Kornblith Hilary. - The Psychological Turn
Kornblith Hilary. - The Psychological Turn
Kornblith Hilary. - The Psychological Turn
To cite this Article Kornblith, Hilary(1982)'The psychological turn',Australasian Journal of Philosophy,60:3,238 — 253
To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/00048408212340661
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00048408212340661
This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or
systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or
distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses
should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,
actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly
or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy
Vol. 60, No. 3; September 1982
Hilary Kornblith
238
Hilary Kornblith 239
present state of mind form a privileged class and that the beliefs in this class are
justified, as are those which can be derived from them, say, by deduction and
induction.
The coherence theory of knowledge is also a kind of apsychologistic theory.
One form of the coherence theory has it that all of the beliefs an agent has at a
particular time are members of the privileged class. It is then claimed that there
is a single epistemic rule: the coherence rule. The coherence rule tells us that
those members of the privileged class which 'fit together' in the appropriate way
are justified for the agent in question at the time in question. Coherence
theorists may thus be seen as attempting to explain precisely what their one
epistemic rule amounts to, that is, as attempting to say precisely what 'fitting
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
together' is.
Psychologistic theorists, however, eschew epistemic rules. Instead, a
psychologistic theory of knowledge is characterised by a description of a set of
justification-conferring processes. It is claimed that if the presence of a belief in
a particular agent at a particular time is to be accounted for by one of these
processes, then the agent is justified in holding that belief at that time. Thus far,
the details of the psychologistic theory have yet to be worked out. No one has
yet offered a complete characterisation of the set of justification-conferring
processes, nor, indeed, has a complete account been offered of what makes a
process justification conferring. Nevertheless, the outlines of such a theory have
already clearly emerged, especially in the work of Alvin Goldman. 1
It is not clear from the manner in which I have characterised these two kinds
of theory thus far that there is any genuine difference between the two. Indeed,
it might seem that the psychologistic theory and the apsychologistic theory
come down to very much the same thing. Doesn't each epistemic rule specify a
justification-conferring process for acquiring beliefs? And doesn't each
justification-conferring processs specified by the psychologistic theory allow us
to formulate an epistemic rule for determining justified beliefs? If these two
kinds of theory are to be seen as differing in anything more than style of
formulation, more needs to be said about the difference between epistemic rules
and justification-conferring processes.
II
Let us say that an epistemic rule is a rule which, when applied to a set of beliefs,
yields a set of beliefs as output. The central project of traditional epistemology
has been to discover those rules which yield justified beliefs as output when
applied to the class of privileged beliefs. Thus we will have a rule which states
that beliefs which have properties PI . . . . . P, are members of the privileged
class of beliefs ~r, and we will have a rule which states that if or is the set of one's
privileged beliefs, one is justified in believing the members of zr', where ~" is
the closure of ~r under operations O1. . . . . Om.
(1) The Applicability Constraint: The rule which specifies the class of
privileged beliefs as well as the epistemic rules specifying acceptable operations
on beliefs must be rules which the agent is in a position to apply. Thus,/'1 . . . . .
Pn must be properties which an agent will recognise his beliefs to have, if they
have them, and O I. . . . . O,, must be operations which an agent is in a position
to perform on the members of set 7r of his privileged beliefs.
Why should one believe that epistemic rules must obey the Applicability
Constraint? I believe the motivation for this constraint to be roughly as follows.
A responsible epistemic agent wants to have only those beliefs he is justified in
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
resulting set of beliefs ~r' will be beliefs which the agent in question is justified in
believing.
Since the justifiable application of these rules is knowable a priori, our
knowledge that these rules are so applicable cannot depend on any feature
peculiar to the actual world. But if the applicability of the rules does not depend
on features peculiar to the actual world, that they may be justifiably applied
must be necessarily true.
While I do not endorse the arguments of this section, I believe that they are
quite important. Even a brief look at an incomplete list of those who have
endorsed arguments like those above should convince the reader that the
importance of these arguments is not negligible, and that their influence on the
development of recent epistemology is immense. 2
III
In light of recent work, it can no longer be denied that a certain psychological
element must enter into epistemological theorising. As G. Harman and A.
Goldman have shown, 3 questions about the justification of a belief cannot be
answered independently of questions about its causal ancestry. For any
favoured logical connection among beliefs, one can describe cases where the
logical connection holds but is not mirrored in psychological connections; where
putative epistemic rules tell us that p provides good reason for q, we may
describe cases where an agent believes both p and q, but does not believe p
because he believes q. Familiar examples involve mad neuro-physiologists,
people who believe propositions because they like the sound of particular
sentences expressing them, and so on. An adequate theory of justification must
thus take account of the psychological connections among beliefs. The question
thus facing contemporary epistemologists is no longer, 'Is the proper theory of
knowledge psychologistic or apsychologistic?', but rather, 'How much
psychology must we allow into our epistemology?'.
In order to further explore the real difference between psychologistic and
3See especially Gilbert Harman, Thought (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973),
pp. 24-33; Alvin Goldman, 'Discriminationand Perceptual Knowledge'; Alvin Goldman, 'What
is Justified Belief?' op. cit.
242 The Psychological Turn
apsychologistic theories, we would do well to consider a question which arises
for psychologistic theories of knowledge. The remainder of this section will be
devoted to motivating that question.
Roughly, psychologistic theories are those which hold that a belief is justified
just in case its presence is due to the workings of the appropriate sort of belief
forming process. Psychologistic theorists are thus committed to a certain
interest in the processes by which beliefs are formed. Now it should be clear
that these processes are ones the details of which are known to few, if any,
persons; certainly the details of these processes are not accessible to
introspection. For example, in the case of depth perception, it has been
determined that changes in relative shadow length influence a subject's beliefs
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
about the relative distance of objects; nevertheless, subjects are unaware that
relative shadow length has this effect. This phenomenon can only be accounted
for if we suppose that there is some state of a perceiver, inaccessible to
introspection, which 'registers' relative shadow length and plays a crucial role in
determining the agent's beliefs about the relative distance of objects. What is
important about this case, of course, is that there is nothing peculiar to the role
shadows play in depth perception; there are numerous mechanisms which play
a crucial role in the production and retention of beliefs which are such that an
agent has no direct access to them.
We are now in a position to formulate the question with which psychologistic
theorists must deal. Psychologistic theorists claim that a person has a justified
belief just in case the process responsible for the presence of that belief is of the
appropriate sort; if we trace back along the causal chain which leads to the
production of a belief, we will find not only transitions among accessible states,
but also transitions among mental states which are not directly accessible to the
agent. Question: To the extent that psychologistic theorists are correct in
claiming that a belief producing process must be of a certain sort if it is to issue
in justified belief, must we be concerned with only that part of the causal chain
which involves transitions among accessible states, or must we look at the
causal chain from start to finish, i.e., in its production of and transitions among
mental states of whatever sort?
IV
If the arguments in favour of the three constraints on epistemic rules given in
section II are sound, then there is good reason to take the psychological turn in a
most conservative manner. If the motivation for the three constraints on
epistemic rules remains untouched when we take the psychological turn, then
the justification conferring processes of psychologised epistemology are nothing
more than those processes which accord with the epistemic rules of
apsychologistic theories. In short, while the notion of performing an operation
on a set of beliefs is clearly psychological - - the fact that an agent has a belief
which could have been arrived at,by performing a certain operation on his other
beliefs does not guarantee that it was arrived at by performing that operation, --
determination of the set of operation O 1 , . . . , Omis a task which has nothing to
Hilary Kornb#th 243
do with the contingencies of human psychology. Someone who adopts a
position like this grants the psychological point of Section III, but denies that it
has any import for epistemological theorising. There are, after all, two distinct
notions of justification, corresponding to the notions of believing for a reason
and having a reason for believing. 4 Being justified, in the sense of believing for a
reason, is clearly a psychological notion. Someone who opposes psychologism,
however, may well grant this point and yet deny that being justified, in the
sense of having a reason for believing, is to be analysed in psychological terms.
In order to determine what the relations among our beliefs ought to be, we need
only logic; psychology comes in only in determining whether these logical
relations are, in fact, instantiated. There is a deceptively attractive argument
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
4 My way of formulating this distinction is due to Robert Audi, 'Foundationalism and Epistemic
Dependence', Journal of Philosophy, LXXVII (1980), pp. 612-613. The same distinction is
drawn, using different terminology, by Roderick Firth and Alvin Goldman. See R. Firth, 'Are
Epistemic Concepts Reducible to Ethical Concepts ?', in Alvin Goldman and Jaegwon Kim, eds.,
Vah~,es and Morals: Essays in Honor of William Frankena, Charles Stevenson and Richard
Brandt (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978); Alvin Goldman, 'What is Justified Belief?', op. cit.
I will examine only one type of argument given for these constraints; this is not to deny that
arguments of a radically different sort might be given. Nevertheless, as the references cited in
footnote 2 indicate, this kind of argument is quite influential.
6 This Principle was suggested to me, in another context, by Patricia Kitcher.
244 The Psychological Turn
conclusion. What kinds of transition among beliefs make for justification?
Suppose that someone believes that p and on that basis comes to believe that q.
Let us further suppose that p provides good reason to believe that q, but the
agent in question does not know this. Is the transition from p to q adequate for
justification?
It might seem that an argument can be given based on the Principle of
Epistemic Responsibility for the conclusion that the inference in question is not
adequate for justification. Suppose that the agent who makes this inference is
examining his beliefs. He notices that he infers q from p, and he doesn't know
whether p proves good reason for q. We have supposed, of course, that p does
provide good reason for q, but the agent doesn't know this. Now if the agent is
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
in fact justified in believing q on the basis of p, the fact that he doesn't know that
p provides good reason to believe q is irrelevant. But now consider a situation in
which the same agent infers s from r, where r does not provide good reason for
s. Here, again, we may imagine the agent examining his beliefs. He notices that
he has inferred s from r, but he doesn't know whether r provides good reason
for s. For all he can tell, he is in exactly the same situation with respect to r and s
that he is in with respect to p and q. The move from r to s is clearly unjustified
and thus, by the Principle of Epistemic Responsibility, we must hold the agent
culpable for his epistemic error. But if the agent is justified in making the
inference from p to q, then the agent has done something epistemically
praiseworthy in one case and epistemically blameworthy in another, where the '
agent is not in a position to tell the difference between the two! Again, the
notion of culpable ignorance does not seem to apply, and this application of the
Principle of Epistemic Responsibility seems unfair. The only way out of this
problem, it seems, is to deny that the inference from p to q is adequate for
justification when the agent does not know that it is adequate for justification.
If this argument is valid, then all those features of a person which make him
justified in believing a proposition must be directly accessible to him; in short,
this is an argument for the Applicability Constraint. Taking the psychological
turn does not seem to block the arguments of section II which led us from the
Applicability Constraint to the A Priority and Necessity Constraints, and thus
the search for epistemic rules once again takes its place at the forefront of
epistemological theorising. Naturalising epistemology, it seems, can be
accomplished merely by appending a footnote to apsychologistic theories.
V
Certain very general considerations about responsibility play a crucial role in the
argument just given, and it will be important to bring them out into the open.
Let it be granted that the Principle of Epistemic Responsibility is true; we are
responsible for the beliefs we have. The beliefs we have are generated by certain
processes which take place in us. In order to fulfill our epistemic responsibility,
must we be able to monitor these processes every step of the way? The
argument just given in defence of epistemic rules presupposes that we must. It
should be clear, however, that we need not.
Hilary Kornblith 245
Consider a person who works in a factory and is responsible for the quality of
products produced by a certain machine. One way in which she might fulfil her
responsibility is by mastering all the details of the mechanism by which the
product is produced, and periodically checking each part of the machine to
insure that the mechanism is operating properly. This is, however, a costly and
inefficientway for her to fulfill her responsibility. A far more sensible approach
would be for her to periodically check the products for defects. If defects are
found, the machine may need overhauling; if not, the machine may reasonably
be assumed to be working properly. No knowledge of the inner workings of the
machine is necessary in order to perform this task.
The same is true with beliefs. Each of us is responsible for the beliefs he has.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
7 This example was brought to the attention of philosophers by Douglas Gasking's 'Avowals', in
R. Butler, ed., Analytical Philosophy (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1962).
246 The Psychological Turn
chicks on the basis of those chicks' visual appearances. In well trained chicken
sexers, this epistemic habit is a good habit and might thus better be described as
an ability - - the ability to discriminate male from female chicks. Poorly trained
chicken sexers do not acquire good epistemic habits; they do not acquire
abilities.
The Principle of Epistemic Responsibility tells us that chicken sexers are
responsible for their beliefs. In light of the above discussion, we might put the
Principle in the following way: People are responsible for their epistemic habits.
Chicken sexers are thus responsible for the manner in which they come to form
beliefs. The complete psychological description of the process via which chicken
sexers acquire their beliefs about chicks will undoubtedly include transitions
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
among states the very existence of which the chicken sexer is unaware. By
holding the chicken sexer responsible for the reliability of his belief producing
processes, we hold him responsible for these transitions. This amounts to
nothing more, however, than holding him responsible for his epistemic habits,
and this is no more unreasonable than holding him responsible for his other,
non-epistemic, habits.
People are thus responsible for acquiring good epistemic habits just as much
as they are responsible for acquiring other good habits. Of course, in acquiring a
habit, one acquires a tendency to move from mental state to mental state, and
these transitions are not always accessible, much less known, to the person who
goes through them. This does not, however, make the burden of responsibility
for one's habits unduly heavy. If it did, we could never be responsible for any of
our acts, epistemic or otherwise.
The epistemic ability possessed by the chicken sexer is an acquired ability,
and the remarks I have made thus far have an obvious application to all
acquired epistemic habits. Does the Principle of Epistemic Responsibility apply
to innate epistemic habits as well? I believe it does. What the Principle of
Epistemic Responsibility requires, in effect, is that we constantly be on the look-
out for false beliefs. If we have some habit which tends to produce false beliefs,
we are responsible for giving up that habit. But this has nothing to do with
whether our habits are acquired or innate; that a habit is innate does not mean
that it cannot be given up. We are thus responsible for all our epistemic habits.
The truth of the Principle of Epistemic Responsibility thus in no way requires
that we apply the Applicability Constraint to our account of justification
conferring processes.
There is a deeper reason, however, for rejecting the Applicability Constraint,
for, on one straightforward reading of what it requires, it cannot be satisfied. If it
is held that no belief is justified unless it was arrived at under the guidance of
epistemic rules, and in order for a belief to be arrived at under the guidance of
an epistemic rule, the epistemic rule itself must be justifiably believed, then we
are confronted with a very familiar regress. In order for any belief to be
justifiably held one must justifiably believe some epistemic rule, but in order to
believe that one must have arrived at it under the guidance of some further
epistemic ruie, which in turn requires justified belief in thatepistemic rule, and
SO o n .
Hilary Kornb# th 247
A defender of the Applicability Constraint may insist that my reading of the
phrase 'under the guidance of epistemic rules' is too strong. In order to arrive at
a belief under the guidance of epistemic rules, it will be insisted, one need not
actually believe the rules. This reading need not be so weak as to allow that
whenever p, if p, then q, and q are believed that q is arrived at under the
guidance of the epistemic rule which licenses the operation of modus ponens.
Rather, in determining whether a particular belief is justified, we look at the
particular inferences which were actually made m this is where the psychology
comes in m and we then determine whether these inferences are licensed by
the epistemic rules. If they are, then the inferences take place under the
guidance of the epistemic rules.
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
This weak reading of 'under the guidance of epistemic rules' solves one
problem for the defender of the Applicability Constraint, but, at the same time,
destroys its motivation. The motivation behind insisting that epistemic rules be
applicable is simply that unless an agent can consider these rules, recognise their
truth and then apply them, the agent will not be able to decide what he ought to
believe. On the weak reading of proceeding 'under the guidance of epistemic
rules', however, the agent need neither consider the rules nor recognise their
truth. What then is the point in insisting that the rules be applicable? It must, of
course, be possible for our reasoning to be governed by the epistemic rules, but
once the strong reading of 'under the guidance of' is dropped, as it must be, that
we act under the guidance of epistemic rules requires no more in the way of our
applying them than that we digest under the guidance of the laws of chemistry.
There is no need, however, to revert to the weak reading if the scope of the
strong reading is restricted. When we insist that all beliefs must be arrived at
under the guidance of epistemic rules in order to be justified, the strong reading
leads to an infinite regress. If, however, we exempt beliefs in the epistemic rules
from this requirement, the regress is halted. It will not do to claim that beliefs in
the epistemic rules are justified no matter how they are arrived at, for this is not
true. Any belief can be had for bad reasons. Nevertheless, while other beliefs
require some special action on the part of the agent to be justified m namely,
reasoning under the guidance of epistemic rules ~ it might be claimed that
beliefs in the epistemic rules, while not justified whenever held, need not be
subject to the same strict requirements as other beliefs. If applicability is to be
preserved and the regress avoided, it must be possible to chart this middle
course.
It is here that the A Priority Constraint comes in. If the epistemic rules are a
priori knowable, one may be justified in believing them without actually
applying epistemic rules. There are, to be sure, ways in which one might come
to believe the rules which would fail to justify one's belief ~ for example, if one
were to believe them on the basis of bad authority - - but as long as these ways
can be ruled out, the belief in the epistemic rule is justified. The requirement for
justified belief in epistemic rules is purely negative, for they are justified so long
as they are not the product of illusion, bad authority, etc.; other beliefs,
however, are only justified if they are arrived at under the guidance of epistemic
rules. This is, I believe, the position one must adopt if the Applicability
248 The Psychological Turn
Constraint is to be honoured.
In order to fill out this position, one must give some account of the property
which illusion, bad authority, and so on, have in common in virtue of which
beliefs in the epistemic rules arrived at by these means are not justified; let us
call this common property P. It must be sufficient for a belief in an epistemic
rule to be justified that the means by which it was arrived at lacks property P,
we cannot require that the agent believes that it lacks property P without a
vicious regress. The result is thus a psychologistic theory of justification for
beliefs in the epistemic rules together with an apsychologistic theory of
justification for all other beliefs.
It is not possible to adopt an apsychologistic theory through and through-- to
Downloaded By: [Canadian Research Knowledge Network] At: 20:41 29 March 2009
See especially, 'Naming and Necessity', in G. Harman and D. Davidson, eds., Semantics of
Natural Language (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1972), pp. 253-355. For a particularly illuminating
account of the defect in this argument, see Philip Kitcher, 'A Priori Knowledge', Philosophical
Review, LXXXIX (1980), pp. 17-18, and 'A Priority and Necessity', Australasian Journal of
Philosophy, 58 (1980), pp. 89-101.
Hilary Kornblith 249
If the arguments I have offered are correct, the importance of taking the
psychological turn in epistemology has been vastly underrated. The central task
of apsychologistic epistemology was to discover the correct set of epistemic rules
- those rules in accordance with which an epistemic agent would have to
-
epistemic rules, they are necessary truths, though my reasons for thinking this
are based on a Kripkean notion of necessity and not on the notion of necessity
which, I believe, motivates the apsychological account described. In any case,
such a claim requires an argument, and until arguments are given, I see no
reason for placing any constraints like those discussed on epistemological
theorising.
My suggestion that epistemologists ought to give up the project of looking for
applicable, a priori knowable and necessary epistemic rules is not meant to
amount to the view that epistemology is dead. A naturalistic epistemology
brings with it a new set of problems and a new set of projects. If I am right, the
old project of finding epistemic rules is dead, but the field of inquiry of which
that project was a part is very much alive. Work has only begun on an adequate
account of what it is that makes a belief forming process justification conferring.
VI
Thus far I have argued that the psychological turn should effect a substantial
change in epistemological theorising. I do not mean to suggest, however, that
the concerns which motivated traditional theories can be ignored. There is, I
believe, a real worry for psychologistic theories of knowledge which derives
from the arguments presented in section IV, and I do not believe that this worry
has been adequately addressed yet.
There seem to be at least two kinds of case in which a process which seems to
be justification conferring does not yield a justified belief:
(a) While the agent's belief is caused by what seems to be a justification
conferring process, the agent believes that the belief was caused by a
process which is not justification conferring.
status of a belief is, at least in part, a function of the process by which the belief
was produced; this is not to say that it is not a function of other things as well.
Indeed, it should be clear that if we divide psychological processes into types
in any reasonable sort of way, the justificatory status of a belief must depend on
something more than the type of process by which it was produced. If you and I
both come to believe that a certain object in front of us is an orange, and we
both come to believe this on the basis of the object's visual appearance, then on
any intuitively reasonable~account of how to divide psychological processes into
types, you and I have just undergone the same type of psychological process.
This does not, however, guarantee that our beliefs have the same justificatory
status. If I have independent reason to believe that the object which appears to
be an orange is in fact a piece of artificial fruit, and yet, for whatever reason, this
bit of information does not in any way affect my belief about the object in front
of me, then I will not be justified in my belief while you are justified in yours.
Similarly, if I have special reason to doubt my ability to recognise oranges and
yet still come to have the belief that the object in front of me is an orange, I will
again be unjustified in my belief while you are justified in yours.
An adequate account of justification will thus have to allow that the
justificatory status of a belief is at least a function of two variables: the process
which is responsible for the presence of the belief and the agent's background
beliefs. Two processes of the same type may yield beliefs of different
justificatory status if they operate in environments of suitably different
background beliefs.
Cases Of type (a) are merely one kind of example which show the importance
of background beliefs in helping to determine the justificatory status of a belief.
Examples of this sort do not exhibit a defect in psychologism; they exhibit a
defect only in a crude psychologistic theory which insists that the justificatory
status of a belief depends on the type of process responsible for its presence, and
nothing else.
Cases of type (b) have a different sort of solution. What is at issue here has
come to be known as the social character of knowledge. Harman, for example,
has urged that an otherwise unexceptional means of arriving at beliefs will not
be justification conferring in a suitably hostile environment; in particular, a
belief cannot be justified, whatever the process which produced it, if there is a
widely known challenge to the belief in the agent's community which the agent
Hilary Kornblith 251
VII
I would like to turn to one final point, and this has to do with the motivation for
the project of discovering the proper set ofepistemic rules. My point here is
substantially similar to a point made by Alvin Goldman. n Suppose that, like
Descartes, one believes that human beings are in a position to choose their
beliefs; in short, that there is free choice of belief. If this were so, then a
responsible epistemic agent would have to develop a set of rules for deciding
what beliefs he ought to adopt. Thus, we see the need for epistemic rules.
The view that there is free choice of belief, however, is no longer widely held,
and I will take for granted here that it is false. If it is, then once again we see that
the motivation for the project of discovering the proper set of epistemic rules
disappears. Epistemic beliefs are no longer seen as a necessary prerequisite for
justified non-epistemic beliefs; they are more plausibly viewed as products of
reflection o n the non-epistemic beliefs one already has and on the manner in
which one has acquired them. 13
If we allow that beliefs are not subject to direct voluntary control, must we
also give up the Principle of Epistemic Responsibility? Isn't it contradictory, or
at best unfair, to insist that we are responsible for the beliefs we have and yet
deny that the processes by which we form our beliefs are subject to our direct
voluntary control? I believe that the answer to both of these questions is, 'no'.
The possibility of reconciling our lack of free choice of belief with the Principle
of Epistemic Responsibility rests on the fact that while our beliefs are not