International Encyclopedia of The Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd Edition
International Encyclopedia of The Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd Edition
International Encyclopedia of The Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd Edition
Putnam
For
the
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition
Maria
Baghramian
School
of
Philosophy
University
College
Dublin
Dublin
4,
Ireland
1
Keywords
Conceptual
Relativity,
Ethics,
Externalism,
Functionalism,
Language,
Logical
Positivism,
Mathematics,
Mind,
Putnam,
Quine,
Realism,
Science,
Value
Abstract
American
philosopher,
Hilary
Whitehall
Putnam
(1929-‐)
is
one
of
the
most
influential
analytic
philosophers
of
our
time.
He
is
particularly
well-‐known
for
his
contributions
to
philosophy
of
science,
philosophy
of
mind,
and
philosophy
of
language.
His
work
is
also
marked
by
a
criticial
engagement
with
his
earlier
views
and
several
changes
of
key
philosophical
posititions.
The
present
article
distinguishes
between
early,
middle
and
late
periods
in
Putnam’s
writing
and
discusses
the
most
seminal
ideas
of
each
period.
Particular
attention
is
paid
to
Putnam’s
treatment
of
the
question
of
realism
over
the
three
periods.
2
Life
Hilary
Whitehall
Putnam
is
one
the
most
influential
and
prolific
analytic
philosophers
of
our
time.
He
has
written
extensively
on
a
wide
array
of
philosophical
topics
but
is
particularly
well
known
for
his
contributions
to
philosophy
of
science,
philosophy
of
mind,
and
philosophy
of
language.
Putnam
was
born
in
Chicago
in
1929
but
the
family
soon
moved
to
Paris
where
his
father,
the
eminent
translator
and
literary
editor
Samuel
Putnam,
was
to
translate
the
complete
works
of
Rabelais
and
edit
the
Paris
Review.
In
1933,
the
family
returned
to
the
United
States
and
eventually
settled
in
Philadelphia
where
Putnam
lived
until
his
graduation
from
the
University
of
Pennsylvania
in
1948
with
a
degree
in
Philosophy,
Linguistics
and
German.
After
a
year
in
Harvard,
Putnam
moved
to
UCLA
in
1949
to
do
a
PhD
under
the
supervision
of
the
eminent
logical
positivist
Hans
Reichenbach.
Reichenbach’s
profound
influence
led
to
a
life-‐long
preoccupation
with
philosophy
of
physics,
mathematics
and
an
increasingly
critical
engagement
with
logical
positivism.
Putnam’s
early
academic
career
was
at
Northwestern
(1952–1953)
and
Princeton
University
(1953–1961)
followed
by
four
years
in
MIT
(1961–1965),
where
he
was
Professor
of
the
Philosophy
of
Science
and
instrumental
in
setting
up
a
new
department
of
Philosophy.
From
1962
until
his
retirement,
Putnam
has
been
a
member
of
the
Department
of
Philosophy
in
Harvard,
first
as
Walter
Beverly
Pearson
Professor
of
Modern
Mathematics
and
Mathematical
Logic
and
later
as
the
Cogan
University
Professor.
He
is
a
Fellow
of
the
American
Academy
of
Arts
and
Sciences,
a
Corresponding
Fellow
of
the
British
Academy,
and
was
a
president
of
the
American
Philosophical
Association
(Eastern
Division).
His
numerous
awards
include
the
Rolf
Schock
Prize
in
Logic
and
Philosophy
from
the
Royal
Swedish
Academy
and
The
Ulysses
Medal
from
University
College
Dublin,
Ireland.
He
is
married
to
the
philosopher
Ruth-‐Anna
Putnam.
Work
3
The
sheer
breadth
and
variety
of
Putnam’s
writing,
accompanied
by
a
radical
practice
of
rejecting
or
reformulating
his
earlier
positions,
make
the
task
of
summarizing
and
evaluating
the
full
span
of
his
work
difficult,
if
not
impossible.
The
present
article
distinguishes
between
the
early,
middle
and
late
periods
in
Putnam’s
writing
-‐
what
I
call
Putnam
1,
2
and
3
-‐
and
discusses
the
most
seminal
ideas
of
each
period.
Despite
frequent
changes
of
views
and
philosophical
orientations,
however,
a
number
of
prominent
themes
are
evident
in
Putnam’s
writing,
among
them
are
the
questions
of
realism
and
its
discontents,
a
preoccupation
with
questions
of
the
status
of
science,
a
continuous
concern
with
questions
of
norms
and
values,
and
a
general
aversion
to
dichotomized
thinking.
Early
Putnam
Putnam’s
early
publications
have
the
imprint
of
his
encounter
with
Rudolf
Carnap,
the
most
important
of
the
logical
positivists,
whom
he
came
to
know
during
his
Princeton
years.
Two
topics
were
central.
The
first
was
on
questions
of
synonymy
and
analyticity,
the
topic
of
W.V.O.
Quine’s
seminal
‘Two
Dogmas
of
Empiricism”
(Quine
1951),
where
Quine
had
argued,
against
Carnap,
that
the
distinction
between
analytic
and
synthetic
statements,
or
sentences
true
by
virtue
of
their
meaning
only
vs.
those
true
by
virtue
of
facts
is
untenable.
Putnam’s
“The
Analytic
and
the
Synthetic”
(1962)
is
where
he
establishes
his
own
distinct
philosophical
voice.
The
article
is
also
the
first
clear
example
of
Putnam’s
aversion
to
philosophical
dichotomies
and
beginnings
of
a
life-‐long
critique
of
logical
positivism.
Putnam
agrees
with
Carnap
that
there
is
an
obvious
and
‘gross
distinction
between
“All
bachelors
are
unmarried”
and
“There
is
a
book
on
this
table”’
(1975a:
36).
However,
he
is
also
in
agreement
with
Quine
that
‘overworking
the
analytic–synthetic
distinction’
distorts
our
views
of
its
significance
for
science
or
Philosophy”
(1975a:
33).
The
distinction,
he
argues,
could
have
a
role
provided
that
we
do
not
treat
it
as
a
sharp
dichotomy
but
as
a
continuum.
There
is
a
small
group
of
concepts,
he
calls
them
‘one-‐criterion
concepts’,
which
have
a
single
criterion
for
application.
For
instance,
the
only
criterion
for
the
application
of
‘bachelor’
is
that
of
being
an
unmarried
man
and
we
cannot
abandon
this
criterion
without
depriving
‘bachelor’
of
its
use,
hence
4
the
analyticity
of
‘all
bachelors
are
unmarried
men’.
A
majority
of
concepts,
on
the
other
hand,
are
‘law
cluster’
concepts
where
‘any
one
law
can
be
abandoned
without
destroying
the
identity
of
the
.
.
.
concept
involved’
(Putnam
1975a:
52).
He
thus
shows
a
way
of
thinking
about
the
Quine
-‐
Carnap
debate
that
retains
the
initial
insight
of
the
defenders
of
analyticity
while
avoiding
its
philosophical
pitfalls.
The
second
area
of
focus
in
this
early
period
was
mathematics
and
its
philosophy.
Putnam‘s
co-‐publication
of
the
proof
of
Hilbert’s
Tenth
Problem
(1961),
in
collaboration
with
Martin
Davis,
established
his
reputation
as
a
mathematician.
A
collection
of
articles
on
philosophy
of
mathematics,
edited
with
Paul
Benacerraf
in
1964,
was
his
first
book-‐length
publication.
Putnam,
in
that
early
period,
was
a
realist
about
both
mathematics
and
science
but
his
realism
about
mathematics
piggy-‐backs
on
realism
about
science.
In
what
has
become
known
as
the
‘Quine-‐Putnam
Indispensability
Argument’,
Putnam,
in
similar
lines
of
thought
put
forward
by
Quine
(e.g.
Quine
1960),
argues
that
much
of
science
is
either
expressed
in
mathematical
terms
or
uses
mathematics
as
an
indispensable
component.
And
to
the
extent
that
scientific
hypotheses
are
true,
in
the
sense
of
corresponding
with
a
mind-‐independent
reality,
then
so
are
the
mathematical
theorems
that
underpin
it.
He
says,
‘quantification
over
mathematical
entities
is
indispensable
for
science,
both
formal
and
physical:
therefore
we
should
accept
such
quantification;
but
this
commits
us
to
accepting
the
existence
of
mathematical
entities
in
question’
(Putnam
1972:
57).
A
realist
interpretation
of
science,
thus,
supports
realism
about
mathematics.
Science
Putnam’s
key
idea
on
realism
about
science
is
known
as
the
‘no
miracle’
or
Putnam-‐Boyd
argument
to
the
best
explanation.
Using
an
abductive
format
and
taking
a
similar
approach
to
the
indispensability
argument
for
mathematics,
Putnam
and
Boyd
argued
that
the
best
explanation
for
the
predictive
and
explanatory
success
of
a
scientific
theory
is
its
truth
or
approximation
to
truth.
Their
argument,
in
a
nutshell,
states:
5
(1)
Mature,
that
is
well-‐supported
and
long-‐established
scientific
theories
result
in
successful
predictions.
(2)
The
best
explanation
for
these
predictive
successes
is
that
such
theories
are
true
or
approximately
true,
i.e.
they
reflect
what’s
going
on
in
the
natural
world.
(3)
Non-‐realist
arguments,
such
as
instrumentalism,
cannot
explain
the
success
of
science.
Therefore,
mature
scientific
theories
are
(approximately)
true.
