Alber - Moreness and Lessness
Alber - Moreness and Lessness
Alber - Moreness and Lessness
Reconsidered
Author(s): Jan Alber
Source: Style, Vol. 36, No. 1, Time, Music, and Textuality (Spring 2002), pp. 54-75
Published by: Penn State University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5325/style.36.1.54
Accessed: 28-05-2018 23:54 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5325/style.36.1.54?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Style
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Jan Alber
University of Freiburg
1. Introduction
According to J. E. Dearlove, the fragmentary short prose works that Samuel
Beckett produced in the period following the publication of Comment C’est (1961),
i.e., “All Strange Away” (1963-64), “Imagination Dead Imagine” (1965), “Enough”
(1965), “Ping” (1966), “Lessness” (1969), and “The Lost Ones” (1966, 1970),
might strike readers as “utterly alien and incomprehensible,” and by thrusting the
burden of creating order and meaning on readers, “demand a new critical response”
(“Last Images” 104, 116). Similarly, Mary Bryden points out that some readers
have reacted adversely to Beckett’s later prose, seeing it as “perversely uncom-
municative” and “teasingly mysterious” (137). The short prose work “Lessness” is
definitely one of the most enigmatic texts of the period after How It Is. Because of
the initial shock that this strange and incomprehensible prose work might produce
in readers, it may be used as a case to test the new narratological approach Monika
Fludernik puts forward in Towards a ‘Natural’ Narratology (1996).
Fludernik attempts to counteract some of the shortcomings of classical
narratology and other traditional approaches to narrative theory. Her aim is the
radical “reconceptualization of narratology” and “the creation of a new narrative
paradigm”(xi), a paradigm, however, that despite its interdisciplinary make-up, will
still be identifiable as narratological. As Gibson notes, Fludernik sets out to redefine
narrativity in terms not of plot but of cognitive or what she calls “natural” parameters.
These parameters are based on our experience, on our sense of embodiedness in the
world (“Review” 234). Whereas structuralist narratology employs formal categories
defined in terms of binary oppositions, Fludernik wishes to institute organic frames
of reading. She reconstitutes narrativity on the basis of experientiality, a feature
derived from research on oral narrative established by Labov (Language). At the
same time experientiality relates to Käte Hamburger’s thesis that narrative is the
only form of discourse that can portray consciousness, particularly the conscious-
ness of someone else (83). Since, for Fludernik, the prototypical case of narrative
is given in its oral version (textual make-up is considered to be a variable), the
“natural” narratological paradigm, as Ronen suggests, identifies narrativity with
conversational parameters in a storytelling situation (647). Furthermore, Fludernik
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
56 Jan Alber
and Beckett critics, as well as in M.-L. Ryan’s proposal of the term “antinarrativity”
(379-80). Fludernik offers an entirely different solution to this problem. Rather than
pointing out the negative features of this kind of narrative, Fludernik’s approach
describes its structure in terms of experientiality (Lieske 374). Therefore, in the
present paper I wish to treat “Lessness” in so far as it relates to the visualizing of
a story (plot) situation and/or a storytelling situation (Fludernik, Towards 269).
More precisely, in my “natural” narratological analysis I shall concentrate on the
establishment of story-world, that is, on characters, setting and plot, as well as on
the storytelling frame and the language of storytelling. According to Fludernik, a
text like “Lessness” does not completely disrupt the process of narrativization, but
“merely dilute[s] constants of mimetic conceptualization to the point where realist
frames become tenuous and are reduced to the notions of malleable or inconstant
character, setting and event outlines” (273).
The purpose of the present paper is threefold. First, I wish to demonstrate the
superiority of Fludernik’s “natural” narratology to structuralist narratology in ac-
counting for marginally narrative texts like Beckett’s “Lessness.” Second, I shall
illustrate the utility of Fludernik’s new paradigm for the literary interpretation
of such an incomprehensible avant-garde text. Third, I will discuss some of the
shortcomings or what I call the “lessness” of “natural” narratology.
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 57
entiality reposes not only on the changes brought about by external developments
or effected through the goal-oriented actions of a central intelligence. Rather, it
is related particularly to the resolution effect of the narrative endpoint and to the
tension between tellability and narrative “point” (Labov, Language 366; Fludernik,
“Historical” 374-77). In other words, for Fludernik, the emotional involvement with
an experience and its evaluation provide cognitive anchor points for the constitution
of narrativity (Towards 13). She argues that embodiment constitutes the most basic
feature of experientiality; specificity and individuality can in fact be subsumed under
it. Embodiedness evokes all the parameters of a “real-life” schema of existence in
a specific time and space frame. Experientiality combines a number of cognitively
relevant factors. The most important of these is the presence of a human protago-
nist and his experience of events as they impinge on his situation. Experientiality
always implies the protagonist’s consciousness. “Narrativity can emerge from the
experiential portrayal of dynamic event sequences which are already configured
emotively and evaluatively, but it can also consist in the experiential depiction of
human consciousness tout court” (30). Fludernik demotes the criteria of sequen-
tiality and logical connectedness from the central role they usually play in most
discussions of narrative. For her, the bounded sequentiality of “The king died and
then the queen died of grief” (Forster 87) holds little or no interest as narrative.
