative act or product
1
Plato, Phaedrus, 245a, in The Collected Dialogues, eds. Edith Hamilton and Huntington
Cairns (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1961).
84 berys gaut
2
The notion of a product should be understood broadly throughout this discussion:
besides physical things, ideas, procedures, techniques, and so on, count as products.
3
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis, Ind.:
Hackett, 1987), sec. 46, Ak. 307–308.
4
See Margaret Boden, The Creative Mind: Myths and Mechanisms, 2nd ed. (London:
Routledge, 2004), 2.
creativity and skill 85
My claim is that flair involves a kind of skill. Why might one deny this?
Let us start with Plato: why is the difference between the creative person
and the drone not a difference in the possession of a kind of skill? In
the Ion, Plato has Socrates argue that Ion, a rhapsode (a kind of creative
recitor of poetry), does not have his ability to speak well on Homer’s
poetry by skill. If he did, he could explain not only the particular excel-
lences in Homer, but also the particular merits and failures of other
poets, on whom he admits he can say nothing. Moreover, Ion can offer
no account of how it is that he can speak so well on Homer. (Socrates
also claims that the creative process in Ion is irrational. Socrates has
more than one reason for this; but one of them seems to rest on the
thought that skill is a matter of bringing about one’s ends by deploying
suitable means. If one thinks of a rational process of making something
as the taking of means to bring about the existence of the object, then
if there is no skill, there is no taking of means, so one is not engaged
in a process of rational making.)
Plato’s reasons for denying the role of skill in Ion’s creative process
are peculiarly unconvincing. For there are specialized skills, and we
are familiar with an academic world in which one person can write
well on one poet, and have very little to say about another. Moreover,
Ion’s inarticulacy about his ability is a familiar feature of many kinds
of skill: one cannot explain how one rides a bicycle, but it is a genuine
skill for all that.
5
For a related defense of the three-part definition, see my “Creativity and Imagi-
nation,” in The Creation of Art: New Essays in Philosophical Aesthetics, eds. Berys Gaut
and Paisley Livingston (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 149–151.
The Goodyear example is taken from David Novitz, “Creativity and Constraint,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (1999): 67–82, at 75, though Novitz employs it for
a different purpose.
creativity and skill 87
However, there is a way to defend the idea that creativity does not
involve a kind of skill that is in the spirit of Plato’s project. According
to several influential writers, the creative process is not goal-directed,
that is, it is not teleological. In being creative, I do not adopt the means
to some already pre-determined end. R. G. Collingwood argued along
these lines, and so did Monroe Beardsley and Vincent Tomas.
One version of the kinds of considerations to which these writers
appeal can be reconstructed as a five-step argument. First, if one is to
take the means to an end, one has to know the end. For instance, if
I want to make a table, I must know what the table is to be like if I
am to set about making it. Second, if, however, the process of making
something is creative, then one cannot know the end: for if one knows
the end, one has already created the object. For instance, a poet creating
a poem cannot already know what the poem is, for if he knows this,
he has already created the poem. To have conceived of it is to have
made it. Contrast this with making something uncreatively, such as a
table, where one can know what the table is to be like, without having
made it, since one must go on physically to make it (by skill) before it
exists. Third, it follows from the first two steps that creative making
cannot consist in the taking of means to ends—the creative process
cannot be teleological. Creating the poem cannot be a matter of tak-
ing means to an end. (Taking the means here can only mean writing
the poem down, having already thought of it: but merely writing it
down is something subsequent to the creative process, not part of it.)
Fourth, exercising a skill requires the taking of means to bring about
one’s ends. Fifth, it follows from the last two steps that creativity can-
6
not involve a skill.
However, as just stated, the argument is open to an objection at
step two about the proposed ontology of the artwork. Perhaps some
kinds of artworks are abstract universals or types, such as poems and
musical works, and so they do exist merely when conceived. But other
artworks, such as paintings and sculptures, essentially involve material
components. So the claim that conceiving of the artwork is identical
6
R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1938
[reissued 1958]). Collingwood holds that “To create something means to make it non-
technically, but yet consciously and voluntarily” (128); technical making is craft making,
which involves a means-end structure and skill (16–18). Collingwood also holds that
works of art are always created in this sense, and that they are imaginary objects, distinct
from their physical embodiments (chap. 7). Collingwood does not explicitly link creation
to creativity, but this version of the argument captures the spirit of his position.
88 berys gaut
with its creation is false in such cases. Hence, the anti-teleological argu-
ment would at best apply only to some artworks (and more generally
only to the creation of abstract universals or types).
However, we need not enter into the ontological debate about the
nature of artworks here, since an alternative version of the argument
does not rely on the claim that the artwork is created when its idea is
created. Rather, it holds that the creative act is completed when the artist
has the idea of the artwork. It is the thinking up of the artwork that
is the creative act. Some kinds of artworks (perhaps) essentially involve
material objects, but the creative aspect of their making is nevertheless
exhausted by the artist’s conceiving of them. Their physical realiza-
tion, in contrast, is a matter of noncreative manual labor in the case
of sculpture and painting, or noncreative writing down of words or
notation in the case of literature and music. So at step two, this varia-
tion of the argument holds that if the process of making something is
creative, then one cannot know the end: for if one knows the end, one
has already been creative. The argument then proceeds smoothly without
the debatable ontological claim.
Something like this variation of the argument is adopted by
Vincent Tomas:
To create is to originate. And it follows from this that prior to creation the
creator does not foresee what will result from it . . . [Otherwise he] would
have to have the idea of it in mind. But if he already had the idea in
mind, all that would remain to be done is to objectify the idea in paint
or in stone, and this would be a matter of skill, or work. . . . By the time
they [sculptors] have the idea, the creative act, which in this case is the
production of the idea, is finished. But to produce that original idea, the
sculptor does not first have to produce an idea of it.7
So, according to Tomas, creativity cannot consist in finding the means
to realize a pre-determined goal, and therefore does not involve skill;
rather, it consists in thinking up an original idea. Thinking up this
idea does not consist in finding the means to yet another idea, or
there would be an infinite regress of ideas. Note that Tomas applies
this claim not only to arts, such as poetry and music, whose products
are abstract universals, but also to material arts such as sculpture. The
sculptor thinks up an idea and in so doing is creative, but he can leave
it to hired stonecutters to execute his plan.
7
Vincent Tomas, “Creativity in Art,” Philosophical Review 67 (1958): 1–15, at 4.
creativity and skill 89
8
Ibid., 13.
9
Monroe Beardsley, “On the Creation of Art,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
23 (1965): 291–304.
10
John Hospers (“Artistic Creativity,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43 [1984–
1985]: 243–255) also notes this point at 245. However, he uses it to argue that there
is no real difference between the teleological and propulsive theories.
90 berys gaut
chocolate mousse recipe, found tasty in the past), varying the ingredients
in quantity and type, and so on. So one deploys one’s cookery skills,
but does not follow a routine; if one’s quest is successful, one will have
developed a new routine (a new recipe) for a better chocolate cake, but
one’s actions did not, and could not, if they were creative, consist in
following a routine. Moreover, one’s actions could not be random, since
otherwise (as in the case of my traumatic encounter with the paint and
the darkened room) they would not be creative either.
I have been creative (albeit not at a terribly exalted level), if I
produce a tastier chocolate cake. Yet that process was goal-directed
throughout, contra Tomas. It also involved skills, though not the follow-
ing of routines. So creativity is compatible with goal-directedness, for
two reasons. First, creativity can consist in a greater specification of
one’s goal. I wanted to bake a better chocolate cake; but I initially had
no idea as to the precise features of this end: how, precisely was it to
taste? As I experimented further, I managed to get clearer about the
exact qualities of the final product. So one way in which one can be
creative is by further refining one’s goal. A painter, for instance, can
be creative by virtue of starting out with a rough idea of the sort of
painting he wishes to make, and then get his goal more precise as he
tries out various options. So creativity can involve teleological reasoning
because one aspect of this reasoning is a more detailed specification of
one’s goal (a process sometimes put in terms of finding the constitutive
means, as opposed to causal means, to one’s ends).
Second, an aspect of creativity lies in finding the means to accomplish
one’s end. It is possible to be creative in finding the means to one’s
goal, even if the goal is completely precise. One may, have decided
on the exact taste that one wants for one’s cake, but not know how to
achieve it. A similar process of controlled, skillful trying out of various
options may lead one to reach it. Alternatively, imagine aiming to bake
a five-foot high cake. One may know exactly what one is trying to make,
but have no idea about how to go about making it, and be creative in
finding those means. So there is such a thing as creativity of means as
well as creativity of ends. The same applies to the arts: an architect,
for instance, may be creative in thinking up the design of a building,
but his structural engineer may also be creative in finding a way physi-
cally to realize the architect’s apparently impossible design. Consider
the creativity required to be Frank Gehry’s structural engineer.
Talk of teleology may seem to miss something essential to cre-
ativity. What of inspiration, the creative idea that comes from
92 berys gaut
11
Peter Kivy, The Fine Art of Repetition: Essays in the Philosophy of Music (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1993), 68.
12
Graham Wallas, The Art of Thought, ed. Jonathan Cape (London: Jonathan Cape,
1926), 79–96; reprinted in Creativity, ed. P. E. Vernon (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1970).
13
Henri Poincaré, The Foundations of Science, trans. G. B. Halstead (Science Press,
Marrickville NSW, 1924), 383–394; reprinted in Vernon, Creativity, quote from 83 in
Vernon.
creativity and skill 93
from being teleological, or from involving skills: many skills are uncon-
scious: those involved in riding a bike standardly are, for example.
However, the precise nature of the process is properly a matter of
psychological investigation. What we need here is the simple point that,
unless we deny the possibility of psychological explanation, then there
is some psychological process that terminates in the moment of inspi-
ration; there is no reason to deny that this process as a whole can be
teleological and involve skills. In the same way, looking for something
is an active process; the success-condition, seeing the thing looked for,
is a passive occurrence; but the process as a whole is teleological and
may involve skills by virtue of the active process of looking.
There is a second reply to the inspiration objection. Whether an
idea for a work counts as an inspiration will crucially depend both on
a person’s skills and on his interests. Douglas Dunn once remarked
in a lecture that he had had the idea for a poem when, talking with
a friend, they both discovered that in their youths they had opened
Blue Note jazz records imported from America and inhaled the odor
of them: “The smell of America!”14 What made this an inspiration?
Well, Dunn was struck by a thought which he believed that, given his
skills, he could likely work up into a good poem and because Dunn
aims to write poetry. A non-poet might have merely gone on to think
‘What a stink!’
On the other hand, a philosopher, such as Kant, might be inspired
to produce a great philosophical work by the thought that events are
individuated by the causal relations in which they stand. Even Douglas
Dunn might be hard put to make a poem out of that. So what ideas
count as inspirations is relative to what a person thinks that he can go
on to do with them, and that depends on his abilities and interests.
Since one’s interests specify one’s goals, the notion of inspiration is
thus conceptually related to that of one’s goals. Indeed, one can think
of the creative person’s activity as involving a kind of search for ideas,
which might be the germ for works: the searching might be active, or
merely consist in openness to useful ideas or experiences thrown up
by the world or by a person’s unconscious. The creative person is thus
on the lookout for ideas and experiences that may form the germs for
achievements in her field, be it poetry or philosophy.
14
Douglas Dunn, “Creativity in Poetry,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture,
Dundee, 14 November 2003.
94 berys gaut
15
For more on the notion of a criterion, see my “ ‘Art’ as a Cluster Concept” in Theo-
ries of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2000).
96 berys gaut
16
See for instance, Anna Craft, Creativity across the Primary Curriculum: Framing and
Developing Practice (London: Routledge, 2000); Anna Craft, Bob Jeffrey and Mike Leib-
ling, eds., Creativity in Education (London: Continuum, 2001); and Tina Bruce, Cultivating
Creativity in Babies, Toddlers and Young Children (London: Hodder and Stoughton, 2004).
17
E.g., Richard Wollheim, Painting as an Art (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1987), 46.
18
Martin Kemp, ed., Leonardo on Painting, trans. Martin Kemp and Margaret Walker
(Yale University Press, 1989), 222.
creativity and skill 97
19
For a general discussion of how constraints may promote creativity, see Jon Elster,
Ulysses Unbound: Studies in Rationality, Pre-Commitment and Constraint (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000).
98 berys gaut
may be low on the H-creativity scale is not to deny that their ideas
are highly saliently new to them: that they are often very P-creative.
In addition, while it is true that education can sometimes undermine
children’s creativity, it does not follow that creativity cannot be taught:
it only follows that some kinds of teaching can undermine rather than
foster it.
So far, we have clarified the notion of a skill and discussed whether
creativity involves a skill. But the question also arises of whether cre-
ativity is to be identified with a kind of skill, or whether it merely involves
a skill, and something in addition is required. Consider mountain
climbing. This involves many skills, but more is required to be a good
mountain-climber than possessing these skills: one has to have the right
attitudes and values as well. Someone scared of heights may possess
the relevant skills, but be a very poor climber or no climber at all. The
ability to climb mountains thus involves skills and the possession of
certain attitudes and values. Creativity, I suggest, is like that. In parallel
fashion, someone may have creative ability, but be poor at exercising
the skill, because he or she is too timid to take the risks involved in
being creative. As we will see shortly, there is an internal connection
between being creative and possessing a kind of courage.
It can seem hard to swallow the idea that creativity is an ability involv-
ing a skill, since so much of traditional discourse, both popular and
philosophical, opposes creativity to skill. A brief survey of the alterna-
tives may aid digestion.
The oldest alternative is the supernatural theory: Plato held in the
Ion, as we saw, that the gods or muses speak through the poet: creativity
is a supernatural force. That will be rejected by any even minimally
naturalist psychology; and more importantly, it simply begs the question:
for how do we explain the gods’ creativity? Plato to support his case
cites Tynnichus, the original one-hit wonder, who produced a famous
praise-song, but nothing else of note, as an example of how the gods
can pick on a person to demonstrate their creativity, but never again
favor him.20 However, it is striking that creative people tend to produce
several creative things, not just one.
20
Plato, Ion, 534d–e.
creativity and skill 99
21
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, sec. 46, Ak. 307; sec. 57, Ak. 344.
100 berys gaut
Besides attacking the anti-teleological model, I have argued that the kind
of skills involved in creativity are non-routinized. The latter thought has
two interesting implications for the question of the value of creativity,
one to do with freedom, the other with courage.
Why should we value the skills involved in creativity particularly
highly? Part of the answer is that we value them on instrumental
grounds, since their exercise can produce valuable things. But we also
value creativity non-instrumentally, for its own sake. In general, we
value skills for their own sake; but why do we particularly value cre-
ative skills? An explanation is available on the account defended here:
creative persons exhibit a kind of freedom, they are not bound by
routines, but they can stand back from them, consider whether they are
for the good, and act in a way that is goal-directed but not routinized.
Creative persons, then, are free in the sense that they are not bound
by the established practice of routines. Creativity manifests a certain
22
See Gregory J. Feist, “The Influence of Personality on Artistic and Scientific Cre-
ativity,” who presents a comprehensive survey of the relevant literature, in Handbook of
Creativity, ed. Robert J. Sternberg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
creativity and skill 101
23
See Christine Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1996), 92–94.
24
Albert Einstein, “Letter to Jacques Hadamard,” in The Creative Process, ed. Brewster
Ghiselin, (New York: Mentor, 1952), 43.
102 berys gaut
25
For a defense of these claims and their greater elaboration, see my “Creativity
and Imagination.”
creativity and skill 103
26
Versions of this paper were read at Dundee University, Leeds University, Stirling
University, the Institute of Education at London University, and the British Society
of Aesthetics annual conference in 2005. I would like to thank the audiences at these
occasions for their many helpful comments.
CHAPTER SIX
Peter Lamarque
suppose that the world was no different, in musical and artistic terms,
after 1808, when Beethoven completed his Fifth Symphony—especially
on the grounds that the Fifth Symphony has always existed as a sound-
structure-type—is hyperbolic. The differences before and after this event
are manifest and far-reaching. Perhaps, though, it might be argued, it is
not the work itself that had this influence but the discovery of the work
or the spreading awareness of the work. In any case, that a change was
wrought upon the world when the compositional work was completed
seems undeniable. So let us focus on that change.
The enquiry needs to be pinned down a bit more. For one thing, it
does not need to be distracted with attempts to define art. Some of the
works on the list will be works of art in an honorific sense, but many
would not merit that title. There are paintings and poems and songs that
are not normally considered art but are nonetheless completed works
and need to be included. Questions of value, however, are inescapable
in the enquiry. Michel Foucault, writing about linguistic works, nicely
brings out the practical as well as theoretical problems in delimiting
works, and the peculiar role of judgments of value:
What is a work? What is this curious unity which we designate as a
work? . . . If an individual were not an author, could we say that what he
wrote, said, left behind in his papers, or what has been collected of his
remarks, could be called a ‘work’? . . . Even when an individual has been
accepted as an author, we must still ask whether everything that he wrote,
said, or left behind is part of his work. The problem is both theoretical
and technical. When undertaking the publication of Nietzsche’s works, for
example, where should one stop? Surely everything should be published,
but what is ‘everything’? Everything that Nietzsche himself published
certainly. And what about the rough drafts of his works? Obviously. The
plans for his aphorisms? Yes. The deleted passages and the notes at the
bottom of the page? Yes. What if, within the notebook filled with apho-
risms, one finds a reference, the notation of a meeting or of an address,
or a laundry list: Is it a work or not? Why not? And so on, ad infinitum.
How can one define a work amid the millions of traces left by someone
after his death? A theory of the work does not exist . . .1
Foucault despairs of finding a determinate answer to the practical ques-
tions he raises for the scholarly editor. Surely he is right that there is
not always a clear line round what should count as an author’s ‘work’
worthy of preservation. He is also right that value judgments relating to
1
Michel Foucault, “What is an Author?” in The Death and Resurrection of the Author,
ed. William Irwin (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 2002), 11.
on bringing a work into existence 107
2
I borrow the terms from Paisley Livingston, whose discussion in “Counting Frag-
ments, and Frenhofer’s Paradox,” (British Journal of Aesthetics 39 [1999]: 14–23), I have
found very useful.
3
Harry Deutsch, “The Creation Problem,” Topoi 10 (1991): 209–225.
108 peter lamarque
the paint have brought the painting into existence but all the creative
work has been done for them. In general:
(t)he creative part of creating a painting may in fact consist of doing
less than bringing the painting into existence. It may consist in devis-
ing a scheme for where on the canvas the paint should go; or it might
consist merely in creatively envisaging in some detail what the painting
will be like.4
The problem is not peculiar to painting by numbers. Arguably an
analogous situation arose in Renaissance studios where a Master painter
would give instructions to teams of workers on what should be painted
where. Creativity is credited to the Master although the underlings bring
the painting into existence. It is not only creativity that is at issue in
such cases. There are also issues of work identity. When avant-garde
artists do something apparently similar, the question arises of what
kind of works they are creating. Thus the conceptual artist Sol LeWitt
laid down specifications for certain of his works without putting them
into effect himself. One such, Wall Drawing No. 623 Double asymmetrical
pyramids with colour ink washes superimposed, which has been realized (if that
is the word) in a mural in the National Gallery of Canada, consists of
instructions as follows: “colour ink wash: the background is grey, blue,
grey, blue; left pyramid: the apex is left—four sides: 1—red, blue, blue,
red, blue; 2—yellow, blue, grey, blue” and so on. But what is the work?
Given that there can be different ways of realizing the work and given
that LeWitt is a conceptual artist, it could be argued that the work is
the idea rather than the painted mural itself.5 (Even if this is right in
this particular case, it should not be taken as a general endorsement
of idealist theories of the work, such as R. G. Collingwood’s, which
identify the work in every case with something mental.) Clearly to know
if and when a work has come into existence we need to know what
kind of work it is. But it is worth distinguishing a value-free conception
of creation where it literally means bringing into the world something
that did not exist before, in contrast to an honorific sense implying
originality or ‘creativity.’
4
Deutsch, “The Creation Problem,” 211.
5
The case is discussed by David Davies in Art as Performance (Oxford: Blackwell,
2004), who argues for the centrality of the idea in the work’s identity: “The fact that
there are actual enactments of LeWitt’s constraints . . . bears upon the appreciation of
the work only by, as we might put it, ‘enlivening’ the idea, supplementing the inten-
sionality of the vehicle as verbally specified,” 232.
on bringing a work into existence 109
II
between the medium manipulated into a structure and the work itself ?
Is the musical work identical to the sound-structure-types of which it is
constituted or is it something distinct? Is the literary work identical to
its constitutive word-sequence-types (its text) or is it distinct?
Before addressing these questions directly, more needs to be said about
the crucial idea of a medium. So far a medium has been identified
with the materials, broadly conceived, of which works are constituted.
These materials are not necessarily physical—they can take the form
of abstract entities—but in each case it is not implausible to describe
artists (or makers of works generally) as manipulating a medium as an
essential part of the process of making a work. Works are made out
of the materials of a medium. However, within aesthetics it is now
common to distinguish a medium of this kind—the kind that David
Davies calls a ‘vehicular medium’6—with another kind, sometimes
called an ‘artistic’ medium.7 There is no settled view as to exactly how
the latter should be defined. For Jerrold Levinson “ ‘Medium’ in this
sense is closer to ‘art form’ than to ‘kind of stuff,’ ”8 while for David
Davies, “attention to the artistic medium of a work necessarily refers
us to the intentionality of a maker who acts in light of these supposed
understandings in manipulating a vehicular medium.”9
Drawing on both these approaches, we might say that an artistic
medium involves the conception of a work by its maker as being a work of a
certain kind. The important point is the intentionality. A work’s artistic
medium is not determined (exclusively) by art, historical, or third person
classification but by the way in which the work is conceived by the person
making it. There might be cases where the artistic medium is unknown
to art history (perhaps this is true of the prehistoric cave paintings),
making the work virtually impossible to understand or appreciate.
The combination of vehicular and artistic medium allows for a richer
understanding of what it is to make a work. For an artist is not just
manipulating materials but is doing so under some conception of what
kind of work is aimed for. Of course, it would be wrong to suppose
this conception is always precise or unchanging. Artists might set out
with only the vaguest conception of what they are doing and might
6
Davies, Art as Performance, 56ff.
7
The term comes from ibid.
8
Jerrold Levinson, Music, Art, and Metaphysics: Essays in Philosophical Aesthetics (Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1990), 29.
9
Davies, Art as Performance, 60.
on bringing a work into existence 111
while he was still working. But that says no more than that the work
was finished when the work was finished. We still do not know what
difference it made to the world that ‘is the Pietà’ became true of a piece
of marble, nor how that should be construed. The proposed account
is misleading in its comparison between the predicates ‘is a sculpture’
and ‘is smooth-textured’ or ‘is white.’ Although it might be true that the
predicates are all applicable to one and the same object, the piece of
marble, only the latter two predicates identify intrinsic qualities of that
object. However the qualities came to be possessed by the marble, for
example, through polishing and cleaning, they remain physical qualities
of the object. Exactly those same qualities could have been possessed
by the object without any human intervention. Such, though, is not
the case with the property being a sculpture. That property is essentially
connected to human agency. Nothing is a sculpture—indeed nothing
is a work of any kind in the sense intended—except as a product of
human agency. But even more than that, if we apply our earlier finding,
there must be intentionality deep in the very concept of a work. A work
is the product of an agent’s manipulation of a medium and becomes
a work, and the work that it is, only under a conception supplied by
the agent. A necessary condition for a piece of marble becoming a
sculpture is that it be conceived as a sculpture by its maker.10 Without
that it remains just a piece of marble.
Behind the view discussed lies an analogy which, although initially
plausible, is flawed. It is an analogy with an activity like cooking. A
cook will ‘manipulate’ the ingredients until a dish is complete. When the
cooking is done new predicates are applicable to the finished product:
being a fried egg, being a sponge cake. It is tempting to see being a sculpture
as analogous, as the same kind of predicate. In both cases, there is a
process completed and the coming into existence of something that
was not there before. But disanalogies have already been identified.
