BHAGLAND (The Stoic Concept of Lekton) (P) PDF
BHAGLAND (The Stoic Concept of Lekton) (P) PDF
BHAGLAND (The Stoic Concept of Lekton) (P) PDF
Introduction
Seneca describes the Stoic notion of lekton as a ‘movement of thought’ which makes an
language, as the thing said by an utterance.1 There are different ways to characterize this
notion of lekton, and one point of debate has been over whether the lekton is properly
sense parasitic upon these products of the mind, and thus dependent on the mind.
However, Michael Frede and David Sedley both interpret the notion of lekton as akin to
our notion of facts, and thus attributes to them a significant mind-independency and
ontological self-sufficiency. Frede holds that the ontological status of a lekton is such that
thought. David Sedley maintains that lekta form a rational structuring of the world which
our thoughts map on to, and this rational structuring is not dependent on the mind.
In what follows I will assess these two interpretations of the ontological status of
the lekton characterized as the content of thought. Frede’s interpretation has strong
explanatory powers, but I will argue that the ontological status he attributes to the lekton
is inconsistent with the metaphysical properties defined for this notion in Stoic doctrine.
Neither does Sedley’s argument convince us that the mind-independency of the lekton
involves a certain degree of ontological self-sufficiency. I will argue that the only kind of
1
Seneca: Letters 117.13, Long and Sedley: The Hellenistic Philosophers, Vol. 1, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge 2002 (henceforth LS), 33E.
2
conceptual distinction between the mind and the lekton. A logical or conceptual
In the Stoic theory, the notion of a lekton refers to an incorporeal entity, which is
distinguished from a corporeal, or body, in two ways: By its ontological status, and by its
causal role. As an incorporeal, the lekton was explained as an entity, but not an existing
entity. The Stoic criterion for an entity to exist was that the entity had the powers to cause
change in another body, that is, the power to act upon or be acted upon by another
corporeal. The lekta were regarded as entities, but not existing entities, and consequently
did not have the causal powers of existing things. The ontological status of the
incorporeal lekta was subsistence. The commentary in Long and Sedley suggests that the
notion of a lekton was originally put forward in the Stoic account of causality.2 The
sources distinguish between the body, which is the cause, and the predicate, which is the
effect of the cause. According to Sextus Empiricus “[t]he Stoics say that every cause is a
body which becomes the cause to a body of something incorporeal. For instance the
scalpel, a body, becomes the cause to the flesh, a body, of the incorporeal predicate
‘being cut’”.3 Clement states that “becoming and being cut – that of which a cause is a
cause – since they are activities, are incorporeal. […] Causes are causes of predicates, or,
as some say, of sayables [lekta]”.4 Why did the Stoic theory insist that the ‘activity’
2
LS p. 164ff.
3
Sextus Empiricus: Against the Professors 9.211, LS 55B.
4
Clement: Miscellanies 8.9.26.3-4, LS 55C.
3
Sedley, the notion of a lekton served a particular theoretical role in this account, namely
to explain how the identity of objects was preserved across changes in the object. If the
effect or change to a body were to be regarded as a body in itself, that would have as a
consequence that every time a body underwent a change, a new body would be produced.
When the flesh was cut by the knife, the original ‘flesh’ no longer existed, but would
have been replaced by a new body describable as ‘cut flesh’. If a body and its changed
state would both be corporeals, then there would be no explanation of the intuition that
the original body remained the same, even though it was subject to certain minor
changes. Classifying the changes of the body as incorporeal predicates (lekta) caused by
something acting on the body, the Stoics could maintain that the original object persisted
through change. Because the original body persisted even as it underwent various
activities and changes, the incorporeal predicate is in a certain sense distinct from the
body itself; as Long and Sedley call it, they subsist objectively.5
corporeal it is associated with. Michael Frede takes the metaphysical account of the
lekton to suggest that the lekta are in a certain sense independent of the corporeals they
are associated with. This, Frede claims, is also the case with the lekton as it is associated
with mental corporeals as thoughts and utterances; the proper way to interpret the notion
would seem that the lekton that is signified by an utterance or the propositional content of
thought, is at least parasitic on its linguistic or mental corporeal, and certainly not mind-
independent. Frede in fact argues that the lekton has an ontologically self-sufficient
independency from its mental corporeal, that is, the lekton subsists even though it is not
5
LS, commentaries p. 340and p. 164.