In Fludernik’s model there can be narratives without plot, but there cannot be any
narratives without a human experiencer at some narrative level. The fictional ex-
istence of an anthropomorphic experiencer is the sine qua non for the constitution
of narrativity. In contrast to traditional narratologists, who endow plot-oriented
narratives with proto-typical narrativity (Prince, Narratology 146), Fludernik
argues that events or actantial and motivational parameters in and of themselves
constitute only a zero degree of narrativity, a minimal frame for the production of
experientiality. I also wish to note that Fludernik refuses to locate narrativity in the
existence of a narrator (Towards 26). For her, all narrative is produced through the
mediating function of consciousness. According to Fludernik, consciousness is the
locus of experientiality and can surface on several levels and in different shapes.
2.2. The Three Ingredients of “Natural” Narratology
Since William Labov and Joshua Waletzky (1967) hypothesized that narrative
structures can be found in oral accounts of personal experience, conversational sto-
rytelling, as Minami notes, has received much attention (467). Fludernik has been
influenced by “natural” narrative and relies on the results of research in discourse
analysis established by Labov in Language in the Inner City (1972). In her approach,
“natural” narrative includes only spontaneous conversational storytelling (Towards
13-14). According to Fludernik, one has to conceptualize the move from orality to
literacy as a continuum that affords the narratologist interesting insights into the
various functions of elements within their narrative pattern (53). Fludernik views
“natural” narrative as a prototype for the constitution of narrativity and argues that
narrative is always “natural” in the sense that, as Ronen suggests, it is anchored in
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
58 Jan Alber
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 59
to read it as a kind of “intertextual play with language and with generic modes”
(35). In this analytical context, as Lieske notes, experimental texts are not mimetic
in terms of reproducing a prototypical version of narrative experience but in their
structured anticipation of the readers’ attempts to reinterpret them mimetically, if
only at the level of an explicitly “anti-mimetic” language game (374).
Similarly, Fludernik develops a constructivist concept of realism. She does
not relate realism to the nineteenth—century movement of realism. Rather, she
links it with the specific mimetic evocation of “reality” and specific forms of the
mimetic representation of individual experience. Fludernik sees realism as an inter-
pretational strategy. In the process of narrativization, readers make texts conform
to “real-life” parameters. Realism in Fludernik’s sense closely corresponds to “a
mimetic representation of individual experience that cognitively and epistemically
relies on real-world knowledge” (38). The process of reading narratives as narra-
tives inevitably involves an activity of narrativization on the readers’ part. Readers
project a realistic frame on the text and its enunciational properties. Fludernik
demonstrates that the wide range of anti-illusionistic techniques radically disrupts
conventional realistic story parameters and does not allow readers a realist mode
of understanding. At the same time, as Lieske points out, she stresses that such
disruptions do not inevitably destroy narrativity per se but deconstruct the overall
narrative coherence of the text and affect the most fundamental properties of nar-
rative discourse (374).
2.4. The Four-Level Model
Fludernik summarizes the cognitive categories and criteria of “natural” nar-
ratology in a four-level model. This model runs somewhat parallel to the three
Mimeses developed in Ricoeur’s Time and Narrative. Mimesis I relates to pre-
figuration (54-64), Mimesis II to configuration in the shape of emplotment (64-
70), and Mimesis III to reconfiguration (70-87). Fludernik’s level I is identical to
Ricoeur’s Mimesis I. It includes the pretextual “real-life” schemata of action and
experience such as the schema of agency as goal-oriented process or reaction to
the unexpected, the configuration of experienced and evaluated occurrence, and
the “natural” comprehension of observed event processes as well as their supposed
cause-and-effect explanations. Furthermore, on this level, teleology, i.e., temporal
directedness and inevitable plotting, combines with the narrator’s after-the-fact
evaluation of narrative experience, as is typical of “natural” narrative, and with
the goal-orientedness of acting subjects. Fludernik’s level II introduces the “natu-
ral,” macro-textual schemata or frames of narrative mediation. On this level she
distinguishes between the “real-world” scripts of TELLING and REFLECTING,1
the “real-world” schema of VIEWING, and the access to one’s own narrativizable
experience (EXPERIENCING). Further, Fludernik situates the schema of ACTION
or ACTING on level II (Towards 43-44). Fludernik’s level III constitutes a fine-
tuning of level II through well-known “naturally” occurring storytelling situations,
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
60 Jan Alber
generic criteria and narratological concepts. At this point I wish to emphasize that
Fludernik’s levels II and III do not reproduce Ricoeur’s Mimesis II. Rather, they
characterize features that are partially relevant for Ricoeur’s reconfiguration on
the level of Mimesis III. In contrast to the cognitive parameters on levels I and II,
which are basic-level experiential frames, the categories on level III are culturally
determined. One might argue that they are metaphorical extensions of concepts
from levels I and II. Nevertheless, they are “natural” because they operate in a non-
reflective manner and relate to one’s experience of hearing and reading stories. I
also wish to note that readers’ interpretations do not (yet) constitute the cognitive
parameters on level III. Rather, they provide cognitive tools for the interpretation
of narrative texts (45). Finally, Fludernik’s level IV is that of narrativization, the
level on which the “natural” parameters from levels I to III are utilized in order to
grasp, and usually transform textual inconsistencies and oddities. Narrativization is
the process of naturalization that enables readers to re(-)cognize as narrative texts
that appear to be non-narrative according to the cognitive parameters on levels I and
II or III (46). The “natural” frames on levels I to III do not effect narrativization.
Rather, narrativization utilizes “natural” parameters as part of the larger process of
naturalization applied by readers. Although narrativized non-“natural” text types
do not become “natural,” a new cognitive parameter may become available (330).
For instance, second-person fiction (Fludernik “Introduction,” “Second,” “Second-
Person Narrative”) does not become “natural” in the process of narrativization.
Rather, a semantic and interpretative perspective renders this type of narrative
recuperable, because readers have recourse to “natural” categories. It may institute
a new genre or a new narrative mode and will then have to be included as a refer-
ence model on level III.
I shall now turn to my own “natural” narratological analysis of Samuel Beck-
ett’s “Lessness.” I am of course aware that other readers might narrativize the text
differently.
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 61
mirrored earth mirrored sky” (197). From our “real-world” knowledge we can infer
that since the world of “Lessness” is not black but grey, a dim light has to emanate
from somewhere. But the text does not contain any information about the source of
the light. Moreover, as in “Enough,” there is “no stir,” that is no wind, in the world
of “Lessness,” and, as in “Ping,” the silence of this world is unbroken: “no sound”
(197). “Day and night” (198) appear to be abandoned in “Lessness.” The piece is
“timeless” (199), and the narrative voice characterizes the world of “Lessness” in
terms of “changelessness” (197). Philip H. Solomon argues that the hour in ques-
tion must be 6 a.m. or 6 p.m. “Each is a moment of transition with respect to light
and dark—the grey of dawn or the grey of dusk” (66). In “Lessness,” time seems
to have come to rest in a transitional period.
The “setting” of “Lessness” resembles places in the “real world.” The scat-
tered ruins of this piece may consist of stone. Indeed, the narrative voice mentions
sand, earth, and sky. Since there is no wind and no sound, however, the world of
“Lessness” also differs from “real-world” settings. Moreover, “Lessness” makes it
impossible to differentiate between earth, sky, and the scattered ruins, because they
are all ash grey. In contrast to the other “Residua,” which are set in a measurable
container, the narrative voice of this piece does not give us any information as to
the size of the enclosure in “Lessness.” The only hint we get is the phrase “the ruins
flatness endless” (199). Spatial structure appears to be lacking altogether. Further-
more, the fact that there is no movement with time seriously impairs a “realistic”
reconstitution of story-world.
3.2. The Future
The enclosure of “Lessness” contains an immobile “little body ash grey locked
rigid” (197). The body’s contours have been eroded: “Legs a single block arms
fast to sides little body face to endlessness” (198). The figure’s sex is undecid-
able. The “genitals” of this “little block” are “overrun” (198) and its features are
barely defined: “grey face features crack and little holes two pale blue” (197);
“grey smooth no relief a few holes” (198). The body is incapable of action: “Face
to white calm touch close eye calm long last all gone from mind” (198). In a very
ambiguous manner, the text indicates that the figure is alive: “Grey face two pale
blue little body heart beating only upright” (197). This might imply that the body
is the only constituent of story-world in an upright position, and consequently that
the figure is alive, or that the body’s heart beats only in an upright position. The
figure is grey like the rest of this world. Furthermore, the narrative voice refers to
the figure’s past and to a possible future. I wish to note that in such instances, the
voice refers to the figure in terms of the personal pronoun “he.” Additionally, the
text presents the future as a return to past possibilities: “He will curse God again
as in the blessed days face to the open sky the passing deluge” (197); “On him
will rain again as in the blessed days of blue the passing cloud” (197). Later on,
the references to past and future turn out to be dreams and figments: “Never was
but grey air timeless no sound figment the passing light” (197); “Never but this
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
62 Jan Alber
changelessness dream the passing hour” (197). Susan Brienza and Enoch Brater
point out that in the two sentences containing the personal pronoun “he,” which I
have quoted above, the past is superimposed on the indefinite future by using the
phrase “as in the blessed days” (250-51). They argue that a cycle of endlessness
in time results, because both the “deluge” and the “cloud” will not pass nor have
they passed. The present participle “passing” creates an action suspended in time,
which is endless, like the “waiting” in Waiting for Godot (1985).
The figure in “Lessness” is most radically dehumanized. The narrative voice
describes the little body exclusively in terms of bodily fragments. Additionally,
its bodily parts are not recognizable. Readers will hardly confuse the block-like
figure with inhabitants of the “real world.” This figure is indistinguishable from the
box-like chamber. In fact, it seems to have become a brick of the scattered ruins.2
In other words, one cannot possibly differentiate between the figure and the “set-
ting.” The only “features” that distinguish the body from the rest of story-world
are pale blue eyes, and its possibly upright position. Moreover, the figure does not
express any signs of intentionality or goal-orientedness in terms of Fludernik’s
cognitive level I. Its “life signs” are reduced to its upright position or the beating
of its heart. I do not think that the figure’s “eyes” can be seen as a life sign, since a
dead body may (at least for some time) have pale blue eyes as well. Furthermore,
the figure’s past and future turn out to be mere illusions. The body is trapped in
the timeless zone of fiction.
At this point, I wish to note that both the “setting” and the figure in “Lessness”
differ from familiar narratological concepts on Fludernik’s cognitive level III. But
in contrast to Buning, who merely points out the “absence” of traditional story
parameters and characterizes “Lessness” in terms of an “anti-literary tendency”
(102), “natural” narratology takes a closer look at such allegedly absent constitu-
ents. On the basis of experientiality, “natural” narratology attempts to explain why
these constituents are so different from traditional concepts. I would argue that
the description of the “setting” and the figure in “Lessness” are reminiscent of the
perception of an insane person or a person on drugs. We should keep this in mind
while looking at other aspects of “Lessness.”
3.3. The “Plot”
The body in “Lessness” is incapable of action, and the “setting” undergoes no
noticeable transformation. The narrative voice presents us with repeated descrip-
tions of the rudimentary features of the strange world of this piece. Indeed, the
voice postulates an imaginative realm of dreams and future possibilities. “Lessness”
consists of 120 sentences, and is divided into twenty-four paragraphs. Upon closer
inspection, we realize that the text consists of sixty sentences, each of which occurs
exactly twice. There are sixty sentences in the first twelve paragraphs. Later on,
they are repeated in a different order. Ruby Cohn divides the sentences thematically
into the following six groups or families (265): (1) the ruins as “true refuge”; (2)
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 63
the endless grey of earth and sky; (3) the little body; (4) the space “all gone from
mind”; (5) past tenses combined with “never”; (6) future tenses of active verbs
and the “figment” sentence “Figment dawn dispeller of figments and the other
called dusk” (199; 201). Martin Esslin uses the following categories for the same
groups: (1) the ruins; (2) the vastness of earth and sky; (3) the little body; (4) the
fact that the enclosed space is now forgotten; (5) a denial of past and future; (6) an
affirmation of past and future.3 J.E. Dearlove points out that the titles of the first
four families are fairly consistent, whereas the last two groups are more enigmatic
because they deal with daydreams and figments in reference to past and future. For
Cohn, the distinction is one of tense, whereas for Esslin, the difference is one of
assertion (“Last Images” 120). Beckett’s method of composition in Sans (1969),
the original French version of “Lessness,” is extremely creative. Cohn reports that
Beckett wrote each of the sixty sentences on a separate piece of paper, mixed
them all in a container, and then drew them out in random order twice. This became
the order of the hundred twenty sentences in Sans. Beckett then wrote the number
3 on four separate pieces of paper, the number 4 on six pieces of paper, the number
5 on four pieces, the number 6 on six pieces, and the number 7 on four pieces of
paper. Again drawing randomly, he ordered the sentences into paragraphs according
to the number drawn, finally totaling one hundred twenty (265).
According to Poutney, “Lessness” confronts us with the fact that an arbitrary
and capricious world of chance lies beyond man-made, imposed order (56). “The
confusion is not my invention,” Beckett told Tom Driver. “It is all around us and
our only chance is to let it in” (Finney, “Assumption” 63). The formal patterning
in “Lessness” may give readers the impression that a random number generator
produced the text. This is, to some extent, true.4 Furthermore, there is a complete
absence of memorable events in “Lessness.” Nothing happens at all in it. Events
most certainly do not constitute the primary focus of this text. Hence, we are not in
a position to reconstruct a proper event-series in terms of the ACTION schema on
Fludernik’s cognitive level II. Since there is a complete elimination of “plot,” the
text exclusively consists in (vague and distorted) descriptions. Moreover, “Less-
ness” lacks teleology and closure. In contrast to Brienza and Brater, who argue that
“the abrupt last line does not leave us with the impression that the piece might go
on indefinitely” (254), I would argue that the cyclical way in which the narrative
voice describes the central “situation” of “Lessness,” in combination with the final
sentence (“Figment dawn dispeller of figments and the other called dusk” [201]),
which is circular in itself, suggests that this short prose work may indeed continue
forever. Whereas Mood simply argues that “Lessness” is “plotless” (78), “natural”
narratology concerns itself with whether there is not a different story buried under
the (admittedly quite) uneventful cloak.
3.4. The Language of Storytelling
The syntax of “Lessness” is most radically disrupted. The piece shares with
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
64 Jan Alber
“Ping” its sentence style and structure as well as the absence of any punctuation
except periods. The “scattered ruins” (197) might be a description of the words
themselves. The narrative voice uses verbs sparingly; present tense verbs are
entirely absent. The personal pronoun “he” occurs only in connection with sen-
tences dealing with the past or the future. This voice gives us the impression that
human existence is possible only in the past or in the future. Later on, however,
the voice reveals this to be a mere illusion. Occasionally, it also drops articles and
prepositions. Its radical reductionism generates a terse, staccato-like style, and is
reminiscent of a computerized programme. Moreover, the reduced syntactical form
creates pseudo-independent phrases like individual images. Thus, Murphy argues
(114) that the words may be said to face on “all sides endlessness.” For instance,
as I have shown above, we can read the phrase “heart beating only upright” in
several different ways. Likewise, in the sentence “little body little block genitals
overrun arse a single block grey crack overrun” (198), it remains unclear whether
the genitals, or the arse, or both are overrun, and the “grey crack” is ambiguous
(eye, tip of penis, vagina, or anus?). Additionally, in all but two of the twenty-
four paragraphs, we come across words containing the suffix “-less” or the suffix
“-lessness” (“endless,” “timless,” “issueless,” “endlessness,” “changelessness”).
These words, like the neologism “Lessness,” stand out and set up a network of
tenuous meanings. Furthermore, we are faced with a mass of repeated elements in
which no clear subordination of one to another is established (Knowlson and Pill-
ing 176), so that we may concentrate on different elements each time we read the
text. There are thirty-eight phrases containing “all,” as in “all sides” (198) or “all
light” (197), that seem to be cancelled out by the thirty-four occurrences of “no,”
as in “no sound” (197) or “no hold” (198) (Brienza and Brater 252), and a number
of contradictory constructions like “all gone” and “never but” are used. This may
give readers the impression that the narrative voice constructs a rudimentary world,
and, at the same time, deconstructs it.
The language of “Lessness” is reminiscent of a person in a state of shock, or
a madman, i.e., the babbling of a deranged person. This piece most radically fore-
grounds the linguistic medium. The construction of “sentences” is so awkward that
it seriously impairs the reconstruction process. Hence, the text draws our attention
to the “sentence”-structure itself. The narrative voice reduces language to repetitious
echoings in a syntaxless chain of words and phrases. The deliberate nonfluency,
in combination with the repetitive structure of this piece and the proliferation of
conspicious “less(ness)” words, generates a style in which the words draw attention
to themselves more as signifiers than as signifieds. The language is free-floating in
proper Derridean fashion. Indeed, the strategy of constructing and simultaneously
deconstructing is reminiscent of Robbe-Grillet’s “mouvement paradoxal” (130).
3.5. The Storytelling Frame
While Ruby Cohn argues that in “Lessness” we are confronted with an observant
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 65
third-person narrator (262), Mary F. Catanzaro thinks that the narrative voice should
be attributed to the “little body,” the faceless storyteller of this piece (“Musical”
47). Although I find both accounts of the text convincing, one might argue that
since the personal pronoun “he” occurs several times, Cohn’s interpretation makes
much more sense. The dispassionate depiction of the rudimentary world of this
piece is reminiscent of third-person neutral narrative. We get, Fludernik suggests,
the typical “camera-eye” effect of the mechanical shutter that registers incoming
stimuli but does not interpret them (Towards 175). Since the depicted images are
distorted ones, however, we get the impression that there has to be something wrong
with the “camera.” Further, I wish to note that the non-figural “camera-eye” cannot
convincingly be ascribed to any position of fixity. Throughout, the text gives a sense
of two distinct points of view operating, namely the point of view of the body, on
the one hand, and the point of view of the “narrator,” on the other (Murphy 113).
In this piece, the subject-object division is made obsolete. The disembodied voice
may simultaneously be related to both points of view, that is to “narrator” and nar-
rated alike. Hence, we may be confronted with first-person or third-person neutral
narrative. The deliberately defocalized presentation of “Lessness” constitutes a
serious problem for “natural” narratology not only because it rules out possible
anchor points for experientiality but also because the narrative voice remains covert
and impersonal (Chatman 197) throughout the piece. Is it then possible to establish
experientiality anywhere in the text?
I think that we can read “Lessness” as the projection of the consciousness or
imagination of the “character,” the “narrator,” or both, the “narrator”-narrated. To
begin with, the human faculty of imagination plays a crucial role in the depiction
of story-world. One can only distinguish between the sand, the sky, the ruins, and
the figure with the “eye of imagination,” not with the “eye of flesh.” Furthermore,
the piece evokes desire for a state where time has come to rest or where the mind
enjoys “the blue celeste of poesy” (199). I would argue that the projected mind in
“Lessness” carries out a mental experiment, namely the experiment of imagining
the end of time. Like the attempt to imagine the death of imagination in Beckett’s
“Imagination Dead Imagine,” this mental experiment is based on a paradox, since
time is ultimately necessary to imagine a state in which time has come to rest.
As the work unfolds, the projected consciousness realizes that the experiment of
imagining the end of time is doomed to failure. The form of “Lessness,” that is the
repetition of the sixty sentences, which constitutes the most outstanding feature
of the text, contradicts the subject matter of this piece. “The passing hour” (197)
is not a “dream” but the ultimate reality of human existence. “Dusk” and “dawn”
are not “figments” but “dispeller[s] of figments” (201). This short prose work is
not “timeless” and cannot be characterized in terms of “changelessness” because
the mind it projects moves within time, and, in doing so, changes the order of the
sixty sentences. The “true refuge,” in which one can have the illusion of an eternal
present, is ultimately “issueless” (197) since time will always go on.
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
66 Jan Alber
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 67
in any of the three books I have cited and mentions postmodernist texts merely in
passing. As Lieske points out, Fludernik’s approach is particularly important in the
context of poststructuralist debates about the end of narrative or the death of the
author because it reclaims postmodernist fiction for narratological analysis despite
this fiction’s lack of conventional plot or logical coherence (374).
Moreover, Fludernik’s narrative paradigm has helped this essay to an entirely
new interpretation of “Lessness.” One might argue that “natural” narratology paves
the way for a new reading of this initially alien and uncommunicative text. I have
utilized the following schemas, frames, or scripts as parts of a larger attempt to
narrativize Beckett’s “Lessness.” First, I have employed the schema of temporal
directedness and that of agency as a goal-oriented process on Fludernik’s cogni-
tive level I for the context of a thought experiment. Second, I have referred to the
REFLECTING frame on level II, which turns the act of telling into a process of
self-reflexive rumination, for the mental activity in the course of a thought experi-
ment. Third, I have utilized narratological concepts and familiar knowledge about
first- and third-person neutral narrative on level III in order to establish a storytelling
situation. As I have shown, narrativization by means of the consciousness factor
acquires a central status in experimental writing like “Lessness” where the read-
ers’ establishment of experientiality serves to identify some sort of teller-figure,
a registering mind. Even though the readers’ attempts to establish experientiality
are seriously impaired, we may read “Lessness” as the projection of the readers’
consciousness or of the consciousness of the block-like figure, the “narrator,” or
both, the “narrator”-narrated. One might argue that the projected mind carries out
a mental experiment that is similar to the attempt to imagine the death of imagina-
tion, namely the experiment of imagining the end of time. Further, I would argue
that the projected consciousness in this piece struggles with its imaginings in the
course of the mental experiment and realizes that the task of imagining the end
of time is ultimately impossible. Hence, we can read “Lessness” as the agonized
ruminations of a mind that struggles with some kind of traumatic experience. I
think that the projected consciousness realizes not only that its own existence but
also that its “heroic” attempt to break out of the stream of infinite time are noth-
ing but insignificant ripples on the surface of infinite time. Time imprisons us all.
The mind begins to understand that while the stream of infinite time will never
stop, both its existence and the mental experiment will sooner or later end. This
quasi-traumatic experience of feeling the ultimate meaninglessness of one’s own
existence could, in a way, account for why the images that can be reconstituted on
the basis of the information given in the text are very distorted ones. One might
argue that the projected mind finds itself in a state of shock. Consequently, the
language of this mind is syntaxless and its perception, deranged. It may experience
feelings of terror, hallucinations, or psychosomatic disturbances. I suspect that we
are all more or less familiar with such disruptions of ordinary human experience.
As far as “Lessness” is concerned, Fludernik suggests, embodiment is reduced
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
68 Jan Alber
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 69
she attempts to include almost every text in her definition (347ff.), the term “nar-
rative” becomes meaningless. The more a term includes, the less it means. And
this is the “lessness” of “natural” narratology.
Another problem is, of course, that the new paradigm is supposed to deal with
an incredibly large number of “narrative” texts. I doubt that Fludernik’s quasi-
universal naturalizing mode of reading can do justice to all these texts. As I have
shown, if one is willing to, it is even possible to narrativize a machine-generated
text like “Lessness,” actually structured by a throw of the dice, as the expression
of a subject’s thought. A “natural” narratological analysis ultimately has to ignore
certain aspects, like the mechanical structure of “Lessness,” in order to make a text
fit into its new consciousness-oriented paradigm. Such a piece calls for another
mode of reading than the naturalizing mode prescribed by “natural” narratology.