Being a fried egg (like being smooth-textured ) is a physical property, or
strictly being fried is a physical property of an egg. It is defined as such
independently of human intention. Most eggs are fried deliberately for
human ends but that might not always be the case. There could be
10
There might be ancient or primitive works the creators of which did not possess
the concept of sculpture. We should be wary, though, of how to treat these. It might
be that they have been appropriated into the sculptural tradition by those who found
them. Arguably, those who found the works, not those who created them, made them
as sculptures.
on bringing a work into existence 113
too must be rejected. A work is still essentially identified with the ‘stuff ’
of which it is constituted but the change wrought in the world when
the work comes into existence is that the constituting material acquires
intentional and relational properties that previously it did not possess. To
be a sculpture is to be a piece of marble (wood, for example) shaped and
configured by human agency and which has come to possess intentional
properties such as being conceived as a sculpture, being an object of appreciation,
being a representation of David, being in the classical style. The parallel now
is not between being a sculpture and being smooth-textured or even being a
fried egg but between, say, being a sculpture and being elected Mayor. When
Jones is elected Mayor something of a different order happens to him
than when he puts on weight or loses his hair. The latter are physical
changes, the former changes in status. Jones’s election as Mayor brings
with it a range of institutional powers and responsibilities. Acting as
Mayor, Jones can formulate and implement policies on local matters,
can represent the city on official occasions, can make appointments
and award prizes; in addition, people will expect certain attitudes of
him as Mayor, a degree of respect or deference, demanding of him
an obligation to act with dignity and decorum, ‘upholding the office.’
Analogously, when a work comes into existence, it too acquires a status
conventionally defined. Certain expectations arise for works, however
humble. They are open to special kinds of appraisal, they are located
in traditions and styles, they invite appreciation as works of a particular
kind, and they can be attributed meaning or symbolism.
The idea that works, on becoming works, acquire a distinctive status
and a distinctive range of intentional properties is correct and impor-
tant.11 The analogy with an institutional role like becoming a Mayor is
illuminating. But how far can the analogy be pressed? Later we shall find
reasons for caution. Is being a work a property that something can have
at some times but not at others? Nelson Goodman, who invites us to
ask not ‘What is art?’ but ‘When is art?’ answers in the affirmative:
an object may be a work of art at some times and not at others. Indeed,
just by virtue of functioning as a symbol in a certain way does an object
become, while so functioning, a work of art. The stone is normally no
work of art while in the driveway but may be so when on display in an
art museum. In the driveway, it usually performs no symbolic function;
11
See Peter Lamarque, “Work and Object,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 52,
no. 2 (2002): 141–162.
on bringing a work into existence 115
12
Nelson Goodman, “When Is Art?” in The Arts and Cognition, eds. David Perkins &
Barbara Leondat (Baltimore, Md.: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977), 17.
13
Goodman, “When Is Art?” 10n, 19.
14
Goodman, “When Is Art?,” 18.
116 peter lamarque
III
15
See, for example, Mark Johnston, “Constitution is Not Identity,” Mind 101 (1992);
Michael B. Burke, “Copper Statues and Pieces of Copper: A Challenge to the Standard
Account,” Analysis 52 (1992): 12–17; D. Zimmerman, “Theories of Masses and Prob-
lems of Constitution,” Philosophical Review 104 (1995) 53–110; Lynne Rudder Baker,
“Why Constitution is Not Identity,” Journal of Philosophy 44 (1997): 599–621; Judith
Jarvis Thompson, “The Statue and the Clay,” Nous 32 (1998); Eric T Olson, “Material
Coincidence and the Indiscernibility Problem,” Philosophical Quarterly 51 (2001); Kit Fine,
“The Non-Identity of a Material Thing and Its Matter,” Mind (2003).
16
Roman Ingarden, “Artistic and Aesthetic Values,” British Journal of Aesthetics 4,
no. 3 (1964): 198.
17
Eddy M. Zemach, Real Beauty (University Park: The Pennsylvania State University
Press, 1997), 147.
on bringing a work into existence 117
18
Joseph Margolis, What, After All, Is a Work of Art? (University Park: The Pennsyl-
vania State University Press, 1997), 34–35.
19
Fine, “The Non-Identity of a Material Thing and Its Matter,” 206.
20
Levinson, Music, Art & Metaphysics, 68.
21
Ibid., 69.
118 peter lamarque
22
Criticisms of qua-objects appear in, for example, Harry Deutsch, “The Creation
Problem,” Topoi 10 (1991): 212–213; Mark Johnston, “Constitution is Not Identity,” Mind
101 (1992): 91; Stefano Predelli, “Musical Ontology and the Argument from Creation,”
British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (2001): 288–289. For a more positive account, see Kit Fine,
“The Problem of Non-Existents I. Internalism,” Topoi 1 (1982): 97–140.
23
Zemach, Real Beauty, 160.
on bringing a work into existence 119
24
Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: a Constitution View (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000), 32–33.
25
For discussion, notably on the constitution issue, see D. Pereboom, “On Baker’s
Persons and Bodies,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64, no. 3 (2002): 615–622;
M. Rea, “Lynne Baker on Material Constitution,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
64, no. 2 (2002): 607–614; G. Wedeking, “Critical Notice: Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons
and Bodies,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32, no. 2 (2002): 267–290.
26
Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies, 27.
120 peter lamarque
this can happen with the monument and the stone. The explanation is
that the monument is ‘a new kind of thing with new properties.’
Kit Fine also defends the negative thesis; he gives prime attention to
the statue and the alloy from which it is made but views that example
as paradigmatic of a wider relation between a material thing and its
matter.27 What is important for our purposes are not the detailed argu-
ments for and against constitutionalism28 but the metaphysical conclu-
sion—intuitively disturbing—that two different material things might
occupy the same space at the same time. A statue can be a material
entity but is not the very same material entity as the piece of marble that
constitutes it. One reason why this result is not repugnant to common-
sense lies in a crucial feature, namely that the coincident objects are not
of the same kind. The metaphysical principle that commonsense, if not
logic itself, should preserve is that no two objects of the same kind can occupy
the same space at the same time.29 But acceptable versions of the positive
thesis maintain that works and ‘mere’ physical things are not of the same
kind, even in the cases where the works are physical things.30
Many aestheticians have advanced the negative thesis but it is strik-
ing how diverse are the views that emerge from a rejection of identity.
Roman Ingarden, for example, insists:
in its structure and properties a work of art always extends beyond its
material substrate, the real ‘thing’ which ontologically supports it, although
the properties of the substrate are not irrelevant to the properties of the
work of art which depends upon it.31
From this starting point, he develops a view of the work as a col-
laborative effort between artist and observer centered on the notion
of ‘concretion’:
27
Kit Fine, “The Non-Identity of a Material Thing and Its Matter,” Mind 112
(2003): 195–234.
28
Kit Fine’s argument in “The Non-Identity of a Material Thing and Its Matter”
is primarily linguistic, showing that those defenders of the identity thesis who marshal
arguments from “opacity” to combat putative exceptions to Leibniz’s Law are them-
selves led to “intolerable consequences.” Baker’s argument, in contrast, is not primarily
linguistic but metaphysical in showing that properties like being a statue are not only
relational properties but are also essential in some cases.
29
See David Wiggins, Sameness and Substance (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1980).
30
The point is also emphasised by Robert Stecker in Interpretation and Construction:
Art, Speech, and the Law (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003), 91–92.
31
Ingarden, “Artistic and Aesthetic Values,” 198.
on bringing a work into existence 121
32
Ibid., 199.
33
R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1938), 305.
34
Ibid., 304–305.
122 peter lamarque
35
Ibid., 308.
36
Jean-Paul Sartre, The Psychology of Imagination (New York: Carol Publishing Group,
1991), 280.
37
By, respectively, Gregory Currie, An Ontology of Art (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1989);
Davies, Art as Performance; Jerrold Levinson, “What a Musical Work Is,” in Music, Art,
on bringing a work into existence 123
and Metaphysics: Essays in Philosophical Aesthetics (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press,
1990); Joseph Margolis, “Works of Art as Physically Embodied and Culturally Emergent
Entities,” British Journal of Aesthetics 14 (1974).
124 peter lamarque
38
Joseph Margolis, Art and Philosophy: Conceptual Issues in Aesthetics (Atlantic Highlands,
N.J.: Humanities Press, 1980), 20–21.
39
George Dickie, “The New Institutional Theory of Art,” in Aesthetics and Art Criti-
cism: The Analytic Tradition, An Anthology, eds. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen
(Oxford: Blackwell, 2003), 49.
on bringing a work into existence 125
kind then works of that kind no longer exist.40 This is partly the truth
behind Ingarden’s observation that works are the ‘common product of
artist and observer.’ It is only through a kind of social compact between
people with like-minded interests that the recognition of a work as a
work is possible.
We should conclude, then, that to bring a work into existence is
indeed to bring a new entity into the world, not just to reorder what
is there already. The conclusion is important, if hard won, because
it means that whenever a work is completed there has been genuine
creation even if in some cases we have to withhold the plaudits accom-
panying the more evaluative sense of artistic creativity.
40
See Lamarque, “Work and Object,” 155–156.
PART TWO
Paisley Livingston
I Introduction
1
Vincent van Gogh, “Letter to Anton Ridder Van Rappard,” in The Creative Process,
ed. Brewster Ghiselin (New York: Mentor, 1952), 55.
2
Paul Valéry, “L’invention esthétique,” in Oeuvres, vol. 1, ed. Jean Hytier (Paris: Gal-
limard, 1957), 412–415.
130 paisley livingston
II Poincaré on Creativity
3
Henri Poincaré, “L’invention mathématique,” Bulletin de l’Institut Général Psychologique
8 (1908): 175–187; reprinted in Science et méthode (Paris: Flammarion, 1908), 43–63;
reprinted in L’Invention mathématique (Paris: Jacques Gabay, 1993), 35–51; trans. by George
Bruce Halstead as “Mathematical Creation,” in The Foundations of Science (London: Sci-
ence Press, 1924), 383–394; all translations in this chapter are Paisley Livingston’s.
4
Virginia Woolf, Jacob’s Room (Orlando, Fla: Harcourt, 1922).
5
Poincaré, “L’invention mathématique,” 52.
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 131
returned to the question. I had all the elements, and had only to assemble
and arrange them. Accordingly I composed my definitive treatise at a
sitting and without any difficulty.6
At first glance, Poincaré may seem to be espousing an inspirationist
conception of creativity—the idea that genuine creativity is largely if
not entirely a matter of sudden, involuntary illumination or insight.
A closer look at Poincaré’s narrative reveals, however, that he is no
straightforward exponent of a simple inspirationist thesis. Instead,
Poincaré deserves to be acknowledged as an early exponent of the view
that creative achievements are often the product of different sorts of
interacting psychological processes, including the stages of preparation,
incubation, insight, and revision that have become a commonplace in
the literature on creativity.7
According to Poincaré, a necessary condition of what he calls
“appearances of sudden illumination” is that they are “first preceded
and then followed by a period of conscious work.”8 Prior, conscious
work is necessary to inspiration because it sets in motion what Poincaré
called la machine inconsciente (the unconscious machine).9 The basic idea
here is uncontroversial: someone who is truly idle, in the sense of not
being at any time engaging in any relevant projects, will not be likely
to experience the sort of episodes of inspiration that Poincaré and
many other creative persons have described. Yet Poincaré gives other
reasons why inspiration must be accompanied by conscious effort:
unless the researcher or artist makes a prior selection of the elements
upon which the mind is to operate, the search will be too open-ended
and will most likely be fruitless as a result. Conscious, voluntary work
posterior to moments of inspiration is necessary because the ideas that
6
Ibid., 53.
7
See, for example, Graham Wallas’s influential pamphlet, The Art of Thought (London:
Jonathan Cape, 1926). More recently, Poincaré’s views have been taken up by Howard
E. Gruber, “Insight and Affect in the History of Science,” in The Nature of Insight, eds.
Robert J. Sternberg and Janet E. Davidson (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1995), 397–432.
One of the few authors who emphasizes Poincaré’s historical importance on this topic
is Robert W. Weisberg, Creativity: Understanding Innovation in Problem Solving, Science, Invention,
and the Arts (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley & Sons, 2006), chap. 8; I first saw Weisberg’s
book while revising the notes to this essay. For additional philosophical background
on artistic creativity, see “Introduction: The Creation of Art: Issues and Perspectives,”
in The Creation of Art: New Essays in Philosophical Aesthetics, eds. Berys Gaut and Paisley
Livingston (New York and Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 1–32.
8
Poincaré, “L’invention mathématique,” 53.
9
Ibid., 54.
132 paisley livingston
pop into one’s mind usually require some development and polishing.
Also, it is necessary to verify them: although inspiration tends to be
accompanied by a second-order attitude, a belief or feeling, to the
effect that the inspired thoughts are correct, worthwhile, or otherwise
appropriate, sometimes this feeling of ‘absolute certainty’ is belied by
subsequent examination or critical reflection.
To sum up, the moments of idleness or ‘incubation,’ when the artistic
or scientist has set aside his or her work and takes up some unrelated
pastime, can be crucial to the creative process. Yet if thinkers are, at
such times, ‘idle’ in the sense of not being consciously occupied by
work, in fact, their minds are not at all idle in the sense of being useless,
empty, or unoccupied, for in an ‘unconscious machine’ has been set in
motion and is hard at work. Or to shift to another image employed by
Poincaré, one wheel on the pulley is idle so that the other wheels can
work all the more efficiently.
One of the most original and fascinating aspects of Poincaré’s dis-
cussion of creativity is his attempt to say something about how the
process of incubation works, and more specifically, about how this
process is functionally related to the efforts of the conscious ego or
self. Poincaré repeatedly insists that the key to mathematical innova-
tion, be it conscious or unconscious, cannot simply be the application
of ‘a tremendous power of attention’ or of a heightened capacity of
calculation. The symbolic combinations to be searched through are
simply too numerous for this to be the key to discovery. The possible
permutations are in principle infinite, and even if the unconscious mind
has generative capacities that far exceed those of conscious attention
or reasoning, its superior success cannot be explained in these terms:
“Invention consists precisely in not constructing useless combinations,
but in constructing those that are useful, which are a tiny minority. To
invent is to discern, to choose.”10
Should this point be granted, and if it is further allowed that some
unconscious mental process is at times highly successful at realizing the
relevant sort of discernment, it would seem to follow that the uncon-
scious ego must employ tact and discernment so as to achieve a kind of
selection or ‘divination’ of a (or even the) useful combination. Yet Poin-
caré rejects this conclusion. It is not a solution of the problem simply
to assume that the unconscious mental processes can reliably identify
a new, useful combination or idea without working through any of the
10
Ibid., 48.
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 133
11
Ibid., 62.
12
Colin Martindale, “Creativity and Connectionism,” in The Creative Cognition
Approach, eds. Steven M. Smith, Thomas B. Ward, and Ronald Finke (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT, 1995), 249–268; D. T. Campbell, “Blind Variation and Selective Retention
in Creative Thought and Other Knowledge Processes,” Psychological Review 67 (1960):
380–400; Dean K. Simonton, “Foresight in Insight? A Darwininan Answer,” in The
Nature of Insight, eds. Robert J. Sternberg and Janet E. Davidson (Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press, 1995), 465–494.
13
On the semantics of creativity and divergent conceptions of creation, see Gaut
and Livingston, “Introduction,” The Creation of Art; Margaret A. Boden, The Creative
Mind: Myths and Mechanisms (London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson; 1990); 2nd ed. rev.
(London: Routledge, 2004); Monroe C. Beardsley, “On the Creation of Art,” Journal
134 paisley livingston
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 23 (1965): 291–304; David Ecker, “The Artistic Process as
Qualitative Problem Solving,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 21(1963): 283–90;
Vincent Tomas, “Creativity in Art,” The Philosophical Review 67 (1958): 1–15; R. Keith
Sawyer, Explaining Creativity: The Science of Human Innovation (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2006).
14
Poincaré, “L’invention mathématique,” in Science et méthode, 17.
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 135
15
Ibid., 59.
136 paisley livingston
16
Paisley Livingston, “On an Apparent Truism in Aesthetics,” British Journal of
Aesthetics 43 (2003): 260–278.
17
Kendall L. Walton, “Categories of Art,” Philosophical Review 79 (1970): 334–367;
Richard Wollheim, “Criticism as Retrieval,” in Art and its Objects, 2nd ed. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1980), 185–204. One way to couch the key idea here
is to say that the “supervenience base” of aesthetic qualities is far broader than the
perceptible features of some artistic structure or object on display.
18
An example is a Sienese picture attributed variously to Sassetta, Sano di Pietro,
and the Master of the Osservanza, The Meeting of St Anthony and St Paul, ca. 1430–1435
(47 × 33.6 cm), The National Gallery, Washington D.C.
19
For example, the Seto stoneware teabowl named Asaina (Momyama period,
1568–1615). The neo-Confucian scholar Dazai Shundai, for example, called such items
“filthy and damaged old bowls”; cited in Paul H. Varley, “Chanoyu: From the Genroku
Epoch to Modern Times,” in Tea in Japan: Essays on the History of Chanoyu, eds. Paul
H. Varley and Kumakura Isao (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1989), 175.
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 137
20
David Schmidtz, “Satisficing as a Humanly Rational Strategy,” in Satisficing and
Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason, ed. Michael Byron (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2004), 30–58.
21
Todd I. Lubart, “Models of the Creative Process: Past, Present, and Future,”
Creativity Research Journal 13 (2000–2001): 295–308.
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 139
22
This critique is stated, for example, in R. Keith Sawyer, Explaining Creativity: The
Science of Human Innovation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), chap. 6.
23
Eliaz Segal, “Incubation in Problem Solving,” Creativity Research Journal 16 (2004):
141–148.
24
Mette Hjort and Scott MacKenzie, eds. Purity and Provocation: Dogma 95 (London:
British Film Institute Press, 2003).
140 paisley livingston
25
Jon Elster, Ulysses Unbound: Studies in Rationality, Precommitment, and Constraints (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 212.
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 141
26
Virginia Woolf, Night and Day (London: Flamingo, 1919).
27
For Mansfield’s criticisms, see Clare Hanson, ed., The Critical Writings of Katherine
Mansfield (London: Macmillan, 1987), 56–63; for plausible comments on Woolf ’s reac-
tion and more general relation to Mansfield, see Angela Smith, Katherine Mansfield and
Virginia Woolf: A Public of Two (Oxford: Clarendon, 1999).
28
For background on Woolf and artistic modernism, see Hermione Lee, The Novels
of Virginia Woolf (London: Methuen, 1977), 11–24.
142 paisley livingston
29
Virginia Woolf, “An Unwritten Novel,” in Monday or Tuesday (New York: Harcourt,
Brace, 1921).
30
Entry of Monday 26 January 1920, The Diary of Virginia Woolf, vol. 2, ed. Anne
Olivier Bell (Harmondsworth: Penquin, 1981), 13–14.
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 143
31
Virgina Woolf, “The Leaning Tower,” in A Woman’s Essays: Selected Essays, ed.
Rachel Bowlby (London: Penquin, 1992), 163.
32
For this general claim about Woolf ’s revisions and an example, see James King,
Virginia Woolf (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1994), 315.
144 paisley livingston
33
Virginia Woolf, Orlando: A Biography (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1928); To the
Lighthouse (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1927); Jacob’s Room & The Waves (New York:
Harcourt, Brace, 1923 © 1931).
poincaré’s ‘delicate sieve’ 145
34
Jerrold Levinson, “Elster on Artistic Creativity,” in The Creation of Art, 235–256.
146 paisley livingston
35
R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1938),
316.
36
This point is underscored and developed by Stein Haugom Olsen in “Culture,
Convention, and Creativity,” and by Noël Carroll in “Art, Creativity, and Tradition,”
in The Creation of Art, eds. Gaut and Livingston, 192–207, 208–234 respectively.
37
A first version of this paper was initially presented at Stanford University at a
conference on rational choice and the humanities organized by David Palumbo-Liu. I
think David for his helpful editorial advice. Another version was presented in Providence,
Rhode Island at the annual meeting of the American Society for Aesthetics. I thank
my respondent on that occasion, Gary Fuller, for his comments and encouragement.
David Davies and other members of the audience raised some helpful questions. The
work described in this paper was partially supported by a grant from the Research
Grants Council of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region, China (Project No.
LU3401/06H). I am very grateful for this support.
CHAPTER EIGHT
Michael Polanyi
1
Reprinted from Chemical and Engineering News 44 (1966): 85–93. © 1966 American
Chemical Society, and The Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. Denis Dutton and
Michael Krausz (The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1981),
91–108, all rights reserved.
148 michael polanyi
success lives on in his discovery and is shared by those who recognize it.
It is reflected in the confidence they place in the reality of that which
has been discovered and in the way in which they sense the depth and
fruitfulness of a discovery.
Any student of science will understand—must understand—what
I mean by these words. But their teachers in philosophy are likely to
raise their eyebrows at such a vague emotional description of scientific
discovery. Yet the great controversy over the Copernican system, which
first established modern science, turned on just such vague emotional
qualities attributed to the system by Nicolaus Copernicus and his fol-
lowers, which proved in their view that the system was real.
Moreover, after Isaac Newton’s confirmation of the Copernican
system, Copernicus and his followers—Kepler and Galileo—were
universally recognized to have been right. For two centuries their
steadfastness in defending science against its adversaries was unques-
tioningly honored. I myself was still brought up on these sentiments.
But at that time some eminent writers were already throwing cold
water on them. Henri Poincaré wrote that Galileo’s insistence that
the earth was really circling round the sun was pointless, since all he
could legitimately claim was that this view was more convenient. The
distinguished physicist, historian, and philosopher, Pierre Duhem, went
further and concluded that it was the adversaries of Copernicus and his
followers who had recognized the true meaning of science, which the
Copernicans had misunderstood. While this extreme form of modern
positivism is no longer widely held today, I see no essential alternative
to it emerging so far.
Let us look then once more at the facts. Copernicus discovered the
solar system by signs which convinced him. But these signs convinced
few others. For the Copernican system was far more complicated than
that of Ptolemy: it was a veritable jungle of ad hoc assumptions. More-
over, the attribution of physical reality to the system met with serious
mechanical objections and also involved staggering assumptions about
the distance of the fixed stars. Yet Copernicus claimed that his system
had unique harmonies which proved it to be real even though he could
describe these harmonies only in a few vague emotional passages.2 He
did not stop to consider how many assumptions he had to make in
formulating his system, nor how many difficulties he ignored in doing
2
De Revolutionibus [On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres] (Nuremberg, 1543), Preface
and bk. 1, chap. 10.
the creative imagination 149
so. Since his vision showed him an outline of reality, he ignored all its
complications and unanswered questions.
Nor did Copernicus remain without followers in his own century.
In spite of its vagueness and its extravagances, his vision was shared
by great scientists like Kepler and Galileo. Admittedly, their discoveries
bore out the reality of the Copernican system, but they could make
these discoveries only because they already believed in the reality of
that system.
We can see here what is meant by attributing reality to a scientific
discovery. It is to believe that it refers to no chance configuration of
things, but to a persistent connection of certain features, a connection
which, being real, will yet manifest itself in numberless ways, inexhaust-
ibly. It is to believe that it is there, existing independently of us, and
that for that reason its consequences can never be fully predicted.
Our knowledge of reality has, then, an essentially indeterminate
content: it deserves to be called a vision. The vast indeterminacy of the
Copernican vision showed itself in the fact that discoveries made later,
in the light of this vision, would have horrified its author. Copernicus
would have rejected the elliptic planetary paths of Kepler and, like-
wise, the extension of terrestrial mechanics to the planets by Galileo
and Newton.3 Kepler noted this by saying that Copernicus had never
realized the riches which his theory contained.4
This vision, the vision of a hidden reality, which guides a scientist
in his quest, is a dynamic force. At the end of the quest the vision is
becalmed in the contemplation of the reality revealed by a discovery;
but the vision is renewed and becomes dynamic again in other scientists
and guides them to new discoveries. I shall now try to show how both
the dynamic and the static phases of a scientific vision are due to the
strength of the imagination guided by intuition. We shall understand
then both the grounds on which established scientific knowledge rests
and the powers by which scientific discovery is achieved.