4
the content of an actual or even possible thought or utterance. This is a strong claim, but
in a moment we will discover that this interpretation has a strong explanatory force as it
How does the mind-independency of the lekton follow from the metaphysical
characterization of the lekton? Frede takes the metaphysical account of lekta as primary,
and claims that the status of the lekta in the metaphysical theory as objectively or
observe an event, say the above of the flesh being cut, we have an impression of that
faculty’, or mind) of humans is rationality, that is, the power of articulated thought and
event is, as we saw above, accounted for in the metaphysical theory as an object
The Stoic theory of mind and knowledge holds that the human hegemonikon is a
corporeal entity, that is, the mind qua mind (not just brain) is a physical thing.
corporeal, namely the object that is revealed by the impression we have. This is
consistent with the Stoic theory of causality, where we saw that only a body had the
causal powers to cause a change in another body, which is exactly what happens when
the human hegemonikon obtains knowledge of a thing or event. The human mind grasps
the object revealed by the impression and the hegemonikon is altered as a consequence of
this. Given this theory of the mind, what is it that the Stoic mind grasps when the thinker
5
observes the event of the flesh being cut? As the mind can only grasp something
predicate or lekton. What the hegemonikon grasps must be the object with its properties
(the flesh with ‘cut’ properties) since this is corporeal, and not what we would call the
fact or state of affairs of the-flesh-is-being-cut, that is, not the lekton, which cannot be
grasped since it is defined as incorporeal and thus without the ability to affect the
hegemonikon. So the object of thought is not the lekton, it is the object of the impression
we are having.
defined as the capacity of articulated thought and speech. Therefore our impressions are
conceptualized impressions. The impression we have when we observe the event of the
flesh being cut is thus, according to doctrine, a conceptualized impression, and Frede sees
lekton. He identifies this mental lekton as the propositional content of the thought.
which is also described as that which is said. ‘That which is said’ is regarded as the
meaning of the sentence uttered, that is, what results from the concatenation of the words
semantic characterization, Frede refers to Sextus as saying that lekta are ‘things that are
said’ in the sense that “to say something is to utter an expression which is significative of
6
Sextus Empiricus: Against the Professors 8.11-12, LS: 33A.
6
the thing one has in mind”,7 that is, some feature of thought. This ‘thing one has in mind,’
the thought.
propositional mental item is not identical to the thought itself (Frede p. 112-113), and
moreover, this non-identity implies a certain independence of this content from the
thought itself. Taking the metaphysical account of lekta to be primary, Frede notes that
lekta are metaphysical items of a certain kind that are specifically contrasted with bodies,
independency from the body that caused them was theoretically necessary in order to
preserve the identity of the body itself. Frede infers that the same distinction should
pertain between the corporeal hegemonikon and the incorporeal propositional content of
thought.
suggestion than a positive argument for the mind-independency of the lekton. The
strength of Frede’s proposal lies in its explanatory power, but before we evaluate its
According to Frede, the traditional assumption that the semantic notion is theoretically
theory, the lekton is characterized as that which is signified by an utterance, and thus a
lekton as a semantic entity seems to be entirely dependent on there being an utterance (or
sentence) for the lekton to be signified by. Consequently, when the understanding of the
7
Sextus Empiricus: Against the Professors, 8.80, Michel Frede. “The Stoic Notion of a Lekton,” in Stephen
Everson (ed.): Language, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1994, p. 111.
7
mental function of the lekton is modeled on the semantic function, the analogous claim
will be that a lekton can only subsist in so far as there exists a thought of which it is the
content. In this way the lekton is taken to be a mind-independent entity (Frede p. 116 ff.).
But, Frede cautions, we should be hesitant to assume this too readily, because we
may instead take the metaphysical account as formative of the interpretation of the
mental function of the lekton. When we take the metaphysical account to be the foil of
our understanding of the mental function of the lekton, the notion of subsistence should
make us hesitant to assume that the mental lekton only exists “as the actual or even the
possible contents of thought” (Frede p. 118). Frede’s proposal has many levels, and it is
not at all obvious that one level entails another. Let us take them in order. The weakest
claim that Frede’s interpretation makes is the suggestion that thought and its
propositional content are not identical. The content of a thought should not be conflated
with the thought itself, because whereas the thought is a state of the hegemonikon and
thus corporeal, the content is incorporeal and subsists, rather than exists. Frede’s
subsequent inference is made with reference to Sextus Empiricus’ claim that the lekton is
something which we grasp as something which subsists upon our thought.8 This,
according to Frede, now indicates that lekta are something that subsists alongside our
thoughts, which can be considered the second stage of his inference. What is the
significance of this ‘alongside’ or ‘upon’? The non-identity of the corporeal thought and
the incorporeal lekton has driven an ontological wedge between the thought and its
contents, and now Frede seem to infer that the propositional content is distinct from the
thought itself in a sense that is presumably stronger than the non-identity of the two
resulting notion of lekton with his notion of facts, which are such that “whether or not
anybody has thought of them or will ever think about them, whether or not they get stated
So, to summarize the argument: The lekta are not identical to the corporeal
thought they are associated with, but ontologically independent in such a way that it
occurs “alongside” the thought itself, which suggests a kind of ontological juxtaposition
rather than dependency. This association is fortified by Frede’s final claim, that it is
possible for a lekton to subsist even though it is not the actual or even possible content of
thought. This third and final move is not defended separately, but seems to be taken to
follow from the preceding two levels of the argument. I will not address this gap in the
argument, but assume that some support can be found for this interpretation if it is
explanatory forceful. It will appear that Frede’s account has much explanatory power
already as a consequence of the first theoretical level of his argument. However, the final
and third inference finds no such support, and I will show how this strong claim has
Frede’s focus on the non-identity of a thought and its propositional content allows for a
thinker observes, say, Socrates strolling across the Agora, the thinker has an impression
that reveals to his mind the object Socrates disposed in a certain way, and the corporeal
mind grasps this object. The lekton is the propositional articulation of this physical
9
change of the mind, and we now take it to subsist alongside, or with a certain
independence from the physical state of the mind. Now, when the thinker misconceives
the event in front of him, the man is not actually Socrates but someone else, then, because
between the thought grasping a different object than the object figuring in the
propositional articulation of the thought. Moreover, the claim that the lekton is not
identical to the thought also allows for the same lekton being caused by two different
mental states, that is in particular, two different minds. The lekton expressed by “Socrates
and to another observer’s hegemonikon being disposed in a certain way. The two
hegemonika are non-identical as they are the minds of two distinct thinkers, but by
identifying the content of the thought with the lekton, we can hold that the two thinkers
entertain thoughts with the same content. The idea of the content of thought being the
same in two thinkers is also a necessary condition for communication between thinkers.9
For one thinker to communicate with another thinker, one thinker must be able to
understand what another thinker has in mind. For this to be possible, the thoughts must be
sufficiently similar, which is only possible when the lekton is not identical to the mind
itself. This articulated thought can be expressed through language and can be
corresponding lekton.
unattractive for an interpretation that has as aim to establish that lekta are significant
metaphysical entities. Frede insists that the lekta’s incorporeal subsistence signifies that
9
I use a loose sense of ‘same’ in this context and do not problematize this notion.
10
lekta must be understood as hypostasized, self-sufficient facts, that is, as proper entities in
the ontology that are not dependent on thought and speech to subsist. As entities ascribed
full membership in the ontology, one should expect the lekta to have a distinct and
essential function in the ontology. Otherwise, the ontological status ascribed to the entity
appears to be unwarranted. Above, we briefly looked at the role that the lekta play as
corporeal entity in the extramental world that is revealed by an impression and grasped
by the mind. What the hegemonikon grasps is the object-property combination itself, the
properly existing flesh that has the property ‘cut’. But as we saw, this object-property
‘cutting-of-flesh’ which the object undergoes, and according to Frede, this lekton is a fact
with a self-sufficient ontological status. But it is not this lekton that the mind grasps,
because the lekton is an incorporeal, and according to the definition, incorporeals have no
causal powers and can not affect the corporeal mind. The ontologically self-sufficient
lekton apparently has no role in the process in which the mind obtains knowledge of the
external world.