By narrativizing “Lessness,” we miss the central point of a postmodernist text that
foregrounds ontological chaos, i.e., ontological questions concerning the self, or
the mode of existence of the self (McHale 9-11); we impose a normalizing strategy
on the text rather than deal with its fundamental otherness. Throughout the writing
of this paper, I had the odd sensation that the easier it is to narrativize Beckett’s
“Lessness,” the more modernist the text becomes or seems.5 To put this slightly dif-
ferently, I thought that my consciousness-oriented, “natural” narratological analysis
ultimately involves some kind of modernist reading strategy. It is obviously much
easier to establish a consciousness factor in a kind of writing that deals excessively
with the depiction of consciousness (e.g., in texts by James Joyce, Virginia Woolf,
Ernest Hemingway, or William Faulkner) than it is to do so in a kind of writing
that calls the very existence of consciousness into question. There is a fundamental
contradiction between the aims of postmodernist literature, i.e., pieces like “Less-
ness” and texts written by experimentalists like B.S. Johnson, Christine Brook-
Rose, Alasdair Gray, or Brigid Brophy, on the one hand, and Fludernik’s attempt
to narrativize them on the other. In Towards a ‘Natural’ Narratology, Fludernik
postulates something like a biological core, a minimal cognitive basis.6 In contrast
to this, both postmodernist literature and poststructuralist thought (in Jacques Der-
rida, Michel Foucault, Julia Kristeva, et al) call the very existence of a biological
core and a minimal cognitive basis into question, and look at human beings as free-
floating signifiers. One can of course argue that such self-reflexive word-gaming
constitutes a last-ditch scenario for narrativization in terms of “natural” cognitive
parameters, and that it ultimately has its roots in the “real world.” Nevertheless,
I think that where experientiality resolves into words, “natural” narratology finds
its ultimate horizon. Where language has become pure language, structured by a
machine, or free-floating in Derrida’s sense, disembodied from speaker, context,
and reference, both human experience and Fludernik’s concept of narrativization
by means of human experience become redundant.
Since narrativity (in both the traditional and Fludernik’s sense) is not a neces-
sary condition of inclusion in the literary canon (one need only consider the mass
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
70 Jan Alber
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 71
Notes
1
“Reflecting” refers to the mental activities outside utterance that turn the
act of telling into a process of recollection and self-reflective introspection or
rumination (44).
2
The body in “Lessness” is reminiscent of the figures in Play, where we are
confronted with “three identical grey urns.” We learn that “from each a head pro-
trudes, the neck held fast in the urn’s mouth” (147).
3
Esslin’s list is from his introduction to the BBC Radio 3 production of “Less-
ness” (25 February 1971) and is quoted by Brian Finney (Since 39-40).
4
J. M. Coetzee uses the computer program Univac 1106 to deal with the
combination of sentences in “Lessness.” His results verify mathematically that no
significant ordering principle governs the arrangement of phrases, sentences, or
paragraphs (195-98).
5
As far as modernism is concerned, I refer to Brian McHale’s distinction
between modernist and postmodernist fiction. According to McHale, modernist
fiction, particularly the stream-of-consciousness novel, foregrounds epistemological
questions, i.e., questions of knowledge and consciousness, whereas postmodernist
fiction foregrounds ontological questions, i.e., questions of modes of existence (9-11).
6
Experientiality is an essentialist notion; Fludernik assumes that experience
is the same for everyone.
Works Cited
Bal, Mieke. Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative. Second Ed.
Toronto: U of Toronto P, 1997.
Beckett, Samuel. “All Strange Away.” Samuel Beckett: The Complete Short Prose,
1929-1989, 169-81.
___. Comment C’est. Paris: Les Editions de Minuit, 1961.
___. “Enough.” Samuel Beckett: The Complete Short Prose, 1929-1989, 186-92.
___. How It Is. London: Calder & Boyars, 1964.
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
72 Jan Alber
___. “Imagination Dead Imagine.” Samuel Beckett: The Complete Short Prose,
1929-1989, 182-85.
___. “Lessness.” Samuel Beckett: The Complete Short Prose, 1929-1989, 197-201.
___. “The Lost Ones.” Samuel Beckett: The Complete Short Prose, 1929-1989,
202-23.
___. “Ping.” Samuel Beckett: The Complete Short Prose, 1929-1989, 193-96.
___. Play. Collected Shorter Plays of Samuel Beckett. London: Faber and Faber,
1984. 145-60.
___. Samuel Beckett: The Complete Short Prose, 1929-1989. Ed. S. E. Gontarski.
New York: Grove, 1995.