I have pursued this problem for many years by considering science
as an extension of ordinary perception. When I look at my hand and
move it about, it would keep changing its shape, its size, and its color
but for my power of seeing the joint meaning of a host of rapidly
changing clues, and seeing that this joint meaning remains unchanged.
3
Ibid., bk. 1, chap. 4.
4
See H. Dingle, The Scientific Adventure (London: Pitman, 1952), 46.
150 michael polanyi
image switches round to the way we normally see it. But some more
recent observations have shown that this interpretation is false.
It happened, for example, that a person perfectly trained to get
around with upside-down spectacles was shown a row of houses from
a distance, and he was then asked whether he saw the houses right side
up or upside down. The question puzzled the subject and he replied
after a moment that he had not thought about the matter before, but
that now that he was asked about it he found that he saw the houses
upside down.5
Such a reply shows that the visual image of the houses has not turned
back to normal; it has remained inverted, but the inverted image no
longer means to the subject that the houses themselves are upside down.
The inverted image has been reconnected to other sensory clues, to
touch and sound and weight. These all hang together with the image
once more, and hence, though the image remains inverted, the subject
can again find his way by it safely. A new way of seeing things rightly has
been established. And since the meaning of the upside-down image has
changed, the term ‘upside down’ has lost its previous meaning, so that
now it is confusing to inquire whether something is seen upside down
or right side up. The new kind of right seeing can be talked about only
in terms of a new vocabulary.
We see how the wearer of inverting spectacles reorganizes scrambled
clues into a new coherence. He again sees objects, instead of meaning-
less impressions. He again sees real things, which he can pick up and
handle, which have weights pulling in the right direction and make
sounds that come from the place at which he sees them. He has made
sense out of chaos.
In science, I find the closest parallel to this perceptual achievement
in the discovery of relativity. Einstein has told the story of how from
the age of sixteen, he was obsessed by the following kind of specula-
tions.6 Experiments with falling bodies were known to give the same
results on board a ship in motion as on solid ground. But what would
happen to the light which a lamp would emit on board a moving ship?
5
See F. W. Snyder and N. H. Pronko, Vision with Spatial Inversion (Wichita, Kans.:
University of Wichita Press, 1952). For fuller evidence and its interpretation in the
sense given here, see H. Kottenhoff, “Was ist richtiges Sehen mit Umkehrbrillen und in welchem
Sinne stellt sich das Sehen um?” Psychologia Universalis 5 (1961).
6
See P. A. Schilpp, ed., Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist (New York: Tudor, 1951), 53.
152 michael polanyi
Supposing the ship moved fast enough, would it overtake the beams of
its own light, as a bullet overtakes its own sound by crossing the sonic
barrier? Einstein thought that this was inconceivable, and, persisting
in this assumption, he eventually succeeded in renewing the concep-
tions of space and time in a way which would make it inconceivable
for the ship to overtake, however slightly, its own light rays. After this,
questions about a definite span of time or space became meaningless
and confusing—exactly as questions of ‘above’ and ‘below’ became
meaningless and confusing to a subject who had adapted his vision to
inverting spectacles.
It is no accident that it is the most radical innovation in the history
of science that appears most similar to the way we acquire the capacity
for seeing inverted images rightly. For only a comprehensive problem
like relativity can require that we organize such basic conceptions as
we do in learning to see rightly through inverting spectacles. Relativity
alone involves conceptual innovations as strange and paradoxical as
those we make in righting an inverted vision.
The experimental verifications of relativity have shown that the
coherence discerned by Einstein was real. One of these confirmations
has a curious history. Einstein had assumed that a light source would
never overtake a beam sent out by it, a fact that had already been
established before by Michelson and Morley. In his autobiography,
Einstein says that he made this assumption intuitively from the start.
But this account failed to convince his contemporaries, for intuition was
not regarded as legitimate ground for knowledge. Textbooks of physics
therefore described Einstein’s theory as his answer to the experiments of
Michelson. When I tried to put the record right by accepting Einstein’s
claim that he had intuitively recognized the facts already demonstrated
by Michelson, I was attacked and ridiculed by Professor Grünbaum
who argued that Einstein must have known of Michelson’s experiments,
since he could not otherwise have based himself on the facts established
by these experiments.7
However, if science is a generalized form of perception, Einstein’s
story of his intuition is clear enough. He had started from the principle
that it is impossible to observe absolute motion in mechanics, and when
he came across the question whether this principle holds also when
light is emitted, he felt that it must still hold, but he could not quite
7
See A. Grünbaum, Philosophical Problems of Space and Time (New York: Knopf,
1963), 378–385.
the creative imagination 153
ultimate reach and that it would prove worth the torment of its pursuit;
and again, Einstein proved right. Kepler too might reasonably have
concluded, after some five years of vain efforts, that he was wasting
his time, but he persisted and proved right.
The power by which such long-range assessments are made may
be called a strategic intuition. It is practiced every day on a high level
of responsibility in industrial research laboratories. The director of
such a laboratory does not usually make inventions, but is responsible
for assessing the value of problems suggested to him, be it from out-
side or from members of his laboratory. For each such problem the
director must jointly estimate the chances of its successful pursuit, the
value of its possible solution, and also the cost of achieving it. He
must compare this combination with the joint assessment of the same
characteristics for rival problems. On these grounds he has to decide
whether the pursuit of a problem should be undertaken or not, and
if undertaken, what grade of priority should be given to it in the use
of available resources.
The scientist is faced with similar decisions. The kind of intuition
which points out problems to him cannot tell him which problem to
choose. He must be able to estimate the gap separating him from discov-
ery, and he must also be able roughly to assess whether the importance
of a possible discovery would warrant the investment of the powers
and resources needed for its pursuit. Without this kind of strategic
intuition, he would waste his opportunities on wild goose chases and
soon be out of a job.
The kind of intuition I have recognized here is clearly quite different
from the supreme immediate knowledge called intuition by Gottfried
Leibniz or Benedict (Baruch) Spinoza or Edmund Husserl. It is a skill
for guessing with a reasonable chance of guessing right, a skill guided
by an innate sensibility to coherence, improved by schooling. The fact
that this faculty often fails does not discredit it; a method for guessing
10 percent above average chance on roulette would be worth millions.
But to know what to look for does not lead us to the power to find
it. That power lies in the imagination.
I call all thoughts of things that are not present, or not yet present—
or perhaps never to be present—acts of the imagination. When I
intend to lift my arm, this intention is an act of my imagination. In this
case imagining is not visual but muscular. An athlete keyed up for a
high jump is engaged in an intense act of muscular imagination. But
even in the effortless lifting of an arm, we can recognize a conscious
156 michael polanyi
nometer, the frequency of the twitches shot up to about six times their
normal rate.8
This is the mechanism to which I ascribe the evocation of helpful
clues by the scientist’s imagination in the pursuit of an inquiry. But we
have to remember here that scientific problems are not definite tasks.
The scientist knows his aim only in broad terms and must rely on his
sense of deepening coherence to guide him to discovery. He must keep
his imagination fixed on these growing points and force his way to what
lies hidden beyond them. We must see how this is done.
Take once more the example of the way we discover how to see
rightly through inverting spectacles. We cannot aim specifically at
reconnecting sight, touch, and hearing. Any attempt to overcome
spatial inversion by telling ourselves that what we see above is really
below may actually hinder our progress, since the meaning of the
words we would use is inappropriate. We must go on groping our way
by sight and touch, and learn to get about in this way. Only by keep-
ing our imagination fixed on the global result we are seeking can we
induce the requisite sensory reintegration and the accompanying
conceptual innovation.
No quest could have been more indeterminate in its aim than
Einstein’s inquiry, which led to the discovery of relativity. Yet he has
told how during all the years of his inquiry, “there was a feeling of
direction, of going straight towards something definite. Of course,”
he said, “it is very hard to express that feeling in words; but it was
definitely so, and clearly to be distinguished from later thoughts about
the rational form of the solution.” We meet here the integration of
still largely unspecifiable elements into a gradually narrowing context,
the coherence of which has not yet become explicit.
The surmises made by Kepler during six years of toil before hitting
on the elliptical path of Mars were often explicit. But Arthur Koestler
has shown that Kepler’s distinctive guiding idea, to which he owed his
success, was the firm conviction that the path of the planet Mars was
somehow determined by a kind of mechanical interaction with the
8
See R. F. Hefferline, et al., “Escape and Avoidance Conditioning in Human
Subjects without Their Observation of the Response,” Science 130 (1959): 1338–1339;
R. F. Hefferline, “Learning Theory in Clinical Psychology,” in Experimental Foundations
of Clinical Psychology, ed. A. J. Bachrach (New York: Basic Books, 1962).
158 michael polanyi
9
See Arthur Koestler, The Sleepwalkers (London: Hutchinson, 1959).
10
Ibid., 334.
11
Ibid., 316.
12
Michael Polanyi, Personal Knowledge (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958),
150–160.
the creative imagination 159
13
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1961).
the creative imagination 161
14
See Schilpp, Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist, 49.
162 michael polanyi
F. E. Sparshott
This essay does not seek to anatomize the creative process, but looks at
the credentials of the very idea of such a process in the field of poetry.
It is in three parts, somewhat loosely interrelated. The first part inquires
into the legitimacy of inquiring into the ‘creative process’; the second
describes some aspects of my own experience, to see whether anything
in the processes of my creating deserves to be called a creative process;
and the third asks why one should try to effect a union between such
disparate concepts as those of creation and process.
II
It may seem reasonable that someone who has both published exten-
sively on aesthetic theory and made a public profession of poetry should
be asked to testify from personal experience on the creative process.
Yet a poet’s first impulse when asked how he writes poems is usually to
resist the question. ‘With pencil on paper,’ he will say; or ‘in English’;
or ‘with difficulty’; and so on. These may be truths, but the questioner
is likely to feel they are the wrong truths. Yet why should these not
be the only truths there are? Why should there be a further question?
Anything that ends in a poem must be a poetic process, and anything
that ends in an original poem must be a creative process. What more
could one say? A way of writing should have no interest for the public
independent of what is written and published, and when the worth of
1
Reprinted from Philosophy and Literature 1 (Dearborn: The University of Michigan
Press, 1977), reprinted in The Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. D. Dutton and
M. Krausz (The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1981), 47–73,
all rights reserved.
166 f. e. sparshott
you raise your arm? Philosophers have liked to ask that question, and
conclude that though the arm-raiser may invent or discover means, pro-
cedures, or re-descriptions, sooner or later he must come to something
that he admits he just does. Otherwise he would never get his arm up.
One might postulate an ‘arm-raising process,’ just as one speaks of a
creative process, as a fancy way of saying that people just raise their
arms, as poets just write poems, without being able to say altogether
how. A poet is someone to whom writing a poem has become some-
thing as intimately familiar as raising his arm, the difference being that
what he is intimately familiar with is the way of doing it that he has
developed for himself.
In this more reasonable frame of mind, one can after all say some-
thing more general about the creative process. How does the poet
think of something to write about? The answer must be: it just comes
to him. And how does it come to him? Maybe somebody brings it.
Bridegrooms evoke epithalamia as editors elicit articles. But if nobody
brings anything, if there is no commission or request, how does it come
to him? And now the inexperienced or very infrequent writer cannot
say. It simply does. That is exactly what it is to be an inexperienced or
infrequent writer, that there is no set condition on which he writes. But
the experienced writer can say. He keeps on the watch for occasions,
seeks them out. He scrutinizes his world for occasions of just such poems
as he knows how to write. And how does he recognize such an occa-
sion? Because he sees in it the possibility of just such development as
lies within the scope of his practice. Again, that has to be exactly what
it is to be an experienced writer. To have experience is nothing other
than to be able to recognize and exploit occasions for skill. It might be
thought that what this describes is the practice of the unoriginal and
uncreative writer, but it is not so. Even the most astonishing innova-
tor astonishes in the sum of his work, or the total development of his
practice, or in one or two works that are new departures, and not in
each work taken singly in relation to the others. On the other hand,
the experience of the poet is not that of the farmer. The farmer must
recognize the right day for grubbing the rutabagas, and it is the same
day that another farmer would recognize, and would be an equally
good day for anyone placed as he is placed to get them in. But what
the poet has to recognize is the proper occasion for the exercise of his
own style and no other, and it is rarely that even a sympathetic poet
can suggest to another what such an occasion would be.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 169
When the poet has thought of something to write about, how does he
know what to write about it? The answer is almost as before: it comes
to him. But not quite as before, because it must already have come to
him. In recognizing an occasion or an opportunity, he must have recog-
nized it as an occasion for doing this or that. But we may set that aside,
for unless the completed work springs to his mind ready-made there is
work yet to do. How does he know how to do this work? It comes to
him. And how does it come? Again, it may be brought, or some of it
may. It is possible that someone should tell him what meter to use, what
rhymes, what analogies, and so on to any extent. His ignorance may
be thus aided, his expertness thus tested. If I give a child a paint-by-
numbers set I suggest at once that he shall paint, what he shall paint,
and how he shall paint it; and a less explicit variant on this procedure
might stimulate production without quite excluding creation. But, of
course, any part played by such intrusion is outside our interest when
it is specifically the creative process that engages our attention.
Given a donnée, then, how does the knowledge of how to develop it
come to the poet? Once more, the poet who lacks experience cannot say.
He can know how to follow a rule, but not how to depart from it, and
if he departs he must do it in fear and trembling or in foolhardiness.
With the experienced poet it must be otherwise. Strictly, he cannot say
how it comes to him, for anything he could say would amount to a rule
he could cite. But, though he cannot describe it fully, there is nothing
he knows better than his own way of proceeding. That, and nothing
else, is what his art is. He knows what to do next, and this is not what
the rule of his art prescribes but what determines his style. And the
truly original and creative artist is the one whose style determines a
way of developing and changing his ways of proceeding themselves,
who sees in the next occasion for his art not an opportunity to do what
he knows how to do but an opportunity to do what he knows to be
the next thing.
But how does the poet know it will continue to come to him? The
artist’s perpetual fear that the sources of his inspiration will suddenly
dry up seems real and reasonable, but there is something factitious
about it, as though a man were to fear he might forget how to speak
his native tongue—or how to raise his arm. Such things do happen.
But in the ordinary course of events, as Aristotle remarks in oppos-
ing the suggestion that a man might ‘forget’ his moral principles, one
does not forget what one does all the time. I forget my French, which
170 f. e. sparshott
I speak seldom, but not my English, which I speak every hour and in
which I frame all my thoughts.
Here is the heart of the matter. The artist, the poet, is to be known by
his sustained habit of attention. As he scrutinizes his world for themes,
so he looks ceaselessly up and down for ways of proceeding. His style
is a style of search, not a habit of acceptance. His mind is a restless
scanner, an inward rat. The other day an inventor was interviewed on
television and asked if he might not run out of ideas. He said he would
not. “I think all the time. If you think for forty hours a week, you’ll
think of something.” The layman who asks the writer how he gets his
ideas seems to think that such ideas would be forcing themselves spon-
taneously on a mind as idle as his own. But nothing is more evident
to the artist than that he is working at his art, and the layman is not.
What poets have most evidently in common is not a mysterious contact
with secret springs, and certainly not any shared mental process, but
simply a steady application to the actual writing of poetry. Anybody
can be a poet who really wants to be, though wanting will not make
him a good one. What the layman does not do, and probably could
not do, is bring himself to attend steadily, day after day and year after
year, to the business of the art.
To ask a poet to describe the creative process is to ask him to
formulate a rule, or something that will do in place of a rule, by fol-
lowing which any idle ninny could make a poem. But writing poems
is something idle ninnies cannot expect to do without forfeiting their
idleness and ninnyhood. A poet is not an idle ninny who just happens
to own a sort of magical sausage-machine that he might lend (or of
which he might deliver the patent) to his neighbor, like lending him a
power-mower. If there is a creative process it cannot be a substitute for
intelligent work. It must be a way such work is done.
III
Talk of the creative process, it seems, covers two questions the poet
may be asked: how he came to bend his attention steadily in that unre-
munerative direction, and how he comes to write this or that poem. If
I now answer these questions for my part, it is not because I wish to
speak for ‘the poet,’ since each must answer for himself, but because
what I think about these matters must reflect what has happened to me,
and the way I interpret my experience must be colored by my theories.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 171
My answers will be honest, within limits, but I cannot answer for their
truth. The way I now recall my life may not be at all the way it was.
In my assumption of the vatic mantle—a suitably portentous phrase,
stressing the self-image rather than the work to be done; and a mantle,
unlike a persona, covers the contours but leaves the face exposed—I
recognize five stages and look to a possible sixth.
The first stage was my realization that the poetry we were taught at
school was something I understood better than my teachers—or rather,
understood in a way they did not. I had a feel for what was going on,
like someone watching players at a game he knows. That was when
I was a child, eleven or twelve. The second stage came a year or two
years later. It was the realization that I knew how poetry worked, what
governed the choice to say this rather than that. The poems I was
then writing were not good ones, even by the standards appropriate
to children’s verse, but they were rooted in a confidence that I knew
what I was doing—a confidence that I have never lost, and have never
experienced in any other form of activity, even in those in which my
practice seems objectively to have been more successful.
I have sharp and vivid recollections of the occasions on which the
two realizations I have mentioned came to me—or rather, perhaps, of
the moments that have come to stand for these discoveries. The differ-
ence between the two stages thus marked seems very real and evident
to me, though I am less sure that I can put the sense of it into words:
it is the difference between finding something congenial and finding it
rational, between a feel for the whole and a grasp of its workings. But
it may after all be that the real difference is between the two images I
retain, and the two incidents they purport to stand for.
The third stage begins with the recognition, at fifteen or so, that
poetry was what I came into the world to do: not something I could
do, but something it was my business to do. R. G. Collingwood, in his
Autobiography, tells how the conviction that philosophy was his business
was precipitated in him at the age of eight, though he did not then
know what the business was.2 I recognize in his account something
akin to my own experience, and suspect it may be a common one in
the onset of prophetic vocations.
The fourth stage is not linked to any date or event. It was the realiza-
tion, somewhere in my twenties, that it was not in me to be a first-rate
2
R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography (London/N. Y.: Oxford University Press,
1939).
172 f. e. sparshott
poet; specifically, that my gift was not such that it would be rational to
organize my life around it or sacrifice all other pursuits and interests to
it. I have called this a realization; but it may rather have been a decision,
or even the entry on a new style of self-dramatization. But a decision
or self-assessment was in any case called for. It is part of our romantic
orthodoxy that devotion to any art must conflict (or demands readiness
to conflict) with moral and social obligations; and even without that
orthodoxy everyone must confront the question of what weight each of
his major concerns is to have in the economy of his life. So I decided
to be a minor poet. Poetry would be something interstitial, something
I did when not preoccupied. But this was a change of policy, not of
attitude; poetry still was, and still is, the only thing I took completely
seriously. But I encased my seriousness with irony and formed my life
around the inwardly farcical but outwardly respectable career of the
academic philosopher.
The fifth stage began in 1958, when at the prompting and with the
help of a friend, I began to publish my work. From this point, poetry
was no longer a private affair, a matter of my self-image, but part of
my ordinary engagement in the world. Publication normalizes poetry.
A sixth stage would begin if I were to begin to write, or to believe
myself to be able to write, extremely good poems. Poetry would then
be something I would think it proper to give things up for. But this
does not seem likely.
Such is my poetic process (wholesale). There seems to be a clear
enough pattern to it: first seeing that a practice is congenial, then see-
ing it as a field for confident operation, then the sense that practice in
this field is not merely possible but called for, and at the same time the
recognition of the associated role and the decision to present oneself
in one of its versions; and finally, in maturity, the recognition that the
role is to be played in a certain fashion and under certain conditions
suggested by an adult assessment of social reality and one’s own place
in it. But this clear pattern turns out not to be very interesting, because
on inspection it proves to be one that everyone must follow who is to
adopt a career on the basis of its attraction rather than because it is
socially accessible. In fact, it seems likely that an analogous path must
be traced even by those who merely drift along the line of least resis-
tance into a hereditary niche. It too must seem at first merely congenial,
because one has grown up with it; then feasible and intelligible; then,
as one confronts adulthood, it must begin to figure as what one is going
to do with one’s life; then, as one matures in one’s occupation, one
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 173
Of a very few poems I cannot say how they originated because they
appeared spontaneously completed, requiring only to be written down
and slightly revised. These poems do not seem on the whole to be better
or worse than those in whose genesis deliberation played a greater part,
and differ from them in only two ways: that they contain rather more
banal Freudian imagery (of pegs and holes, birds and oceans), and that
they tend to contain weak elements that for a long time escape notice
or resist revision. These spontaneous poems seem neither more nor less
characteristic of me than the others. And indeed one does not see why
any great gulf should be fixed between the willed and the unwilled.
Someone who habitually writes verse might be expected to develop such
a facility that he could and sometimes would do so without thinking
about it, much as an experienced driver can direct his car through
heavy traffic without giving any thought to where he is going.
It is often thought that the operations of the unconscious mind in
composition (to which the ‘instantaneous’ or ‘spontaneous’ poetizing
I have referred to might be thought to attest) are accompanied by
agonies of ‘incubation’ and other psychological disturbances, and that
these are an integral part of the creative process. My own experience
has been that such pains, irritabilities, abstractions, fatigues, and other
signs of unconscious effort are not particularly associated with poetry
or creative writing. They occur at a certain phase in the composition
of philosophical writings, or the solution of personal or administrative
problems, or any complex matter. As many have reported, the phase is
that at which a problem is mooted but the terms in which it is formu-
lated are too nebulous, or too complex, to repay systematic problem-
solving, any attempt at systematic or step-by-step procedures being at
once frustrated by the conviction that the terms of the problem are
unclear or just wrong. It is then that one waits and agonizes, contracts
a migraine, quarrels with one’s family, goes for long walks, dreams, or
tosses in insomnia. These distressing episodes seem in my own experi-
ence to be related to the phase in the problem to be solved, and to have
no connection with antecedent or current events in my personal life.
The popular image of ‘the oyster and the pearl,’ according to which
such distresses bear witness to the nacreous covering of an intrusive
irritant in one’s psyche, seems based on an interpretation of only one
class of cases—and, I suspect, a conjectural interpretation at that. The
painful incubation marks rather the phase in problem solving that calls
for intensive work of a kind one cannot consciously do.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 175
3
It is my good fortune that my productive processes are properly synchronized with
anticipated deadlines. Many unfortunate artists and writers are so constituted that the
passing of a deadline is needed to initiate the process, just as some people are unable
to set out for the opera before curtain-time.
176 f. e. sparshott
have been four periods in my life when I wrote verse regularly, a poem
or a large part of one more or less everyday. In Housman’s case, these
periods were by his own account times of excitement, answering no
doubt to gusts of inspirational afflatus or surges of hormonal flow. In
my case, no such disturbance is easy to discern, though of course there
is no knowing what an analyst or a lie detector might dredge up.
The first of these periods of regular production, from January 1
to the middle of March, 1944, was undertaken as a matter of policy
in the context of adoption of the role of verse-writer, the date fixed
in advance—one begins diaries with the new year. So any relation to
personal disturbance must at least have been mediated.
The second period, in January 1966, had a double occasion that
again called for no troubling of the waters by angels. In the first place,
a hiatus between teaching engagements had left my mind free from
preoccupations for the first time in years; in the second place, recent
publication of a volume had depleted my stock of unpublished poems.
Again, the decision to go into regular production on a certain date and
for a certain time was taken beforehand. On this occasion I confirmed
that I could, given a clear mind, sit down with a sheet of paper and be
sure that in no more than an hour I would certainly have come up with
a poem or a substantial part of one; though that does not mean that I
did not, or need not, keep on the watch for the rest of the day.
The third period of regular composition, from late August to October,
1969, was different. A reading of Matsuo Bassho –’s Journey to the Deep North
reactivated an old interest in Japanese verse and occasioned the project
of writing a series of occasional poems in Japanese forms, at least one
every day. These, being very short, could be composed in short times
of peace, without needing protracted freedom from preoccupations.
Not surprisingly in view of the nature of the initial stimulus, the series
of poems that resulted tended to be on the theme of travel, but in fact
it turned out to be more cohesive than that and ended in a sequence
that took on the evident though unheralded character of an end. One
might therefore postulate some internal unconscious dynamic governing
the form of the whole that some form of structural or psychological
analysis might lay bare. However, the poems did not, as a sequence or
individually, come from any felt disturbance or other specific experience
other than that of reading a book that suggested a model.
The fourth period, from June to October 1970, presents a more
complex case. Superficially, the situation was as in 1966. The recent
publication of a book had depleted my unpublished store, and the start
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 177
IV
The phrase the creative process is used in two different ways. Some-
times it is used generically to refer to all processes, whatever they may
be, whose outcome meets some appropriate criteria for originality. At
other times it is used to refer to some specific process whose character-
istic outcome is supposed to be original work. It is not always clear in
which sense the phrase is being used, and the distinction is not always
recognized. Yet the distinction must be made, for if original work is
ever produced it must be produced somehow or other and the phrase
cannot lack application in the former sense; but it does not follow that
the phrase has any application in its latter sense.
Three different accounts of the creative process have achieved some
currency. One, associated with Paul Valéry,4 and ultimately inspired by
Edgar Allan Poe,5 is exemplified in Part II of this paper: it reduces to
saying that some possible component or aspect of a poem serves as
a starting point and is then elaborated, partly heuristically and partly
systematically. Since all this says is that one must start and then continue,
this is clearly taking creative process in the former of the senses distin-
4
For example, Paul Valéry, Aesthetics (New York: Pantheon, 1964), 130ff.
5
E. A. Poe, “The Philosophy of Composition,” Collected Works (New York: Crowell,
1902), vol. 14.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 179
guished above. It tells nothing about how poems are made, except that
they are poems and they are made. A second account of the creative
process is associated with Robert Graves,6 T. S. Eliot,7 and a host of
romantic writers.8 A schematized version of it might go as follows. First
comes the original formulation of a problem or conceiving of a theme
(preceded possibly by the poet finding himself in an excited, troubled,
or sensitized condition). Second comes a period of random search not
directed by the will, unconscious incubation, and so on. Third comes
a flash of insight, a relief from suspenseful tension, a sense of how
things will go together. Fourth comes the deliberate elaboration of
this insight; and fifth is the criticism and refinement of the elaborated
solution. This five-stage model will be referred to from now on as ‘the
standard version,’ and seems to take creative process in its second sense,
for it appears to describe a psychological process whose correlation with
creative solutions to problems or original achievements would need to
be established empirically.9 The third account of the creative process
to achieve currency is that elaborated by Arthur Koestler from a hint
of Sigmund Freud’s.10 Here, creativity is attributed to the unforeseen
interaction of two or more thought-patterns previously elaborated
independently. But does this take creative process in the former or the
latter of the senses we distinguished? It might be either. Although it
seems merely to say how originality actually comes about in typical
cases, it might be construed to mean that in every truly original work
one must be able to find a complexity of the kind indicated, so that
we are merely performing a logical analysis that must in some form or
6
Robert Graves, The Crowning Privilege (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1959), 214.
7
T. S. Eliot, “Tradition and the Individual Talent,” in The Sacred Wood (London:
Methuen, 1920).
8
Cf. F. E. Sparshott, “Xanthippe,” in Looking for Philosophy (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s
University Press, 1972).
9
At a recent general meeting of the League of Canadian Poets at Fredericton,
N.B., the three contributors to a panel on the writing of a poem gave accounts all
of which conformed to the following pattern. The poet is attracted by a large public
or personal theme, which seems to call for a poem, but sees no way of setting about
it. Then, an incident in the poet’s life reminds of him of an incident connected with
the troublesome theme, and in a state of excitement, he writes a shortish poem or
fragment interpreting one in terms of the other. On the basis of this he is then able
to work systematically at the large theme. The pattern itself seems as interesting as
the coincidence: this might be a typical way of finding an authentic mode of entry
into a major theme.
10
See Arthur Koestler, The Act of Creation (New York: Macmillan, 1964), and the
article by Koestler contained in this volume. [“This volume” refers to the original
publication in which this chapter appeared.—Eds.]
180 f. e. sparshott
11
Aristotle, Poetics vii, 1450b26–31.
12
The notion of an absolute end brings an analogous inexplicability. How can
anything have no consequences? Only in the hererocosms, the separate universes, of
art, can an end be a completion that is not also the beginning of something.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 181
13
See R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1938).
182 f. e. sparshott
sense the ‘same feeling’ that he began with;14 but there is not, because
the end has the status of an absolute beginning in the light of which
earlier phases are of no account, sublated, aufgehoben, or something.
And what is transmitted from artist to public is supposed not to be in
a code or to admit of decoding, because the artist’s encoding was also
a deciphering and all paths of transmission are magically bypassed.
This is strange stuff indeed, but the strangeness may be demanded by
the nature of the case. Attempts to apply information theory to art
seems to fail just because they see no need for such oddness.15 They
simply take it for granted that a work of art is the encoded version
of a pre-existing message that the artist wishes to transmit. It is only
on this supposition that the concept of redundancy can be pressed
into service to give precision to the notion of style. But if in fact there
was no original message—for otherwise the process would have been
reproductive rather than creative—there is no way it is transmitted,
no code, no bits of information, no redundancy. The model cannot
be applied at all.
Where there is no initial message to be encoded and transmitted, we
cannot tell message from noise. The creative process is thus necessarily
indeterminate. Yet it must be strongly ordered, since the end is ordered.
Vincent Tomas has spelled out how this is possible, in an account that
we could crudely adapt to the terms of Part I of this paper as follows.16
The work must start from a donnée that has to be regarded as gratuitous,
an absolute starting point. But the artist perceives it as structured in
a way that permits and calls for a line of further development. It is
fidelity to this line of development that serves to regulate his continuing
creation. Normally, it is the author’s style, which includes his style of
changing his style that serves as a matrix both for the structures origi-
nally discerned and for the continuations suggested, though of course
it may happen that the development envisaged is in some ways, even
in many ways, unprecedented. In any case what serves as controlling
factor is the present condition of the uncompleted work in the light of
the possibilities originally contemplated. But we have to add that every
recognizable intermediate stage in the work’s progress serves as a new
14
See, however, Collingwood’s Essays on Philosophical Method (Oxford: Clarendon,
Press, 1933) for an explication of the patterns of thought involved.
15
Cf. A. A. Moles, Information Theory and Esthetic Perception (Urbana: University of
Illinois Press, 1966).
16
Vincent Thomas, “Creativity in Art,” Philosophical Review 67 (1958): 1–15.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 183
17
Conformably with this recognition, Mikel Dufrenne, who speaks of the artist as
responding to the call of the as yet uncreated work, describes it as an “indeterminate”
call. See Mikel Dufrenne, Phenomenology of Aesthetic Experience (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 1973), 35.
184 f. e. sparshott
18
For example, see John Hospers, “The Concept of Artistic Expression,” Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society (1954): 55.
19
Ruth L. Bunzel, The Pueblo Potter (New York: Columbia University Press, 1929).
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 185
20
Here is an example plucked from the remainder table: “It could be argued . . . that
the painting was a kind of relic, a kind of certificate or guarantee that certain activities
had taken place previously which you were not there to witness.” Donald Carroll and
Edward Lucie-Smith, Movements in Modern Art (New York: Horizon, 1973), 132.
186 f. e. sparshott
truly original artist may be misprized until familiarity has revealed the
right way to look at his work, the perspective from which his patterns
are visible. We are therefore tempted to look to something other than
what we find in the work for testimony to its seriousness or even to
its worth. This extraneous aid could be the testimony of an informed
critic, or the artist’s proved reputation won by work in a more familiar
mode. But it could also be something extraneous in the production of
his work, such as his labor and eventual satisfaction; or, perhaps rather
less extraneous, the occurrence of a process that we deem likely on
the face of it to issue in serious work. We may think of the creative
process as guaranteeing at least some sort of novelty, and, if the novelty
for which it is a recipe is by no means the originality of the highest
form of art, our description of it may serve as a guarantee that in a
serious and experienced worker the outcome can be neither hackwork
nor a mere flash in the brain pan. Even so qualified an assurance
may be of comfort to the humble camp-follower of the arts in these
difficult days.
If occurrence of the sort of process sketched in our standard ver-
sion can be taken as presumptive evidence of seriousness, part of the
reason may be that what the version describes is what we think ought
to take place when something truly original is done. It may be that
the standard version and its variants are popular, not because there is
any reason to think that anything of the sort often or ever takes place,
but because it seems fitting: a work of art is as if it were the outcome
of such a process. As human beings, we feel able to pronounce on the
fittingness and congruence of human affairs and attitudes. We do not
feel the need to have recourse to the behavioral sciences to assure us
that our sense of how life goes has empirical backing. On the contrary,
we feel free to deride these sciences if they either otiosely confirm or
absurdly conflict with our lifelong experience of being human.
It seems then that our standard version may function less as an
inductive generalization than as an expression of our untutored and
uncriticized sense of what ought to be the case, our way of imagining
what it must be to create. It is but one step more to claim for it the
status of a myth. Plato in his Symposium metaphorically describes artis-
tic and intellectual creation as ‘giving birth in beauty.’21 Our standard
account may be construed as an explanation of this metaphor. The
triggering experience answers to insemination, the initial formulation
21
Plato, Symposium 206b–212a.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 187
22
See M. H. Abrams, The Mirror and the Lamp (New York: Oxford University Press,
1953), chap. 8.
23
The phrase unconscious incubation seems to have had its original home in Wil-
liam James’s The Varieties of Religious Experience (London: Longman’s, Green and Co.,
1902), with the phenomena of religious conversion.
188 f. e. sparshott
the two starting points are in principle separate and that each is a true
beginning. The transposition of the creative process from psychological
and genetical to analytical terms is exemplified in a vigorous argument
by Monroe C. Beardsley, who urges that what we call creativity and
originality is properly to be located within the work of art itself, and is
the emergence of complex resultant qualities that could not have been
inferred from an enumeration of the constituents and their relations:
this non-inferrability is popularly construed as unpredictability, put into
a temporal frame of reference, and projected back onto the artist—as
though works of art were produced by human beings instead of appear-
ing, as we all know, ready made on the walls of galleries.24
Although proponents of the old ‘new’ criticism may be contented with
an account of creativity and originality in analytical or phenomenologi-
cal terms, there are reasons why artists and cultural critics cannot be.
There is an important difference between human and divine creation:
the Creator’s claim to originality is (in orthodox theology) unimpeach-
able, but human beings must establish their bona fides. Creation, prop-
erly, is the production of new being, of something that did not before
exist but now has a being of its own and in its own right. The concept
of creation is then basically less that of process and outcome than that
of an achievement. What matters is that there should now be something
that owes its being to another, God or man, but in itself is perfectly
real. In the paradigm case of the divine creation, this suffices: before,
there was no world, but now there is a world, and God will answer for
it. But when we speak of human achievements an ambiguity creeps in.
With half our minds we think that achievement, creation and original-
ity are relative to their point of origin. We do not deny originality or
creativity to either Charles Darwin or Alfred Russel Wallace on the
other’s account, and there is a sense in which Darwin’s achievement
would have been no less if Wallace had reached his conclusions a decade
before but left them unpublished. So it is that to sustain a plagiarism
suit the plaintiff must show not only that the form produced by the
alleged plagiarist coincides with the preexisting form, but that he had
access to it. It may be in part because memory is delusive, the external
history of creation often unknown and unverifiable, and the channels
whereby ideas are transmitted manifold and hard to trace, that we like
to invoke a creative process, an agonizing labor that at least shows that
24
Monroe C. Beardsley, “On the Creation of Art,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criti-
cism 23 (1965): 291–305.
every horse has a mouth: a personal poetics 189
the alleged creator did not know he was doing anything so undemand-
ing as plagiarizing. Just so, councilors were at one time summoned to
attend the birth of a prince, lest some low-born brat be smuggled in
a warming-pan; but, if decorum precludes observation of the royal
childbed, some reassurance may be had from the observation that the
Queen was previously pregnant and is pregnant no more, and that the
putative birth was heralded by appropriate groans.
It may be that the status of our standard version is more that of a
parable than of a myth. The hard-headed will say that when the Pueblo
potter says she dreamed her design the real purport of her claim is
that she did not copy it. So it may be that to claim to have undergone
the creative process is but a dramatic way of claiming true authorship.
And why claim true authorship? Copyrights may be involved, and the
artist must live. But that is not all. The value of originality has become
deeply embedded in our whole way of thinking about art and even
about science.25 We think of art in terms of its history. The truest work
of art, perhaps the only true work of art, we think, is one fit to figure
in the history of art: the only true point is a turning point.
25
For an early manifestation cf. Edward Young, Conjectures on Original Composition in
a Letter to the Author of Sir Charles Grandison (London: Printed for A. Millar and R. and
J. Dodsley, 1759).
CHAPTER TEN
Michael Krausz
I work with special handmade brushes. They are made of the hairs of
deer, elk, and fox. They have their own life. After dipped in a solution—
like India ink or dried pigment mixed in water—with a slight pressure
on museum board, they make very fine, thin lines. With greater pressure
a brush’s bulbous base releases a swath of pigment on to the surface.
I usually have a general idea of what the painting will look like. But
the materials take on a life of their own. They suggest their own pos-
sibilities. The unintended spontaneous movements of my fingers and
arms allow brush and pigment to respond as they may. Sometimes the
unintended emergent results are welcome, sometimes not. Sometimes
brush and pigment respond with extreme delicacy, variety, and wit.
Other times they respond with ponderous contortions. Sometimes the
result is a scene that I could not have imagined. Sometimes the scene
provides a space that invites my entry.
As I work on a particular piece, I do so with the foreknowledge of its
place in a series of works. Just as a single work may give rise to emer-
gent features, so too may a series of related works give rise to emergent
features. These features may become apparent when the series is viewed
as a whole, as in a solo exhibition. Creating a given artwork provides
an occasion to discover and explore its emerging scapes.
My art-making has a history closely related to my self-transforma-
tion. In 1971, I had a nondualistic experience in the studio of a friend.
When being surrounded by her large abstract shaped canvases, I sud-
denly experienced myself in the space of the work instead of looking
at it. More than that: I experienced an ‘interpenetration’ of my self
and the space of the painting.1
1
I borrow this apt term from John Dewey, who describes such experiences as: “com-
plete interpenetration of self and the world of objects and events,” in Art as Experience
(New York: Capricorn Books, 1934), 19.
192 michael krausz
2
Wassily Kandinsky elaborates the idea of inner necessity in his book, Concerning the
Spiritual in Art, and Painting in Particular (New York: Wittenborn, Schultz, 1963). See also
my Interpretation and Transformation: Explorations in Art and the Self (Amsterdam: Rodopi,
2006), chap. 9, 10.
3
See J. N. Findlay, “The Perspicuous and the Poignant,” in Aesthetics, ed. Harold
Osborn, ed. (London: Oxford University Press, 1972).
creativity and self-transformation 193
II
4
David Novitz, “Art, Narrative and Human Nature,” Philosophy and Literature 13,
no. 1 (April 1989): 72.
5
Ibid. 65.
6
Ibid. 62.
7
For his discussion of “peak experiences,” see A. H. Maslow, Religions, Values, and
Peak Experiences (New York: Viking Press, 1963). Also, for his discussion of “flow,” see
Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi, Creativity: Flow and the Psychology of Discovery and Invention (New
York: Harper Collins Publisher, 1996).
8
Arthur Danto, Mysticism and Morality (New York: Basic Books, 1972), 110–111
(my emphasis).
creativity and self-transformation 195
9
Alexander Goehr, Independent (1 June 1991), quoted in Anthony Storr, Music and
the Mind (New York: Ballantine books, 1992), 97 (my emphasis).
10
Chang Chung-yuan, Creativity and Taoism: A Study of Chinese Philosophy, Art and Poetry
(New York: Harper Colophon Books, 1970), 203–204 (my emphasis).
11
See Vibha Chaturvedi, “Reflections on the Interpretation of Religious Texts,” in
Interpretation and its Objects: Studies in the Philosophy of Michael Krausz, ed. Andreea Deciu
Ritivoi (Amsterdam: Rodopi Publishers, 2003), 308.
196 michael krausz
12
See Larry Briskman “Creativity and Self-Development: Comments on Michael
Krausz’s ‘Creating and Becoming’ ” unpublished. An abridged version of this paper
was presented at a symposium on “Creating and Becoming,” at the annual meeting
of the Society for Philosophy of Creativity, Eastern Division Meeting of the American
Philosophical Association, Washington, D.C. (28 December, 1978). A version of the
APA presentation was published as Larry Briskman, “Creating and Self-Development:
A Reply to Michael Krausz,” Leonardo 13, no. 4 (Autumn 1980): 323–325.
creativity and self-transformation 197
ity. Yet from such moments of nonduality we can draw inspiration for
subsequent creative activity.
To consider a work’s strengths and weaknesses, criticism and com-
mentary demand looking at works apart from oneself. They must occur
in a dualistic mode. But nondualistic experiences are not outside the
range of creativity. While nonduality can inhibit productivity, we should
not dismiss nonduality as irrelevant to creative processes. It can be an
ingredient of a creative life journey, a part of a larger project of self-
transformation.
III
13
Larry Briskman, “Creative Product and Creative Process in Science and Art,”
The Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. Denis Dutton and Michael Krausz (The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1981), 135. Reprinted in this volume, chap. 2.
198 michael krausz
14
Ibid., 144.
creativity and self-transformation 199
IV
15
Briskman “Creativity and Self-Development,” 4 (my emphasis).
202 michael krausz
16
John Dewey, Art as Experience (New York: Capricorn Books, 1934), 35 (my emphasis).
17
This essay revisits and develops my, “Creating and Becoming” in The Concept of
Creativity in Science and Art, eds. Dutton and Krausz, 187–200. For their helpful comments
and suggestions, I thank Karen Bardsley, Elizabeth D. Boepple, Larry Briskman, Roy
Fitzgerald, Mark Harris, Peter Lamarque, Thomas Leddy, Anne Sclufer, Jill Stauffer,
Ulli Wiesner, and Mary Wiseman.
CHAPTER ELEVEN
Albert Hofstadter
1
Reprinted from The Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. D. Dutton and
M. Krausz (The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague/
Boston/London, 1981), 201–208, all rights reserved.
206 albert hofstadter
new totality of form-content, matter, and spirit, which will enliven the
life process.
This life-quandary is widespread today. The people who are most
involved in it, that is, the younger people who are now confronted with
the task of determining the form and content of their life, experience
the rebellion of life within their own selves, and they find themselves in
profound alienation from much of the traditional culture. So they are
in the midst of the crisis that is characteristic of creativity generally:
the crisis of estrangement, alienation, otherness, difference.
This language of alienation, estrangement, otherness, and difference
brings us directly into touch with the context of dialectical phenomenol-
ogy. If anything is characteristic of the dialectic, it is the appearance of
the phenomenon of alienation or estrangement, or more generally of
difference, opposition, and otherness. These are one half of the story
of the dialectic; the other half is given in the correlative names for
unity: reconciliation, appropriation, and ownness. Hegel says ‘Versöhnung,’
Heidegger ‘Ereignis,’ and both ultimately come to the same thing as
‘appropriation’ and ‘ownness.’ It is ultimately in the structures of own-
ness that human creativity shows itself and its products. The meaning
of creativity lies in the attainment of genuine ownness.
In thinking about creativity we tend to think first of the artist as
creator and his activity as creation. In earlier days one thought first,
rather, of God and of His act of creation. Our present tendency is a
reverberation of the romantic movement in life and art, which placed
the artistic individual at the center, and which put special accent on his
subjectivity as the source of truth rather than on submitting his sub-
jectivity to a reality outside him as foundation of truth. But creativity
belongs everywhere, and perhaps it would be better if we looked more
frequently to spheres outside art for subjects of investigation. We shall
recollect that Whitehead thought creativity to be so pervasive, present
in every pulse of process that gave rise to a new actual entity, that
he declared it to be the first and most universal of all the categories.
Therefore, in what immediately follows, I would like to bring to your
attention, as an instance of creativity a nonartistic matter, the appar-
ently unlikely matter of the master-slave relationship. Since it is one
of the most achieved parts of Hegel’s phenomenology and has been
much examined in recent years, and since it lies at the basis of the
possibility of advanced socialized life, it is of particular interest as a
means of directing our attention to creativity in life and experience
apart from art.
208 albert hofstadter
2
Colin Turnbull, Wayward Servants (Garden City, N.Y.: Natural History Press,
1965).
on the dialectical phenomenology of creativity 209
fraternal within itself, but also, within the confines of a very limited
geography and socio-psychological topography. But all advanced culture
depends on the prior establishment of political power and the relation
of ruler to ruled. Much of human history has lain in the production
and transformation of this relationship towards the point at which
eventually its asymmetry can be entirely removed.
The theme I wish to stress, then, is that the master-slave relation-
ship, as such, is something that is created in the struggle between the
confronting egos as the mode of unity—the mutual appropriation,
reconciliation, or ownness—which sublates (aufhebt—cancels, preserves,
while transcending) the opposition of the two agents, raising them up
into being the subjects of a new totality, with a new content and form,
which gives (albeit only a passing one, nevertheless) a fulfillment to their
mutual need for recognition.
The idea of master-slave, lord-bondsman, was an indispensable
creation in the history of the development of human society, and
it still remains as an indispensable creation in the history of human
individuality. Much of childhood’s suffering, as well as its fulfillment
and security, lies in the recognition it is compelled, by its own weak-
ness, to give to the adult-parent ego, finding its own selfhood in the
maturity, strength, and above all credible authority of the parent. The
suffering is greater when that authority later comes into question and
when, therefore, a new creative art of social appropriation of self and
other is needed—that is, the achievement of a new unified totality of
content, form, and the subjectivity of its own selfhood. This is part of
the search for one’s identity as outcome of the identity crisis and is the
clear counterpart, in the actual struggle for life, of the artist’s search
for artistic identity as he grows out of dependence on earlier forms,
traditions, and masters and finds himself cast into the outsideness and
indeterminateness of new existence.
Let us try to see how the master-slave relationship—despite the
negative attitude we presently have towards the subjection of ruled to
ruler, political subject to despotic king or dictator, serf to lord, slave to
slave owner—was nevertheless an actual creation, a step forward into
novelty and constructive order.
The egos, to begin with, are isolated within themselves; each, outside
the other, is not the other, and the other is not it; they are really differ-
ent. But difference among egos cannot remain as mere otherness: the
different is the strange and alien, and what is strange and alien is, or
rapidly becomes, hostile, an enemy. The further off people are from
210 albert hofstadter
us, the easier it is for us to regard them, and for them to regard us, as
actually or potentially hostile. We approach one another with caution,
for, being distant, without nearness, we are not neighbors, and so it
does not grieve one when the other is mishandled; on the contrary,
even we, who have been educated and disciplined in the values of the
high religions of the East and the West, find it easy enough to take the
position of master to the other as slave, determiner to determined.
The two thus become enemies. It is tempting to think that they could
have started at the very beginning as friends; but one does not know
how to think ‘friend’ except through thinking ‘enemy.’ Friendship needs
the long discipline of living together in the security of a social environ-
ment that cares for both. Enmity needs only the initial encounter of
those who are other to one another.
The two become enemies, however, because they need one another.
