CW XIV. First Philosophy PDF
CW XIV. First Philosophy PDF
CW XIV. First Philosophy PDF
FIRST PHILOSOPHY
LECTURES 1923/24
TRANSLATED BY
VOLUME XIV
FIRST PHILOSOPHY
LECTURES 1923/24
AND RELATED TEXTS FROM THE MANUSCRIPTS (1920-1925)
TRANSLATIONS
PREPARED UNDER THE AUSPICES OF
THE HUSSERL-ARCHIVES (LEUVEN)
FIRST PHILOSOPHY
Lectures 1923/24
and Related Texts from the Manuscripts (1920-1925)
TRANSLATED BY
SEBASTIAN LUFT
THANE M. NABERHAUS
Edmund Husserl (deceased)
Translated by
Sebastian Luft Thane M. Naberhaus
Department of Philosophy Department of Philosophy
Marquette University Mount St. Mary’s University
Milwaukee, WI, USA Emmitsburg, MD, USA
This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature B.V.
The registered company address is: Van Godewijckstraat 30, 3311 GX Dordrecht, The
Netherlands
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Edmund Husserl
First Philosophy
Lectures 1923/24
and Related Texts from the Manuscripts (1920–1925)
by Sebastian Luft
1 On the criteria for selecting these research texts, cf. below, pp. lxxix f.
2 According to Schuhmann’s chronicle, the following persons were in attendance at
the time: Helmuth Bohner, Reinhold Saleski, Fritz Taeger, Ludwig Landgrebe, Marvin
Farber, Günther Stern, and Ernst Zermelo (cf. Schuhmann 1977, p. 273). There is also
some evidence that Rudolf Carnap attended this lecture course (cf. Mayer 2016).
3 Boehm writes that among the people who were privy to this text, besides the students
in attendance, belong “friends and students” at the time (Boehm 1954, p. xv), though he
does not mention any names. From his own admission, Husserl’s Baltic student Theodor
Celms had access to this text when he composed his 1928 Der phänomenologische
Idealismus Husserls, cf. Celms 1928/1993.
xiv introduction to the translation
Fink were assigned, was ordered by Husserl only for texts deemed of
great importance and ultimately for publication, although, as in the
case of the present text, most of these typescripts—with the excep-
tion of Cartesian Meditations, which was only published in French
translation—never saw the light of day during Husserl’s lifetime.4
As the simplicity of the title “First Philosophy” indicates, Husserl
understood first philosophy to denote nothing other than his phe-
nomenology. He understood the latter to be first philosophy, which
is called upon to serve as a first philosophy in the sense of Aristotle
and Descartes (who are invoked at the very beginning), that is, in its
function of grounding all other sciences and ultimately also establish-
ing philosophy as metaphysics, addressing (and ultimately answering)
the “highest and ultimate questions.” Although Husserl’s ambitions as
of the Logical Investigations, where he sketches the Leibnizian idea
of a mathesis universalis or a pure logic, were immense, they were
arguably never as great as during the present period (the early 1920s),
and here, in the present lecture course.5 Whatever one makes of such
grand systematic attempts, especially in light of Husserl’s own com-
mitment to the “small change” of microscopic analysis versus the “big
bills” of system-building, one has to acknowledge that Husserl himself
attempted to compose such a system or at least a systematic intro-
duction and an overview over his philosophy and considered this task
as being of utmost importance. The topics treated in this text were
the opening moves of this systematic presentation as well as crucial
elements of the systematic scope of his phenomenology.
For many reasons, however, Husserl was dissatisfied with the result.
This is especially due to his own insuppressible tendency to digress,
to delve deeper into the problems and revise his earlier presentation,
leading him time and again to veer off topic, and ultimately to be his
4 Among these typescripts belong the lectures on the phenomenology of inner time-
consciousness, Ideas II and III, the Logische Studien (after Husserl’s death published by
Landgrebe as Experience and Judgment), and the Sixth Cartesian Meditation, a text of
Fink’s but commissioned and heavily annotated by Husserl.
5 The term “lecture course” is here used as a translation of the German Vorlesung, so
as to not confuse this text with a single lecture (or talk), but ensure that we are dealing
here, rather, with a one-semester lecture series (the German winter semesters, then and
now, run from around mid-October until mid-February, with a rather short Christmas
break).
introduction to the translation xv
own strongest critic. In many respects (to be discussed below), this text
presents a “shipwreck” (Landgrebe),6 but is, perhaps for this reason
more than any other, one of the most interesting texts Husserl pro-
duced.7 That Husserl ultimately withheld the text from publication
due to the obvious problems in composition and trajectory is, thus,
justified in hindsight from his own standpoint; that one of the first
editors would overrule the master’s verdict is telling, however. Indeed,
Boehm himself judges the text (especially with respect to part II of the
lecture course) and its composition to be “thoroughly problematic”
(Boehm 1958, p. xi8). Such a verdict does not mean, however, that it
may not be treated as what it is: one of the more problematic and cer-
tainly controversial texts Husserl has written. Even those who may not
be especially fond of this systematic aspect of Husserl’s work cannot
afford to disregard this text (and its important appendices).
That the text has not been translated into English has been, up
to now, a great lacuna in scholarship, especially given that the text,
or parts of it, have been translated into French, Italian, and Spanish
(and translations into other major languages are currently underway9).
This translation intends to finally fill this gap. Given the importance of
this text in Husserl’s oeuvre, it is bound to lead to a reassessment of
one of Husserl’s most controversial claims, that his phenomenology,
in the mature form of a transcendental idealism, should come forth
as a first philosophy. Especially in light of the newer interest in a phe-
nomenological metaphysics10 and the recent publication of Husserl’s
6 The reasons Landgrebe lists for this verdict (inspired by Heidegger) are thereby not
endorsed; I will discuss critically Landgrebe’s famous thesis (“departure from Carte-
sianism”) in section IV, below.
7 It should be mentioned that many of Husserl’s philosophically important readers
(beginning perhaps with one of his strongest critics, Heidegger) were never overly
impressed by his systematic ambitions and were more smitten with his small-scale
analyses and descriptions.
8 In the same context Boehm asserts that, based on an oral communication from
Roman Ingarden, Husserl showed this second part to nobody (Boehm 1958, p. xi, n. 1).
Based on Celms’ assertion (cf. above, n. 3), this is manifestly incorrect.
9 The text has been translated (in part or in full) into French (Arion Kelkel), Italian
(there are two translations, by Vincenzo Costa and Paolo Bucci, of part II only), and
Spanish (Rosa Helena Santos de Ilhau). Translation projects into Japanese (Tetsuya
Sakakibara) and Korean (Ki-Bok Kim) are underway.
10 Cf. Tengelyi 2013.
xvi introduction to the translation
11 These topics are treated in many of the research manuscripts, including some of this
volume, but the texts Husserl dedicated to this topic in the order of his literary estate
have only recently been published (in Husserliana XLI, 2014).
introduction to the translation xvii
the lecture was delivered Monday, Tuesday, Thursday, Friday from 5–6pm, the full hour
traditionally meaning “c.t.” = cum tempore, thus beginning at 5:15, ending on the full
hour. The lecture course was announced “publ[ice],” that is, open for anyone and thus
not only for students (“privatim”). The only other public lecture course in that semester
was that of the Neo-Kantian Richard Kroner, “History of Newer Philosophy,” which
makes it likely that Husserl’s lecture had a very good turnout (compared to Husserl,
Kroner was fairly unknown). In that semester, Husserl also taught a seminar on “Phe-
nomenological Exercises for Advanced Students,”Wednesdays from 11–1. Other courses
in phenomenology in that term were taught by Oskar Becker. Other notable figures
teaching that semester in Freiburg were the Neo-Kantian Jonas Cohn and the Kant
scholar Julius Ebbinghaus.
13 Husserl delivered 54 lectures, which would make it a typical 13–14 week semester,
his lecture courses throughout his career, Husserl faithfully read off
the manuscript, according to his own pronouncements, almost never
veering off the text to speak extemporaneously. One can assume the
same practice in this lecture course. In the case of this lecture, Husserl
gave the manuscript afterwards to his assistant Ludwig Landgrebe on
a weekly basis. The latter typed the lecture, giving each a title (perhaps
in consultation with Husserl) and also attempting to give the text of
the lecture course as a whole a structure consisting of two main parts
with several sub-sections.14 Husserl, in turn, read and annotated Land-
grebe’s typescript and wrote a plethora of marginalia and additional
research manuscripts, often much more extensive than the lectures
themselves. A selection of these are reproduced in footnotes (in the
case of marginalia) and, if longer, in the texts printed in the appendix.15
14 Landgrebe writes in a later text, reflecting back on his time with Husserl: “My first
task [as assistant] was the transcription [Nachschrift] and the editing [Ausarbeitung] of
his lecture course on ‘First Philosophy’ in the winter semester of 1923/24. After every
lecture, Husserl handed me his stenographic manuscript pages, which he for the most
part had penned immediately before.” (quoted in Schuhmann 1977, p. 273). Boehm
claims (Boehm 1954, pp. xiiif.) that Landgrebe gave each lecture a title, ordered the
text as a whole into subsections, and later wrote a synopsis (Inhaltsübersicht). However,
it also appears that Husserl himself at least conceived the titles of the two main parts
(critical history of ideas; theory of the phenomenological reduction), as his manuscripts
referring to these parts indicate (see below, the supplemental texts). It is not unimportant
to point out that there is a slight discrepancy between the facts that Husserl’s assistants
often ordered the lecture courses systematically (a practice that is followed in the lecture
course editions of the Husserliana) and that Husserl himself wrote each lecture as a
discrete text each time. He might have had a systematic order or structure in mind (prior
to the semester, but which he often overthrew), but for the sake of reconstructing the
composition of the entire text, he composed each lecture anew, oftentimes beginning by
summarizing the main points of the previous lectures, but then pursuing the theme he
was interested thenceforth. This practice, it should be noted, makes it quite difficult for
an editor to furnish a systematic treatise from the manuscript base. In other words, the
systematic structure that many editions of Husserl’s lectures display has (for the most
part) been produced by the editor and makes an impression that is more systematic
than the at times ad hoc choices of themes or digressions in fact manifest.
15 Boehm’s appendices also contain lectures Husserl gave and drafts of texts Husserl
intended to publish, for instance the Kant lecture on Kant’s 200th anniversary (1924).
Some of the latter have already been translated (e.g., the Kant lecture). Boehm also
distinguishes between “Abhandlungen” (treatises) and “Beilagen” (supplements, often-
times, though not always, with references to the lecture course).This distinction, however,
is in many respects artificial and has not been reproduced here. Hence all texts in the
appendix to this volume are here simply named “supplemental texts.” It cannot always
introduction to the translation xix
be said with certainty if Husserl wrote them as comments to the lecture course (although
many times he refers to certain passages) or as “regular” research manuscripts.
16 Among these are the articles Husserl published in the Japanese journal The Kaizo,
18 See the introduction by the editor of Hua. XXXV, Goossens, on a detailed recon-
struction of these historical events.The book Cartesian Meditations, which was published
only in French translation during Husserl’s lifetime, contains five meditations, the fifth
(the famous meditation on intersubjectivity) was added later, i.e., it was based on an
impromptu lecture in Strasbourg. It does not, in other words, belong to the original
composition of the four lectures (as in London and Paris).
19 As he writes in 1919: “The greatest hopes rest on the pure and rigorous formation
of these new disciplines [of philosophy], as you shall see; hopes which humankind can
hope to place on the further progress of scientific culture.” (Hua-Mat IX, p. 6). It is thus
humankind as a whole that can have hope, not just scientists, and not just for science for
the sake of science, but “scientific culture,” that is, culture (encompassing science) that
will be elevated to a higher plane.
introduction to the translation xxi
of the several crises facing humankind at this time (the others were
presumably omitted due to the censorship he experienced). Although
the Nazi takeover of 1933 might not have been on the horizon a decade
earlier, the time only a few years after the Great War and in the mid-
dle of the financial depression was nonetheless ripe with economic
and political crises. Husserl felt his vocation as a philosopher clearly
challenged, and although the present text is more narrowly focused
on the problem of conceiving a first philosophy, these efforts have to
be seen in the broader context just sketched, since, as we shall see,
culture as a whole depends on foundations laid by the true philosophy,
phenomenology.
As mentioned, Husserl intended to use these lectures as the basis
for his systematic presentation to be published in the form of a (per-
haps multi-volume) book.20 It is important to mention, in this context,
that in so doing he was taking up once again a plan that he had begun
a year earlier, in the lecture course of the winter of 1922/23, Einleitung
in die Philosophie (Introduction to Philosophy, Husserliana XXXV),
which, in turn, goes back to the “London Lectures” of the spring of
1922.21 This earlier lecture course also had the purpose of introducing
phenomenology through a meditation on the very idea of philosophy.
Only when this idea has been laid out could it be made plain that
phenomenology, and only it, would fit the bill for this idea. The lecture
course of 1922/23 is in many respects thematically quite different from
that of 1923/24.22 Yet both lecture courses must be seen in connection
20 See the plans for the systematic (multi-volume) work Husserl sketched together
with his assistant Fink in Hua. XV, p. xxxvi. Yet one must distinguish the plan of writing a
system of phenomenology, giving an overview over the many themes of phenomenology,
from that of a systematic introduction to phenomenology, which would prove to be the
proper, rigorous-scientific form of philosophy.
21 The London Lectures are published, in the form in which they were delivered in
London, in Husserl Studies (Husserl 1999) and also in the appendix to Hua. XXXV,
however here only the texts that were omitted later in the lecture course were printed.
That is, some parts of the London Lectures were integrated verbatim into the lecture
course. Cf. also the editor’s elucidations of these historical details (Goossens 1999 and
2002).
22 One thing Husserl does in the earlier course is to carry out the “apodictic critique”
of phenomenology, or what also calls a “critique of the critique” (cf. Goossens 2002).
Husserl mentions this task in First Philosophy in passing only and does not return to it,
although it is also mentioned as a task to be carried out in Cartesian Meditations (Hua.
xxii introduction to the translation
I, p. 177). Given its crucial role for the sake of the fully critiqued phenomenological
method, it is curious that Husserl never returns to it.
23 These overlaps are detailed in (Goossens 2002).
24 For a list of Husserl’s historical lectures and seminars, cf. Hua. VII, pp. xxviif. Cf.
Philosophy), which Husserl delivered several times between 1916 and 1920 (published in
Hua-Mat IX), does include an historical précis of ca. 200 pages ranging from Descartes
to Kant (ibid., pp. 288–477) and some musings on the “beginning Greek philosophy
or science” (ibid., pp. 7–27), yet the “critical history of ideas” in the first half of the
1923/24 lecture course is a completely new composition with a much clearer “teleologi-
cal” structure, which culminates in phenomenology as the “destiny” of all of Western
philosophy.
introduction to the translation xxiii
26 Another possibility, hinted at by Landgrebe (though without any proof, cf. Landgrebe
1962, pp. 259 f.), is that Husserl simply gave up on the plan of producing a publishable
text: “It is the path [explicitly in part II] of an experimenting adventurer in thought
whose successes are constantly thrown into question in the reflections which accompany
the lectures and whose goal is not fixed from the start so that it actually leads elsewhere
than initially foreseen” (ibid., p. 259).
27 These discussions are indeed executed in much greater detail in the supplementary
ways into the reduction” (the Cartesian, the psychological, and the
ontological one), Husserl here introduces this second path for the
first time publicly.28 At the same time he acknowledges to his listeners
the limits and shortcomings of the earlier Cartesian path, which he
utilized in Ideas I, and which led to the famous reproaches of Husserl
being a Cartesian, an idealist, or a solipsist. Such a public self-critique
is rather rare in Husserl’s oeuvre. Although Husserl is quite content
with the opening up of this new path, the presentation is far from
complete and comprehensive, due to the semester rushing to a close,
and the lecture ends once again with some rather hasty remarks on
phenomenology as transcendental idealism and a “new” monadology.
Thus, while he accomplished quite a bit systematically, the presen-
tation of the material, as it stands at the end of the semester, is far
from satisfactory. Indeed, it is presumably for this reason that Husserl
shortly afterwards abandoned the plan to use this text as the basis for
his systematic introduction. As important as this systematic result is,
one has to conclude that the manner of arriving at it is long-winded,
full of ruptures and digressions. Nonetheless, the central importance
of this text in Husserl’s oeuvre is undisputed.
Husserl continues to plan and plot out a comprehensive system-
atic work (or systematic introduction), though by his own lights he
never succeeds.29 Formal and Transcendental Logic of 1929 can serve
as an introduction to his genetic logic, and Cartesian Meditations of
1930 was deemed acceptable “only” to his French readers. After 1933
Husserl had essentially abandoned all plans. His last work, the Crisis of
European Sciences, is a last and frantic attempt at such a presentation,
which he undertakes in a last effort to give at least an introduction to
28 Kern’s “three ways” essay has become canonical in its systematic presentation (cf.
Kern 1962). However, this presentation overlooks the fact that to Husserl the question
of the paths into the reduction was problematic at all times in his life after 1905. Not
only are there also other ways into phenomenology (via the critique of the sciences, via
intersubjectivity, etc.), it is also the case that traces of the way via intentional psychology
can be found prior to 1924.The case that some interpreters have made of the importance
of this lecture course for the problem of the ways of the reduction is in some respects
overblown.
29 An overview over these systematic plans is given in Kern’s (editor’s) introduction
to Hua. XV, p. xxxvi. Cf. also the editor’s introduction to Hua. XXXIV, which adds some
newly found material.
introduction to the translation xxv
his phenomenology. This last work is remembered, rightly so, for the
existential urgency with which Husserl introduces phenomenology as
a solution to the crisis of his day. However, especially in its historical
part, the Crisis in many ways falls short of the much more detailed
presentation in First Philosophy.
Scholars later have tried to make sense of the systematic place of
First Philosophy in the context of Husserl’s work in general, since
the phrase “first philosophy” is not used by Husserl prior to 192330
and also recedes into the background after 1924. It was no lesser than
Husserl’s own pupil Heidegger, who claimed (in the 1929 dispute in
Davos with Cassirer), that “for a period, Husserl had fallen into the
arms of the Neo-Kantians,”31 which presumably meant the temptation
to conceive of phenomenology as a “first philosophy” in the sense of
an ultimate foundationalism.32 This claim also implies that at a later
time Husserl would have wrested himself from this embrace and that
it was only a temporary phase. Later scholars have also argued along
Heidegger’s claim that this task, and hence this text, presents a curios-
ity within Husserl’s writings (see section IV, below). While it will be
shown below that this claim is in many respects unfounded, it is true
that in this text Husserl is perhaps more radical in his systematic ambi-
tions than elsewhere. Husserl is dead serious when he characterizes
phenomenology as the “secret desire of all of philosophy.” What he
means by this claim can perhaps be best understood by studying the
present text.
Let me, in the following, address some of the central points tied to
his claim that phenomenology should come forth as “first philosophy.”
30 Interestingly, Natorp uses the phrase proté philosophía in his 1901 review of Husserl’s
Prolegomena (quoted in Boehm 1954, p. xix), not to identify Husserl’s draft of a pure
logic, but rather to argue that Husserl’s achievement may not yet have accomplished
this (though it should). It is not far-fetched to see Natorp as a very strong influence
in Husserl’s later attempt at such a first philosophy, as Natorp influenced Husserl in
other aspects of his thought, especially in the 1920s (cf. Luft 2010, for more on Natorp’s
influence on Husserl).
31 Heidegger 1973, p. 247.
32 It is a different issue whether this captures the intentions of either school of Neo-
Kantianism well. If it is to mean that philosophy should provide a firm foundations for
all scientific efforts and be a permanent bulwark against skepticism, neither of the major
schools of Neo-Kantianism would lay claims to such ambitions.
xxvi introduction to the translation
Understanding these can help the reader understand the main inten-
tions driving Husserl. But before that, I will start out with a simple
definition of what phenomenology is; this will provide the basis for my
discussion of Husserl’s attempt to bring phenomenology forth as first
philosophy.
world is experienced in all forms, and the way the subject has this
experience. It is thus an investigation from the standpoint of the expe-
riencing agent in her having experience in the broadest sense.
As discussed so far, phenomenology is mainly a descriptive exercise
or a descriptive science. As describing the structure of intentionality
in its different forms, it also aims to arrive at general insights that
go beyond one’s merely personal whimsy. Of course the investigator
has to start from her (first person) experience, but what she describes
are structures that hold for consciousness (or intentionality) as such,
regardless of the fact that the person doing the describing is located in
France or Finland or on the moon, regardless that she has two eyes, and
that she studies the perception of a tree, a tiger in the forest, an object
on the moon, or an imagined monster or a remembered loved one.
The descriptor, hence, has to abstract from her own perspective and
describe structures that hold as such. Every science has to move from
individuals to generalities. Phenomenology is in this sense a science
like every other science, aiming at general insights about, or essences
concerning individuals.
Consider a basic example that Husserl was fond of: in the case of
perceiving, the object that I see shows itself to me from a side facing
me and a hidden (but co-meant) backside. The general structure of
perception (mine, and everybody else’s who has the ability to perceive)
as a form of intentionality (regardless of who has it) is thus that its
objects necessarily show themselves in profiles and that the perceiving
agent cannot see all profiles at once. Phenomenology as a descriptive
science abstracts from the fact (of, for example, the person’s histori-
cal and geographical setting and her physical make-up) and aims at
general structures. While there are levels of generality in empirical
generalizations, phenomenology is philosophy and is thus aimed at
insights that are a priori (independent of experience) and essential
(necessarily true). In order to reach essential truths, the phenomenol-
ogist has to aim at insights that are true as such and not only valid for
a certain group of exemplars (e.g., the human being). Though starting
from her own experience, she aims at truths that are true independent
of any existing experience, but true of any possible experience. It is, in
this sense, an a priori science of consciousness in the same way that
arithmetic is an a priori science of numbers. Thus far, I have clarified
what “eidetic science of subjectivity” means.
xxviii introduction to the translation
Although it seems easy at first glance (in the sense just given) to give
a definition of what Husserl means by “First Philosophy,” it becomes a
challenge to further explain this concept when he claims, a fortiori, that
specifically phenomenology should come forth as a discipline that is
more than just a descriptive, but also foundational discipline.34 Rather,
33 Cf. also Schuhmann (2004) for an in-depth account of Husserl’s idea of philosophy.
34 On Husserl’s alleged foundationalism and exactly which kind of foundationalist
he is, cf. the helpful discussion by Berghofer (2018), who also gives a survey of this
discussion both in contemporary philosophy of mind as well as in the scholarship on
Husserl beginning with Føllesdal and up to more recent works by Drummond, Beyer,
and Zahavi. It should be pointed out, however, that Berghofer, too, repeats the old error
that Husserl does not distinguish between adequate and apodictic evidence until the
Cartesian Meditations (cf. Berghofer 2018, p. 12). As is clear from the present discussion,
this distinction was one of the main issues dealt with as of 1922 and it was a defining
moment for the characterization of his phenomenology as First Philosophy.
introduction to the translation xxxi
35 Schuhmann (2004, p. 62) also takes this position and argues for a “compiling method”
for assembling what he calls (with Fink) an “‘operative concept’ of Husserlian phe-
nomenology” (ibid.).
36 This is notably not the case for Husserl, for whom metaphysics is “second philoso-
sciences. The first principle upon which to base all other mediately
certain axioms is the certainty of the “I think, I am,” which remains
even after the most radically possible doubt, doubting that God exists
and that he is, instead, assumedly a genial but evil deceiver manipulat-
ing our every sensation and thought (cf. Descartes 1904, pp. 17–23).
With this meditation, historically, the idea of a first philosophy is firstly
linked to the thinking substance, the ego cogito or the subject. This is
why Kant and Husserl could justifiably call Descartes’ Meditations the
(dimly anticipated) origin of transcendental philosophy.
Despite Husserl being closer to Descartes, nonetheless both ele-
ments, that of a foundational discipline dealing with first principles
and the necessity of the turn to the ego cogito in order to accomplish
the former, are present in Husserl in various ways, and he acknowl-
edges his predecessors. At the very beginning of the lecture course,
Husserl explicitly begins with an invocation of Aristotle’s notion of
“First Philosophy,” which he also immediately connects with the term
“metaphysics” (below, p. 3), though he makes it clear that he is not
interested in the historically correct account but rather in the “formal
preliminary indication of the theoretical intention” (ibid.) guiding its
inceptor. Also, Descartes’s Meditations are mentioned in the same
passage as “represent[ing] a completely new beginning in the history
of philosophy in their attempt to discover, with a radicalism unheard of
up to then, the absolutely necessary beginning of philosophy” (below,
p. 8).
Thus, it must be said that First Philosophy has first and foremost
for Husserl the role of a foundational discipline. Moreover, since
Kant’s critique of reason, it takes the shape of a transcendental cri-
tique of knowledge or cognition (epistemology). His closest allies here,
despite all differences, are thus clearly Descartes and—though he is not
mentioned here—Kant, especially via the mediation through his Neo-
Kantian contemporaries. Natorp has already been mentioned above.
Boehm mentions another person who may have also been influential,
the Neo-Kantian Eduard von Hartmann (1842–1906), who, he claims,
was “presumably the first to call ‘epistemology’ ‘first philosophy’”
(Boehm 1954, p. xviii). Von Hartmann writes in his Philosophy of the
Unconscious of 1878, “Epistemology is the true philosophia prima”
(quoted in Boehm, ibid., n. 2). Husserl had this book in his possession;
since, however, the copy in his personal library bears no annotations, it
introduction to the translation xxxiii
38 Husserl knew of von Hartmann’s notion of the unconscious.There are five books and
all scientists, that is, all those who have dedicated, or intend to dedi-
cate, their lives to the search for Truth, which is the path towards bliss
(“Seligkeit”). Universal science, as a general science, encompassing
every individual science as specific formation thereof, is dedicated to
the pursuit of truth for the sake of truth, of “theoria and nothing but
theoria” (Hua. VI, p. 326).39 This is the way Husserl makes his opening
moves in the present lecture course.40
It is historically interesting that the two main inspirations Husserl
credits here are not Aristotle and Descartes, but rather the latter and
“the incomparable twin-star Socrates-Plato” (below, p. 8). What links
Descartes and Socrates-Plato together, in Husserl’s estimation, is that
their philosophizing (as search for “pure truth”) is inspired first and
foremost by the specter of skepticism, that is, by the doubt in firm
truths and fixed principles, principles which enable knowledge to come
forth on the secure path of science. Yet principles are necessary not
only in science and knowledge, but indeed in all practical life as well.41
If one recalls Husserl’s personal motivations for becoming a philoso-
pher, which he recounts at times somewhat ceremoniously,42 he too
saw skepticism in theory as well as in praxis—but more importantly
in the latter—as the greatest threat to the flourishing of humankind.
Indeed, the paradoxes raised by skepticism are not first and foremost
problems arising in the philosophical armchair, but make themselves
39 This notion of “truth for the sake of truth” and “theory for theory’s sake” does not
mean, however, that philosophy should not have practical application. To the contrary,
all philosophy is ultimately aimed at practice in the sense of enabling the good life; cf.
Schuhmann 2004, pp. 64f., for an elucidation of the relation of theory and praxis.
40 A part of these texts, it should be noted, Husserl took from an essay he published in
the “Japanese-German Journal for Science and Technology” (vol. 1) in 1923, entitled
“The Idea of a Philosophical Culture” (Hua. VII, pp. 203–207). A translation of this
text will be published in the Husserliana-Collected Works volume containing the Kaizo
articles. Husserl also begins the lecture course of 1922/23 with similar reflections on the
nature of the ideal of science and the ideal scientist, cf. Hua. XXXV, pp. 43 ff.
41 Husserl ignores that this presumably was an important motivation for Aristotle
mann 1977, p. 344. There he says, according to a recollection from Roman Ingarden, “I
had to philosophize, otherwise I could not live in this world.”
introduction to the translation xxxv
felt most crucially in practical life. Indeed they are, in the latter shape,
“fateful problems for mankind on its way to genuine humanity” (below,
p. 9).43 What is needed to combat skepticism, in most general terms, is
“complete clarity” and “clarification” of all opinions, as to which are
true (to the extent they can be justified), and which are mere opinions.
This clarity can only be achieved—and here we get a first indication
of phenomenology’s role in this endeavor—by a return to “ ‘insight’,
or ‘evidence’” (ibid.). The “principle of principles” (“that each intu-
ition affording [something] in an originary way is a legitimate source of
knowledge”44) ought to be invoked and applied already in everyday
life.Thus, completely clear evidences are the foundations for any scien-
tific endeavor; they are the only thing upon which arguments or correct
inferences can be founded. Trying to arrive at complete clarity and
evidence is not already the working out of first philosophy, but it is this
burning necessity that marks the Cartesian drive to “once in a lifetime”
(semel in vita) start over and subject every commonly held opinion to
radical scrutiny and to come up with first principles supporting other
assertions. Everything must be subjected to the famous Socratic lógon
didónai, to giving oneself a radical account, ideally spanning one’s
entire life. This is the first impulse to gaining any clarity and, a fortiori,
lasting knowledge, enabling both the flourishing of theoretical and
practical life.
While continuous with the last point, the project of a first philosophy
takes on a more concrete shape in Husserl’s vision once this project,
which begins with Socrates as a practical one, becomes applied to the
theoretical project of science in the broadest sense in which it is synony-
43 It is here where Plato departs from Socrates, in Husserl’s estimation, for the latter
only engaged in thinking “only as a practical reformer” (below, p. 9). The relation to
Husserl’s ethical thought cannot be broached here, though clearly for Husserl, in most
general terms, philosophy should be in the service of the good life. These motives come
to the fore especially in his late ethical writings, cf. Hua. XXXVIII and LX, cf. also here
the editors’ (Peucker and Sowa) introductions to these volumes.
44 Hua. III/1, p. 51 (Dahlstrom trans.).
xxxvi introduction to the translation
mous with philosophy. This happens with Plato. As long as the quest
for clarity is still merely a practical matter (as in Socrates), it is not yet
radically reflected. Such a life is, in Husserl’s terminology, still naïve. It
becomes philosophical the moment it reflects on its ultimate grounds
and thereby loses all naiveté. It thus becomes fully justified in every
respect. This complete justification in every respect is an ideal, to be
sure; but only true philosophy, rising above the everyday, can posit this
ideal as a limit idea to which the individual scientist is to approximate
herself asymptotically. Only then can the scientist in her individuality
claim to be a true scientist, as following the ideal set up by the true
philosopher; just as, in the practical sphere, one can only claim for one-
self to be a truly good person once every guiding principle for action
has been justified.45 To do this in general, every dogmatic assumption
must be suspended. Thus, the phenomenological epoché, the withhold-
ing of assent to any truth claim, finds its equivalent in the “ethical
epoché” that every person must undertake, insofar as she wants to
realign her life to an absolutely justified principle.46 The ethical aspect is
foundational for the epistemological one.This does not mean, however,
that every person should become a scientist or philosopher; rather,
the scientist practices this “renewal” with more rigor than is possible
in the practical sphere and with a clearly defined methodological form
of reflection, which cannot be demanded by the prescientific person.
Thus, the ultimate motivation for any human being is, to Husserl,
to become a good and honest person (to oneself, to others), and the
same standard ought to be applied to the good scientist and philoso-
pher with respect to her ethos, which can only be the never-ending
search for insurmountable truth. Once this goal has been conceived
in its purity, which is eo ipso a philosophical achievement (since it
is not contingent or applied to anything in particular, it is the “goal
qua goal”), it must then be applied to the particular sciences. Every
single scientist should also adhere to this ideal of being able to jus-
salient especially in his ethics. The fully justified person is beholden to herself and her
own evidences exclusively. The contrast would be to the ideal laid out in virtue ethics,
where the norm comes from the virtuous other who is admired by the people.
46 Cf. Hua. XXVII, pp. 3–94 (the “Kaizo Articles”) for a presentation of this line of
thought.
introduction to the translation xxxvii
tify every actual and possible deed (in the field or the laboratory)
and judgment (in fixating findings). As enacting this idea of a first
science or first philosophy, they thereby are “second philosophies”
in referring themselves back to the very idea of the master science,
which posits the pursuit of truth as ideal. A first philosophy thus for-
mulates in ideal terms the very principles under which every individual
researcher must stand if the enterprise of science as the search for
truth can ever come off the ground and withstand the never-ending
attacks on the part of the arch enemy,“the hydra of skepticism” (below,
p. 59).
47 Cf. again Schuhmann 2004, pp. 65–68 for a succinct summary, also highlighting the
not Husserl’s prioritizing (after the reduction) consciousness over the world entails an
ontological commitment, or whether it is metaphysically neutral precisely due to the
reduction. For a discussion of this, cf. Zahavi 2002.
introduction to the translation xli
50 Husserl was aware of the distinction between the Kantian and Neo-Kantian projects,
especially in his subtle usage of the term “erkenntniskritisch,” cf. below, p. 35.
xlii introduction to the translation
51 For a classic presentation of the method of eidetic variation, cf. Para. 87 of Experience
and Judgment. It is also mentioned in passing in the manuscripts, cf., for instance, text
no. 9 of the supplemental texts below.
52 Cf. also below, p. 479 (the only other place in the present volume where he uses it in
his sense). In the lecture course itself, when Husserl uses the term “metaphysics,” he
uses it in the ordinary sense or in that of the philosopher in question.
As an aside, it would be interesting to investigate whether Heidegger’s project of
a metaphysics, which he pursues in his “metaphysical decade,” in the 1930s, could be
construed as an execution of this project, which is never worked out in detail by Husserl.
introduction to the translation xliii
53 This project is, once more, to be distinguished by what Husserl and his last assistant
This recalls the distinction between the two modes of evidence that
Husserl discerns in the early 1920s, adequate and apodictic evidence.
The importance of this distinction cannot be overstated. Phenomenol-
ogy in general studies the various types of evidence; yet not every
evidence is ultimately “trustworthy,” so to speak. Only laying bare what
can count as apodictic evidence (and distinguishing it from evidence
that is merely adequate) can fulfill the demand for an ultimate justi-
fication of evidences that cannot in principle be falsified. The demand
for an apodictic critique is thus not an invitation for high-flying spec-
ulation, but rather the reining in of the sphere of apodicticity within
the field of evident experience.55
The story of this apodictic critique deserves to be recounted briefly.
This critique is mentioned, as noted earlier, at the end of the Cartesian
Meditations and stated there as a desideratum. However, as also noted
earlier, Husserl did perform this critique in the 1922/23 lecture course
Introduction to Philosophy. Though left unpublished, Husserl himself
drew attention to it later; e.g., he mentions this text in a footnote in
Formal and Transcendental Logic (cf. Hua. XVII, p. 295). Yet, both the
transcriptor of these manuscripts of 1922/23, Husserl’s assistant Land-
grebe, and Kern, an editor of three Husserliana volumes, downplay or
even ignore it. For instance, Kern claims that Husserl has “postponed
[this critique] ad Calendas Graecas” (Kern 1964, p. 202), thus stating
a factual error. It is only with this self-critique that the project of a
complete ground-laying of phenomenology comes to its completion.56
Whether it really was completed in view of the rather puzzling fact that
Husserl carried out this critique in 1922/23 and referred to it in 1929
but never published it, will have to be the topic of further research.
One last comment on Husserl’s conception of phenomenology as
first philosophy. Using these terms in contemporary philosophy has
a rather adverse effect to many working in the areas of epistemology,
the philosophy of mind, and even phenomenology itself. Grandiose
notions of “first philosophy” grounding all other scientific endeavors
VI. Cartesian Meditation, which is, as Fink claims, a piece of “constructive” phenomenol-
ogy.
56 For a detailed explication of these historical circumstances, cf. Goossens 2002.
xlvi introduction to the translation
Husserl does not discuss his word choice for his historical med-
itations, titled “kritische Ideengeschichte.” Yet from his systematic
ambition it should be clear that an English rendering as something
like “intellectual history” (in the way practiced by, e.g., intellectual
historians such as Isaiah Berlin57) would be wholly inadequate. It is
completely blind to “non-philosophical” factors, such as the thinkers’
social reality, and is a completely philosophical affair. It is perhaps
helpful to assume that this phrasing is Husserl’s term for what the
Neo-Kantians called history of problems (Problemgeschichte), as a
historiography focused on the development of philosophical ideas and
problems. Yet there are some differences, as we shall see. In general,
57 Berlin writes: “Historians are concerned with the discovery, description and expla-
nation of the social aspects and consequences of what men have done and suffered.”
(Berlin 2013, p. 7) And later about his method: it is “a kind of transcendental deduction
(in the Kantian sense) of historical truth. It is a method of arriving not, as hitherto, at
an unchanging reality via its changing appearances, but as a changing reality—men’s
history—through its systematically changing modes of expression.” (ibid., p. 15).
xlviii introduction to the translation
58 In this sense, Husserl would agree with the scope of Cassirer’s history of problems
focused on the problem of cognition “in philosophy and the sciences in modernity.” Cf.
Cassirer 1994.
59 Cf. Husserl 2010.
60 Husserl leaves open whether other anthropological types exist, such as native African
or American ones. A charitable reading would concede that, though Husserl does not
mention them, his mere ignorance of them kept him from touching on them. Such
a reading would be corroborated by Husserl’s favorable reception of research into
so-called “primitives” by the French ethnologist Lucien Lévy-Brühl or of Cassirer’s
investigations into myth as a symbolic form.
introduction to the translation xlix
ferently, the newer research solves old problems, only to raise new
ones, which are then those with which the next generation is occupied
(and so on), in the Neo-Kantian parlance of “Gaben” (givens) being
“Aufgaben” (tasks) for further and never-ending research. As this type
of historiography sees it, each thinker in her way transcends her con-
tingencies and rises to the realm of pure ideas, where she partakes in an
atemporal conversation, spanning across the millennia. In this way, the
conversation continues, not in order to reach a highest goal, but in order
to keep culture alive. History of problems, in other words, is not at all
times teleological, at times it is regressive, disrupted, or changes course.
By contrast, the way Husserl sees the history of Western science
and philosophy is a seemingly endless struggle between the builders
and the destroyers; those, in other words, who build the edifice of
science, and those (the Skeptics in different guises), who continually
tear down what the former have achieved. The ones who tear down
reappear in different shapes, yet all stemming from the same “hydra
of skepticism.”61 It is not until phenomenology comes on the scene
that the beast is finally put to death and the path towards science,
approximating itself infinitely to this limit idea, is taken.As of then, the
teleology of science can begin, approaching Truth asymptotically. It is
not that phenomenology has discovered such a teleology; Husserl only
claims to have finally gotten the idea of an infinite progress started on
a secure footing.
