EURORGAN S.P.R.L. - Éditions OUSIA Revue de Philosophie Ancienne
EURORGAN S.P.R.L. - Éditions OUSIA Revue de Philosophie Ancienne
EURORGAN S.P.R.L. - Éditions OUSIA Revue de Philosophie Ancienne
- Éditions OUSIA
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/24358483?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
EURORGAN s.p.r.l. - Éditions OUSIA is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Revue de Philosophie Ancienne
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS
1. Introduction
Cosmology, as the more recent term for the study of the cosmos,
encompasses cosmogony, and uses the astronomical and ail other
physical data in order to formulate laws and théories about the origin,
the évolution, and the physical content of the universe. Cosmogony
has a more restricted field of reference by focusing rather on the origin
of the universe.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
34 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 35
(a) The first phase refers to the processes by which the initial s
of the uni verse is described, and in which the world is led when
everliving fire is kindling in measures. It is the cosmogonical pha
which fire is prépondérant among the other elements, which are s
water) and earth. This phase terminâtes in the formation of the b
of the world. In this phase we can rank the following fragment
cite first the introductory remarks of Clement, for frr. 30, 31
Theophrastus for fr. 124, before giving the fragments in italics):
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
36 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 37
9 E.g., Kirk, who omits the discussion of this fragment in his book Hera
clitus, The Cosrnic Fragments, Cambridge University Press, 1954.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
38 Theodoras Christidis
3. Our interprétation
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 39
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
40 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HER ACUTUS 41
One must know that war is common and right (justice) is strife and that
ail things are becoming by strife and necessity.
This is the second phase: the universe emerges according to the same
always world-order, and continues to work according to laws encom
passed in the term of logos. And then cornes fr. 31b, which introduces
the idea that the universe will turn into fire, as: <earth> is dispersed as
sea ['sea is dispersed', Clement understood] and is measured so as to
form the same proportion as existed before it became earth, that is
again a State of dynamical equilibrium, and now 'the fairest order in
the world is a heap of random sweepings' (fr. 124). We, therefore,
return again in the first phase of dynamical equilibrium and disorder.
From there on, a new universe will start his life; as Clement says: εκ ôè
τούτου αύθις γίνεται γή και ουρανός και τα εμπεριεχόμενα. The
question now is: why the orderly world is led to this quasi-ecpyrosis,
i.e. why the order is destroyed and how a new order can emerge? Isn't
the universe stable?
Many cri tics consider that the universe is stable. There are changes
in it, but in général the sum total of the elements is conserved quantita
tively, according to the interprétation which considers that there is a
unique and eternal universe13. Some quantity of fire is changed in
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
42 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 43
Fr. 91: πάσα θνητή φύσις έν μέσω γενέσεως και φθοράς γενομέ
φάσμα παρέχει καί δόκησιν άμυδράν και άβέβαιον αύτής... ποτα
γαρ ουκ εστίν έμβήναι δις τφ αύτφ καθ' Ήράκλειτον, ούδέ θνητ
ούσίας δις άψασθαι κατά έξιν άλλ' όξύτητι κα'ι τάχει μεταβολ
ακίόνησι και πάλιν συνάγει, μάλλον δέ ούδέ πάλιν ούδ' ύστε
άλλ' άμα συνίσταται κα'ι άπολείπει και πρόσεισι και απεισυ δ
ούδ' εις τό είναι περαίνει τό γιγνόμενον αύτής ...
Every mortal nature, being in the middles of coming-to-be and pass
away, provides a phantom, a dim and uncertain apparition of itself
for it is impossible to step twice into the same river according to H
clitus, or to lay hands twice on mortal substance in a fixed conditio
but by the swiftness and speed of its change it scatters and aga
gathers, or rather not 'again' or 'afterwards', but at the same time
cornes together andflows away, and approaches and départs; theref
its becoming does not terminate in being ...
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
44 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 45
it. This thought can lead us to admit that in Heraclitus' physical theory
the most probable state of the universe is a state far from equilibrium
rather than that of a state of equilibrium.
The case of a system far from equilibrium is directly exposed in fr.
125 cited above: 'the kykeon disintegrates if it is not moved'; this can
be expressed in another way by saying: if we move, that is shake or
stir, the mixture of ingrédients of which this drink is composed, then
we have the kykeon. If we leave it unmoved, that is if it reaches equili
brium, then kykeon disintegrates. Thus, the condition, in order to have
a new thing (here the kykeon), is to make it go in a state far from equi
librium. This is again an empirical observation of Heraclitus, which is
also akin to contemporary ideas14.
In agreement with these thoughts about the fragments we have
dealt with tili now we can interpret frr. 84a,b quoted earlier (p. 42). The
'μεταβάλλον άναπαύεταϊ gives the outcome of processes of beco
ming, which is a new form, a new entity, a new thing; the formation of
this thing is foliowed by a period of rest, that is of a stable state; but
only for some period; because change is always awaiting everything,
even the apparently stable structures. This is the meaning of fr. 84b: it
is weariness to toilfor and be ruled by the same; nothing can stay infî
14 Of course, Heraclitus did not think in the same way we think today,
using terminology like 'dynamical equilibrium'or 'farfrom equilibrium'. The
case of kykeon is best described, we think, by using this expression of contem
porary physics.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
46 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 47
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
48 Theodoras Christidis
και ταϋτα μεν ένταϋθά που ζητεί την σκέψιν, άφορισμόν άπαι
τούντα μέχρι πόσου το τεταγμένου, καϊ δια τί το πλέον αδύνατον ή
εις τό χείρον ή μετάβασις.
And these phenomena askfor a scrutiny,for it is demanded to be defi
ned up to which degree the order ( is présent there) and for what reason
it is impossible to have more order than to go over to the worst.
18 Fr. 121: "The Ephesians, every grown man of them, deserve to be hanged
and leave the city to beardless youths; for they have exiled Hermodorus, the
best man among them, saying: 'no one should be best among us; if there be any
such, let him be so elsewhere and among others'.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 49
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
50 Theodoras Christidis
Let us give the crucial verses, in which the transition from the fire
to the Mind era is described:
20
The Derveni Papyrus, ib., p. 30.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 51
[Thus] knowing that thefîre when is mixed with other entities agita
(i.e. stirred or churned) them andprevent the entities from assembli
because of the heat, (Zeus, i.e. air/Mind) removes a sufficient quant
of fîre in such a distance so that it (flre) could no longer prevent t
entities to clump.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
52 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 53
"A proper answer to this question would call for a much more extens
investigation than I could carry out in this paper. All I can do here i
propound a hypothesis, and follow it out, in the hope that the results
obtained will commend it to others. It is that the main historical
influences on Heraclitus' thought were the great Milesians, Anaximander
and Anaximenes, and that our best chance to understand the problems
which confronted him and the meaning of his own answers to them is
to discover as best we can the links which connect his thought with
theirs..."22
The process follows this pattem; the first principle (άρχή) is the
άπειρον, from which the γόνιμον23 of the warm and cold is separated;
these opposites are the elements from which the beings are made. Thus,
from a State of high symmetry and less order arise the beings we see in
cosmos, which have less symmetry and more order. This leads to diffé
rent states, in which some elements are in greater quantifies than others;
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
54 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 55
"We have seen why the commentator on Orpheus [i.e. the author of
Papyrus] would be drawn to Heraclitus: not only do both poet an
philosopher express interest in the same topics (most notably, t
harmony of opposites and the rôle played by Justice and the Furies
maintaining this harmony), they both do so, according to the Comm
tator, in enigmatic language which needs unpacking. (The dou
meaning of αίόοϊος, for example, occurs in both Heraclitus and
commentary.) Note too how often the Commentator adopts the sam
tone as Heraclitus in distinguishing himself from the ignorant man
Cols. VIII.6, IX.2, XII.4-5, XVII.16, XXIII.1-2. He doubtless thoug
himself a kindred spirit to a famous predecessor. It may also be poss
to infer that Heraclitus was himself drawn to Orphie writings beca
he found therein a truer grasp of the workings of the cosmos than
found in Homer, Hesiod, and the other authors he criticizes. How
much he borrowed and adapted from Orphie texts, and from the relate
Bacchic and Pythagorean beliefs and practices, we shall probab
never know for certain. Clement, it is true, claims that Heraclitus deri
most of his doctrines from Orpheus27, but Clement was probably read
much late Orphie poetry modelled on Heraclitus as though it we
Heraclitus who learned from Orpheus... None the less, for ail o
uncertainty, it seems fair to state that Heraclitus was stuck by the
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
56 Theodoras Christidis
28 It is not contingent, because some lines earlier Hippolytus cites the whole
fr. 51.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 57
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
58 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 59
Time by itself is for the most part the cause of decay; for it is the
number of change and change gets the existing off itself.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
60 Theodoras Christidis
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
COSMOLOGY AND COSMOGONY IN HERACLITUS 61
Theodoras Christidis
Umversity οί Ihessaly, ureece.
E-mail thchrist@uth.gr.
This content downloaded from 190.119.190.27 on Wed, 20 Mar 2019 19:50:19 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms