Human Interaction and The Law : Lon L. Fuller
Human Interaction and The Law : Lon L. Fuller
Human Interaction and The Law : Lon L. Fuller
Lon L. Fuller
• This essay was delivered as an address to the thirteenth annual meeting of the Board
of Editors of this publication, September 26, 1969.
2 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
garded as a kind of museum piece offering an object for serious study only to
anthropologists curious about the ways of tribal peoples.
This neglect of the phenomenon called customary law has, I think, done
great damage to our thinking about law generally. Even if we accept the
rather casual analysis of the subject offered by the treatises, it still remains
true that a proper understanding of customary law is of capital importance
of certain disapproved actions, but also the obverse side of this negation, the
meaning it confers on foreseeable and approved actions, which then furnish
a point of orientation for ongoing interactive responses. Professors Parsons and
Shils have spoken of the function, in social action, of "complementary ex-
pectations"1; the term "complementary expectations" indicates accurately
the function I am here ascribing to the law that develops out of human
Surely, our reaction would be, this is a most curious way to open a
discussion of language. We would be apt to say:
But this statement does not tell us what language is for. Plainly its pur-
pose is communication. If that is its purpose, why then of course men
will go on using generally the same sounds their fathers did and that
their neighbors do now: the reason they do this is simply that they want
to be understood.
Yet in spirit and thought this imaginary introduction to linguistics is not far
from what we find about customary law in treatises on jurisprudence. It will
be well to turn briefly to some appraisals of customary law taken from the
existing literature.
A much-quoted discussion is to be found in Holland's Elements of Juris-
prudence. He asserts that the characteristic which marks customary law is
that "it is a long and generally observed course of conduct." He goes on to
explain:
extent to which one man's beliefs and acts will be seen as affecting his fellows
will depend upon the degree to which men see themselves as parts, one of
another, and upon their beliefs about the intangible forces that unite them.
Within the extended family the distinction between other-regarding and self-
regarding acts will assume an aspect very different from what it has in our
own society, composed, as that society is, largely of strangers with a strong
Now I suggest that any responsible public official would reflect a long time
before embracing such an alternative. Its danger would lie in the damage it
would inflict on the neat symbolism of a one-to-one ratio, in the confusion it
might introduce into the accepted meaning of the acts involved. This is a case
where both sides would probably be well-advised to stick with the familiar
ritual since a departure from it might forfeit the achieved gains of a stable
9
References to most of the literature on this subject will be found in Max Gluckman,
The Judicial Process among the Barotse of Northern Rhodesia, 2nd ed. (1967), chs. V
and IX.
10
E. Adamson Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man (1954), p. 28.
LON L. FULLER 11
Is it likely that his fellow tribesmen would be content to visit on the offender
some moderate measure of social censure? If this illustration seems contrived,
it may be observed that in our free society it is an accepted legal principle
that a man incurs no liability for expressing to another a low opinion of his
intelligence and integrity. If a lawyer trying a case in court were to take
advantage of this freedom in addressing the judge, he might very well find
11
See Claude Levy-Strauss, The Savage Mind (1962, English trans. 1966).
12
Op. cit. supra note 9, pp. 82-162, 387-398. (Gluckman's answer to critics on this
point will be found in the second reference.)
12 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
ing vehicle careening back and forth across the road apparently out of con-
trol. In situations like these what is demanded is plainly something like the
judgment and concern of "the reasonable man"; in such a context the rule
of the road can furnish at most a kind of presumptive guide as to what to
do when other factors in the situation offer no clear solution.
Primitive society, like vehicular traffic, is run by a system of interlocking
13
Op. cit. supra note 9, pp. 37-45.
LON L. FULLER 13
of the rule that you pass the oncoming vehicle on the right. At this point the
anthropologist begins to lose his patience and demands that the earthling give
him some simple, easily understood reason why the rule that you overtake on the
left is the appropriate rule to go with the rule that you pass the oncoming
vehicle on the right. Those of us who feel we might have some difficulty in
producing a prompt response to this demand may take some consolation in
T H E BRIEF ACCOUNT of contract law that follows has been included here
primarily for the light it may shed on customary law, which is often and
properly said to contain a "consensual element." In this shared aspect contract
law and customary law are indeed near-cousins, and a study of either will
help to understand the other. In the course of the analysis that follows, I shall
have occasion to revisit from a somewhat different perspective some of the
14 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
sense like that which may attach to a promise explicitly spelled out in words.
All are agreed that a person, a tribe, or a nation does not incur an obligation —
"legal" or "moral" — simply because a repetitive pattern can be discerned in
his or its actions. All would probably also agree that the actions which create
customary law must be such as enter into interactions, though a complication
ensues when we recall that under some circumstances inaction can take on
14
Judge Fitzmaurice, quoted in Clive Parry, The Sources and Evidences of International
Law (1965), p. 60 n. 2.
LON L. FULLER 19
The most obvious example is offered by the plea of self-defense; a man is still
legally privileged to kill an aggressor if this is necessary to save his own life.
But how shall we interpret "necessary" in this context? How far can we ex-
pect a man to run some risk to his own life in order to avoid taking the life
of another? Again, there is the question of reducing the degree of the offense
when a man kills in "hot blood," as when he comes upon another making
to court and will subject themselves, not only to the cost, but also to the
opprobrium of an adverse judgment. There are areas of human concern, then,
where the cliche that you can't make men act morally by law does not hold.