Moreover, a lekton is also the content of the resulting state of the hegemonikon,
and an adequate interpretation of the lekton ought to be able to provide a story about how
the mental and the extramental occurrences of the lekton are related. However, given the
inability of the hypostasized metaphysical lekton to affect the mind, it is left unexplained
how the corresponding entity that is the propositional content of a thought is related to
the occurrence of the incorporeal predicate. According to Stoic doctrine, the causal route
is closed for the lekta, therefore, Frede’s fortification of the ontology of the two kinds of
11
lekta does not provide an adequate explanation. The metaphysical lekton has no power to
produce its mental equivalent, and it is the corporeal objects that do all the work of the
causal interaction. If the mental and the extramental lekta correspond, it is no thanks to
each other, they are only products of the respective corporeals, which are causally
efficacious.
have an essential and non-substitutable function in the ontology. What we have seen
however, is that lekta are ontologically dispensable, because they perform no function of
the kind expected from a member of the ontology. They are causally inefficacious
as long as they simply do not have an essential role in the metaphysics. Therefore,
Frede’s efforts to argue for the ontological self-sufficiency of the lekta has left unclear
the relationship between the content of thought and the predicates associated with
lekta should be able to use the new theoretical apparatus to account for the interaction
between the mental and the extramental, but we have argued that such an account fails.
Frede insisted that lekta were mind-independent entities in the strong sense; namely as
self-supporting ontological entities that were not dependent on being the actual or
possible content of thought. We argued that this characterization of lekta is not supported
12
by the role of the lekta in the ontology. Their ontological status as subsisting undermines
the interpretation that lekta are metaphysically independent entities, that is, entities with a
self-supporting and thus fully adequate role in the ontology. So, contrary to Frede’s
interpretation explain? We saw that Frede’s suggestion was able to account for thoughts
being false. However, it is also the case that to account for the truth of thoughts, or for
some sense or other independent of the mind itself. We can see why this is the case if we
corporeal entity and a thought is a state of this corporeal entity. The mind of one thinker
is thus a different entity than that of another thinker. One of our conclusions above was
that this characterization of the mind necessitated something that could transfer from one
mind to another, or, as we indicated, something that could be sufficiently similar for the
two distinct minds, in order to be recognized by both minds as a particular lekton, i.e., a
emphasizes that this transferability is also necessary for the very coherence of the notion
of content and a fortiori for the applicability of the notions of true and false.
If the content of a thought is identical to the thought itself, then, under the Stoic
theory of the mind, it will be impossible for another thinker to access the thought. This
has as a corollary that the thought of the first thinker cannot be assessed as correct or
incorrect by another thinker. This, according to Wittgenstein, entails that it makes not
13
sense to say that the thought has a content at all. Why? Whenever a thinker would have a
certain non-cognitive impression (which are not self-evidently true impressions) this
would result in him having a thought with, say, the content c. Whenever he has a
different non-cognitive impression he would have another thought, one with the content
d, and so on for a number of different impressions of this kind. According to the Stoic
doctrine, if the content of the thought is identical to the hegemonikon, the content of the
particular thoughts would non-transferable and thus only accessible to the thinker
himself. However, if the content of a thought is only privately accessible, then it is only
the thinker himself that can decide whether he has a thought with the content c or d, that
might identify the object of the non-cognitive impression wrongly, but no one else can
access his mental content, so only he can correct the content of his thought. The question
‘Am I thinking that c, or am I thinking that d?’ can only be determined by himself.
According to Wittgenstein, it is not sufficient that the thinker himself determines the
seeming right and being right, and ‘seeming right’ is an unacceptable definition of
that the object of the impression is c. It might be that his impression is of d, but no one
can correct him, and any self-correction only amounts to more ‘seeming that’. When
impression, then the thought has no determined content and a fortiori cannot be assessed
for truth or falsity. Such a thought is in any event a poor candidate for a Stoic lekton, as
one of the main properties of a lekton is being determinately true or false.10 A complete
10
Sextus Empiricus: Outline of Pyrrhonism, 2.81-3, LS: 33 P2.
