Argumentation and Interpersonal Justification
Argumentation and Interpersonal Justification
Argumentation and Interpersonal Justification
ALVIN I. GOLDMAN
University of Arizona
Department of Philosophy
Soc. Sci 213
Tuscon, AZ 85721
USA
ABSTRACT: There are distinct but legitimate notions of both personal justification and inter-
personal justification. Interpersonal justification is definable in terms of personal justifica-
tion. A connection is established between good argumentation and interpersonal justification.
Both of these arguments are valid, and one of them has true premises. So
one of them satisfies the conditions of (3) for being a good argument. But
neither is a good argument, says Feldman, since I have no reason to accept
either conclusion. Or, even if being valid gives them some merit, neither
is any better than the other, even though one in fact has true premises.
Hence the logical conditions for being a good argument are not sufficient
for argument goodness. Feldman goes on to claim that crucial to the
goodness of an argument is the epistemological or epistemic status of the
premises for the argument user. Although I do not fully agree with Feldman
in faulting the logical notion of good argument, I do agree that an episte-
mological sense of good argument is (also) extremely important, and I shall
follow Feldman in making use of his epistemological account.
Feldman offers roughly the following definition of the epistemological
conception of a good argument:1
160 ALVIN I. GOLDMAN
We are now in a position to address Thesis 2. This thesis says that no social
discursive process can create or transmit justification. But definitions (5)
and (6) that we have constructed clearly undercut this thesis. They provide
clear senses in which a speaker might justify a proposition to a hearer. As
long as it is possible for an argument to be (epistemologically) good relative
to a person, then justification-creation and justification-transmission are
possible social relationships. As long as there is such a thing as P-justifi-
cation, and such things as ‘proper connections’ between premises and
conclusions (whether deductive or inductive), the indicated relationships
can obtain. Admittedly, the existence of such things is not wholly uncon-
troversial. But if these things are granted, the interpersonal conception of
justification (or several such conceptions) is readily generated.
IP-justification is not equivalent, of course, to mere persuasion (even in
the case of the persuasion-entailing sense of IP-justification). A speaker
might persuade a hearer of a proposition with an argument that is not epis-
temologically good relative to either the speaker or the hearer. That would
be persuasion without IP-justification. (Of course, it might still be a case
of subjective IP-justification, but it would not be objective IP-justification.)
In the final segment of this paper, I turn to the topic of good argumen-
tation, where I mean by ‘argumentation’ not a set of sentences or propo-
sitions, which is what I take an ‘argument’ to be, but an act of presenting
an argument to an audience or an interlocutor. Elsewhere (Goldman, 1994)
I have claimed that the principles or criteria of good argumentation do not
coincide with the criteria for good arguments understood in the logical
sense. For one thing, argumentation should be appropriately directed or
tailored to the speaker’s audience (or interlocutor), an element absent in
the criteria for a good argument in the logical sense. Here I want to discuss
the connection between good argumentation and IP-justification.
In what way should a piece of argumentation be tailored to its intended
audience? First of all, let us concentrate on cases in which the speaker
means to endorse or defend the presented argument, thereby excluding cases
in which one merely puts an argument forth for consideration, examina-
tion, or inquiry (cf. Meiland, 1989). Is it equally acceptable for the speaker
to endorse or present any argument that she herself accepts? I suggest as
a further constraint that a speaker should try to present arguments that have
ARGUMENTATION AND INTERPERSONAL JUSTIFICATION 163
NOTE
1
Feldman’s full definition also specifies that an argument is good relative to a person only
if it’s not ‘defeated’ for him/her. I omit the topic of defeaters because it would require too
much space. As far as I can see, however, proper treatment of defeaters would not change
any of the points made in the rest of the paper.
REFERENCES