Scientific
realism
is
the
claim
that
mature
scientific
theories
are
true.
Therefore,
scientific
realism
is
true.
Putnam
explains:
The
positive
argument
for
realism
is
that
it
is
the
only
philosophy
that
does
not
make
the
success
of
science
a
miracle.
That
terms
in
mature
scientific
theories
typically
refer
(this
formulation
is
due
to
Richard
Boyd),
that
the
theories
accepted
in
a
mature
science
are
typically
approximately
true,
that
the
same
term
can
refer
to
the
same
thing
even
when
they
occurs
in
different
theories
-‐
these
statements
are
viewed
not
as
necessary
truths
but
as
part
of
the
only
scientific
explanation
of
the
success
of
science,
and
hence
as
part
of
any
adequate
description
of
science
and
its
relations
to
its
object
(Putnam
1975a:73).
Mind
Putnam’s
other
major
contribution
in
this
period
was
to
philosophy
of
mind.
The
two
dominant
theories
of
the
mind
in
the
second
half
of
twentieth
century
were
logical
behaviorism,
which
reduced
the
mind
to
dispositions
to
behavior
and
patterns
of
stimulus
and
response,
and
Mind–Brain
identity
theory
that
claimed
that
mental
states
are
identical
with
states
of
the
central
nervous
system.
Putnam,
starting
in
the
1962
article
‘Brain
and
Behavior’,
republished
in
Putnam
1975,
argued
that
the
view
that
a
mental
state,
such
as
experiencing
pain,
can
be
reduced
to
certain
types
of
behavioral
states
is
untenable
because
it
ignores
the
fact
that
pain
is
a
private
sensation.
Identity
theory
is
also
defective
because
it
disallows
the
possibility
of
ascribing
mental
states,
such
as
pain,
to
creatures
6
with
a
physical
makeup
different
from
that
of
humans.
If
pain
is
identical
with
certain
neuronal
activities
in
the
human
brain,
then
creatures
with
no
such
neurons
won’t
be
capable
of
experiencing
pain.
Functionalism
was
Putnam’s
positive
contribution
to
philosophy
of
mind.
His
version
of
the
theory
is
known
as
Machine
Functionalism
because
of
the
parallels
he
draws
between
mental
states
and
the
functional
states
of
universal
Turing
machines
or
computers.
A
mental
state
is
characterized
by
its
causal
relations
with
external
stimuli,
or
imput
from
the
senses,
behavioral
responses,
and
relations
with
other
mental
states,
e.g.
beliefs
and
desires.
Mental
states
are
the
causes
of
our
actions
within
the
background
of
our
beliefs
and
desires
about
the
world
but
are
not
reducible
to
behavior.
Even
sensations,
such
as
pain
could
be
explained
functionally.
Things
that
feel
pain
do
so
not
because
of
the
particular
brain
state
they
are
in,
but
because
they
are
in
a
certain
functional
state.
One
strength
of
Functionalism
is
that
it
ensures
the
autonomy
of
the
mind
and
shows
that
‘The
question
of
the
autonomy
of
our
mental
life
does
not
hinge
on
and
has
nothing
to
do
with
that
all
too
popular…
question
about
matter
or
soul-‐stuff.
We
could
be
made
of
Swiss
cheese
and
it
wouldn’t
matter’
(Putnam,
1975:
302).
Just
as
different
machines
need
not
share
the
same
hardware
to
carry
out
the
same
computation,
mental
states,
including
sensations
and
emotional
states,
could
be
functionally
alike
but
physically
different.
What
matters,
Putnam
argued,
is
functional
organization
which
realizable
in
very
different
hardware,
be
it
by
silicon
based
robots
or
by
Martians
with
a
different
evolutionary
history
and
biological
make-‐up.
The
“multiple
realizability”
of
mental
states
became
orthodoxy
of
cognitive
science.
Decades
later,
Putnam
would
repudiate
functionalism
for
reasons
that
are
quite
similar
to
his
rejection
of
behaviorism
and
identity
theory
(Putnam
1987
and
1992).
Earlier
Putnam
had
rejected
a
reductionist
account
of
the
relationship
between
the
mind
and
the
brain,
he
now
warns
against
the
reduction
of
mental
states
to
machine
states
or
brain
software.
In
the
same
way
that
mental
states
cannot
readily
be
identified
or
co-‐related
with
behavioral
or
brain
states,
mental
and
psychological
states,
such
as
hoping,
desiring,
fearing
etc.,
also
cannot
be
co-‐
7
related
software
in
a
straightforward
singular
manner.
In
arguing
against
mind-‐
brain
identity
theory,
Putnam
had
maintained
that
mental
states
are
multiply
realizable
because
they
are
‘compositionally
plastic’.
He
now
believes
that
mental
states
are
also
‘computationally
plastic’
because
a
propositional
attitude,
such
as
a
belief
can
be
realized
by
many
different
computational
states
(Putnam
1994:
47).
The
morale
is
that
intentional
mental
states
cannot
be
reduced
to
either
physical
of
computational
states.
Language
Putnam’s
contribution
to
philosophy
of
language
has
been
momentous.
For
much
of
the
twentieth
century,
philosophy
of
language
was
dominated
by
what
is
commonly
known
as
‘descriptivism’
–
the
approach
to
meaning
adopted
by
the
founders
of
analytic
philosophy,
Gottlob
Frege
and
Bertrand
Russell.
According
to
descriptivism,
names
refer
to
what
they
stand
for
via
what
Frege
calls
‘sense’
or
conceptual
content
and
what
Russell
calls
‘Definite
Descriptions’.
For
Russell,
for
instance,
what
defines
“gold”
is
a
conjunction
of
properties
such
as
its
color,
texture,
weight,
etc.;
“gold”,
thus,
is
a
shorthand
term
standing
for
a
longer
list
of
the
properties
we
associate
with
that
substance.
Meaning,
thus,
is
distinct
from
reference
and
is
mediated
by
descriptions
of
that
reference.
Putnam
and
Saul
Kripke,
in
his
Naming
and
Necessity
(1980),
turned
this
position
on
its
head.
In
‘The
Meaning
of
‘’Meaning’’’
Putnam
sets
out
to
refute
what
he
sees
as
a
‘grotesquely
mistaken’
view
of
language
(1975:21)
arising
from
the
tendency
to
ignore
the
role
of
the
natural
and
social
environment
in
establishing
the
meaning
of
words
in
general
and
names
in
particular.
Two
incompatible
assumptions
are
at
fault,
he
says.
First,
that
to
know
the
meaning
of
a
term
is
to
be
in
an
appropriate
psychological
state
and
second
that
meaning
determines
reference.
Traditional
theories
of
meaning
are
unsatisfactory
because
they
are
individualistic
rather
than
social
and
neglect
the
contribution
of
external
reality
to
meaning.
The
crucial
point
missed
by
descriptivism
was
that
both
the
reference
and
the
meaning
of
natural
kind
terms,
‘water’,
‘gold’,
‘brain’
for
8
instance,
are
determined
by
causal
interactions
between
these
physical
entities
and
referring
minds,
i.e.
language
users.
According
to
Putnam,
natural
kind
words
have
an
‘unnoticed
indexical
component:
water
is
stuff
that
bears
a
certain
similarity
relation
to
the
water
around
here’
(1975:234).
The
reference
of
the
term
‘’water”,
has
been
fixed
by
pointing
out
to
a
stuff
and
saying
something
like
‘this
is
water’
(Putnam
1975:
231).
This
initial
baptism
and
the
continuity
of
usage
have
established
causal
relation
between
the
speakers
and
what
they
are
talking
about.
People
on
earth
and
twin
earth
may
have
the
same
kind
of
mental
images
running
through
their
head
when
they]
think,
respectively,
of
water
and
twater.
Yet
‘water’
in
English
has
a
different
meaning
from
‘water’
in
Twin
Earth
English.
Thus
meaning
is
independent
of
the
‘inner’
mental
states
that
people
possess,
rather,
it
depends
on
external,
natural
and
social
factors.
As
he
famously
puts
it
‘cut
the
pie
any
way
you
like,
‘meanings’
just
ain’t
in
the
head!’
(Putnam
1975:
227).
9
Not
all
language
users
would
have
knowledge
of
the
underlying
composition
of
natural
kinds.
Or
even
be
able
to
always
identify
such
kinds
accurately.
Putnam
introduces
the
idea
division
of
linguistic
labor
to
explain
such
cases
(1975:
227).
Words,
he
argues,
have
producers
and
consumers,
the
experts
and
the
ordinary
users
of
language.
The
users
often
know
only
the
stereotypical
descriptions
associated
with
a
natural
kind
term
and
sometimes
they
get
even
those
wrong.
One
role
of
stereotypes
is
to
facilitate
communication
between
speakers
who
ordinarily
have
very
little
knowledge
of
the
underlying
structure
of
natural
kinds.
To
find
out
whether
a
particular
object
falls
under
a
natural
kind
term
users
have
to
defer
to
the
knowledge
of
the
experts.
For
instance,
ordinary
speakers
know
gold
through
the
stereotypical
properties
(shiny,
yellowish,
precious
metal),
but
in
order
to
authenticate
whether
a
piece
of
metal
is
gold
they
defer
to
the
superior
knowledge
of
the
relevant
experts.
The
Twin-‐Earth
thought
experiment
has
become
a
paradigm
of
philosophical
methodology
in
the
analytic
tradition
and
its
use
has
been
extended
beyond
the
semantics
of
natural
kind
terms
to
other
areas,
including
ethics,
philosophy
of
mind,
and
theories
of
content
and
Putnam
has
remained
constant
in
defending
the
view.
Middle
Putnam
A
preoccupation
with
what
Putnam
calls
the
‘great
question
of
realism’
(Putnam,
1994:
295)
or
the
question
of
how
language
connects
with
the
world,
is
a
unifying
thread
in
Putnam’s
work,
but
the
issue
takes
center
stage
in
Putnam
2.
The
early
Putnam
was
a
realist
not
only
about
the
existence
of
material
objects
but
also
about
mathematical
and
purely
theoretical
entities
such
as
numbers,
fields
and
physical
magnitudes.
The
most
striking
feature
of
Putnam’s
work
in
the
middle
period
is
the
rejection
of
some
of
the
core
assumptions
of
realism
that
he
had
previously
embraced.
The
emergence
of
Putnam
2
can
be
dated
back
to
the
presidential
address
he
gave
at
the
Eastern
Division
of
the
American
Philosophical
Association
in
10
December
1976,
subsequently
published
as
‘Realism
and
Reason’
(1977).
Putnam
used
the
occasion,
rather
dramatically,
to
repudiate
his
earlier
views,
a
position
he
came
to
call
‘metaphysical
realism’.
Metaphysical
realism,
he
argued,
is
committed
to
the
views:
a-‐The
world
consist
of
fixed
totality
of
all
objects.
b-‐The
world
has
a
fixed
totality
of
properties.
c-‐There
is
a
fixed
set
of
‘language-‐independent’
objects
(some
of
which
are
abstract
and
others
are
concrete)
and
a
fixed
‘relation’
between
terms
and
their
extensions.
d-‐There
is
a
sharp
distinction
between
properties
we
discover,
the
factual,
and
the
properties
we
project
onto
the
world
(i.e.
the
evaluative).
e-‐There
is
a
fixed
relation
of
correspondence
in
terms
of
which
truth
can
be
defined
(Putnam
1990:
27).
Putnam
offers
several
arguments
to
show
the
incoherence
of
metaphysical,
the
earliest
and
most
controversial
of
which
is
the
Model
Theoretic
Argument.
The
argument
was
presented
in
at
least
three
different
formulations
and,
at
least
initially,
relied
on
the
Löwenheim–Skolem
theorem
in
mathematics
(Putnam
1977).
The
most
influential
version
is
the
Permutation
Argument
(Putnam
1981)
where
it
is
claimed
that
it
is
possible
to
systematically
permute
the
way
singular
terms
and
predicates
refer
without
changing
the
truth-‐values
of
the
sentences
containing
these
terms.
The
argument
particularly
targets
the
Metaphysical
Realist’s
assumption
that
there
is
a
fixed
‘relation’
between
terms
and
their
extensions
(c
above)
and,
that
there
is
a
fixed
relation
of
correspondence
between
propositions
and
states
of
affairs
(e
above
list).
Take
any
epistemically
ideal
theory,
one
that
meets
all
operational
and
theoretical
constraints
possible,
for
instance
it
is
consistent,
complete,
well-‐formulated.
According
to
the
Metaphysical
Realists,
for
such
a
theory
to
be
true
then
it
also
should
satisfy
a
unique
word-‐world
relationship,
i.e.
its
terms
should
refer
determinately
to
objects
and
entities
(or
classes
of
objects)
in
the
world.
However,
Putnam
contends
that
there
could
be
no
such
thing
as
determinate
reference
as
required
by
the
realists.
Any
assignment
of
truth,
by
envisaging
a
relationship
of
reference,
presupposes
an
interpretation
of
the
referring
language;
the
model-‐theoretic
argument
shows
that
for
any
given
11
language
there
could
be
many
such
interpretations
and
consequently
many
different
ways
of
assigning
(correct)
reference.
Consider
Putnam’s
example
of
‘the
cat
is
on
the
mat’.
The
sentence
comes
out
true
in
an
interpretation
where
‘cat’
refers
to
the
animal
cat
and
‘mat’
to
an
object
we
put
on
the
floor,
but
it
also
comes
out
true
if
we
use
an
alternative
interpretation
where
‘cat’
refers
to
leaves
and
‘mat’
refers
to
trees.
Thus
metaphysical
realism
is
shown
to
be
based
on
an
incoherent
demand.
It
may
be
argued,
using
Putnam’s
own
externalist
theory
of
meaning,
that
‘cat’
refers
to
cats
not
to
leaves
because
it
stands
in
the
appropriate
causal
relation
to
cats
and
not
to
leaves.
Putnam
responds:
‘’How
‘causes’
can
uniquely
refer
is
as
much
of
a
puzzle
as
how
‘cat’
can
on
the
metaphysical
realist
picture”
(1978:
126).
To
think
that
there
is
metaphysical
glue
binding
‘cat’
to
the
animal
cat
is
to
subscribe
to
‘a
magical
theory
of
reference’
(1981:
47).
12
coherently
stated.
But
if
the
scetpcical
hypothesis
is
incoheren,
then
so
is
metaphysical
realism.
Internal
Realism
‘Internal
realism’
is
Putnam
2’s
proposed
alternative
to
metaphysical
realism,
where,
under
the
influence
of
Michael
Dummett,
in
place
of
his
earlier
correspondence
theory,
he
advocates
an
epistemic
view
of
truth.
Internal
realism
is
committed
to
three
core
doctrines:
1)
There
is
more
than
one
true
theory
or
description
of
the
world.
2)
There
is
no
“ready
made
world”.
3′)
“truth
is
an
idealization
of
rational
acceptability
–
some
sort
of
ideal
coherence
of
our
beliefs
with
each
other
and
with
our
experiences
as
those
experiences
are
themselves
represented
in
our
belief
system
–
and
not
correspondence
with
mind-‐independent
or
discourse-‐independent
‘state
of
affairs’.”
(Putnam
1981:
49-‐50)
A
crucial
feature
of
internal
realism
was
its
commitment
to
an
epistemic
view
of
truth.
Truth,
Putnam
2
argued,
is
not
independent
from
knowledge,
but
at
the
same
time,
it
should
not
be
identified
with
contingent
and
changeable
epistemic
achievements
of
a
single
time
and
a
place,
but
with
what
we
can
know
and
justify
under
ideal
epistemic
conditions.
The
assumption
is
that
if
there
were
such
things
as
epistemically
ideal
conditions,
then
statements
that
were
justified
under
such
conditions
would
be
true.
As
Putnam
puts
it,
truth
is
independent
of
justification
here
and
now,
but
not
independent
of
all
justification.
(Putnam
1981).
The
view
aimed
to
deal
with
the
problem
of
access
by
minded-‐beings,
such
as
us,
to
a
mind-‐independent
world.
We
cannot
step
outside
our
language,
our
mind-‐set
or
perspective
and
compare
our
beliefs
about
the
world
to
the
world
as
it
is
in
itself.
To
give
any
substance
to
such
a
view
we
need
to
postulate
a
God’s-‐
eye
view
of
reality,
a
view
not
accessible
to
us
mere
mortals.
The
epistemic
view
of
truth
bypasses
the
need
for
a
God’s
eye
perspective
while
allowing
for
the
possibility
of
objectivity
in
truth
and
knowledge.
13
The
second
important
component
of
internal
realism
is
conceptual
relativity,
the
view
that
there
could
be
alternative,
non-‐compatible
descriptions
of
objects
and
their
properties.
The
key
motivation
for
conceptual
relativity
is
the
conviction
that
the
very
idea
of
an
unconceptualized
world
is
incoherent.
All
our
experiences
of
the
world
are
shaped
by
our
concepts,
here
too
we
cannot
have
a
God’s
Eye
point
of
view,
but
only
“the
various
points
of
view
of
actual
persons
reflecting
various
interests
and
purposes
that
their
descriptions
and
theories
subserve’
(Putnam1981:
50).
To
show
the
force
of
the
argument
Putnam
proposes
a
scenario
where
one
and
the
same
situation
can
be
described
as
involving
very
different
numbers
and
kinds
of
objects
(Putnam
1987,
1989,
1990).
Let
us
take
a
world
containing
objects
a,
b,
c.
Our
usual
way
of
counting
tells
us
that
there
are
three
objects
in
that
world.
However,
according
to
‘mereology’,
a
theory
of
part/whole
relationship
first
formalized
by
the
Polish
logician
Stanislaw
Leśniewski
in
the
early
twentieth
century,
for
every
two
particulars
there
is
an
object
that
is
their
sum.
Given
this
basic
mereological
starting-‐point,
the
world
just
described
will
contain
not
three
but
seven
objects.
Putnam
asks:
faced
with
a
world
with
three
individuals,
does
the
question
how
many
objects
are
there
in
this
world
have
a
determinate
reply?
The
answer
is
no,
because
any
reply
would
depend
on
how
we
interpret
the
word
‘object’.
From
an
atomist
perspective,
the
perspective
most
of
us
take
for
granted,
there
would
be
three
independent,
unrelated
objects
a,
b,
c
in
this
world.
While,
according
to
the
mereological
conceptual
scheme
the
world
will
consist
of
seven
objects,
a,
b,
c,
a+b,
a+c,
b+c,
a+b+c.
The
example
makes
the
internal
realist’s
point
that
we
cannot
coherently
talk
of
a
world
consisting
of
language-‐independent
objects
or
properties
for
the
very
idea
of
object
is
mediated
by
the
concepts
we
use.
In
the
late
1980s,
Putnam
reached
the
conclusion
that
internal
realism,
and
its
epistemic
view
of
truth
in
particular,
faced
problems
similar
to
those
besetting
metaphysical
realism
and
its
concomitant
correspondence
theory
of
truth.
The
metaphysical
realist
needs
to
explain
how
access
to
the
external
world
is
possible,
how
the
human
mind
could
reach
out,
so
to
speak,
and
epistemically
14
touch
the
world.
Putnam
came
to
believe
that
there
was
a
similar
problem
in
explaining
our
‘referential
access
to
“sufficiently
good
epistemic
conditions”’
(Putnam
1994:
462).
The
growing
concern
with
this
question
led
to
the
emergence
of
a
third
phase
in
Putnam’s
philosophical
journey.
The
Later
Putnam
The
emergence
of
Putnam
3 can
be
dated
to
his
1990
Gifford
lectures
in
St.
Andrews
University.
The
still
ongoing
change
of
position,
however,
particularly
in
c omparison
w ith
the
more
radical
break
between
Putnam
1
and
2,
has
been
more
nuanced
and
gradual.
Putnam
3
defends
what
he
variously
calls
‘common
sense’,
‘natural’,
or
‘ pragmatic
realism’
and
rejects
both
his
early
metaphysical
realism
and
the
later
epistemic
view
of
truth.
While
internal
realism,
at
least
in
its
inception,
had
a
Kantian
flavor;
Putnam’s
work
in
the
1990’s
was
influenced
by
Wittgenstein
and
by
Pragmatism.
The most crucial feature of this latest
philosophical project is ‘a recovery of the natural realism of the common man’
(Putnam 1999: 24).
In earlier work, Putnam had treated sensations as the interface between the human
mind and the external world. By early 1990s, however, he came to find this option
unworkable - a realization that set the scene for the gradual emergence of his third
reply to the big question of realism. Natural
realism
emphasizes
the
role
of
our
direct
unencumbered,
contact
with
the
world,
unhampered
by
sense
data
or
any
other
intermediaries.
We
can
be
natural
realists
because
we
perceive
the
world
itself,
and
not
the
sense
data
caused
by
that
world.
Natural
realism,
Putnam
claims,
reflects
our
common
sense
‘that
“external”
things,
cabbages
and
kings,
can
be
experienced.’
(Putnam
1999:
20).
One
important
feature
of
his
thinking
in
this
phase,
and
a
carry
over
from
Putnam
2,
concerns
the
role
and
status
of
values
in
a
world
of
facts.
Putnam
first
questioned
the
intelligibility
of
the
in
a
sharp
division
between
factual
statements
and
normative
judgments,
so
popular
among
the
logical
positivists,
in
1986.
Some
of
his
more
recent
publications
(Putnam
2002,
2004,
2011)
deal
in
15
greater
detail
with
the
same
theme.
Putnam’s
aim
is
to
dispel
the
wide-‐spread
beliefs
that
while
science
deals
with
objective
facts
moral
values
are
purely
subjective.
Since
Hume
the
fact/value
division
has
been
a
cornerstone
of
naturalist
or
scientific
world-‐view.
Putnam
argues
that
this
orthodoxy
is
the
wrong
starting
point
for
understanding
both
science
and
ethics.
It
is
often
claimed
that
scientific
statements
have
a
representational
content,
they
represent
states
of
affairs,
while
value
judgments
express
our
attitudes
and
emotions
and
give
prescriptions
and
commands.
For
this
reason,
factual
judgments
are
objectively
true
or
false
while
ethical
positions
are
projections
and
expressions
of
our
subjective
preferences.
Putnam’s
key
argument
against
this
popular
position
is
that
the
distinction
is
unsustainable
because
factual
statements,
as
well
as
the
practices
of
science
which
enables
us
to
decide
what
counts
as
a
fact,
are
always
value
laden,
in
the
sense
that
they
presuppose
some
epistemic
values
(Putnam
1981:
128).
In
other
words,
the
very
act
of
theorizing
about
the
factual
world
is
a
value-‐laden
activity.
Here,
once
again,
we
see
Putnam’s
desire
“to
break
the
grip
that
a
certain
picture
has
on
our
thinking;
the
picture
of
a
dualism,
a
dichotomous
division
of
our
thought”
(Putnam
1990:
71).
Conclusion
Philosophy
for
Hilary
Putnam
is
an
ongoing
project
involving
a
critical
but
generous
engagement
with
numerous
philosophical
ideas
and
perspectives,
including
those
of
his
older
self.
It
is
a
never-‐ending
attempt
at
renewing
the
subject
matter
and
acknowledging
our
fallibility
in
the
face
of
the
formidable
task
of
addressing
some
of
the
most
fundamental
questions
facing
us.
The
best
summary
of
Putnam’s
approach
to
philosophy
is
by
Paul
Franks,
one
of
his
many
students
to
have
become
prominent
philosophers
in
their
own
right.
Franks
says:
“Putnam
is
not
best
understood
in
terms
of
his
“position”
or
“positions”
but
in
terms
of
the
dialectical
tensions
and
complexity
that
expresses
themselves
through
his
positions”
(quoted
in
Putnam
2012:2).
This
article
has
been
a
summary
of
both
his
various
influential
positions
and
the
dialectical
relations
between
them.
16
Selected Works
1951
(1990).
The
Meaning
of
the
Concept
of
Probability
in
Application
to
Finite
Sequences.
Ph.D.
dissertation,
University
of
California,
Los
Angeles,
1951.
New
York:
Garland,
1990.
1972.
Philosophy
of
Logic.
New
York:
Harper
and
Row,
1971.
London:
George
Allen
and
Unwin.
1975a.
Mathematics,
Matter
and
Method,
Cambridge:
Harvard
University
Press
1975.
Mind,
Language
and
Reality,
Cambridge:
Harvard
University
Press
1977.
‘Realism
and
Reason’,
Proceedings
and
Addresses
of
the
American
Philosophical
Association,
Vol.
50,
No.
6,
pp.
483-‐498.
1978.
Meaning
and
the
Moral
Sciences.
Boston:
Routledge
&
Kegan
Paul.
1981.
Reason,
Truth,
and
History.
Cambridge
University
Press
1983.
Realism
and
Reason.
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press.
1987.
Representation
and
Reality.
Cambridge,
MA:
MIT
Press.
1990.
Realism
with
a
Human
Face.
Cambridge:
Harvard
University
Press
1992.
Renewing
Philosophy.
Cambridge,
Mass.:
Harvard
University
Press.
1992.
Pragmatism.
An
Open
Question.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
1994.
Words
and
Life.
Cambridge:
Harvard
University
Press
1999.
The
Threefold
Cord.
New
York:
Columbia
University
Press
2002.
The
Collapse
of
the
Fact/Value
Dichotomy
and
Other
Essays.
Cambridge,
Mass.:
Harvard
University
Press.
2004.
Ethics
Without
Ontology.
Cambridge,
Mass.:
Harvard
University
Press.
2012.
Philosophy
in
an
Age
of
Science:
Physics,
Mathematics
and
Skepticism,
edited
by
Mario
De
Caro
and
David
Macarthur,
Cambridge,
Mass.:
Harvard
University
Press
M.
Davis,
H.
Putnam,
J.
Robinson,
(1961).
"The
decision
problem
for
exponential
Diophantine
equations",
Annals
of
Mathematics
74:3,
425–436.
Putnam.
H.
and
Benacerraf,
P.
1964.
(eds.)
Philosophy
of
Mathematics:
Selected
Readings.
Englewood
Cliffs,
N.J.:
Prentice-‐Hall.
2nd
ed.,
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press,
1983.
17
Putnam,
H.
and
Walsh,
V.
(Eds.),
The
End
of
Value-‐Free
Economics,
Londong,
New-‐York:
Routledge
Baghramian,
M
(2015).
Hilary
Putnam:
Mind,
Language
and
the
World,
London:
Polity
Press
Baghramian,
M.
(ed.)
(2012).
Reading
Putnam.
London/New
York:
Routledge.
Yemima
Ben-‐Menahem
(2005).
Hilary
Putnam.
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Maximilian
De
Gaynesford
(2004).
Hilary
Putnam.
Chesham,
UK:
Acumen
Publishing.
Christopher
Norris
(2002).
Hilary
Putnam:
Realism,
Reason
and
the
Uses
of
Uncertainty.
Manchester:
Manchester
University
Press.
Urszula
M.
Zeglen
&
James
Conant
(eds.)
(2002).
Hilary
Putnam:
Pragmatism
and
Realism.
London
&
New
York:
Routledge.
Andrew
Pessin
&
Sanford
Goldberg
(1996).
The
Twin
Earth
Chronicles:
Twenty
Years
of
Reflection
on
Hilary
Putnam's
"The
Meaning
of
'Meaning'".
New
York:
M.E.
Sharpe.
Peter
Clark
&
Bob
Hale
(eds.)
(1994).
Reading
Putnam.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Goerge
Boolos
(ed.)
(1990).
Meaning
and
Method:
Essays
in
Honour
of
Hilary
Putnam.
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Other
works
cited
Kripke,
Saul,
(1980).
Naming
and
Necessity.
Cambridge,
Mass:
Harvard
University
Press
Quine,
W.V.
(1951).
“Two
Dogmas
of
Empiricism”.
The
Philosophical
Review
60,
20-‐43.
Quine,
W.V.
(1960),
Word
and
Object.
Cambridge:
M.I.T.
Press.
18