14
As a result of our discussion so far we have established that the relationship between
lekta and the mind must be of a kind somewhere between identity and self-sufficient
supported by the ontological properties of the lekton. On the other hand, we argued that it
is necessary for the lekton to have a certain independency from the mind, or else the
Moreover, an interpretation of the lekton must explain how thoughts can be false, and it
must make clear how the propositional content of thought relates to the metaphysical
predicates that are the effects of changes in objects of the extramental world, while
attributing a theoretically viable ontological status to the lekton. These are the
interpretation was the independency of the lekta, his account clearly accommodates false
thoughts and the transferability of thoughts. Neither is his interpretation vulnerable to the
private language argument. However, the fortified ontological status that he attributed to
the lekta was not supported by Stoic doctrine, and as a result of this, it became unclear
how the propositional content of thought was related to the extramental equivalent of the
independent entities with a certain metaphysical self-sufficiency, and he also takes this
ontological status to follow from the metaphysical account. According to Sedley, the
lekta are mind-independent and self-sufficient as they form a rational structure in the
extramental world, a structure which is there for our thoughts to map on to. Thus, Sedley
offers an explanation of how the propositional thoughts and the extramental predicates
are related, which is what Frede was unsuccessful in doing. Does Sedley’s account give
lekta? As we will see shortly, rather than convincing us that this status is entailed by the
reasoning on which Sedley bases his argument can be used to establish the exact
opposite, namely that the lekton that is the effect of a change in an extramental object is
To remind ourselves, the Stoic doctrine holds that in metaphysics, a lekton is the
effect of one body affecting another body. This effect is an incorporeal predicate that is
lekton is the item that makes it possible for the causal process to be analyzed (Sedley p.
400). Then, he says, because causal processes presumably go on in the same way whether
or not anyone is there to analyze them, the lekton may be seen as “a formal structure onto
which rational thoughts […] must be mapped” (Sedley p. 401). Thus, this “structure” is a
are not dependent on minds. We have a proposal for a relationship between propositional
11
David Sedley: “Hellenistic Physics and Metaphysics” in The Cambridge History of Hellenistic
Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1999.
16
thought and extramental events, and, Sedley encourages us, the idea that this formal
structure has a reality is entirely appropriate within the Stoic system: “[I]f rationality is as
much of an intrinsic feature of the Stoic world as dimensionality [time, place], we should
not resist the implication that there are objective parameters against which its rational
Sedley’s argument solves the problem of making sense of the relation between the
metaphysical lekton and the mental lekton by connecting them by a mapping relation
such that the lekta are the metaphysical facts or extramental state of affairs that our
thoughts map on to. By the conveniently vague notion of ‘mapping’, we are not
immediately committed to clarify how the extramental rational structure and the mental
lekta interact, that is, how the predicative lekton results in the mental lekton. As we saw,
the only relevant players in that story were the causally efficacious corporeals at either
end. Characterizing the relation between the extramental and the mental definitions of
lekta as one of ‘mapping onto’ we conceptually relate the lekta of the two realms through
some idea of ‘match’. This match can be construed as a fairly weak relation, namely in
observation that causal processes “go on in the same way whether or not anyone is there
to analyze them” (Sedley p 401). This observation is hardly false, and the claim seems to
be that the occurrence of the effect, i.e. the lekton, is independent of thinkers in the sense
that the human mind is not responsible for the occurrence of the effect. However,
Sedley’s first premise, that the lekton is the item that makes it possible for the causal
process to be analyzed, does not in itself contain the idea that the lekton is independent of
17
the mind. To see this, consider the following. The Stoic doctrine dictates that the causal
effect is identified with the notion of the lekton. Moreover, it is a tenet of the doctrine
object connected with a ‘predicate,’ a construction containing the change that the object
undergoes. There are three possible explanations of the propositional form of the
metaphysical lekton: (1) it is the structure of the extramental world itself, (2) it is
a product of human thought. Sedley holds (1) and explicitly excludes (2), thus I will
disregard this case. Sedley’s (1) thus amounts to the claim (4), that a propositional
structuring of the world has taken place without the need for human rationality being
there to perform this structuring. Unless we presuppose (4) and thus that the lekton is a
and thus the lekton that is referred to in Sedley’s first premise, that item which makes it
possible for the causal process to be analyzed, can originate from human rationality and
propositional thought as well as not. Unless we already take the ontological self-
sufficiency for granted, the origins, and thus mind-independency of the causal lekton, is
up in the air.