For outside the relationship of ego to ego, self to self, the ego cannot
find the ownness it needs in order to be itself. Without the alter ego
the ego is outside the Ereignis—outside the appropriation of being to
being, outside the reconciliation, the Versöhnung, which it needs in order
to come to its own. The step into enmity is already the first step on
the road to the creation of a genuinely human life. Instead of passing
one another by, the two are attracted to each other and in need of one
another. Egos are beings who, being an I, can have a ‘mine.’ And this
means that a further possibility—amazingly new, fecund, fraught with
the deepest potentialities of existence and truth—begins to appear. For,
if an ego can apprehend and appropriate something as mine, it is on
the point of being able to turn around and give itself also as ‘thine.’ It
needs only another ego, in whom it can recognize also the power of
owning, to which it is able to yield.
Both the mine and the thine are necessary for the new unity that
comes about between separate egos who have become enemies. In its
primitiveness each can think first only of possessing the other as its
own, as mine. To possess an other ego as mine means that the other
ego must give itself to me, so that I am its thine. Neither has as yet
learned how to give itself. They know only how to demand and try to
take what is other as their own. Each wants the other to belong to it,
but in the way in which an ego can belong to an ego—that is, by rec-
ognition, acknowledgment, giving of itself to the other (as gift) so that
the other’s self is its own self, its own essence—what is mine is thine,
even to the point of my own self. This is what the one ego wants of the
on the dialectical phenomenology of creativity 211
other; and the struggle to the death to achieve it is itself the creative
process of realizing this new, profound, soul-shaking idea.
Both egos are engaged in this process. The creative agent is neither
the one alone nor the other, but the two of them in a mutual structure
of consciousness of other and of self. There is a We in process of self-
formation, creating itself in and out of the I’s, first by developing in
and through their animosity as alien and estranged, and then by the
struggle of this animosity to bring itself into being in the definite shape
of the master-slave condition.
Underlying the process is the fundamental need and desire, the
passion to be free, to find ownness and otherness, self-recognition
in the other, or, as Heidegger’s phrase goes, to be ‘gathered in the
appropriation.’ This passion is the source of the dialectical structure
of the creative process. Gathering in appropriation needs, first of all,
the Enteignung, the de-appropriating, which is at the same time a ready-
ing of the appropriate to the appropriate, so that there can be a true
appropriation, an Ereignung, in which the others find their own. From
the mere sameness, the abstract difference, of the two egos, there had
to develop first their real difference, their opposition and alienation,
precisely in order that the struggle should begin in which they might
find in each other their own.
I have not the space to specify in detail how not only the master
finds his own in the slave, but also how the slave first begins to find
what is truly man’s own, and not merely this individual’s own, in the
discipline of rule, so that a creative process is started that looks towards
reconciliation at a level of ultimacy.
The struggle of the artist with his medium, and also with his society
and culture, his artistic competitors, his own past education, his habits
and the pregiven cast of his mind, the temptations of popular suc-
cess, and so many other factors of difference, is also a struggle to be
with all these as own, to transform others and self into a new shape,
gathering them all into a new appropriation in which they fit so as to
be able to live in freedom.
The struggle of every creative person—and this means every person
so long as he or she tries to continue to live in a meaningful way—is
this same dialectic of plunging into the alienation in order to reach
towards the appropriation, opening one’s self and one’s situation to the
factors of difference, opposition, and estrangement so as to permit the
possibility of a new living gathering.
212 albert hofstadter
As the bridge gathers the opposing shores of the river, the country
and city, the fields and streets, the one life and the other, into a recipro-
cal totality of ever-moving life, so the creative person bridges otherness
to gather what is alien into a new ownness.
The categories we must use to comprehend creativeness, wherever it
is, are those of identity, differentiation, and recovery, of estrangement
and reconciliation, the alien and the own, the gathering of differents
and opposites into the appropriation of a reciprocal ownness.
These are the categories of dialectical phenomenology, which have
yet to be tried for their power of enlightenment.
CHAPTER TWELVE
David Davies
1
Kenneth Clark, Looking at Pictures (London: John Murray, 1960).
2
P. Steadman, Vermeer’s Camera (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001);
D. Hockney, Secret Knowledge (London: Thames and Hudson, 2001).
3
J. Livingston Lowes, The Road to Xanadu (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1927).
214 david davies
4
For a discussion of this example, see G. Iseminger, “An Intentional Demonstration,”
in Intention and Interpretation (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992), 76–96.
5
See for example, C. R. Hausman, “Criteria of Creativity,” in The Concept of Creativity
in Science and Art, eds. Dutton and Krausz (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981), 75–90.;
B. Gaut, B. and P. Livingston, The Creation of Art (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2003), 8–11; Gaut, “Creativity and Imagination,” in Gaut and Livingston, The
Creation of Art, 149–151.
6
Consider also Monet’s experimentation in capturing l’effet du neige, culminating
in pictures where this is captured with no use of white pigment at all, or Morris
Louis’s exploitation of the possibilities of the newly developed acrylics in his staining
technique.
the artistic relevance of creativity 215
II
7
See for example, J. Crook and T. Learner The Impact of Modern Paints (Lon-
don: Tate Gallery, 2000); D. Bomford, Art in the Making: Degas (London: National
Gallery, 2004).
216 david davies
8
L. Briskman, “Creative Product and Creative Process in Science and Art,” in The
Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. Dutton and Krausz, 135–136.
9
Ibid., 137.
the artistic relevance of creativity 217
10
N. Carroll, “Art, Creativity, and Tradition,” in The Creation of Art, eds. Gaut and
Livingston, 208–234.
11
I develop this terminology at much greater length in chap. 3 of my Art as Perfor-
mance (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004).
218 david davies
III
12
G. Currie, An Ontology of Art (New York: St Martin’s Press, 1989), chap. 2. For an
AE response to our question about the artistic relevance of provenential properties,
see M. C. Beardsley, “On the Creation of Art,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 23
(1965): 291–304.
the artistic relevance of creativity 219
IV
13
See, for example, J. Levinson, “What a Musical Work Is,” Journal of Philosophy
77 (1980): 5–28; Arthur Danto, Transfiguration of the Commonplace (Cambridge Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1981), chap. 1; Currie, An Ontology of Art, chap. 2; Davies,
Art as Performance, chap. 2, 3.
14
Danto, Transfiguration of the Commonplace, chap. 1.
15
Levinson, “What a Musical Work Is.”
16
J. L. Borges, Labyrinths (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970), 62–71.
17
For those allergic to such hypothetical examples, consider the ‘white canvasses’
of Kasimir Malevich, Robert Ryman, Yves Klein, and Hélio Oiticica, the artistic
differences among which are in no way explicable in terms of perceptible differences
among the canvasses.
220 david davies
18
Patrick Maynard (“Drawing as Drawn: An Approach to Creation in an Art,”
in The Creation of Art, eds. Gaut and Livingston, 53–86) argues that how a drawing is
made is indeed directly accessible in this way.
the artistic relevance of creativity 221
19
J. Levinson, “Elster on Artistic Creativity,” in The Creation of Art, eds. Gaut and
Livingston, 235–256.
222 david davies
20
D. Davies, “Against ‘Enlightened Empiricism,’ ” in Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics
and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Matthew Kieran (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005), 22–34.
21
D. Dutton, “Artistic Crimes: The Problem of Forgery in the Arts,” British Journal
of Aesthetics 19 no. 4 (1979): 304–314.
22
See Currie, An Ontology of Art, chap. 3; Davies, Art as Performance, esp. chap. 8.
the artistic relevance of creativity 223
23
I take it that this is what Kathleen Stock’s proposal (“On Davies’ Argument from
Relational Properties,” Acta Analytica 20 [2005]: 24–31) amounts to, given the non-
empiricist gloss that she provides for talk of ‘manifest’ properties.
24
Hockney, Secret Knowledge.
224 david davies
25
D. Matravers, “Two Comments and a Problem for Davies’ Performance Theory,”
Acta Analytica 20 (2005): 32–40.
the artistic relevance of creativity 225
VI
26
For a development of this idea in defense of a moderate intentionalist view
of interpretation, see P. Livingston, “Pentimento,” in The Creation of Art, eds. Gaut
and Livingston.
the artistic relevance of creativity 227
VII
27
Clark, Looking at Pictures.
the artistic relevance of creativity 229
VIII
28
B. Vermazen, “The Aesthetic Value of Originality,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy
16 (1991): 266–279.
29
Ibid., 271.
30
Ibid., 270.
230 david davies
oeuvre? Vermazen maintains that any preference for the first portrait
can pertain only to its historical value, not to its artistic value.
Vermazen’s second argument focuses on a possible counter-example
to his claim about the artistic relevance of originality. Russian formalists
held that the proper goal of a literary work is to defamiliarize either
the objects represented or the subject’s act of receiving the text. On
one version of this view, the poet’s task is to ‘deautonomize’ its act of
creation and the reader’s act of reception by means of foregrounding,
and successful foregrounding seems to require that the text of the poem
depart from what has been done before in striking ways. Thus, it might
be argued, striking originality in what the poet does is a necessary
condition for achieving the proper goal of poetry, and thus of artistic
value. Vermazen counters this line of argument by claiming that, if
originality is tied to foregrounding, it is not an enduring property of
the work even if it is an enduring property of the generative act of
the poet. For how a stylistic property of the text affects the readers
depends upon the background that they bring to their encounter with
the text. While certain stylistic features may have deautonomized the
reading experience for contemporaries of the poet, they will cease to
have that effect as readers become familiar with the poem, or as the
stylistic ‘novelties’ become an accepted part of the literary culture.
Thus foregrounding is not an enduring feature of the work required
for its proper appreciation, and originality, even if it is a precondition
for foregrounding, is not thereby artistically relevant.
Given the nature of Vermazen’s arguments, and given the conceptual
links between originality and creativity as characteristics of an agent’s
generative activity, it seems that, if these arguments count against the
relevance for artistic value of originality, they extend to the purported
artistic relevance of creativity. Where an artist’s creativity results in a
valuable innovation in the use of an artistic medium, for example, it
might be argued that appreciating and assessing the value of the work
itself depends only on grasping the artistic qualities realized through
the innovation and neither on the originality nor the creativity of the
artistic activity that brought that innovation about.
I think we have good reason to question at least the second of
Vermazen’s arguments, which rests on the assumption that the artistic
qualities rightly ascribed to a work in its proper appreciation depend
upon how its strikes the receiver in whatever context the receiver finds
itself. This assumption, or something like it, is necessary if, as Verme-
zen claims, we are to count the ‘foregrounding’ effect sought by the
the artistic relevance of creativity 231
formalist poet as a property of the poet’s action but not of the poem
because only receivers contemporary with the poet will achieve this
effect. But this assumption seems highly questionable if we look at the
kinds of properties we want to ascribe to works. Marcel Duchamp’s
Readymades, for example, strike the artistically informed modern viewer
as familiar, unthreatening, and almost endearing given the much more
extreme offerings of late modern visual art. But to appreciate Duchamp’s
works, and to correctly assess their artistic value, we must characterize
them as shocking, radical, provocative, and subversive. What matters
in determining the experienced artistic qualities of a work that bear
upon its appreciation and evaluation is how the work would affect
an appropriate receiver. In the case of certain affective properties that
depend upon the anticipated context of reception for the work, our
own responses may not track those of an appropriate receiver, and our
failure to experience a particular quality does not show that the work,
qua object of artistic appreciation, lacks that property or has lost it.
Rather, it only shows that certain appreciable properties of the work
may not be directly available to us since we fail to share the anticipated
context of reception for the work. We can recognize the shocking and
radical nature of Duchamp’s Fountain because we can gauge how the
work struck members of the target audience, not because we ourselves
find it shocking. So, returning to the case of the Russian formalist
poems, that certain stylistic features are foregrounded is a feature of
the poem and not just of the artist’s activity, even though they are not
foregrounded for us when we read the poem.
Suppose that we grant that originality is a precondition for foreground-
ing, and that foregrounding can be a property of the work. Vermazen’s
first argument can still hold that it does not follow that originality has
some independent bearing on a work’s artistic value. What contributes to
the work’s artistic value, he might claim, is the foregrounding itself, and
the work acquires no additional value, qua work, from the originality
that is a precondition for that foregrounding. But, even if we grant this
claim about artistic value, it seems that originality, in the case in ques-
tion, is artistically relevant in the sense of C3. Knowledge of originality
bears crucially upon the work’s proper appreciation, and thereby on its
proper evaluation. For foregrounding to work for a particular receiver,
the medium must be manipulated in a manner with which she is unfa-
miliar, and for foregrounding to be a property of the work itself this
must be the case for all appropriately informed receivers. But a given
receiver for whom a feature of the work is foregrounded can justifiably
232 david davies
impute foregrounding to the work only if she assumes that she is react-
ing in the way an appropriately informed receiver would react—in
other words, only if she recognizes that what is unfamiliar for her will
be unfamiliar for such a receiver—that is, that the relevant features of
the work are original for such a receiver. In other words, even if it is
foregrounding, and not originality, that contributes to a work’s artistic
value, it is only in virtue of recognizing the work’s originality that the
receiver can justifiably ascribe the property of foregrounding and the
consequent artistic value. So, in at least this special case, originality is
artistically relevant by C3.
Again, in this special case, the same considerations apply if we
consider those stylistic originalities that are rightly viewed as creative—
where the originality, given the context, is traceable to what the artist
intentionally did. For intending to do X is plausibly taken to be at least
a necessary condition for X’s being part of what one achieves, even if
some of the properties rightly attributed to a work are not intended by
the artist: for such unintended properties are not part of what the artist
achieved. But then, to the extent that we take what an artist achieves,
in the product sense, to bear on the appreciation of the artist’s work,
foregrounding will be part of the its concrete achievement only if the
artist’s manipulations of the medium are not only original for appro-
priate receivers but also intended to be original. The deliberate and
intentional generation of something novel that contributes to the value
of a work seems to be just what is involved in artistic creativity. So, in
the special case under consideration, the originality of a work and the
creativity of the artistic process seem to be artistically relevant in the
sense of C3 in that knowledge of both of these dimensions of a work
is required for its proper appreciation, even if we agree with Vermazen
that the originality (and by extension the creativity) does not make an
independent contribution to the work’s artistic value.
IX
limited to the special case—it does not, for example, admit of any exten-
sion to the Franz Hals case cited by Vermazen. Furthermore, creativity
is deemed to be artistically relevant only indirectly, through its bearing
on the ascription of contentful features bearing on the work’s artistic
value. No artistic value has been shown to attach to creativity itself. As
suggested earlier, our reflections strongly suggests that, if a case is to
be made for the artistic relevance of creativity in any richer sense, that
case must be made by taking aspects of the generative process to bear
directly upon the artistic value of a work, rather than seeing any such
bearing as necessarily mediated by what was achieved or produced by
that activity. In other words, to defend the artistic relevance of creativ-
ity in anything other than the very limited sense for which I have just
argued, we need to espouse an augmented, rather than an experiential,
criterion of artistic relevance. But this, as I also suggested earlier, may
have wider ramifications for our conception of artworks.
PART THREE
Margaret Boden
I Introduction
Creativity is the ability to come up with ideas that are new, surprising,
and valuable.1 I am using ‘idea’ as shorthand, catchall term here. It
can be a concept, a poetic image, a scientific theory, or even a particu-
lar form of taxation, all of which are commonly called ideas. But it
can also mean a style of painting or dancing, a way of building
a bridge or skinning a cat, a millinery design, a cooking recipe, a
recipe for home-made bombs—or even a plan for delivering them to
maximum effect.
As that long list suggests, we find creativity in every area of life: not
just art, science, or business. Moreover, it is an aspect of normal adult
human intelligence. So every one of us has it, although some of us
display it more often, and more convincingly, than others do. By ‘more
convincingly,’ I mean that some people repeatedly produce ideas highly
regarded as valuable—and which, so far as is known, no one else has
ever had before. (They are ‘historically’ creative, or H-creative.) Most
people, by contrast, produce only moderately interesting ideas, many
of which are already known by other people, even if new for the indi-
vidual concerned. (They are ‘psychologically,’ or ‘personally,’ creative:
P-creative, for short.)
What different people regard as interesting varies, so new ideas
can be valuable in many different ways. Encyclopedia writers, gallery
curators, chemists, sculptors, property developers, entrepreneurs, and
advertising executives focus on different sorts of creative idea, differ-
ent sorts of value. But for all these groups, they are most interested in
H-creativity. However, if an idea is H-creative it must necessarily be
P-creative too.
1
Margaret Boden, The Creative Mind: Myths and Mechanisms (London, Routledge,
2004).
238 margaret boden
the new idea had been a possibility all along. For example, compare
discovering a beautiful village tucked away in a hollow between two
spurs of the Motorway. Its location had always been marked on the
map, but we had not examined the whole map closely. Or, we may
be surprised by something that we had previously thought impossible,
and which we still see as utterly counterintuitive. For example, think
of the very first exhibition of Impressionist paintings, or imagine the
impact on non-physicists of the introduction of wireless, or television.
In such cases, a particular creative idea appears as if it simply could
not have arisen—yet it did. These three sorts of surprise correspond
to three ways of coming up with new ideas, three different answers to
our question, How does creativity work? In other words, they point to
three types of creativity—discussed in Section II, below.
Another kind of surprise focuses not on the nature or likelihood of
the idea itself but on its being offered to us as something valuable. As
remarked above, values in many areas are disputable—and even highly
changeable. Sometimes, they can change virtually overnight—due to
commercial decisions in the fashion industry for instance (enticing the
public to buy new clothes even though they are not strictly needed),
or to what some widely admired ‘celebrity’ happened to wear to a
high-profile party. At other times, the change may take years to hap-
pen. The first Impressionist paintings had to be shown in a special hall
because the official exhibition would not accept them. After having
been nearly universally rejected at first, they can now be seen every
day on birthday cards and boxes of chocolates. This gradual change
from disgusted rejection to clichéd acceptance is a special case of the
value-change that typically accompanies the third type of creativity
discussed below.
There may, of course, be some universal (or nearly universal) values,
more resistant to cultural change. Two possible examples are the prefer-
ence for symmetry and shininess. Quite apart from their cross-cultural
popularity, there are good biological reasons why valuing these two
characteristics has evolved.2 In addition, psychologists have identified
other naturally evolved tendencies to favor perceptible features, and
behave towards them in a particular way; certain shapes or textures,
for instance, suggest opportunities for locomotion, feeding, holding,
stroking, or courting. These nearly-universal values are prominent in
2
Margaret Boden, Mind as Machine: Myths and Mechanisms, two vol. (London: Rout-
ledge, 2006), vol. 1, 553–556.
240 margaret boden
craftworks, which is why the crafts are readily intelligible across cultures.3
But even biologically based values can be deliberately transgressed and
their opposites admired in their stead. Think of the highly asymmetrical
architecture of Daniel Libeskind, for example.
In short, the surprise we feel on encountering a creative idea is
sometimes due, in part, to the unfamiliar values that we are being
invited to adopt. Mostly, however, it is due to the novelty of the idea
in itself. We are surprised that it even happened, regardless whether
it is obviously ‘valuable.’ Here, the three sorts of surprise listed above
correspond to three different ways of coming up with new ideas, three
different answers to the question, How does creativity work?
3
Margaret Boden, “Crafts, Perception, and the Possibilities of the Body,” British
Journal of Aesthetics 40 (2000): 289–301.
4
Boden, The Creative Mind, chap. 3–6.
creativity: how does it work? 241
5
Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago, Ill., University of
Chicago Press, 1962).
242 margaret boden
6
Charles Rosen, Arnold Schoenberg (New York: Viking, 1975).
244 margaret boden
7
Boden, The Creative Mind, chap. 6–8, 12; Boden, Mind as Machine, vol. 2, 1059–1068.
creativity: how does it work? 245
8
David Cope, Computer Models of Musical Creativity (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press, 2006).
9
Hank Koning and Julie Eisenberg, “The Language of the Prairie: Frank Lloyd
Wright’s Prairie Houses,” Environment and Planning 8, no. 3 (1981): 295–323.
246 margaret boden
10
Jon Bird and Paul Layzell, “The Evolved Radio and its Implications for Modeling
the Evolution of Novel Sensors,” in Proceedings of Congress on Evolutionary Computation,
CEC ’02 (Brighton, UK: Sussex University, 2002), 1836–1841.
11
Boden, The Creative Mind, chap. 6.
12
Kim Binsted and Graeme D. Ritchie, “Computational Rules for Punning Riddles’
Humor,” International Journal of Humor Research 10 (1997): 25–76.
13
Boden, The Creative Mind, 286–300.
creativity: how does it work? 247
14
David N. Perkins, The Mind’s Best Work (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1981); Boden, The Creative Mind, chap. 10.
15
Howard Gardner, Creating Minds: An Anatomy of Creativity Seen through the Lives of Freud,
Einstein, Picasso, Stravinsky, Eliot, Graham, and Gandhi (New York: Basic Books, 1993).
248 margaret boden
16
Tony Buzan, Mind Maps at Work: How to Be the Best at Work and Still Have Time to
Play (London: Thorsons, 2004); Edward De Bono, De Bono’s Thinking Course (London:
BBC, 1982); De Bono, Six Thinking Hats (London: Penguin, 2000).
creativity: how does it work? 249
17
Joseph H. Kunkel, “Vivaldi in Venice: An Historical Test of Psychological Proposi-
tions,” Psychological Record 35 (1985): 445–457.
18
Boden, The Creative Mind, 25–28, 62–71.
250 margaret boden
position to experiment with it. As always, however, they will also need
to be able to evaluate their own novel ideas. Learners are especially
likely to resist this form of creativity—perhaps rightly so: not all trans-
formations are valuable. Whereas mere exploratory tweaking is unlikely
to destroy the interest of the novel idea (although it may lessen it), a
radical transformation can do so.
It would be helpful, too, if the ‘transformational’ creator could be
encouraged to present ideas in ways that will help other people to
understand and accept, them. Understanding requires a realization
of the similarities between the new style and the previous one, and a
sensitive explanation on the part of the originator should be able to
provide this. Acceptance is even more elusive, and may require addi-
tional persuasion on the part of the creator, for which there can be
no set formula.
Here we come full circle, for the self-confidence needed to persevere—
and perhaps eventually to persuade—in transformational creativity
is the greatest of all. Whichever form of originality we are trying to
encourage, however, the person’s motivation must be fostered in addi-
tion to their ‘brain power.’
CHAPTER FOURTEEN
Arthur Koestler
I Introduction
1
Originally appeared in Challenges of Humanistic Psychology, ed. James F. T. Bugental
(New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967), 30–40; reprinted in The Concept of Creativity in Science
and Art, eds. D. Dutton and M. Krausz, eds., (The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus
Nijhoff Publishers, 1981), 1–17, all rights reserved.
2
Arthur Koestler, The Act of Creation (New York: Macmillan, 1964).
252 arthur koestler
The motions of the tides have been known to man since time immemo-
rial. So have the motions of the moon. But the idea to relate the two,
the idea that the tides were due to the attraction of the moon, occurred,
as far as we know, for the first time to a German astronomer in the
seventeenth century, and when Galileo read about it, he laughed it off
as an occult fancy.3 Moral: The more familiar each of the previously
unrelated structures are, the more striking the new synthesis and the
more obvious it seems in the driver’s mirror of hindsight.
The history of science is a history of marriages between ideas,
which were previously strangers to each other, and frequently consid-
ered incompatible. Lodestones—magnets—were known in antiquity
as some curiosity of nature. During the Middle Ages, they were used
for two purposes: as navigators’ compasses and as a means to attract
an estranged wife back to her husband. Equally well known were the
curious properties of amber, which, when rubbed, acquires the virtue
of attracting flimsy objects. The Greek word for amber is elektron, but
the Greeks were not much interested in electricity, nor were the Middle
Ages. For nearly two thousand years, electricity and magnetism were
considered separate phenomena, in no way related to each other.
In 1820, Hans Christian Oersted discovered that an electric current
flowing through a wire deflected a compass needle, which happened to
be lying on his table. At that moment the two contexts began to fuse
into one—electromagnetism—creating a kind of chain reaction which
is still continuing and gaining in momentum; forever amber.
From Pythagoras, who combined arithmetic and geometry, to Ein-
stein, who unified energy and matter in a single sinister equation, the
pattern is always the same. The Latin word cogito comes from coagitare,
‘to shake together.’ The creative act does not create something out of
nothing, like the God of the Old Testament; it combines, reshuffles,
and relates already existing but hitherto separate ideas, facts, frames
of perception, associative contexts. This act of cross-fertilization—or
self-fertilization within a single brain—seems to be the essence of
creativity. I have proposed for it the term bisociation. It is not a pretty
word, but it helps us to make a distinction between the sudden leap
3
I owe the term “Haha reaction” to Dr. Brennig James’s paper, “The Function of
Jokes,” (unpublished), which he kindly sent me.
the three domains of creativity 253
of the creative act and the more normal, more pedestrian, associative
routines of thinking.
The difference between the two could be described as follows: Orderly
thinking (as distinct from daydreaming) is always controlled by certain
rules of the game. In the psychological laboratory, the experimenter
lays down the rule: ‘name opposites.’ Then he says ‘dark,’ and the
subject promptly says, ‘light.’ But if the rule is ‘synonyms,’ then the
subject will associate ‘dark’ with ‘black’ or ‘night’ or ‘shadow.’ To talk
of stimuli in a vacuum is meaningless; what response a stimulus will
evoke depends on the game we are playing at the time.
But we do not live in laboratories where the rules of the game
are laid down by explicit orders; in normal life, the rules control our
thinking unconsciously—and there’s the rub. When talking, the laws of
grammar and syntax function below the level of awareness, in the gaps
between the words. So do certain simple rules of common or garden-
variety logic and of courtesy and convention, and also the complex
and specialized rules which we call ‘frames of reference’ or ‘universes
of discourse’ or ‘thinking in terms of ’ this or that—of physiological
explanations or ethical value judgments. All thinking is playing a game
according to fixed rules and more or less flexible strategies. The game
of chess allows you a vast number of strategic choices among the
moves permitted by the rules, but there is a limit to them. There are
hopeless situations in chess when the most subtle strategies will not save
you—short of offering your opponent a jumbo-sized martini. Now in
fact there is no rule in chess preventing you from offering your opponent
a martini. But making a person drunk while remaining sober oneself
is a different sort of game with a different context. Combining the
two games is a bisociation. In other words, associative routine means
thinking according to a given set of rules, on a single plane, as it were.
The bisociative act means combining two different sets of rules, to live
on several planes at once.
the second place, the world moves on, and new problems arise which
cannot be solved within the conventional frames of reference by apply-
ing to them the accepted rules of the game. Then a crisis occurs: The
position on the scientist’s checkerboard is blocked; the artist’s vision
is blurred; the search is on, the fumbling and groping for that happy
combination of ideas—of lodestone and amber—which will lead to
the new synthesis.
The Aha Reaction. Gestalt psychologists have coined a word for that
moment of truth, the flash of illumination, when bits of the puzzle
suddenly click into place. They call it the Aha experience. One may
regard it as a synonym for the ‘Eureka!’ cry. Imagine it written on a
blackboard, thus:
Aha
We shall see in a moment the reason for this display. There is an empty
panel on each side—for the Aha response represents only one type of
reaction after the bisociative click. There are others. Let me tell my
favorite anecdote:
A nobleman at the court of Louis XV had unexpectedly returned from a
journey and, on entering his wife’s boudoir, found her in the arms of a
bishop. After a short hesitation, the nobleman walked calmly to the win-
dow and went through the motions of blessing the people in the street.
“What are you doing?” cried the anguished wife.
“Monseigneur is performing my functions,” replied the nobleman, “so I
am performing his.”
Well, some readers will be kind enough to laugh; let us call this the
Haha reaction:4
Haha Aha
The Haha Reaction. Now let us inquire into the difference between the
Haha and the Aha reactions. Why do we laugh? Let me try to analyze
first the intellectual and then the emotional aspect of this odd reaction.
The nobleman’s behavior is both unexpected and perfectly logical—but
of a logic not usually applied to this type of situation. It is the logic
of the division of labor, where the rule of the game is the quid pro quo,
the give-and-take. But we expected, of course, that his reactions would
4
I owe the term Haha reaction to Dr. Brennig James’s paper, “The Function
of Jokes.”
the three domains of creativity 255
5
For a review of the theories on laughter, see Arthur Koestler, The Act of Creation
(New York: Macmillan, 1969), chap. 1–2; Koestler, Insight and Outlook (New York: Mac-
millan, 1949), pt. 1, Appendix 2.
the three domains of creativity 257
forms toward the more sensual and emotive, ending in the thought-free
beatitude of the oceanic feeling—the cloud of unknowing.
But how does one define the emotional climate of art? How does
one classify the emotions which give rise to the experience of beauty?
If you leaf through textbooks of experimental psychology, you will
not find much mention of it. When behaviorists use the word ‘emo-
tion,’ they nearly always refer to hunger, sex, rage, and fear and to the
related effects of the release of adrenalin. They have no explanations to
offer for the curious reaction one experiences when listening to Mozart
of looking at the ocean or reading for the first time John Donne’s
Holy Sonnets. Nor will you find in the textbooks a description of the
physiological processes accompanying the reaction: the moistening
of the eyes, perhaps a quiet overflow of the lachrymal glands, the
catching of one’s breath, followed by a kind of rapt tranquility, the
draining of all tensions. Let us call this the Ah reaction and thus
complete our trinity.
Haha! Aha Ah. . . .
Laughter and weeping, the Greek masks of comedy and tragedy, mark
the two extremes of a continuous spectrum; both are overflow reflexes,
but they are in every respect physiological opposites. Laughter is medi-
ated by the sympathicoadrenal branch of the autonomous nervous
system, weeping by the parasympathetic branch. The first tends to
galvanize the body into action; the second tends toward passivity and
catharsis. Watch how you breathe when you laugh: long, deep intakes
of air, followed by bursts of exhalatory puffs—‘Ha, ha, ha.’ In weeping,
you do the opposite: short, gasping inspirations—sobs—are followed
by long, sighing expirations—‘a-a-h, aah.’6
6
Cf. Koestler, The Act of Creation, 271, 284; and, for a bibliography on the psychol-
ogy and physiology of weeping, 725–728.
258 arthur koestler
7
Ibid., 285–300.
the three domains of creativity 259
Children and primitives are apt to confuse dream and reality; they not
only believe in miracles but also believe themselves capable of perform-
ing them. When the medicine man disguises himself as the rain god, he
produces rain. Drawing a picture of a slain bison assures a successful
hunt. This is the ancient unitary source out of which the ritual dance
and song, the mystery plays of the Achaeans, and the calendars of the
Babylonian priest-astronomers were derived. The shadows in Plato’s
cave are symbols of man’s loneliness; the paintings in the Altamira
Caves are symbols of his magic powers.
We have traveled a long way from Altamira and Lascaux, but the
artist’s inspirations and the scientist’s intuitions are still fed by that same
unitary source—though by now we should rather call it an underground
river. Wishes do not displace mountains, but in our dreams, they still
do. Symbiotic consciousness is never completely defeated but merely
relegated underground to those unconscious levels in the mental hier-
archy where the boundaries of the ego are still fluid and blurred—as
blurred as the distinction between the actor and the hero whom he
impersonates and with whom the spectator identifies. The actor on the
stage is himself and somebody else at the same time—he is both the
dancer and the rain god.
Dramatic illusion is the coexistence in the spectator’s mind of two
universes, which are logically incompatible; his awareness, suspended
between the two planes, exemplifies the bisociative process in its most
striking form. All the more striking because he produces physical
symptoms—palpitations, sweating, or tears—in response to the perils
260 arthur koestler
8
See T. S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1962); K. R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (London: Hutchinson, 1959).
9
See E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illusion (London: Phaidon Press, 1962).
the three domains of creativity 261
mechanical pump, he did the same; and when the caricaturist draws a
nose like a cucumber, he again does just that. In fact, all combinatorial,
bisociative patterns are trivalent—they can enter the service of humor,
discovery, or art, as the case may be.
Let me give you another example of this trivalence. Man has always
looked at nature by superimposing a second frame on the retinal
image—mythological, anthropomorphic, scientific frames. The artist
sees in terms of his medium—stone, clay, charcoal, pigment—and in
terms of his preferential emphasis on contours or surfaces, stability or
motion, curves or cubes. So, of course, does the caricaturist, only his
motives are different. And so does the scientist. A geographical map has
the same relation to a landscape that a character sketch has to a face.
Every diagram or model, every schematic or symbolic representation of
physical or mental processes is an unemotional caricature of reality—at
least unemotional in the sense that the bias is not of an obvious kind,
although some models of the human mind as a conditioned-reflex auto-
mation seem to be crude caricatures inspired by unconscious bias.
In the language of behaviorist psychology, we would have to say
that Cézanne, glancing at a landscape, receives a stimulus, to which
he responds by putting a dab of paint on the canvas, and that is all
there is to it. But in fact, the two activities take place on two different
planes. The stimulus comes from one environment, the distant land-
scape. The response acts on a different environment, a square surface
of 10 by 15 inches. The two environments obey two different sets of
laws. An isolated brushstroke does not represent an isolated detail in
the landscape. There are no point-to-point correspondences between
the two planes; each obeys a different rule of the game. The artist’s
vision is bifocal, just as the poet’s voice is bivocal, as he bisociates
sound and meaning.
10
J. Hadamard, The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field (Princeton: Prince-
ton University Press, 1949).
264 arthur koestler
11
E. Kris, Psychoanalytic Explorations in Art (New York: International Universities
Press, 1952).
the three domains of creativity 265
That is why the history of science echoes with as many bitter and
venomous controversies as the history of literary criticism. Moreover,
the verification of a discovery comes after the act; the creative act itself
is for the scientist, as it is for the artist, a leap into the dark, where
both are equally dependent on their fallible intuitions. The greatest
mathematicians and physicists have confessed that, at those decisive
moments when taking the plunge, they were guided not by logic but
by a sense of beauty, which they were unable to define. Vice versa,
painters and sculptors, not to mention architects, have always been
guided, and often obsessed, by scientific or pseudo-scientific theories and
criteria of truth: the golden section, the laws of perspective, Dürer and
Leonardo’s laws of proportion representing the human body, Cézanne’s
doctrine that everything in nature is modeled on the cylinder and
cone, Braque’s alternative theory that cubes should be substituted for
spheres, Le Corbusier’s modulator theory, Buckminster Fuller’s geodesic
domes. The same goes, of course, for literature, from the formal laws
imposed on Greek tragedy to the various recent and contemporary
schools—romanticism, classicism, naturalism, symbolism, stream of
consciousness, socialist realism, the nouveau roman, and so forth—not
to mention the intricate rules of harmony and counterpoint in music.
The English physicist Paul Dirac, a Nobel laureate, said recently, “It is
more important to have beauty in one’s equations than that they should
fit experiment.”12 The counterpart to this is the statement by Georges-
Pierre Seurat on his pointillist method, “They see poetry in what I have
done. No, I apply my method, and that is all there is to it.” In other
words, the experience of truth, however subjective, must be present for
the experience of beauty to arise, and vice versa: An elegant solution
of a problem gives rise in the connoisseur to the experience of beauty.
Intellectual illumination and emotional catharsis are complementary
aspects of an indivisible process.
12
P. A. M. Dirac, “Evolution of the Physicist’s Picture of Nature,” Scientific American
208 (1963): 45–53.
266 arthur koestler
13
Koestler, The Act of Creation, 447–474.
CHAPTER FIFTEEN
CREATIVITY IN SCIENCE1
Rom Harré
To create is to produce or generate what did not exist before, and most
importantly, it is to produce not only an individual that did not exist
before but one of a new and hitherto unknown kind. In science the
most obvious product of creativity is a sort of discourse, the flow of
theory. But theory is itself a secondary product, a description of potent
things and products which produce the phenomena we experience. And
yet, at least initially, the potent things and processes described in theory
are not part of that experience. It is in our conceiving of ideas about
them, by imagining possible potent things in which and among which
causal activity occurs, that creativity is exercised.
But if theory is to provide understanding, it must be intelligible, and
that intelligibility must derive ultimately from the intelligibility of the
novel entities and forms conceived in the creative scientific imagination.
So novelty must be tempered by connection with the known, or at least
with that amongst the known which we take to be intelligible. What it
is for something to be intelligible will emerge in the course of the
discussion. But the only possible connection that would allow both
intelligibility and novelty is that of analogy. New things and processes
must be like known things and processes in some ways, but must be
unlike them in others. The forms of unlikeness may be very various.
Unlikeness may derive from the absence of some common property,
as photons have no rest mass, or it may derive from a combination of
a set of properties never found together in ordinary experience, as the
spatio-temporal continuum must be both continuous and infinitely
divisible. Sometimes, as in the latter case, the resolution of the consequent
1
Originally published in The Concept of Creativity in Science and Art, eds. D. Dutton
and M. Krausz (The Hague/Boston/London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1981),
19–46, all rights reserved.
268 rom harré
2
Arthur Koestler, The Sleepwalkers: A History of Man’s Changing Vision of the Universe
(London: Hutchinson, 1959).
3
E. Goffman, Relations in Public (New York: Harper and Row, 1972).
4
K. R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963).
270 rom harré
classified by reference to the kind of thing they assert about the world.
The logical form of such propositions and the logical structure of the
discourse within which they appear is not, of course, irrelevant to our
understanding of them, but, I hold, is far from exhaustively determin-
ing all that a philosopher might want to say about them.5 Thus, for
example, a causal proposition cannot be identified by its form alone,
say that of a conditional, but is only truly causal if it explicitly or
implicitly refers to an existing natural agent potent to bring about the
causation when unconstrained and suitably activated. Thus, ‘ignition
of petrol causes combustion’ is intelligible as a causal proposition on
two counts, neither of which can be dispensed with: it has the form
‘If i then c,’ and it refers to ‘petrol’ an inflammable liquid. Our under-
standing of the proposition as causal depends upon our understanding
of petrol as inflammable, that is, as something which naturally tends
to burn in natural conditions when lighted.
Let us first ask in the most general way, but with more care than is
usually applied to these matters: What is the content of a theory? We
shall avoid, for the moment, the few very general, very atypical theories,
that one finds in fundamental physics, be it classical or modern, and
stay with the kind of theory that is typical of chemistry, or medicine,
or physiology, or social psychology (of the reformed, ethogenic, sort).
Commonly then, in addressing a theory, we confront a discourse which
seems to be describing some arrangement of things with certain definite
properties, the modulations and changes of which are responsible for
the phenomena we are theorizing about. It might be that the distribu-
tion and form of animals and plants, both geographically and geo-
logically, requires explanation. Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel
Wallace produced theoretical discourses describing a process, which,
repeated billions of times, was responsible for the phenomena, as they
saw them, in the light of the theory.
Already much has emerged. Notice first how readily one slips into
speaking as much of an explanation as a theory in this sort of example.
I shall return to this point. Notice too that the way the observations of
naturalists present themselves to the great biologists, the form of order
they saw in them (such as spotting the gradation of the size and form
of the beaks of Galapagos finches) was a product of holding the theory.
This is not just a psychological observation, and we must pause to
5
Rom Harré, “Surrogates for Necessity,” Mind 82 (1973): 358–380.
272 rom harré
6
See W. Whewell, The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, new ed. (London: Cass, 1967).
creativity in science 273
What then of the supporting evidence that these great men cite in
their works? What relation does it bear to the conception of unexpe-
rienced processes responsible for all the phenomena of organic change?
We know from the arguments of the Humean tradition that it can
provide no logical support for the generalization of the theory or for
the claim of the theory to universality within its domain. To understand
the role of evidence in science we need to take a radically different
view of it, more radical than Popper’s fallibilism. I shall try to show
by examples that a great scientist cites supporting evidence, not as
premises or even as evidence in the legal sense, but as anecdotes, illus-
trative of the power of the theory to make certain widely-selected
phenomena intelligible. Conceiving of the citation of evidence as
anecdote brings the explanatory power of the theory to the fore, and
raises the philosophical problem of what it is to make the phenomenon
intelligible. So Darwin’s account of the gradations of beak shape among
finches from different islands in the Galapagos group appears not as a
premise from which his theory might be inferred, together with all the
other available evidence, but rather as an anecdote illustrative of the
power of the icon to make the phenomena intelligible.
This can be shown in other cases in just as striking a fashion. In a
currently influential work, Asylums, Erving Goffman sets out a theory
of institutions, based upon the idea that an institution should be con-
ceived both as a device for fulfilling its official functions, that is, as a
hospital is a place where the staff cure people, and as a setting for the
staging of dramas of character, where personas are created and
defended, so that a hospital is a place where people perfect dramatic
performances as ‘surgeon,’ ‘nurse,’ and, of course, ‘patient,’ learning
to conform to and excel in these dramaturgically conceived ‘roles.’7 In
his discussion of those closed institutions he calls ‘asylums,’ Goffman
cites instance after instance of people doing things that become intel-
ligible only if conceived on his dramaturgical model, his icon of the
nunnery or the barracks or the hospital as a theatre. Each citation is
an anecdote, in which the power of the dramaturgical theory to make
phenomena intelligible is illustrated. At the same time, it becomes plain
that certain structures and textures of life in such places become visible,
7
Erving Goffman, Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other
Inmates (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Books, 1961).
creativity in science 275
8
C. Lévi-Strauss, Triste Tropiques, trans. J. and D. Weightman (London: Cape, 1974).
276 rom harré
9
See J. J. Gibson, The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems (London: George Allen
and Unwin, 1968).
creativity in science 277
I shall try to show that though the creative imagination of scientists is,
in a certain sense, free, and indeed we shall come to see in exactly what
sense, nevertheless, analytical schemata can be constructed to represent
the dynamics of concept-construction, in an idealized form, and from
which canons, exemplified in rules, can be abstracted. The essential
point to be grasped, in considering the acts of the imagination in its
reproductive phase, is that in producing an icon of a possible reality,
the imagination is not modeling something known, but something which
is in its inner nature unknown. We know how the mysterious structures
and things behave, since they have produced the patterns of phenom-
ena we wish to make intelligible, so at least our icon must depict a
possible being which behaves analogously to the unknown real being.
But simply to conceive possible realities in terms of their behavior
is no advance on positivism, since we already know the behavior pat-
terns of things and express these in the laws of nature. The task of
the reproductive imagination is deeper, for it must enable us to gener-
ate a conception of the nature of the objects which behave exactly like,
or in various degrees analogously to, the real things actually in the
280 rom harré
(1) They must be the kinds of things, structures, processes, and prop-
erties the current world picture regards as admissible existents—gases
rather than imponderable fluids (1800), material atoms rather than
atmospheres of heat (1850), electric charges rather than solid atoms
(1920), neural networks rather than mental substance (1960), and
so on. The metaphysics of science consists in the discussion of the
coherence and plausibility of the world pictures, literally concep-
tions of structures, that occupy space and endure for a time, and
any possible systems they may form, which serve as general sources
for conceptions of possible realities, though, in one of the examples
I have cited, that of elementary electric charges, we are on the
borders of possible experience.
creativity in science 281
conceiving structures of potentials, but here at least they are but dis-
pensable models of our abstract conceptions of reality. They are, at
best, a system of metaphors for holding onto the sense of the abstract
objects, and it is to this role that another aspect of the sense of the
notion icon is directed. An icon as a religious painting is not just a
picture of some worthy person, but is a bearer of meaning, generally
abstract with respect to that which it depicts. In their transcendental
employment the models generated by this phase of the imagination
are truly icons.
Common sense would have it, no doubt, that the test of the imagina-
tion in conceiving objects in the realm of possible experience is whether,
when our senses are extended by the development of some device, such
as the stethoscope or the microscope, the hypothetical object or process
appears, that is, it is a matter of whether and to what extent reality,
when it is revealed in experience, matches the icon. But common sense
needs defense. There is a tradition in philosophy of casting doubt upon
the authenticity of what is perceived, by insisting that only the existence
of and properties of the immediate elements of various sensory fields
involved are known for certain. Happily, as far as stethoscopes, probes,
microscopes, telescopes, and slow motion film are concerned, one can
establish a gradual transition from the objects and processes of unaided
perception, to the sounds, shapes, colors, motions, and so on, brought
into our experience with the help of instruments. One can hear the
same sound with or without the stethoscope, but one can also hear
clearly sounds heard only faintly or not at all without it. Thus, we
establish a continuity of the existence of percepts. By this achievement,
the world of possible experience penetrated by instrumental aids
is made one with the world of actual experience, so the extended
world is no more nor less dubious or inauthentic than the world of
unaided perception, the ordinary world. And this is all we need for
the control of creativity at the reproductive phase of the work of
the imagination. Philosophers may continue to argue about the epis-
temological and metaphysical status of material objects, but their dis-
putes and distinctions cannot detach bacteria from bodies, nor galaxies
from ganglia.
284 rom harré
But discipline in the world imagined to lie beyond all possible expe-
rience cannot be based wholly upon instruments. However, there is a
kind of penumbral region, wherein structure is simply spatial, where
structures whose elements are beyond all possible experience may
nevertheless be displayed. I have in mind the photographs of molecu-
lar structure obtained by field ion microscopes, or the tracks of ‘par-
ticles’ observed in cloud chambers. While the phenomenal properties
of the structure are linked to its elements only by long and sometimes
ill-understood causal chains, the structure so projected is at worst iso-
morphic with the structure of the thing or process being examined, at
best that very structure itself. However, if we consider cases deeper into
the inexperienceable, only reason can come to the aid of the creative
imagination, and that only a posteriori. At the deepest level, the best that
we can do is show by argument that the structure of elementary pow-
ers we have imagined as the ultimate structure of the world fulfills
certain necessary conditions for the possibility of our having the kind
of experience we do have, and there may be a still more general form
of argument which would link certain structures (and certain powers)
to the possibility of any experience at all. In fulfilling these conditions,
the world as we experience it is made intelligible.
A process or structured object becomes intelligible if the following
conditions are met:
(1) From the imagined fundamental world structure the form of the
process or object can be deduced, that is, from the tetrahedral
distribution of the valences of the carbon atoms the observed form
of the diamond can be deduced with the help of certain ancillary
hypotheses, that is, the structure of the valences provides a reason,
relative to accepted physics, why diamond has the form it has. Form, as
we may say, is inherited from form. The intelligibility of the form
of diamond comes not just from the fact that the proposition
expressing this stands in a certain logical relation with some other
propositions, but that among those other propositions are some
descriptives of some underlying and fundamental form, that is a
structure of units or elements that are, for that case, not further
decomposable. Thus, to cite structure is to make intelligible, and
by linking structure via the deductive link, which has the effect of
preserving content, that intelligibility which derives naturally from
citation of structure alone, is transferred to the form of the diamond.
But sensory qualities, like color or timbre, cannot be so made intel-
creativity in science 285
But when we create icons in the pursuit of the social sciences, we can-
not take it for granted that there is a real structure, some independent
world, of which that icon, however imperfectly, is a representation.
Indeed, both the existential status of society and the significance of
societal concepts is highly problematic and cannot be taken for granted.
We speak of the nation, the army, the middle class, as we were speak-
ing of the island, the Thames valley, and so on. Our power to create
societal concepts is, as we shall see, a creativity of another kind.
I shall approach this difficult problem through two examples, illustrat-
ing different facets of the role of societal concepts, and their associated
icons in our lives. Both examples will illustrate how we are unprepared
to live in an unintelligible environment, that is, an environment which
does not either exhibit structure or clearly manifest an underlying
structure. Imagine a large complex of buildings unified by a boundary
wall, and a common calligraphy in the labels displayed at various
entrances (that a hole in a wall is an ‘entrance’ is also a social, not
a physical, fact, so in this analysis an underlying and unexamined
286 rom harré
But sciences and societies have a history. And the question as to why
a particular form appears, makes itself visible in various manifestations,
at a particular time and in particular circumstances, must be tackled.