These are, I believe, precisely the areas where the law's sanctions reinforce
interactional expectancies and facilitate a respect for them.
In dealing with primitive systems a distinction is sometimes taken between
15
E.g., Henry Maine, Ancient Law, 10th ed. (1884), pp. 359-361.
24 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
w Supra, p. 9.
LON L. FULLER 25
is also operative here a confusion arising from the fact that we realize that
normally a lawgiver can change any one of his laws simply by repealing it and
providing a quite different law for the governance of events thereafter hap-
pening. It seems curious that the agency that can rewrite the whole book
of laws should be held to respect the most insignificant of its enactments in
judging events that occurred while it was still in effect. There is the paradox
17
Op. cit. supra, note 8, p. 186.
18
I have attempted to deal with these complexities in my book, The Morality of Law,
rev. ed. (1969), esp. chs. II and V.
26 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
ing a legal system will be seen as a very different kind of enterprise than is
suggested when it is described simply as an exercise of "authority" for the
purpose of effecting "social control."
In the analysis now being concluded three distinct kinds of law have been
passed in review: customary law, contract law, and enacted law. This list
omits a fourth expression of law, namely, adjudicative law as exemplified in
19
In my book, Anatomy of the Law (1968, paperback 1969), I have undertaken an
analysis of the special virtues and defects of the common law system, pp. 84-112 (1968
ed.), pp. 133-174 (1969 ed.).
LON L. FULLER ' 27
IMPLICIT IN ALL that has gone before in this essay is the view that law and
its social environment stand in a relation of reciprocal influence; any given
form of law will not only act upon, but be influenced and shaped by, the
established forms of interaction that constitute its social milieu. This means
20
A useful summary of the ways in which sociologists have attempted to distinguish
different forms of the social bond will be found in Ferdinand Tonnies, Community and
Society (1957), pp. 12-29.
28 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
21
Miller v. Miller, 78 I o w a 177, 182, 42 N . W . 6 4 1 , 642 ( 1 8 8 9 ) .
22
Graham v. Graham, 33 Fed. Supp. 936, 938 (E. D. Mich. 1940). See generally,
Foote, Levy and Sander, Cases and Materials on Family Law (1966), ch. 2, pt. II, pp.
297-366; note, "Litigation between Husband and Wife," Harvard Law Review, 79 (1966),
pp. 1650-1665; McDowell, "Contracts in the Family," Boston University Law Review, 45
(1965), pp. 43-62.
LON L. FULLER 29
23
Op. cit. supra note 8, p. 404.
30 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
24
Lucy Mair, An Introduction to Social Anthropology ( 1 9 6 5 ) , p . 181.
25
A study by Colson reported in M a x Gluckman, Politics, Law, and Ritual in Tribal
Society ( 1 9 6 5 ) , p p . 296-299.
26
Conrad Arensberg, The Irish Countryman ( 1 9 6 8 ) , p p . 155-162.
27
T h e thesis of t h e study b y F r i e d m a n , Contract in America ( 1 9 6 5 ) , might b e stated
as t h e tendency of c o n t r a c t u a l relations to convert themselves into something like cus-
t o m a r y law. H o w e v e r , F r i e d m a n ' s study does n o t , i n m y opinion, t a k e sufficient account
of t h e special qualities of t h e economic b a c k g r o u n d of t h e p h e n o m e n a studied; it should
definitely h a v e been called C o n t r a c t i n Wisconsin, n o t C o n t r a c t in America. A n o t h e r
valuable study is Stewart Macaulay, "Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A Pre-
liminary Study," American Sociological Review, 28 (1963), pp. 55-67.
LON L. FULLER 31
So much for the interactions between contractual law and its social context.
Turning now to customary law, the first observation is that this form of law
is at home completely across the spectrum of social contexts, from the most
intimate to those of open hostility. That the family cannot easily organize
itself by a process of explicit bargaining does not mean there will not
grow up within it reciprocal expectancies of the sort that, on a more formal
operated, it is plain, in quite different social contexts, though this does not
mean that a Malinowski might not find elements of reciprocity or exchange
among the Barotse, or that a Gluckman could not find apt occasion to apply
the concept of "the reasonable man" among the Trobrianders. I would suggest
generally that if we seek to discover constancies among the different systems
of customary law we shall find them in the interactional processes by which
28
I am not at this point, of course, referring to such problems as child abuse, com-
pulsory education, and the like.
34 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF JURISPRUDENCE
It is important to observe that the very qualities of enacted law that make
it an inept instrument for regulating intimate relations are precisely those
which lend to it a special capacity to put in order men's interactions within
the larger impersonal society. Within that wider context the basic necessity
is to impose rules that will serve to set the limits men must observe in their
interactions with one another, leaving them free within those limits to pursue
from the man himself, becomes considerably clouded, however, when we con-
sider what happens before and after the confrontation that takes place in
open court. Before the case is brought to court the defendant has to be ar-
rested, and it would certainly be a rare policeman who routinely—and without
taking into account the nature and circumstances of the offense — arrested
every person he believed to have committed a crime. Certainly in dealing
31
I have tried to show the inadequacies of formal legal rules and processes of adjudica-
tion for dealing with "polycentric" problems in "Collective Bargaining and the Arbitrator,"
Wisconsin Law Review, 3 (1963), 18-42, and "Irrigation and Tyranny," Stanford Law
Review, 17 (1965), 1021-1042.