It should also be noted that the history Husserl tells is not a seam-
less one from antiquity to modernity. The period of the Middle Ages
is entirely leaped over; Husserl seems to endorse a narrative that cel-
ebrates the birth of science and philosophy in ancient Greece, holds
that they were forgotten and obscured in the “dark” middle ages, and
were re-awakened in the Renaissance when the perennial discoveries
of the Ancients were reborn and instituted anew.
61 Such a view, it may be argued, of the skeptical challenge is rather naïve after Kant
and especially Hegel. Kant sought to find a middle path between skepticism and dog-
matism through his transcendental method. Hegel sought to integrate and disarm the
Skeptic through his dialectical method. In the Neo-Kantian history of ideas we also
find a Hegelian motive; rather than tearing down, the Skeptic is elegantly woven into
the story told by showing how they brought forth valid points, to which the successors
responded constructively. Husserl’s skeptic is purely destructive.
l introduction to the translation
Indeed, the rebirth of the ancient spirit struggles with the same
enemy, skepticism. The skeptical deterrents of modernity are not
wholly without merit, however, for along the way they do give impor-
tant impulses, which were distractions from the grand path of science
at the time, but, once purified to their real intentions, can be positively
taken up into the edifice of science. This is the way Husserl reads,
for instance, the British Empiricists, who conceive of the idea of a
“science of the psyche,” however inadequately, but whose truth will
be redeemed with phenomenology. The term Husserl also uses for
his enterprise, “transcendental empiricism,” shows that he sees phe-
nomenology as the grand synthesis of the main tendencies of modern
philosophy.
This text presents the most sustained treatment of some major fig-
ures in their historical sequence in Husserl’s oeuvre. This belies the
old saw that Husserl had no knowledge about the history of philoso-
phy. His interest is self-serving, as Husserl does not intend to present
these figures in their historical context and with a textual-philological
fidelity.62 So the reader should not look to this text to enlighten her
about Socrates, Plato or others. Husserl, instead, sees their impulses
charitably as leading to and culminating in phenomenology. Although
Husserl has been mocked for his historical naiveté and although it
cannot be denied that he read the classics in the Western canon rarely
in the original, nor even in primal sources, what Husserl says about the
philosopher in question is always interesting and insightful, especially
in his criticism. Husserl’s discussions of Locke, Berkeley, Hume are
quite engaging and keen, especially as he then goes on to highlight their
shortcomings and point to how phenomenology overcomes them. For
instance, he demonstrates how empiricism harbors hidden prejudices,
such as objectivism and psychologism, and how the natural-scientific
62 It should be noted that philological or historical fidelity is rarely the interest of orig-
inal philosophers dealing with thinkers of the past. Consider, e.g., Hegel or Heidegger.
introduction to the translation li
brief but succinct terms (Lectures 39–40). All of this is meant to show
how phenomenology encompasses all spheres of experience, transcen-
dentally purified. The question becomes, next, how is it possible to gain
such an overview?63
63 Reminding the reader of the distinction between apodictic and adequate evidence,
Husserl is here clearly no longer concerned with the foundational issue of apodictic
evidence, but pursues evidence in all shapes and forms, so to speak.
introduction to the translation liii
To summarize, these are the major themes of this text in the light
of Husserl’s earlier position and his entire oeuvre:
be seen in this light: to him, they are nothing but contemporary iterations of skepticism.
67 As Husserl tries to show in another manuscript (probably meant to be an article
critical of Heidegger), even Heidegger’s signature question as to the being of the entities
leads to the reduction, cf. Hua. XXXIV, pp. 264–278. On the evidence of this text being
the basis of such an article, cf. Janes/Luft 2019.
lviii introduction to the translation
epoché and quasi-epoché in lecture 44 is by far the most difficult passage of the lecture
course and an excellent example of Husserl’s talent for microscopic analysis.
69 Cf. also the passage invoking pedagogical principles of Herbart, cf. below, p. 327.
introduction to the translation lix
70 Cf. letter to Roman Ingarden from October 11, 1933: “Strange times. Can I work, can
I live, de-nationalized as non-Arian? It was hard enough, finally I have forced myself,
and I am back to work now for the last three months, almost with my old energy, despite
being 75. [I am working] on my Nachlass! Posterity will seek it.” (Hua-Dok. III/3, p. 291).
Cf. also Luft/Wehrle 2017, pp. 114 f.
lx introduction to the translation
know.71 It is for this reason that the manuscripts are some of the most
difficult material of the phenomenologist’s oeuvre to assess, but also
some of the most exciting writings he left to posterity.
Nonetheless, the supplemental texts of this volume, appended to the
main lecture by Husserl himself or selected by the editor, do revolve
around some main themes, which shall briefly be mentioned here. The
status of these texts—this much must be clear—is not that they are
mere musings on the side, but present important digressions, deepen-
ings and systematic additions to the publicly available material and are
deemed by some as even more important than the published material
(including lecture courses, which were, after all, public). At the same
time, they rarely pursue one train of thought, but show Husserl’s mind
wandering freely in texts, which at times roll along aimlessly, at oth-
ers peter out (somewhat disappointingly), at still others abound with
flourish and energy, sometimes even rhetorical panache. The quantity
of the material presented here amounts to about half of the main text,
though perhaps it would have been desirable to include much more
(on the criteria for selecting these texts, cf. section V below). But in
order to keep this volume manageable, a certain focus had to be placed
on texts in closer proximity to the main text. Here are some of the
dominant (though by far not exhaustive) themes treated here:
2. Self-critical reflections
tation and how it could have been improved. This gives a peek not
only into Husserl’s manner of composition, but also into Husserl’s
underlying agenda.
Regarding content, Husserl is only slowly beginning to realize the
importance the distinction between the two modes of evidence—
adequate and apodictic—has for the self-critique of phenomenology.
Its importance has already been discussed before; but this distinc-
tion can also be read in conjunction with Husserl’s turn to genetic
phenomenology in the same period (a topic that makes almost no
appearance in the present texts), where Husserl, too, comes to real-
ize the limits of phenomenological evidence and the need to expand
the scope of analysis. A good amount of texts touch on the issue of
evidence.
74 It is to be kept in mind that the full text of the Crisis did not appear until it was
published in the Husserliana in 1962! Up until then, only part I (merely 18 pages!) of
the publication of 1936 (published in Belgrade) was available.
75 The new rise of Husserl at this point took place mainly in English-language scholar-
ship, and the latter differs from the earlier English-language scholarship on Husserl in
that it takes his transcendental project seriously.
76 Other translations exist into Italian, Spanish, and French.
lxvi introduction to the translation
77 During his time in the United States, Kuhn (1899–1991) was professor at the Univer-
sity of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, from 1937 to 1941, and Emory University, Atlanta,
from 1947–1949. He then returned to Germany to become professor first in Erlangen,
then from 1953–1967 in Munich.
78 Wagner mentions the second-tier discussion waged by students of Rickert, Rudolf
Zocher and Friedrich Kreis in articles of the early 1930s (cf. Wagner 1953/54, p. 1, n.),
and the reply by Fink in his famous 1933 article in Kant Studien, which was endorsed by
Husserl.
introduction to the translation lxvii
79 Wagner follows these laudatory remarks with a scathing critique, ibid., pp. 17–22.
His main point is that in the distinction between world-constituting subjectivity and
constituted world Husserl held on to a problematic (Platonic) “two-sphere theorem”
(ibid., p. 21).
lxviii introduction to the translation
80 Another text that appeared in the same year is that of Gerhard Funke (1958).
81 The original term, “erzwungenes Ende,” presumably refers to the official end of its
public flourishing once it had been denounced as “Jewish” and “degenerate” (“entartet”)
by the Nazis.
introduction to the translation lxix
congruity with the German Idealists and their contemporary heirs, but
also in all of this tradition’s (ultimately problematic) originality. That
the majority of Husserl’s attention was focused on this issue has had a
crucial (though perhaps detrimental) impact on the reception of his
work throughout history.
Henrich’s discussion focuses on Husserl’s attempts to exploit the
tradition in order to find an ultimate ground of knowledge. Here Hen-
rich agrees with Husserl’s assessment that Hume attempted to open
the door to transcendental philosophy but failed at that and instead
opened the door to a problematic psychologism. The same tendency—
opening this door but failing—is discernable in Husserl’s discussion
of Kant, as Henrich sees it. Henrich makes it clear that Husserl is not
interested in the historical Kant (or Descartes, etc.), but in “the type
[of philosophy] inaugurated by Kant” (ibid., p. 16), in this case the
“method of regressive transcendental reflection” (ibid., p. 17).
The most suggestive discussion is Henrich’s confrontation of Hus-
serl with Hegel and Hegel’s contemporary followers, such as Wagner,
Wolfgang Cramer, and Richard Hönigswald, a discussion that consti-
tutes a delayed Auseinandersetzung. Henrich confronts Husserl with
Hegel on Hegel’s terms. Henrich asserts that both Hegel and Husserl
took issue with Kant’s method of deduction and the way the latter
deals with the skeptical challenge. Both agree that Kant did not go
far enough, yet both idealists attempt to find a dialectically opposed
solution. Husserl attempts to ground all knowledge in an “absolute sub-
jectivism” that he also calls (as Henrich quotes),“an absolute science of
pure consciousness” (ibid., p. 17, below, p. 440), which aims to be abso-
lutely transparent to itself. On the other hand, Hegel’s attempt consists
in a heightening of the ideas of contradiction and negation: “According
to Hegel, only the classical form of skepticism can rise to the level of
philosophical knowing, that skepticism hence, which demonstrates the
impotence of thinking from the relationality and contradictoriness of
thinking itself.” (ibid., p. 18) Henrich thus contrasts Husserl’s “science
of absolute origins” and Hegel’s idea of “absolute knowledge” (ibid.).
While Husserl wants to avoid an infinite regress of grounding relations,
Hegel embraces the “circular structure of absolute knowledge in the
Logic. Philosophical ultimate foundation can only be realized through
a nexus in which the concepts of pure thinking justify themselves from
themselves, which nexus hence returns back into itself” (ibid., p. 20).
lxx introduction to the translation
82 Gadamer later characterized this period, and the role of Landgrebe’s article in it, as
follows (and reading between the lines, Gadamer distances himself from its interpre-
tive tendency): “This is not how I alone felt [i.e., “that in essential points I was guided
both by Husserl and Heidegger,” ibid.], … this is also how Landgrebe, Eugen Fink,
Gurwitsch, Biemel felt, as well as all kinds of others who had survived the Nazi period
introduction to the translation lxxi
and the war in emigration or half-emigration, if one may count Leuven as that. They all
attempted to emphasize, as strongly as possible, the commonalities between Husserl and
Heidegger, and to judge the opposition, which one would have liked to see so dearly for
political reasons, as untenable. And how they did this! Not by showing that Heidegger is
based entirely on Husserl, but rather the other way around, that Husserl’s philosophical
thoughts in his late years indeed came very close to Heidegger. There is an article by
Ludwig Landgrebe, which I myself printed in the Philosophische Rundschau, which
bears the title ‘Departure from Cartesianism’. There, Landgrebe wanted to show that
Husserl in truth in the end, in the consequence of his own thinking about time and time-
consciousness, had abandoned his Cartesian starting point, which he had repeatedly
emphasized through his return to the transcendental ego, and that he had pursued the
same path of thought as Heidegger” (Gadamer 1995, p. 113).
83 Along with other Husserl students such as the Dutchman H.J. Pos, Landgrebe was
engaged after the war in founding the Institut International de Philosophie. The latter
exists to this day and is responsible for organizing the biyearly world congress for phi-
losophy, which attempts to bring philosophers from all countries of the world together
(each country is allowed to nominate two delegates). By today’s standards, Landgrebe,
as the appointed heir of the phenomenological movement, must be viewed as a major
player in the philosophical scene world-wide.
lxxii introduction to the translation
84 Heidegger writes in the margins of Being and Time, regarding paragraph 21, “The
– To begin with the historical details, which he invokes for his sys-
tematic point:
(a) Landgrebe claims that Husserl announced several times but
never carried out an apodictic critique (cf. p. 283). The result
is that Husserl appears as neglectful, making grand gestures
with no follow-through. But Husserl did carry out this self-
critique in the 1922/23 lecture course (as discussed above)
and, moreover, Landgrebe himself was its transcriptor! Can
such an omission be traced to mere forgetfulness on the part
of Landgrebe?86
The question then becomes whether Landgrebe’s claim that
Husserl suffered “shipwreck” concerning his plan to furnish a
complete Cartesianism is in point.This is a different question,
but certainly Landgrebe’s argument for it, that “he could not
furnish it because he never did what he announced” is simply
faulty.
(b) In the same context, Landgrebe cites the famous statement
from the appendices of the Crisis that the dream of philos-
ophy as a science is over (p. 283), and he comments: “Here
we see how the dismissal of the guiding idea of an apodictic
ment to Dieter Henrich (cf. Henrich 1958, p. 24, fn 17), Landgrebe says that the critique
of transcendental experience is contained in the second half of First Philosophy, whereas
he claims in the “Husserl’s Departure from Cartesianism” text that Husserl was merely
promissory in this respect.
lxxiv introduction to the translation
87 Cf. Hua-Mat. IV (lecture course “Natur und Geist” of 1919), where he speaks not
only of “lifeworld” plainly, but of “die anschauliche [intuitive] Lebenswelt” (p. 187),
the “vortheoretische [pre-theoretical] Lebenswelt” (p. 223) or “die natürliche [natural]
Lebenswelt” (p. 227).
88 I cannot discuss all scholarship on Husserl’s First Philosophy. The above discussion
was meant to highlight its early reception. For other texts, cf. Marvin Farber (1963) and
Hans Friedrich Fulda (1967). For some newer work, cf. Jeffner Allen (1982), Robert
Sokolowski (2010), Luft (2010), and Faustino Fabbianelli (2017).
lxxvi introduction to the translation
V. EDITORIAL MATTERS
What follows are a few notes on the translation, its policies and the
editorial decisions of this volume. Regarding the present translation,
the translators have, of course, consulted other translations of Husserl
(into English and into other languages) and Cairns’ helpful Guide
for Translating Husserl. They have, for the most part, attempted to
follow the best practices in translating Husserl89 and to refrain from
neologisms where existing translations, problematic as they may be,
already exist. Reflecting on possible translations for certain words has,
however, led them away from stipulating one-to-one translations for a
given German word. The reason for this is Husserl’s own terminologi-
cal inconsistency, which would render any fixed translation for certain
terms problematic, in some cases even absurd. Rather, the translators
opted for a certain flexibility in translating key words, options which
are to be found in the glossary appended at the end. The attempt was
to use a certain “target” or “focal translation” as the default translation
for a certain word, but deviate from it where deemed appropriate.
Where possible ambiguities could ensue due to a word being trans-
lated in different ways or certain puns Husserl uses on (rare) occasion,
the translators have placed footnotes. The translators have attempted,
however, to keep any explanatory footnotes to a minimum.
Furthermore, our attempt was to render this text so that it reads
fluidly and elegantly in English, at least when it comes to those parts
of the text that were heavily edited by Husserl. This goes especially for
the main text of the lecture course, which Husserl worked on exten-
sively, since he intended to publish it. However, when it comes to the
texts stemming from Husserl’s private research notes, it was not at all
times possible to reproduce them in elegant translation, mainly since
the original German is not at all elegant and easily readable either.The
attempt to render a German text that is at times elliptical, with incom-
plete sentences and extremely difficult grammar, into a fluid English
89 The translators have also refrained from “gendering” Husserl, thus bringing him up to
text seems like love’s labor lost. The translators have done their best
to make the translation as comprehensible as possible in English, but
fidelity should not be sacrificed for an easy read, which these texts
never were from the beginning in the original. Hence, the reader of
the English text, at times perhaps frustrated by Husserl’s difficult and
oftentimes highly convoluted syntax, should find solace in the fact that
the reader of the original German faces the same obstacles.
* * *
The translators had to take into account the fact that many of the
editorial footnotes the editor of the German edition made are now
obsolete in the light of newer texts that have appeared in more than
60 years since Husserliana VII and VIII and taking into account newer
discoveries in the Nachlass and other texts that have since become
available in other literary estates.90 Simply translating these (such as
references to texts that were not published then but are available
now, or manuscripts not localized in the papers at the time but found
in the meantime) would have in fact created many misunderstand-
ings and even errors. Instead, where appropriate, the translators have
updated Boehm’s notes where he, for instance, referred to a text that
is now published (where Boehm cited the Archival signature) and
with the citation to the Husserliana. All of these updates can only
help the current reader gain a better overview of Husserl’s corpus. In
cases where the notes deviate from those of the original editor, the
translators have also placed some explanatory footnotes where they
seemed appropriate and added some references, again all of this with
the intention of keeping any interruption due to the editor’s and trans-
lators’ interventions to a minimum. The translators created three foot-
note apparatuses. Additions by the editor appear in pointed brackets
90 Indeed, at the time Boehm was working on these editions, archival research into
Husserl and the entire Phenomenological Movement was still in its infancy. (Van Breda
established the Archives in 1938, but real editorial work did not begin until after
World War II). Many texts have since been discovered and other Nachlässe (liter-
ary estates) have been established and archived, e.g., in Munich, and elsewhere. Hence,
a good amount of this material was not available to him at the time of his editorial
work.
lxxviii introduction to the translation
* * *
91 Hua. IV (Ideas II), V (Ideas III), and VI (the Crisis text) are the first editions to
contain manuscript material in the appendix in addition to the main composed texts of
Husserl. Boehm’s edition contains ca. one half manuscript material besides the main
text (the lecture course). The first volumes to contain exclusively manuscript material
were Kern’s editions of the manuscripts on intersubjectivity (Hua. XIII, XIV, and XV)
and Marbach’s on pictorial and image-consciousness (Hua. XXIII). It should also be
kept in mind that in the early days of the Husserliana, the edition was considered a
preliminary edition, with the “real” historical-critical edition yet to come. But as of the
mid-seventies, the editorial standards held up to those desired for historical-critical
editions. Some old editions have, moreover, been re-edited critically (Hua. III and VI
by Schuhmann, Hua IV and V by Dirk Fonfara).
introduction to the translation lxxix
course together again in the form in which it was presented in the win-
ter semester of 1923/24. This procedure is further justified by the fact
that not all supplemental texts Boehm selected are included here (to
be justified below). It is a common practice in the English Husserliana
Collected Works to rectify questionable editorial decisions of earlier
Husserliana volumes,92 and hence the philological rigor that should
have been applied to the original edition has been applied now. The
reader, however, can trace the German edition through the original
pagination given in the margins.
* * *
92 Cf., e.g., Husserliana-Collected Works, Vol. IX, Analyses Concerning Passive and
Active Syntheses, which also restores the original lecture course, which is to be found
scattered in Vols. XI, XVII, and XXXI of the original Husserliana.
lxxx introduction to the translation
* * *
93 Cf. esp. the excerpts on Plotinus and Nicolas of Cusa, Hua. VII, pp. 328–330.
94 This policy was also adopted, it should be noted, by David Carr in his translation of
the Crisis.
introduction to the translation lxxxi
VI. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
2015, Luft read portions of the main text in his graduate seminar on
“20th Century German Phenomenology” at Marquette University and
would like to thank the participants for their enthusiastic discussion
of the text. If such a reception on the part of highly talented gradu-
ate students is any indication for the future, this text is bound to be
received well by students, professional philosophers and experts in
phenomenology.
Thane Naberhaus is grateful to Mount St. Mary’s University for
granting him a leave of absence during the spring and fall 2010 se-
mesters to work on this translation. Portions of the translation in draft
form were used in his course “Contemporary Philosophy” at Mount
St. Mary’s.
Idealismus und seine Gegenwart. Festschrift für Werner Marx zum 65.
Geburtstag. Hamburg: Meiner, pp. 147–165.
Funke, Gerhard (1958), “Transzendentale Phänomenologie als Erste Philoso-
phie,” in: Studium Generale 11, pp. 564–582; 632–646.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1989), Truth and Method. Trans. J. Weinsheimer &
D. Marshall. New York: Crossroad.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1995), Hermeneutik im Rückblick (Gesammelte
Werke, vol. 10), Tübingen: Mohr/Siebeck.
Goossens, Berndt (2000), “Einleitung des Herausgebers,” in: Edmund Husserl,
Die Londoner Vorträge, in: Husserl Studies 16, pp. 183–254.
Goossens, Berndt (2002), “Einleitung des Herausgebers,” in: Edmund Husserl,
Einleitung in die Philosophie (Vorlesungen 1922/23), Husserliana XXXV,
pp. xv–lxvi.
Heidegger, Martin (1973), Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik. Frank-
furt/Main: Klostermann.
Heidegger, Martin (1993), Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Niemeyer.
Henrich, Dieter (1958), “Über die Grundlagen von Husserls Kritik der philo-
sophischen Tradition,” in: Philosophische Rundschau 6 (1958), pp. 1–26.
Husserl, Edmund (1974), “Kant and the Idea of Transcendental Philosophy,”
in: Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, pp. 9–37 (trans.T. Klein & W. Pohl).
Husserl, Edmund (2010), “Sokrates—Buddha,” ed. by S. Luft, Husserl Studies
(26), pp. 1–17.
Kern, Iso (1977), “The Three Ways to the Transcendental Phenomenological
Reduction in the Philosophy of Edmund Husserl,” reprinted in Elliston, F.
and McCormick, P. (eds.), Husserl. Expositions and Appraisals. West Bend:
University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 126–149 [originally published in Ger-
man as “Die drei Wege zur transzendentalphilosophischen Reduktion in
der Philosophie Edmund Husserls,” in: Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 24/1962,
pp. 303–349].
Landgrebe, Ludwig (1970), “Husserl’s Departure from Cartesianism,” in:
R.O. Elveton (ed.), The Phenomenology of Husserl: Selected Critical Read-
ings. Chicago: Quadrangle Books, pp. 259–306 [originally published as
“Husserls Abschied vom Cartesianismus,” in Philosophische Rundschau,
ed. by H.-G. Gadamer & G. Krüger, reprinted in Landgrebe’s Der Weg der
Phänomenologie, Gütersloh, 1963, pp. 163–206].
Luft, Sebastian (2002), “Phänomenologie der Phänomenologie.” Zur System-
atik und Methodologie der Phänomenologie in der Auseinandersetzung
zwischen Husserl und Fink. Dordrecht: Springer (Phaenomenologica 166).
Luft, Sebastian (2010), “Phenomenology as First Philosophy: A Prehistory,” in:
C. Ierna/H. Jacobs/F. Mattens (eds.), Philosophy, Phenomenology, Sciences.
Essays in Commemoration of Edmund Husserl. Dordrecht: Springer, 2010,
pp. 107–133.
bibliography lxxxv
First Philosophy
Lectures 1923/24
and Related Texts from the Manuscripts (1920–1925)
PART ONE Hua. VII, p. 3
⟨Section One
From Plato’s Idea of Philosophy to the Beginnings
5 of its Modern Realization in Descartes⟩
⟨Chapter One
The Idea of Philosophy and its Historical Origin⟩
is precisely the first. Since the sciences are not arbitrarily ordered
in a free combination but rather bear within themselves an order,
and hence principles of ordering, First Philosophy will naturally be
the name for that philosophy which is first “in itself,” i.e., accord-
5 ing to inner essential principles. By that one could mean that it
is the first in value and dignity, bearing within itself the Holy of
Holies of philosophy, as it were, whereas the others, the “second”
philosophies, would represent merely the necessary preliminary
steps, so to speak the antechambers of that highest holiness. But its
10 meaning could also be a different one—one, in fact, that for essen-
tial reasons is the more obvious choice. It is, at any rate, the one
that we shall prefer here. Sciences are the products of purposive
work,a and in the rational progression of the purposive activities
belonging to them, unity of purpose creates a unity of order. Each
15 science presents us with an endless manifold of spiritual formations;
we call them truths. The truths of a science are not, however, an
incoherent heap, just as, correlatively, the activity of the scientist
is not an isolated and aimless searching for and creating of truths.
Each individual result stands under higher guiding purposive ideas,b
20 and ultimately under the highest purposive idea, that of science
itself. Just as the rule for formative work is thereby indicated in
a preliminary way, so too do all of the individual truths take on a
systematic form, that is, a teleological form which is imprinted upon
them. Individual truths enter, in fixed orderings, into truth-unities
25 of truths of lower and higher purposive form, binding themselves
together, e.g., into conclusions, proofs, and theories. At the highest
point, an ideal total unity of theory as such belongs to science as
a whole, a universal theory which expands endlessly and devel-
ops itself to an ever higher degree with the endless progress of
30 science. | VII, 4/5
The same will also have to hold for philosophy, as long as we
conceive of it as a science. Accordingly, it will have to have a theo-
retical beginning for all of its truth-products and produced truths.
The name “First Philosophy” would then point towards a scientific
35 discipline of beginnings. We would expect that, for the beginning, or
a Wissenschafts-Lehre
[Hua.] XXXV.—Trans.
the idea of philosophy and its historical origin 7
this First Philosophy is called upon | to reform our entire scientific VII, 6/7
edifice and to deliver us from all scientific specialization.
I will begin with an introduction, which will furnish us with the
indispensable inner presuppositions for our endeavor. Up to this
5 point, we do not even know which of the many and unfortunately
very unclear concepts of philosophy we are to choose to guide us.
No matter which concept we chose, it would at first stand before us
only as an emptily abstract, formal word-thought.a Thus it would
not have the power to arouse our minds and energize our wills. We
10 are dealing here, as I have said, with nothing less than a reform of
philosophy as a whole and, included therein, with a universal reform
of all sciences whatsoever. And wherever one is concerned with
radical and universal reform, no matter in which domain of culture,
the motivation is a deeply stirring spiritual need. The general spir-
15 itual situationb fills our soul with such deep dissatisfaction that to
continue to live in its current forms and norms is no longer possible.
Yet if we are to consider the possibilities for altering this situa-
tion, for creating satisfying goals and methods of spiritual life in the
sphere in question, then what is obviously called for are penetrating
20 reflections on the inner motivational sources of that situation and
on the whole spiritual framework of a mankind toiling restlessly at
spiritual activities which have become ossified in their typicality.c
Such reflections, however, only gain their full illumination from
history, and history, in turn, interpreted from the present, sheds light
25 understandingly on the present. We want, therefore, to turn away
from the bewildering multiplicities offered to us by the science and
philosophy of today and return to the times of primitive beginnings.
First, then, a historical backward glance will serve as a spiritual
preparation. It will reawaken primal, powerful motivations which
30 can set our interest and our will into motion.
If today I were asked to look back upon the entire history of
European philosophy and say, on the basis of the convictions that I
have come to hold over the course of decades, which philosophers
shine brightest of all, I would name two, or better three. They are
35 the names of the greatest beginners, the greatest path-openers of
Wortgedanke.
a b geistige Lage c sich in einer festgewordenen Typik geistigen
Wirkens abmühenden Menschheit
8 part one · section one · chapter one
philosophy. | First I would mention Plato, or rather the incompa- VII, 7/8
rable twin-star Socrates-Plato. The creation of the idea of true and
genuine science, or of philosophy—which for a long time meant
precisely the same thing—as well as the discovery of the problem
5 of method, lead back to these thinkers, and as a perfect creation to
Plato.
Second I would name Descartes. His Meditationes de prima
philosophia represent a completely new beginning in the history of
philosophy in their attempt to discover, with a radicalism unheard
10 of up to then, the absolutely necessary beginning of philosophy,
while deriving this beginning from absolute and entirely pure self-
knowledge. From these noteworthy “Meditations on First Philos-
ophy” stems the tendency, found throughout the whole modern
period, of recasting all philosophy as transcendental philosophy.
15 This tendency indicates a basic character not only of modern philos-
ophy, however, but also, as can no longer be doubted, of all scientific
philosophy as such, now and for all time.
Let us first consider the older, Socratic-Platonic beginning of a
genuine and radical philosophy, beginning with some preliminary
20 remarks.1 The earliest philosophy of the Greeks, naively directed
toward the external world, experienced a rupture in its development
through sophistic skepticism. Through sophistic argumentation, the
ideas of reason in all their basic forms appeared to lose their value.
The true in itself—Being, Beauty, and Good in themselves—was
25 portrayed as a deceptive fantasy, shown, by means of impressive
argumentation, to be mere supposition. This caused philosophy to
lose its sense of purpose. For a being, beauty, and goodness that were
at bottom merely subjectively relative, there could be no principles
and theories true in themselves, no science, or (what meant the same
30 in those days) no philosophy. Yet not only philosophy was affected.
The entirety of practical life was robbed of its fixed normative goals, | VII, 8/9
and the idea of a practically rational life lost its value. Socrates was
1 Husserl took the text from here up to p. 10 (to “of this essence whatsoever.”)
verbatim from his essay “Die Idee einer philosophischen Kultur” (“The Idea of a
Philosophical Culture”), which is reprinted in the appendix to Hua. VII, pp. 203ff.,
but which will be included in the English translation of the Kaizo articles (forthcom-
ing).—Trans.
the idea of philosophy and its historical origin 9
uine ones or, in the opposite case, that they are generally spuriousa
and irrational. The latter occurs, of course, | when the Beautiful and VII, 10/11
Good themselves as they become manifest in clarification evidently
contradict that which is supposed in advance, thereby annulling the
5 supposition by revealing it as unfounded.
a Begründen b Gesinnungen
1 The text from here to the end of the lecture is taken verbatim from Husserl’s
article “Die Idee einer philosophischen Kultur.” Cf. above, footnote 1, p. 8.—Ed.
the idea of philosophy and its historical origin 13
One can say that with Plato the pure ideas of genuine knowledge,
genuine theory and science, and—embracing | all of these—genuine VII, 12/13
philosophy make their way for the first time into mankind’s con-
sciousness. Similarly, he is also the first to have recognized these
5 ideas as the philosophically most important, because most funda-
mental, topics of research, and to have dealt with them accordingly.
Plato is also the creator of the problem of philosophy and of the
science of method—the method, that is, of systematically realizing
the highest idea of the purpose of “philosophy”a that is implied in
10 the very essence of knowledge. Genuine knowledge, genuine truth
(which is valid in itself and guides ultimatelyb), being in the true
and genuine sense (as the identical substrate of ultimately guiding
truthsc)—these become for him essential correlates. The totality of
all truths which are valid in themselves and possibly attainable in
15 acts of genuine knowing necessarily forms a unity, a unity whose
theoretical integration is to be achieved methodologically: the unity
of the one universal science. This is philosophy according to Plato.
Its correlate, therefore, is the totality of all true being.
With this, a new idea of philosophy comes to the fore, an idea
20 which determines all further developments. Philosophy is hence-
forth no longer to be simply science, is no longer simply the naive
product of an interest aimed purely at knowledge. It is likewise not
merely to be universal science—that already existed previously—
but is rather at the same time absolutely justified science. It is to be
25 a science which at every step and in every respect strives for finality,
doing so precisely on the basis of justifications that have really been
effected and for which the knower (and every co-knower) must, in
complete insight and at all times, take absolute responsibility.
With the Platonic dialectic, this beginning of a new Epoché, it
30 already becomes clear that philosophy in this higher and genuine
sense is only possible on the basis of fundamental preliminary inves-
tigations into the conditions of the possibility of philosophy as such.
Herein lies, as though borne in a living seed, the idea, so important
for the future, of a necessary grounding and systematic ordering of
35 philosophy in two stages—a “first” and a “second” philosophy, so
a zeichnet sich […] vor b “Menschen im großen” c sich […] ausweisen lassen
d aus der Evidenz der Zielechtheit
1 The term is derived from the Greek archon (plural archontes), which means
3 Although the context suggests that Husserl is paraphrasing Plato, the terminology
a Wissenschaftslehre
20 part one · section one · chapter two
judgment, not in the more colloquial sense in which it means “opinion.” The quota-
tion marks have been added to indicate that the German word is not Bedeutung,
Sinn, or any of the other more usual German equivalents of “meaning.”—Trans.
f Urteilsmeinungen
22 part one · section one · chapter two
a Verträglichkeit
the grounding of logic and the limits 23
a Urteilsmeinung
24 part one · section one · chapter two
a Sinn
a Begriffsbildung
26 part one · section one · chapter two
a Bestand b Urteilssinne
the grounding of logic and the limits 27
a Gegenstandssinne
the grounding of logic and the limits 29
a subjektiv-reflektiver Besinnung
⟨Chapter Three VII, p. 31
First Reflections On Cognizing Subjectivity,
Motivated by Sophistic Skepticism⟩
At the close of the last lecture I began to speak of the fact that
while the researches of Platonic dialectics—those radical method-
ological reflections—did indeed issue in a logic, in a scientific doc-
trine of method, this logic, due to its one-sidedness, by no means
10 realized the intended idea of a fully sufficient doctrine of method
and of a philosophy brought into effect by it, a philosophy in the
Platonic sense. What I characterized as one-sidedness was the fact
that this logic never attained a scientific theorization of that the-
matic level which is designated by the correlate-pair “truth” and
15 “true being” and, more generally still, “judgment” (significance of
a proposition) and “object of judgment.” At the same time, how-
ever, I pointed to a second correlation, one that relates these ideal
unities to cognizing subjectivity; that is to say, | I pointed out that VII, 31/32
the identical thing which we call an “assertion” and the “truth” in
20 a manifold of modes of judgment is given in subjective modes of
lived experience.a The same goes for the object of judgment in the
different modes in which it is clearly or unclearly experienced or
otherwise becomes conscious. Let us put ourselves back into the
initial motivations, in this case in the historical motivations that
25 guided the Socratic-Platonic reaction [against Skepticism] and in
so doing initiated the development of the idea of a philosophy of
a new kind and of a doctrine of method that would serve it. He
who, as a scientist, stands before the fact of Skepticism, with its
repudiation of the possibility of every objective cognition going
30 under the title of “science” or philosophy, will at first focus on the
a erkenntniskritischen b Ideenerkenntnis
36 part one · section one · chapter three
a Faktizitäten b Herausstellung
38 part one · section one · chapter three
modes in which cognizing runs its course and in which alone that
which is judged or cognized can make its appearance.
How things stood with this rationality, which is ultimately justify-
ing in every respect, when the new sciences began to emerge—this
5 will be our next question.
a übernehmenden Nacherzeugung
40 part one · section one · chapter three
However, should one not demand more here? Could and indeed
must one not pose general questions here? Are we not dealing here
with generally circumscribable occurrences of cognizing life in pos-
sible cognizing subjects as such, with occurrences that are most
5 worthy of their own theoretical interest? Indeed. When the scientist
engages in his occasional justifying considerations mere sidelights
are cast on the processes occurring within cognizing subjectivity.
The aspects of the object that he gets into his view in a particular
case are only a few of the countless modes in which the object is
10 continuously given to him, so long as he views it as one and the
same—as the identical object that he sees now from the front, now
from the back; which at one moment he has before him in percep-
tion, at another in memory; the object upon which he, absorbed
in his research, focuses exclusively but which then again, during a
15 distraction, recedes into the background of his consciousness; which
now stands before him clearly and distinctly, now in a blurred way,
etc.
Would not a theoretical investigation of all that, a research that
focuses theoretically on cognizing activity as such, in all its modes,
20 and then subsequently on the particular kind of cognizing activity
that we call scientific—would not such a research necessarily yield
general insights, insights that would also be of great value to the
individual working scientists within the various sciences? Indeed,
would these insights not enable the scientist to carry out a justifi-
25 cation of a higher kind, a fundamental normative regulationa of his
individual activity? He himself, the scientist of each science, is thus
most invested in this. Indeed, we are dealing here with the theo-
retical investigation of that enormously diverse active life running
its course within the cognizing scientist during his mental activity.
30 It is this life in which—though it remains concealed from him—
his cognizing accomplishment itself consists, or, put differently, in
which consists the inwardness of the configuration | of that which VII, 39/40
continuously lies before his glance as a cognitive formation, goal,
and path. Thinking theoretically and accomplishing his theoretical
35 work, he lives in these processes, which he himself does not see.What
he has in view are the results that take shape in these processes, as
a prinzipielle Normierung
42 part one · section one · chapter three
1 Reading in einer festen und ihnen entsprechenden art- und gattungsmäßigen Typik
instead of in einer festen und sich entsprechenden Art und gattungsmäßigen Typik—
Trans.
44 part one · section one · chapter three
a Urteilsgebilde
46 part one · section one · chapter three
a Erkenntnis-Subjektivem
first reflections on cognizing subjectivity 47
scientific research and thought with the goal of a true theory ranging
over a region of objects that is to be determined in its true being and
being-such. Yet not only is it the case that genuine knowing cannot
be normatively regulated and investigated for the purpose of nor-
5 mative regulation without a thorough investigation of non-genuine
knowing (which, in accordance with the most general characteris-
tics of its genus, may still be called a kind of “knowing”); we must
also take note of the fact that what we call theoretical or scientific
knowing is only a privileged higher form [of knowledge] that relates
10 back to lower levels—for example, to the various forms of sensuous
intuiting and sensuous imagination, with the sensuously intuitive
modes of judgment belonging to them, which not only historically
precede scientific judgments as typical forms of the cognitive life
of prescientific humanity (and indeed are already to be found in
15 animals) but which also play a role in scientific thought itself as
an always and necessarily co-functioning basis and underlay.a Of
course, the full scope of a science of cognitive subjectivity would
have to extend as far as the factual contexture of its region in gen-
eral can be explored; and this region would already have to be
20 conceived in as broad a way as actual generic commonality could
ever extend. No one would, e.g., think of establishing a science of
triangles and a science of circles alongside one another. In the same
manner, in our context, one will not demand merely a science of
cognizing, scientific reason but instead an all-encompassing sci-
25 ence of knowing as such, construed in the broadest | sense, in which VII, 46/47
the totality of even the most primitive formations of perception,
memory, and playful fantasy are as much subjects of theoretical
inquiry as any formation of a priori and empirical-scientific theo-
rizing.
30 In the end, however, we are driven even further. Who could
want to sever cognitive subjectivity from feeling, striving, desiring,
willing, and acting subjectivity, from the subjectivity that values in
every lower and higher sense and that works to achieve its ends?
Theoretical reason is typically placed in parallel to valuing reason,
35 e.g., aesthetically valuing reason, and again in parallel to practical
reason, in which case what one has especially in mind is the proper
ical nature, for animals and humans, and then for social life. Among
these the primary interest was in a science of man, in anthropology,
with psychical anthropology of course intertwined with physical,
since from the natural-objective point of view mental and corporeal
5 being are factuallya intertwined in the unity of the animal.
Thus already in antiquity there arose, in the great spirit of an
Aristotle, a first outline of a universal science of subjectivity, i.e., a
psychology, which was to concern itself with all mental functions
and hence also the functions of human reason. One of the objective
10 sciences in the series of empirical sciences dealing with the cosmos,
one science alongside | the others, thereby enters into a special rela- VII, 52/53
tion to logic and ethics, and through these to all the other sciences
and their regions.