To get clear on the basis for a diachronic analysis, one must distinguish
the productive process of a ‘next stage’ from the sequence of those
stages. Only by clearly separating them can the problem of their several
intelligibilities be solved. In general, I would wish to claim that just as
in the sequential stages of plant and animal life there is no pattern
from which a law of those stages can be inferred, that is, they have no
intelligibility as a progression, so there is no pattern in the sequence
of stages of sciences or societies. Patterns are discerned and described,
but I would wish to argue that these reflect current ethnographies and
current obsessions—God’s will working itself out in history, economic
determinism, and the like—the projection of which on the sequence
creativity in science 289
of stages is the source of historicism. But that does not mean to say
that the process of historical change cannot be understood, and that
it cannot be made intelligible. I follow Stephen Toulmin in his claim
that the general form of all historical explanations was invented by Darwin
and Wallace, a form which allows for the intelligibility of a historical
sequence without falling prey to historicism.
The form of our understanding of the diachrony of social and
scientific creativity will be evolutionary in the natural selection mode.
Thus the origin of new forms, be it animal, vegetable, or structures in
thought, will be taken to be (relatively) random, with respect to the
environment in which those forms will be tested. Thus, in the moment
of inception, all novel forms will have the character of random muta-
tions, and thought forms, fantasies, will be taken to be innumerable.
We shall return in a moment to the important issue of how far the
inception of thought forms is disconnected from their environment, and
we shall find that it is not quite so clearly free as organic mutation.
But by what sort of environment are they selected? We must acknowl-
edge the complexity of that environment. New ideas are contemplated,
deliberated upon by people, and in the course of these deliberations
are accepted or rejected, or sometimes merely forgotten, or abandoned
because of the appearance of a novelty more in fashion. Sometimes
they are tested, as to what further intelligibility they lend to what we
think goes on, and sometimes even as to what they lead us to think
there is. Sometimes ideas are rejected out of hand, as silly, threatening,
‘unintelligible,’ ‘obscene,’ and so on. How is some order to be brought
to this multiplicity?
The credit for the introduction of the basic idea of evolutionary
epistemology must go to Popper, and hindsight, I feel sure, will regard
this as his great contribution to philosophy. Effectively, Popper proposed
to bring order to the selecting environment by the use of a principle
of formal logic.10 The instrument of natural selection upon ideas whose
appearance is serendipitous with respect to that environment, and of
only psychological interest, is the principle of modus tollens, that a
proposition which has false consequences is false. By itself, ‘falsification’
is just a logical principle, but in Popper’s works it is uncritically coupled
with an epistemological principle—‘rejection’—that is, whatever is
10
K. R. Popper, Objective Knowledge, an Evolutionary Approach (Oxford: The Clarendon
Press, 1972).
290 rom harré
11
S. E. Toulmin, Human Understanding, vol. 1 (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1972).
292 rom harré
Thomas Leddy
I Introduction
1
One critique of constructivism is Robert Stecker, “The Constructivist’s Dilemma,”
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55, no. 1 (1997): 43–51. Stecker elaborates his ideas
further in Interpretation and Construction: Art, Speech and the Law (Malden, Mass.: Black-
well, 2003). A central text is Michael Krausz, ed., Is There a Single Right Interpretation?
(University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2002). A nice recent version of
constructivism is found there in Jitendranath Mohanty’s, “Intentionality, Meaning, and
Open-Endedness of Interpretation,” 63–75, where he says, “A reason why in these cases
[for example, poetry] there is no final interpretation is that while the text as printed
matter . . . is a work complete in itself, as an aesthetic object it is constituted by the
printed text and the responses of the reader. . . . The total aesthetic object, growing as
it does through time and history, demands ever new interpretations” 75.
2
Robert Stecker, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art (Lanham, Md.: Rowman, and Little-
field, 2005); Stephen Davies, The Philosophy of Art (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2006).
3
Opponents do not consider that this happens in everyday discourse, for example
when I say “I meant by X so-and-so.” Peirce, saw this when he said, “Every utterance
naturally leaves the right of further exposition in the utterer; and therefore, insofar
as a sign is indeterminate, it is vague, unless it is expressly or by a well understood
convention rendered general.” Charles Sanders Peirce, “Issues of Pragmaticism,” in
Pragmatism and Classical American Philosophy, 2nd ed., ed. John J. Stuhr (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2000), 119.
294 thomas leddy
what is meant is that each interpreter constructs its own text, which
then is the one that is interpreted, then there is no basis for disagree-
ment since they are talking about different texts. These are serious
problems. Still, the idea of constructivism intrigues, not least because
it includes a dynamic element lacking in competing theories. Most
non-constructivist theories see interpretation as involving the production
of an accurate representation of a meaning which has always existed,
unchangingly (since the work’s creation), whether in the text, in the
mind of the author, or within the cultural context of original reception.
This leaves out the possibility of creative interpretation, except in the
shallow sense that one could be creative in coming up with a way to
find or describe the pre-existent meaning.
My thought is that creative interpretation is not only possible but
also better than interpretation that is not creative. I am speaking of
the kind of interpretation that creates as it interprets, and thus that
constitutes an understanding of the text in a novel and valuable way.
There is a strong distinction between an interpretation that is merely
‘correct’ and one that brings the text alive through connecting it with
lived experience while still remaining consistent with the text. The
second sort is better in general, although the first might serve some
purposes. Interpretations are only going to be live if they achieve a
higher level of creativity, one that is both discovery and invention.4
Interpretations of literary texts are more or less creative in this sense.
More creative interpretations bring out the evolving meaning of the
work in its interaction with the surrounding environment.
To accomplish my task, we need to avoid four possible misinterpre-
tations concerning the term ‘creative’: (1) Creative is not understood
here to simply mean conducive to more aesthetic pleasure. (2) Although
we sometimes use the term creative in a negative way, I use it here
only in the positive sense. (3) Although people sometimes understand
the most creative interpretations to be the ones that make the most
unusual connections, this approach to defining creative is problematic
in that it emphasizes the element of novelty in creativity over that of
value.5 (4) To conclude that either an interpretation is creative or it is
4
This emphasis on discovery and invention is consistent with what Michael Krausz
has called constructive realism; see his “Constructive Realism: An Ontological Byway”
in Interpretation and Transformation: Explorations in Art and the Self (New York: Rodopi,
2007), chap. 7.
5
Annette Barnes, On Interpretation: A Critical Analysis (Cambridge: Basil Blackwell,
1988), 99.
creative interpretation of literary texts 295
6
John Dewey. Art and Experience (New York: Capricorn Books, 1934), 162. As
Michael Krausz says, “Dewey defines a work of art as a complex, co-created by the
experiencing viewer and the art product.” Limits of Rightness (Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield, 2000), 30.
7
See Stephen Davies, The Philosophy of Art, for a discussion of this distinction. Davies,
however, uses “text” to refer simply to the sequence of words.
296 thomas leddy
8
George Orwell, Animal Farm (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1946).
9
It is instructive that even Davies, who holds to this distinction, uses the term
“significance” in its broader meaning when he says in the first line of his chapter on
interpretation “When the significance of something is not apparent on its face, interpre-
tation is involved in seeking to explain and understand it.” The Philosophy of Art, 108.
creative interpretation of literary texts 297
For the last twenty-two years, I have belonged to a book group, which
discusses literary works on a monthly basis. Some things seem evident
to me based on this experience. My experiences with this group will
be my guide for what I will say in this paper. In this, I depart from
typical discussions of literary interpretation which seem to be almost
exclusively derived from observing the activities of literary critics or of
people who are simply reading in private. I choose the book-group over
literary critics and private readers as my exemplar, first because I believe
a dialogical element to understanding literary works, fairly obvious in
the context of a book-group discussion, may be only implicit in the life
and work of a literary critic. Second, literary critics and the aestheti-
cians who focus on them often fail to see the forest for the trees, tend-
ing to focus on little things while missing the big picture. Third, I believe
aesthetics should not ignore everyday life situations of which my book-
group activity is an example.
It is understood within my book-group that each of us has our per-
sonal interpretation of the work. One’s basic interpretation is what one
understands the work to mean, one’s ‘take’ on the work, one’s ‘reading.’
It can be expressed, in different ways: (1) as a series of answers to ques-
tions like ‘How do you understand this passage?’ or ‘How do you explain
this?’; (2) as a series of reactions, positive or negative, to the interpreta-
tions of others; as something that follows after a phrase like ‘I think
the author was trying to say that . . .’ or ‘The main point of the book
seems to be . . .’; or (3) as recommendations or suggestions to others on
how to read the work. One can also produce a second-level interpreta-
tion, which takes the form of an essay, and this in turn can be called
‘one’s interpretation of the work.’10
One thing I take from this is that one’s interpretation of the text
should not, as some philosophers assume, be strongly distinguished
from one’s understanding of it. Interpretation, for example, should not
be limited to something we do when we feel particularly puzzled or
confused.11 For, even when we do not feel confused, and would insist
10
This would take us beyond the book-group, but not too far, for sometimes book-
group members end up posting written accounts of the work to the group.
11
David Novitz, “Against Critical Pluralism,” in Is There a Single Right Interpretation?
Krausz, ed., 101–121, is an example. I criticized an early view of Novitz’s in my “Robust
Realism Rejected,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 42, no. 3 (1984): 317–319.
298 thomas leddy
12
John Gibson, “Interpreting Words, Interpreting Worlds,” Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism 64, no. 2 (2006): 439–450.
13
Davies, The Philosophy of Art, is one example.
14
“Interpreting Art and Literature,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48, no. 3
(1990). Brodie is the lead character in Muriel Spark, The Prime of Miss Jean Brodie (New
York: Harper, 1999).
creative interpretation of literary texts 299
15
Henry James: Daisy Miller, Washington Square, Portrait of a Lady, The Bostonians, The
Aspern Papers (Chapelle Designers, 2004).
300 thomas leddy
16
Irvin D. Yalom, The Schopenhauer Cure (New York: HarperCollins, 2004).
17
George Bernard Shaw, The Adventures of the Black Girl in Her Search for God (New
York: Capricorn Books, 1959 © 1933).
18
Walter Mosley, The Man in My Basement: A Novel (Boston: Little, Brown, 2004).
19
Michael Krausz has observed that Buddhists might well have different aims in
interpretation than tracking truth, for example, creation of a more caring world (Limits
of Rightness, 115–116). This view would be consistent with what I say here, especially
given my definition of truth and my comments at the end of this paper.
creative interpretation of literary texts 301
20
Novitz, “Against Critical Pluralism,” 117.
21
With Robert Stecker, I hold that to say two interpretations are incompatible is to
say that they contradict each other. See his “Incompatible Interpretations,” The Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50, no. 4 (1992): 291–298.
302 thomas leddy
actually happens in the process of two or more people reading the same
text with each successively offering an interpretation of it in mutual
response. Part of what happens here is that the two are also interpret-
ing each other.
We could pursue various strategies. I might try to understand as
much of what my friend says as possible as actually true, charitably
reading his interpretation of the text.22 This could be a good thing.
However, such a reading may be, from another perspective, a distortion.
We can resolve this issue by insisting that charitable reading is not
always good and that it should be evaluated in terms of whether it
increases understanding. In a charitable reading, what gives meaning
to my interlocutor’s pronouncements is what gives significance to the
text for me.
Although no two ways of seeing a text are ultimately incommensu-
rable (as it is possible to reach agreement, or at least mutual under-
standing, through an on-going exchange, with the text as the standard)
two or more competing interpretations may be incompatible for a time.
Most discussions about incompatibility are vague because they fail to
note that true incompatibility usually requires someone in a debate to
interpret someone else’s claim to be stating the exact opposite belief:
-p to p. This kind of strict disagreement does sometimes happen in the
book-group.
For example, I sometimes believe that my Buddhist friend’s interpre-
tation of a particular passage is false, and I sometimes even believe
(when in an uncharitable mood) that his entire way of seeing the text,
or even things in general, is false. If I say, for example, that his inter-
pretation of a sentence or some larger unit of the text is false, then at
that time, and on that point, our interpretations are incompatible: we
have a case of p and -p. However,—this may appear to be a surprising
thing to say—this is not very friendly. It is not an accident that the term
‘incompatibility’ does not just refer to contradiction but also to the
inability of two individuals to get along. The role of friendliness and
unfriendliness in interpretive debate is under-appreciated in theory of
interpretation. This is not to say, however, that one should never inter-
pret in an unfriendly way.
22
Readers may think of Donald Davidson here. A nice discussion of implications of
Davidson’s theory is to be found in Reed Way Dasenbrock, “Do We Write the Text We
Read?” in Falling into Theory: Conflicting Views on Reading Literature, ed. David H. Richter
(Boston: Bedford Books, 1994), 237–248.
creative interpretation of literary texts 303
23
Christy Mag Uidhir, in commenting on an earlier version of this chapter, has said
that this implies that no incompatible interpretations simpliciter are possible. My posi-
tion might be better stated as that the notion of incompatible interpretations simpliciter
is incoherent. “Simpliciter” refers to something unconditional or ultimately simple: but
nothing in human experience falls into this category.
24
Peirce’s point in “Issues of Pragmaticism” is relevant here.
304 thomas leddy
25
For example, Davies, The Philosophy of Art. For an earlier discussion, see my
“Against Surface Interpretation,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57, no. 4
(1999): 459–465.
creative interpretation of literary texts 305
26
Michael Krausz, “Interpretation and Its Objects: A Synoptic View,” in Interpretation
and Its Objects: Studies in the Philosophy of Michael Krausz, ed. Andreea Ritivoi (Amsterdam,
Rodopi, 2003), 13.
306 thomas leddy
27
Barnes, On Interpretation, 120.
creative interpretation of literary texts 307
28
Ibid., 53.
308 thomas leddy
the realist objection to pluralism that “there is just one set of properties
that a work of art has at one time.”29 The set of properties is a set of
potentialities that is generally actualized pluralistically. These properties
are generated by the text in its interaction with the world via its inter-
pretations by readers. Each reading of a text is a construction insofar
as it creates an understanding of it.
My view should not be confused with what Sondra Bacharach has
called ‘epistemic historicism,’30 which holds that all of the properties
that emerge later were already there latently in the work. Arthur Danto
for instance holds that a work has all of the style properties from the
start, and that these only become apparent with further art-historical
development. Against epistemic historicism, my position is what Bacha-
rach calls ‘metaphysical historicism,’ in which the properties change
historically, although the relevant properties are not ordinary properties
but potentialities. A nice aspect of metaphysical historicism is that it
does not require backwards causation.
However, Bacharach offers her thesis as an alternative to relativism,
whereas I accept relativism. Also, Bacharach appears to believe that
the properties are really there in a time-indexed way, whereas I view
them as potentialities. Possibilities, on my view, are not latent properties
that are always there. Instead, they are to be found in a gestalt that
includes not only the text but background factors that change with time
relative to the reader and the act of reading.
In all of this, I do not think it much matters whether one is trying
to interpret the actual intentions of the author, the intentions of a
hypothetical author, or the meaning of the text as something that is in
some sense independent of the author or the time. All of these are
legitimate goals; the only problem with their respective associated
theories is that they insist that the goals of the other theories are not
legitimate. Better interpretations, I think, come through utilizing a good
mix of these strategies, perhaps by alternating them.
Proponents of these theories often argue that only with their theory
can the one definitive interpretation be established. However, each
method by itself generates competing interpretations based on compet-
ing points of view. If actual intentionalism won out over all the other
theories, this would not lessen the number of interpretations of texts.
29
Novitz, “Against Critical Pluralism,” 115.
30
Sondra Bacharach, “Towards a Metaphysical Historicism,” The Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism 63, no. 2 (2005): 165–173.
creative interpretation of literary texts 309
The intended meaning of the author is just another abstract ideal which
exists as potential and can be actualized in a variety of ways in our
interpretations of it. It is just that the game, in this case, allows that we
delve into the writer’s biography and notes, while this is not allowed if
we operate by the rules of, for instance, hypothetical intentionalism.
It is said by some, and the idea is associated with constructivism,
that the properties of the literary work change. To what extent is this
true? Properties change in the sense that the range of possibility for
interpretation changes. The text itself does not change, nor do the
circumstances of its creation. The range of possibilities changes partly
because of the history of interpretation of the text. But the importance
of this history may be overrated since only academic readers pay much
attention to it. More important is just cultural history, which includes,
among other things, the history of theories of interpretation. As new
styles of interpretation, but more importantly, as new styles of thinking
arise, new ranges of interpretation are possible, and others fall out. We
approach a text with radically different assumptions based on the kind
of world in which we exist.
I view creativity as a process that is continuous from the initiation
of the work by the writer (or other artist) through the so-called comple-
tion of the work, and then on into the interpretive activity of its read-
ers and critics.31 Although the term creative interpretation is often
associated with those who believe that the reader, or a certain kind of
reader, is in some sense the true creator, this is not my position. I have
no problem with the reader approaching the text in a way that utilizes
the writer’s words in ways definitely not intended by that writer. But I
have no sympathy with the idea that readers can simply intend the
work in their own way. The reader does not replace the writer as the
creative artist. But neither is the reader to be excluded from the creative
process. Instead, readers continue the creative process begun by the writer
through their interpretation of the work.
Many singularists are willing to admit that there is some sort of
legitimate process in which readers add material to the text, filling in
the gaps left by the author, to create something of their own. For
example, if the author does not mention the color of the hero’s hair,
the creative or ‘elaborative’ reader will, singularists suggest, imagine
31
For elaboration, see my “A Pragmatist Theory of Artistic Creativity,” The Journal
of Value Inquiry 28 (1994): 169–180.
310 thomas leddy
the hero’s hair color. Sometimes it is thought that such readers are
actually just using the text as a jumping off point for something of
theirs, as a collage artist might use works of art produced by others in
its new work of art.32 The strategy depends on a false dichotomy because
it assumes that the only legitimate alternative form of reading is just a
form of puzzle-solving.
Another dimension of creativity is the creativity of the culture. The
culture is creative through the writer and the reader. In particular, I
believe that the reader and the writer share in what I have called in
an earlier paper ‘the Socratic quest.’33 They search out (discovering and
creating simultaneously) the evolving essences of things. The debates
over interpretations are actually, indirectly (often not even that indi-
rectly), debates over essences, which themselves change as the debate
moves on. This is why debates over interpretation are important: they
help us shape and reshape our world. That is why we often name the
competing interpretations after major worldviews: Marxism, Freudian-
ism, Buddhism, and so forth. In interpreting a literary work we are
interpreting ourselves and our worlds.34 To understand creativity in the
arts we must understand it in terms of these layers of dialectical con-
frontation, between interpreters, between artist and writer, and between
all of these and various forces within the culture. This is why interpre-
tation of literary works can never work on the same model as inter-
pretation of natural phenomena.35
The subject matter explored in a text has its own development, its
own history. The key concepts of the text exert their own power. They
may exemplify changing perspectives in a history of changing perspec-
tives. This dimension cannot be neglected. A novel that raises the
question of suicide encourages discussion of suicide. Everyone knows
this, but aestheticians do not often view the discussion of suicide gen-
32
Novitz, “Against Critical Pluralism.”
33
Thomas Leddy, “The Socratic Quest in Art and Philosophy,” The Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism 51, no. 3 (1993): 399–410. See also my “Metaphor and Metaphysics,”
Metaphor and Symbolic Activity (Special Issue on Metaphor and Philosophy) 10, no. 3
(1995): 205–222; and my “Metaphor and The Philosophy of Art: Dynamic Organi-
cism,” Theoria et Historia Scientarium, International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies: special
issue Metaphor, ed. Tomasz Komendzinski, 6 (2002/1): 43–64 for further discussion.
34
See Charles Guignon, “Truth in Interpretation: A Hermeneutic Approach,” in
Is There a Single Right Interpretation? ed. Krausz, 264–284, for a similar view that draws
from Heidegger and Gadamer.
35
This point is in accord with Joseph Margolis’, “ ‘One and Only One Correct
Interpretation’ ” ibid., 26–44.
creative interpretation of literary texts 311
36
Thanks to Dave Cellers, Stephen Davies, Karen Haas, Michael Krausz, Christy
Mag Uidhir, and Richard Whittaker, for comments on earlier drafts of this chapter.
CHAPTER SEVENTEEN
John M. Carvalho
derivative, and the merely novel.”1 Creativity, Alperson tells us, adds
something to the world that is not only new but meaningful, but also,
he says, the realization of a distinctly human power that is the posses-
sion of distinguished human beings. What exactly this power is, he
concludes, what distinguishes it from all the other distinctly human
powers and traits, and how it comes to distinguish certain human beings
from others, has not been satisfactorily decided. Could that be because
there is still something extra-human about the power that distinguishes
creative human beings from the rest of us clinging to Alperson’s
account? Can we not advance on this common and still romantic view
that finds creativity only in what adds to our world by exceeding the
routine and derivative? Can we find something creative, instead, in
what subtracts the mundane and pedestrian from our experience of
the world? Can we press this alternative further by considering creativ-
ity in fields other than art, fields like science, or even philosophy?
Though the subject of his handbook entry is creativity in art, some
of what Alperson attributes to creativity there appears to be applicable
to the conceptual and theoretical processes that characterize philosophy.
The idea, for example, that creativity in art begins with the awareness
of a problem, and that it proceeds through deliberation and inspiration
to a concretely elaborated result, compares favorably with the way
philosophers work. A philosopher might identify a problem, ruminate
on some of the received wisdom on the subject, and finally elaborate,
in an essay or a book, some intuition that provided its inspiration.2
Alperson points out, however, that this general account of creativity
does not appear to be equipped to capture the significant degree of
originality, profundity, and insight we ordinarily associate with it. Nei-
ther does it account for the important “social, historical, and cultural
context of artistic creativity.”3 For this reason, Alperson concludes his
essay by worrying that a general description of creativity in art may
not be forthcoming. Still, something remains to be learned from the
1
Philip Alperson, “Creativity in Art,” in The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, ed. Jerrold
Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 245–257; quote from 246.
2
The outline for such a view could be drawn from the work of Graham Wallas, The
Art of Thought (London: Jonathan Cape, 1926); Catherine Patrick, “Creative Thought in
Artists,” Journal of Psychology 4 (1937): 35–73; Vincent Götz, “On Defining Creativity,”
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 39 (1981): 297–301, as interpreted by Alperson’s
reading of Monroe Beardsley, “On the Creation of Art,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism 25 (1966): 159–165).
3
Alperson, “Creativity in Art,” 251.
creativity in philosophy and the arts 315
4
Gilles Deleuze, “What is the Creative Act?” in French Theory in America, eds. Sylvère
Lotringer and Sande Cohen (New York: Routledge, 2001), 99–107; Gilles Deleuze and
Félix Guattari, What Is Philosophy? trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1994).
316 john m. carvalho
perhaps which, when philosophy does its job, we do not create or invent,
but discover—because it is there in nature to be found. The conditions
for the possibility of knowledge in Immanuel Kant are pure concepts
of the understanding, not created by the understanding, but given there
and which, by giving sense to the syntheses of the imagination, are the
source of the judgments we make about nature. Yet, where would Kant
be without the concept of an understanding that negotiates the demands
of pure, a priori concepts and the syntheses in the imagination of the
perception of a phenomenal world? Where would Kant be without a
host of concepts created to make his transcendental philosophy make
sense? Where would Kant be without the concept—rare, exceptional
and original with Plato—of the truth of a thing embodied in a Form
external to its material reality and a Form of the Good which, though
it could not be known, gave the power of being known to the Forms
and everything informed by Forms? Where would we be without the
concept of the dialectic created by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel to
show how Kant’s synthetic a priori judgments sustain the Cartesian
intuition about the ego cogito against the skepticism of Hume? This short
inventory (which we could expand easily) suggests that philosophy at
its best is creative—so far—because it adds something of lasting value
to our experience and understanding of the world. Whether there is a
subtractive dimension to this creativity remains to be seen.
Deleuze makes the case for the creation of concepts as the sine
qua non of philosophy in an essay, a lecture really, transcribed, col-
lected, and translated for a handbook called French Theory in America,
where he declares:
Philosophy is not made for reflection; it is not made to think about other
things. . . . If philosophy exists it is because it has its own content. If we ask
ourselves what the content of philosophy is it is very simple. Philosophy
is a discipline equally as creative, equally as inventive as all the other
disciplines. Philosophy is a discipline that consists of creating or inventing
concepts. Concepts do not just exist. . . . Concepts must be fabricated.5
Deleuze, here, reprises and abbreviates the themes he articulated with
Guattari in What is Philosophy? For Deleuze and Guattari, stupidity not
ignorance is the default state of human reason. The ignorant man
knows he does not know and so has already started to think, but the
stupid man—perhaps also the ‘wise’ man—believes he knows, because
5
Deleuze, French Theory in America, 99.
creativity in philosophy and the arts 317
6
For this use of the concept of the Open see Henri Bergson, Matter and Memory,
trans. N. M. Paul and W. S. Palmer (New York: Zone Books, 1988), chap. 4; Gilles
Deleuze, Cinema 1: The Movement-Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986), chap. 1; Gilles Deleuze, Bergsonism,
trans. High Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (New York: Zone Books, 1988).
7
For the concept conceptual persona, see Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy?
61–84.
8
For the concept of philosophical buggery see Gilles Deleuze, Negotiations 1972–1990,
trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), 6.
318 john m. carvalho
about the writers and artists he has singled out for exception in his own
work? Well, following that naughty ‘image of thought,’9 we might say
that he invents concepts for these writers and artists that draw out of
them images or ideas we might not see or conceive otherwise. This is
significant because the thinkers and artists he singles out for close
scrutiny and appreciation are all especially difficult. They are difficult,
on the one hand, because they cannot be easily explicated or under-
stood. One cannot easily see or conceive what Nietzsche, Beckett,
Bacon, or Godard are up to in their work. We might be tempted to
think that this is just because the concept that would explicate their
philosophy or art is lacking or has yet to be created. Just as soon as the
concept is grasped, we suppose, their work and the creativity in it will
become clear. On the other hand, these thinkers and artists are difficult
in the way a child can be difficult: unruly, temperamental, with a mind
of its own. Viewed this way, the philosophy or art in question defies
any final conceptualization, poses problems for which there are no final
solutions, and demands a full appreciation of what has been created.
It also demands the creation of ever-new concepts by those who would
dare to explore its implications. It dares us to ‘complicate the thing’ (as
Marcel Duchamp said about his strategy for naming readymades)
precisely to prolong and promote the life of the thought (or the thing),
the art, and the creativity in it. The philosophers and artists Deleuze
appreciated most all share this quality of creativity: they cannot be
solved. Instead, creativity in their work poses problems that, for a phi-
losopher like Deleuze, are just so many invitations to create concepts
that preserve the life of the problems posed.
The principle of selection is one such concept created at one time
to respond to the problems posed by Nietzsche’s concept of the will to
power. The main problem posed by the will to power is, roughly, this:
how do we make sense of what Nietzsche says recurs eternally in all
forms of life without making it a discreet entity of the sort that would
demand a distinct ontology and without giving it a status generalizable
across (if not universally present in) all the forms of life in which it
eternally recurs? In Nietzsche and Philosophy,10 Deleuze proposes that the
9
For the concept of the image of thought see Gilles Deleuze, Proust and Signs: The
Complete Text, trans. Richard Howard (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
2000), 94–102; Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1994), 129–167.
10
Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson (New York: Colum-
bia University Press, 1983).
creativity in philosophy and the arts 319
will to power is the one force among the many disparate forces popu-
lating and competing to drive the destiny of an individual that com-
mands those forces. The will to power commands not because it is
different from those forces. The will to power commands because it
selectively shapes or plasticizes itself to the multiple, particular condensations
and displacements of energies presently cathected in consciousness. It,
thereby, gives the individual direction, a selective disposition, a ‘will’ if
you will. For the thousand and one goals of Nietzsche’s Zarathustra,11
the will to power is a yoke, not because it is an external force imposed
on the otherwise unruly drives, but because it is the force that has
selected a form for itself that gives consistency to the forces condensed
and displaced around it. This will has attracted a quantum of force to
itself that results in a qualitative shift in power.
This concept, the principle of selection—created to prolong the
problems posed by Nietzsche with the will to power—already anticipates
the concept of creativity as subtractive filtering or analogical reduction
created by Deleuze to prolong and vitalize the problems posed by art.
The will to power is not something new added to the life of an organ-
ism. The will to power results from a selective filtering out, a subtrac-
tion of those forces that at any moment do not contribute to the creative
potential, the destiny realizable by a constellation of other forces. The
concept of a principle of selection is Deleuze’s creative contribution to
the will to power as conceived by Nietzsche. From all of what might
be made of the will to power, the principle of selection subtracts every-
thing that might foreclose on the problems posed by it.
To account for creativity in art, Deleuze adapts and remodels this
same subtractive concept. Here, the default state called stupidity in his
concept of thinking is identified as cliché in his concept of the arts.
Cliché in art can be described most generally as the compulsive itera-
tion of narratives, images, sounds, and scenes we have been told,
subject to, or shown repeatedly to keep us from reading, hearing, see-
ing, feeling, or thinking anything other than what we already read, hear,
see, feel and think. Creativity in the arts gives value to painting, pho-
tography, filmmaking, composition, writing, and design by giving
us something else to see, feel and think. Creativity in the arts, in this
way, makes our lives worth living, while the eternal return of cliché in
art threatens to take our lives away. When Nietzsche exhorted us to
11
See Friedrich Nietzsche, “On the Thousand and One Goals,” in Thus Spoke Zara-
thustra, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1966), pt. 1, sec. 15.
320 john m. carvalho
love our fate, amor fati, presumably he did not also exhort us to love
stupidity and cliché Perhaps we should consider that more carefully at
another time.
At this time, I want to focus on painting to elaborate the significance
of cliché in art, taking advantage of some things Bacon inspired Deleuze
to say about creativity in the art of painting.12 Deleuze argues that
when a painter stands before a canvas for the first time, it is not empty
but full, full of all the images and things that have ever been applied
to canvas by the variety of institutionalized practices and techniques
artists have employed and, predictably, resisted in the history of paint-
ing. Rosalind Krauss says something similar when she claims that the
structural features of the canvas invariably re-inscribe the history of
art in every however avant-garde painting.13 But Deleuze’s point is dif-
ferent. For Deleuze, the challenge the artist faces is not how to add
something new and of interest and value to the canvas, the compulsion
that plagued the avant-garde, but how to subtract from the canvas what
does not fit its creative impulse, openness to the Whole, line of flight.
The question is how the artist is to leave behind on the canvas some-
thing that is at once recognizable but not reducible to what has already
gone before it—a cliché.
We see this nearly literalized in an example from Paul Cézanne, a
painter Deleuze holds in high regard and to whom he favorably com-
pares Bacon. It concerns Cézanne’s Large Bathers, three different paint-
ings with the same title on which he worked simultaneously from 1900
until his death in 1906. One is in London (1900–1906) and two are in
Philadelphia (at the Philadelphia Museum of Art [1904–1906] and
at the Barnes Foundation [1900–1906]). When Cézanne set out to
paint these bathers in 1900, how many bathers were there already
standing and sitting and wading and stretching and striding on those
large canvases?14 Every other painting of bathers—and the very idea
of bathing—from those clothed in Georges Serat’s Bathing at Asnières
12
Gilles Deleuze, Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, trans. Daniel W. Smith (Min-
neapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2003).
13
Rosalind Krauss, “The Originality of the Avant-Garde,” in The Originality of the
Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985), 151–170.
Krauss argues there that the weave of the canvas and the crossed stretcher bars that
support it sign the perspective system that sustains the whole history of painting so that
painting only ever repeats its history however far it tries to deviate from it.
14
The dimensions of these paintings vary from 52” × 81” in the Barnes painting
to 68” × 77”, and in the London bathers, to 82” × 99” in the large bathers in the
Philadelphia Museum of Art.
creativity in philosophy and the arts 321
15
The photograph is reproduced by T. J. Clark in Farewell to an Idea: Episodes from a
History of Modernism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999), 148.
322 john m. carvalho
The round area is the concept Deleuze creates to draw our attention
to, and extend the problem addressed by, a particular framing device
in Bacon’s paintings. It shows up most dramatically in Figure at a Wash-
basin (1976). In this painting, the round area is defined by a parallel-
piped outline that surrounds the figure as an echo of the oval of the
washbasin and the circular drain into which the figure in the painting
appears to be emptying his viscera. In this image, the figure becomes
Figure, not a figure of anyone or anything but Figure itself, a stand-in
for the figure in every image, but without becoming figural, the subject
of a clichéd narrative iterated to make sense of this image. Who is this
figure? Is he sick? Is she bulimic? The contortions of the body make
it appear as if something more is going on here than some simple
ritual of oral hygiene. But what can it be? It is precisely the isolating
function of the round area that it subtracts the context in relation to
which this figure might become compulsively figural, might make nar-
rative sense. So isolated, the figure becomes a fact, an image that does
not and cannot illustrate or explain his sickness or distress, her exag-
gerated hygienic techniques or even his isolation from any other detail
either inside or outside the painting that might explain him. An exten-
sion of the modernist impulse, this figure simply is.
Boned flesh is my way of rendering the concept of meat that Deleuze
deploys to account for themes literalized in Bacon’s art, as in Painting
(1946) or Figure with Meat (1955), and extended to the bodies of the
figures that populated Bacon’s canvases, as in Painting (1978) or the
central panel of the triptych Crucifixion (1965). Bacon’s figures have no
spine, no supporting armature or structure. Instead, in Bacon’s figures,
Deleuze tells us “flesh and bone confront each other locally.”16 The
incidental weight of the one is not dependent on the overall structure
of the other. Instead, flesh hangs on bones, and the spirit that might
animate the body or give it meaning has taken a bodily form, become
“a corporeal and vital breath, an animal spirit.”17 This is especially
evident in Bacon’s portraits—of M. Leiris (1978), for example, or of
Bacon himself in Self-Portrait (1976)—which image heads but not faces,
meat on a bone and not fleshed out visages. Faces tell a story, illustrate
an internal world constituted by the anonymous, floating narratives
that penetrate everyone of us, reducing what can be reflected in that
16
Deleuze, Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, 21.
17
Ibid., 19.
324 john m. carvalho
face to “one cliché among others in a world that surrounds us.”18 Bacon’s
portraits “dismantle the face to discover the head,”19 the local form on
which the flesh hangs.
Here, Bacon subtracts, as a butcher might, the skeleton of what
would make the image an illustration of the kind of life we have heard
about time and again. Bacon gives us a modulation of the human form
that is, Deleuze says, decidedly analogous: a human being becomes an
animal to suffer, to scream, as in Bacon’s series of portraits after Diego
Velázquez’s Portrait of Innocent X (1650) such as Head VI (1949) and Study
after Velázquez’s Portrait of Pope Innocent X (1953). In these portraits, and
in his series of Studies from the Human Body, Bacon images a body with-
out organs, a deterritorialization of the body (a pope becomes a man,
becomes an animal, to feel) that is the condition for its reterritorializ-
tion in a form (a scream) that cannot be narratively trivialized, a form
that is, again and again, condemned to break down. This is, Deleuze
thinks, an unqualified and uniquely creative achievement of Bacon’s
art, one that Deleuze highlights and complicates for us with a concept,
meat or, as I would have it, ‘boned flesh.’
There is, however, a third subtractive gesture that Deleuze will say
signals the distinct triumph of Bacon’s art: the logic of sensation con-
stituted by Bacon’s use of color. According to Deleuze, Bacon achieves
an immediate subtractive effect in the specific tonal quality of his col-
ors. Flat, saturated, making up a distinctly artificial palette, these are
not colors that appear in nature. The yellows (Study from the Human Body
[1986]), oranges and teal greens (Study from the Human Body [1970], and
the reds (Blood on the Floor [1986]), when used to define the field for one
or more figure, have a patently plastic appearance and sensibility. There
is nothing to connect them to one another or to the figure apart from
the equally artificial relations that can be established between them by
what Deleuze calls (borrowing the term from Charles Sanders Peirce)
the diagram; Bacon himself called it an armature or a graph. As
Deleuze applies this concept, the diagram operates on and in the act
of painting to connect and trouble the random marks, lines and traits,
scrubbed and wiped local zones of color, thrown paint and framing
devices that fill these canvases. The diagram is at once the operative
set of these marks, zones of color and thrown paint and the frame that
18
Dan Smith, “Translators Introduction,” ibid., xxiii.
19
Ibid., 19.
creativity in philosophy and the arts 325
sets them into operation with one another. In setting these features of
the act of painting together, the diagram tends toward chaos and
catastrophe, but in this operation it also sustains, Deleuze says, the germ
of an order or a of rhythm beat out between the diagram and its col-
lapse. “Of all the arts,” Deleuze declares, “painting is undoubtedly the
only one that necessarily, ‘hysterically,’ integrates its own catastrophe
and consequently is constituted as flight in advance.” It would no doubt
be more careful and correct to say (I see no way of saving Deleuze’s
point here) that Bacon’s paintings share this tendency to integrate
catastrophe with certain accomplishments in music (by John Coltrane,
for example), dance (by Merce Cunningham), photography (by Mike
and Doug Starn), and theater (by Beckett).
Continuing with the concept of the diagram, Deleuze says it can fail
to be creative in two crucial ways, failures Bacon’s art ostensibly avoids.
It can fail when it becomes an optical preoccupation in the act of
painting—an obsession with setting up catastrophes that consistently
dissolve in satisfying, abstract rhythms (the example he gives is Piet
Mondrian). It can also fail when it so overloads the surface manually
as to botch the diagram and make it inoperative (the example he gives
is Jackson Pollock). In the first case, Deleuze objects to the over-coding
of the field of the painting, to the digital opticality of the rules govern-
ing works of this sort. Besides Mondrian, Deleuze mentions Auguste
Herbin. Presumably Sol Lewitt would also fit in this category, along
with others. In the second case, Deleuze objects to the subordination
of the eye to the hand as in ‘action painting’ (retaining this quaint
nomenclature) where there is a reduction to all-over sensation unde-
terred by any code (including the code of the easel). “Michaux” Deleuze
writes, referring to the Belgian artist, journalist and poet Henri Mich-
aux, “went further than Pollock because he remained a master of the
diagram.”20 Presumably he means by this that recognizable figuration
in Michaux’s canvases keep them from devolving fatally into an all-over
effect. We are finally, perhaps, at a point where we can discern somewhat
more precisely what Deleuze counts as creativity in art.
For Deleuze, Bacon exemplifies creativity in art by refusing the lure
of cliché without repressing or rejecting it. Mondrian, Wassily Kan-
dinski, or Mark Rothko, as Deleuze would have it, repress cliché and
substitute for it a hyperbolic visual or spiritual code that deprives their
20
Ibid., 89.
326 john m. carvalho
21
Ibid., 94.
creativity in philosophy and the arts 327
This may sound, finally and ironically, like a very modernist view of
creativity in art, an echo of the romanticism, about which we warned
at the start, achieved by very different means. From out of the raw
materials of canvas and paint, and by an involuntary process, what
Deleuze calls the diagram, art is made to appear. However, neither a
valorization of the kind of novelty that modernity or romanticism
prizes, nor talk of a genius, exists in this account. Moreover, nothing
redeeming exists in a god who would populate the planet with creatures
from the world of Bacon’s paintings or Cézanne’s baths. Neither can
we easily imagine ourselves aspiring to emulate such divinity. The ten-
sion present in such figures does not capture the presence and absence
of God but the decidedly human potential to create and to think not
ex nihilo but from out of the materials produced and left behind by
artistic, technological and ecological acts that were not themselves
divinely inspired.
On this description, creativity in the arts does not add anything
obviously new or interesting to the world. Instead, it strips away all the
distracting, reductive, mundane, and compulsively iterated elements
populating the Whole to draw the flow of art, involuntarily, toward a
creation, which stands out in its singularity, in its irregularity, in its dif-
ference. While this singularity may appear new and original in our
experience, it was always there but overlooked until everything that
distracted us from noticing it could be subtracted from its field. We
might expect that fields and flows like this exist for all the arts. More
likely, though, Deleuze would have said that a flow for art exists in
general and techniques specific to the different arts for extracting cre-
atively what we call painting, literature, film and so on, are always
contextualized by precisely the social, historical, and cultural circum-
stances of their production to which Alperson would alert us.
Having followed this Deleuzean concept of creativity this far, perhaps
we can start to point in the direction of a response to some of Alper-
son’s cautions and concerns on this score. The question of how to
account for the social, historical, and cultural context of creativity
would be restated or repositioned as the problem of how to subtract
or filter out enough of that context to find an exception, something
irregular in it that does not collapse into the everyday, into cliché. What
needs to be explained is not a distinctively human power to make
something meaningful and new from the available raw materials, but
how and where this or that otherwise undistinguished individual con-
nects with these and not those materials in ways that draw out something
328 john m. carvalho
22
Gilles Deleuze, “Sur Leibniz: Cours Vincennes 15/04/1980,” in Les Cours de Gilles
Deleuze, retrieved 22 May 2008 from http://www.webdeleuze.com.
creativity in philosophy and the arts 329
to create. Certainly not. In the first place, the creatures in the paintings
discussed above, that might be described as sired from behind, suffer
only in those narratives that keep them from being born. On the can-
vases of Bacon and Cézanne, they thrive and exude life, as the progeny
Deleuze ‘fathers’ enliven the thought of the figures he subjects to
‘philosophical buggery.’ Still, if philosophy exists only where we find
creativity, and we do not force creativity on thought the way Deleuze
says Mondrian and Pollock forced the diagram on art, then we will not
find creative philosophy in the hermeneutic or analytic re-codification
of philosophy’s perennial themes. Neither will we find it in an absolute
rejection or deconstruction of philosophy’s abiding ideas and codes.
We will find it, instead, in the playful abandon and irreverent transgres-
sions that leave philosophy’s limits intact as a measure of the creative
modulations they have made in the code. The aim of creative philoso-
phy would be to introduce not the rare but the irregular, not the unique
but the singular. The lasting value of this philosophical creativity will
be to become fruit forever more creative thought. “Whether you like
them, these fruits of ours?” Nietzsche once asked. “But what is that to
the trees! What is that to us, to us philosophers!”23
23 .
Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New
York: Random House, 1967), Preface.
INDEX
Koestler, Arthur, xxi, 35n31, 55, 157, Margolis, Joseph, 117, 124
179, 187, 251 master-slave relationship, 207–209, 211
The Sleepwalkers, 269 mathematics, 45, 55, 73, 130, 268
Korsgaard, Christine, 101 Matisse, Henri, 136, 137
Krausz, Michael, xvii, xix, xx, 191, Woman with a Hat, 136, 137
300n19, 305 Matravers, Derek, 224
“Kubla Khan” (Coleridge), 213, 224, Maxwell, James Clerk, 282
227 electrodynamics, 33
Kvium, Michael, 136 May, Rollo, 3, 12
The Courage to Create, 3, 12
Lamarque, Peter, xviii, 105 means, 19, 25n20, 29n22, 32, 56,
Large Bathers (Cézanne), 320, 322 68, 86, 145, 156, 168, 207, 252,
Lascaux (Cave of ), 259 326 to end, 87n6, 87–92, 94,
laughter, 255–258 270, 327
Lawrence, D. H., 317 mechanical, 206
Le Corbusier, 265 medium, artistic, xvii, xviii, xx, 11, 12,
Leddy, Thomas, xxii, 293 14, 49, 50, 59n21, 109–113, 123,
Leibniz, Gottfried, 155 124, 136–138, 146, 211, 214, 217,
Leibniz’s Law (Indiscernibility of 218, 220, 228–232, 262, 326
Identicals), 116–118, 120n28 vehicular, compared with, xviii, 110,
Leigh, Vivien, 50 113, 123, 218, 220
Levinson, Jerrold, 110, 117, 124, 144, Melville, Herman, 317
145, 219, 221, 222 Meno (Plato), 153, 154
Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 275 mentation, 263, 264. See also thinking
LeWitt, Sol, 108, 108n5, 325 metaphor, 4, 16, 89, 103, 142, 187, 194,
life-work, xx, 202, 242 283, 305, 311
To the Lighthouse (Woolf ), 144 in Plato’s Symposium, 186
Livingston, Paisley, xix, 129 meter, 169, 261
Locke, John, 276 metaphysics, 55, 205, 269, 280
lodestones, 252, 254 Michaux, Henri, 325
logic, 73, 120, 253, 254, 265 Michelangelo, 119
creation, objective of, 59n21 Pieta, 111, 112, 119
creativity, objective of, 51 Michelson, Albert Abraham, 152
deductive, 270 microsociology, 269
of division of labor, 254 Milton, John, 306
formal, 270, 289 mind, 12, 53, 54, 58, 124, 180, 248,
Freud, devoid of, 263, 264 261, 262
of humor, 255 acts of the, 161
of scientific discovery, 147 of the artist, 122, 129, 131, 145
of sensation, 324 author’s, 294
logicism, 291 creative, 262
logicist assumptions, 290 creator’s, 238, 269
Louis, Morris, 214n6, 228 of the genius, 133
Louis XV, 254, 255 intangible powers of the, 162
Lowes, Livingstone, 213 invention, aroused to, 96
The Road to Xanadu (Lowe), 213 objective, 21, 55
philosophy of, 205
M. Leiris (Bacon), 323 property of the, 56
Mach, Ernst, 66, 73, 161 quiescent state of, 160
la machine inconsciente (the unconscious rational, 264
machine), 131 reasonable frame of, 168
A Man in My Basement (Mosley), 300 spectator’s, 259, 260
Mann, Thomas, 50 (un)conscious, 132, 134, 139, 174, 266
Mansfield, Katherine, 141 under/upper, 143
index 341
Vermeer, Johannes, 213, 214, 220, 221, whole, xxi, xxii, 134, 171, 176, 180,
224, 225 181, 187, 286, 317, 320, 322, 326,
Woman with a Wine Glass, 213 327
Versöhnung, 207, 210. See also ownness Wilder, Thornton, 50
Victorian fiction, 142 Withdrawal and Return (Toynbee), 266
Vidor, King, 49 Wollheim, Richard, 137
Vinterberg, Thomas, 97, 214, 221 Woman with a Hat (Matisse), 136, 137
Festen, 214, 227 Woman with a Wine Glass (Vermeer), 213
vitalism, 317 Woolf, Virgina, 130, 141–144
volition, 63 Jacob’s Room, 130, 141, 143, 144
To the Lighthouse, 144
Wall Drawing No. 623, 108 Night and Day, 141
Wallace, Alfred Russel, 188, 271 Orlando, 144
Darwin-Wallace Theory, 272, 273, “An Unwritten Novel,” 142
289 The Waves, 144
Wallas, Graham, 92 Wordsworth, William, 163
Walpole, Hugh, 50 workhood, 124
Walton, Kendall L., 137 work product(s) (WP), 224, 225
War and Peace (Tolstoy), 286, 287 worlds, three interacting (World 1,
The Waste Land (Eliot), 59 World 2, World 3), 21, 22, 54–56, 58,
The Waves (Woolf ), 144 59, 201
Wayward Servants (Turnbull), 208 Wright, Frank Lloyd, 245
Welles, Orson, 50
West, Nathanael, 50 Yalom, Irvin, 300
What is Philosophy? (Deleuze and The Schopenhauer Cure, 300
Guattari), 315, 316, 322
“When Is Art?” (Goodman), 115n12 Zarathustra (Nietzsche), 319
Whewell, William, 272 Zemach, Eddy M., 116, 118
Whiteheadian view, 6
Philosophy of History and Culture
ISSN 0922-6001