Now, what about the commonsensically true second premise, that that causal
processes “go on in the same way whether or not anyone is there to analyze them”? In
Stoic doctrine, the bodies themselves and their properties are corporeal, whereas the
attribute that is considered the effect of a change is incorporeal, and we have seen how
the effect must be considered distinct from the body itself in order to preserve the identity
of the body across changes in the body. But so far, it is nothing which dictates that this
18
preservation of identity must regard the body itself, rather than our conceptual grasp of
the body. Presumably, the objects in the world do their things completely independent of
human presence. However, the analysis and grasp of the objects is ours, and what a
thinker need in order to analyze is concepts and a certain kind of ordering. In order for a
thinker to analyze the causal processes that takes place without him, it is necessary that
he structures the world conceptually. Therefore, the account of the lekton as separated
from its body can be taken to state that which is necessary for rational thinkers to have a
that forces us to conclude that the lekta are ontologically prior to or independent of the
mind.
Now, where does this leave us with regard to the account we are looking for, of
the relationship between the lekton of the extramental causal processes, and the
propositional content of thought? We have argued that any interpretation of lekta must
distinguish them from the mind itself, lest the construal fall prey to a private language
argument for thought. What about our present interpretation, which insists that rather than
the metaphysical predicates being mind-independent, they are on the contrary products of
the human mind? Can we both reconcile this with the private language argument, and
produce an account of the relationship between the two types of lekta? Sedley’s notion of
‘mapping’ would explain the relation in a less ontologically committing way by way of
fortification of the two sides. However, if we could show that what we have been
referring to as the metaphysical lekton is identical to the mental lekton, then there
19
wouldn’t even be two sides, and the ‘sameness’ would give itself. We have distinguished
between the two types of lekta and done so mainly for didactic reasons, but it is clear that
it follows from our argument against Sedley, that if the lekton that contains the
the world, then the ‘metaphysical lekton’ simply is the lekton that is the propositional
content of thought. Wouldn’t this immediately fall prey to the private language
argument? Not if it is the case that the mental lekton is logically distinct from the mind,
and if the metaphysical lekton is identical to the mental lekton, then it is still non-
identical to the mind. Moreover, our account of the relationship between the two
characterizations of the lekton has left no gap between the side of the mind and the
predicates that are caused by objects in the external world. When there is no gap, there is
no association of one thing at each side. There is no need to match our thoughts onto the
metaphysical predicates, because these two things are simply the same thing.
The two accounts of the Stoic notion of lekton that we have considered, have both taken
it to follow from aspects of the theory that the mind-independency of the lekton involved
an ontological self-sufficiency. I have argued that in either case, this fortified ontological
status does not follow. The present interpretation has frugally reduced the mind-
independency of the lekton to a logical or conceptual distinction between the lekton and
its corporeal. It has turned out that such a distinction is sufficient for our interpretation to
accommodate the important features of thought that Frede and Sedley’s interpretations
can explain. Stoic metaphysics required that the predicative lekton was not identical to
20
the corporeal itself, it had to be disassociated enough to preserve the identity of its
corporeal object throughout change. As a matter of doctrine, lekta are distinguished from
their corporeals in terms of the difference in ontological status; lekta subsist, whereas
corporeals exist. We claimed that it was sufficient for this to be a logical or conceptual
distinction, that is, a feature of the thinkers’ analysis of the extramental world. Further,
our discussion identified requirements of distinctness from the mind. In order for an
interpretation to account for false thoughts, and for thoughts to have content, the lekton
cannot be identical to the thought itself. To obtain the required non-identity it is sufficient
to logically or conceptually distinguish between the thought and the content of thought.
The same kind of distinction allows for the sameness of propositional thought in two
the lekton to its associated corporeal. This is a very weak form of independency, and
identity to the mind entails no substantiated ontological status beyond being ‘not nothing’
Moreover, we have not been given a need to claim more of an ontological status of the
lekta. They are not nothing, and they are not identical to their corporeals, and to satisfy
these requirements we need to postulate no more ontological status for them than being a
conceptual or logical ‘something,’ which would thus be our interpretation of the notion of
subsistence. Mind-independency has been defined in the weakest possible sense, a sense
that certainly does not involve an ontological self-sufficiency of the kind assumed by
Frede and Sedley. However, our argument has been that this ontologically very weak
21
characterization of the notion of lekton ca explain everything that this notion should be
able to explain.
Bibliography:
Frede, Michael: “The Stoic Notion of a Lekton,” in Stephen Everson (ed.): Language,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1994.
Long, A.A., and Sedley. D.: The Hellenistic Philosophers, Vol. 1, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge 2002.
Sedley, David: “Hellenistic Physics and Metaphysics” in The Cambridge History of
Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1999.