To be sure, the way that psychology comes on the scene makes
15 it a constant cross for philosophers. From the beginning it was not
able to master the problematic that we, by taking cognition and
unities of cognition as our point of departure and in conjunction
with the methodological disciplines of logic and then ethics, have
become aware of in these lectures. What was lacking, however much
20 one spoke of the faculties of cognizing and practical reason, was
the method that would, in the right way, bring out, systematically
and descriptively—thus getting a theoretical grasp on—the spheres
of acts to which these faculties are related and hence in general
consciousness as consciousness of something. This was, however, a
25 fundamental failure, one that of necessity rendered impossible the
development of psychology into the fixed form of a genuine science
advancing by means of rational descriptions and explanations. For in
every pulse of life, human and animal mental life is a consciousness
of this or that. Taken as a whole, this life can be characterized as
30 a continually unitary stream of consciousness forming itself ever
anew: of presenting, judging, feeling, striving, acting consciousness,
of a consciousness that has an exceedingly diverse manifold of for-
mations in which, constantly changing in accordance with objects
and subjective modes of appearance, on the one hand subjective
35 lived experiences, such as sensory data, feelings, and volitions, them-
selves become conscious, and on the other hand, together with these,
a real
56 part one · section one · chapter four
a Kunstlehre
the historical beginnings 57
that all logical laws only had the validity of zoological1 laws? And
would it not follow from this that a change in the human species, a
suitable change in the factical rule-governed processes of human
cognitive activity, could and indeed would bring with it a change in
5 the laws of logic? If we give up the absolute validity of these laws,
however, we run into serious difficulties. How would it be if logical
laws actually had only an empirical-anthropological validity, along
with the fact of the human | species itself, with its peculiar biologi- VII, 54/55
cal features, including the psychological ones that are presupposed
10 here? And what about the fact of the entire world, which is no less
presupposed here? Knowledge of the world comes from science,
and in the case of the human being from physical and psychical
anthropology. Only when this science is really valid can we in fact
and in truth say that man exists and is governed by these and those
15 psychological laws. If, however, that which from beginning to end
gives this and every science whatsoever fundamental legitimacy—
i.e., logic, through its logical principles—were to depend on the
fact of man, then logic would depend on that which could only be
made valid as legitimately existing in the first place through logic
20 itself. This is obviously circular. Indeed, the circle already becomes
apparent when we consider the highest logical principle: if the law
of non-contradiction had a merely empirically relative validity, one
dependent on the fact of the human species, that would imply that
there could conceivably be a change in this species that would ren-
25 der it no longer valid. But then one would also be able to say of this
modified human being that he existed and did not exist, that he had
certain properties and did not have them, that he was and was not a
modified human being, etc.
As we can see, taking for granted without further thought that
30 each and every scientific discipline is related to the world, where
this world is presupposed as an unquestioned fact of experience,
leads to difficulties. This goes especially for the way in which it is
taken for granted that logic relates to the fact of the world and
in particular to the factual existence of the human being with his
35 capacity for cognition. In its original design and determination as
1 Husserl uses this term in the sense of the Greek zoon, i.e., living entity—Trans.
58 part one · section one · chapter four
a Wahrheitsleistungen
the historical beginnings 59
would necessarily have done justice to that which was truly power-
ful in them, in the positivity of its own fundamental justifications.
However many valuable insights philosophy was able gain from this
constant battle against skepticism, it could not as it were strike at
5 its heart so long as skepticism derived its power in secret from that
dimension which philosophy had not yet grown eyes to see, namely,
the sphere of pure consciousness. | VII, 57/58
a Wahrheitssinn
the historical beginnings 61
a “bewährende”
62 part one · section one · chapter four
A glance at the history [of philosophy] shows that this was a pow-
erful impulse, one that soon made its effect felt in a great emergence
and in the complete reshaping of [philosophy’s] development. Since
the Meditationes philosophy has been consumed by the unremitting
35 attempt to elevate the novel problems emerging from below in an at
66 part one · section one · chapter four
1 Cf. the second part of First Philosophy, starting with Lecture 28.—Trans.
the historical beginnings 67
as our principle,] then the entire universe in the usual sense of the
term—the entire world given to us through our senses—vanishes
immediately from the circle of what can be accepted as valid. For the
senses, as everyone must grant, can deceive; at every moment there
5 is the possibility that we err in following them. If, however, I can
and perhaps even do call the entire world into doubt, there is one
thing that is indubitable: just this, that I doubt, and further, that this
world appears to my senses; that I presently have this or that percep-
tion; that I pass judgment on it in this or that manner, emotionally
10 value, desire, will, etc. I am, sum cogitans: I am the subject of this
streaming conscious life, with these perceptions, memories, judg-
ments, feelings, etc., and in this streaming I am absolutely certain of
this, in absolute indubitability. I exist, even if the universe, including
my body, should not; I exist whether or not this dubitable world | VII, 64/65
15 exists. Thus arises my absolute being and being-for-myself, with my
absolute life as an absolutely self-contained being, and it is pre-
cisely this that we for our part earlier designated as “transcendental
subjectivity.”
Obviously this I is nothing at all other than the purely grasped
20 concrete I as I, the purely spiritual subject to which every co-positing
of that which is not it in itself is foreign. If, however, this pure I
in its consciousness now experiences an objective world with its
senses and erects sciences in its cognizing acts, how is this not a
mere inner having of subjective appearances and subjectively gen-
25 erated judgments in subjective experiences of self-evidence? If it is
self-evidence, the insight of reason, which gives the preference to
scientific judgments over the vague and blind judgments of every-
day life, this self-evidence is itself a subjective conscious occurrence.
What justifies my giving this subjective quality the value of a crite-
30 rion for a truth which is valid in itself, for a truth which has a claim to
validity that reaches beyond subjective experience? And especially
now, where cognition is of an allegedly extra-subjective world, what
justifies me in according the belief that the world exists and that
this objective science is truly valid the extra-subjective value that it
35 demands, given that I am only immediately and indubitably certain
of myself and my subjective lived experiences?
Descartes loses himself here, in the attempt to prove the legit-
imacy of self-evidence and its trans-subjective reach, in vicious
68 part one · section one · chapter four
circles that were noted early on and have often been criticized.
He concludes—regardless of how, from the finite peculiarity of
the human pure Ego, [he thinks he can reach] the necessary exis-
tence of God—that with the criterion of self-evidence, God can-
5 not deceive us. The use of this criterion is then permitted and,
guided by it, the objective validity of mathematics and mathe-
matical natural science is inferred, and with it the true being of
nature, precisely in the way this science cognizes it. From there
he founds the two-substance doctrine, according to which the true
10 objective world consists, in ultimate philosophical truth, of material
bodies and the spiritual entities connected causally to them, each
existing absolutely in itself and for itself in the way my own Ego
does.1 | VII, 65/66
This is the train of thought that determines the new develop-
15 ment. Its first culminating point, the Ego Cogito, was to a certain
degree, undoubtedly, a generally understandable discovery. [But] it
was such a new and incomparably important insight that it could
not fail to have an enormous and lasting impact. For the first time,
subjectivity—immediately conscious of itself in its being in and
20 for itself, and capable of being experienced for itself in absolute
indubitability—was laid bare, and firmly framed, in its pure being
for itself, in the stream of consciousness in which its life consists.
And it was also made evident that whatever exists for an I and
can be posited, can be thought in any way by it can only be so as
25 something appearing in the conscious life of that I, as something
it is subjectively conscious of in some way. Therewith, precisely
that “merely subjective” domain was scientifically exposed to which
skeptical relativism—albeit precisely skeptically—reduced all cog-
nizable being by means of the thought: if everything that can be
30 thought or known is an appearance, then only subjective data, which
we call appearances, are cognizable, and there is no cognition of
being in itself, of the true.
Now, I have already said that Descartes lacked an immersion
in the genuine sense of the urgent task set for philosophy by this
35 relativism: for philosophy, for science in general, which now could
a“Reich der Mütter.” The phrase alludes to Goethe’s Faust II. Goethe’s own reference
is to the “mothers of knowledge” in Greek mythology.—Trans.
76 part one · section one · chapter four
⟨Chapter One
5 The Fundamental Limitation of Locke’s
Sphere of Vision and its Reasons⟩
We can also express what we said at the end of last lecture in the
following manner. Locke did not see the radical problem of cog-
10 nition raised by ancient skepticism, and so this problem, naturally
enough, is not the topic of his Essay. And yet the Essay purports
to be a theory of the understanding, an epistemology—indeed an
epistemology that is supposed to bring to an end the perpetual dis-
putes of metaphysics, and to complete and perfect all the sciences
15 through a clarification of the true meaning of their achievements
and of the ultimate source of their basic concepts and methods. The
focus here is on what is fundamental, both on what the sciences in
general and as such have in common and on what determines the
differences between essentially distinct types of sciences, such as
20 the difference between empirical and purely rational sciences.
If Descartes, in his quest for a true and genuine philosophy as a
system of absolutely grounded, absolutely self-justifying sciences,
hit upon the problems of cognition, and if he at least called for a
theory of the understanding that should precede all genuine science,
25 it was precisely Locke who intended to actually develop such a the-
ory, and indeed exactly for these purposes. And yet Locke is not the
rightful heir to the Cartesian spirit, and he | did not take up the most VII, 78/79
valuable impulse that lay in the Meditations. To be sure, we also
found it necessary to reproach Descartes for the fact that, despite
30 having hit upon the transcendental problem of cognition, he failed
to see it—misunderstood it—which was why his project of a radi-
a ein “Vermeinen”.
82 part one · section two · chapter one
a Recht
the fundamental limitation 89
it follows for him that one cannot know whether this support might
not be the same as the one that, in the scientific treatment of external
experience, is taken to underlie material substance.
The way the new natural science, and the metaphysics bound up
5 with it, influence Locke and the theory of the understanding in the
entire modern period does not require a detailed critical appraisal
regarding the particular preconceptions taken over from that sci-
ence. The critique is already accomplished by pointing generally to
the erroneous circularity inherent in the fact that a theory of reason,
10 according to its own peculiar sense, is a critique of reason as such,
and not a critique in the ordinary sense of a testing of the legitimacy
of particular cognitions on the basis of presuppositions that are
granted as obvious. In other words, the aim of a theory of reason is
to clarify how it is that in the medium (which we cannot get beyond)
15 of subjective acts of meaning of whatever form—experiencing, the-
orizing, judging, valuing, opining in the practical sphere—something
like objective legitimacy emerges in so-called activities of reason;
to clarify how it gains its original sense in a particular mode of
validity—that of insight—and how from here there arises | the force VII, 95/96
20 of an unalterable norm, be it of simple truth, of possibility, prob-
ability, or whatever. Indeed, the theory of reason arises out of the
awareness that all consciousness, all acts of meaning, and hence acts
of meaning concerning every type of objectivity, are carried out in
the self-contained sphere of the “cogitating” Ego, and that all talk
25 of truth and legitimacy draws its sense, in subjectivity itself, from
certain particular acts of meaning, acts which ground all insight
and which have, depending on the particular type of meaning-act
and what is meant in it, their distinct forms of sense. Should there
develop the need, in relation to the hiddenness of this cognizing
30 life—which remains, as it were, anonymous during the activity of
objective cognizing—to bring this anonymity into the light of day;
should enigmas and doubts arise out of these obscurities; and should
objective cognition and the objective achievement of reason become
topics of investigation for a theory of reason; then such obscurity,
35 and with it the problem of reason itself, affect every act of cognition,
every act of objective meaning and grounding, in the same way. Each
and every objective conviction is thus contained in the universality
of the problem. What objective presuppositionlessness in a theory
the fundamental limitation 99
a Recht
100 part one · section two · chapter one
a Vorstellungen
the fundamental limitation 101
a Bedeutungsvorstellungen
102 part one · section two · chapter one
Indicative of this is the famous simile of the tabula rasa, which Locke
revives from the ancient tradition. The soul, once it awakens to con-
sciousness, resembles a blank white paper onto which experience
inscribes signs. What make their appearance in the soul, or rather in
5 the inner sphere of experience, are ever new such signs, ever new
ideas, appearing in succession.1 In this simile a tendency toward
1 We must not overlook the confusion that Locke has created with his opposition
between sensation and reflection [Husserl uses the English terms here—Trans.], a
confusion that, along with his other confusions, has passed over into the psycho-
logical and epistemological traditions. [The English terms sensation and reflection]
are usually translated [into German] as “outer” and “inner” experience [äußere und
innere Erfahrung], but what one fails to notice thereby—being caught up in the con-
fusion oneself—is that [the English term] sensation functions in two ways. In the first
place, it functions as the cogitatio in the Cartesian sense, together with its sensational
cogitatum—the latter, as phenomenon (as an idea on the slate of consciousness)
remaining unaffected by whether or not the experienced things in question exist
or indeed whether the whole world, as Descartes has it, remains in “doubt” as a
possible transcendental illusion. The existence of this sensational Cogito along with
its cogitatum is the indubitable self-evidence (which Locke does not dispute) of the
Ego Cogito, and precisely for this reason it belongs among the ideas on the slate
of consciousness. If we form the correct concept of pure conscious experience—or,
if one prefers, of “inner” experience—then this concept encompasses all “ideas,”
including the ideas of sensation in this sense. On the other hand, this sensation is by
no means a [type of] external experience, whose objects ⟨are⟩ not ideas but rather
spatial things experienced “through” the sensuous ideas. However it may be with
this “through” and with the relation between the pure thing-phenomenon as idea
and the thing externally experienced in the natural attitude, this much is certain:
what we have here are two distinct items, and in [100/101] moving from one to the
other, a change of attitude occurs. In one attitude we enact the perceptual belief
and “have” this existing thing; in the other we inhibit this belief and have instead
of the thing the “thing-phenomenon.” Accordingly, we must not call both of these
“external experience” (external perception and its derivates). Obviously the cor-
rect concept is that of thing-experience (enacted in belief), while the other concept
results in a particular form of “inner” experience, namely, the experience of the
thing-phenomena, and reflectively of perceptual meaning or believing about things.
Once this confusion has been clarified, we can nevertheless characterize Locke’s
method as a reduction of all epistemic problems to the ground of inner experience,
the pure experience of ideas or of consciousness—all that being understood in the
proper sense. Of course, then, we are not permitted to continue to characterize,
under the title “sensory ideas,” both the externally experienced things (or even the
unexperienceable substances it is allegedly necessary to hypothesize) and at the
same time the thing-phenomena as “ideas.” This radical confusion, which carries over
to the qualities of things (as opposed to quality-phenomena with their adumbrating
sensory data, etc.), pervades the literature in psychology and epistemology—despite
the demonstrations I provided long ago—to this day.
104 part one · section two · chapter one
the normal and modified sense, this assertion, according to its sense,
claims to put one entity into relation with another, and the relation
itself is put forth as, is affirmed to be, a relation between actually
existing objects (regardless of whether they be real or ideal). | It is VII, 106/107
5 otherwise, as we can see, with the relation of the act to its object
that resides in the act itself; the object to which the act relates itself
is and remains its object however things may be with regard to its
true being. Nevertheless, if I relate myself in perception to some
object in my surroundings, for instance to that tree there by the
10 brook, and say accordingly, “I see this tree,” then this of course
implies, in the normal sense of such talk, that the tree in truth exists,
while on the other hand it is at the same time meant as that which
is perceived in this perceiving. We therefore have here a normal
assertion of a relation in which an intentional relation is at the same
15 time coincluded and coasserted. If we, however, call the existence
of the tree into question or if we purposefully abstain from every
position-taking as to its existence, this alters nothing in the fact
that the perceptual experience is in itself perception of “this tree”
and remains what it is—perception of the latter, related in itself
20 to its immanent object—even if it should turn out afterward that
this perception would have to be judged an illusion. For the sake
of clarity we would therefore do well to distinguish between: the
immanent object of the particular [act of] consciousness (the imma-
nent intentional object), as that of which we are conscious as such in
25 the immanence of this consciousness, and the object simpliciter, as
that which is asserted in a normal assertion as the substrate-object
(the “about which”)—asserted, that is, with the sense that it exists
in truth. If we are living ⟨in⟩ ontic belief, if this object counts for
us as something that actually exists—as when in straightforward
30 experience we have “the” tree, that one over there, as given—then
in our normal attitude and parlance we simply assert, “this tree
…,” and every such assertion then obviously intends the tree as
real.
What is required, therefore, is a change of attitude, the enact-
35 ment of a modification of sense, in order to bring into view,a in the
pure immanence of the lived experience itself, the “supposed object
a erkenntlich zu machen
critical disclosure of the genuine 111
it must be seen that through this type of synthesis, the “fixed and
abiding Ego” of this conscious life is perpetually constituted and
made conscious.
This double polarization under the titles Ego and object, which
all conscious life as such has with absolute necessity, is of such a
10 kind that to imagine it had an analogue in natural reality would
be countersensical. What is real has real constituents, real parts
and moments, real forms of combination. But a synthesis of con-
sciousness has, in the form of these poles, immanent contents that
are irreal. If one has begun at all to see, begun to understand, that
15 these irrealities must be codescribed as inseparably contained in
consciousness—and indeed in all the changing modes in which they
belong to the consciousness in question—then true infinities of
descriptive work open up before one.
One then notices above all the diversity of possible directions
20 of reflection, in conjunction with which it first becomes apparent
that the conscious having of something, for example, the perceiving
of something perceived, the expecting of something expected, the
judging of something judged, and the like, is not something empty
or descriptively impoverished in comparison to what one becomes
25 conscious of in these acts, having at best qualitative differences—
as if perceiving and remembering, for example, differed only by an
ineffable “quality of consciousness.”a
These are, rather, highly complicated modes of consciousness,
undergoing modifications in quite distinct dimensions and car-
30 rying out ever new intentional achievements, achievements that
already stand behind each one of these crudely designating names:
“perceiving” (and still more specifically “perceiving of a thing”),
a“Qualität der Bewusstheit”. The neologism “Bewusstheit” was coined by Natorp and
is translated here as “having-conscious.”—Trans.
114 part one · section two · chapter two
still further things that are beneficial; with his ingenious gaze he
spots the countersense of Locke’s doctrine of external existence and
that of every causal inference to the transcendent-physical realm.
According to Locke, the internal perceptual image of the external
5 thing is an associative complex of sensory data from the various
senses springing causally from the external things of nature. The
mind cannot but underlay such an associative complex with a je
ne sais quoi as “bearer,” whereby a causal inference from effect
to transcendent cause plays its part. Admirably, | Berkeley objects VII, 113/114
10 that such an inference is indemonstrable and unimaginable. For
on the basis of what, according to Locke, are the only immediate
givens—those of the tabula rasa, among which are included all sen-
sory data—it is quite understandable how inferences can be made,
in associative-inductive fashion, from the given psychic data to new
15 data, from given sensory complexes to new complexes; or again, how
one can infer from a sensorily experienced body to an alien psychic
life that is not experienced, by analogy with the experienced unity
of one’s own body and one’s own psyche. But it is meaningless to
make an inference to a je ne sais quoi, something that is in principle
20 incapable of being experienced and for which every analogue in
one’s own immanent sphere is lacking. However much Berkeley,
in the main lines of such thoughts, was on the right path, he could
not provide a real clarification [of these matters] or a theory of
the intentional constitution of exteriority in interiority, because he
25 himself was blind to intentionality just as much as Locke was and
thus was unable to uncover an intentional problematic.
To begin with, it must surely be surprising that Locke, and the nat-
ural scientists who shared his interpretation, took so little issue with
the doubling, indeed the thousandfold multiplying, of the world.
30 On the one side we would have so-called nature itself, the supposed
archetype, while on the other we would have in every subject a
unique system of perceptual images, each of which, however, with
some difference from nature, would itself likewise be a nature, a real
world for itself.And furthermore we would have the oddity that sub-
35 jects, as human subjects, were through their bodies supposed at the
same time to be parts of the objective world, so that the subjective
worlds would simultaneously be woven into the so-called objective
world. One could object that these are not worlds but only images
118 part one · section two · chapter two
or less resembles it. But the trees and houses that I am now seeing
are not analogues of other houses and trees simply because they
resemble them.An analogue is something in which something else is
mirrored as similar, something given that serves as a representative
5 for something else that is similar to it, a symbol of similarity; and in
so serving it has not an objective quality but a characteristic way of
functioning in the subjective apprehension. Hence, it presupposes a
special analogizing consciousness in which alone the analogue has
its actual locus of sense.
10 And this is all the more the case for the actual image.An image is
an image only | for someone who, in a peculiar act of consciousness, VII, 117/118
a depicting one, appreciates its meaning as image; in something intu-
itively given or in the concrete single features that offer themselves,
something else, something not itself given, must, in the manner
15 of consciousness, present itself, just as in the painted or sketched
landscape that hovers intuitively before us a landscape that is not
itself seen but is rather merely illustratively depicted presents itself.
What is present in perception here is the thing hanging on the wall,
the framed canvas, or the copperplate engraving lying on the table.
20 The painted image is a figment that we become conscious of along
with this perception, and it is itself only present for me thanks to
a peculiar act of consciousness through which the figment coap-
pears by means of such a founding through perception. If in this
figment something different, something existing but not present,
25 is to presentiate itself to me, then I must precisely enact the cor-
responding conscious act of depicting presentiation, in which the
intuitive figment takes on the meaning and validity of a presentiating
presentation.
Plainly we are dealing here with modes of consciousness that are
30 fundamentally different from simple perception, modes that are not
in play when we simply see a thing. And the same holds with respect
to the having of a sign for something else vis-à-vis the having of the
thing itself. To the sign as such belongs the specific consciousness
of being-a-sign for another thing, a mode of consciousness with a
35 quite peculiar intentional structure.
Should we now say: Indeed, ordinary perception is, admittedly, not
from the start an analogizing representing or a representing through
an image or indication. It is perceiving and nothing more. But what
122 part one · section two · chapter two
through which they signify for the conscious subject precisely what
they signify and are what they are accordingly as they are possible or
actual. For each basic type of objectivity, we must study, with regard
to their structure, the correlative basic types of consciousness and
5 conscious syntheses in which as an achievement of consciousness
an objectivity of the sort in question is constituted as unity of valid-
ity. To this structure belong, of course, the modes of givenness on
ever new levels already emphasized frequently above—concerning
the temporality that belongs to the immanently intentional indi-
10 vidual object, for example, the modes of the now, the just-past, the
about-to-come; or, concerning spatial objects and their spatiality,
the modes of orientation conforming to | here and there, left and VII, 121/122
right, and so on, the modes of givenness from diverse perspectives,
those of spatial shape but also those of the colorations that “extend”
15 across these; or the modes of givenness according to the changing
sides of the thing; in short, the entirety of the “merely subjective”
that natural-scientific consideration excludes. But each and every
objectivity, including those that are ideal, is a unity of diverse modes
of givenness. Parallel to the concrete conscious experiences whose
20 immanent-intentional objects they are, the “objectivities in the how”
come to a “synthetic unity.” This, however, must in every respect
be uncovered, exactly described, and thereby made intelligible in a
seeing reflection.
A naturalistic psychology and epistemology is fundamentally
25 blind to all such problems concerning the correlation between acts
of cognizing and other forms of consciousness, on the one hand,
and “their” objectivities, on the other, concerning the subjective
constitution of the world in cognizing subjectivity—blind, in other
words, to every problem concerning subjectivity as the source of
30 all sense-giving and validity. And this means that they are blind
to the genuine epistemological problems of cognition and, in its
empirical inflection, even to the genuine psychological problems of
cognition. While we did not, therefore, overlook the advance that
was inaugurated in Locke’s Essay when, in contrast to Descartes,
35 he undertook to found a science of the data of the Ego Cogito, it is
now clear that he was unable to break through to the genuine foun-
dational science for all cognition and, on the other side, to a genuine
objective psychology founded on the basis of inner experience.
126 part one · section two · chapter two
a Erbübel.—Trans.
132 part one · section two · chapter three
to this moment for our own convenience. If, for instance, several
things resemble each other in being red, we can separate off the
moment of agreement, which recurs in all of them in like manner,
as an idea for itself, which of course is something individual. But
5 the mind utilizes this individual as a representative or model in
order subsequently to conceive of every occurring concrete thing
that also contains this moment red as a red thing, that is, as a thing
that contains a moment red that is like the abstract model red. Just
this is what makes possible the so exceedingly useful function of
10 general designation—the formation and employment of general
terms such as “red,” “round,” etc., and then, following upon this,
general asserting.
Yet to whatever degree recourse is had here to functions of con-
sciousness, to acts of comparison, abstraction, representation, and
15 normative regulation, and in however detailed a manner Locke
otherwise treats of psychic acts such as collecting, referring, com-
bining, distinguishing, identifying, and so on, there is nevertheless
no talk, here or in any similar cases, of an analysis and description
of the consciousness of generality as consciousness of … or of an
20 intentional clarification of its objectivating achievement. An under-
standing of the problematic of intentionality is utterly | lacking. He VII, 128/129
therefore also fails to see that in the functions of general thinking, as
their characteristic objectivating accomplishment, peculiar objectiv-
ities emerge in a progressive implication and indeed, in the original
25 forms of this thinking, originally emerge intuitively, that is, as imme-
diately self-given. If Locke does not even arrive at the descriptive
conclusion that diverse conscious experiences of sensory perceiving
can, in their immanence, be conscious of the numerically identical
thing; if it even escapes him that what is real, what is individually
30 transcendent, is capable of appearing in perception, not erroneously
but quite literally in its bodily identity as that which is perceived by
the latter; how much more, then, does he fail to see that something
quite analogous holds for the mental grasping of generality, that is,
with reference to general essences (in Platonic terms, “ideas”), and
35 that it holds no less for the insightful grasping of general states of
affairs or relations of ideas.a Empiricism as a whole fails to see this,
soul or the present soul of another or those of the entire past, etc.—
nor about psychological laws, but rather about nothing more than
what he sees and grasps with insight, wholly immediately, which is
simply this: red is different from green, and the like. And is it not
5 clear that any application of psychological laws here completely
alters the sense of these axioms? And furthermore: if it were a nat-
ural law of the psyche that such relational connections always arise
wherever we are conscious of the termini of the relation, then in a
given single case only the individual relation should exist, whereas
10 what is in question is not how a mere individual case is possible, but
rather how knowledge of general law, and indeed of axiomatic law,
is possible as genuine knowledge.
At bottom, therefore, we always find the same method, which
places behind the slate of consciousness a subject that knows all
15 this and achieves in thought precisely what would have to appear
on the table itself, i.e., in inner consciousness itself, as a conscious
achievement—which, however, one forcefully wishes to explain
away.
Thus, as we can see, empiricism is a mere sham intuitionism or a
20 mere sham empiricism. For it is only an illusion that it carries out
its principle to make no assertion that is not drawn from intuition;
it is mere illusion that it goes back to experience, to self-grasping
intuiting, and measures every assertion against the things and states
of affairs themselves. We become convinced of this not only on the
25 basis of psychologistic interpretations of axiomatic thought, and
then of rational thought in general, that if taken seriously would
have to lead to this thought’s | outright rejection; and we become VII, 136/137
convinced thereby not merely of the countersensical skepticism
that lies, and lies here in its most extreme form, in the fact that
30 now indeed the cognition and validity of logical axioms, such as
that of non-contradiction, is also affected; no, we also become con-
vinced that, at bottom, for empiricism not even the possibility of
a judgment concerning something individual remains intact and
comprehensible for us.
35 We must bear in mind only the following.An individual assertion
such as “this tone is higher than that one” has a uniform assertional
sense whose truth I immediately recognize precisely when I directly
cognize that which is asserted itself, that is, the state of affairs itself.
empiricism’s theory of abstraction 141
Now, it should be emphasized, first, that the concepts tone and being
higher appear here as constituents of the assertional sense and, in
being measured against intuition, as constituents of the asserted
state of affairs itself. It is in keeping with the verbal sense of the
5 words tone and higher that they become fulfilled through intuition,
and yet not through the mere sensory experience of two tones and
a sensory combination of them; instead, the intuitive fulfillment
concerns these sensory particulars precisely as particular instances
of generalities. Skepticism about generality, however, also annuls
10 the general in the particular case, and since individual assertions are
inconceivable without co-meant conceptual generalities, this alone
would be enough to for us to recognize that empiricism appears to
render even singular assertions concerning individuals incompre-
hensible and impossible.
15 But the following is of still greater interest. How do things stand,
then, with the entire sphere of grammatical forms for assertions,
beginning already with individual assertions—with the subject form
and the predicate form, with the is and the not, with the and and the
or, the if and the then, and so on? We say in ordinary speech: “I see
20 that this house has a red roof,” “I hear that this tone is higher than
that one,” and we speak not merely of seeing or hearing the house,
roof, tone itself. In nature there are things, but what is surely not in
nature are these states of affairs with their subject and predicate
forms or the relation higher than and, on the other side, as a distinct
25 thing, the opposing relation lower than, which in each case again is
a dependent | moment of the intuitive portion of the entire propo- VII, 137/138
sition, of the state of affairs. In point of fact, to experience is not
merely to experience individual data; experiencing is the conscious-
ness of the self-giving, the self-grasping, the self-having of anything
30 at all that is meant, in any form of consciousness whatever—of that
which is meant in innumerable assertional forms with their individ-
ual shapes and which can then, in this sense-formation, precisely
be given, itself intuited, and grasped as truly existing. Without this
broadening of the idea of intuition, which is exactly measured to
35 fit conscious acts of meaning, including those that are totally unin-
tuitive, in all its forms, there can be no talk of a description of the
cognitive situation or of a settled understanding about cognition
and true being.
142 part one · section two · chapter three
general, etc.This much is clear here: once one has in one’s possession
pure ideas such as mathematical ideas and the ideas of pure apo-
phantic logic, pure generality on the side of objects has to bring with
it an equally pure generality on the side of consciousness. In other
5 words, one becomes aware that transcendental consciousness in its
basic configurations and its transcendental achievements can and
must be considered using the method of essential intuition—that
is, as we can say, using the purely grasped Platonic method. Every
pure idea pertaining to a genus or a mathematical form of objec-
10 tivities in general points back to an eidetic problematic concerning
the modes of consciousness that relate to objectivities having the
relevant nature or form; and these modes of consciousness them-
selves are thereby conceived in eidetic generality, and in the actual
investigation they must be exhibited as “ideas” using the eidetic
15 method.
In this way, what emerges from the critique of empiricism is the
idea of an entirely different science of subjectivity based on pure
“inner experience,” an eidetic science of the Ego as such, of possible
pure consciousness as such, of possible objects of consciousness
20 as such, in which all facticity is suspended and is only included
within the range of pure possibilities as one such possibility. If we
delve more deeply into these matters, it even turns out that every
transcendental | question to be posed about individual objects and VII, 139/140
individually determined consciousness, for instance of these human
25 beings and this world, can and may only be treated in the manner of
geometrical questions in reference to a determinate thing in nature
and to nature in general as a something determinate. This means:
the necessary method is that in which the individual case is regarded
as an individual instance of a priori generality, so that the problem is
30 shifted from the realm of the factual to the realm of pure possibility
and its a priori. Transcendental philosophy is first and foremost, and
necessarily, a priori philosophy, and only then application to the
factual.
However, we cannot yet discuss what exactly is meant by this.
35 At any rate, we retain for now that which lights the way for us,
though admittedly still from a great distance: the idea of a universal
essential science of pure subjectivity and its pure conscious life, a
science that, as eidetic (“a priori”), explores the universe of the ideal
144 part one · section two · chapter three
5 ⟨Chapter One
From Locke to the Radical Consequence of
Berkeley’s Purely Immanent Philosophy⟩
Philosophie des Als-Ob (The Philosophy of “As-if”), first published in 1911, was
already in its eighth edition by 1922.—Trans.
150 part one · section three · chapter one
1 As ancient as these confusions may be, they are, on the other hand, still ineradi-
1 The passages quoted and referred to here are taken from the Introduction (not
the Preface) to Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature, pp. xix–xx in the Selby-Bigge
edition (Oxford: Clarendon, 1896). Husserl had this book in his library (in the edition
by Longmans, Green, London 1882) as well as several German translations.—Trans.
from locke to berkeley 161
a sachlich. Expressions based on the noun Sache—a word for which there is no precise
English equivalent—are used frequently in this lecture. A Sache, as Husserl uses the
word here, is roughly what Hume called a “matter of fact,” and indeed for the most
part this is precisely the rendering we have used. Husserl tends to reserve the word
Ding for material things in the sense of spatiotemporal objects that can enter into
causal relations describable in purely physical terms, whereas Sachen, like Humean
matters of fact, comprise both “outer” (physical) and “inner” (mental) items. How-
ever, the material or quasi-material aspects of Sachen are very much at the center
of Husserl’s concerns in this lecture, and accordingly we have frequently translated
sachlich as “material.” On the other hand, the term also carries connotations of
objectivity and impartiality; hence the rendering in the present context.—Trans.
b sachliche
164 part one · section three · chapter two
Yet Hume does not presuppose all this but rather proves it
precisely through a systematically advancing and assumption-free
psychology that proceeds from the items that are immediately
given to the psyche and empirically ascertains the fundamental
5 laws obtaining for them—the law of association, of recollection, and
the like—as the primitive laws of all intrapsychic genesis. Everything
that exists for the individual subject under the title “experienced
world of bodies and minds,” all the quite familiar objective forms
such as space, time, causality, thing, power, capacity, person, com-
10 munity, state, law, morality, and so on, must be explained through
this psychology, as must the method and achievement of all sciences
that pretend to deliver cognition of the entire world or individual
regions of the world. Of course, the result of this most profound of
psychological explanations of the totality of being and the totality
15 of science runs like this: The entire world, including all objectiv-
ities, is nothing but a system of illusory forms, of fictions, which
necessarily arise in subjectivity in accordance with immanent psy-
chological laws; and science is a self-delusion of subjectivity, or an
art of expediently organizing fictions for the purposes of life.
20 But now it is necessary to look a little more closely at the sup-
posed freedom from presuppositions and radical objectivitya of
Hume’s psychology and epistemology, and more generally at the
entire shape of his methodology. We notice, first, that every funda-
mental consideration of the kind that Descartes deems necessary
25 for a systematic grounding of philosophy is entirely absent. For
Descartes, this was a matter of such great importance that he made
repeated attempts, in ever new forms, at such a fundamental con-
sideration, as is evident from his Discours and his Meditationes and
his Principia on the one hand, and his posthumous writings on the
30 other. Since philosophy is supposed to become an absolutely self-
justifying universal science, the fundamental consideration is to be
the foundational | meditation that deliberates about the proper way VII, 159/160
in which a universal and absolute justification of cognition, as a justi-
fication that systematically encompasses all scientific and in general
35 all genuine cognition, must proceed, and that devises and justifies
the necessary procedure as such. Such a radical reflection on the
a Sachlichkeit
hume’s positivism 165
a sachfern
166 part one · section three · chapter two
weak, and all that in various modifications? | But here, indeed, we VII, 162/163
are speaking of a counting-as-something, of an act of meaninga with
this or that sense.
We also become aware of the need to do justice to the difference
5 between memory, or, alternatively, expectation, and mere phantasy,
be it of something past or present or future, and of the fact that in the
repetition of “ideas” that are ideas of the same thing, quite diverse
“entities” serve to present to us one and the same thing, and that
this presenting of the selfsame thing is a conscious meaning of this
10 selfsame thing, possibly of something ever more clearly highlighted,
determined, authenticated, and so on. Everything that is given pre-
cisely as first and in the Cartesian sense as indubitable, everything,
that is, that is given prior to all objective facts and hypotheses, prior
to all hypothetical and explanatory theories—the presenting-to-
15 oneself-as-this-or-that as such, the taking-for-this-or-that as such,
or, in a word, consciousness—falls by the wayside, so to speak, and
along with it precisely that which makes subjectivity subjectivity,
subjective life subjective life.
Thus, an impression is a matter of factb and as such it is distin-
20 guished by materialc characteristics—and what disappears is nothing
less than its being the experience of something experienced, of
something self-given.This vanishes and yet it is presupposed, already
indeed in the fact that one incessantly pretends that these data are
given in immediate self-evidence. But mere matters of fact are what
25 they are, with their material properties; as matters of fact they exist,
but they signify nothing, they mean nothing, they bear within them-
selves nothing of sense, nothing of the differences between meaning
and what is meant, nothing of empty presentation or self-grasping,
of being something identically selfsame that is repeatedly meant
30 and given, or meant and given concurrently. To hope to find any of
this in matters of fact or as material properties is countersensical.
Certainly it is true that immanent lived experiences, too, insofar
as they are regarded exclusively as events running their course in the
universal form of immanent time, extending through an immanent
35 stretch of time, have a kind of composition out of genuine parts
and properties that admits of a kind of material description. These
a Sein b Bewußtsein
172 part one · section three · chapter two
1 Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, p. xi. Husserl again quotes from the German
translation.—Trans.
hume’s positivism 173
highlight the being and the being-thus of this region. What is con-
tained in this notion of the “straightforwardly given”? This is not a
problem of objective science. That everything which is pregiven for
its theoretical treatment, the objective region with all the objects
5 that become its particular special themes; that all this is a sense
which is immanently constituted in the conscious fashioning of pure
subjectivity—of this objective science knows nothing. A science of
pure, of transcendental, subjectivity, on the other hand, has precisely
pure consciousness as such, or, alternatively, this pure constitutive
10 fashioning, as its theme. Precisely in this manner, it has ⟨as its theme⟩
every presupposed as well as every authenticated and authenticat-
able objectivity, not as naively posited in absolute fashion but as
contained in the concretion of real and possible consciousness that
is thematic for it. And the how of this achievement, the way it comes
15 to be, purely subjectively in these or those modes of consciousness—
this is its problem.
From here we can fully understand the sense of the demand for
an ultimate grounding of all cognition and science in this peculiar
“psychology,” that is, in the | transcendental science of “pure” sub- VII, 168/169
20 jectivity, and at the same time we can understand the sense of a
radical intuitionism and its demand for an ultimate clarification
of cognition, a clarification of the basic concepts and in general of
the collective “foundations” of all the sciences. For all sciences—I
refer here of course to the pretranscendental sciences, the “objec-
25 tive” or “positive” sciences that arose historically—contain a radical
defect owing to the naiveté in which they simply accept what is
pregiven (this or that region of reality, and an entire world encom-
passing them) and in which they fashion concepts, principles, and
indeed ideal sciences, ideal realms of objects. These sciences can
30 only become absolutely grounded when one descends from their
beginnings and grounds to the primal grounds and primal begin-
nings, to the true αρχαί. These latter, however, lie collectively in pure
consciousness, in which every possible being is subjectively consti-
tuted according to content or sense and according to its ontic value
35 with respect to reality and truth in conscious formations belong-
ing together essentially. As long as one has not comprehended the
sense-giving and the verifying achievement carried out or to be
carried out in pure consciousness itself, in which being itself and
hume’s positivism 175
His naturalism consists not only in the fact that he reifiesa conscious-
ness, treating it as if it were something natural, but also in the fact
that, on the ground of inner consciousness, he allows a bad empiri-
cism to prevail, one that believes that all that can be accomplished
5 here is to bring inner facts of experience under empirical concepts in
order then to be in a position to establish empirical laws inductively.
Of course Hume knows very well that inductive laws cannot be
grounded absolutely, that induction can have only provisional valid-
ity. Indeed, more than that: he knows that all inductive inferring rests
10 on association (for a famous section of the work itself is devoted
to proving just this), and furthermore, he knows that such inferring
could only be accompanied by necessary validity if the principles
of association were themselves necessary or, as we can also say, if
they were capable of being grounded absolutely. But exactly these
15 fundamental principles governing all empirical inferences, which
are for him the ultimate foundational laws of his entire psychol-
ogy, are treated by him merely | as inductively ascertained laws. VII, 170/171
Thus, on a foundation of immediate self-evidence, a self-evidence
that is unfortunately, however, the absolute self-evidence of merely
20 immanent experience, laws are put forth not in similarly absolute
self-evidence but in absolute irrationality. The naive reliance on
induction is a poor substitute for absolute insight. For this funda-
mental psychological science is now completely suspended in the
air; if it is not grounded in absolute self-evidence but grounded
25 in the same naiveté as objective science, then, indeed, the entire
undertaking of an ultimate grounding of cognition is deprived of
all sense, and is so precisely at the level of this ultimate foundation.
Again we have identified here a basic ground of Hume’s skepti-
cism. Implicitly the complete irrationality of all cognition is assumed
30 already in the fact that pure consciousness is made to be a seat of
mere irrationality, in the fact that one readily expects it to be sus-
ceptible of lawful regulation but of a kind that can never be grasped
rationally with insight: a set of merely empirical laws for which there
are no grounds of validity that are absolutely graspable with insight
35 on this pure foundation.
a versachlicht
hume’s positivism 177
a dinglichen
180 part one · section three · chapter two
the person. Indeed he had denied a distinct impression for the Ego
and had broken up the entire subjective unity into a heap or bundle
of perceptions. But everyone believes he experiences himself as a
person, just as he believes he experiences unified things; and in both
5 cases these experienced unities are thought to exist even when they
are not experienced. We continuously attribute such a sense, that of
existence-in-itself, to them.
Furthermore: in explaining natural science as a science, and more-
over as cognition stemming from mere habit, Berkeley simply made
10 things too easy for himself. Certainly, association creates complexes
of coexistence and succession. But is this all—and how would natu-
ral science be possible if this were all? For then there would be only
inferences from habitual circumstances to habitual consequences,
inferences that we make in our everyday life, but do not regard as
15 scientific. Can one then doubt that natural science is genuine science,
science that is permeated by the light of rationality? Can one doubt
that necessity dwells in its inferences, that the laws it ascertains
are mathematically exact, with a validity that is rigorously general?
How are they supposed to be merely general expressions of habitual
20 expectations? Rationalism had defended the | rational character of VII, 174/175
the new natural science in the most vigorous way, setting it on a par
with mathematics. In any case one would have to take into account
what it thus claimed.
To be sure, Berkeley had denied that the causality which is the
25 title for all empirical inferences is genuine causality, which itself is
proper only to the mind in its mental effecting and producing. But
even if he may have been right that the originally mental concept
of effecting and force cannot be attributed to material things ani-
mistically, he still should not have overlooked the peculiar sense of
30 rational necessity and lawfulness belonging to the natural-scientific
concepts of cause, effect, force, and law of forces, on which alone
natural scientists depend. Berkeley therefore disclosed nothing
intelligible whatsoever about nature and natural science, because he
paid no heed to the basic sense in which both are generally taken:
35 nature [as] a nexus of necessity in space and time, bound up with
the change and stability of identical things existing for themselves;
and natural science precisely [as] science, the cognition of rational
necessities on the basis of apodictic principles.
hume’s positivism 181
which was not distinguished from rational necessity of the type that
governs mathematical and logical inferences.
Hume’s impressive—if not essentially new—division of causal
from purely rational necessity is the starting point for the problem
5 of the rationality of this latter kind of necessity in general, or, alter-
natively, of the rationality of natural-scientific modes of inference.
Here one acts as though the rationality of relations of ideas and the
rational inferences belonging to them were no problem, that is, were
completely understood, since to deny this would lead to absurdity.
10 On the other hand, the putative rationality of causal inferences is
now dissolved into a fiction through their reduction to a thoroughly
irrational origin in the | association of ideas—dissolved into a psy- VII, 178/179
chologically explicable confusion of blindly compelled belief resting
on habitual association with that kind of rationality which alone is
15 genuine.
The art of Hume’s skepticism consists in treating human cogni-
tion as a stage upon which reason and imagination enter as actors
and annihilate one another as irreconcilable enemies. Reason has
its strictly delimited sphere of authority;a its borderland bears the
20 inscription “countersense.” Within this sphere of authorityb there
are only ideas and relations of ideas, but nothing of a real world.The
latter belongs in the domain of a different power, “imagination,”
which, in accordance with immanent-psychological laws, particu-
larly (though not exclusively) those of the association of ideas and
25 habit, produces the nature that we experience as its fictitious cre-
ation by secretly permitting itself unlawful, indeed countersensical,
border-transgressions. The process is always the same: imagination,
following its blind laws, first generates a countersense and then,
to make this first countersense more palatable, fabricates a new
30 countersense to go with it. The general principle of the imagination
lies in a peculiar kind of inertia belonging to the human soul owing
to which it cannot stop itself, once it has gained habitual momentum
through its previous experiences, and must overshoot experience.
Wherever anything of the regularity of coexistence and succession
35 has presented itself to the soul in actual experience, it must imme-
diately pass over to an extension of this regularity beyond what was
a Herrschaftssphäre b Rechtssphäre
hume’s positivism 185
aAllgemeinschaft. The word is Husserl’s neologism, and a pun on the German words
allgemein (general, universal) and Gemeinschaft (community).—Trans.
190 part one · section three · chapter three
interpretation of the objective being that is explored in them as fact, which accrues
to them through the application of eidetic phenomenology, and through a universal
regarding of all regions of objectivity in relation to the universal community of
transcendental subjects, the universe, the universal theme of the positive sciences,
takes on a “metaphysical” interpretation, which means nothing other than an inter-
pretation behind which it makes no scientific sense to search for another. But behind
this interpretation, a new problematic opens up on phenomenological ground, one
that cannot be further interpreted: that of the irrationality of the transcendental fact,
which expresses itself in the constitution of the factual world and of factual spiritual
life—that is, metaphysics in a new sense.
a Für-mich-dasein
modern rationalism and metaphysics 201
lies stretched out before us—and yet not only are they difficult to
gain access to, but they are also justified methodologically in such a
form that we are forced to say: Kant’s critique of reason remains
just as far removed from a transcendental philosophy, as ultimately
5 grounding and ultimately grounded science, as does that of Leibniz.
The regressive methodological procedure plays for him the largest
role. How is pure mathematics possible? How is pure natural science
possible?, and so on. How must we conceive of sensibility in order
for pure geometrical judgments to become possible? How must the
10 manifold of sensible intuition come to synthetic unity in order for
rigorous natural science, that is, the defining of experiential objects
as truths valid in themselves, to become possible? Kant himself
demands and carries out “deductions,” the deductions of the forms
of intuition and of the categories, which he calls “metaphysical” and
15 “transcendental”; he likewise deduces the schematism, the neces-
sary validity of the principles of the pure understanding, and so on.
To be sure, he does not merely carry out deductions, and of course
they are not deductions in the ordinary sense of the term.And yet, it
is a constructive thought procedure, followed afterward by intuition,
20 and not a procedure that, ascending from below, advancing intu-
itively from authentication to authentication, makes | intelligible VII, 197/198
the constitutive accomplishments of consciousness, let alone one in
keeping with all the points of view that are available to reflection.
That which is in a sense the deepest interior of constituting con-
25 sciousness is scarcely touched at all in Kant; the sensible phenomena
that he occupies himself with are already constituted unities of an
immensely rich intentional structure that is never subjected to a sys-
tematic analysis. Similarly, though judgment plays a fundamentally
determinative role, yet when it comes to a phenomenology of judica-
30 tive experiences and of the manner in which, in their alterations,
the proposition and its ontological modalities become unified, no
attempts are made. For this reason, although a great deal is seen in
the way of formations in pure subjectivity, and important stratifica-
tions of them are discovered, yet everything floats in an enigmatic
35 milieu and is the accomplishment of transcendental faculties that
remain mythical.
Things might perhaps have been different had Kant been awo-
ken from his dogmatic slumbers not by the Hume of the Essay
204 part one · section three · chapter three
but by that of the Treatise, and had he studied carefully this great
foundational work of the English skeptic. Perhaps he would have
discovered, behind the skeptical countersense, the necessary sense
of an immanent intuitionism, and the idea of an ABC of transcen-
5 dental consciousness and its elementary achievements—an idea
that Locke already had.
In one main point, which is partly decisive for the possibility of a
scientifically adequate theory of transcendental consciousness and
reason, Kant lags behind Leibniz. The latter has the merit of being
10 the first in the modern period to understand the deepest and most
valuable sense of Platonic idealism and accordingly to identify ideas
as unities that give themselves in a peculiar intuition of ideas. One
can no doubt say that for Leibniz intuition as self-giving conscious-
ness was the ultimate source of truth and of the sense of truth. And
15 thus every general truth intuited in pure self-evidence has, for him,
absolute significance. For this reason it also makes sense to him to
claim an utterly absolute significance for the essential peculiarities
of the Ego that are glimpsed in such self-evidence. In Kant, however,
the concept of the a priori puts us in a persistent state of embar-
20 rassment. The | character of generality and necessity by means of VII, 198/199
which he characterizes it points toward absolute self-evidence, and
thus it would be, as we must expect, an expression for an absolute
self-giving, the repudiation of which would be a countersense. But
we soon see that he does not mean it in this way, and that the a
25 priori lawlike regularity through which transcendental subjectivity
forms objectivity in itself (according to its rational form, which is
precisely what makes objectivity possible) ends up only having the
significance of a general anthropological fact. In this way, Kant’s
critique of reason falls short of the idea of an absolute foundational
30 science, one that cannot possibly be a priori in his sense but that
can only be a priori in the genuinely Platonic sense.
Thus for Leibniz the thought suggested itself, although he did not
pursue it, of devising a systematic science of the pure and absolutely
necessary essence of an Ego as such, as the subject of a conscious
35 life and one that constitutes objectivity in itself; a science that, by
means of intuitive seeing and then systematic derivations, brings to
the fore absolute truths and absolutely general truths; an a priori
science that is a priori in the good and the only valuable sense, inso-
modern rationalism and metaphysics 205
far as it does not put anything forth that could be denied without
countersense; it would be a science that was the ultimate source for
all cognition and for every science whatsoever—a science of the
deepest a priori, in which every other a priori constitutes itself at a
5 higher level.
PART TWO1 VIII, 3
THEORY OF THE
PHENOMENOLOGICAL REDUCTION
⟨Section One
5 Preliminary Meditations on the
Apodictic Beginning of Philosophy⟩
⟨Chapter One
Introduction: The Motivation of the Beginning
Philosopher in the Absolute Situation⟩
Concerning the following lectures, cf. Appendix 10, pp. 506 ff.—Ed.
1
Part II of First Philosophy was delivered in the second half of the winter semester
2
1923/24.—Trans.
furthermore a universal science. History | was not able to realize this VIII, 3/4
idea, and the index of this circumstance was the persistent current
of skepticism that developed, at times openly, at times in a con-
cealed manner. We followed the course of this development under
5 an unwavering radical critique and made ourselves starkly aware
of this fact: all justifications have their ultimate source and their
unity in the unity of cognizing subjectivity, grasped in transcenden-
tal purity. What was needed, therefore, was a science of primordial
sources, a first philosophy, a science of transcendental subjectivity.
10 From it, all genuine sciences would have to derive the origin of all
their basic concepts and principles and all the other principles of
their method. Precisely because of this commonality in the domain
of their ultimate origins, these sciences of necessity showed them-
selves to be branches of the one, the sole, philosophy. Having thus
15 gained, in the most general terms, a preliminary concept of a tran-
scendental phenomenology and of a genuine philosophy flowing
from it—a purposive idea of the most general kind, and hence one
that had to make itself felt in theories before all others—and having
discovered the necessary purposive idea of all future developments,
20 let us now set about actualizing this idea through our own efforts,
that is, bringing the philosophy corresponding to it into concrete
existence from out of its first beginnings.
The seeds of transcendental philosophy we find historically in
Descartes. Recalling his meditations may aid us in some ways, and
25 particularly in the attempt at a genuine first beginning.1
It is the merit of the philosophical genius that even in his false
theories or in his primitive trains of thought, which seem almost
to lose themselves in trivialities, there lies a higher truth, hidden
and yet perceptible: a truth in statu nascendi, far removed from any
30 proper formulation and grounding but yet, filled with presentiments,
pointing toward the future, while at the same time being quite read-
ily recognizable, for those later-born ones who possess it as a fully
matured truth, as the true germ of the subsequent developments. So
it was with Descartes’ Meditations, and especially with the first two
1 With regard to the following, cf. lectures 9, 10, and 11 from part one, as well as
1 Husserl remarks on the margin of this and the following passage: “insufficient.”
affinity; or, alternatively, because I see that it is not the case that
all beautiful things, though they be of equal value when considered
in themselves, for that reason already must be practically equal for
me, and see that here, in the present case, they cannot be, insofar as
5 a personal valuation, rooted in my innermost inwardness, is suited
to the one value-sphere, marking it as an absolute value for me.
Thus, this one world of beauty—so I must say to myself—is the
one to which I belong from the innermost center of my personality,
and which for its part belongs to me as my own, as that which calls
10 me, in an entirely personal way, and as that for which I am called.
I, as who I am, cannot separate myself from this realm of beauty
(or, speaking practically, from this realm of the good in the pure
sense); to realize it is my task; here I find the realm of my vocational
obligations. And if I follow this calling, what am I doing but losing
15 myself, myself as a finite, as a sensible, inauthentic, untrue Ego, in
order to gain myself, my genuine and true, my infinite Ego, purified
of all that is earthly? Living thus—having a presentiment of the
eternal in the earthly, of the pure in the impure, of the infinite in
the finite, and realizing it as pure beauty in an unwearying act of
20 love—I gain not merely “happiness” but “bliss,” that is to say, that
pure satisfaction in which alone I am satisfied; and in just this way
I realize myself as the only one whom I can call myself in spirit and
in truth.
Under the form of generality we of course also had in mind as
25 included the special case that is in question for us here. We spoke
generally of him who committed himself on the basis of a calling
and had in mind particularly him who committed himself to phi-
losophy, the true | philosopher who is only true when he follows VIII, 16/17
a call, the call that sounds out to him from the idea of a sapientia
30 universalis and demands of him absolute devotion. Only he is a
philosopher who consecrates himself to philosophy, just as it is only
he who consecrates himself entirely to art who is the artist. To be
interested in philosophy, to ponder upon questions of truth from
time to time and even to work on them continually: this is not yet
35 to be a philosopher, just as to dabble in painting and modeling,
even for one’s entire life, is not yet to be an artist. What is lacking in
such cases is the radicalism of the will to finality, of the will that has
in view the infinity of the pure idea and the infinities of an entire
introduction 221
world of ideas, and that can only satisfy itself in living toward the
eternal poles—in which living-toward, and by living fully in creative
activity, it realizes itself as eternal Ego.
Lecture 30: ⟨The Pure Cultural Attitude as Such and the Original
5 Institution of a Philosophical Radicalism⟩
art. A pure love of art can be awoken in someone early on, already
in youth, and can become a practical devotion, perhaps becoming
specialized in the practice of landscape painting; and in this way the
person may blunder into this vocation without taking special note
5 of it, without, so to speak, a solemn decision. The explicit choice
of a vocation, which may occur later, then has the character of a
mere confirmation, and at the same time of an explicit forming of a
habitual will to life and action that had already arisen naturally. The
same can happen in relation to science, and this is not an infrequent
10 occurrence in cases where talent develops early.
Things are entirely different with the philosopher. He necessarily
requires a decision of his own that creates him, for the first time and
originally, as a philosopher—a primal instituting, so to speak, that is
his original self-creation. No one can blunder into philosophy.
15 This is because a “certain naiveté” stemming from the love of
knowledge and the creation of knowledge necessarily comes at the
beginning and is accompanied by an incompleteness that is hidden
to it, one at best dimly felt, but not understood. This incomplete-
ness is first revealed by skepticism, and this entails that it comes to
20 light as what it is only when the cognitive subject begins to direct
his attention to | the relation of the objects of cognition and the VIII, 19/20
cognized truths to the one who cognizes, and then falls into the
familiar so-called epistemological difficulties. In the end he must
convince himself that each and every kind of cognition is affected by
25 these difficulties, that no cognitive value is to be put forth in naive
absoluteness and held to be absolute in a naive attitude, precisely
because each one has its inseverable relation back to the subject of
cognition and its cognizing formational activity. He must acknowl-
edge that, if a pure cognitive value is to be acquired and endorsed
30 here at all, it must be conceived and understood in this correlation
with the cognizing activity. It becomes ever clearer to him that noth-
ing can be achieved with occasional reflections and amalgams of
naiveté and reflection, that from them, rather, only countersense
results. It becomes clear that merely logical critique, such as is prac-
35 ticed by the scientist himself and such as is in turn made formal only
by dogmatic logic, cannot help here, precisely because all logical
forms, and logic itself, are accompanied by the very same dimen-
sions of unintelligibility. Only in this way does the necessity for a
224 part two · section one · chapter one
new, a universal and absolute radicalism arise, one that attacks all
naiveté fundamentally and that wants, by overcoming it, to attain
final truth—and only this is the true and actual truth—and further-
more wants to attain it in the spirit of universality. Thus arises the
5 will to a beginning and to a systematic advance of a completely
novel, all-encompassing, thoroughgoingly transcendental science, a
science that no longer contains any skeptical abysses but in which,
rather, everything is completely bright and clear and secure.
Before Plato there stood the skeptical Sophists, and in opposition
10 to them he aspired, with a new radicalism, to a new science. Skepti-
cism accompanies and admonishes the whole of the philosophy and
science that follow, the ancient as well as the medieval, perpetually
exhorting them to a radicalism of the ultimate, which alone can
overcome skepticism and make absolute science possible. Skeptical
15 nominalism extends into the modern period; Platonism, renewed
and strengthened in the Renaissance, is opposed by it, as well as by
the ancient skepticisms and empiricisms which are revived at the
same time. | In Descartes there arises anew and with primal power VIII, 21/21
the will to an absolutely radical grounding of science, defining the
20 modern age. There is now the idea of philosophy as a definitively
valid science possessing nothing in advance that it has not given to
itself absolutely. And yet British empiricism comes along, and lives
on until the present day, as an open or veiled skepticism. Before us all
there stands Hume, and the positivism emanating from him. Before
25 us all there stands modern, self-subsistent science, with its scientific
ideal that is originally—and essentially still today—derived from
mathematics, although this same archetypal mathematics exhausts
itself in vain efforts to bring the kind of clarity to the basic elements
of its method, its elementary concepts, propositions, and inferential
30 principles, that could allow it finally to make good on its reputation
for exemplary precision. All of this stands before us, the ones who,
in understanding the insufficiency, indeed the hopelessness, of all
such efforts, desire a philosophy. Thus the idea of philosophy itself
entails a kind of final validity and a kind of radicalism of final valid-
35 ity that cannot grow in a natural and unremarked manner out of any
naturally naive love of knowledge or out of any love of science that
is still naive, such as reigns in the positive sciences. What this idea
presupposes in the cognitive subject, in order for it to emerge as a
introduction 225
are chased away. This occurs, however, precisely when all scientific
accomplishments are regarded in the full concrete nexus of accom-
plishing subjectivity and are never studied unless accompanied by a
concomitant study of this correlation.
5 If we conceive of the philosopher as beginning in his absolute
situation and after having made the original decision to do justice to
it as a philosopher, then the necessarily first task is to set in motion
meditations on a possible method, in the progress of which the empty
generality of the philosophical idea of a beginning must become
10 an ever more concretely fulfilled idea, and the concrete sense of
philosophy must reveal itself ever more completely. And the same
will | have to hold for the method in respect of the elements and VIII, 22/23
connections that become determined with ever greater richness.
Having come this far, we could at once enter into the medita-
15 tions themselves and begin with what for the beginner is the first
philosophical act, one that follows as an absolute demand in pure
consequence of his philosophical will: namely, with the universal
overthrow of all previous convictions, however obtained—that is,
with that overthrow which Descartes demanded, “once in life,” of
20 all those qui serie student ad bonam mentem,1 which plainly refers
to that absolutely good cognitive conscience, that absolute self-
justification, of the philosopher.
But before we begin with this, I would like to conclude this intro-
duction with a not unimportant consideration which is intended
25 to show you in brief that philosophy—however much it may be
related to the universal realm of mere cognitive values, alongside
which, indeed, there exist other value categories and accordingly
other forms of pure culture—carries within itself a significance that
spans all pure culture and, precisely thereby and correlatively, a
30 significance for rational humanity as a whole and every universal
rational humanity, back to which culture is related. In speaking of
this universal significance, however, we are thinking of it not in
the sense of a mere historical fact, but in the sense of an essential
necessity binding together science and culture.
original phrase reads “qui serio student ad bonam mentem” (“who earnestly strives
after good sense”).—Trans.
introduction 227
a Gemüt
228 part two · section one · chapter one
good and bad, of the useful, the advantageous or the harmful, have
their source in the will that is conjoined to the evaluating heart.
It is the same if we look around us at the various realms of cul-
ture; culture encompasses formations of praxis, which are grasped
5 as such through an understanding, following along behind, of the
corresponding acts of the heart and will: of will-intentions, such as
those running through aesthetic feeling-intentions, that motivate a
striving and acting aiming at an objective realization of the aesthetic
formations in question. And what is thus understood can become
10 the object of an experiencing grasping and of predicative deter-
mination and even of a scientific problematic—in which case the
aesthetic and practical attitude transforms itself into a cognizing
one. Only when we deliberately exclude, voluntarily and abstrac-
tively, all predicates the source of whose sense lies in the heart and
15 will, as the natural researcher does, do we obtain sciences of pure
cognition. In | these sciences—that is, in the natural sciences—the VIII, 24/25
heart and the will do contribute an influence, but only in the form of
the will to cognition or, alternatively, of valuing-truth-as-cognitive-
aim, but not in the sense that the heart and the will would be the
20 source of the objective predicates’ sense, as in the case of predicates
of beauty and so on. All cultural sciences in the specific sense of
sciences of cultural formations have in their thematic domain not
mere nature with predicates of mere nature, but rather precisely
those predicates stemming from the heart, that is, the ones that
25 point back to the subject creating formations in evaluating and
willing.
Here the universality of the encompassing by the realm of cog-
nition of all the realms of accomplishment stemming from feeling
and willing subjectivity clearly comes to the fore, as, to be sure,
30 does, correlatively, a similar encompassing through which the valu-
ing heart and the will in its striving and acting reach across the
entirety of subjectivity and all its intentional functions. What this
means for science, however, is that in it, as the objectivation of cog-
nizing reason, all valuing and practical reason are mirrored and
35 co-objectivated as well; or that in the cognitive forms of theoreti-
cal truth, all other truth—for instance, every value-truth (what we
call true and genuine values) and practical truth—articulates itself,
determines itself, in predicative forms, and also takes on grounding
introduction 229
such as that between mere fact (which leaves aside every type of
normative predicate), value, and practical ought-to-be; or, within
the factual, differences such as that between mere nature and spirit
(personalities, personal products, that is, culture), and so on.
⟨Chapter Two VIII, 26
The Idea of Apodictic Evidence and
the Problematic of the Beginning⟩
a “endgültige”
the idea of apodictic evidence 235
1 Husserl notes in the margin of the preceding passage: “Work out anew and
shorten significantly”; cf. Appendix 10, pp. 506 ff., cf. Appendix 12, pp. 528 ff., which
can also be viewed as a variant from p. 231, l. 6 up to here. But also compare from here
up to the end of the lecture Husserl’s critical note, cf. Appendix 10, pp. 506 ff.—Ed.
236 part two · section one · chapter two
they do not alter the singular content of the evidence from the orig-
inal perspective and do not annul this evidence in its “positivity,” do
nevertheless signify an imperfection with regard to cognition that
cannot be tolerated. With this we for the first time fully understand
5 the | distinction we encountered earlier between deficiencies of VIII, 31/32
evidence that leave open the possibility of an annulment of cog-
nition and those that do not do this but instead denote something
missing from what is precisely a one-sided instance of evidence and
from our equally one-sided cognition itself (while denoting at the
10 same time unseen abysses for a possible and perhaps quite perilous
declension from the natural directions of cognition).This distinction
was also directly intended to account for the deficiencies in all those
instances of evidence that founder when it comes to the transcen-
dental, of all merely natural–naive evidence, which we above also
15 called the evidence of positivity.
At any rate, we must constantly keep both of these in mind
in our search for a true beginning; on the other hand, we must
preface this search with the most general principle of justification,
under which every cognition stands—that which is one-sided in its
20 naive positivity as much as the reflective–transcendental kind—and
which articulates the demand for genuine grounding, grounding on
the basis of pure evidence. We as beginning philosophers, willingly
directed toward the idea of universal cognition based on absolute
justification, desire to follow, and to do so in the most rigorous gener-
25 ality of the will, the principle of pure “evidence.”This we understand
in the following way.
We wish to accept nothing as cognized in the finally valid sense,
that is, to accept nothing as existing and existing in such-and-such a
way and in any particular mode of being, that does not itself stand
30 before our eyes, grasped by us in itself precisely in the manner in
which it is meant and posited in our cognitive belief. It is in this
sense that from the outset we therefore also want to allow the radi-
calism of the ultimate to hold sway—want, that is, in a manner of
speaking to pass over in all cognition to the limit of evidence, or
35 at all times to attempt to pass over to it. Our cognitive satisfaction
is supposed to be, as far as possible, an “absolute” one. It would
then be an absolute attainment of what we were aiming to achieve
cognitively. This demands at the start that our cognition be a mode
the idea of apodictic evidence 237
cognition, the practical intention, | by means of a simple belief about VIII, 34/35
what is, strives for the self-having of the entity that is meant, and
that indeed in each case there is or can be such a thing as evidence,
and evidence of different levels, up to the limit of adequation—
5 as a presupposition for the corresponding graduated scale of the
satisfaction of our cognitive striving? Nothing is clearer, indeed,
than that I, perceiving an object, grasp it itself, existing over there,
and grasp it as itself, and again that I (to take a case of adequation),
“seeing” that 2 < 3, have and grasp the state of affairs that I mean as
10 it itself and that I, grasping in this way, have with my cognitive striv-
ing actually reached the goal itself, behind which, in its adequation,
there is nothing further to seek. Obviously what has been “seen”
is nothing other than the “it itself” in relation to what was meant,
which therewith becomes both what is meant and what is self-had,
15 self-grasped, simultaneously.
One more thing is to be noted here as a characteristic of adequate
evidence. It comes to the fore when we put such evidence to the test
by means of a passage through negation or doubt. If I attempt to
negate or posit as doubtful an instance of adequate evidence, then
20 the impossibility of the non-being or doubtfulness of what is evi-
dent, of what is grasped in absolute self-giving, immediately becomes
apparent, and does so in turn with adequate evidence. We can also
designate this peculiarity of adequate evidence as its apodicticity. It
is plain that, conversely, every instance of apodictic evidence is ade-
25 quate. We can, accordingly, treat the two expressions as equivalents
and can favor the one or the other in particular depending precisely
on whether we want to lay emphasis on adequation or apodicticity.1
This reflection leads us, finally, to the fundamental sense of the
Cartesian maxim of indubitability, which Descartes employs at the
30 beginning of his meditations as the principle of complete justifica-
tion. This occurs in the form of his well-known method of rejecting
as unjustified, for the purposes of achieving an absolute grounding
of cognition, anything that might engender even the slightest cause
for doubt. | VIII, 35/36
the Residue of Completely Nullifying the World,” Hua. III/1, pp. 103–106, to which
this passage stands in implicit contradiction. There, Husserl writes: “[I]f we think of
the possibility of the not-being (inherent essentially in every instance of a transcend-
ing thing), then it becomes clear that the being of consciousness, of every stream
of experience in general, would necessarily be modified, to be sure, by nullifying the
world of things, but would not be affected in its own existence.” (Hua. III/1, p. 104.
Trans. by D. Dahlstrom)—Trans.
the idea of apodictic evidence 247
still, the | observing perception never comes to an end. But this VIII, 42/43
belongs to the innate sense of the experience itself—the perceiver
is quite well aware of the horizons of diverse possible experiences
reaching beyond what is actually perceived.1 | VIII, 43/44
⟨Chapter One
5 World-Perception and World-Belief⟩
1 Johann Friedrich Herbart: “So viel Schein, so viel Hindeutung aufs Seyn.” Sämt-
liche Werke, vol. 8, Langensalza 1893 (reprint: Aalen: Scientia, 1964), p. 53.—Trans.
252 part two · section two · chapter one
opposite of the English “nothing less than.” (In modern German, confusingly, the
phrase has come to be used in both senses, and Husserl uses it in both senses as well.)
See the next paragraph for another instance.—Trans.
2 Cf. Critique of Pure Reason, A 111.—Trans.
world-perception and world-belief 253
a Weltvorstellung
254 part two · section two · chapter one
alebt er bewußt in eine Welt hinein b in einen Horizont unendlicher Zukunft hinein
zu werden
world-perception and world-belief 257
blance. That the world, the one just now given in the flesh, might
in truth not exist after all, that this world given in the flesh might
be a semblance, a transcendental semblance, is a permanently open
possibility. But in this case it belongs to the | semblance that we VIII, 53/54
5 called transcendental that it would be completely senseless to seek
after a correction through a corresponding truth, or, alternatively,
to inquire after a true being that could be posited instead of, in lieu
of, this non-existing world. This would not be much different than
if we were to ask what true thing existed in place of the mermaid
10 that we had just freely imagined, how we could re-correct this non-
entity so that it would become a something, the true something that
erroneously appears to us as a mermaid.
We must not, of course, allow a false sense to become attached to
our results, as if we had said, for instance, that it follows from them
15 that the world we experience “perhaps” does not exist—“perhaps”
in the ordinary sense of “very well possible” if not altogether “prob-
able.” Or as if we needed to be prepared for the world to come to
an end; as if an apocalypse were just as possible as that a clear sky
“could” become covered in a cloak of clouds, and suchlike. Instead
20 what we say is: the existence of the world is completely beyond
doubt, and this indubitability lies enclosed within the perception of
the world itself in which we live continuously. Whoever, confused
by skeptical arguments, judges and believes that the world does not
in truth exist, or even merely judges that one must constantly be on
25 the watch for this possibility, that person follows the motivation of
theoretical (and in particular, no doubt, terminological–conceptual)
arguments and does not attend to the sense-content of world-
experience and the infrangible world-belief that lies within it in
spite of all such arguments. It is a belief that does not tolerate the
30 slightest conjecture or the real possibility of its being otherwise.
Nothing speaks in favor of the world’s not existing, and everything
speaks in favor of its existing; we actually experience, and experi-
encing is actually a stream of concordant confirmation, as it always
has been. But what is crucial for us here is the fact that this com-
35 plete empirical certainty, this empirical indubitability, nevertheless,
as empirical, leaves open the possibility that this world does not
exist—the fact that it can be seen intuitively that this possibility
obtains, even if absolutely nothing speaks in favor of its being real-
world-perception and world-belief 259
ized. The following remarkable result will become important for us:
the statement that this world is a pure nothingness, a mere transcen-
dental semblance, | is compatible with the empirically indubitable VIII, 54/55
perceptual certainty of the existence of the world. Accordingly, the
5 hypothetical supposition of the non-existence of the world that I
experience with indubitable empirical certainty is not an arbitrary
hypothetical statement, certainly not one like “1 is more than 2” or
“A square is round.” Any countersensical statement can be molded
into a hypothetical supposition; but it is then precisely a counter-
10 sensical supposition. Here in our case, however, we are dealing with
an evidently possible supposition, that is, one that can be seen intu-
itively as being free of countersense, and the fact that it concerns the
universe that I experience (and while it is being experienced in its
indubitable givenness in the flesh) is, for us beginning philosophers,
15 of great interest.
Yet we may not yet claim this as a firm result when we have not
yet taken into account an obvious objection. Surely, one could say,
it is a merely contingent fact that the perceptions of some subject
or other run their course in the form of that universal harmony
20 that originally makes possible, in the concordance of a restituting
correction, the consciousness of a world existing in the flesh and
becoming ever more readily cognizable as the one and only true
world. And surely the possibility is open that a human being’s har-
monious perceptual stream could be transformed into a senseless
25 jumble, into a swarm of appearances. But what does this mean other
than that that a human being, and ultimately every human being,
could become insane? The possibility of insanity surely has no bear-
ing on the possibility of the non-existence of the world. On the
contrary, it is precisely here that we see the necessity of holding fast
30 to the world’s unique, absolutely necessary being. After all, does not
the possibility of insane persons already presuppose the existence
of the world?
Now admittedly, this would not be an especially strong counter-
argument. But the criticism it levels will serve us well in our attempts
35 at clarification.
To begin with, the objection can serve to motivate a necessary
improvement on our initially quite natural yet impermissible way of
expressing ourselves in the communicative plural. I, the one med-
260 part two · section two · chapter one
itating, must after all say to myself: prior to all science, which I of
course have rendered null and void, the world is given to me through
original experience, through my external perception. | Self-grasping, VIII, 55/56
grasping-in-the-flesh of things, of the world in general: this is nothing
5 other than the enacting of “external perception.” If I now, as the one
who experiences, carry through for myself this series of meditations
that have occupied us collectively and in the natural we-attitude, if I
carry them through with respect to my own world-perception, which
belongs to my own inner life, then what results for me is that I can
10 accept no apodicticity for the existence of the world that I myself
experience. Likewise I recognize for myself the possibility that my
course of perception could become disharmonious, and could do
so in such a manner that the world previously experienced in me
dissolved into nothingness.
15 But if I ask myself how things stand with other experiencing
subjects, in whom experience could run its course in normal con-
cordance without any regard to the senseless disharmony of my
experience, then I will readily give myself the answer: human beings
are originally given to me only on the basis of certain of my external
20 perceptions, more particularly, only by virtue of the fact that of the
things given to me in the thing-world that I experience concordantly,
certain of them are distinguished as lived-bodies, and in particular
are distinguished by the fact that in them a “mental life”—sensing,
ideating, feeling, willing, and so on—is embodied. At first I discover
25 myself as human being by experiencing this embodiment in the most
original manner in that particular body which I call my own. If I
then find other things of the same spatio-thingly type, behaving with
the same typicality as that of my own lived-body, then I experience
them in the manner of empathy as manifestations of other subjects,
30 and in this way I experience other human beings, human beings of
whom I myself am one.
Thus it is presupposed here in advance that in general my expe-
rience, as spatio-thingly experience, proceeds in the form of that
concordant experiential life in which a spatial world is there for me.
35 If, as I can see intuitively and with evidence (and can do so again and
again), the possibility exists that my stream of experience could be
transformed, as described above, in such a way that it would lose its
continuously confirming experiential belief and experiential sense,
world-perception and world-belief 261
in such a way that, therefore, there could no longer be any talk of this
world, of “existing things,” of experienced or (in freely initiated acts
of perception) experienceable things | in general, then there also VIII, 56/57
could no longer be any talk of my lived-body, and none, therefore, of
5 animals and of human beings—and so none of human beings whose
concordant unfolding experiences, experiences that constitute an
actual world, I could invoke. I can only invoke other human beings
who are, in the realm of my open but yet still valid experience,
if not experienced then at least experienceable—discoverable in
10 space, the form of the freely accessible experiential horizons, when
I freely initiate and run through active lines of perception. But if I
no longer have any horizons of belief, but at best only world-fictions
with fictitious horizons, then “world” becomes a title for infinitely
many phantasy-possibilities which are, taken together, empty. As
15 a consequence, other human beings, too, are then for me likewise
empty possibilities, each of which is the same as every other and like
them counts as a “nothing.” Let us not forget the nature of these
empty possibilities. That human beings live on Sirius is for me, who
has as given an existing spatial world in the unbroken unity of my
20 experiences, likewise an “empty” possibility, insofar as nothing in
my experience speaks in its favor; but it is by no means a completely
empty one, insofar as I could set out on actual experiential paths
and gain knowledge through which it could finally be determined
whether such human beings exist or not. No experiential paths, no
25 paths of “I can” observe, I can gain experiential knowledge and
make a determination, lead into the realm of, as it were, absolute
fictions, which are not inscribed into the universe and do not inhabit
its horizons of “real” possibilities, and which therefore have no share
in the force of the concord of experience (or, what is the same, of
30 the actual universal perception).
It now becomes clear to me that if I, as meditating philosopher
of the beginning, desire to carry out a universal critique of mundane
experience, then I may not do so in the communicative attitude,
in which I presuppose the actual or even only the really possible
35 (i.e., possible in the ordinary empirical sense) existence of human
beings. For I would then have already assumed something that is
itself in question, something that, according to the universal sense
of critique, is itself among the things to be submitted to criticism.
262 part two · section two · chapter one
And yet there lies contained within the sense of this percep-
tion a certain mediacy, one that distinguishes it essentially from
the perception of my own lived-body. In the latter case, we saw, the
thingly lived-body, but also the psychical element embodied there,
5 and the way it is embodied, are perceived in an originary manner.
The psychical element is my own, after all. In contrast, although
the other physical lived-body is, to be sure, perceived in my spatial
surroundings, and in just as completely an originary manner as mine
is, the psychical element embodied in it is not. It is not actually
10 and genuinely self-given but only co-meant appresentatively. In this
respect there is a similarity with that anticipation through which
something co-perceived, as itself concomitantly meant there, | is VIII, 62/63
contained in every external perception—such as the unseen back
side of the seen thing. But the analogy is not complete; it is an indi-
15 cation but not an anticipationa that could be transformed into a
self-grasping.b What this indicating intention demands and makes
possible is not a redeeming perception, as is the case in all moments
of preliminary indication occurring within spatio-thingly perception.
Rather, we are compelled to say, the perception of another lived-
20 body is, in keeping with its distinctive essence, perception through
originary interpretation. This originariness is grounded in its being
essentially and inseparably related back to my own primordial lived
bodiliness, in which I have the primordial experiencing of an incor-
poration of the subjective in something appearing in thingly form.
25 When I perceive that thing there, which in its entire behavior resem-
bles my lived-body, I cannot help but apprehend it as something in
which a subjective element is embodied, indicated in determinately
particular ways in the manner of a hand-moving, head-shaking,
tactile sensing, etc. of an I. By apprehending this thing from the
30 start according to what immediately embodies itself in it, I appre-
hend it itself concomitantly as a lived-body, to which belongs a
concretely full subjectivity persisting in a more or less indetermi-
nate fashion, a subjectivity that must experience itself in the “I am”
but that is not me myself. This spatio-thingly seeing and originary
35 interpreting viewing, which binds itself together in the apprehending
of another’s lived-bodiliness, this understanding as expression, is,
a Vorgriff b Selbstgriff
268 part two · section two · chapter two
* Lately, and quite inadequately, this experience through interpretation has com-
monly come to be called “empathy.”
1 Regarding what follows, cf. Husserl’s critical comment, Appendix 10, pp. 506ff.—
Ed.
supplementations and clarifications 269
1 At the time, the name of the main street in Freiburg’s pedestrian zone. During
the Nazi reign, the street was named “Adolph-Hitler-Straße” and renamed “Kaiser-
Joseph-Straße” after World War II.—Trans.
270 part two · section two · chapter two
be put forth here is thus directed. The existence of the world and all
that is comprised in it must be included in the universal overthrow.
In what manner experiences of the world, and following them
sciences of the world, could ever be philosophically re-validated
5 or resurrected, I do not now know, although I do know that such
a thing would be forever excluded, or that a justification of empir-
ically grounded cognitions would forever remain impossible, if it
were demanded that they satisfy the cognitive norm of apodicticity
according to their straightforward sense, with which they are empir-
10 ical certainties. Such would be an evidently absurd demand. This
may now make me somewhat concerned and raise the question of
whether I | will have to change something in the future concerning VIII, 68/69
my radical demand for apodictic justification; or, if it should not
turn out, albeit with a certain modification of sense, that experience
15 was after all an apodictically justifiable source of cognition; and
accordingly if it should turn out that completely justified empirical
sciences could in fact derive their right, their true and genuine right,
from apodictically evident principles, and could only derive them
from these.1 But as a beginner I cannot yet tackle such questions. I
20 am still looking for the Archimedean point, upon which I can rely
absolutely firmly, the ground of cognition upon which I can begin my
first, so to speak absolute work. I hold fast to the radical demand for
apodictic justification and follow the thoughts which were awoken
by my negative result of the absolute critique of universal empirical
25 cognition and by the course of this critique itself.
1 The first critique pertains to the critique of the existence of the world, whereas
a Sinnesgestalt
1 Husserl comments on this sentence: “This could have been intended from the
and through which all objective experienced being is for it, and
moreover conscious being of every type and form?
The answer is clear: [all of this is possible] through the means
of our methodological bracketing of the existence of the universe.
5 For now I see, after having overcome the belief in the world and
having put it out of power in the most effective form of an evidently
possible hypothetical negation of the entire world, that for me now
also my self-positing as worldly reality, as human being, has become
impossible. On the other hand, I also see that my self-experience
10 is not only enactable, but that it remains in an uninterrupted enact-
ment and in constant validity. I as human being would no longer
exist, or I can always put out of power my existence as human
being. But at all times I do exist and so does my streaming life; at
all times that to which my gaze is directed first and foremost is, in
15 this context, my mundanely existing life and my apprehending and
experiencing myself | as “human being in the world.” Putting the VIII, 77/78
world into brackets, hence, includes concurrently a bracketing of my
self-enworlding apperception.This is, hence, a method of undressing
my empirical-objective cloak that I have inwardly put on myself or
20 rather that I always again put on myself in a habitual apperceiving—
which remains disregarded during my naive life experience. This is,
hence, a method to bring for myself this very fact to cognition, and
in general to cognition that I live, in my ultimate and true reality, an
absolutely encapsulated life of my own, which is a life in a constant
25 objectivating accomplishment, a life which, forming mundane expe-
riences, forms in itself an objective world as its phenomenon, thus as
a phenomenon in this ultimate subjectivity. The [world] is what it is
from my transcendental forming, as appearing to me, being valid for
me, existing in my own authentications, and confirming itself as real.
30 I can already see that all objectivity appearing to me, indeed,
whatever I ever have or could have objectively conscious beyond
the real world—that I may only take such objectivities as some-
thing appearing in my appearance, as something confirming itself
in my confirming, as phenomenon forming itself intentionally in an
35 absolute conscious accomplishing belonging to my transcendental
life.
Yet, this look ahead will give me enough food for thought at
a later stage. For now I declare this in the self-explanation of my
opening up the field of transcendental experience 283
1 Husserl carried out this apodictic critique in the lecture course one year prior to
1 On the following, cf. Husserl’s critical remark, cf. Appendix 10, pp. 508 f.—Ed.
⟨Section Three VIII, 82
On the Phenomenology of the Phenomenological
Reduction. Opening Up a Second Path
to the Transcendental Reduction⟩
5 ⟨Chapter One
The Transcendental Temporal Form of
Subjectivity’s Transcendental Stream of Life⟩
this entire continuity of perceiving, through which the path and the
goal were valid for me as reality in perception, and the striving,
willing, doing, which was my active experiencing together with my
perceiving, [all of this] is not annulled through the inhibition of
5 my judgment with respect to mundane being. Hence, not only do
I have given currently as present transcendental experience the “I
remember,” but contained in it the memory of my past transcen-
dental life. The same goes obviously for every memory. Every one
of it permits evidently a double transcendental reduction, one of
10 which yields the memory as my transcendental current experience,
while the second, reaching strangely into the reproductive content
of memory, reveals a piece of my past transcendental life. If I, in
so doing, walk along the chain of my recollections, I let myself be,
as it were, continually guided by a newly emerging recollection all
15 the way up to a current present and if I practice the transcendental
reduction with respect to the line of recollections being awakened
continually, | then I thereby view my continual transcendental past VIII, 85/86
up to the now; but only a certain part of it; for, if I ask, conversely,
about the pasts prior to that, reproductively awakening ever new
20 distant recollections, then I see, practicing the phenomenological
reduction, that my transcendental life continually reaches back into
an endless past.
Things are somewhat different with respect to the future, inas-
much as the “predicting” of anticipation is not only not an actual
25 seeing, but also not an exact analogue of the seeing-again-before-
oneself in the manner of a presentifying recollection. But regardless,
we can also practice phenomenological reduction with respect to
the pre-anticipated, and we find again through the transcendental
reduction a double transcendental [moment], on the one hand the
30 anticipation as a present transcendental experience and on the other
hand, contained therein as anticipation, the anticipated content;
and insofar as constantly every present is continually accompanied
by a future horizon of anticipation, we again have, analogously to
the endless horizon of transcendental past, an open endless hori-
35 zon of a transcendental future. We see, together with the world,
objective time, that time which is the form of mundane objectiv-
ities as existing, is put out of play. But on the other hand: I, the
transcendental I, live a transcendental life, which presents itself
290 part two · section three · chapter one
1 On the following up to p. 314, cf. two critical remarks of Husserl; cf. Appendix 10,
p. 509.—Ed.
2 Reading korrekter instead of konkreter—Trans.
292 part two · section three · chapter one
a Auseinander
the transcendental temporal form 293
into view a reflecting I that has already become patent, and so on.
But then I can and must also see that the “many” act poles are in
themselves | evidently the identical I, or that one and the same I VIII, 90/91
has its appearance in all of these acts and has in each and every
5 appearance a different mode; I see that it, splitting itself into a plu-
rality of acts and act subjects, is nevertheless one and the same,
the same I which splits itself here.1 I see that egoic life in activity is
nothing but a constantly-splitting-itself-in-active-comportment and
that at all times anew an all-overlooking I can establish itself which
10 identifies all ⟨of those acts and act subjects⟩ or rather, and said in
a more originary manner: I see that I can establish myself as an I
that gains an overview over myself in higher reflection; that I can
become conscious of myself in an evident synthetic identification of
identity of sameness of all of these act poles and of the difference of
15 their modal manners of existence. And hence I say: I am at all times
and everywhere the same, I am as reflecting I the same who grasps
himself as an unreflected I in an aftergrasp, who as a self-perceiver
observes myself as the one who ⟨for instance⟩ perceives a house.2
Once we have become clear of this peculiar state of affairs and
20 have assured ourselves especially of the multiplication of the enact-
ing I’s, we can now assert the following important statement, again
in conjunction with the example of the perception of the house.
In the normal case of a reflection upon my naively enacted house
perception I observe, in my reflective perception, not only the “I
25 perceive this house,” and I am not merely observer of my house-
perceiving I and of this particular perceiving, but I also share the
perceptual belief of this I; I as reflecting I co-enact the belief of the
house-perceiving I. This is to say, just as for me, insofar as I see and
observe this house, precisely this house, and what I now assert as
30 really existing with respect to it, exists, holds valid for me as existing
so in my perceptual belief, thus for me as reflecting I all of that
also exists as actual in the same manner. Together with the self-
perception and the perception of | the house-perception I also allow VIII, 91/92
the latter to hold valid; I am also the enacting subject for this validity.
Hence the result, that every statement of the form “I see this
object,” concurrently means for me: “I believe that this object is
real”; and the same holds for everyone in ordinary parlance. But this
normality is opposed to an anomaly, and now you will immediately
5 understand why I had to carry through this entire self-clarification.
For, it is necessary to emphasize, by contrast, that it does not always
have to be this way, as it normally is; namely, that I as a reflecting I
by no means always have to be co-believing. And, what is of special
importance for comprehending the method of the phenomenologi-
10 cal reduction: I can, as a matter of my freedom, renounce this natural
co-belief in reflection. I can do this in a manner that I comport
myself purely as an observer absolutely disinterested in the exis-
tence and being-thus of the perceived house and in the existence of
the world as such.
⟨Chapter Two
On the Theory of the Theoretical Attitude
of the Phenomenologist: What the
Epoché Means and Accomplishes⟩
1 On this and the following, cf. Husserl’s critical note, cf. Appendix 10, p. 509—Ed.
subjective, subjective images. “The” world “itself” I do not ever experience. Or: I can
in no way know if a world in itself exists.
Or I can acknowledge the experienced world as the world itself, but I can doubt
whether it is true, but [I can do this] in a way that I hold this style of concordant
unified constitution for a preliminary one, which I can and must reasonably trust
practically for the time being. I hence comport myself as if the one world were in
truth (completed), that is, practically—as long as no stronger motives of probability
speak against it; but I believe I have a reason to assume that such a complete truth
either not exist or be doubtful.
Cf. also Hume’s tricktrack. [Cf. Hume’s An Essay on Human Nature, Book I,
4.7.—Trans.]
1 Cf. on the following up to p. 309 Husserl’s critical note, cf.Appendix 10, pp. 509f.—
Ed.
on the theory of the theoretical attitude 299
1 The original manuscript read “es,” which would refer to nothing in particular,
rendering the meaning roughly as “the way things are, were, or will be.” The edi-
tor corrected “es” to “er,” which would refer the “it” to the act, present, past or
future—Trans.
on the theory of the theoretical attitude 301
* On the other hand, all factuality [alles Sachhaltige] also remains contained in
my reflecting I, insofar as the latter, carrying out the higher-level acts of any reflec-
tion whatsoever, now indeed gets a grip on the subjective life and in particular all
that subjective [content] belonging to the corresponding things that were given to
it straightforwardly before—the position-takings, modes of givenness of any type
related to it—but for that reason [the reflecting I] does not relinquish this factuality.
It now takes on in addition to its original thematic meaning, which contains nothing
subjective, the subjective modes that have become thematic now, modes in which it
was given, perhaps with the understanding that it is only conceivable in any such
subjective modes of givenness.
302 part two · section three · chapter two
1 On the following, cf. Husserl’s critical remark; cf. Appendix 10, p. 510—Ed.
on the theory of the theoretical attitude 303
1 From here to p. 309 cf. Husserl’s critical remark, cf. Appendix 10, pp. 510f.—
Ed.
on the theory of the theoretical attitude 305
function; but they are for that reason by no means only enacted
on the side. For the artistically active I lives in them in the main
enactment. However, the domineering function, the one that reigns
over the process, continues throughout the serving function, namely
5 the acting will, as the willing directed at the realizing action and
through the latter towards a final telos. Serving has thereby, as we
can see, a different meaning, depending on whether we consider
the founding valuing and sensual perceiving or the serving inter-
mittent phases of acting | with their unfinished intermittent forms, VIII, 101/102
10 although there are types of necessary foundings everywhere to be
found here. Such different interwovennesses, such different forms
of the action’s being together and intermingled belong, in different
levels of complication, to the act life of the naive I, devoted to the
intentional objects, hence latent to itself.
15 Corresponding to the multifariousness of acts, one also needs to
pay attention to the multifariousness of the characteristics of the
intentional objects belonging to them. Accordingly, the cognizing I,
oblivious to itself in [the process of] cognizing, depending whether
it believes in certainty, or assumes or doubts or negates, has before
20 itself (as it were), as what it intends thematically, what it alone has
in view, different things; thus at one moment something existing
simpliciter, next this something as something possibly existing, or
doubtful, or as non-existing, and so on, whereby the “something”
represents the state of affairs, respectively. In the acts of the heart,
25 which mingle in different ways with such acts, the naively devoted I
has before itself its intentional [something] with the characters of
pleasant or unpleasant, of loved or hated, of appreciated or feared,
of beautiful, of useful, and so on.
One can now call an act of interest in the pregnant sense one
30 which has an object, which the I not only has in conscious view,
of which it is aware somehow on the side, as it were, but at which
it is directed in a pregnant sense, which it is after, which it wants
to attain. But there are even more differences. The noise coming
from the street which “bothers” me does not belong to my theme,
35 to the theoretical thought, whose completion is my “aim.” But it
can, in itself, be a means for other mental aims. And after all, I
live now, for instance as a mathematician, in a special problem,
but it is precisely a special mathematical one, and the unity of the
306 part two · section three · chapter two
instance as an art historian; but this can only occur once the aes-
thetic interest has enacted itself and the value—and in it the telos of
the heart—lies ready to hand, so to speak, as already valued, as self-
valued through value-taking, for a theoretical interest to be directed
5 at it, and firstly | for a perception directed at the aesthetic object, VIII, 104/105
the perception of a value-object.
The following holds generally: Once I have enacted to a certain
extent acts and complex actions of any type whatsoever in naive
devotion—regardless whether they still continue or after a complete
10 stop—I can become aware of my doing or my just-having-done, I
can reflect: for instance, while I am engaged in a scientific theo-
rizing or in an aesthetic contemplation or an external planning or
an executing forming of a work. Once this happens, once I raise
myself thusly as a reflecting I above myself as ⟨I⟩ that is active in the
15 respective actions, the act of reflection does not itself have to be—as
we presupposed this without further ado in our earlier exemplary
analyses of the intellective act sphere—an intellective act, hence
not only, for example, a reflective perceiving of the “lower” acts
and their intentional contents or a reflective relating-back in the
20 manners of retention or recollection, as a reflective directing-oneself
at what the lower I has just done, and so on, upon which a reflective
thinking and theorizing can then ground itself. Rather, there also
exist specific reflections of the heart, which can then, certainly, just
as other acts of the heart, experience a thematic transformation
25 into doxic reflections, but of a changed sense. I, as reflecting I, can
likewise have in myself my intentional object, in pleasure and dis-
pleasure, in love and hate, in striving, in practical considerations
and decisions, in realizing deeds, in myself as the subject of such
acts of the heart enacted in past naiveté. I love, and in reflection
30 I take pleasure in the fact that I love, the way in which I love, or,
in displeasure in myself, I chide myself for this. I had willed and
acted, and reflecting retrospectively I regret that I have acted thusly.
Conscience is a name for a class of such reflective auto-relatednesses
as egoic position-takings of the heart related back to oneself, which
35 then oftentimes translate into a judging about oneself, a judging
concerning one’s own value.
Here one can see at the same time that the reflecting I can also
at times agree or disagree in these reflective acts of the heart con-
on the theory of the theoretical attitude 309
cerning their position- |takings with the I upon which one reflects. VIII, 105/106
The latter is the case when, for instance, I now condemn a hate that
was earlier enacted, or if I dismiss an earlier aesthetic appreciation,
a remorse, and the like, in the current, opposite attitude of the heart,
5 and accordingly in every case of a critique of the heart. This, too,
can occur, that the act, that is, the domineering act of the reflecting
I, is a different one from that of the reflected I. Instead we can also
say, expanding now on what has been said earlier, that the interest
of one and the same I can be a different one.1
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical comment on this passage, Appendix 10, p. 511. Husserl
redrafted part of the text above (p. 308, l. 7–25) in light of this critical comment.—Ed.
310 part two · section three · chapter two
tional object or the theme of this act on the part of the reflected I,
hence that I am co-interested both in the objective being and the
value-being and in the work as work. I am, accordingly, co-enacter
of the acts of the lower I, through which the work of art is there for
5 me not only as an existing thing, but precisely as a work of art, as a
thing in which a value-content—one that the artist has embodied
actively—gives itself. If I, however, withdraw—from any motives
whatsoever—from this co-enactment of the acts of the heart and
the will, at which I am directed in reflection, if I become the pure,
10 disinterested onlooker and theoretical observer of these acts, then all
of them, the founded and the founding [acts], the dominating and
serving ones, are put out of action for me, hence also every unified
theme belonging to their synthesis. As the reflecting I, I am then
not the I that carries out the perceptual belief in which the work
15 of art as a thing takes on the subjective validity as existing; I am
also not that I that takes on the emotional validity of the value-
shape of the art work in its value-taking activity, in the multiple
attainment of valuing intentions, an emotional validity in which it
is given to the heart; and I am equally not the I that would per-
20 haps, in a change of attitude, observe the artwork, acknowledge it
in theoretical experience, describe it and assess it in categories of
art history.
Instead, as a reflecting theoretical I, I can—you see how what
we said earlier in the limited act-sphere with respect to the non-
25 participating onlooker repeats itself—be interested through absten-
tion from all of these co-enactments of the lower theoretical acts
purely in them themselves as these experiences. That these acts
attribute validity of something really existing not only in perception
to the perceived,a but also value-taking to something taken-as-
30 valuable,b as well as to what they feel as valuable [they attribute]
the validity of something beautiful, to something appearing sensu-
ally the validity of a work, and so on, this is obviously something
which characterizes them essentially as act experiences that cannot
be taken away from them. But only that they attribute this or that
35 validity |, that they mean the existing as the existing, the valuable as VIII, 107/108
a Wahrgenommenen b Wertgenommenen
on the theory of the theoretical attitude 311
an absolutely evidently given being, such as that one that 2 < 3, must
not count for me as phenomenological I. And this not-counting
means that I suppress any position-taking concerning existence or
non-existence of this arithmetical state of affairs. If I were a mathe-
5 matician and if I were moved by the interest in mathematical being,
then the evidence of this givenness would be in necessary action for
me. But as mathematizing I, I am simply not a phenomenological
I that I am when I, at first doing mathematics, regard my mathe-
matizing while I am reflectively split-off [from doing mathematics]
10 and am purely interested in what this mathematizing is in itself,
how it looks from within—without any judging position-taking with
respect to what counts objectively for it. Thus, there can be no talk
here of a skeptical attitude, of a skeptical Epoché. I do not have to
repeat that the Epoché that the skeptic practices as a doubter would
15 be interest in mathematical existence, and not interest in the purely
subjective experience, as it is in itself.*
Hence, to appeal, in the logical normative regulation of cognition,
to evidence is a logical and not a phenomenological reflection; in this
latter reflection, evidence is a form of experience, whose structure
20 interests me as a subjective fact, in the former, however, I say to
myself in reflection that I view the objectivity itself, that I cannot
doubt what is thusly viewed |, that I must co-believe where I see in VIII, 109/110
evidence. Here I am in the will to cognition, in intentional direction
towards the ontic telos, and I assure myself that I have truly reached
25 the telos, the entity itself. But it is precisely all interest in the ontic
We may also point out that phantasy and reality are separate
but can also mingle; or rather, both can arise separate or mingled:
the act consciousness through which reality is valid for me can arise
as perceived, remembered, judged, valued, practically shaped, and
5 on the other hand the act-consciousness in which the imagined
reality exists for me, imagined presence in the flesh, imagined past,
imagined judgments, value positings, activities, in which they are
conscious to me and then conscious in the modified manner of the
“as if.” Examples of such minglings are all cases in which something
10 is imagined into my surroundings conscious to me as perceptually
present or otherwise conscious in a belief; as if I imagine that mer-
maids would perform a dance here before us, or if I imagine all kinds
of adventures that I encounter on a hike through a tropical rain
forest. On the other hand, it is clear that, just as a pure consciousness
15 of reality without phantasy, there can be a pure phantasy without a
co-active consciousness of reality. In the latter case all consciousness
of reality is, so to speak, out of action. In a self-oblivion, in which not
even my lived-body and my closest perceptual environment receive
the grace of being regarded, thus an actively grasping and reality-
20 positing experience, I live entirely in the world of the “as if,” and
all my perceiving, representing, thinking, | feeling, acting is itself an VIII, 113/114
activity in the “as if”: as is the case, for instance, when I live, lost in
dreams, in my forest adventures, in all the amazing things that I see
and hear, what I encounter in fright. In this case phantasies are pure
25 phantasies, and I myself am only as I in the phantasy in my field
of objects. In other cases, however, where I only re-imagine reality
and imagine also myself as co-active in the imagined surroundings,
I have a mix, and to the extent that I myself belong to this phantasy,
I am myself a mix, namely a re-imaigned I, whose stock of reality
30 remained untouched.
Let us now transition to the phenomenological reduction. Just as
all other acts, the acts in which phantasy objects—things, humans,
I myself as somehow active I and so on—appear in the “as if”
are originarily and naively enacted, but perhaps also grasped by
35 the reflecting I through the splitting of the I after this enactment
or partially in the midst of it and become a reflective theme in
different manners. Of course I can also establish myself here as phe-
nomenological observer, as interested purely in the experience and
318 part two · section three · chapter three
a Ineinanderschachtelungen
the conscious activity of natural egoic life 319
I have been told that the last lectures have been perceived as
5 fairly difficult. This is not without reason; in principle, there are
general reasons at play here that I want to discuss now, interrupting
somewhat the systematic train of thought.
A first entering—so to speak, into the intimacies of the phe-
nomenologically pure subjectivity—cannot be but very difficult,
10 and this is so precisely because we are dealing here with currently
lived life, in its being-for-itself and being-in-itself: Life of the I, this
is: to be consciously related to any given objectivities, and among
these, to be related in a special manner of specific acts. As a wak-
ing I, it is directed at objects in these acts, and it is occupied with
15 them in cognition, valuing, action. In natural life—I mean here prior
to the motives taking effect, which force the transition into the
phenomenological attitude—everybody knows of his egoic life, he
knows of his egoic relatednesses and his manifold real and ideal
objectivities. He knows of them from natural reflection. But the latter
20 can never yield a knowledge of pure subjectivity, one cannot even
glean it from here. For it is its nature always to have objectivities—
through a previous and retained objective knowledge—and now
to relate the reflectively grasped I as act subject to these objectiv-
ities, whereby, in addition, the I itself is apprehended and posited
25 as objectively human. In this natural reflection one cannot see (as
long as it is exclusively dominant) that every having of objects and
every determination in experience and thought, in which they exist
for the I, is itself already an achievement of the I and its conscious
life, and that at all times the I in its own life and doing essential to
30 it—in its sensually experiencing, thinking, valuing, actively creating
and other acts—brings about in itself and for itself the appearance
and validity of objects. Hence, consciousness itself, intentional life,
as it lives in itself |, as these and those subjective apperceptions VIII, 120/121
with their corresponding characters of subjective validities arise in
35 it from purely essential motivations belonging to it—[all of this]
remains necessarily hidden; this entire life, through which for me
my respective world—things, humans, values, works, human actions,
324 part two · section three · chapter three
socialities, and so on—are there for me as with one stroke, but upon
closer inspection, they only exist for me in communication with
others, so that we are referred, here, to the community of the I’s, and
of all I’s or their intersubjective and unified life, which functions as
5 this intersubjectively constituting life.
This pure life can be opened to the observing gaze and to the-
oretically experiencing and determining work only through the
method of phenomenological Epoché, which occasions a new uni-
versal manner of observation, a new type of reflection of the I upon
10 itself and upon all its worlds as worlds of its enacted consciousness.
Only through this reflection, the pure I and its pure life, the entire
realm of pure subjectivity, becomes visible and describable. We are
dealing here, indeed, with a very “unnatural” attitude and a very
unnatural observation of self and world. Natural life enacts itself
15 as originally—at first entirely necessary—given over and lost to
the world. The unnatural life1 is the life of pure and radical self-
reflection, self-reflection upon the pure “I am,” upon the pure egoic
life and the manners in which what gives itself as objective in any
sense whatsoever in this life, takes on precisely this sense and this
20 manner of validity as objectivity: purely from inner and genuine
achievement of this life itself.
Hence one understands the difficulty of a first entering into the
realm of pure subjectivity and of the pure enactment of that pure
“know thyself!” from which, as shall become ever more clear, phi-
25 losophy as a whole wells up. Any instruction to ever so complicated
activities on the ground of natural cognition and in the context
of the natural attitude of life we can satisfy fairly easily, its diffi-
culties otherwise notwithstanding; for in all individual steps only
something typically known and familiar is brought upon us. From
30 childhood on—and this is precisely | the accomplishment of child- VIII, 121/122
hood development—we have come to know, in all directions, the
typicality of the natural world. But this means, we were at all times
engaged in motivations through which all types of consciousness
and all types of egoic acts could spring into action through which
transcription (the stenogram does not distinguish between lower and upper case).—
Trans.
the conscious activity of natural egoic life 325
* It is irrelevant whether one takes the analysis of nature of the Ancients, or the
causal and functional analysis of the Moderns.
1841) according to whom there are two levels of education (Stufen des Unterrichts):
Vertiefung and Besinnung (deepening and reflection), c.f. J.F. Herbart (1806/1887):
Allgemeine Pädagogik aus dem Zweck der Erziehung abgeleitet. In: Kehrbach, Karl
(Ed.): Joh. Fr. Herbart’s sämtliche Werke in chronologischer Reihenfolge. Bd. 2.
Langensalza, pp. 1–139, esp. pp. 38f. Several of Herbart’s books on pedagogy were in
Husserl’s library and Husserl lectured on “The History of Pedagogy” several times
between 1903–1916. Transcripts of students are extant.—Trans.
328 part two · section three · chapter three
1 Cf., from here to p. 332, Husserl’s critical comment, cf.Appendix 10, pp. 512f.—Ed.
the conscious activity of natural egoic life 329
1 Cf. Husserl’s two critical comments on this paragraph, cf.Appendix 10, pp. 513f.—
Ed.
2 Cf. Husserl’s further critical comment on this sentence, cf. Appendix 10, p. 514—
Ed.
the conscious activity of natural egoic life 331
we have gained thereby is, as we predicted but what will only clarify
itself in the following, only the phenomenological purity in the sense
of empirical psychology.1
We proceeded in this line, observing the main types of acts
5 individually and reducing them to such phenomenologically pure
contents; we busied ourselves to demonstrate with respect to them
the wonderfully intertwined intentionality and thus at the same time
attempted to bring to a first understanding the peculiarity of sub-
jective being and subjective accomplishment, as it manifests itself in
10 every type of such acts. At any rate, such analyses will be necessary
if we want to show that through the phenomenological method a
new realm of experience vis-à-vis common experience reveals itself.
We were engaged in this investigation. But I immediately want
to give you a view ahead, so you may understand how through such
15 individual reducing with respect to the acts of the empirical-human
I ultimately a path shall be opened in order to gain transcendental
subjectivity, to make experiencable that I which would remain even
if the entire world would not exist, thus even if my lived-body did
not exist and hence there would no longer be talk of an I in the
20 ordinary sense, that of a human being.
The answer to this question is: Instead of carrying out, as a
reflecting I, the reduction as described, that is, with respect to indi-
vidual acts and nexuses of acts, and in direction to what each of
these acts posits individually, I constitute | myself as transcendental- VIII, 128/129
25 phenomenological I, and that is, in the form of the subject practicing
transcendental-phenomenological reductions and that firstly makes
its own transcendental subjectivity the open-endless field of its phe-
nomenological experience and research in general. It is now the
question what this is supposed to mean. The answer is: I become
30 this transcendental spectator and my Epoché itself becomes a tran-
scendental one by being encompassing and radical in a sense that
the earlier psychological reduction has not yet known.2 For, if I
practice the phenomenological reduction with respect to an indi-
1 Husserl writes in the margin of the last two sentences: “No!” Cf. Appendix 10,
p. 514. Husserl later crossed out “not yet transcendental” on p. 330, l. 33 above.—Ed.
2 Cf. Husserl’s critical comment (as well as on pp. 345ff.); cf. Appendix 10, p. 514—
Ed.
332 part two · section three · chapter three
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical comment on the following; cf. Appendix 10, pp. 515 f.—Ed.
⟨Section Four VIII, 132
Phenomenological Psychology, Transcendental
Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy⟩
⟨Chapter One
5 The Accomplishment and Problematic of a
Phenomenological-Psychological Reduction⟩
But now we also see how something else and novel is possible,
which pulls asunder the entire ground from this natural attitude and
puts out of power all validities which are precisely the ones that
create this ground.1
5 Indeed, nothing stands in the way of grounding a universal
Epoché, as a universal decision of the will in the sense of inhibiting
all my interests entirely, through which not only is valid what is valid
for me now, but through that which habitually held for me in the
past still | holds; moreover, through which, on the basis of this basic VIII, 143/144
10 ground of validity, will hold valid in natural manner whatever will
hold valid for me in the future; or rather, would hold valid for me, if
I did not intervene through my Epoché. With this universal decision
of the will, insofar as it is meant as one that is continually valid,
I rule my further life. For, in its constant enactment I have to put
15 out of play every enacted validity or each one that offers itself for
enactment, I have to reject, in the manner of bracketing, its power
of being-valid-for-me. I speak of “offering itself.” For at first the
universal Epoché, which now enters the stream of my life, changes
nothing concerning the essential structure of this life. It does not
20 change the fact that I constantly find myself as related not only to
these or those individual things, humans, numbers, political or ethi-
cal ideals with which I concern myself concretely, in real acts, and
with personalities that are intertwined with realities; instead I know
myself also as co-related to an entire world, to the real universe
25 to which these things, these human beings belong, and at the same
time, perhaps, as co-related to certain ideal realms to which the
respective ideal objects belong with which I currently busy myself.
This is to say that that phenomenological Epoché and reduction
that I have to enact in carrying out my universal will must reach
30 beyond the individual act in question; or that the unraveling of impli-
cations belonging to each one leads in itself beyond it insofar as
every object has its objective horizon, every validity has its horizon
of validity. This, however, indicates manifold lines of continuous
intentional intertwinement, for which exists the constant demand
their course, strings in which little by little ever new regions of the
world would (have to) come to perception, and in an ideal totality
of a possible | perceiving, all mundane realities. But this, of course, VIII, 148/149
does not mean that each perception really encompasses such an
5 infinity, as a real infinity of empty predelineations and thereby of
systems of possible perception. And yet, the infinite realm of what is
as yet unknown and not yet determined is somehow predelineated
in every perception, or in its empty horizon of consciousness it is
in a certain manner represented and predelineated as validity in
10 a certain inactual manner. For except for what is predelineated at
each moment in a certain meaning of the intuited content of actual
perception as co-existent or presumably co-existent, indeed the uni-
tary style of the continually streaming possible experience is for the
least part predelineated; thus precisely this [fact is predelineated],
15 that every new experience must yield new predelineations, that the
continual actual experience would have to fulfill these, would have
to determine them in greater detail, but that it would perhaps also
have to determine them otherwise; [furthermore it is predelineated]
that anticipations can be disappointed, that for this [anticipated
20 experience] something else, something completely unknown, can
take its place, and likewise always again. Infinite space surround-
ing every experiencing is not a form that the experiencing agent
could populate, above and beyond actual experience and validity,
with random phantasies; instead, it is a form of possible existence of
25 validity, which—no matter how indeterminate it is with respect to
number and type and distribution of actual things, and even with
respect to the manner in which thingly reality as such continues—is
always still a form of validity, a form for infinite possibilities, which
are not mere phantasy possibilities.1
30 The horizon of consciousness encompasses, with its intentional
implications, its determinacies and indeterminacies, its known
realms and open spaces,a its proximities and distances, not merely
a surrounding in the present, one existing in the now; instead, as
already has become clear from recollection and anticipation, which
a Spielräume
1 Cf. to this and the following Husserl’s critical remark, cf. Appendix 10, p. 516—
Ed.
352 part two · section four · chapter two
upon closer inspection, the world as ontically valid for the expe-
riencing agent in a given moment is a title for the entire stock of
positive validities unified through concordance. On the other hand,
one would have to investigate the structure of the world itself as
5 ontically valid, the world which, no matter how in individual cases
ontic convictions may change (straightforward valid reality becomes
annulled appearance, and the like), the world itself abides as existing
in its general structural form: at all times, it is spatiotemporal-causal
physical nature, at all times it contains deeply rooted within it a
10 manifold of bodily-animate creatures, of animalic creatures, of ani-
mals and humans, standing in social relations, forming societies,
communities, and the like. At all times, a manifold spiritual form
of subjects who are engaged with nature manifests itself in nature.
Hence, mere nature and mere animality are never actually experi-
15 enced, but instead a surrounding animateda as culture—with houses,
bridges, tools, art works, and so on. These most general structures
of the at all times valid world are constantly at hand for every
experiencing agent, it is a constant world of experience, constantly
there and ready for practical doing. These are such structures as
20 intentionally implicated contents in the respective living horizon,
in the animating and revealing activities, and in the further living
actions of continual acknowledgment and knowledge founded in
them, in continual novel valuings, novel positings of goals, of active
re-creations.
25 In these last reflections, we mainly considered the horizon of the
world as horizon of the actual surroundings. But we also have, as
abiding precipitations of validity from acts, in which ideal objectivi-
ties and open infinities of ideality receive their primal instituting, our
ideal “worlds,” if we want to call them so. Hence, for instance from
30 acts of pure counting and the continual forming of [the numbers] 2,
3, 4 …, precisely with this subjectively concluding consciousness of
the “and so on”—of the “we could thusly add on again and again”
unit for unit—we gain the consciousness of the validity of the being
of the infinite line of numbers. The latter belongs, once formed, to
35 our habitual cognitive possession, of which we have to say, again,
that it, although unawakened during whole spans of one’s lifetime |, VIII, 151/152
a vergeistigte Umwelt
the realm of transcendental experience 353
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical remark to this passage, cf. Appendix 10, p. 516—Ed.
the realm of transcendental experience 355
aVice versa. [Boehm takes this comment to mean that the sentence should read, more
correctly, as follows: “Once I have experienced any random individual affections and
carried out different individual acts, I can reflect upon these affections and actions.”
Cf. his editorial comment in Hua. VIII, p. 524.—Trans.]
356 part two · section four · chapter two
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical remarks to this and the following; cf.Appendix 10, pp. 516f.—
Ed.
the realm of transcendental experience 357
a wertnehmend
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical remark to this passage; cf. Appendix 10, p. 517—Ed.
358 part two · section four · chapter two
* Hence temporalization of the entire monad and of the entire monadic totality at
every moment of life, in every experience.
362 part two · section four · chapter two
1 Husserl remarks on this sentence, and perhaps the entire passage: “Imprecise.”
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical remark to this and the prior passages; cf. Appendix 10,
p. 517—Ed.
⟨Chapter Three
The Philosophical Significance of the
Transcendental-Phenomenological Reduction⟩
After having now carried out the new method of the transcen-
dental reduction in its entirety and after having constructed it itself
10 in a methodological ascent from its lower stratum of a merely
phenomenological-psychological reduction, we may well say that
it has enriched us enormously in this methodological grounding.
Not only [is it the case] that the Cartesian reduction, based on the
proof of the possible non-existence of the experienced world, had
15 a direct but only limited result. Through the starting point of the
non-existence ⟨of the experienced world⟩ it led our considerations
to subjectivity, but only as experiencing and thereby as unaffected
by this non-existence. What was needed, henceforth, was a further
development of the method, we had to show, then, that no cognitive
20 positing of the world could remain in validity, but we also had to
show that no validity of ideal objectivity could remain in power.
In short, if we really wanted to delimit the entire circumference of
pure subjectivity as transcendental, we were in need of additional
investigations only at whose end the method as a finished method
25 would be the equivalent of the one we had developed now. But
even if this were yet to be achieved, our novel procedure has the
great advantage that it opens up for us the broadest and deepest
understanding of the structure of subjectivity itself, upon which rests
the possibility of the Epoché, and thereby a deepest understanding
30 of its pure significance. Were we to be already full-fledged phe-
nomenologists, we could say, the new procedure yields not only the
method of the phenomenological reduction, but at the same time a
phenomenology of the phenomenological reduction.
same time, a ground that is at all times one that is ready to be experi-
enced and that remains unquestioned. In this method, however, this
ground is not a merely emptily postulated one or one merely talked
about emptily and distantlya with the proposition “Ego Cogito,” but
5 this ground immediately comes before our eyes concretely and in
its own essential peculiarity as an infinite transcendental life, as a
life that, if we limit ourselves to our own life immediately graspable
in immediate transcendental self-experience, bears on the one hand
a centering in the Ego, the transcendental “I,” and, on the other,
10 the relation to manifold intentional objectivities, each one an inten-
tional unity of manifold modes of consciousness. What is great and
astonishing coming to the fore here is that even if, as I indeed can, I
renounce each and every possible worldly belief, yes, every possible
belief that I bear within myself as beginner, and could bear within
15 myself, when I hence cease to take myself as child of the world, as
natural human being—that I then have lying before me an endlessly
open field of a novel experience, indeed that I have prepared it for
myself precisely through this method: the experiential field of my
transcendental subjectivity. What makes this field immediately most
20 relevant to me, the beginning philosopher, is this apodictic evidence
of the I-am, already becoming apparent in this first grasping. This
bold radicalism, really to overthrow everything—all that was valid
for me and could ever be valid—⟨opened up⟩ for me an apodictically
evident validity, an entity that was not and could not be encapsu-
25 lated in this totality. The ontic universe of the world child is not the
ontic universe as such.
But perhaps things are just such that to surrender everything
means to gain everything, that this radical renunciation of the world
is the necessary path to view the ultimately true reality, and thereby
30 to live an ultimately true life. Perhaps in this unseeming evidence
of the Ego Cogito—and in the mediately grounded evidence of
transcendental intersubjectivity—lies all possible truth and science
in absolute justification and in the sought-for | ultimately suffi- VIII, 166/167
cient philosophical meaning. Perhaps it is true in the most rigorous
35 understanding that self-knowledge, but then only radically pure or
transcendental self-knowledge, is the only source of all ultimately
a in leerer Sachferne
368 part two · section four · chapter three
a Vernunftleben
372 part two · section four · chapter three
so on.All of this could be carried out in the same naiveté, in the same
faith in the evidence of experience and the evidence of the intuition
of possibilities, the evidence of logical inference, and so on, just as in
the objective science, thus without an actual pretense to philosophy.
5 We would then have a rational and an empirical phenomenology
prior to all philosophical interest and prior to any philosophy itself.
How such a phenomenology would look in concrete execution, is
not our business here. But its possibility deserves to be spelled out
before actually executing it.
10 But we shall emphasize clearly and entirely without doubt one
thing, the most basic and most comprehensible: If I, carrying out
the phenomenological reduction, or as we also say, to indicate the
habituality of this reduction, in the phenomenological attitude survey
my transcendental life, then I have, to the extent that this intuitive
15 realization may succeed, a homogeneous continuum of transcen-
dental self-experience: insofar as this unfolding yields concordant
self-intuition. Occasional discontinuities—as when, in the process of
clarification of a transcendental self-recollection, certain disagree-
ments arise—balance themselves out in a similar manner as in my
20 natural-objective recollection. For instance, different recollections
may have merged with one another, overlapped, but in a further
clarifying approximation these overlaps and confusions | will dis- VIII, 172/173
entangle themselves in a concordant intuitive continuity of one
recollection. Nothing is decided, whether this is necessarily the case
25 in apodictic necessity, but, in any case, it belongs to the most familiar
style of recollection. Hence I have de facto a steady transcendental
universe of transcendental experience, just as I have an empirical
universe from natural, objective (external and internal) experience.
I have it as existing for me by virtue of the concordance of transcen-
30 dental experience, which always re-establishes itself, and by virtue
of the experiential belief, which documents itself, as it were, in the
horizon of each present, in this abiding style of concordance that
always re-establishes itself. Just as the real universe of the world is
given as the one infinite nexus of concordant external experience,
35 the irreal subjectivity, the infinite totality of my transcendental life,
is given as a continual unitary nexus of a possible transcendental
experience.
374 part two · section four · chapter three
1 The original passage, which was later crossed out by Husserl, reads: “That none
of this can be the case, however, this will become clear precisely through a deeper
understanding of what is to be achieved through the Epoché. For myself, as I must
confess, the first insight into the phenomenological reduction was a very limited
one, in the sense described above. For years I saw no possibility to craft it into an
intersubjective one. But finally a path opened up, which is of decisive importance for
the enabling of a full transcendental phenomenology and—on a higher level—of a
transcendental philosophy. I shall describe it now briefly.”—Ed.
2 Cf. Husserl’s critical comment; Appendix 10, p. 517—Ed.
376 part two · section four · chapter three
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical remark on the following up to p. 380, l. 19; cf. Appendix 10,
p. 517—Ed.
378 part two · section four · chapter three
1 Cf. Husserl’s critical remark; cf. Appendix 10, pp. 517 f.—Ed.
transcendental-phenomenological reduction 381
How do things stand, now, concerning the alien conscious life and
its expression in alien lived-bodies? To pose the question already
means answering it. The alien lived-bodies are, as things, realities
for me, and are such so long [as they exist], so long as they are
5 indubitable certainties for me, never to be surrendered, the expe-
riential style predelineates the concordant courses [of experience]
and the continual course | of this style. But if this is the case, then the VIII, 180/181
analogy with my lived-body indicates something else yet, namely
alien conscious life, and what is indicated there is now no longer
10 something transcendental-subjective from my own circle of life. I
can now only take into consideration the alien mentality accord-
ing to its transcendental content. The latter is what is indicated in
transcendental purity, and thus I have, together with my universe of
living appearances encompassed in the title Ego Cogito, mediately
15 co-experienced in the indication of empathy a second transcendental
life, and so in general many other [transcendental lives].
The transcendental reduction, accordingly, yields directly my
Ego, mediately this and that alter Ego, and as such, in general, an
open manifold of alien subjects indicated or to be indicated through
20 experienceable lived-bodies. But this indication is itself an expe-
riential certainty and has its peculiar manner of confirming itself
concordantly.
implicit validities. I, hence, inhibit all naiveté of | validity and of all VIII, 182/183
objective being holding valid and establish myself as observer, who
grasps in his own experience how this really comes to pass which is
called: “something is there for me as thing, as a human being, as art
5 and religion, as state and people, and so on; it holds valid for me as
my reality, I am certain of it as existing, I believe in it, I experience
it, I know it, and so forth.” As transcendental observer I have, in
a universal embrace, the concrete, cognizing-living subjectivity, in
which everything that is vague or clear, erroneous or insightful plays
10 itself out, and in which all entities as meant in my meaning and, if I
am lucky, as experienced in my experience, grasped in my grasping,
insightful in my insight, disclosed in my disclosing, are contained.
All appearances of my cognizing life, those of my factical life
running its course and having run its course, but also those to be
15 construed in pure possibility—to be constructed a priori accord-
ing to their general, eidetically necessary and eidetically possible
formations—all of these are now in my realm of investigation.
Herein will lie, as is obvious, the great task of eidetic phenomenology,
to gain clarity as to which types of cognitive occurrences are conceiv-
20 able and under which eidetic laws they stand. It is evident from the
outset that what I call, in the natural attitude, an object simpliciter,
an objective nexus, a state of affairs, and so on, [any object] of which
I can ever know, that is real for me in any way possible, that (I say)
every such objectivity is a unity of identity, intentionally conscious
25 in manifold actual or possible conscious experiences. In all of these
experiences, this objectivity is meant, in all of them it is—regardless
of the very different modes of subjective appearances—meant as its
identical objective meaning and in the mode of certainty of belief.
That what is meant is in all of these modes the same is to say that
30 such manifold conscious experiences with their manifold modi-
fied manners of appearances produce, in synthetic concatenation,
an overarching consciousness of one and the same existing object,
which, however, can only be conscious in different subjective modes.
Of course there are cases, and it is a known type of possible occur-
35 rences |, that such a synthetic consciousness cannot retain its unity VIII, 183/184
of identity, that two different consciousnesses aim, at first, at a unity
of meaning, but that they separate themselves in conflict, and that,
then, in further occurrences to be described in greater detail, not
384 part two · section four · chapter three
a Subjektsein
390 part two · section four · chapter three
originarily constituted for itself, and the entire absolute being is the
being of the universe of transcendental subjects standing in actual
or possible community with one another. Hence, phenomenology
leads to monadology, anticipated by Leibniz in an ingenious aperçu.1
* February 1924.
a Gegenständen b Objekten
a Naturwahrheit
kant’s copernican turn 393
But one can also ask what else one has presupposed, possibly
what one can or must presuppose, for instance the open infinity of
objects of possible experience and experiential confirmation, which
has consequences for the relation of the immanent time of appear-
5 ances and the objective time of objects (that the latter has to be
distinguished from immanent time). Moreover, since every appear-
ance can be repeated many times over and since the time for its
individuation in coexistence does not suffice, a form in which objec-
tive coexistence (of objective concurrence) is ordered ⟨is necessary⟩,
10 which itself has to exhibit itself in the coexistence of appearances
themselves in appearance, just as objective time must exhibit itself
in appearance in the immanent order of appearances. And so on.
Thus, intuited and intuitable open forms for all intuitable objects
must exist, ordered forms in which one can orient oneself, and
15 they must already belong to mere possibility in phantasy (in mere
phantasy-representation of possible transcendent objects), because
they belong, precisely, a priori necessarily to appearances as appear-
ances of transcendent things,a of “objects.”b
Kant’s arguments concerning space and time derive their power
20 from the unexplicated presupposition that sensible appearances are
not only to mean merely immanent data and complexes of sensa-
tion of these appearances, but appearances of things, which appear,
and are supposed to appear, in the impressions “within ourselves,”
that is, as our experiences. In other words, we have external per-
25 ceptions and these are, on the one hand, our own experiences—as
that which is “internally perceivable,” which appears within—on
the other hand these are indeed perceptions of spatiotemporal exis-
tence external to us, and this means: Things present themselves to
us in consciousness, and completely as a matter of course, things
30 with respective spatiotemporal determinations such as spatial form,
temporal form, position in space and time, sensibly qualified as thus
and so, things that are in and of themselves or appear to be, which
appear in experience in all manners as what they are or as what
appears of their being, but which are not themselves experiences,
35 something subjective-psychic.
a Gegenständen b “Objekten”
kant’s copernican turn 395
This calls for reflection and one needs to ask: Which compo-
nents of what appears, and as meant as belonging | to the perceived VII, 211/212
thing, are to be distinguished generally? And if we then distinguish
between the specific qualities, that is, such thingly qualities which
5 present themselves psychically in sensible data of impression, and
spatiotemporal determinations, one needs to make the further dis-
tinction between unique or repeatable determinations. But here we
find the distinction to be restricted to the spatiotemporal ⟨compo-
nents⟩: a) the generalizable duration, form, and so on, as such, b)
10 the individual position in space and time, the principium individ-
uationis. The general spatiotemporal determination individualizes
itself, and through it the sensible qualities.
Accordingly one needs to consider here: What accounts for the
radical difference between spatiotemporal and the specifically qual-
15 itative determinations? Here the titles “space” and “time” make
their appearance, not as qualities but as universal forms into which
the spatiotemporal qualities insert themselves in a certain man-
ner through individuation. Here the peculiarity comes to the fore
in the Kantian arguments: if we let perception vanish somehow
20 in phantasy, if we cross out in thought the perceptual object, then
“general” space remains, of which its form covers a certain spot.
Instead of the thing we have then a piece of empty individual space.
And if we do so accordingly with all things, then empty space as
such remains, the pure and general form of individual space-time-
25 shapes and hence of possible things of perception and of possible
things in general. Every thing carries general space along with it,
of every perceptual thing one can effectuate an infinity in the pro-
cess of possible intuition, every thing is “geometrically” movable,
starting from every thing one can construct an infinite space, and
30 it is the same space which can be generated from any thing, and so
on.
What is the meaning of the necessary intuitability of space?
It is the necessary individual form of possible things as things of
possible perception that are only to be intuited spatiotemporally.
35 If I freely vary any perceptual appearance or a possible appear-
ance (in pure phantasy), then concerning optical, haptic (and so
on) qualities, I arrive at no necessity. At best I notice here the
necessity | of some sensible qualification. Contrary to that I arrive VII, 212/13
396 supplemental texts · 1
a Merkmalserscheinungen
kant’s copernican turn 399
a Getriebe
400 supplemental texts · 1
* Herein lies as an a priori according to which impressional data run their course
in regularity, such that appearances constitute themselves and that appearances
can further sustain themselves in nexuses of harmony. Which regularities? Only the
appearances themselves can exhibit them, by exposing their structure of meaning
and constitution.
402 supplemental texts · 1
especially, not necessary that all subjects be rational, that all have a
lived-body at their disposal which would be sufficiently capable of
cognition and would supply the necessary presuppositions for objec-
tive cognition. There may be bodily and psychophysical “cripples,”
5 as long as there are at least some straight-grown “humans.”
But the being of the world presupposes rational and normal
subjectivity.
To be sure, this is what becomes plain from this entire reflec-
tion. And [the being of the world] presupposes not some random
10 factical rational subjectivity, but one whose sensibility obeys a uni-
versal ruling, whose form and expression can only be conceived as
expressible via the world which constitutes itself as a phenomenon
of cognition.
The question on the part of the human being in the natural atti-
15 tude as to the ground of the factum of this world becomes, in the
transcendental attitude of interiority, the question as to the ground
of the being of these factical subjectivities and of the constitution
of the world which takes place in them, including that of all fac-
tically fulfilled conditions of the possibility of such constitution.
20 What meaning the notion of “ground” at play here can have and
what it possibly is that does not let us rest in peace with this factum,
that is a new question referring to a higher level of transcendental
research.
One question that might arise here is which form such a method,
25 as a manner of grounding necessarily objectively valid judgments
and truths, would have to have. It is clear from the outset that all
concepts of an objective theory have to be purely logical ones, but
ones that, gained in this method, have taken on a real meaning.— | VII, 220/21
The appearances of all subjects, which are and are to be related
30 to one and the same object, and thusly to every object, in a possi-
ble intersubjective exchange, have to be determined in themselves.
Every subject must have access to every as of yet unexperienced
object, through one or many paths of intuition—and not merely in
this empty generality, as if free phantasy could occupy these paths
35 (spatiotemporal paths of somatic function) at random with aestheti-
cal harmoniously connected intuitions; instead the possibility would
have to exist to anticipate the appearances as entirely determinate
ones.
404 supplemental texts · 1
a Dingwelt
406 supplemental texts · 1
course of perceptions, I can also arrange this course with the inten-
tion of getting to know more precisely the objects and the world, of
stepping out further into open space with the intention of learning
more, and into time filled with the unknown or what has perhaps
5 been forgotten.
On the other hand, this continual “getting to know better” of a
world, which is mine, is not yet getting to know an intersubjective
world for all.
There is only one thing possible here: that all sensible determi-
10 nations stand in a lawful nexus with non-sensible determinations,
which are necessarily common to all rational subjects as subjects of
possible perception and experience.
The systems of locationa of space and time are necessarily com-
mon [to all], they must be, as principles of individuation, titles
15 for intersubjective cognizability in order that in general the same
objectivity be cognizable as the same. By the same token, all pri-
mary qualities—duration, spatial form, relative positions in space—
must be cognizable intersubjectively, despite their sensible, also
lived bodily-psychophysically determined manners of givenness.
20 In thought, which is necessary communal, real-mathematical con-
cepts need to correspond to them, as opposed to merely sensible
concepts.
Of course we all share in common the entire material of formal-
logical and formal-ontological concepts, and of course [all of them]
25 in their relation to what is perceptually given, to what is real. But
here we have to consider, in complete generality, the forms of unity
and forms of the unfolding of the manifolds, such as sameness, dif-
ference, identity, connection to a whole, part and part in a whole,
substrate and accident, relation, and so on, which belong to any
30 conceivable intuition (not just external intuition) and to any con-
ceivable originally generating consciousness (as consciousness of
something objective of any form whatsoever); [to these forms also
belong] condition and what is conditioned, |, collective, disjunctive; VII, 223/224
in short, all that belongs, or can belong, to all possible sensible intu-
35 itions in activity and passivity and what is itself not “perception”:
a Stellensysteme
kant’s copernican turn 407
a Vermögensbegriffe b Innerlichkeit
408 supplemental texts · 1
a Gedankenbildung
kant’s copernican turn 409
which | nevertheless is considered, more often than not, deceptive, VII, 225/226
as semblance, as illusion and the like, of a subjective so-called under-
standing, authenticating, judging, scientific reasoning. If we here talk
of objects and relations of semblance, realities, probabilities, then
5 they are objects posited in the subject itself, posited and subjectively
“understood” “truths,” thus themselves belonging to subjectivity.
Also the being-external-to-me of a world is a subjective finding
in me, also space and time of the experienced world are in me as
represented, intuited, considered, thus as such subjective. This is no
10 devaluation, but simply the expression of an undeniable, necessary
state of affairs. And this state of affairs now harbors the problem
of understanding, in one’s own immanent cognizing, which directs
itself to naive cognizing and what is naively cognized as such—[the
problem] of understanding what, so to speak, this looks like what
15 cognizing subjectivity can achieve and does achieve as an authenti-
cation of truth of a world cognized within [this very subjectivity],
and what are the subjective conditions of the possibility for such an
authentication of truth to be possible a priori, that this subjectivity,
thus, cognizes legitimately the being of the world, and precisely this
20 world, from its own autonomy and its self-understanding.
Kant took the step toward the transcendental turn, as we know
from his development, completely originally, realizing within himself
the general developmental tendency of philosophy since Descartes.
In truth, the problem of modernity was posed through the Cartesian
25 discovery of the Ego Cogito, in truth this was already the discovery
of transcendental subjectivity, only it was understood neither by
himself nor by most of his successors. Kant also did not realize that
already Leibniz’ Monadology, in the meaning given to it by its cre-
ator, was a first attempt at a transcendental theory, and he realized
30 even less that Hume, his great antipode in the critique of reason, had
drafted in the great work of his youth a nearly pure transcendental
philosophy, but in the form of an absurd sensualism. Hume’s Treatise
had remained nearly without effect in the eighteenth century and
never came into Kant’s field of vision.
35 Apart from the predecessors in the transcendental attitude,
Kant’s problematic is not only completely original, | but new. Leibniz VII, 226/227
provided a transcendental aperçu and no actual systematic theory
for the clarification of transcendental subjectivity and the world
410 supplemental texts · 1
a Aufbau
⟨I⟩
within myself? I cannot even say: “true is for every human being
what appears to him,” but only “true is for me what appears to me.”
“Everyone”—this is itself my opinion, which does not transcend
me. Thus I end in solipsism, which, as it seems, Gorgias has asserted.
5 There is nothing objective, no objective science. Only my | being VII, 331/332
and that of my opining is given, and even apodictically given, and
nothing else is at all conceivable.
Hence the incomprehensibility of cognition:
1) How is cognition as immanent achievement of the cognizing
10 agent—as an achievement, in which in himself objectivity comes
about as cognitive formation, as subjectively cognized as such—to
be investigated, how is the entire edifice of this achievement to be
elucidated? What is a result [of this achievement] here is a result
from me, in me, and yet is supposed to be objective. This leads to:
15 2) How can we understand that I, the cognizing agent, cognize
myself as objective in my cognizing achievement and as a cognitive
formation, and that I also cognize others and cognize them as cog-
nizing agents, as conscious subjects in general just as myself and as
agents, who communalize themselves with me in successful or erring
20 cognizing, and so on, in short, as co-subjects standing alongside me
in objectivation, indeed, [subjects] on whom I count as critics? How
can we understand that all cognizing and cognition is “in” me and
is also, as cognized being, being-for-myself, and yet that I am not
the only I, but that other I’s have to be cognized by me and have
25 to be acknowledged as coexisting with me and co-responsible for
objective being with me through the communalization of cognition?
And how are we to understand that for me and for the others
that are cognizable for me (and this includes: others that are con-
ceivable for me), co-subjects of the same world—as existing for us
30 all, hence constituted by all of us consciously in a communalization
of cognition—[that these others] have to exist, as human beings
existing in the same world and cognizing, as human beings, the same
world?
In historical motivation, this skeptical questioning comes first
35 and bears within itself implicitly the motivation for the first ques-
tion, namely: How do I understand cognition as achievement within
me, through which I build up the world and in it other human beings
in their significance and ontic validity?
416 supplemental texts · 2
⟨II⟩
⟨III⟩
a Sinngebilde
418 supplemental texts · 2
but Ego. With this Ego, “mine,” of the one who reflects, and not
mine among other human beings, thus in the world, transcendental
subjectivity is discovered, which I can only discover as reflecting
upon myself in the most radical questioning-back of validity—and
5 not, say, another: another [I] is, to be sure, another-for-me.
Here we find the great difficulty of the relation of this Ego of
the transcendental attitude of world-renouncement to the human
I, and here is the first great temptation to later equate the pure
monas with the soul in the world, hence the temptation to iden-
10 tify the transcendence of the external world vis-à-vis my human
subjectivity with the objectivity of the world which authenticates
itself in my realm of consciousness as Ego. Descartes succumbs to
this temptation and hence to the fundamental error of viewing the
conscious world, or the experienced realities, which authenticate
15 themselves inwardly as cogitata, as mere ideae, representations of
the truly objective world, of a world outside, external to the Ego,
and hence of asking realistic questions.
Instead of the countersensical problem of realism the true prob-
lem is to clarify what this anonymous, completely unknown life of
20 consciousness with its manifold cogitata, of the manifold manners
of appearance, and so on, looks like and what sense here the in-
itself, the “for-everyone,” the other take on in their achievement of
consciousness and how, on the path from primordiality to the oth-
ers and from there to the world-in-itself, all confusions concerning
25 objectivity and the in-itself resolve themselves.
3
⟨I⟩
* 1923.
420 supplemental texts · 3
⟨II⟩
* Whether or not the idea of my existence is exhausted herein: in any case, being
and the course of nature stand in a wondrous essential relation to the Ego, and
more precisely to the course of the lived experiences that are possible for me in the
a difficult point in the critique of descartes 423
does not see that | the non-existence expresses, in terms of meaning, VII, 337/338
a correlative style of disharmony in the universe of my possible cog-
itationes. He is the arch father of psychologism which permeates the
entire modern transcendental philosophy and which it could never,
5 in principle, overcome; he is in this function already through the
fateful turn from the Ego to the mens, which, in conjunction with the
absurd metaphysical dualism, firstly enabled Locke’s epistemology.
On the other hand, he is also the father of all genuine transcen-
dental philosophy, insofar as from that point on the demand of
10 relating back to cognizing subjectivity all objectivity and all science
determining it in the logical forms of theory was felt as a necessity
and had to be felt as such, just as much as all attempts to fulfill this
science in scientifically compelling clarity and non-contradiction
failed. In this regard, the Cartesian achievements are highly signifi-
15 cant and certainly never to be lost.
⟨III⟩
Yet, regardless how badly things may stand with respect to the
rigor of the Cartesian analyses, indeed already [stand badly] con-
cerning the methodological clarity about the general level that it
20 needs to uphold in order to attain a goal: an ingenious instinct gov-
erns the general train of thoughts, so much so, that they terminate,
in fact, in a great discovery, which is at the same time the discov-
ery of the beginning. The latter already achieves the next step of
the argument, or rather, this discovery leads us in our consistent
25 transformation of the Cartesian thoughts to general necessities.
This step to the at first so innocuous Ego Cogito lies in the sim-
ple demonstration that this proven possibility of the non-being of
the objective world (of the universe in the encompassing sense),
way that every change in nature would have to necessarily condition changes for
my consciousness. On the other hand, it remains the case that the non-existence of
the world does not disrupt my existence and that the I-am has an evidence that is
independent of [the world’s] existence or non-existence. Since also the non-being of
the world meant in experience, no less than its being, prescribes a law to my Ego, it
is immediately clear that one cannot talk of causality here. How is that which does
not exist to practice causality?
424 supplemental texts · 3
within itself. The basic idea here is that first “sensible” experience—
namely, spatio-thingly experience—is in principle “inadequate,” its
certainty is a priori presumptive and remains so in all progressive
confirmation, never guaranteeing apodictically the being of what is
5 experienced. Thus firstly, the universal physical nature is possibly-
non-existing, regardless of its being experienced harmoniously. But
with the possibility of the hypothesis of the non-existence of nature
also the hypothesis ⟨of the non-existence⟩ of the universe of all
objects becomes possible, which also derive their creditworthinessa
10 from sensible (“natural”) experience, objects, hence, which are also
experienced in an experience, which is founded in natural experi-
ence. This, however, concerns all experiences of human beings and
animals and of all of their psychic life, which is in any way sensibly
mediated (through so-called empathy, through “expressions” on the
15 part of lived-bodies). And in this manner I, thus, strike out, with
the possible assumption of the non-existence of nature, the entire
world, as it were, for myself; and if now a sphere of being nonethe-
less remains, then it is not a last tag-end and little piece of the world,
since, indeed, no piece of the world can be separated off from it
20 and could be made independent of the rest of the world in any
meaningful way. It is also not something concretely real outside of
the world, since, as can easily be seen, all internality and externality
of concrete realities only make sense within the unity of the world.
Now one may object: But whether I say Ego Cogito or “I am,” | VII, 339/340
25 whether I say it simpliciter or with the fictitious hypothesis of the
non-existence of the world—is it not still I, am I not still this human
being, who moves experientially in space, touches with his hands,
looks around with his eyes, and so forth? Of course it is I; but what
makes me a human being, hence a member of the world, and indeed
30 with the meaning that I associate with the word “human being,” this
by no means belongs into the realm of the apodictic evidence, which
determines the “Ego” and encapsulates it apodictically within itself:
Just as, in each individual case in order to gain this my Ego, for
instance in the seeing of a house, I need to satisfy the methodologi-
35 cal demand of excluding the existence of the experienced world on
the objective side, thus, put out of play the existence of this house,
a Kredit
426 supplemental texts · 3
derives its sensible root from bodily experience. The soul is a soul
of the lived-body, empirically bound to the latter, indicating and
expressing itself in it according to rules.
Descartes, however, who, in the hastiness of his reflections, does
5 not make the method clear to himself, a method which was newly
predelineated to him with the attainment of transcendental sub-
jectivity, seeks to transform, due to the causal interpretation of
external experience, the instinctive causal inference to the transcen-
dent into an exact one, and the blind instinctive inference into a
10 scientifically certain one; furthermore [he seeks to show] that the
true essence of transcendent nature can only disclose itself in the
form of mathematical natural science and that all true being of the
entire world of experience can only determine itself in the sense of
a two-substance-doctrine. As is known, his path led via a theological
15 theory of evidence. The full, absolute reality, which can be cognized
by the Ego, wound up as God and the God-created world of bod-
ies and souls; thereby, now, the world could also find a teleological
explanation, above and beyond the exact research, achieved by the
exact sciences, into its own essential qualities.
20 This philosophy was, as every philosophy of a similar method-
ological type, afflicted with the absurdity that it purported to be
philosophy, universal science from absolute justification, but pur-
sued paths, whose ideas were not derived from absolute justification,
indeed which would have been found to be absurd in such a justifi-
25 cation.
The Ego Cogito in its transcendental purification is the neces-
sary beginning for every philosophizing person; but it is only the
beginning—the beginning of a philosophy beginning to constitute
itself—if one sees that with this title an endless field of labor is
30 opened up for concrete research, which is not only itself absolutely
justified, but to which all other sciences that are philosophical in the
radical sense are related back according to the possibility of their
cognition. This, now, is to be truly attested to in the continuation
of our meditations,1 it is to be seized and to be determining for the
35 grounding of a science of transcendental subjectivity, which is to
* With regard to the sensible “ideas,” already Berkeley had denied, in his ingenious
originality, the meaningful possibility of an inference to respective material sub-
stances, to transcendent objects, but without success, since he held on to the principle
of causal inference to something transcendent (God as transcendent cause).
430 supplemental texts · 3
All philosophers taking their cue from Leibniz are afflicted with
5 the absurdity of dogmatism in philosophy and theory of knowledge,
thus also the Kantian critique of reason. That it avoids natural-
ism, psychologism, historicism in the ordinary sense—that is, in the
ordinary sense of an explicit grounding of epistemology on natural
science, on psychology (the empirical science of animalic psychic
10 life as facticity in the nexus of psychophysical nature) or even on
history—is only to say that it avoids one of the very widespread
forms of absurdity. But it is not so certain that it, for that reason,
really escapes the specific charge of psychologism. At the least one
may be permitted to raise the question whence Kant derives all
15 the knowledge as to the psychic capabilities which he presupposes
from the very beginning in his critique of reason, while he at the
same time does not present them as essential necessities and indeed
cannot present them as such, since he only acknowledges one type
of essential necessities, the analytical ones. Even if they should be
20 derived from pure consciousness, the great claim to rigorous science
could not be made so long as the meaning and the legitimacy of such
assertions, and in general all assertions in the immanent sphere, had
not been subjected to a scientific investigation. A transcendental
epistemology can only be carried out in the framework of a universal
25 epistemology, and the latter only as a science of pure consciousness.
But regardless: everywhere in Kant’s critique of reason lies, at its
foundation, a dogmatic objectivism that operates with transcendent
metaphysical suppositions.
When Kant presupposes the plurality of subjects and attributes
30 general properties to them, these presupposed cognitions stem obvi-
* 1924.
432 supplemental texts · 4
* The regressive method ⟨takes its point of departure⟩ from the factum of objec-
tive science and correlatively from the idea of an objectivity (one which exists “in
itself” vis-à-vis everyone’s cognition), which determines itself (as an endless task) as
identical in progressive approximation for each cognizing agent.
1 In the following passages, Husserl alternates between Tatsache (fact) and Fak-
tum (factum), the latter of which was a central term of Marburg Neo-Kantianism.
Hermann Cohen famously maintained that the regressive transcendental method
needs to start out with the “factum of the sciences” (das Faktum der Wissenschaften).
In the translation, “Faktum” is rendered as factum, “Tatsache” as fact.—Trans.
a critique of the regressive method 433
Hence, this [critique] goes even further than the reproach that
Dilthey has rightfully brought forth against him, that his critique of
reason does not attempt a critique of historical reason, no critique
of cognition whatsoever in the human sciences and has not even
5 seen it in its necessity. In the meaning of philosophy lies not only a
universality in the transcendental investigation of all possible tran-
scendental problems of cognition, that is, according to all possible
transcendent scientific problems, but a radicalism, which, in going
back from such cognition to a cognizing of this cognition in the
10 sphere of immanence, goes back even one further step and must
make this cognizing itself a theme, this cognizing-as-epistemologist,
and thus must make, in general, the cognizing of pure conscious-
ness and of the conscious I into a theme. An absolute science of
pure consciousness, which encapsulates in itself thematically all
15 iterations, in which consciousness elevates itself in reflection to a
consciousness of a higher level and hence generates a reflective
intentionality, enacts itself in cognitions; cognitions, which itself are
of the type of consciousness of the higher level, and this, too, belongs
to the encompassing problem of cognition. Just as the type of itera-
20 tion, in which mathematical operations and concept-formations can
effect themselves in infinitum, does not limit mathematical cogni-
tion, but instead implies insights which reach beyond all iteration
and its infinity; in the same manner must it be possible to control
the iterations of consciousness and gain insights which govern the
25 principles of all immanent cognition and its possible reflective lev-
els. Epistemology is necessarily related back upon itself, and the
seeming circularity of this being-related-back must come to a reso-
lution through insights into laws, from whence it becomes entirely
comprehensible, from whence arises precisely the insight, that all
30 iterations in consciousness obey them.
In [Kant’s] aftermath, attempts to move these problems forward
in the direction of a radical philosophy are not lacking, especially
attempts at a critical transformation of the Kantian philosophy and
in the direction of its radicalization. Maimon, Reinhold and Fichte,
35 as is known, are to be mentioned here; but what is also known is
their hastiness and their reverting back to immanent mythologies
or violent constructions of immanent teleologies, from which no
positive gain could be made.
a critique of the regressive method 441
11924. As the editor remarks, this text was written in close connection with lecture
thirty (above, pp. 221–230). The beginning of the present text, until p. 441, l. 4, which
partly overlaps with the lecture (cf. above, p. 227, l. 1–p. 229, l. 16), seems to have
been a summary of Landgrebe’s in his typescript and replaces the following text
in Husserl’s original manuscript—Trans.: “The introductory remark, which I had
completed recently, would have required an expansion. If my remark connected
philosophy as a universal science to all types of reason, thus also to all norms of a
possible active life, then the idea is at hand that the idea of philosophy as science—
absolute and universal science—is the function of a philosophy in the broader sense:
that of a human life which absolutely justifies itself; it would be necessary, accordingly,
to sketch this idea and to unfold it and to show that the all-sided scientific unfolding
of this idea as a practical purposive idea necessarily belongs to the possibility of a
community that is rational in the highest sense and that philosophy, in the fullest
consequence of the scientific unfolding of this idea, lies in the traditional sense of
absolute universal science itself. Philosophy as science is not one of humanity’s
theoretical dalliances [Liebhaberei], but a necessary element and a means of its path
towards freedom of reason. This path must, however—if a true rational humanity is
to be possible—have the shape of a becoming that determines itself freely and as
such precisely that of a science from absolute freedom.”
meditation on the idea of an individual life 443
can, for instance, pass over from an act of purely valuing pleasedness
into a judging attitude, in which I predicate what is “pleasing” in the
object, a predicate which is pre-predicative and which has its origin
in the hearta prior to being grasped in an experience; likewise other
5 predicates, such as those | of good and evil, of the beneficial and VIII, 193/194
the purposive or harmful, have their origin in the willing connected
to the valuing heart. Things are the same when we look around
the different realms of culture; culture encompasses formations of
praxis, which are, as such, apprehended in comprehension through
10 a empathic understandingb of the respective acts of the heart and
the will. And what has been grasped thusly can become the object
of an experiential grasping and predicative determination and even
of a scientific problematic.
In this manner, the universality comes clearly to the fore, by
15 means of which the realm of cognition encompasses all types of
achievements stemming from the subjectivity of the heart and the
will, and to be sure, correlatively, a similar encompassment through
which the valuing heart and the will in striving and acting reach
across the entire subjectivity and all of its intentional functions. This
20 means for science, however, that in it, as the objectivation of cogniz-
ing reason, also all valuing and practical reason mirrors itself and
also objectivates itself; or that in the cognitive formations of theoret-
ical truth all other truth, hence every truth with respect to values and
praxis, expresses itself in predicative forms, determines itself and
25 also takes on cognitive forms of reasoning. It is the heart that values
purely within itself, and it is the active will that forms, purely within
itself or as itself, the beautiful work. The truth, the unity of the value
and then of the work express1 themselves originally naively again in
the heart, in pure satisfaction. But ultimately the genuineness of this
30 truth of valuing takes responsibility in cognizing, which predicates
in the judging attitude and its logical forms concerning value and
non-value and which relates the contingently experienced value-
intuition comprehensively back to generally intuited value norms
and gains thereby a higher responsibility, as responsibility of cogni-
a Gemüt b Nachverstehen.
5 ⟨I⟩
20 ⟨II⟩
a Werkgebilde
454 supplemental texts · 6
But what about cases where the action is from the beginning
aimed at “spiritual” goals? Such goals will have their objective (and
thereby intersubjectively graspable) character in the style of the
achievements of objective culture. But they are to be regarded con-
5 cerning their ideal meaning and being, purely in their external shape,
and ⟨are⟩ in this ideality “the same,” regardless of how they have
taken on a sensibly objectified externality or whether they have
taken on such a shape at all. The artwork could—this is certainly
only one, but at any rate also a practical, possibility—be fully formed
10 by the artist purely internally, without having taken on “reality” in
external form at the same time, without having “really” been carried
out externally. But already this manner of speaking indicates that
it belongs to the normal meaning of such a spiritual work from
the very beginning to be sensibly-objectively shaped, thus it also
15 belongs to what one aims at from the very start in effecting action—
it is to be, as artwork, an object in the world, and not merely a
subjectively construed one, a mere thought of a work, hence at best
an archetype, a plan for the work—while indeed an intent would
be possible, in which one would have aimed exclusively at the pure
20 inner forming of the meaningful image for itself, precisely the one
which makes up the spiritual meaning of the sensibly embodied
work.
What, now, about the distinction between reflective doing, inner
planning and plotting, and external realization in the sphere of
25 spiritual works?
Here we would have to say at the outset: In a certain sense every
work and the corresponding action are something spiritual—only
through their spiritual meaning or their significance [are they] action
and work, and hence what is conceived in inner reflection enters,
30 in the external execution, into the latter and | its action (more pre- VIII, 206/207
cisely: the practical preconception, the sketch, comes to be, in this
synthesis, a fulfilling, realizing identification with the external action
and the work). But in the case of spiritual works in the specific
sense, the sensible externality does not belong, in its individuality, to
35 the work—as a spiritual work, as this unique artwork. The unique-
ness is not, as in the case of a hammer, at the same time that of
the physical-thingly being. A literary work, a symphony, and upon
closer inspection also a portrait do not have their identity rooted in
reflection as activity 455
note, in this passage, how Husserl uses the term Selbst- in different combinations,
e.g., Selbstwert (worth in itself), Selbstverantwortung (self-responsibility).—Trans.
456 supplemental texts · 6
* This is not the case when I, as is usual, want to create an objective work.
† Indeed, it always is supposed to become it, this is its destiny.
reflection as activity 457
they only are, in general, values in this infinite nexus; hence at all
times relative. The work of every science is something infinite, and
all these infinities belong to an all-encompassing science, universal
science.
5 In science, as in every spiritual achievement aimed at something
ideally valuable in itself, the reflection beginning with a relatively
unclear, vague and distant idea and further via goals and paths leads
to what is intended in the mode “it itself.” The clarification, the
purely spiritual phantasy formation in the sense of the fulfillment
10 of the aiming intention creates, in a temporal order, value products,
and that is, as intermediary products, belonging to the ultimately
intended value, be it as a preliminary stage (a draft), which is already
of the type of value of the goal, be it as a piece of the final work, as
building it itself up. In science, the expository and clarifying activity
15 leads to ever new spiritual end formations, for instance, in the deduc-
tive science to axioms, conclusions (the nexus of analytic premise
and conclusion), proofs. But each of these ends is only a relative end,
just as its value is only a relative value, which enters, in progression,
into the higher value, is included in it, sublated in it, and is not lost,
20 but yet remains merely a relative value. The creative activity fulfills
itself—and in this fulfillment it necessarily aims further, through its
goal and beyond, into infinity. The creative deed of the individual
researcher never fulfills itself in something singular and only has
meaning in that the individual knows himself as a functionary and
25 as a member of a generation of researchers reproducing itself into
infinity, whose correlate—as infinite theory—is science.
If, in order to enable science as such, | a general reflection VIII, 209/210
is required (as becomes clear), what science “as such” actually
demands as a formal-general idea, then the internal work of this
30 reflection is the construction—in making explicit and fulfilling
clarification—of the formal-general idea of “science” in general
and from there necessarily of the idea of a universal science as
such—and also this result itself belongs, as a basic element, to the
science which is to be carried out. Here we have the peculiarity that
35 in a certain sense this idea of a possible universal science, of a phi-
losophy as such as the preliminary sketch of this philosophy itself to
be carried out comes into relief—as a preliminary sketch regarding
the universal form according to which such a universal science is
458 supplemental texts · 6
to be carried out; but [it is also peculiar] that, on the other hand,
this spiritual sketch itself belongs to the system and to the universal
theory of philosophy itself. Matters are similar to making drafts of a
map in geography, where the first geographical achievement strives
5 to be a formal grid for the special work that is to ensue, the form
to be filled out subsequently, which is, however, already part of this
science itself.
Once this empty idea of a universal science comes into view
or once the question as to its possibility and the manner of its
10 realization is raised, then what is required is a universal reflection
concerning the goal and the paths to be pursued, a reflection, which
does not aim to be, and in a certain also is not, the executing activity
itself. For rational reflection, which is not straightforward critique of
someone who is finished [with this reflection], but merely a reflec-
15 tion as to how one could have acted and how goals and paths would
have had to be construed, allows for norms of “reason” to be expli-
cated, norms, which, depending on the goals in question, can be
more general or more concrete, as the case may be. Here, norms are
practical truths—true goals, true paths. Accordingly, one will also
20 have to distinguish a general reflection upon the “possibility” of this
universal science, that is, upon the general form of its truth, upon
the general essential conditions of its genuineness, from the science
itself following these norms.
But here one will have to emphasize that this distinction only has
25 the meaning of a distinction between first science, which explicates
the norms in reflection, in | which the idea that has become distinct VIII, 210/211
and clear lays itself out in its essential parts, and the ensuing order
of sciences which stand under these norms and which have become
formed according to this order. Insofar as both are inseparable, the
30 work of reflection is not to be viewed as something prior to the
universal science, as something external to it, but as its beginning
and grounding element.
Thus it becomes clear from the outset that a universal science
must have as its necessary beginning a reflection, whose goal is the
35 doctrine of the norms for such a science, hence this doctrine is itself
a science of its possible truth and genuineness according to its basic
essential conditions.
7
Scientific Propositions.
10 We understand, as mathematicians, the method of geometrical
assertions, we have evidence, and when we hear something geo-
metrical, we place ourselves in the geometrical attitude required,
enact the respective normal motivations that are presupposed for
the evidence. How is it possible that the application of geometry
15 to physics has its difficulties? That one can argue whether physical
1 1923.
The path into transcendental phenomenology as absolute ontology, which over-
comes all relativities by starting out from positive ontologies and the universal
positive ontology (path of the lecture course of 1919/20).*
First question: How can one ground an ontology in positivity? All onta—all real
ones in the real world—are relative upon one another. There are ontologies under
the nexus of a universal ontology—as a universal a priori science of the world, of a
world as such.
The second item: An entity is an entity of cognition, all entities for us are some-
thing appearing, meant, authenticating themselves (and so on) in subjective modes:
relativity upon cognizing subjectivity.
Only a transcendental universal science discloses and makes thematic all rela-
tivities and [only in this all-science] an ontology as absolute ontology is possible,
encompassing the relative ontologies of the world.
Basic idea of these meditations: the guiding clue of my Freiburg investigations
and lectures.
* Husserl gave a lecture course in the winter semester of 1919/20, Einleitung in
die Philosophie [Introduction to Philosophy], which is now published in Hua.-Mat
IX.—Trans.
460 supplemental texts · 7
space is the same as the geometrical (the | Euclidean), whether the VIII, 219/220
geometrical space is not a mere limit case, in relation to which phys-
ical space presents a mere approximation, but not in the sense in
which one construed geometrical purity as a limit case of empirical
5 formations and positions [in space]? What would be the question
in this case? Investigation into the geometrical “idealizing intu-
ition,” investigation into the possibilities obtaining here. If there
are different ones, they would have to express themselves in dif-
ferent axioms. The evidence of Euclidean axioms (or the complete
10 and concrete system of Euclidean-geometrical axioms) would then
be evidence for one of the possibilities. It could not exclude other
possibilities that were only incompossible as holding valid together
with the former, but on the other hand compossible in the sense
of typical possibilities within the genus (represented through an
15 absolutely necessary group of axioms). Here the question becomes,
which essential character space as such must have, as the form of
every possible intuitable nature (transcendental-aesthetically), which
is to exist in itself and is to confirm its identity; one asks whether
the “exact” characteristics of space, which the possibility of a pure
20 persistence of identity prescribes, encompass something general,
which can yet differentiate itself, in order for different types of
spaces to result within the pure and exact idea “space as such”
and “geometry as such.” But nature as such leads us, as a corre-
late, to perception and to the lived-body of perception as such;
25 nature and subjectivity is “intuitively” inseparable. Can we stop here
transcendental-aesthetically? Geometrical evidence is a branch of
evidence in the ontology of nature, we are related to possible nature
as such.
Everything in external perception is given—and can only be
30 given, essentially—in a relativism. Evidently given (namely, per-
ceived) are appearances, sensible things, in strata; visible thing,
tactual thing and so on. ⟨They are given⟩ in relation to the lived-body
of the experiencing agent, and this relation is part of the constitu-
tive meaning of the appearing objectivities, not of the meaning of
35 nature, but part of the fully constituted meaning of the world (of the
total constitutive meaning encapsulated in complete constitution).
⟨They | are objectivities⟩, which are only experiencable insofar as the VIII, 220/221
lived-body, as co-functioning, is co-present in the field of intuition;
path into transcendental phenomenology 461
objective region, can be derived. For the object of nature this means:
we must derive from perception the concrete and full system of per-
ception, a system in which would lie the “fully” perceived thing, that
is, according to all essential directions, which belong inseparably to
5 the perceived as such.
Although thing is a region of its own, it is thereby not a com-
plete and independent one. The physical thing is no “substance,”
and likewise, physical nature is no concrete unity in the ultimate
sense. I must continue on. Next I must take the correlation of
10 nature and functioning subjectivity, I must consider nature and
lived-bodiliness, lived-bodiliness and psychic spirituality—all in
relation to one another; these relations are, precisely as essentially
correlative, co-determining of meaning. The universe of intuition,
as possible perception, must be viewed in totality and fixated in its
15 essential typicality, if I want to make completely comprehensible
the origin of all worldly truth, and at first truth of nature, or better:
the complete and genuine meaning, which tolerates no empty, yet
indeterminate or even unnoticed horizons.
Only from these primal sources* can I derive adequate con-
20 cepts and the respective axiomatic systems, which are necessary to
form the foundational concept of the a priori ontology. Of course
it becomes clear here that the a priori ontologies themselves | are VIII, 223/224
essentially related upon one another and are not mutually indepen-
dent, separable from each other. They all are one-sidednesses of
25 the a priori. It becomes clear that, the moment we strive for com-
plete evidence and firstly that completeness of possible experience
and possible eidetic intuition, which takes into consideration all
essential necessities that also concern any experienced object or
essence in focus, that we arrive at the universe of all intuitabilities as
30 such—and thereby at the universe of subjectivity as constituting. At
first we may begin to describe appearing objects as such and then
make explicit their essential properties and we may know nothing
of phenomenology—nothing of transcendental subjectivity and its
constitutive functions. But pursuing the essential dependencies, we
* Primal sources: Pure and rigorous scientific cognition presupposes the construc-
tion of a complete possible experience—complete in the sense that it gives voice to
all horizons.
464 supplemental texts · 7
* The only thing missing here is the discussion of the difference between the rel-
ative natural a priori, which is always “relative,” and of the formal, “absolute” a
priori. ⟨In other words⟩, what is missing to complete this felicitous exposition is the
following fundamental discussion:
The starting point was the ontology of nature, natural mathematics, connected
to the essential relativity of the object of experience (of the object of perception), in
relation to normal lived-bodiliness and normal subjectivity as such. This relativism
must become completely clear in all directions and must be mastered conceptually;
the ontological a priori has, then, its levels and correlations that must be scientifically
fixated in all directions.
On the other hand, we do have an empty formal a priori, formal objectivities and
higher-level theoretical formations. These, too, are correlates, namely to transcenden-
tal constituting subjectivity. But here matters are indeed different than concerning a
geometrical, a natural-ontological (and so on) a priori; what is missing here, on the
ontological side, are the peculiarities and correlations that co-determine meaning,
what remains is only the general constitutive correlation. Hence, in a certain sense
an arithmetical proposition is an apodictically valid and irrelative truth-in-itself.
Hence this must be clarified in all directions and only then are the most general
considerations given above purely grounded.
(But this is taken into consideration in my lectures on the theory of science—
as immature as they may have been at the time—and in the Introduction lecture of
1919/1920 [cf. footnote 1, p. 459, above] through the fact that I presented the analytic
first and later clarified its empty-formal meaning together with the idea of a formal
science of mere consequence of judgment.)
path into transcendental phenomenology 465
1 On the lecture of 1919/20 cf. footnote 1, p. 459. In the winter semester 1910/11
Husserl held a lecture course on Logic as Theory of Cognition, now published in Hua.
XXX. Husserl published a fragment of this lecture course in Formal and Transcen-
dental Logic, appendix I, Hua. XVII, pp. 299–313, “Syntactical Forms and Syntactic
Matter, Essential Forms and Essential Matter.”—Ed. & Trans.
2 The London Lectures of 1922 and the “broader execution” in the 1922/23 lecture
course Einleitung in die Philosophie are now published in Hua. XXXV. With “my
phenomenological lecture courses” Husserl presumably means his lecture courses in
general.—Trans.
466 supplemental texts · 7
* Accordingly one must not say: No ontology of nature may actually be constructed
straightforwardly and self-obliviously, and only in the case of geometry it is seem-
ingly different. It is simply an old tradition. Also the researcher of nature (Galilei)
who aims at a principal grounding had to make the subjective thematic and had to
path into transcendental phenomenology 467
What I have then is a cognition of being, which can only posit itself
as absolute through such a self-oblivion, and a nature, which is
only seemingly independent (a substance), but is, in truth, bound to
essential correlations.
5 Why can a dogmatic science not justify itself absolutely, expose
its foundations absolutely, arrive at complete evidence?
I have full evidence of essences when I reign over a totality of
essential possibilities and essential necessities, when I modify the
possibilities in all directions, which allow for a modification, and
10 hence gain every essence in the totality of its essential correlates
and understand it.
And from here one must show that only a transcendental sci-
ence, which encompasses all possible objectivities in the universe
of all possibilities, encompasses them precisely in [the universe of]
15 transcendental subjectivity, and that [this science] thereby yields
“substantial” cognition [and] can gain full insight and ultimate truths
or can proceed forward in its investigation under the idea of finality
and become systematic philosophy. | VIII, 227/228
All truth is relative: Ultimate science overcomes this relativism
20 by showing the path and pursues it; a path, which secures for us the
reign over all relativities and all essential correlations. If this is to
be realized, it must be possible to construct a priori systematically
the essence of transcendental subjectivity in a system.
justification. This holds especially for all sciences of the world, but
also for metaphysics related back to it, and on the other hand for
the normative sciences.
I later put it as following:
5 a) What is required is the phenomenological reduction, as a reduc-
tion to actual and possible transcendental subjectivity or to its actual
and possible transcendental experience.
b) This calls for an apodictic critique of transcendental experience,
but also a critique of “logical” cognition which may be established
10 on this transcendental ground of experience as “phenomenology.”
Hence what is required is a phenomenology and a critique of its
cognition. What is shown here is that this apodictic critique of phe-
nomenological cognition is related back to itself, iteratively. This,
thus, is what genuine First Philosophy is about (i.e., at first “naive”
15 phenomenology and [then] apodictic critique, as the most radical
critique of cognition, related to [the former]).
2.) The second path I conceived as taking its point of depar-
ture from the contrast of the mythical-practical worldview and the
worldview of theoretical interest. In the latter respect lies the actual
20 beginning: the establishment of purely theoretical experience and
cognition, of the “sober” worldview, from which arises autonomous
culture, communal life and communal accomplishments in sober
“reason”—and under the guidance of doxic reason. I then wanted
to view the world of “purely theoretical” experience. It gives itself
25 as existing, as continually abiding as identical and harmonious in
the stream of experience. I want to come clear on what belongs
to the world of experience |, when I conceive of experience in all VIII, 252/253
earnestness in the pure identity of the experiencing agent, hence as
continuing to exist in pure harmony. I reflect, thus, upon experience
30 and the world of experience and pursue the universal structures
that this pure world of experience exhibits and then—in an eidetic
modification in free variation—which it must exhibit as a necessary
system of invariants.
This is to yield the systematic distribution of the possible sciences
35 of the world. What about the logic of my procedure of thought in
these investigations?
In exhibiting the structure of nature I happen upon the fact
that nature is at first given in subjective givennesses. I want to
470 supplemental texts · 8
1 The text from here to “critique of their applicability.” (p. 476, l. 23 below) is
absent in the Husserliana edition of 1959, because the editor was not able to locate
the missing pages at the time (cf. Hua. VIII, p. 538, where Boehm speculates that
the missing pages were “probably destroyed”). These pages have since been found
(signature A III 4/92–94) and the editorial omission is rectified in the translation.
However, it is an Archive policy that texts from Husserl’s unpublished writings may
not be published in translation prior to the original German. Hence, in the following
the original of the missing passage—Trans.
“Wenn ich so vorgehe, dann ist die erste Wissenschaft, die ich gewinne, die ana-
lytische Logik und Mathematik. Sie nimmt eine normative praktische Wendung
an. Es kann wohl schon das Verhältnis von theoretisch sachlichem Interesse und
Interesse an Sollensbestimmungen erörtert werden.
Die erste Wissenschaft ist ‘Wissenschaftslehre’, aber formale, Wissenschaft von
der Form möglicher Wissenschaft.
Warum doch keine erste Philosophie erwächst, das weiß man auf diesem Wege
noch nicht. Allerdings wenn man in der Naivität die universale Weltwissenschaft
als Philosophie definiert, so ist das erste Philosophie. Aber erst später kann man
sehen, dass die Forderung letzter Begründung und letzter Selbstverständigung durch
eine solche Weltwissenschaft nicht erfüllt werden kann und dass diese Forderung
nicht etwa eine Pedanterie ist, sondern die notwendigste aller Forderungen der
theoretischen Autonomie.
So hätten wir also als I. Teil: natürliche Logik oder: die ersten logischen Besin-
nungen und der Weg zu einer natürlichen Logik. Wann hat diese Logik keine Sorge
vor ‘Paradoxien’? Als bloße Konsequenzlogik gefasst, muss sie alle ihre Begriffe
aus der Evidenz der Deutlichkeit schöpfen. Wenn sie also Unendlichkeitsbegriffe
einführt, so muss dafür Sorge getragen sein.
Die historische Arithmetik und Algebra ist als Größenlehre erwachsen in Ver-
schmelzung mit Geometrie, zunächst von ihr nicht getrennt. Es kommt aber sehr
viel darauf an, dass die formale mathesis in ihrem echten Sinn erkannt und danach
in reiner Methode in der ihr spezifisch zugehörigen Evidenz der Deutlichkeit aus-
gebildet wird (anschauungsfreie Analysis, Arithmetik). Jeder Begriff muss seine
exemplarische Klarheit haben; auch der Begriff der Deutlichkeit, die ja hinsichtlich
ihrer Gegenstände auch eine Klarheit ist. Klarheit des bloßen Satzes als Satzes
ist nicht Klarheit der ihm zugehörigen Wahrheit. Nur ist das Beirrende, dass die
Rede, ‘ein Satz sei klar’ (ist mir klar, ist jedem klar), immer besagt, dass er auf
entsprechende bewahrheitende Anschauung zurückgeführt oder zurückzuführen
sei, in der die Wahrheit, die den Satz als Bedeutungsstruktur enthält, sichtlich ist,
und der Satz in seiner Adäquation, in der Anpassung an die Wahrheit, an die ‘Sache
selbst’. Wie mir scheint, stammen alle Paradoxien daher, dass die Begründung der
attempt at a distinction of the stages 473
a “Wissenschaftslehre”
It is still unknown why there still does not arise a first philos-
ophy on this path. Yet, if one defines, in naiveté, universal science
as philosophy, then this is first philosophy. But only later one is
able to see that the demand of ultimate grounding and ultimate
5 self-comprehension cannot be fulfilled through such a science of
the world and that this demand is not some pedantry, but the most
necessary of all demands issuing from theoretical autonomy.
Thus we would have as the first part: natural logic, or: the first
logical reflections and the path towards a natural logic. How long
10 does this logic not worry about “paradoxes”? Conceived as mere
logic of consequence, it must derive all concepts from the evidence
of clarity. Once it, thus, introduces infinite concepts, it must deal
with them at that time.
Historical arithmetic and algebra has arisen as doctrine of mag-
15 nitudes in combination with geometry, at first not separated from
one another. But much depends on understanding formal math-
esis in its genuine sense and [how it] then becomes carried out
in pure method in the evidence of clarity belonging specifically
to it (non-intuitive analysis, arithmetic). Every concept must have
20 its exemplary clarity; the same goes for concepts of distinctness,
which is, regarding its objects, a clarity as well. Clarity of the mere
proposition as proposition is not clarity of the truth corresponding
to it. But it is misleading that the phrase “a proposition is clear”
(it is clear to me, is clear to everyone) always means that it leads
25 back, or is to be led back, to a corresponding verifying intuition,
in which the truth, which contains the proposition as a meaning-
structure, is evident, and the proposition in its adequation, in fitting
with the truth, to the “matter itself.” It seems to me that all para-
doxes stem from the fact that the grounding of mathematics is not
2) Nachdem eine höhere Stufe erklommen ist, spaltet sich der Begriff der Philoso-
phie, der philosophischen Begründung und Klärung und damit der Begriff des
Dogmatischen. Es bedarf, so heißt es dann, einer Mathematik (und einer Wissenschaft
überhaupt), die sich vorerst des absoluten Bodens versichert hat, auf dem alle Theo-
rie und sonstige Leistung erwächst—des transzendentalen Bodens. Nun heißt die
transzendental fundierte Mathematik allein die philosophische. Ist die philosophis-
che der vorigen Stufe reinlich ausgeführt, so bleibt sie zwar nach dem Gesamtbestand
ihre Sätze bestehen, aber durch Rückbeziehung auf den transzendentalen Boden
und die transzendental konstitutive Erkenntnis haben diese Sätze ihren letzten Sinn
und die letzte Kritik ihrer Anwendbarkeit gewonnen.”
attempt at a distinction of the stages 475
carried out from the very beginning in the necessary principal clar-
ity. This requires a reflection upon the truly radical beginnings and
in each new accomplishment [it requires] a new reflection, to what
extent a self-givenness truly becomes established, to what extent
5 the attained is actually attained, to what extent the path [traveled
to attain this truth] truly is a path. No tradition! No pregivennesses,
only what one ⟨has⟩ given to oneself, what one has not posited arbi-
trarily, but only what one actually finds in one’s own creation as
evident creation.
10 In actually carrying this out what is demanded is a constant
reflection from what is seemingly given as objective (substrate, mat-
ter of fact, and so on) back to the subjective [element] of achieving
action, a placing-back of what is thought as empty, as symbolic, into
its subjective originality, in which it comes to self-givenness. But
15 as much as this reflective attitude, with respect to this manner of
givenness and in the evidence of cognizing acting, is a piece of the
intentional research, nonetheless one does not need an intentional-
constitutive research at this point for the construction of a clarified
positive mathematics, specifically a positive (dogmatic) mathemat-
20 ics. Indeed, we have repeatedly said that taking into consideration
the deed of cognizing yet again considers only an objectivity of a
higher level; the deeper constitutive syntheses, from which it itself
emerges, remain out of question.
What alone matters—in order to gain an encompassing scientific
25 mathematics in the framework of positivity—is the furnishing of a
completely apodictic evidence and the exposition of the principles
of this apodicticity.
Here we have to note: All ont⟨ic⟩ principles of the justification
of mathematics belong themselves to mathematics. Here, thus, the
30 completeness of the mathematical principles is the presupposition
for this justification. On the other hand, this justification also con-
tains noetic principles; what is required is also a formal noetics, a
formal doctrine of thinking, acting, achieving.
To this belongs the stock of reflections concerning thinking and
35 thoughts, and so on, with which the meditations begin, only that one
later requires a principal formulation and an explicit acquisition as
formal noetic logic. The latter is the first pre-transcendental critique
of cognition.
476 supplemental texts · 8
* Human beings and animals as objective facts lead, at first, perhaps to personal
reflection, but then they do lead back to intentional life and thereby to an intentional
psychology; it was precisely the discussion of the latter that was skipped here.
† But at this point the unbuilding would have to set in: nature and naturalized
spirit—on the other hand personal spirit (and so on) as “fact”—and then in the
“spiritual” or personal sphere as a sphere capable of standing under norms—the
normative formations and the special normative sciences.
a eine Ungefähr-Welt
9
sive path to cognizing subjectivity [is] not yet the regressive path to
transcendental subjectivity. Scientific consideration of subjectivity—
for this purpose we already have psychology and human sciences.a
Conceived as universally executed—all positive sciences are dissolved
5 in human sciences, in a universal human science.* What kind of sci-
ence [is this?] Psychology and human sciences in the ordinary sense.
The “noetic” disciplines, too, as positive sciences. The abstractness of
all positivity, also of noetic, logical, ethical positivity.Abstraction from
the Ego Cogito in the ordinary sense.What is required is a noetics in a
10 novel sense (phenomenological), which sublates all abstraction. One-
sidedness [even] of genuine personal psychology. Common concept
of action: a positivity of a higher level; comment on this: modes of
directedness and modes of appearance. Full universality alone leads
to full concretion: every object is a correlative occurrence of subjec-
15 tivity. The insight that the full and pure subjectivity in total would
persist, even if the world would not exist …
Procedure: the given world, description of its universal structural
typicality. Eidetic variation, cognition of the correlation, at first in its
psychological form. Psychological reduction.† | VIII, 276/277
* Let us presuppose the attitude towards a universal science; the way that offers
itself naturally is, then, that of positivity with the goal of a positive science of the
world. The consistent path leading from science of nature to science of spirit [Geis-
teswissenschaft] leads to nature being intentionally encompassed in spirit and spirit
[being encompassed] in spirit itself. Natural science and nature itself, science of
the world and the scientifically understood world itself as such become one forma-
tion in universal spirit. This motivates the idea of an absolute science of the spirit
[Geisteswissenschaft] as way to an absolute universal science.
† Not worked out in further detail. This entire consideration, on the two paths of
the Ego Cogito and of the natural concept of the world, is carried out in a certain
naiveté. Science is cognition from insightful inference; it does not want to permit
anything without reason, and wants to permit ⟨especially only⟩ what is “objectively”
inferred; it practices persistent critique, hence. But the philosophical considerations
are carried out merely in naive evidence, and in like manner, the philosophical uni-
versal science, which is to be derived from them, was construed as carried out in
naive evidence.
What is lacking, hence, is a theory of transcendental-phenomenological evi-
dence—a reflection upon the conditions of the possibility of apodictic cognition
and science—a theory of scientific reason as transcendental, absolute reason—and a
grounding of this universal science from apodictic principles, principles that have
a Geisteswissenschaft
482 supplemental texts · 9
entific in-and-for-itself, that is, it is precisely this for us; that is, in
the realization of its truly true being in constitutive subjectivity. But
special analyses would be required to build up the sense of “true”
self and “true” world (genuine humanity, and so on).
5 This is my transcendental path of the Ideas (the path of mod-
ern transcendental philosophy since Descartes (who was oriented
towards an epistemology and a critique of reason), a path which
never came to a radical self-understanding and thorough execution,
goes, in a certain manner, into this direction as well).
10 II.) But behold, is another path then not possible that has long
given me trouble to find the correct form and path of pursuit? The
two natural points of departure: of the “I am” and of the “the world
is,” are they not both starting points and, if correctly developed,
entryways into universal science, into genuine philosophy: thus both
15 ultimately leading to the same [result], at first in an epistemo-critical
naiveté, then in absolute justification? It is certainly not the case
that I want to speak in favor of splitting up the positive sciences!
And it is also not the case that I do not want to give their current
method their full due!1
20 Let us begin “dogmatically,” but directed at the actual univer-
sality of world-cognition. Let us implement the genuine principle
of positivity, or the genuine principle of grounding all cognition
in experience: experience understood, in complete generality, as
self-giving. How can I proceed? How can I get beyond positive
25 science? | VIII, 283/284
For starters, I keep an eye on universality and remain steadfast
in my will to radically realize it. Hence I truly pursue all nexuses. I
take everything that is given, as it is given in experience and insight-
ful cognition of a higher level; but then [I remain] not only in the
30 thematic perspective towards this givenness, but also in the ⟨per-
spective⟩ towards the subjective manners in which it is given, the
manners of appearance, also the full subjective doing and experi-
encing in general, thus truly in all directions.*
1 Reading this sentence as a double negative, i.e., Husserl affirms that he wants to
given in natural-practical life as itself existing and valid as real becomes later a mere
appearance of …
490 supplemental texts · 9
matter when or who would ever enact these or those possible for-
mations of insight, he would have precisely “the same.” On the other
hand I also understand that, if I realize this sameness with insight,
everybody could realize it, and I understand the “nativity” of these
5 identities, and so on. All of this leads to syntheses and correlates. If
I consider this—and this already means: if I also make again here
something seen with insight into a theme, as seen with insight of
this seeing itself and the repeatable post-meanings, empty meanings
and so on, and thus at the same time with what is seen with insight
10 precisely also this seeing with insight, with the respective habitual
acquisitions—then I free myself from “unconscious” “abstraction”
of positivity and I see the positive itself at the same time as mere
abstractum, as something dependent, essentially inseparable from
consciousness, as real and possible consciousness, and inseparable
15 from conscious subjects and their abiding acquisitions of validity.
Likewise everywhere. Everywhere I take cognition together with
what is cognized, as something belonging together essentially, and
the cognized in a co-consideration of all of its actual and possible
subjective modes and of the cognizing subjects, to which they belong
20 in actuality or possibility.
All of this I consider and effectuate, without knowing anything
of a transcendental subjectivity and without ever speaking of it. The
step that I take—from naive positivity (the positive sciences) to the
consistent co-consideration of the respective cognizing subjectivity
25 or its (and all respective) subjective modes of what is positively
cognized— |does not yet have the character of the step back to a VIII, 285/286
transcendental subjectivity.
Now I reflect: among the positive sciences—those related to the
objective world in general—stand also psychology and the manifold
30 human sciences. They deal from the very start with subjectivity. If, as
is self-evident, it is also demanded for them that what they cognize
becomes thematic and investigated in correlation with the subjec-
tive modes of cognition, then this demand seems to be superfluous
concerning their kind [of research]: at least when we do not take
35 special human sciences of the spirita individually, but all at once
and concatenated through the general human science, thus uni-
* Once the essential connection between subjective modes and true being has
become clear, then the objective world corresponds to the cognitive correlate
“subject-intentional world as such.” This subjectively cognized and cognizable world
as such—this is actuality and potentiality of evidences of different levels, and so on.
492 supplemental texts · 9
But among the natural sciences of the world we will not factically
find such an all-sided or even universal science of the subjective
under the title “human sciences,” none that would even have an
idea of the vastness and type of the goal of a universal science of the
5 subjective indicated above. Not without reason one distinguishes
among the positive sciences as such (the sciences of the world) nat-
ural sciences and sciences of the spirit. The latter are—disregarding
the confused historical psychology of consciousness—sciences of
human personalities and their personal products.1 Part of these are,
10 to be sure, also the cognitive formations, and we have indeed, as a
human-scientific logic (= as “noetic”), a doctrine and a normative
doctrine of logical actions (forming concepts, forming insights, mak-
ing correct inferences, and so on). Noematic logic, logical analytics,
circumscribes the products, which are to be gained in evident cog-
15 nizing, according to their form, the noematic-logical laws and their
theories. These evident formations (their forms and laws, respec-
tively) are brought into relation to the cognizing worldly-personal
subject | and are viewed as formations of cognizing action, which is VIII, 287/288
self-giving in original production. Thus, the theme is logical action
20 according to its steps of action: the construction of practical for-
mations according to their practical intermediary steps, but not
differently than in the other human sciences where, for instance,
in aesthetics, the aesthetical work precisely of the creative person
is observed, only that one here pursues the aesthetic motivations
25 (the aesthetical premises) and in the previous case, the cognitive
premises; here the logical, there the aesthetical steps of the products,
in which the final product is achieved through action—regardless
of the further motivations of the extra-aesthetical and extra-logical
sphere, which can equally be, and actually are, considered in histor-
30 ical human sciences.
1 The meaning of this sentence becomes clear subsequently: The human sciences
as personal sciences deal with persons as active and their actions (in the broadest
sense)—not with the actually constituting consciousness. [Husserl refers here to the
exposition below, as of p. 499, l. 15—Ed.]
the cartesian path 493
* It should be explained in detail that this abstraction in the spiritual act concerns
both: at once the subjective modes of the thematizing acts (= actions; judging, valuing,
and so on), which, as such, give rise phenomenologically to many new reflections, and
the themes themselves (the practical formations), which have their, albeit hidden,
manners of appearance.
a Kunstlehren
the cartesian path 495
* Here it needs to be shown further: If I pursue the universal and pure total sub-
jectivity in psychological apperception, I discover that, if I think it through to a
complete universality, it encompasses already, ultimately, nature, the psychophysical
world, therein it itself, that it is, thus, the absolute in its being, unaffected even if the
being of the world remained in question, and then that the world is an index, and so
on—parallelism.
a Einheitsgesichtpunkte
496 supplemental texts · 9
While writing this I see that, judging from the hints on the last
page,1 everything that is grasped by the psychologist of spirit bears
an abstraction concerning the acts and act formations, an abstrac-
tion that is to be enacted in several manners: In an act we have
5 an action (activity in the broad sense) of the I, which is directed
at a goal, and here we have the deeper transcendental modes of
being directed at—striving, with the intention to …—and the modes
of appearances of that towards which they are directed, those of
the appearing, of what is realized in the fulfillment of the striving
10 intention. Now one can bring everything under the titlea mode of
“appearance,” the I-action has its own “manners of appearance”
just as the objectivity towards which it strives and what enters into
it itself “intentionally” and in the fulfillment of the intention as what
is realized in the mode of “itself.” Look at all that stands under
15 the title “mode of appearance”! Then also the phenomenological
modification of the object where determinations manifest them-
selves, but also the manifestations in the I in its habituality, and so
forth. But indeed | one needs to distinguish: the world, the universe VIII, 291/292
of pregivenness—and the actual world: actual as what is themati-
20 cally experienced, considered in thematizing acts of thinking, as a
thematic substrate of thought formations—judging, determining—
actual in evaluating thematizings, in phantasy modifications of what
is experienced, in considerations and experiences of practical possi-
bilities (as “to be realized” by me), in executing, acting realizations.
25 Also part of it: what is inactual but can again be actualized. Two
forms of actualities! The latter: which realizes anew the pregiven
entity in its being, which interprets it, confirms its being, further
determines its being-thus, striving for its ontic truth—hence: from
actuality of “acting” ⟨arises⟩ inactuality as a mode of actuality. But
30 world exists from constituting activity; what constitutes transcen-
1 Husserl means his own previous reflections prior to this paragraph. What now
follows, Husserl designates as “comment on the last two pages.” This refers to p. 493,
l. 1, up to here—Ed.
the cartesian path 497
* Here one would have to consider explicitly the necessity to overcome the
descriptive level of the sciences—and especially of the natural sciences—through
idealization.
† Perhaps “positional meaning” is a good term to describe what plays the thematic
role for the human sciences and the normative sciences themselves, and what is not
yet fully phenomenological. Here I do not yet have sufficiently clear distinctions.
Thematic intentionality and phansiological intentionality (the modes of “appear-
ing”).
the cartesian path 499
1 The text that now follows was written, as Husserl remarks, “apparently a few
years later ⟨as the previous one, written in 1923⟩, or as correction of the old pages.”
Husserl also calls it a “supplement” to pp. 492 ff.—Ed.
500 supplemental texts · 9
mations, in which typicality, and so on; on the other hand, what they
have had before their eyes factically as absolute norms—singular
ones or laws of norms—and how clearly they have grasped them
and to what extent they have realized them; | VIII, 298/299
5 2) finally the evaluation of humankind and its spiritual surround-
ings as standing under absolute norms (from the standpoint of the
human scientist), regardless whether the evaluated ⟨humankind⟩
was guided by these [norms] or not; also, to what extent humankind
as a development is to be understood as standing under the idea of
10 absolute norms, and so on.*
We thus have
1) the factual sciences of the human spirit, that is, in earthly
finitude;
2) the a priori sciences of the human spirit:
15 a) the a priori of a human person according to its unique essen-
tial structures, in its relative concretion as a personal individual, as
abiding in its affections and actions, and as such on the basis of a
spiritual passivity;
b) the a priori of a human community, human being-together-
20 with-one-another in the world as a personal being-together; on the
other hand
c) in general the correlative a priori of human surroundings, of
the world as experienced surroundings of the human being and
human community: included therein the psychophysical a priori; the
25 universal a priori of the human spirit in its implications—implying
the universal a priori of nature, of the experienced world as such,
also of nature and world as such as logically true, as existing in ontic
possibilities, as the world in human practical possibilities and as the
ideally best possible surroundings of the individual and communal
30 human being in every ontic possibility as practical for him. The
human being as person = subject of acts, thus always “potential” in
his possibilities.
The universal a priori of purely personal intersubjectivity in its
immanent logified infinity—the absolute, universally pure human-
* In the relativity of everyday life we evaluate ourselves and the others ⟨as well⟩,
and that is (1) by presupposing at first their factical thoughts and deeds, also their
factical norms, but then (2) absolutely: so in general.
504 supplemental texts · 9
ad 208ff.: Insufficient.
5 ad 230–235, l. 8: Rework and shorten significantly.
ad 235, l. 9–239: Instead of the following elucidations ⟨from 235,
l. 1⟩ until p. 239, the principle of indubitability should be introduced
first, in the same vague manner in which it appears in Descartes’
Meditationes at first, and not immediately developed, in the extreme
10 form, into the principle of apodictic indubitability (see also the reca-
pitulation beginning p. 238, l. 9). For in order to shatter the belief in
the certainty of the world, it suffices to apply this principle already
in its vague version. Applied in the latter sense, it leads, through the
exclusion of the world, to pure subjectivity, in which again | different VIII, 310/311
15 givennesses would have to be distinguished, apodictically certain
ones and such that are not apodictic. The necessity of positing the
principle of indubitability in its extreme version thus only discloses
itself when one has already reached the ground of pure subjectivity
through the application of this principle in the vague version, and
20 it then leads to the distinction between the transcendental and the
apodictic reduction (p. 284). Thus, in what follows until then, the
talk of “apodictic” reduction or critique should be avoided.
On this note: No, I have no special reason to doubt that the world
not exist. But I ask myself if it is indeed so completely certain that
25 …, and if I reflect upon, say, mathematical evidence, I become aware
that one here has to distinguish between empirical and apodictic
indubitability.
ad 240, l. 27–29: Why?
On the same passage: On the train of thought.
* The exemplary analyses with the purpose of gaining an overview over pure
subjectivity range from pp. 286–291 and then again from 316–322. What lies in the
1 “Kant and the Idea of a Transcendental Philosophy” (Hua. VII, pp. 230–287;
trans. T.E. Klein & W.E. Pohl, in: Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, vol. 5, Fall
1974, pp. 9–56) was a speech that Husserl gave in 1924, the 200th anniversary of
Kant’s birth and was to be worked out for publication in Kant Studien. The text was
never published by Husserl, however.—Trans.
husserl’s critical notes on the train of thought 509
1 But cf. also Texts 21 (pp. 575ff.) and XXV (Hua. VIII, pp. 621ff.)—Ed. Text XXV
1 P. 305, l. 29–p. 307, l. 7 in the present version of the main text have perhaps already
1 After this note follows the revised version of the text, which has been inserted
by the editor in the main text, cf. above, p. 308, l. 7–25. This text replaces the original
version, which reads: “After the I has enacted for a certain stretch all such acts in
naive devotion, or also after its full completion (say the I which at first lives in the
shaping of a scientific theory or in the attitude of a continual aesthetic observation
or an external labor), it can become aware of its doing or what it has done; it can
transition into the attitudes and possible actions of reflections upon itself.
Once I, who has naively carried out such random complex actions, establish
myself as a reflecting I, then the act of reflection does not have to be simply of the
type of the reflections preferred thus far, thus, for instance, not simply of the type of
perceiving reflection or also reflections upon memory, related back to my past acts
of the I.”—Trans.
husserl’s critical notes on the train of thought 513
1 This note is separately dated with “1925.” On it and the following notes cf. Text
21 (pp. 575ff.).—Ed.
husserl’s critical notes on the train of thought 515
* This is still not neatly stated: cf. the distinction, of implications, between real and
horizonal ones.
516 supplemental texts · 10
1 Husserl had the habit of marking manuscripts that he deemed worthless with
It is still the case, and naturally so, in the case of intuitive recol-
lection. But what about the case of an unclear indication, in the case
of unclear and indistinct anticipations? But there are also distinct
ones, and in the logical sphere [there is] the “distinct” judging vis-à-
5 vis the indistinct one. Indeed, this is a matter of the greatest principal
importance.
11
1 Here and in the following, Husserl is playing on the literal meaning of justifica-
tion, Rechtfertigung, playing on the cognate Recht, which is here translated as “right”
as well as “justification”—Trans.
the principle of sufficient reason 521
a Normgerechtigkeit
522 supplemental texts · 11
not yet really decided (that is, taken a firm stand) or if I merely
say: “it seems so,” and then furthermore also: “it seems to be the
case but of course one thing conflicts with the other” and “I doubt”
whether it is this or that: or whether I have decisions, say old, firm
5 convictions, and added on to this newly decided convictions, where
I only later notice how they collide with each other and when I
then “become doubtful,” unsettled, how things stand, how they will
resolve themselves.
A first notion of “questionable” would be the intentional char-
10 acter of the question itself, precisely the one that our language
expresses in the general meaning of the word “question.” The ordi-
nary meaning of “questionable” is the following, however:
Questionable is that which can be called into question.
In a certain sense I can call into question every judgment that is
15 not given to me evidently, and in a certain sense in turn [I can call
into question] every evident judgment that is not completely evi-
dent. But then the “calling into question” is metaphorical talk. For I
call, accordingly, also every intention towards insight and towards
perfect insight a questioning with respect to insight and grounding.
20 At all times I can immerse myself into asking as if I were really
uncertain and could ask, and would ultimately ask for justification:
whereby I then would also strive for the justification itself, only that
it would have the form of the decision. But in general, all striving-
for-testing, which wants to convince itself over and over (to call upon
25 the witnesses), is motivated, in the scientific attitude, through the
idea that memory could deceive, that the fulfillment would perhaps
not be a completely perfect one, and so on. But this is not an empty
but a real possibility which, becoming conscious, makes it doubtful
to a certain extent how things stand here and now. And thus even
30 evident certainty, which has become a habitual possession, leads
once more to uncertainty, to doubt and to questioning. Everything
becomes questionable once again. But I do strive towards unques-
tionable cognition, unquestioned convictions. This is, to be sure, a
problem peculiar to phenomenological description: the problem
35 of an individual-subjective and intersubjective certainty | of sci- VIII, 332/333
entific ascertainments and the idea of their firm stand in evidence
that can always again be produced—as an idea to which one can
approximate oneself practically. “Moral” certainty.
524 supplemental texts · 11
a Angekränkelt, from krank, ill. A rather colloquial term, meaning something like “a
little bit ill.”—Trans.
the principle of sufficient reason 525
* Of the consciousness “to have it worked out,” to have attained the truth-goal,
which one has set out to attain.
526 supplemental texts · 11
necessity, it cannot be false. But this is a truth that can be made evi-
dent in principal generality and [is] itself an adequate and apodictic
truth.
If falsehood is a non-value or is the possibility that a judgmental
5 meaning would have to be sacrificed in the transition to fulfilling
intuition (through disappointment, through conflict with the respec-
tive intuition, which fulfills it partially), [if it is] not something willed,
not something to be striven for, then the principle to not allow a
“blind” (non-evident) judgment and not one that does not authen-
10 ticate itself completely through adequate grounding, is a principle
of practical reason, it has its practical apodicticity in its common
generality.a
This reflection, thus, leads to a general principle that is at the
same time theoretical and practical. As theoretical, it is the “defini-
15 tion” of adequate or “sufficient” grounding, in which already lies, as a
practical element, the possibility of such a grounding; furthermore,
the further principle that every adequate grounding necessarily
ascertains truth, that is, that it excludes, as such, falsehood, in pure | VIII, 334/335
generality; or the principle that what is judged in such a grounding
20 as existing and existing-such, can impossibly be non-existent, that it
is inconceivable that it not exist or be differently [is all included in
this principle].
Every truth of genuine science is by necessity apodictic.
As practical principle—since truth as such is the highest and
25 principal goal of science and thereby possibly falsehood is to be
absolutely and principally to be avoided according to its essence—
it is the highest principal order of science, as a special case of the
principle, to strive as such and only for truth in judging, to not permit
a judgment as one that is adequately grounded.
30 Its categorical imperative reads: “Judge adequately in pure apo-
dicticity.” Never settle with naive evidence but only with the one
that you could in principle transform into apodictic evidence. Or:
Judge only with an absolutely sufficient reason.
Herein lies, thus, a demand for the critique of evidences and of
35 the testing of their range. In the absolute demand of evidences, of
original groundings (groundings, thus, related to self-giving), which
a generellen Allgemeinheit
the principle of sufficient reason 527
1 From the manuscripts on First Philosophy (1923/24), part II. This text can also
what “absolute grounding” could mean and what it can achieve, the
exposure of transcendental subjectivity? If there “is” a philosophy of
this sense guiding us, a universal science of absolute grounding, then
it belongs to it itself, according to its sense, to expose the absolute
5 ground from which it departs and upon which it grounds everything
in absolute manner, perhaps to first of all lead up to it and to expose
its absoluteness as such through clarification and determination.
13
* Prior presumption: The world is, and it is cognizable for that very reason, and
for that reason it can be brought to cognition again and again and harmoniously
through normal experience.
1 Circa 1923—Ed.
what is given as apodictically-absolute 533
* What is missing here: meanings of habitual acquisitions from actual belief, and
so on.
observe, which he distinguishes from Erfahrung, experience, on the one hand, and
Einsicht, insight, on the other. Since its meaning is not altogether different from the
more common term Anschauung, the term has been translated as “intuition.”—Trans.
534 supplemental texts · 13
Meanings of all types and forms are “modalizable,” | their cer- VIII, 364/365
tainty of belief or being can become modified, can become doubtful,
questionable, mere possibility, probability, but can even become
naught. Every such modification concerning such a meaning—and
5 even a meaning sprung from experience—is a devaluation for the
function of cognition, and the modification into negation, the modi-
fication of intuitive certainty into the quasi-intuitive consciousness,
which we call semblance—a consciousness in which what is viewed
takes on the character of naught, of what is crossed out—says as
10 much as total devaluation. The ontic validity simpliciter, in which
the objectivity was intuited in the previous certainty, modifies itself
into false, crossed-out validity, non-validity, the experienced being
into experienced semblance. From now on the previous experience,
as often as we revert to it—and likewise, in general, the earlier
15 intuition—is called a mere seeming experience, seeming evidence.
The norm-prescribing reduction of all meanings to intuitions,
thus, means a reduction to genuine and not seeming intuitions.
Apparently I—and all of us who want to test and perhaps “secure”
meanings by finding appropriate intuitions (experiences, insights)
20 against which they can “validate” themselves or against which they
shatter—was guided by the conviction that there are “genuine” evi-
dences, experiences and insights in the sense that we apparently
presuppose when we talk of “genuineness”: that such intuitions, once
enacted, receive their validity once and for all and for everyone,
25 that they are only repeatable in the identical sense and in complete
certainty and that they allow, in the overview over the repetitions,
only ever again the same objectivity in the same unshattered being
to be viewed subjectively and intersubjectively; likewise, that no
other genuine intuitions, which are understood as related to the
30 same objectivity, can ever enter into contradiction with the respec-
tive viewings. In short, genuine intuitions are not modalizable, or, as
we can also say immediately, what is intuitable in a genuine man-
ner as existing can never be intuited as non-existent or existing as
dubitable.
35 If there were not something like genuine intuitions, whose very
genuineness we could grasp, and of which we can ensure ourselves
in intuiting—and again in genuineness—then all striving for cog-
nition would be meaningless. Why did I strive, above and beyond
what is given as apodictically-absolute 535
1 The words from “if not because I was of the conviction” to “in the sense of” were
without the amendments, and we have opted to leave the sentence as it was written
by Husserl—Trans.
536 supplemental texts · 13
1 1925. Cf. also the manuscripts on reduction of the I-am to what is actually per-
ceived and, on the other hand, reduction of the world to what is actually perceived.
[The text of these manuscripts to which Husserl refers is to be found below as Text
21, pp. 575ff.—Ed.]
to what extent can one even posit the demand 543
have merged together. Here I have, thus, a clear idea of what can be
called a rational goal of cognition that is directed to an object that
can be authenticated, or what can be called rational justification of
the ontic positing of an object, while, at the same time, the goal of
5 cognition, the true, can not be given apodictically and adequately
in any cognition.
What follows from this for the cognition of nature is that it is
rational in a same sense—as long as it moves within the general
harmoniousness of external experience and does not become aware
10 of the fact of this harmoniousness (a purely subjective one), which
is itself not apodictic, as a rational one, and of the principle that,
as long as this fact is rationally fixed, every mundane judgment is
rational that fulfills the conditions of evident yet empirical indu-
bitability. Presupposing the infinitely open fact of harmoniousness
15 as hypothesis (as long as it may exist, and then necessarily in this
form of openness), what results is the relative apodicticity for the
form of the world, but also for the being of the concrete world,
while its concrete ontic content that goes beyond the form is not
apodictically cognizable. But every entity is again accessible a priori,
20 to the essence of harmonious experience also belongs the presup-
posed ideal possibility of the “I can always again experience and
step closer in experience,” and it also belongs to this that, in free
experience and experiential thinking towards a closer determining
and correction, an approximation to a mundane entity (as correlate
25 of the hypothesis and in its relativity of cognizability) is possible—
then especially translated into “intersubjective accessibility”—just
as this entity is nothing other than an index of this approximation
in experience and theory. | VIII, 397/398
What, then, is the goal of the striving for cognition—under the
30 titles “truth” and “true being”? Cognition aims at being, this means:
at attaining being itself. But this means: cognition as meaning is to
be transformed into the fullness of being itself and shall thereby
become fulfilled meaning, only such a meaning can utter with insight
that and how being itself is and can thereby be a directly confirmed
35 meaning. Precisely in this manner it has its right, because it at the
same time, as being right, bears rightness in itself as fulfilled and
rests with that itself which it wanted to attain or which the cognizing
agent wanted to attain in his meaning.
544 supplemental texts · 15
in which it lets | a nature appear harmoniously. Every external expe- VIII, 399/400
rience is self-giving of its external object, and the entire external
experience is the self-giving of the world. In the fact of the empirical
indubitability of the style of the entire external experience lies an
5 indubitability with respect to the being of the world. Every belief
in the world as existing is indubitable, insofar as the previous style
of harmoniousness originarily motivates as originarily giving the
expectation of its continuation. In the continual progress lies a con-
tinual confirmation: with respect to this, one can easily attribute
10 an apodictic necessity to the belief. As long as it runs its course
in this manner, every new belief of every new phase is necessarily
indubitable, it is a necessary belief, insofar as nothing annuls it and
can annul it. Expectation is original self-giving of what is to come as
such, as to be expected as empirically necessary, and it is self-giving
15 that confirms itself concurrently in the progress and concurrently
offers a foothold for the right of the future. The being of the world
is not plainly apodictically certain, but it is ⟨given⟩, on the basis
of the indubitability of the concordance of experience as such, in
relative apodicticity, insofar as—if this concordance is fixed, under
20 the hypothesis that it [is valid], as long as it is valid—it is no longer
possible to doubt the existence of the world or to negate it. But if
the latter is now rationally grounded, then it offers a ground for
rational judgments of experience with regard to the world.
If I investigate the essence of external experience in pure sub-
25 jectivity and the latter in a universal concordance of external expe-
rience, then I cognize apodictically the essential structure of a
world—as a world of possible concordant external experience—and
the essential structure of all relations between an experiencing I,
experienced actions and appearances and appearing objects running
30 their course therein. I cognize the essential connection between the
idea of an existing world and the system of possible experiences
as a system of possible actions of access on the part of the expe-
riencing I to the entity existing in this indubitability, that is, to the
world according to all individual thingly entities factored into it. In
35 this apodicticity of essential investigation I cognize that while every
individual experience has, as self-giving, its grounded and grounding
certainty, it can ⟨nevertheless⟩ deceive, but that every progress of
experience, in terms of bringing [what is experienced] closer and
to what extent can one even posit the demand 547
a mitmeint
to what extent can one even posit the demand 551
a vormeint
552 supplemental texts · 15
The following has not been taken into consideration in the doc-
trine of reflection:
5 The mature human being is a social creature, and all sociality is
carried out through reflection. As a social creature he lives in the
habitus of constant reflection, he constantly converses with others
and converses constantly also with himself, he has himself as practi-
cal and—enclosed therein—as valuing and doxic theme, just as the
10 others. | VIII, 408/409
Just as, according to the laws of the formation of appercep-
tive continuing validity and apperceptive conferment, not only the
attentively seen things are there for us, but necessarily have their
spatio-thingly backgrounds, and just as the respective manifold of
15 unattended-to things ⟨are⟩ nevertheless perceived as things, ready
to be attended to, but are already—on an unclear, undeveloped
apperceptive level—precisely things for us, and spatially oriented,
already fitted with an “approximate” special meaning-content—it is
the same with the Ego, regardless of the unattended-to other Egos
20 in the field of perception. But this means: One needs to distinguish
a double latency of the Ego for itself:
1) the original latency of the subject that has not matured to
“self-consciousness”;
2) the latency of the human Ego, which is a subject of acts.
25 Namely:
I am always apperceived for myself as human Ego. Even when
I am fully devoted to mere observation of nature and am “self-
oblivious,” I am in my field of perception as human Ego. Here one
needs to distinguish the associative mesh through which my psychic
30 life is united with my bodily processes and that likely accomplishes
1 From the manuscripts on First Philosophy, Part II; probably 1923 or 1924—Ed.
what kind of ego is it that i cannot cancel out? 563
* But I can also turn the absolute I-think anthropologically: I, the human being,
carry out the absolute I-think.
† It is not to be overlooked that we cannot maintain apodictic evidence here,
but that we forego the apodictic reduction and only practice the phenomenological
reduction, as reduction to the “stream of experience.”
564 supplemental texts · 19
tion) exist for the I, that it belongs to the I as the one I—in every
reflection I find myself, and the identical I, in necessary congru-
ence with itself. I see that the life that streams on, so to speak in
the naiveté of Ego-lessness was only not aware of the I, but that
5 the I was there. I see, especially, that this life | is not exhausted in VIII, 411/412
the waking life in the form of the actual “I think” (of the I that
is directed attendingly, grasping, position-taking or quasi-position-
taking), but that there is such a thing as background phenomena,
which are, however, not without Ego in the true sense. I become
10 aware of this affection and what belongs to it, I now know that nec-
essarily at all times my life (also when it is reflected life in which
I am conscious of myself) contains moments of naiveté, that my
Ego cannot be awake for everything and that even when it prac-
tices universal reflection and encompasses its entire life in a certain
15 way, one thing is not included therein: the direction of the gaze,
in which the reflecting Ego directs itself at its manifold life and at
itself as subject of this life, the grasping and positing, the thematic
comportment, and so on. Again and again, thus, an ungrasped “I
think” is present, and thereby also the Ego of this I-think, in the
20 manner in which it is the pole therein. But if reflection grasps it,
then it becomes evident once more that this pole, which only now
becomes visible, is the “identically same” Ego pole, as which it was
grasped.
This, precisely, is what is peculiar and yet evident, that the I,
25 as pure I, is a thousandfold and makes its appearance a thousand
times in separate acts—and yet cognizable as the same in numerical
identity.
To be sure, the Ego is here an object in the broadest sense and
has in this thousandfold a thousandfold modes, and ⟨this Egoity⟩ is
30 for itself an intentional object which, as with all intentional objec-
tivities, is only conceivable as objectivity in this or that mode: while
at the same time the objectivity is cognizable as the identical one
(object pole) through all these modes.
On the other hand, in all reflections the Ego is objective—and at
35 the same time the Ego is present at all times, which is not objective.
This not-being-objective only means not-being-attended-to, not-
being-grasped. The respective “not objective” Ego is, however, as
the later reflection and grasping teaches us, “there,” it is the living
what kind of ego is it that i cannot cancel out? 565
* The Ego as the Ego of the grasped phenomenon is, precisely, the grasped Ego,
and essentially the grasped phenomenon as “object” of the grasping is not grasped
grasping, and the I as grasping Ego of this grasping is not grasped.
20
to be worked out in ‘1924’ = on the planned ‘book’ of 1924,” that is, material for the
planned elaboration of the lecture on First Philosophy into a book—Ed.
critique of the two steps to the reduction 567
not quite easy to see through it.* It becomes rectified through the
“expansion” of the phenomenological reduction to the monadic
intersubjectivity in the lectures of the fall of 1910.1 Already then
I explained: | It could seem as if the reduction to the “stream of VIII, 433/434
5 consciousness” would result in a new form of solipsism. But the diffi-
culty dissolves once we make it clear to ourselves that the reduction
does not just lead to the current stream of consciousness (and its
Ego pole), but that every object of experience—and the entire
world as valid in the respective streaming experience (and at first
10 as nature)—as it was said in 1910, is “index” for an infinite mani-
fold of possible experiences. The further explanation rested on the
demonstration of the double reduction that all presentifications can
undergo, namely reduction of the presentifications as current expe-
riences and reduction “within” the presentifications. Thereby the
15 system of “motivations” becomes disclosed that belongs, in origi-
nary rightfulness, to every naively posited “existing” thing whose
respective ontic validity—as I would call it today—does not concern
the merely momentary experience, but which intentionally implies
the entirety of this system of possible thoroughgoing experience,
20 a system that is rooted in the momentary experience, but, only as
horizon to be sure, a system as fully determined in style. Accord-
ingly, in the factical stream of the world-experiencing life lies—and
anew from every moment of experience as novel and modified—
an infinity of presumptions, in rightful (= concordant) motivation,
25 always intentionally implied in the universal presumption of the
horizon of the existing world, which is continually valid for me,
which, modifying itself from moment to moment, preserves the style
that is always disclosable as the a priori style of the constitution of
* Check to see whether here, with the reduction to the Ego Cogito, really only the
reduction to the stream of consciousness was meant!
1 The lecture course to which Husserl refers here is Basic Problems of Phe-
in the natural attitude, objective nature, in the sense of the one that
possibly takes on ontic determination from everyone as possible
co-experiencer.*
What, now, about the others? Are they also, in the same | sense VIII, 437/438
5 as reduced nature (as reduced to its original possibility of being
experienced by me), unities belonging to me myself, existing “in”
me as constituted in me, and as such inseparable from my univer-
sal verifying life and its habitualities? Only if I had the others in
my sphere as transcendental sphere, I could not only posit them
10 but also objective nature, in the validity of something constituted
transcendental-intersubjectively.
Now, if I inquire about the others, then they are at first brack-
eted, as the ones that are experienced worldly and posited from
world-experience, as human beings determined as having body and
15 soul. But they do exist for me, as what they are, in their entire ontic
meaning, precisely in the manner of concordance of the synthetically
unified manifold of my experiences, and these are experiences of a
special and apparently many-leveled sort that are very insufficiently
designated by the term “empathy.” They are experiences of human
20 beings, of animalic creatures.
If everything that exists for me, the transcendental Ego, is in truth
only such as the unity of my verifying life and deriving its mean-
ing therefrom, is there not everything my own meaning-formation,
as such not only belonging to my life, but also inseparable from
25 its being? It is indeed “implied” in the latter, intentional unity
encapsulated ⟨in⟩ it? But in the manner of primordial nature? What
is primordial is for the being, which exists for me, what is essen-
tially prior, ⟨the⟩ the founded validity. This indeed holds for every
other lived-body, as body that is primordially-egologically present
30 and verified for me. Here the problem of the constitution of alien
subjectivity or of the other human being sets in, and thereby of
being-human as such: the primordial founds what is for me not
primordial. Here, accordingly, another reduction plays ⟨a role⟩: a
reduction of the bracketed human being to his lived-body, and that is,
a Alleinheit. Husserl coins this neologism from All- (all) and Einheit (unity).—Trans.
penned in 1925. The references were adjusted to the pagination in this edition—Ed.
576 supplemental texts · 21
tion with respect to the world valid for me, then I practice now the
reduction with respect to the world valid for the other, while I now
posit the world concurrently and once again posit other lived-bodies
and human beings. The exclusion of the world, and precisely with
5 respect to the world valid for the other and the qualities valid for
him, and so on, is the means of reducing the soul “empathized” in
him to purity, a purity that is at the same time objective, valid for
me as psychologist, as soul of the lived-body given to me, externally
experienced by me.
10 Just as with all objective experience and experiential cogni-
tion (namely as spatio-worldly), the latter gains the character of
intersubjective validity and of objectivity in this second sense in
intersubjectivity, namely related to the manifold of psychologically
actively functioning subjects. We together cognize in this method
15 the objective-worldly purely-mental that becomes the theme of
a general doctrine of the soul purely as such from “inner expe-
rience”; inner experience in a novel sense, that of the reductive
self-experience and reductive empathetic experience, as modifica-
tion of pure self-experience.
20 But we have to make one further step that no psychology has
taken so far. Namely, opposed to the individual reduction, that of
the individual souls, there is a reduction to the one purely mental
communal nexus in the world, which connects souls to a mental
and thereby personal community. It is the path that leads from my
25 reduced soul, and at first running its course therein, to the other
souls communicating with me.
Noteworthy is the apparent distinction that has to be made
between
I) the meanings, convictions, insights that I have as functioning
30 psychologist: a) in part as “basic” convictions that create for me
a field of pregivenness, a world in which I stand, perhaps also sci-
ences that I presuppose, such as physical biology, physics; b) in part
convictions that I furnish for myself as scientist; | VIII, 446/447
II) on the other hand, those opinions, in general those intentional
35 experiences that I have as themes, that I count as part of my soul, of
me as co-object in psychology. But now one will say: this would have
to include all functioning acts and habitualities. The functioning act-
life, in which psychological thematizing and its work is carried out,
578 supplemental texts · 21
is it not at the same time part of the theme? I can reflect upon it,
and the moment I do it, it is something mental and a psychological
theme.
If I remain in the natural attitude and retain the having of the
5 world, then a reflection upon my functioning life leads to me as
human being, precisely as in relation to itself and functioning in
every way, and this is repeated in all reflections. I can also see in
general that I, the human being, can reflect anew at all times and am
at all times functioning anew prior to the reflective apprehension
10 and that I find, and have to find, this functioning through reflection
as my human functioning. It is evident in this attitude that every
content of self-reflection factors into the content of my soul of my
lived-body and, at once, me as human being. This holds, of course,
for all actual and possible reflections that I “empathize” into oth-
15 ers, and thereby I also distinguish in the others: functioning I, as
at all times necessary content for this I of unthematic subjectiv-
ity that perhaps remains abidingly anonymous, among which, the
thematically-being-directed itself in all of its actions—and what is
thematic for this I, and especially what is psychically thematic. Both
20 belong to the respective human being.
If I practice psychological reduction with respect to myself, if I
reduce, suspending the world valid for me, to perceptual appear-
ances, to being-directed-at … in perception, to all “merely subjec-
tive” remaining for me, then every natural reflection becomes a
25 phenomenological one, I then find all hidden subjective passivities
and activities, I find the functioning I that can always again reflect
upon itself—upon the specific I as center, upon its acts, upon its
reflections of always higher level directed at itself and its acts.
If I at first gain, in this manner, the universal purity—of universal
30 pure subjectivity—in the psychological attitude and with intention
towards the universal and perhaps unified mental, then, as is obvi-
ous, the transition into the transcendental [sphere] is very close at
hand. As psychologist I have retained the world in final validity and
have only sought and found the purely mental in the world—namely
35 in the manner such that I can systematically disclose and describe it.
But I actually grasp the transcendental [sphere], the pure spiritual-
ity, and—during the reduction—nothing remains of the world that,
so to speak, only stays in the background of validity—and even final
critique of the wrong presentation 579
validity—a validity that does not interfere in the least with the con-
tent of my thematic givennesses and observations and only endows
it all with a horizonal index—purely “mental.” Is here | not the idea VIII, 447/448
nearly immediately at hand that I have disclosed for myself a realm
5 of universal experience and cognition, which is independent of all
worldly experience, all positing of the world and thereby cognition
of the world?
I had presupposed the world and I am now still positing it. But
is it not I who posits, and is it not evident that I only have, and had,
10 a world through these types of experiences and subjective habit-
ualities and that the world, humanness and everything objective
makes itself in this or that manner in the subjective, such that here,
as I ⟨see⟩ in transitioning to pure possibilities and eidetic necessities
that essential laws obtain which belong to every worldly validity
15 and verification of this validity—according to which true being is
an index of a special typicality of subjectivity, and so on? Is it not
evident that the being of subjectivity, in the manner in which it
reveals and cognizes itself in purity, precedes every other cognition,
such that the former is presupposed ontically in everything that is
20 ascertained objectively, and furthermore that objective truth in its
authentication presupposes the authentication of pure subjectivity
for itself and according to its subjective validity? The functioning life
is what it is, in and for itself, its true being is cognition of a cognizing
authentication enacting itself in itself on a higher level and is only
25 valid from there, but at first [it is] validity, to be viewed in finality
on the part of the I of this life itself.
I must see, thus, that the world posited simpliciter is not valid sim-
pliciter and cognizable in finality prior to the cognitive positing on
the part of pure subjectivity. What comes first, in terms of cognition
30 and being, is pure subjectivity, and the world is what it is—and what
it is according to being and cognizability—the correlative forma-
tion of this subjectivity, belonging to the latter itself. I may, putting
myself to action methodologically as phenomenologist, bracket the
world for a certain purpose, that means, not wanting to judge with
35 respect to it straightforwardly—in the pursuit of the pure subjective
nexuses, according to reality and motivated possibility, one gains the
world as correlate, hence within the purely subjective. The Epoché
is a suspension of the presupposition of the world, suspension of
580 supplemental texts · 21
* November 2, 1925.
584 supplemental texts · 22
ontic | positing is absolute, only from the perceptual present can the VIII, 469/470
perceptual present of the past have its hold—the memory giving it is
itself present, and its apodicticity bears that of the memory within
something—as far as the latter reaches.
5 I can also see adequately that the present sinks into the past
and that “the” past cannot individually be stricken out, although
its concrete content is not absolutely given. I can see that the form
has a content, and must have one, that presents itself in what can
be currently awakened as “appearance,” but this presentation, what
10 shines through this appearance, is absolute; and one can see in prin-
ciple that this form is inconceivable without content and that this
type of appearance is absolute appearance. By running through the
absolute nexus of the pasts, I discover, in the absolute synthesis
of the appearances of something remaining identical—the pasts
15 with identical content, ⟨the recollections of⟩ the identical event,
and so on—that every “repetition” of “the identical past” in sepa-
rate present recollections, which hang together as one in separate
present recollections, gives “what remains identical” in a different
“subjective” mode—mode of appearance (temporal orientation).
20 I can “always again” come back to what remains identical and see
in principle, generally—in adequate and apodictic givenness—that
the mode must change and that a past content remains identical.
Where something immanent is in question, it is the past immanent
[moment] itself—always again appearing in a novel manner, in a
25 new temporal modality (modality of temporal orientation).
Hence, in the current present and in the freedom of presently
running productions of recollections my past itself, as the temporal
order, as the temporal order of my experiences themselves, is pre-
served. I, who exist, am the concretely existing I in the temporal
30 form belonging to me, the one that is now present, which sinks back
into the past and which assumes its position in the “objectivity”
(in the in-itself) of this temporal form and assumes this position
“forever”—for me, who has to say that what is present now becomes
something past and then is the unity of appearance of an infinity
35 of possible recollections—freely to be produced by me (if I am not
hindered)—and thereby always again as something accessible for
me in the synthetic consciousness of the same, which can always
again be cognized.
the immanent adequation and apodicticity 589
* Approximately 1923.
† Mediately—what kind of mediacy?
592 supplemental texts · 23
1 Approximately 1924—Ed.
600 supplemental texts · 24
a Reihen
III/1)—Ed.
602 supplemental texts · 24
its meaning, gains its field of labor in which are encapsulated all con-
ceivable scientific problems and all problems of humanity as such. It
is completely pointless, it would itself be an empty counter-arguing
if one were to enter into such empty speculations, so far removed
5 from the matters themselves. The construction of phenomenology
itself according to its method, its problematic and concretely execut-
ing work is the only possible answer here. In firstly grounding and
executing transcendental phenomenology, the necessity becomes
plain to begin an absolutely justifying, that is, a rigorous cognition
10 in the true sense of transcendental, or what is the same, to begin
with the cancellation of the world-presupposition. To continue to be
fearful of a seeming evaporation of the actuality of the world means
to shrink from an indubitable necessity. In further execution that
exhibits necessities step by step, from which one cannot recoil in
15 any way, the worry concerning the actuality of the world and of the
cognition of the actual world becomes alleviated all by itself, and it
becomes alleviated through an incomparably novel and insuperably
insightful understanding concerning what actual being of the world
and actual being as such | means: what it means in natural life itself, VIII, 481/482
20 whose essence has become the universal transcendental theme.
It becomes utterly clear now what experience and thought are
capable of achieving, it becomes clear that thinking, as an achieve-
ment itself taking place within transcendental intersubjectivity and
only to be authenticated in the latter, cannot in principle leap over
25 this subjectivity, that transcendental subjectivity ⟨can⟩ ever only
predelineate within itself transcendental subjectivity, that ideal tran-
scendental formations, in turn, can once again only remain within
the transcendental, that their ideality, their in-itself can never mean
a transcending of the transcendental sphere (despite consisting of
30 transcendental individual acts and individual subjects, factical indi-
vidual nexuses, and so on) and that in general real and ideal being
that transcends the total transcendental subjectivity is a nonsense,
as such to be understood absolutely.
Yet ascertaining this state of affairs—of transcendental-phe-
35 nomenological idealism—is by far not what exhausts the entire
content of phenomenology, just as little as it marks its theme.
[Transcendental-phenomenological idealism] is the result that pre-
delineates the form of all meaning of being, to which all conceivable
alleged difficulty 603
Content
Contingency of the judgments concerning external experience.
15 Empirical indubitability not absolute. Lack of finality in principle.
The meaning of this finality. The idea, encapsulated in natural science
and its scientific judgments concerning reality, of a certain finality | VIII, 482/483
(of a novel type). Relative finality—related to the respective status
quo of experiential knowledge, subject to a corresponding harmo-
20 nious progress of further experience = natural-experiential-scientific
finality.
1) The style of the entire external experience. To this also belongs
the experience that every discordance will again dissolve into a con-
cordance. Originary rightful presumption that this style will preserve
25 itself. Belonging to this: the idea of the existing real world which con-
tinues to be valid. The general thesis is the foundation for natural
science, for theories of nature under the idea of finality. Consistent
approximation to finality, but no absolute finality. The certainty of
theories [is] never absolutely given and given in adequate insight.
a zugrundeliegen
608 supplemental texts · 25
a Umbiegung
ground-laying of transcendental idealism 611
a reell
612 supplemental texts · 25
a Inbegriff
ground-laying of transcendental idealism 613
areell. In this paragraph, Husserl uses the distinction reell—irreell, which has been
translated as “real” and “irreal,” respectively.—Trans.
614 supplemental texts · 25
a Leibkörper
ground-laying of transcendental idealism 617
But here we have the great difference, that everyone can perceive
every thing, and that is, that everyone has constituted within himself
originarily every thing, or has implicite co-constituted it, such that
the thing-world would merely be changed, but unaffected in its exis-
5 tence if other subjects would not exist; just as it, on the other hand,
abides as what it is, if it is not actually perceived by any onlooker.
That it is constituted in subjects belongs to its essence, it is nothing
other than the substrate of a constitutive system. But whether this or
that subject exists or does not exist and whether this or that [subject]
10 has actually developed thing-perceptions, developed “capacities” of
external apperception or not, this is not relevant. Only subjects as
such must exist, and at the least one, who are fitted with such func-
tions that in the further course of their life a world-apperception
would have to develop.*
15 As concerns, on the other hand, personal creatures, in this case
in every transcendental subjectivity only one can originarily-
perceptually constitute itself; it is also for that reason that every
person can perceive or originarily experience only himself as per-
son according to his personality, his conditions, his activities, his
20 character traits. For personal apperception is such that it draws
into its apperceptive spell the entire transcendental subjectivity of
this person that consequently appears as purely mental interiority.
Every transcendental subjectivity builds up, in this sphere, a type
of apperception, a self-representation, in which it encompasses its
25 entire transcendental life—actual and possible, reflectively grasped
and graspable in possible reflections.† | VIII, 495/496
relation [495/496] to each other constitutes itself and in that the objectivities imma-
nent to every individual subject, if they are not really immanent, can be experienced
and cognized as identical through intersubjective identification. In this way, the world
is intersubjectively-ideally-immanent.
Every “entity” is an idea: an X, valid, justifying itself, determining itself more
closely or differently in infinitum, and yet a necessarily abiding X in validity; it is an
idea or only objectifiable as idea, as ideal pole (the latter for what is really immanent).
Accordingly, the above difference belongs to the ideas.
Ideas, however, can constitute themselves adequately, such that they are given as
complete in closed constitution (originary self-giving); for instance, the ideal objects
of mathematics.
Other ideas, however, can also experience inadequate, and only inadequate,
self-giving, such as the things through perception with an originary presumption in
infinitum. Here [we have] necessary indeterminacy and determinacy. In the one case,
one can simply take over the constitution from every other subject, in the other,
every alien subject can determine more closely what is indeterminate.
ground-laying of transcendental idealism 621
Against solipsism, both the personal and mental one, and the tran-
scendental one. The phenomenological reduction is no reduction to
a solus ipse.
A solipsism that says: I, the mental creature, alone exist, every-
5 thing else is mere phenomenon—this is nonsense. Ego presupposes
non-Ego, lived-body and thing, Ego in the natural sense is person.
But also the modification of solipsism into the transcendental
[realm], | which already makes the correct distinction between Ego VIII, 496/497
and transcendental subjectivity and which believes that the phe-
10 nomenological reduction and the transcendental interpretation of
nature would annul every possible positing of alien subjectivity, also
a transcendental one, is nonsense. The transcendental interpretation
of empathy provides the self-justifying transition into alien subjec-
tivity, and thereby into transcendental [alien subjectivity]. Just as I,
15 in my transcendental subjectivity, do not only have justified experi-
ence of what I directly perceive, but also have justified recollection,
justified expectation, associative anticipation, presentification, in
the same manner [I have] a presentification, based on the same
justification, of transcendental consciousness—as empathy.
26
a in Wahrheit
1 According to Husserl, perhaps already as early as 1921, but perhaps more likely
around 1924—Ed.
2 The beginning of the text up to here was crossed out in Husserl’s manuscript—
Ed.
phenomenological reduction 623
a zielrichtiger
624 supplemental texts · 26
a triftig
626 supplemental texts · 26
* The temptation lies in this “complete evidence”: it does not fall from the sky and
into the laps of ordinary researchers, but as “complete” it only exists in the form of
phenomenology.
a spezialisierend-besondernd
628 supplemental texts · 26
* But to this one has to say that the epistemology following after that is still naive
logic; thus, this last step has not been presented adequately here. Here we already
have pieces of an a priori logical noetics; a priori laws of a goal-oriented cognitive
doing could already be developed in naiveté (as psychological epistemology), and
this would not actually be transcendental phenomenology (an actual transcendental
logic). Thus here the higher level is in question: the meaning of this transcendental
logic and at the same time the meaning of all that is objectively cognized. There
remains a dimension of “riddles.”
phenomenological reduction 631
as the true being, but instead [an idealism], which derives from clar-
ified cognition—cognition giving sense to all being and all truth
(and from the cognition that this sense-giving cognition is that on
the part of the transcendental Ego and of a possible multiplicity of
5 Egos communicating with it)—the absolutely evident insight that all
being is intentionally related back (and essentially so) to the being
of Egos. These, in turn, are related back only upon themselves, since
they are intentional for themselves and constitute themselves for
themselves, while they can constitute themselves for one another
10 only mediately—through constitutive achievements of their own
subjectivity, called things and lived-bodies—as alter Egos.
Monadology.
Accordingly, only the Egos exist absolutely in their communica-
tive relatedness-back-upon-themselves.They are in their community
15 the absolute bearers of the world, whose being is a being-for-them
and being-constituted-for-them. They are, as absolute Egos, not
part of the world, they are no substances in the sense of empirical
“realities”—indeed, that is, as members of the world, substrates of
“real” properties, which have their true being in the world. They are
20 the absolute, ⟨they are the subjectivity⟩ without whose cogitative
life, which is a cognizing constituting through and through in the
broadest sense of the term, all real substances would not exist.
But insofar as they do not only exist for themselves, but for one
another, as alter Egos, they are Egos and they can only exist in this
25 manner through a substantializing sense-giving, which they attribute
to one another reciprocally and then, in this reciprocity, attribute | VIII, 505/506
to one another themselves1—in the substantialization or realization
of animality and humanity. They have therefore a double being: an
absolute being and a appearing-for-themselves-and-for-another—
30 from an apperception they achieve by themselves—as animalic and
human subjects, animating lived-bodies in the world and belonging,
as animals and human beings, to the substantial-real world. And in
[this world] then all socialities find their place, whose absolute being,
1 That is, which they attribute to one another in general and then individually, one
by one.—Trans.
phenomenological reduction 633
experiencing; experience
Erfahrung experience
erkennen/Erkenntnis to know/knowledge; to cognize/cognition
erkennen to know, to acknowledge, to cognize; to
understand
erleben to experience
Erlebnis lived experience; experience
erschauen to behold; to grasp (mentally), to intuit
evident/Evidenz self-evident/self-evidence;
evident/evidence
Fiktum figment
fixieren/Fixierung fixate
fundieren/Fundierung to found/founding
Gedanke thought
gegenwärtigen to present
geistig intellectual; spiritual
Gegebenheit(en) what is given, given item(s); given(s);
datum/data; givenness
Gestalt form/formation/shape/structure;
configuration
gestalten to (creatively) form, realize, configure
gewahren to perceive attentively
Grund/Gründe ground(s), reason(s), cause(s)
herausstellen to highlight, to identify, to emphasize
Ich ego, (the) I
inner internal
innerlich/Innerlichkeit interior/interiority; inward/inwardness
intendieren to intend
Kenntnisnahme process of taking notice
Konsequenz/Inkonsequenz consequence/inconsequence
konsequent consistent
Leib/leiblich/Leiblichkeit lived-body, bodily, bodiliness
leisten/Leistung to achieve/achievement; to
accomplish/accomplishment
mannigfaltig manifold
meinen to mean; to intend; to opine
Meinen act of meaning, meaning-act; supposing;
opining
Meinung opinion, belief, view; meaning; “meaning”
Mensch im Großen man writ large
normieren/Normierung to prescribe norms/normative regulation
german–english glossary 637
originär originary/original
phantasieren/Phantasie to phantasize/phantasy
psychisch psychic, mental
prinzipiell fundamental/principal/in principle/on
principled grounds/for reasons of principle
Problemgehalt subject matter
Rechenschaftsabgabe giving of account
Recht right; legitimacy; authority
rechtfertigen/Rechtfertigung to justify/justification
reell genuine; real
sachlich actual
Satz proposition; statement; sentence
Seele/seelisch psyche/psychic; soul
Selbsterfassung self-grasping
Sinn sense; meaning
sinnlich sensible; sensuous
Thema subject matter; topic; theme
überhaupt whatsoever, at all, as such; simpliciter
unbeteiligt nonparticipating
Urteil judgment
Unstimmigkeit discordancy
verknüpft connected, interconnected
vergegenwärtigen/Vergegenwärtigung to presentiate/presentiation
vermeinen to suppose; to mean
Verträglichkeit compatibility
Verwirklichung realization
vielfältig various, diverse
vollziehen to carry out; to enact
vorstellen/Vorstellung to present (to oneself); to represent (to
oneself)/presentation; representation
Vorzeichen sign
Vorzeichnung/sich vorzeichnen preliminary indication; predelineation/to
predelineate, to prefigure
Widersinn/widersinnig countersense/countersensical;
absurdity/absurd
wirklich/Wirklichkeit actual/actuality; real/reality
Wissenschaft/wissenschaftlich science/scientific
Wissenschaftslehre doctrine of science/theory of science
Wissenschaftstheorie theory of science
Ziel goal/telos
Zweck/zweck- purpose/purposive
638 german–english glossary
Aristotle 3, 18, 26, 32, 37, 51, 54 f., Hume, David 105, 138 f., 145, 147,
58, 77, 189 149, 156, 159–167, 169, 173, 175–
(Saint) Augustine of Hippo 64 179, 181–187, 203, 224, 297, 397,
409 f.
Bacon, Francis 172, 222
Berkeley, George, Bishop of Cloyne James, William 170
113, 116–118, 138, 145, 152–156,
158f., 162, 178–180, 186, 429 Kant, Immanuel 20, 188, 195, 197–
Brentano, Franz 109, 170 200, 202–204, 252, 391, 393–395,
British Empiricism 130, 224 397, 399, 401, 407–411, 431–433,
435–437, 439
Cambridge Platonism 88
Columbus, Christopher 66 Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm 74, 156,
158 f., 183, 188, 191, 197, 199–204,
Descartes, René 3, 8, 60, 63–69, 71, 390, 409, 431 f.
74–76, 78–82, 90, 93, 96, 99, 103, Lobachevsky, Nicolai 341
106, 108, 125, 135, 147f., 152, 164, Locke, John 73, 77 f., 80 f., 85–108,
183, 188–190, 195, 197, 199, 208 f., 113 f., 119, 124–128, 130–133,
224, 226, 233, 239, 284, 329, 409, 137–139, 145–159, 163, 165, 172,
413, 415, 417–419, 421–423, 425– 178, 183, 191 f., 200, 204, 343, 423,
429 428 f., 491
Dilthey, Wilhelm 440
Maimon, Salomon 440
Eudoxos 36
Euclid 36, 39, 371, 460 Neo-Kantianism 199, 431–433