___. Sans. Paris: Les Editions de Minuit, 1969.
___. Waiting for Godot. London: Faber and Faber, 1985.
Brienza, Susan D., and Enoch Brater. “Chance and Choice in Beckett’s ‘Lessness.’”
English Literary History 43.2 (1976): 244-58.
Bryden, Mary. Women in Samuel Beckett’s Prose and Drama: Her Own Other.
Lanham: Barnes & Noble Books, 1993.
Buning, Marius. “‘Lessness’ Magnified.” From Caxton to Beckett: Essays Presented
to W.H. Toppen on the Occasion of his Seventieth Birthday. Ed. Jacques B.H.
Alblas and Richard Todd. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1979. 101-21.
Catanzaro, Mary F. “Musical Form and Beckett’s Lessness.” Notes on Modern Irish
Literature 4 (1992): 45-51.
___. “Song and Improvisation in ‘Lessness.’” Beckett in the 1990s: Selected Pa-
pers from the Second International Beckett Symposium held in The Hague,
8-12 April, 1992. Ed. Marius Buning and Lois Oppenheim. Samuel Beckett
Today/Aujourd’hui. An Annual Bilingual Review/Revue Annuelle Bilingue.
Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1993. 211-18.
Chatman, Seymour. Story and Discourse: Narrative Structure in Fiction and Film.
Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1978.
Coetzee, J. M. “Samuel Beckett’s Lessness: An Exercise in Decomposition.” Com-
puters and the Humanities 7 (1973): 195-98.
Cohn, Ruby. Back to Beckett. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1973.
Culler, Jonathan. Structuralist Poetics: Structuralism, Linguistics and the Study of
Literature. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1975.
Dearlove, J. E. “‘Last Images’: Samuel Beckett’s Residual Fiction.” Journal of
Modern Literature 6.1 (1977): 104-26.
___. Accommodating the Chaos: Samuel Beckett’s Nonrelational Art. Durham,
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 73
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
74 Jan Alber
___, and Joshua Waletzky. “Narrative Analysis: Oral Versions of Personal Ex-
perience.” Essays on the Verbal and Visual Arts. Ed. J. Helms. Seattle: U of
Washington P, 1967. 12-44.
Lieske, Stephan. Rev. of Towards a ‘Natural’ Narratology, by Monika Fludernik.
Zeitschrift für Anglistik und Amerikanistik 46 (1998): 373-75.
McHale, Brian. Postmodernist Fiction. London: Methuen, 1987.
Minami, Masahiko. Rev. of Towards a ‘Natural’ Narratology, by Monika Fludernik.
Narrative Inquiry 8.2 (1998): 467-72.
Mood, John J. “Samuel Beckett’s Impasse—Lessness.” Ball State University Forum
14.4 (1973): 74-80.
Murphy, Peter. Reconstructing Beckett: Language for Being in Samuel Beckett’s
Fiction. London: U of Toronto P, 1990.
Opas, Lisa Lena, and Joensuu Kujamäki. “A Cross-Linguistic Study of Stream-
of-Consciousness Techniques.” Journal of the Association for Literary and
Linguistic Computing 10.4 (1995): 287-91.
Pier, John. Rev. of Towards a ‘Natural’ Narratology, by Monika Fludernik. Style
31 (1997): 555-60.
Pountney, Rosemary. “The Structuring of Lessness.” The Review of Contemporary
Fiction 7.2 (1987): 55-75.
Prince, Gerald. A Dictionary of Narratology. London: U of Nebraska P, 1987.
___. “On Narratology: Criteria, Corpus, Context.” Narrative 3.1 (1995): 73-84.
___. Narratology: The Form and Functioning of Narrative. New York: Mouton, 1982.
Rabinovitz, Rubin. Innovation in Samuel Beckett’s Fiction. Urbana: U of Illinois
P, 1992.
Ricoeur, Paul. Time and Narrative. Vol. 1. Trans. Kathleen McLaughlin and David
Pellauer. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1984.
Rimmon-Kenan, Slomith. Narrative Fiction: Contemporary Poetics. London:
Methuen, 1983.
Robbe-Grillet, Alain. Pour un nouveau roman. Paris: Editions du Minuit, 1963.
Ronen, Ruth. Rev. of Towards a ‘Natural’ Narratology, by Monika Fludernik.
Journal of Pragmatics 28.5 (1997): 646-48.
Ryan, Marie-Laure. “The Modes of Narrativity and Their Visual Metaphors.” Style
26 (1992): 368-87.
Solomon, Philip H. “Purgatory Unpurged: Time, Space and Language in ‘Less-
ness.’” Journal of Beckett Studies 6 (1980): 63-72.
Stanzel, Franz Karl. A Theory of Narrative. Trans. Charlotte Goedsche, with a
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The “Moreness” or “Lessness” of “Natural” Narratology 75
This content downloaded from 191.85.23.152 on Mon, 28 May 2018 23:54:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms