Jooste Subaltern 2016 PDF
Jooste Subaltern 2016 PDF
Jooste Subaltern 2016 PDF
‘The
Subaltern
Can
Speak’:
Reflections
On
Voice
Through
The
Lens
Of
The
Politics
Of
Jacques
Rancière
by
Yvonne
Jooste
Submitted
in
fulfilment
of
the
requirements
for
the
degree
LLD
(Doctor
Legum)
In
the
Faculty
of
Law,
University
of
Pretoria
August
2015
SUPERVISOR:
PROFESSOR
KARIN
VAN
MARLE
SUMMARY
The
aim
of
the
research
is
to
reflect
on
the
notion
of
political
voice
through
the
lens
of
the
politics
of
Jacques
Rancière.
This
reflection
takes
place
against
the
background
of
the
difficulty
and
complexity
of
issues
surrounding
the
political
voice
of
many
South
African
women.
The
motivation
behind
the
reflection
on
political
voice
arose
out
of
concerns
regarding
the
contradiction
between
the
exemplary
formal
position
of
South
African
women
and
their
lived
realities
as
it
pertains
to
the
contexts
of
poverty
and
sexual
violence
that
many
women
face
and
live
in.
Since
South
Africa’s
transition
to
democracy,
many
activists
and
scholars
have
engaged
with
notions
of
gender
equality
along
the
lines
of
constitutional
discourse,
substantive
equality
and
transformative
constitutionalism.
This
research
seeks
an
alternative
understanding.
I
turn
to
the
work
of
theorist,
Jacques
Rancière
in
order
to
consider
possible
alternatives
and
ways
of
thinking
about
the
notion
of
voice.
I
explore
his
unique
formulation
of
politics
as
well
as
other
theoretical
engagements
in
order
to
open
up
questions
around
the
frameworks
that
determine
the
possibilities
of
political
voicing
and/or
silencing.
The
reflection
also
entails
an
exploration
of
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
famous
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak”.
I
analyse
Spivak’s
essay
along
the
lines
of
Jacques
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics
in
order
to
further
make
sense
of
what
it
means
to
have
a
political
voice.
I
also
read
instances
of
political
statements
and
historical
and
literary
figures
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
politics.
The
aim
is
to
contest
and
question
current
meanings
of
voice
and
to
suggest
that
Jacques
Rancière’s
postulations
can
provide
valuable
insight
on
issues
of
political
voicing,
silence,
politics
and
equality.
This
thesis
is
dedicated
to
my
mother
and
father,
Estelle
Audrey
Jooste
and
Willem
Gerhard
Jooste
TABLE
OF
CONTENTS
SUMMARY
CHAPTER
ONE
Introduction
1.1
Introduction
1
1.2
Background
and
context
2
1.3
Research
questions
16
1.4
Methodology
and
chapter
overview
18
CHAPTER
TWO
The
Politics
of
Jacques
Rancière
2.1
Introduction
28
2.2
Rancière’s
background
30
2.2.1
Introduction
30
2.2.2
Rancière
and
Althusser
33
2.3
The
mature
politics
55
2.3.1
The
police
55
2.3.2
Politics/Equality
61
2.3.3
The
political
subject
72
2.3.4
The
miscount
and
the
wrong
80
2.3.5
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
90
2.4
Conclusion
106
CHAPTER
THREE
Radical
Intellectual
Equality
and
the
Reconfiguration
of
Work’s
Space
and
Time
3.1
Introduction
116
3.2
Joseph
Jacocot
118
3.3
Gabriel
Gauny
in
The
Nights
of
Labor
and
Plato
in
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
132
3.3.1
Plato
133
3.3.2
Gauny
139
3.4
Conclusion
148
CHAPTER
FOUR
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak:
“The
Subaltern
Cannot
Speak”
4.1
Introduction
153
4.2
The
sexed
subaltern
159
4.3
The
sexed
subaltern:
Concluding
remarks
179
4.4
Subaltern
equality
181
4.5
Conclusion
192
CHAPTER
FIVE
Practicing
a
“Method
of
Equality”:
Reacting
Against
Sensible
Intelligibility
5.1
Introduction
196
5.2
Olympe
de
Gouges
202
5.3
Lucy
209
5.4
Abahlali
baseMjondolo
215
5.5
Bhubaneswari
Bhaduri
223
5.6
Conclusion
225
CHAPTER
SIX
Conclusion:
Retracing
the
Way
Towards
the
Possibility
of
Voice
228
BIBLIOGRAPHY
234
CHAPTER
ONE
Introduction
The
one
who
belongs
to
the
demos,
who
speaks
when
he
is
not
to
speak,
is
the
one
who
partakes
in
what
he
has
no
part
in.1
But
the
question
is,
who
has
the
power
of
speech
and
who
has
only
voice?2
In
order
to
enter
into
political
exchange,
it
becomes
necessary
to
invent
the
scene
upon
which
spoken
words
may
be
audible,
in
which
objects
become
visible,
and
individuals
themselves
may
be
recognised.
It
is
in
this
respect
that
we
may
speak
of
a
poetics
of
politics.3
1.1
Research
problem
What
does
it
mean
to
speak
politically
and
what
does
it
mean
to
be
heard?
Conceptions
of
politics
have
always
revolved
around
questions
of
speaking
and
being
heard.
Domination
and
oppression
are
usually
theorised
along
the
lines
of
political
subjectivity,
political
agency
and
having
a
voice.
Political
participation
is
usually
conditioned
upon
the
possibility
of
intelligibility
and
being
qualified
to
speak
and
participate
in
a
specific
framework
or
context.
Within
the
framework
of
political
participation,
people
can
be
described
as
struggling
for
a
greater
say,
for
inclusion
and
for
greater
representation.
These
processes
represent
continuous
negotiation,
contestation
and
confrontation.
Depending
on
the
framework,
the
speech
of
certain
people
is
rendered
intelligible,
whilst
others
are
denied
authoritative
voice
and
are
for
the
most
part
politically
invisible
or
silenced
in
certain
circumstances.
The
idea
of
having
a
voice
and
how
it
is
politically
expressed
is
a
complex
question
and
is
one
that
is
extraordinarily
diverse.
People
express
their
views
differently,
on
different
levels
and
platforms
of
society
and
from
within
the
context
of
multiple
influences
and
discourses.
This
project
revolves
around
making
sense
of
what
it
means
to
have
a
voice
and
it
is
around
the
notion
of
voice
that
the
work
of
French
theorist
Jacques
Rancière
becomes
1
Rancière J Dissensus: On Politics and Aesthetics (2010) 32.
2
Rancière J Malaise Dans L’esthètique (2004) 37.
3
Rancière J in Panagia D “Dissenting words: A conversation With Jacques Rancière”
Diacritics (2001) 115.
1
important.
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
can
be
summarised
by
the
phrase
“ce
que
parler
veut
dire”-‐
what
it
means
to
speak,
or
what
speaking
means.4
The
thesis
is
a
reflection
on
the
notion
of
voice
through
the
lens
of
the
politics
of
Jacques
Rancière.
This
contemplation
takes
place
against
the
background
of
what
I
perceive
to
be
specific
difficulties
of
voice
pertaining
to
many
women
within
the
post-‐apartheid
South
African
context.
I
contend
that
in
this
regard
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
can
provide
a
valuable
theoretical
lens
through
which
to
approach
and
imagine
the
notion
of
political
voice.
Rancière’s
descriptions
of
politics
are
a
continuous
effort
to
make
sense
of
and
dismantle
the
various
obstacles
that
confront
exercises
of
thought,
speech
and
political
voicing
and
I
argue
that
his
formulations
informed
by
his
intellectual
background,
can
shed
significant
light
on
issues
of
speaking
politically.
1.2
Background
and
Context
The
motivation
for
this
research
arose
out
of
real
concerns
regarding
the
difficulty,
precariousness
and
complexity
of
issues
of
political
voice
regarding
many
women
within
post-‐apartheid
South
Africa.
South
Africa
has
one
of
the
most
progressive
constitutions
in
the
world
and
post-‐apartheid
policy
is
dedicated
towards
enabling
a
socio-‐political
environment
that
is
governed
by
principles
of
equality
and
social
justice
for
all.5
Women
have
enjoyed
equal
rights
since
the
transition
from
apartheid’s
authoritarian
rule
to
South
African
democracy.
Specific
policy
and
legislative
directives
aimed
at
gender
equality
have
been
the
focus
of
4
See Pelletier C “Rancière and the poetics of the social sciences” International Journal of
Research and Method in Education (2009) 253-248. Published online 10 November 2009
available at Taylor and Francis Online www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/17437270903
259741?journal Code=cwse20 (accessed 07/12/2014).
5
The new democratic South Africa was established in 1994 after extended negotiations
between the African National Congress and the National Party. The final constitution was
promulgated in 1996. The South African constitution has the familiar features of a liberal
democracy, but also envisions a more substantive vision of democratic inclusion, participation
and accountability. It further strives to transform our society from one deeply divided by the
legacy of a racist and unequal past to one based on democracy, social justice, freedom and
equality.
2
governmental
projects
and
initiatives.6
Yet,
there
are
two
pressing
and
persisting
issues
that
face
South
African
women.
As
will
be
explained
below,
the
country
is
known
as
one
of
the
most
unequal
in
terms
of
race,
class
and
gender
in
the
world
and
as
one
of
the
most
violent
for
women
and
girls.
South
African
women
live
with
continuous
sexual
violence
perpetrated
against
them
and
the
socio-‐
economic
deprivation
of
the
majority
of
the
country
results
in
black
women
remaining
the
poorest
of
the
poor.
The
problem
can
be
sketched
in
the
following
way:
Firstly,
as
mentioned,
South
African
democracy
has
established
the
basis
for
progressive
policy
frameworks
aimed
at
eradicating
gender
inequality.7
These
efforts
have
included
legislation
that
facilitates
the
inclusion
of
women
in
different
public,
economic
and
governmental
sectors.
As
Lynn
Snodgrass
highlights,
on
paper
South
African
women
enjoy
the
highest
status
globally.8
When
judged
against
global
benchmarks,
women
in
South
Africa
have
surpassed
expectations
in
terms
of
6
See for example The Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of
2000, The South African Constitution, 1996 which specifically prohibits unfair discrimination
on the grounds of sex and gender, The Employment Equity Act 55 of 1998 that introduced
affirmative action for “designated groups” which includes black women, women of all races
and people with disabilities and the Women Empowerment and Gender Equality Bill [B50B-
2013] presented in 2014 which makes provision for at least 50% of decision-making posts to
be filled by women. It also aims to improve women’s access to education, training and skills
development and it seeks to protect women’s reproductive health as well as to eliminate
discrimination and gender-based violence.
7
When the apartheid regime ended, the hope was that the deep conservatism with regards
to women’s rights would also end. The new South African government committed to non-
racism and non-sexism took the place of authoritarian rule. Walsh explains that the new
government brought 111 diverse women into parliament. See Walsh D Women’s Rights in
Democratizing States: Just Debate and Gender Justice in the Public Sphere (2011) 185-186. A
core group of talented MP’s working with an array of women’s organisations in civil society
helped pass a series of laws that included the gender equality clause in the final constitution,
the right to abortion, domestic violence legislation, affirmative action programs that targeted
black women, a new maintenance act, and customary marriage reform. As Walsh further
explains, the state support for gender justice on the scale that occurred in South Africa since
the establishment of democracy is rare. See Walsh D (2011) 185. For a detailed and more
comprehensive discussion of the initiatives and processes surrounding South Africa’s
transformation on gender issues see Walsh D (2011) 185-216.
8
See Snodgrass L “South Africa: A dangerous place to be poor, black and a woman” The
Conversation. Published online 11 September 2015 and available at http://theconversation
.com/south-africa-a-dangerous-place-to-be-poor-black-and-a-woman-47287 (accessed on 13/
01/2016).
3
solid
representation
in
state-‐decision-‐making
structures,
extensive
legal
and
constitutional
mechanisms
protecting
the
rights
of
women
and
girls
and
groundbreaking
laws
safeguarding
the
interests
of
women.9
Many,
from
within
a
variety
of
different
contexts,
celebrated
the
South
African
achievements
around
women
and
the
related
notions
of
gender
equality.10
South
Africa
celebrates
women’s
day
and
an
entire
month
once
a
year
is
dedicated
to
programs
that
aim
to
transform
gender
relations.
Anti-‐discrimination
campaigns
and
notions
of
social
justice
for
all
have
almost
become
cliché.11
Therefore,
in
general
the
goal
on
different
levels
of
society
has
been
the
transformation
of
highly
patriarchal
cultures
and
traditions
that
render
women
politically
marginalised.
When
it
comes
to
the
continuous
sexual
violence
perpetrated
against
women,
civil
society,
activists
and
government
have
participated
and
are
continuously
participating
in
drawing
attention
to
the
high
levels
of
rape
in
the
country.
However,
as
Snodgrass
further
mentions,
formal
recognition
has
not
translated
into
fundamental
freedoms
of
dignity,
safety
and
security
in
practice.12
Many
South
African
women
live
in
contexts
comprising
of
extreme
violence
and
as
Snodgrass
rightly
states,
“the
impressive
national
machinery
belies
the
realities
of
most
women,
especially
black
women”.13
Although
South
Africa
does
not
have
accurate
statistics
on
gender-‐base
violence
because
of
the
fact
that
there
are
no
reliable
governmental
databases,
Du
Toit
notes
that
there
is
wide
consensus
with
regards
to
the
fact
that
the
country
has
one
of
the
highest
rates
of
rape
in
the
world.14
Sexual
violence
also
remains
under-‐reported.15
The
Medical
Research
Council
9
As above.
10
See for example Ruiters G (ed.) Gender Activism: Perspectives on the South African
Transition, Institutional Culture and Everyday Life (2008).
11
As above.
12
Snodgrass L The Conversation (2015).
13
As above. Snodgrass also mentions that black women bear the brunt of humiliation,
deprivation and discrimination because of the way in which racism and sexism intersects. She
refers to the deep disconnect between the political elites, such as women who have risen to
power in government, and ordinary South African women. Despite the African National
Congress Women’s League’s impeccable struggle credentials, it has not been able to tackle
controversial gender issues. See Snodgrass L The Conversation (2015).
14
Du Toit L A Philosophical Investigation of Rape: The Making and the Unmaking of the
Feminine Self (2009) 2.
15
Snodgrass L The Conversation (2015).
4
estimates
that
only
one
in
nine
rapes
are
reported
to
the
police.16
It
is
further
estimated
that
one
in
four
men
admitted
to
raping
a
woman
and
that
three
women
per
day
are
killed
by
an
intimate
partner.17
Violence
against
women
is
partly
the
result
of
factors
such
as
poverty,
patriarchy,
inequality,
high
rates
of
unemployment
and
low
levels
of
education.18
Although
these
factors
exist
in
many
post-‐colonial
African
countries,
Snodgrass
states
that
they
cannot
fully
account
for
the
“extraordinary
savagery”
of
South
African
rapes
and
femicide.19
The
violence
against
women
and
girls
is
often
sexual,
whilst
involving
debasement
and
humiliation
and
in
some
cases
even
torture
and
dehumanising
deaths.20
For
Snodgrass
this
cannot
easily
be
explained
by
patriarchal
dominance
or
socio-‐
economic
conditions
(such
as
poverty,
unemployment
and
substance
abuse).
Rather
she
refers
to
“rape
as
a
weapon
of
war
[…]
the
war
against
South
African
women”.21
Secondly,
and
related
to
the
discussion
above,
when
it
comes
to
the
socio-‐
economic
conditions
of
women,
many
South
African
lives
are
constructed
as
disposable.
The
majority
of
the
nation
is
left
to
occupy
zones
of
impoverished
invisibility.22
16
As above.
17
As above.
18
As above.
19
As above. It should be mentioned here that Snodgrass further notes that deep humiliation
is part of South Africa’s history. It has been fuelled by the symbiotic ideologies of apartheid
and patriarchy characterised by institutionalised violence, which rendered whole groups of
people inferior. The effect of deep-rooted historical, social and psychological factors
therefore also plays a role in the on-going sexual violence that characterises the South African
landscape.
20
As above. One of the most notable cases in this regard is the 2013 rape and murder of
Bredasdorp resident, Anene Booysen. The teenager was out with friends at a local pub. In the
early hours of the morning she was seen walking home with a man whom she knew. This
person was subsequently convicted of her murder. She was raped and mutilated and left for
dead at a housing construction site. Booysen had been brutally raped and disemboweled by
having her abdomen slit open and she sustained other numerous injuries all over her body.
The crime was described as a senseless and savage act and it mobilised citizens and
government to prioritise the war against rape.
21
As above.
22
See Selmeczi A “Dis/placing political illiteracy: The politics of intellectual equality in a South
African shack-dweller’s movement” Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements
(2014) 230-265.
5
This
construction
partly
rests
on
the
inherited
geography
of
apartheid
displacements
that
see
many
people
still
occupying
spaces
on
the
margins
of
national
cities
with
poverty
taking
on
a
racialised
and
gendered
logic.
Although
election
campaigns
are
conceptualised
along
the
lines
of
alleviating
poverty
and
transforming
the
conditions
of
the
poor,
the
economic
power
dynamics
have
largely
stayed
the
same
over
the
last
twenty-‐one
years
of
democracy.23
What
is
more
is
that
the
prevailing
political
discourse
at
times
labels
the
struggles
and
protests
of
poor
people
as
less
than
political.
This
discourse
sometimes
views
most
protests
and
demonstrations
by
the
poor
through
the
lens
of
notions
such
as
the
idea
that
all
protest
is
related
to
the
pace
of
service
delivery,
that
protestors
are
violent
and
that
their
protests
are
illegitimate
because
of
the
fact
that
proper
local
governmental
procedures
with
regard
to
claims
were
not
followed.24
In
some
instances
demonstrators
and
protestors
are
described
as
not
being
able
to
understand
the
complicated
mechanisms
of
government,
the
time
that
developmental
projects
take
and
the
difficult
issues
facing
the
state.
In
worse
cases
the
state
is
perceived
as
justified
in
exercising
illegal
evictions
and
violently
23
The South African Constitution envisions the redistribution of the country’s resources and
benefits, socio-economic reparation as well as the reconstruction of the society along
egalitarian lines. After 20 years of democracy however, there still remains an unacceptable
socio-economic gulf between black and white South Africans. As Madlingozi explains, the
gravest legacy that apartheid bequeathed to South Africa is one of systematic poverty,
structural unemployment and socio-economic inequality and the politics of redistribution still
remains a problematic topic within the country. See for example Madlingozi T “Good victim,
bad victim: Apartheid’s beneficiaries, victims and the struggle for social justice” in Le Roux W
& Van Marle K (eds.) Memory and the Legacy of Apartheid: Ten Years After AZAPO v
President of South Africa 107.
24
See Selmeczi A “Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 230.
6
crushing
protest
and
dissent.25
Therefore,
when
the
poor
attempt
to
make
their
voices
heard
or
protest
against
their
circumstances,
certain
discourses
frame
their
protests
as
illegal
or
illogical,
rather
than
political.
Further,
the
majority
of
the
black
population
who
live
under
the
poverty
line
is
female.26
The
lived
realities
of
black
women
therefore
not
only
comprises
of
extreme
violence,
but
also
grinding
poverty.
The
socio-‐economic
conditions
of
many
women
also
make
them
particularly
vulnerable
to
sexual
violence
as
they
have
fewer
resources
to
seek
justice
or
escape
contexts
of
domestic
violence.27
It
would
appear
that
although
there
are
frameworks
of
consensual
activism
and
awareness,
specialised
policy
and
legislation
and
notions
of
the
socio-‐economic
transformation
of
the
country,
it
still
remains
difficult
for
women,
as
a
group
and/or
individually,
to
meaningfully
appear
as
political
subjects.
In
South
Africa,
on
different
levels
of
society,
we
are
aware
and
continuously
made
aware
of
the
epidemic
numbers
of
rapes
and
of
the
fact
that
the
majority
of
the
nation
lives
impoverished
lives
(with
black
women
being
the
most
impoverished).
Therefore,
the
consensually
perceived
“plight
of
women”
has
had
a
converse
effect:
localised
forms
of
action
and
individual
or
specific
instances
of
voice
do
not
appear
to
be
politically
understood,
relevant
and
to
a
certain
extent
some
issues
cannot
even
be
politically
formulated.
When
thought
of
along
the
lines
of
political
speech,
a
paradox
emerges.
It
seems
as
if
women’s
issues
and
broader
gender
challenges
are
within
the
public
realm,
but
that
they
themselves
as
bodies
and
25
The most notable example of the violent crushing of protest was the events at Marikana
near Rustenburg in 2012. A strike occurred at a mine owned by Lonmin Mining Company. The
event was marked by a series of violent incidents between the South African Police Service,
Lonmin Security, the leadership of the National Union of Mine Workers and the strikers
themselves. The strike resulted in the death of 44 strikers whilst 78 were injured. The majority
of the strikers were killed on the 16th of August. The strike resulted in the single most lethal
use of force by the South African Police Service against civilians since the 1960’s and the late
1980’s, the era at the end of Apartheid. The incident caused much controversy, especially
when it was discovered that majority of the victims were shot far from police lines and some
were even shot in the back. The controversy resulted in President Jacob Zuma commissioning
an inquiry into the shooting. See for example D’Abdon R (ed.) Marikana: A Moment in Time
(2012).
26
Snodgrass L The Conversation (2015).
27
As above.
7
beings
are
somehow
beyond
the
realm
of
care-‐
living
in
constant
fear
of
sexual
violence
and
living
in
abject
poverty.
The
issues
of
socio-‐economic
marginalisation
and
sexual
violence
perpetrated
against
women
are
therefore
in
the
realm
of
public
visibility,
but
these
issues
do
not
politically
appear
or
they
are
not
politically
formulated
in
such
a
way
that
would
result
in
the
transformation
of
the
material
and
concrete
contexts
of
many
women.28
These
pressing
problems
take
on
complicated
forms
and
cannot
be
easily
answered.
The
aim
of
the
study
is
by
no
means
to
solve
these
problems
or
to
suggest
concrete
ways
in
which
to
address
them.
Rather,
my
aim
is
to
theoretically
reflect
on
what
it
means
to
have
a
voice
in
order
to
understand
questions
surrounding
political
speech
better.
It
is
therefore
an
attempt
to
contemplate
voice
against
the
background
of
these
complicated
occurrences
of
not
being
heard
or
becoming
politically
relevant
to
the
extent
of
significant
transformation
occurring.
Along
these
lines
the
study,
rather
than
focusing
on
concepts
such
as
political
agency,
subjectivity
and
programs
of
participation,
focuses
on
the
larger
frameworks
that
define
and
delineate
possibilities
of
political
agency,
subjectivity
and
participation.
The
research
therefore
consists
of
a
broader
theoretical
contemplation
than
merely
the
ability
to
express
ones
views
and
interests
in
an
effort
to
influence
policy
and
decision-‐
making
directives.
As
mentioned,
the
position
of
and
issues
surrounding
women
were
and
are
put
central
in
the
conceptualisation
of
formal
policy
and
legislative
directives.
As
such,
the
study
has
a
different
aim.
In
an
attempt
to
make
sense
of
the
notion
of
voice,
the
research
takes
place
along
the
more
general
lines
of
sight
and
forms
of
speech
that
demarcate
who
and
what
can
be
seen
and
heard
in
what
places,
times
and
circumstances.
It
is
my
contention
that
considering
the
disconnect
between
the
efforts
of
government,
the
campaigns
of
civil
society
as
28
In this regard it should be mentioned that the transformation of the material contexts of
women in South Africa is a complex and difficult struggle. As Snodgrass accurately notes,
“[g]ender equality is up against a powerful enemy in societies with strong patriarchal
traditions (such as South Africa), where women, of all races and cultures have been
oppressed, exploited and kept in positions of subservience for generations. Patriarchy,
premised on women’s humiliation and subjugation, is resilient and adapts to changing social
and political contexts, aided and abetted by complicity and silence”. See Snodgrass L The
Conversation (2015).
8
well
as
the
general
awareness
of
the
most
important
issues
that
women
face;
and
the
problematic
everyday
material
contexts
of
many
South
African
women
as
it
pertains
to
ongoing
poverty
and
sexual
violence,
it
becomes
necessary
to
engage
with
the
larger
frameworks
that
determine
who
has
voice
and
who
has
not.
To
be
clear,
the
background
sketched
above
and
the
specific
relationship
between
sexual
violence,
poverty,
women
within
the
South
African
context
and
conceptions
of
voice
and
political
speech,
can
be
addressed
and
analysed
in
a
number
of
different
ways.
For
the
purposes
of
my
analysis
here,
I
locate
the
need
to
theoretically
reflect
on
the
notion
of
voice
because
of
the
disconnect
between
governmental
and
societal
mechanisms
and
frameworks
that
attempt
to
empower
women
and
to
alleviate
poverty
and
sexual
violence
AND
the
concrete
contexts
of
many
South
African
women.
A
contradiction
comes
into
play
when
considering
the
public-‐political
efforts
of
the
South
African
government
and
society
and
the
ongoing
number
of
rapes,
violence
against
women
in
general
and
contexts
of
poverty.
My
motivation
therefore
arose
from
this
specific
background.
In
essence,
my
reading
of
the
background
sketched
above
highlights
the
difficulty,
precariousness,
fragility
and
complexity
of
questions
surrounding
voice
and
speaking
politically
and
being
heard.
The
issue
of
voice
is
therefore
laid
bare
when
considering
the
disconnect
or
contradiction
between
the
exemplary
formal
position
and
recognition
of
women
and
their
everyday
lives.
It
is
therefore
the
detection
of
this
disconnect
and
the
complexities
of
where
and
if
political
voice
can
be
located
or
formulated
within
these
frameworks
that
leads
me
to
explore
the
concept
of
voice.
As
mentioned,
the
issues
of
socio-‐economic
marginalisation
and
sexual
violence
perpetrated
against
women
are
in
the
realm
of
public
visibility,
but
these
issues
do
not
politically
appear
or
they
are
not
politically
formulated
or
voiced
in
such
a
way
that
would
result
in
the
transformation
of
the
material
and
concrete
contexts
of
many
women.
It
is
within
and
from
the
perspective
of
this
problematic
that
I
discern
the
need
to
theoretically
explore
and
think
through
the
question
of
having
a
political
voice.
The
study
is
an
exercise
in
thinking
about
voice
and
its
specific
definition
in
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
on
politics.
The
aim
is
to
show
that
Rancière’s
work
on
9
politics
can
provide
alternative
languages
and
frameworks
of
understanding
from
within
which
to
think
about
political
voicing.
Apart
from
outlining
my
specific
reading
of
the
position
of
women
in
South
Africa,
it
also
becomes
necessary
to
outline
two
distinct
lines
of
thinking
or
discourses
surrounding
issues
regarding
women
and
political
speaking.
These
lines
of
thinking
or
discourses
are
in
no
way
the
only
theorising
or
thinking
surrounding
women
and
political
voicing
in
the
South
African
context.
There
are
many
and
diverse
theoretical
engagements
in
this
regard.29
However,
these
represent
two
important
lines
of
thought
when
it
comes
to
women
and
voice
within
the
South
African
context.
I
outline
them
below
in
order
to
further
contextualise
the
study.
The
first
line
of
thinking
is
closely
related
to
the
background
sketched
above.
Since
South
Africa’s
transition
to
democracy,
many
activists
and
scholars
have
engaged
with
notions
of
gender
equality
along
the
lines
of
constitutional
discourse,
substantive
equality
and
transformative
constitutionalism.30
These
29
There are a variety of different discourses and strands of engagement within the context of
post-apartheid jurisprudential thought. These include engagements from postmodern, post-
structuralist and postcolonial perspectives. See for example Van Marle K “Lives of action,
thinking and revolt: A feminist call for politics and becoming in post-apartheid South Africa”
South African Public Law (2004) 605, Bohler-Muller N “Other possibilities? Postmodern
feminist legal theory in South Africa” South African Journal on Human Rights (2002) 614, Du
Toit L “Feminism and the Ethics of Reconciliation” in Veitch S (ed.) Law and the Politics of
Reconciliation (2007) 185-214.
30
The South African constitution has a general commitment to achieving substantive equality.
The type of equality that it envisions involves large-scale egalitarian, redistributive and social
transformation. It does not only have aspirations of equality, redistribution and social security,
but it also strives to realise multiculturalism, pays close attention to gender and sexual
identity, has an emphasis on participation and governmental transparency, recognises the
importance of environmentalism and extends democratic ideals into the private sphere.
Along these lines the concept of “transformative constitutionalism” refers to a long-term
project of constitutional enactment, interpretation and enforcement committed to
transforming the country’s political and social institutions and power relationships in a
democratic, participatory and egalitarian way. US critical legal scholar, Karl Klare first
introduced this notion in 1998. Ever since the first mention of the concept scholars have
interpreted and applied it in an effort to explain the role of law and the new constitution in a
transformative society. Klare’s article became the most frequently referred to article in the
field of constitutional law and references to the term are legion. The term is usually
understood as a social-democratic concept that strives for the attainment of social justice,
substantive equality and the cultivation of a culture of justification in public interactions as
10
efforts
have
mainly
consisted
of
seeking
to
transform
gender
relations
through
the
law
and
human
rights.
Socio-‐economic
reparation,
violence
against
women
and
transformation
have
been
viewed
and
widely
analysed
along
the
lines
of
our
progressive
constitution
and
democracy.
Many
of
these
efforts
have
done
the
important
work
of
legally
analysing
gender
issues
within
historical,
economic,
political
and
social
contexts
with
added
focus
on
how
race,
gender,
sexual
orientation
and
socio-‐economic
status
intersect.31
However,
some
commentators
have
pointed
to
the
fact
that
the
law
and
human
rights
alone
cannot
effect
significant
change.32
When
considering
the
ongoing
socio-‐economic
divide
and
the
prevalence
of
sexual
violence
described
above,
the
impotency
of
rights
and
legislation
relating
to
specific
rights
of
gender
equality
in
changing
the
concrete
contexts
of
everyday
South
Africans,
becomes
noticeable.
It
can
therefore
be
argued
that
efforts
and
theoretical
interventions
through
the
lens
of
constitutionalism,
jurisprudential
approaches
to
rights,
although
important
and
necessary,
cannot
solely
address
the
continuing
marginalisation
and
oppression
of
women.33
Many
scholars
seem
to
suggest
that
the
contemporary
crisis
that
well as the infusion of the private sphere with human rights standards. See Klare K
“Transformative constitutionalism and legal culture” South African Journal on Human Rights
(1998) 146-188, Pieterse M “What do we mean when we talk about transformative
constitutionalism?” South African Public Law (2005) 155-166.
31
But a few examples include Botha H “Equality, plurality and structural power” South African
Journal on Human Rights (2009) 1-37, Liebenberg S “Towards a transformative adjudication of
socio-economic rights” Speculum Juris (2007) 41-59, Froneman J “Legal reasoning and legal
culture: Our ‘vision’ of law” Stellenbosch Law Review (2005) 1-20, Sibanda S “Not purpose-
made! Transformative constitutionalism, post-independence constitutionalism, and the
struggle to eradicate poverty” in Liebenberg S & Quinot G (eds.) Law and Poverty:
Perspectives from South Africa and Beyond (2012) 40, Moseneke D “The Bram Fischer
Memorial Lecture: Transformative adjudication” South African Journal of Human Rights (2002)
314, Langa P “Transformative Constitutionalism” Stellenbosch Law Review (2006) 351, Roux T
“Transformative Constitutionalism and the best interpretation of the South African
constitution: Distinction without a difference?” Stellenbosch Law Review (2009) 258, Van der
Walt A “Transformative Constitutionalism and the development of South African Property
Law (Part 2)” Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg (2006) 1, Van Marle K “Transformative
Constitutionalism as/and critique” Stellenbosch Law Review (2009) 286.
32
See for example Van Marle K “The spectacle of post-apartheid constitutionalism” Griffith
Law Review (2007) 411-429, “Laughter, refusal and friendship: Thoughts on a ‘jurisprudence of
generosity’” Stellenbosch Law Review (2007) 198-206.
33
South Africa did not escape the language and rhetoric of human rights that swept across
the contemporary world of politics in the 1970’s. This discourse picked up after the end of the
Cold War and quickened again in the latter half of the 1990’s. After South Africa’s transition
11
South
Africa
is
grappling
with
when
it
comes
to
women
requires
a
total
revolution
if
it
is
to
be
adequately
addressed.34
It
is
at
this
junction
that
other
theoretical
engagements
and
interventions
become
important
and
it
is
also
from
within
this
problematic
or
context
that
I
attempt
to
make
sense
of
voice
and
political
speech
so
as
to
consider
other
possibilities
and
alternatives.
Therefore,
rather
than
exploring
the
inadequacy
or
inability
of
law,
constitutionalism
and
human
rights
or
searching
for
alternative
approaches
to
law;
I
turn
to
a
different
exploration.
My
contention
here
is
that
the
important
and
necessary
work
of
illustrating
the
workings,
failures
and
successes
of
legal
and
constitutional
mechanisms
have
been
and
are
being
done.
These
efforts
are
myriad
and
continuous.
My
goal
with
this
research
is
simultaneously
broader
and
narrower.
It
is
an
effort
to
consider
alternatives
and
to
explore
the
wider
frameworks
that
determine
the
possibility
of
voice.
My
contention
is
by
no
means
that
such
an
exploration
would
better
address
the
complicated
background
sketched
above.
Rather,
my
contention
is
that
considering
the
contradictions
between
the
formal
position
of
women
and
the
complexity
of
issues
of
being
politically
heard
and
becoming
politically
relevant,
theoretical
engagement
from
a
variety
of
different
angles
and
approaches
becomes
necessary
in
making
sense
of
these
issues.
My
analysis
of
the
larger
frameworks
that
determine
the
possibility
of
voice
is
also
a
result
of
a
more
complex
and
multidimensional
view
of
the
law
and
its
inherent
relationship
to
society,
power,
politics
and
community.
In
this
regard
my
research
is
influenced
by
critical
legal
theory.35
Although
I
do
not
directly
engage
with
specific
to a constitutional democracy the country fully embraced the rather optimistic potential for
human rights law and advocacy, adopting neo-liberal lines of thinking, whilst establishing all
the necessary democratic institutions. See Hafner-Burton E & Ron J “Human rights
institutions: Rhetoric and efficacy” Journal of Peace Research (2007) 379-383.
34
See the contributions in Ruiters G (ed.) Gender Activism: Perspectives on the South African
Transition, Institutional Culture and Everyday Life (2008).
35
In this regard two critical approaches that influence my work can be mentioned. Both of
these approaches have been adopted in the South African legal context to a certain extent.
The first is tenets that can be associated with the US Critical Legal Studies Movement and the
second approach are engagements with Euro-Brit Critical Legal Studies. With regards to the
first see, in the South African context, Klare K “Transformative constitutionalism and legal
culture“ South African Journal on Human Rights (1998) 146-188 and also see with regards to
the second approach Motha S & Van Marle K (eds.) Genres of Critique: Law, Aesthetics and
Liminality (2013). Although Euro-Brit CLS is associated with theorising along the lines of
12
arguments
within
critical
legal
theory,
my
direction
of
inquiry
in
this
research
is
animated
by
the
belief
that
the
law
should
be
framed
and
analysed
alongside
and
within
broader
social,
political
and
discursive
contexts.
Thus
rather
than
placing
the
law
and
related
mechanisms
of
rights,
policy
and
constitutionalism
central
to
my
analysis,
I
look
at
broader
frameworks
of
politics
and
political
voice
that
ultimately
influences,
creates
and
functions
alongside
the
law
and
its
related
instruments.
Although
I
reflect
on
the
notion
of
voice
against
the
background
of
the
legislative
and
constitutional
efforts
and
the
policy
and
public-‐political
norms
instituted
in
an
effort
to
better
the
position
of
women
since
the
beginning
of
the
post-‐apartheid
era,
my
goal
is
to
reflect
on
these
mechanisms
and
instruments
from
a
different
angle.
More
specifically,
I
reflect
on
these
issues
from
the
perspective
of
thinking
about
voice
within
the
framework
of
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
on
and
imaginative
definition
of
politics.
Further,
the
aim
of
my
analysis
of
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
is
to
illustrate
that
some
of
the
formal
mechanisms
along
the
lines
of
rights
and
constitutionalism
and
theoretical
and
public
interventions
form
part
of
what
may
be
called
the
current
“distribution
of
the
sensible”.36
I
elaborate
fully
on
this
notion
in
chapter
2
of
the
thesis.
At
this
stage
it
can
be
mentioned
that
the
“distribution
of
the
sensible”
refers
to
the
general
laws
of
a
society
that
distribute
and
determine
lines
of
sight,
forms
of
speech
and
implicit
estimations
of
the
capacities
of
people
in
specific
contexts.37
The
notion
of
voice,
rather
than
involving
the
current
ethics, language and ontology (see for example Douzinas C & Gearey A Critical
Jurisprudence: The Political Philosophy of Law (2005)) and US CLS points to the
indeterminacy, contradictions and politics of the law, (see for example Unger K The Critical
Legal Studies Movement (1986), Kennedy D “Form and substance in private law adjudication”
Harvard Law Review (1976) 1685-1778) both schools or approaches emphasise the violence,
power relationships and identity politics of the law. There is a specific emphasis on
interrogating and analysing the law within the social, economic and political contexts in which
it functions and these approaches suggest that the law cannot be separated from issues of
power, morality, community and politics. The law is not viewed as a coherent body of rules
that function objectively and neutrally. Rather, many of these scholars point to the violence
and injustices prevalent in law as well as the law’s ability to, behind the guise of neutrality,
objectivity and fairness, perpetuate inequality and hierarchies.
36
See Rancière J Disagreement (1999) 27-28. See section 2.3.5 below.
37
If viewed from the perspective of the distribution of the sensible, the law, legal
13
distribution
of
the
sensible
or
the
current
accepted
forms
and
frameworks
of
possibility
of
voice,
involves
a
redistribution
of
the
sensible
or
a
recasting
of
these
frameworks.
It
is
therefore
also
from
the
perspective
of
this
line
of
thinking
in
Rancière’s
politics
that
I
turn
to
other
possibilities
or
alternative
ways
of
doing.
The
second
important
line
of
thinking
that
should
be
mentioned
involves
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”38
This
contribution
originally
published
in
1988
has
been
described
as
having
altered
the
fields
of
postcolonial
and
gender
studies.39
Considered
to
be
highly
influential,
the
essay
poses
the
question
of
whether
the
most
oppressed
and
invisible
constituencies
in
society
(subalterns)
can
speak
in
the
sense
of
their
voices
being
politically
heard.
Spivak
specifically
focus
on
women
in
postcolonial
India.
Her
more
general
analysis
involves
emphasising
how
women
living
in
the
southern
hemisphere
bear
the
brunt
of
global
economic
exploitation.
In
general
they
are
not
represented
in
the
global
theatre
of
international
politics
and
when
there
are
attempts
to
represent
the
political
interests
of
women
in
the
“Third
World”,
it
does
not
involve
changing
or
transforming
the
infrastructural
conditions
which
maintain
the
economic
impoverishment
of
rural-‐based
women
of
colour.40
After
her
establishments and mechanisms as well as the institutional language of our constitutional
democracy can be regarded as part of the current distribution of the sensible that seeks to
enforce a society’s consensual order of things. A call for a redistribution of the sensible can
therefore also be viewed as a call for the interrogation of law’s complicity in determining
acceptable forms of speech and the consensual frameworks of voice or authority of voice. See
Jooste Y “Thinking two worlds into one: The ‘distribution of the sensible’ and women’s
renegotiation” Stellenbosch Law Review (2013) 528-537.
38
Spivak GC “Can the Subaltern Speak?” in Nelson C & Grossberg L (eds.) Marxism and the
Interpretation of Culture (1988) 271-313. First reprinted in Williams P & Chrisman L (eds.)
Colonial Discourse and Post-Colonial Theory: A Reader (1994) 66-111.
39
See Morris R “Introduction” in Morris R (ed.) Can the Subaltern Speak? Reflections on the
History of an Idea (2010) 1-2.
40
Morton S Routledge Critical Thinkers: Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (2003) 138-139. Spivak
has consistently vocalised her criticism of global development policies which focus on women
in the “Third World”. In a response to the United Nations conference on Women in Beijing in
1995 for example, Spivak emphasised how the rhetoric on women’s rights in the United
Nations paradoxically overlooks the poorest women of the South, the very women whom the
United Nations are claiming to represent. More recently Spivak has warned against the
rhetoric of United Nations declarations on women’s rights that seem to confuse access to
global telecommunications and the right to bear credit with “Third World” women’s political
empowerment as such.
14
theoretical
analysis
in
the
essay,
Spivak
concludes
that
women,
especially
the
most
economically
marginalised,
cannot
speak.
It
can
be
argued
that
when
engaging
with
women
and
voice
in
the
post-‐apartheid
and
postcolonial
South
African
context,
it
becomes
necessary
to
address
the
concerns
that
Spivak
puts
forth
in
her
highly
recognised
essay.41
Spivak’s
contribution
directly
engages
with
the
possibility
of
political
speech
as
well
as
with
the
conditions
that
efface
voice
in
the
context
of
the
global
South.
As
such
her
contribution
becomes
part
of
my
analysis.
I
explain
and
reflect
on
her
essay
in
the
study.
My
aim
is
to
open
up
the
question
that
she
poses
in
the
title
(and
answers
in
the
negative)
to
discussion
and
contestation.42
As
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
is
my
main
theoretical
41
For a discussion on South Africa as “postcolonial” see Chrisman L Postcolonial
Contraventions: Cultural Readings of Race, Imperialism and Transnationalism (2003) 145-155.
It should be mentioned here that a number of different other theorists could have been
discussed. Two other important theorists for example that could have been discussed within
the context of women and voice, are, firstly, Adriana Cavarero’s work on the embodied voice
of women. (Cavarero A For More Than One Voice: Toward A Philosophy of Vocal Expression
(2005) trans. Kottman P). In this work, Cavarero begins her analysis of voice by starting from
the given uniqueness of every voice. She rereads the history of philosophy by illustrating how
it takes this embodied uniqueness of voice for granted and how it privileges mind over body.
Through the analysis of figures of women, she provides a counter-history where the
embodied voice or the “who” triumphs over the immaterial semantic or the “what” of
speaking. What therefore matters is the “who” that is speaking rather than the
communicative content of a given discourse. She innovatively proposes a politics of voice
that reveals a more feminine or female logic. Cavarero’s work with regard to voice is therefore
relevant to women and speaking. However, I do not engage with her work in this study. My
decision to engage with Spivak in this regard revolves around the relevance of her essay as it
applies to the South African context that can be described as postcolonial and that forms part
of the global south where women make up the poorest of the world. I therefore view Spivak’s
contribution as more fitting within and relevant to the context of the research problem that I
state below. Spivak’s engagement also analyses, in its most basic sense, the possibility of
political speech being voiced and heard and as such, I limit my analysis to her specific essay
on subaltern speaking. Further, after careful consideration, I believe that a thorough
engagement with Cavarero’s work here would have resulted in the project going beyond the
scope of the problems that I am trying to address. However, Cavarero’s work on voice reveals
an important avenue for further or future research on this topic. The second theorist that can
be mentioned here is Hannah Arendt and her arguments around action and speech in The
Human Condition (1958) 75-180. Rancière critically engages with Arendt in his article “Who is
The Subject of the Rights of Man?” South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 103. I discuss his article in
chapter 5 and explore some of the arguments he postulates. I also explain his engagement
with the work of Arendt. Although I do not go into this engagement in depth, the discussions
there should suffice in addressing some of Arendt’s important claims on politics, speech and
action.
42
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 313.
15
focus,
I
discuss
and
problematise
her
essay
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
arguments
as
part
of
my
reflection
on
what
it
means
to
have
a
voice.
1.3
Research
questions
Before
setting
out
the
research
questions
of
the
study
it
becomes
necessary
to
clarify
the
following
assumptions
and
reasoning
behind
the
formulation
of
these
questions:
Firstly,
the
discussion
of
the
background
illustrate
my
concerns
when
it
comes
to
many
South
African
women
and
their
specific
contexts
as
it
relates
to
grinding
poverty
and
ongoing
instances
of
sexual
violence.
Secondly,
given
the
exemplary
governmental
and
public
mechanisms
and
legislative,
democratic
and
other
interventions,
I
detect
a
disconnect
or
a
contradiction
between
the
formal
recognition
of
gender
equality
as
well
as
of
the
issues
that
many
South
African
women
face
AND
the
everyday
contexts
of
many
women.
It
seems,
in
my
reading
of
the
background
sketched
above,
that
democratic
representation,
formal
constitutional
inclusion
and
equality
as
well
as
the
public-‐political
recognition
of
the
importance
of
overturning
patriarchal
systems
does
not
translate
into
the
embodied
political
visibility
of
many
South
Africa
women,
especially
those
women
that
live
in
contexts
of
poverty
and
that
continuously
face
sexual
violence.
This
leads
me
to
ask
questions
regarding
the
notion
of
political
speech
or
political
voice.
The
issues
of
voice
and
political
speech
or
visibility
surrounding
South
African
women
are
complicated
and
this
study
represents
but
one
theoretical
effort
to
make
sense
of
the
notion
of
voice.
Thirdly,
I
assume
with
other
scholars
and
activists
that
legal
and
policy
directives,
constitutionalism
and
efforts
to
transform
and
engage
with
gender
relations
through
and
along
the
lines
of
transformative
constitutionalism,
the
law
and
rights
are
important
in
addressing
sexual
violence
and
the
socio-‐economic
deprivation
of
women.
However,
I
contend
that
other
theoretical
engagements
outside
or
beyond
these
lines
of
thinking
and
from
different
perspectives
are
also
important
and
as
such
I
attempt
to
explore
a
different
line
of
inquiry
in
this
study.
I
argue
that
the
work
of
theorist
Jacques
Rancière
can
provide
a
different
and
valuable
avenue
of
thinking
in
this
regard
and
I
aim
to
explain
his
work
on
politics
in
an
effort
to
reflect
on
the
notion
16
of
political
voice.
I
further
propose
that
it
becomes
necessary
to
engage
with
Spivak’s
important
contribution
on
speaking
in
my
analysis
and
I
contend
that
Rancière
can
provide
other
possibilities
and
shed
a
different
light
on
the
idea
of
subaltern
silencing.
The
idea
is
that
an
analysis
of
the
essay
from
the
perspective
of
the
work
of
Rancière,
can
further
disclose
meaningful
and
reflective
prospects
for
voice.
Ultimately
I
suggest
that
Rancière’s
work
can
frame
questions
in
a
new
way
and
contribute
valuable
insights
when
it
comes
to
the
notion
of
voice
in
the
South
African
context.
The
primary
aim
of
the
research
is
an
effort
to
analyse
the
notion
of
voice
through
exploring
the
work
of
Jacques
Rancière.
This
analysis
takes
place
against
the
background
sketched
above
and
within
the
context
of
what
I
perceive
to
be
the
necessity
of
searching
for
other
or
more
theoretical
possibilities.
In
order
to
make
sense
of
voice,
the
research
problem
unfolds
by
way
of
the
following
questions:
1. In
reflecting
on
voice
and
political
speaking
what
directions
of
consideration
and
useful
lines
of
thinking
are
opened
up
by
an
exploration
and
analysis
of
the
intellectual
background
and
theoretical
work
on
politics
of
Jacques
Rancière?
2. In
what
way
does
problematising
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
politics
identify
moments
within
which
the
subaltern
can
speak?
Or
put
differently,
can
an
analysis
of
her
essay
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
answer
the
question
differently
or
propose
different
questions?
3. When
reading
instances
of
political
speaking
and
literary
examples
and
figures
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
politics
of
speaking,
what
further
or
other
possibilities
of
or
for
voice
are
revealed?
I
explore
these
questions
in
an
effort
to
understand
political
voice
against
the
background
of
the
specific
disconnect
or
difficulties
of
voice
when
it
comes
to
many
South
African
women
in
the
post-‐apartheid
context.
My
aim
is
to
show
that
the
work
of
Jacques
Rancière
can
meaningfully
contribute
to
conversations
around
voice
and
political
speaking.
I
plan
on
illustrating
this
by
firstly
discussing
and
explaining
his
background
as
theorist,
his
work
on
politics
and
his
theoretical
17
engagements
with
certain
historical
figures.
Secondly,
I
aim
to
explain
and
explore
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
essay
on
subaltern
silencing
and
to
consider
it
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
work.
Lastly,
I
plan
to
reflect
on
certain
literary
examples,
political
statements
and
historical
figures
through
the
lens
of
the
politics
of
Rancière.
I
elaborate
more
on
this
in
the
methodology
and
chapter
overview
below
1.4
Methodology
and
Chapter
Overview
The
chapters
of
the
thesis
unfolds
in
the
following
way:
In
the
first
chapter
after
this
introductory
chapter,
chapter
2,
I
start
with
the
main
theoretical
focus
of
the
thesis,
namely
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
on
politics.
I
begin
by
explaining
Rancière’s
current
influence
as
well
as
his
background
and
intellectual
beginnings.
In
this
section
I
also
outline
the
main
arguments
of
Marxist
philosopher
Louis
Althusser
who
as
a
former
teacher
of
Rancière
had
a
significant
influence
on
his
work.
I
shed
light
on
Rancière’s
relationship
with
Althusser
as
well
as
on
the
main
tenets
of
Althusserianism.
In
many
ways
Rancière’s
later
work
on
politics
may
be
regarded
as
a
reaction
against
the
key
tenets
of
Althusserianism.
His
experiences
with
his
former
teacher
shaped
the
rest
of
his
intellectual
life
in
numerous
ways
and
it
therefore
becomes
important
to
shed
light
on
this
period
of
his
intellectual
development.
After
this
period,
Rancière’s
work
can
be
described
as
representing
three
stages.
Starting
from
the
early
1970’s,
the
first
stage
was
a
critique
of
the
main
tenets
of
Althusserian
theory
informed
by
his
experiences
and
training
under
Louis
Althusser.43
He
subsequently,
within
the
second
stage,
engaged
with
questions
involving
education
and
pedagogy
as
well
as
history,
historiography
and
historical
agency.44
It
was
after
and
from
the
experiences
of
these
engagements
that
he
formulated
43
The main work coming forth from this period was La Leçon d’ Althusser (Althusser’s Lesson)
(1973).
44
The main works that can be mentioned here are The Names of History: On the Poetics of
Knowledge trans. Melehy H (1994), The Nights of Labor: The Worker’s Dream in Nineteenth-
Century France trans. Drury J (1989), The Ignorant Schoolmaster: Five Lessons in Intellectual
Emancipation trans. Ross K (1991) and The Philosopher and His Poor trans. Drury J (2003).
18
what
may
be
called
his
mature
philosophy
that
concerns
notions
of
politics
and
social
and
political
agency
and
organisation.45
Over
the
past
ten
to
fifteen
years
his
thought
has
also
become
increasingly
concerned
with
art
and
aesthetics
and
its
relation
to
politics
and
to
possibilities
of
political
participation,
transformation
and
emancipation.46
After
explaining
his
intellectual
background
and
his
critique
of
Althusserian
theory,
or
what
can
be
called
the
first
stage
of
his
theoretical
efforts,
I
explain
Rancière’s
mature
philosophy
by
exploring
five
aspects
or
moments
within
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics,
namely
“the
police
order”,
“politics/
equality”,
“the
political
subject”,
“the
miscount
and
the
wrong”
and
“the
distribution
of
the
sensible”.
These
five
features
involve
the
third
stage
of
Rancière’s
work
and
they
should
be
read
together
in
order
to
get
a
thorough
understanding
of
his
notion
of
politics.
After
discussing
the
various
elements
of
his
politics,
I
reflect
on
Rancière’s
work
against
the
background
and
within
the
context
discussed
above.
The
aim
is
to
reflect
on
the
lines
of
thinking
that
such
a
reading
can
reveal
when
thinking
about
the
notion
of
political
voice.
In
chapter
3
I
explore
two
historical
figures
that
Rancière
explored.
This
discussion
serves
to
illuminate
some
of
his
arguments
and
also
allows
for
an
even
deeper
understanding
of
his
theory.
As
with
his
intellectual
background,
his
engagement
with
certain
historical
figures
and
philosophers
becomes
important
when
attempting
to
understand
his
postulations
with
regards
to
politics.
In
many
ways
the
engagement
with
these
figures
crystallised
Rancière’s
so-‐called
mature
politics.
I
discuss
the
figure
of
Joseph
Jacocot
discussed
in
his
book
on
pedagogy
The
Ignorant
Schoolmaster
in
order
to
explain
Rancière’s
conception
of
equality
45
See Disagreement (1999) trans. Rose J, Dissensus: On Politics and Aesthetics trans.
Cocoran S (2009), On the Shores of Politics trans. Heron L (1995), The Hatred of Democracy
trans. Cocoran S (2006).
46
See Aesthetics and its Discontents trans. Cocoran S (2009), The Emancipated Spectator
trans. Elliot G (2009), The Flesh of Words: The Politics of Writing trans. Mandell C (2004), The
Future of The Image trans. Elliot G (2007), The Politics of Aesthetics: The Distribution of the
Sensible trans. Rockhill G (2004), The Politics of Literature trans. Rose J (2011).
19
that
is
central
to
his
notion
of
politics.47
I
also
discuss
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny
discussed
in
his
book
The
Nights
of
Labor.48
The
discussion
of
Gauny
occurs
alongside
a
discussion
of
certain
aspects
of
Plato
that
Rancière
engages
with
and
criticises
in
his
book
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor.49
Chapter
3
can
be
said
to
encompass
the
second
stage
of
Rancière’s
work.
Apart
from
shedding
further
light
on
Rancière’s
work
on
politics,
the
discussion
of
these
figures
in
chapter
3
also
serves
to
further
reflect
on
the
notion
of
political
voice
within
a
Rancièrian
understanding
of
politics.
These
figures
point
to
certain
ways
in
which
to
approach
and
engage
with
the
notion
of
political
voice
and
I
therefore
contemplate
Rancière’s
engagements
with
these
historical
figures
against
the
background
of
the
disconnect
or
contradictions
that
emerges
when
it
comes
to
many
South
African
women
and
political
voice
sketched
out
in
section
1.3
above.
Since
the
1970’s
Rancière
has
elaborated
on
his
intellectual
project
in
the
form
of
many
articles,
books,
lectures
and
interviews
that
spans
numerous
disciplines.
It
has
been
argued
that
Jacques
Rancière’s
philosophy
of
equality
represents
one
of
the
most
important
and
original
contributions
to
the
political
thought
of
the
late
twentieth
and
early
twenty-‐first
centuries.50
I
therefore
hope
that
engaging
all
three
stages
of
his
work,
will
serve
to
provide
a
clear
picture
of
his
politics.
As
mentioned,
Rancière
is
the
main
theoretical
focus.
The
thesis
can
therefore
also
be
regarded
as
a
way
of
introducing
the
reader
that
has
not
yet
come
across
his
work
to
his
notion
of
politics.
I
examine
the
notion
of
voice
by
using
Rancière’s
work
on
politics.
The
aim
is
to
investigate
what
lines
of
thinking
or
contribution
an
exploration
of
his
theory
can
yield
when
approaching
the
issue
of
voice
and
speaking
politically.
It
is
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
work
that
the
rest
of
the
research
takes
place.
Chapter
4
starts
with
outlining
and
explaining
the
main
arguments
of
47
Rancière J (1991).
48
Rancière J (1989).
49
Rancière J (2003).
50
James I The New French Philosophy (2012) 110.
20
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
As
mentioned,
the
impact
of
Spivak’s
essay
has
been
tremendous.
I
explain
her
main
arguments
with
the
purpose
of
addressing
her
concerns
on
the
impossibility
of
the
subaltern
speaking.
The
discussion
is
not
an
in-‐depth
analysis
of
the
essay,
its
interpretations
and
impact.
Spivak’s
essay
and
the
work
that
resulted
from
it
has
been
cited,
invoked,
imitated,
summarised,
critiqued,
revered,
reviled,
misread,
misunderstood
and
misappropriated
in
English
and
in
translation.51
The
academic
contributions
that
engage
with
it
are
legion
and
its
significance
cannot
be
understated.
Further,
Spivak
has
revisited
the
essay
in
a
chapter
titled
“History”
which
spans
just
over
a
hundred
pages
in
her
book
A
Critique
of
Postcolonial
Reason:
Towards
a
History
of
the
Vanishing
Present.52
An
in-‐depth
and
detailed
analysis
is
therefore
beyond
the
scope
of
this
study.
I
outline
her
main
arguments
and
problematise
and
reflect
on
her
analysis
in
an
effort
to
better
understand
what
it
means
to
have
a
voice.
The
question
that
arises
for
me
is
whether
problematising
the
essay
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
theory
can
result
in
answering
her
question
differently,
or,
if
it
identifies
moments
within
which
the
subaltern
can
speak.
In
her
essay
Spivak
declares
for
various
reasons
that
subalterns,
as
the
most
oppressed
and
invisible
constituencies
in
society,
cannot
be
heard
in
dominant
political
frameworks.
This
argument
partly
rests
on
her
definition
and
construction
of
subalternity.
The
displacement
of
her
arguments
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
politics
serves
to
highlight
important
points
regarding
the
notion
of
voice
and
the
possibility
of
actually
speaking
politically
and
being
heard.
It
therefore
becomes
important
to
address
her
concerns
and
it
is
my
contention
that
the
displacement
of
her
arguments
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
work
can
serve
to
highlight
important
and
valuable
points
regarding
the
notion
of
voice.
It
should
be
emphasised
here
that
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
is
my
main
theoretical
focus.
As
such,
I
engage
with
Spivak’s
essay
from
a
specific
angle
or
perspective,
namely
from
the
perspective
of
some
of
Rancière’s
main
postulations
with
regard
to
politics
and
political
voicing.
A
larger
investigation
or
comparison
of
the
work
of
Spivak
in
relation
to
Rancière’s
work
may
have
51
See Morris R (ed.) (201) 2.
52
Spivak GC (1999) 198-310.
21
resulted
in
some
interesting
theoretical
points
for
consideration.53
As
will
be
explained
in
more
detail,
Spivak
focuses
on
the
specific
obstacles
that
confront
political
voicing
and
as
such
I
explain
some
of
her
most
important
points
on
speaking
politically.54
However,
the
aim
of
the
research
is
not
to
compare
the
two
theorists,
but
rather
to
make
sense
of
political
voicing
through
an
analysis
of
different
notions
put
forth
by
Rancière.
My
aim
is
to
follow
Rancière’s
thought
in
order
to
consider
what
possibilities
of
thinking
can
emerge
when
writing
about
voice
and
as
such
I
limit
my
engagement
with
Spivak’s
work
to
the
extent
of
serving
and
answering
the
specific
research
questions
formulated
above.
In
chapter
5
I
discuss
some
literary
and
historical
figures
and
their
relevant
political
statements
through
the
lens
of
the
politics
of
Rancière.
I
start
with
the
figure
of
Olympe
De
Gouges,
a
French
revolutionary
woman
that
blurs
traditional
political
boundaries
that
Rancière
himself
discusses
and
analyses.55
I
also
explore
the
character
of
Lucy
in
J.M
Coetzee’s
novel
Disgrace
as
a
character
that
overturns
the
normative
framework
that
she
finds
herself
in.56
I
further
discuss
the
South
African
Shack-‐dweller’s
movement
(Abahlali
baseMjondolo)
and
the
numerous
political
statements
that
they
have
made
declaring
their
equality
against
frameworks
that
describe
their
statements
as
less
than
political.57
I
also
discuss
the
figure
of
Bhubaneswari
Bhaduri
that
Spivak
discusses
in
her
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
as
a
woman
who
recasts
gender
positions
and
limitations
against
silencing.
The
discussion
of
these
examples
is
a
reaction
against
the
problems
and
difficulty
of
voicing
described
within
the
background
of
the
thesis.
It
is
also
a
way
of
practicing
a
“method
of
equality”
that
is
used
and
suggested
by
53
In this regard I would like to thank one of the anonymous examiners of the thesis that drew
my attention to the possibility of such a theoretical exploration. Such an exploration would
have allowed for an interesting and possibly meaningful critical engagement with Rancière’s
work. However, my reflections here are more focused in that I follow Rancière’s work and the
possibilities around political voicing that it can open up or point to. The aim here is to lay the
theoretical foundation from where future or further critical and other engagement with
Rancière in relation to the South African context can take place.
54
See chapter 4 below.
55
See Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 103.
56
Coetzee JM Disgrace (1999).
57
Abahlali baseMondjolo (See Abahlali.org. (accessed 28/12/2014).
22
Rancière.
I
therefore
employ
his
concepts
so
as
to
attempt
to
make
sense
of
voice.
I
suggest
that
in
all
these
instances
a
type
of
political
speaking
occurs
and
my
aim
is
to
contemplate
their
meaning
and
significance
along
the
lines
of
Rancière’s
postulations
as
a
way
of
considering
possibilities
of
voice
and
speaking.
It
is
further
important
to
mention
that
the
research
can
be
described
as
a
desktop
study
by
way
of
the
review
and
analysis
of
various
literary
sources.
The
aim,
as
mentioned,
is
to
understand
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
and
specifically
his
description
and
definition
of
politics.
In
this
regard
I
engage
with
some
of
Rancière’s
main
works
on
politics,
but
also
refer
to
a
number
of
authors
that
can
be
described
as
Rancière’s
principal
English
commentators.58
As
Oliver
Davis,
one
of
Rancière’s
most
prominent
analysts,
notes,
it
is
only
relatively
recently
that
Rancière’s
impact
has
begun
to
be
felt
in
the
English-‐speaking
world.59
The
moment
of
reception
of
any
thinker’s
work
and
the
years
following
it
becomes
integral
in
explaining
and
engaging
a
thinker’s
work
as
correctly
and
accurately
as
possible.
The
sources
and
authors
that
I
have
chosen
are
sources
and
authors
more
frequently
referred
to
in
other
academic
engagements.60
These
authors
58
The main Rancièrian works that I engage with are
Disagreement (1999) trans. Rose J,
Dissensus: On Politics and Aesthetics trans. Cocoran S (2009), On the Shores of Politics trans.
Heron L (1995), The Names of History: On the Poetics of Knowledge trans. Melehy H (1994),
The Nights of Labor: The Worker’s Dream in Nineteenth-Century France trans. Drury J (1989),
The Ignorant Schoolmaster: Five Lessons in Intellectual Emancipation trans. Ross K (1991) and
The Philosopher and His Poor trans. Drury J (2003).
59
Davis O Jacques Rancière (2010) vii.
60
One of the most notable sources in this regard is Davis O Jacques Rancière (2010) referred
to above. This book by Davis is the first book-length publication by a single author devoted
entirely to Rancière’s thought. Davis has also recently edited a volume of critical essays on
Rancière’s work. See Davis (ed.) Rancière Now: Current Perspectives on Jacques Rancière
(2013). Another important introductory work that I frequently refer to is Tanke J Jacques
Rancière: An Introduction: Philosophy, Politics, Aesthetics (2011). Tanke situates a distinctive
approach against the background of Continental philosophy and postulates critical questions
on how we might proceed after encountering Rancière. An important volume of essays that I
refer to is Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) Jacques Rancière: History, Politics, Aesthetics (2009).
This book includes essays by Alain Badiou, Jean-Luc Nancy, Peter Hallward, Étienne Balibar,
Yves Citton, Todd May and Kristin Ross. Ross translated Rancière’s important work on
pedagogy The Ignorant Schoolmaster: Five Lessons in Intellectual Emancipation (1991).
Gabriel Rockhill, the editor of the volume, translated Rancière’s important work The Politics of
Aesthetics: The Distribution of the Sensible (2004). I also frequently refer to Todd May. May
has published numerous articles and chapters in books on Rancière. See for example
23
include
principle
translators
of
Rancière’s
work
and
authors
that
played
an
integral
role
in
introducing
his
work
to
the
English-‐speaking
world.61
What
makes
and
explanation
of
Rancière’s
work
difficult
is
the
fact
that
his
body
of
work
is
especially
resistant
to
explanatory
exposition.62
Firstly,
Rancière’s
work
embodies
a
suspicion
of
the
very
act
of
explaining
or
explanation.
In
this
regard
he
employs
a
method
of
equality
that
I
will
elaborate
on
in
chapter
5
of
the
thesis.
His
philosophical
style,
as
Davis
further
explains,
is
declarative
or
“assertoric”
rather
than
explanatory.63
He
proposes
theses
and
seeks
to
constructively
elaborate
new
conceptual
frameworks
of
understanding.
His
thinking
and
writing
strives
to
be
egalitarian.64
Parataxis
or
juxtaposition
is
his
principle
conceptual
mode
and
he
tends
to
eschew
hierarchal
constructions.65
His
approach
can
be
described
as
one
that
intervenes,
often
in
discussions
that
are
already
very
complex.
As
such,
explaining
Rancière’s
work
gives
rise
to
a
particular
set
of
difficulties.
In
this
regard
other
or
secondary
sources
become
important
when
attempting
to
understand
his
notion
of
politics.
My
aim
is
to
present
as
thorough
an
understanding
of
his
work
on
politics
as
possible
within
the
scope
of
this
project.
Most
of
the
sources
that
I
use
read
Rancière
in
light
of
his
intellectual
history
and
background.
As
such,
I
also,
as
mentioned,
explain
his
background
and
the
trajectory
of
his
thought
in
the
first
section
of
chapter
2.
In
his
work,
Rancière
further
offers
a
particular
version
of
interdisciplinarity.66
Rather
than
affirming
disciplines
or
working
within
specific
disciplinary
frameworks,
Rancière
combines
disciplines
and
attempts
to
recast
their
boundaries.
In
an
attempt
to
explain
his
work
as
well
as
attempting
to
capture
something
of
the
spirit
of
Rancière’s
work,
“Rancière and Anarchism” in Deranty J & Ross A (eds.) Jacques Rancière and the
Contemporary Scene: The Philosophy of Radical Equality (2012) 117, “Rancière in South-
Carolina” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 105, “There are no Queers: Jacques Rancière
and post-identity politics” Borderlands (2009) 3, May T “Jacques Rancière and the Ethics of
Equality” SubStance (2007) 24. May also published a full-length book on Rancière politics
titled The Political Thought of Jacques Rancière (2008).
61
See footnote 3 above.
62
Davis O (2010) viii –xi.
63
As above.
64
As above.
65
As above.
66
See Ross K “Historicising Untimeliness” in
in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 24-25.
24
I
use
the
following
approaches
in
my
writing:
Firstly,
in
explaining
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
(in
chapters
2
and
3)
my
writing,
more
often
than
not,
assumes
a
declarative
tone.
As
mentioned,
Rancière’s
writing
is
declarative.
In
this
regard,
he
proposes
theses
and
leaves
the
reader
free
to
take
it
or
leave
it.67
I
therefore
declare
and
assert
some
of
his
standpoints
and
definitions
on
politics,
rather
than
adopting
an
explanatory
tone.
Secondly,
I
identified
a
specific
problem
that
I
want
to
address-‐
understanding
the
notion
of
political
voice-‐
and
rather
than
trying
to
address
this
problem
within
specific
conceptual
frameworks
or
disciplines,
I
follow
Rancière
and
adopt
a
more
interdisciplinary
approach.
I
especially
adopt
this
approach
in
chapter
5
where
I
discuss
some
literary
and
historical
figures
and
political
statements.
Lastly,
Rancière’s
work
embodies
“dissensus”,
a
term
he
uses
to
explain
his
politics.68
Always
looking
to
subvert,
through
an
egalitarian
understanding
and
approach,
Rancière
challenges
forms
of
systematisation.
He
continuously
rubs
against
the
grain
of
established
lines
of
thinking
and
regimes
of
thought.
In
this
regard,
I
also
take
my
cue
from
Rancière
in
my
approach
to
and
description
of
the
problems
that
I
attempt
to
address.
Rather
than,
for
example,
proposing
legal
reform
or
asserting
approaches
to
rights
and
constitutionalism
or
for
that
matter
affirming
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
assertion
that
the
subaltern
cannot
speak
mentioned
earlier,
I
aim
to
question
certain
established
frameworks
against
the
specific
South
African
background
explained
above.
It
should
be
mentioned
here
again
that
when
it
comes
to
the
political
subjectivity,
agency
and
the
speech
of
women
in
the
South
African
context,
there
are
a
number
of
ways
in
which
to
analyse,
approach
or
explain
the
notion
of
political
voice.
This
project
represents
but
one
way
in
which
to
contemplate
these
issues.
The
problem
can
be
framed
in
many
different
ways.
My
exploration
of
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
in
this
thesis
is
but
one
perspective
from
where
to
explore
and
imagine
the
notion
of
political
voice.
It
is
also
important
to
note
that
in
the
heterogeneous
South
African
society,
there
are
vast
cultural,
ethnic,
religious
and
socio-‐economic
differences
between
women.
The
experiences
of
South
African
67
Davis O (2010) viii –xi.
68
See section 2.3.1 below.
25
women
are
diverse
and
even
more
so
diverse
given
the
historical
marginalisation
of
black
women
and
other
women
of
colour
through
the
systems
of
colonialisation
and
apartheid,
which
positioned
white
women
to
a
higher
political
status.
It
therefore
becomes
impossible
to
reduce
women
in
this
context
to
a
social
category
or
describe
them
as
having
a
shared
identity.69
As
will
be
explained
later,
such
as
a
reduction
or
description
runs
counter
to
Rancière’s
analysis
of
politics
and
his
work
rather
points
to
fleeting
and
temporary
identities
and
categories.70
As
it
pertains
to
the
background
sketched
above,
my
aim
is
not
to
offer
a
universal
account
of
the
experiences
of
women,
or
to
make
assumptions
with
regards
to
their
positions,
locales,
capabilities
or
understandings.
Rather,
my
interest
lies
in
the
way
in
which
the
consensual
frameworks
of
government
and
society
describe
and
practice
the
empowerment
of
women
in
South
Africa
and
the
related
efforts
to
create
a
more
equal
society
and
the
contexts
of
many
women
as
it
pertains
specifically
to
the
well-‐known
and
extremely
high
rates
of
sexual
violence
and
dire
socio-‐economic
circumstances
of
the
majority
of
women.
It
is
within
this
configuration
of
the
public-‐political
description
of
and
thinking
about
the
category
of
women
and
the
perceived
solutions
to
certain
problems
that
I
locate
the
need
to
reflect
on
voice
so
as
to
69
Such a description can be referred to as “essentialism” or the notion that “a unitary,
‘essential’ women’s experience can be isolated and described independently of race, class,
sexual orientation, and other realities of experience”. See Harris “Race and essentialism in
feminist legal theory” Stanford Law Review (1990) 585. My goal here and with the description
of the background is by no means to describe a universal suffering or experience that can be
located in the lives of all South African women. As mentioned, my interests rather lies in the
precariousness of the specific relationship between the way in which government and society
in general attempt to empower women in South Africa, the efforts to address rape and
poverty, the fact that sexual violence and poverty still persists and where and when the notion
of political voice can be located or detected within this relationship. My suggestion ultimately
is exactly that Rancière’s politics can point is into new directions of making sense of these
issues or relationships.
70
See sections 2.3.3 and 2.3.4 below. Rancière refers to a process of subjectivation in his
politics. This process is never about asserting identity categories, but always about refusing
the identities imposed by others or systems of power. Rancière proposes discord, polemics
and the disruption and disordering of set and existing identity categories. He is highly critical
of the way in which existing categories of race, gender and socio-economic position function
to silence people’s voices, rather than resulting in political speech. Ultimately this is a
valuable insight that I attempt to demonstrate and I suggest that Rancière’s politics might
point to new ways in which we are to think about categories, such as the category of women,
especially as formulated within consensual frameworks.
26
open
up
possible
different
understandings
and
ways
of
reading,
thinking
and
speaking.
My
aim
is
exactly
to
demonstrate,
through
reflecting
on
the
notion
of
voice,
that
Jacques
Rancière’s
politics,
informed
by
his
intellectual
background
and
animated
by
his
engagement
with
certain
historical
figures,
can
provide
new
insights
and
frameworks
when
it
comes
to
our
understanding
of
the
notion
of
political
voice.
Rancière’s
work
indeed
points
to
different
inventions
and
ways
of
thinking
about
categories
or
descriptions
of
situations
of
inequality,
politics
and
political
voicing
and
his
work
further
suggests
localised,
individual
and
contextual
thinking
in
this
regard.
The
aim
is
to
suggest,
against
dominant
configurations
of
the
relationship
between
political
voice,
women
in
the
South
African
context
and
questions
surrounding
politics
that
Rancière’s
work
can
contribute
in
mapping
different
relationships,
different
approaches
and
different
ways
of
imagining
these
relationships.
The
aim
is
not
to
produce
final
answers
or
solutions
in
any
way.
Rather,
it
is
to
reflect
and
contemplate
possibilities
and
to
postulate
Rancièrian
notions,
readings
and
ideas
so
as
to
open
up
questions
around
voice.
“Reflection”
in
this
regard
does
not
indicate
solving
problems
or
offering
solutions
to
the
contexts
of
sexual
violence
and
poverty
that
many
South
African
women
live
in.
It
also
does
not
indicate
formulating
concrete
steps
in
an
effort
to
go
forward.
It
rather
indicates
a
way
of
opening
up
or
framing
questions
in
an
effort
to
point
to
lines
of
thinking
from
where
further
engagement
can
take
place.
It
therefore
involves
a
journey
that
can
hopefully
point
me
to
new
insights
and
possibilities
from
where
to
think
about
and
engage
with
the
notion
voice.
I
start
in
the
next
chapter
to
discuss
and
explain
Jacques
Rancière’s
innovative
work
on
politics.
27
CHAPTER
2
The
Politics
of
Jacques
Rancière
2.1
Introduction
In
this
chapter
I
discuss
Jacques
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
as
the
main
theoretical
focus
of
the
thesis.
As
mentioned,
I
explain
Rancière’s
formulations
of
politics
so
as
to
understand
and
reflect
on
the
notion
of
political
voice.
The
aim
of
this
chapter
is
to
thoroughly
examine
Rancière’s
work
and
to
reflect
on
the
meaning
of
voice
within
the
context
of
his
description
and
definition
of
politics.
The
chapter
unfolds
in
the
following
way:
In
the
first
section
I
attempt
to
theoretically
situate
Rancière’s
work
by
explaining
his
background
and
intellectual
beginnings.
As
mentioned
in
the
introduction,
the
discussion
of
Rancière’s
background
involves
discussing
his
relationship
with
his
former
teacher,
Louis
Althusser.
Althusser
influenced
Rancière’s
work
in
a
significant
way.
Although
Rancière
later
became
one
of
Althusser’s
most
trenchant
critics,
his
work
was
and
remains
shaped
by
the
experiences
he
had
under
the
tutelage
of
the
Marxist
philosopher.
Indeed,
it
has
been
noted
that
it
was
perhaps
the
circumstances
surrounding
Rancière’s
break
with
Althusser
that
most
decisively
shaped
the
development
of
his
philosophy
as
a
whole
and
the
radical
egalitarianism
that
characterises
it.71
It
is
the
way
in
which
he
distanced
himself
from
Althusserian
theory
that
determined
the
specificity
of
his
subsequent
concerns.
Therefore,
in
order
to
thoroughly
understand
Rancière’s
notion
of
politics,
it
becomes
necessary
to
shed
light
on
his
early
contextual
setting,
especially
his
relationship
with
Althusser.
Moreover,
Rancière’s
work
is
not
easily
identifiable
within
dominant
theoretical
movements.
I
explore
this
point
in
more
detail
below.
For
now
it
can
be
mentioned
that
his
work
is
expansive;
it
stretches
across
disciplines
and
resists
easy
categorisation.
The
broader
difficulty
of
situating
his
thinking
in
any
clear
disciplinary
framework
has
been
noted
many
times.72
It
is
therefore
also
in
an
effort
to
properly
theoretically
locate
his
work
that
the
discussion
of
his
intellectual
beginnings
becomes
important.
I
therefore
discuss
Rancière’s
71
James I (2012) 111.
72
See James I (2012) 111.
28
background
to
the
extent
that
it
informs
his
work
on
politics.
By
way
of
discussing
his
background,
I
begin
by
shortly
describing
Rancière’s
current
scholarly
influence
as
well
as
the
nature
of
his
engagements.
I
also
later
outline
the
political
events
that
transpired
during
the
month
of
May
in
1968
in
France.
These
events
had
an
immense
impact
on
Rancière.
The
upheavals
by
students
and
workers
during
that
time
crystallised
his
objections
to
Althusser’s
thought.
Much
of
Rancière’s
work
thereafter
can
partly
be
understood
as
an
attempt
to
give
discursive
form
to
the
idea
of
radical
equality
that
he
saw
as
implicit
in
the
events
of
May
1968.73
I
further
outline
some
of
the
main
characteristics
of
Althusser’s
project
on
Karl
Marx
in
order
to
allow
for
a
thorough
understanding
of
Rancière’s
reaction
against
Althusser.
The
first
section
is
therefore
an
attempt
to
theoretically
position
Rancière’s
work
by
exploring
and
explaining
his
current
impact,
his
intellectual
beginnings
under
Louis
Althusser
and
his
experiences
around
May
1968.
In
the
second
section,
I
discuss
and
explain
Rancière’s
notion
of
politics.
This
discussion
is
categorised
with
reference
to
five
elements
or
moments
within
his
definition
of
politics,
namely,
“the
police
order”,
“politics
(equality)”,
“the
political
subject”,
“the
miscount
and
the
wrong”
and
“the
distribution
of
the
sensible”.
These
elements
or
moments
in
Rancière’s
thinking
are
closely
related
and
interrelated.
Structuring
his
theorising
in
this
way
should
help
to
offer
a
clear
explanation
of
his
politics.74
I
work
from
the
premise
that
the
discussion
of
the
five
elements
of
his
politics,
considered
in
light
of
his
background,
will
provide
a
comprehensive
explanation
of
his
imaginative
formulation
of
politics.
The
description
of
his
engagement
with
certain
historical
figures
in
the
next
chapter
provides
a
detailed
picture
and
understanding
of
his
thought.
In
the
third
and
concluding
section
of
this
chapter,
I
reflect
on
the
meaning
of
voice
in
the
context
of
the
discussion
of
Rancière’s
politics.
I
contemplate
the
notion
of
voice
within
the
framework
of
his
accounts
and
consider
them
against
the
background
of
the
73
Davis O Jacques Rancière (2010) 1.
74
See for example Davis O (2010) as well as Tanke J (2011) who also broadly structure their
discussions of Rancière’s politics along the lines of these elements or aspects.
29
disconnect
between
the
formal
position
of
women
and
the
lived
realities
of
many
South
African
women
set
out
in
the
introductory
chapter.
2.2
Rancière’s
Background
2.2.1
Introduction
As
mentioned
in
the
introductory
chapter,
it
has
been
argued
that
Jacques
Rancière’s
philosophy
of
equality
represents
one
of
the
most
important
and
original
contributions
to
the
political
thought
of
the
late
twentieth
and
early
twenty-‐first
centuries.75
Rancière
is
now
in
his
eighth
decade
and
interest
in
his
work
has
never
been
greater.
Davis
notes
that
since
the
1970’s
Rancière
has
progressively
elaborated
his
intellectual
project
in
numerous
articles,
books,
lectures
and
interviews
ranging
over
a
daunting
number
of
disciplines.76
During
the
last
decade
several
high
profile
international
conferences
and
keynote
addresses
have
been
devoted
to
his
work.77
The
English
translation
of
his
book
Disagreement,
considered
to
be
his
most
important
work
on
politics,
resulted
in
numerous
articles
that
turned
into
a
steady
stream
of
special
issues,
symposia
and
edited
volumes.78
It
is
said
that
the
potential
of
Rancière’s
work
can
be
found
in
his
ability
and
willingness
to
treat
politics
anew
and
to
approach
the
question
of
politics
from
unexplored
angles.79
His
work
has
influenced,
echoed
and
demanded
critical
reaction
from
leading
intellectuals
such
as
Slavoj
Žižek80
and
Alain
Badiou.81
Rancière’s
corpus
extends
well
beyond
the
boundaries
of
traditional
philosophy
and
includes
engagements
with
the
fields
of
philosophy,
history,
politics,
sociology,
literary
theory,
literary
history,
pedagogy,
aesthetics,
art,
psychoanalysis
and
film
theory.
Although
Rancière
has
an
explicit
aversion
to
systematic
or
organised
philosophies
that
will
be
elaborated
on
later,
he
has
developed
a
robust
project
that
is
redefining
contemporary
thought
about
the
75
In this regard, see James I (2012) 110.
76
Davis O (2010) vii.
77
Davis O (2010) vii.
78
Rancière J Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy (1999) trans Rose J.
79
James I (2012) 110.
80
See Žižek S The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology (1999).
81
See Badiou A Metapolitics (2005) trans. Barker J.
30
complex
relationship
between
politics
and
aesthetics.82
Rockhill
and
Watts
note
that
if
his
reception
in
the
English-‐speaking
world
has
not
kept
pace
with
his
rise
to
prominence
in
France,
it
is
in
part
because
of
the
fact
that
his
idiosyncratic
work
does
not
fit
comfortably
within
dominant
models
and
models
of
intellectual
importation.83
He
is
still
at
times
mistakenly
classified
as
a
structuralist
theorist
because
of
his
early
contribution
to
Louis
Althusser’s
Lire
le
Capital.84
However,
as
mentioned,
he
became
one
of
Althusser’s
most
rigorous
critics.
His
first
book
La
Leçon
d’
Althusser
or
Althusser’s
Lesson
was
a
powerful
collection
of
essays
criticising
his
former
teacher.
Rockhill
and
Watts
further
explains
that
he
has
also
repeatedly
criticised
the
“discourse
of
mastery
and
the
logic
of
hidden
truths”
which
he
identifies
with
the
structuralist
project
reaching
back
to
Marx.85
He
82
See for example Rancière J Aesthetics and Its Discontents (2009) trans. Cocoran S and The
Emancipated Spectator (2009) trans. Elliot G.
83
Rockhill G & Watts P “Introduction: Rancière: Thinker of Dissensus” in Rockhill G & Watts P
(eds.) Jacques Rancière: History, Politics, Aesthetics (2009) 1.
84
Althusser L (ed.) Lire Capital (1996) originally published in 1965.
85
Rockhill G & Watts P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 1. See Rancière J La Leçon d’
Althusser (1973). Structuralism was one of the most influential theoretical movements in
twentieth century thought, especially French thought. It reached its height in the mid-1960’s
with the appearance of major collective studies of “narratology” (See Communications 1966),
the writings of Jacques Lacan, particularly Écrits (1966), Michel’s Foucault’s The Order of
Things (1966), Louis Atlhusser’s For Marx (1966) and Reading Capital by Althusser and Etienne
Balibar (1965). In general, as Macey explains, structuralism can be defined as an attempt to
unify the human sciences by applying a single model of methodology based on Saussurean
linguistics. Macey D Dictionary of Critical Theory (2000) 364-364. This general linguistic model
derives from Saussure’s insight that language is not a list of names of things, but a system of
signs consisting of a signifier (an acoustic image) and a signified (a concept). Macey D (2000)
364-365. Signs do not designate an external reality and are meaningful only because of the
similarities and differences between them. As Macey explains, the so-called Prague School
made a further significant contribution to the development of structuralism by introducing
the idea of functionalism, which is the idea that the meaning of linguistic units is the function
they perform within the system of language. Macey D (2000) 364-365. What becomes
pertinent in structuralism is that language is no longer seen as a means of expression at the
disposal of a speaking subject, but rather language, or the symbolic in Lacanian terms, is the
precondition for both thought and social existence. See further Culler J Structuralist Poetics:
Structuralism, Linguistics and the Study of Literature (1975). The proceedings of the John
Hopkins’ Conference on The Languages of Criticism and the Science of Man in October 1966,
marked the American “moment of structuralism”, though, it also became clear in retrospect
that the conference and especially Jacques Derrida’s contribution (“Structure Sign and Play in
the Discourse of Human Sciences”) inaugurated a critique of structuralism. Macey D (2000)
364-365. Derrida described deconstruction as a criticism of structuralism. Although it is
difficult to identify it with any specific school of thought, poststructuralism is usually
associated with the work of Deleuze, Foucault, Lyotard, Derrida, Baudrillard and Rorty. These
31
therefore
cannot
be
described
as
a
structuralist,
nor,
can
he
be
described
as
a
poststructuralist,
the
other
dominant
theoretical
movement
of
his
time
and
context.
86
It
even
becomes
difficult
to
decide
whether
Rancière
is
a
philosopher,
a
historian,
an
anti-‐philosopher,
or
an
archivist
of
popular
struggles.87
As
mentioned
in
chapter
one,
Rancière’s
work
introduces
irreversible
disturbances
in
the
fixed
demarcation
of
disciplines.88
The
boundaries
of
disciplines
are
blurred.
The
boundaries
between
the
sayable
and
unsayable,
the
proper
and
improper,
the
legitimate
and
illegitimate
are
all
dismantled.
Rancière
plays
with
the
intervals
between
various
discourses.
His
aim
is
always
to
derail
the
regimes
of
thought
“that
would
assign
certain
ways
of
doing,
speaking
and
seeing
to
a
stable
set
of
competences,
qualities,
or
properties.”89
It
might
be
precisely
the
fact
that
his
theorists can all be described as poststructuralists. Poststructuralism is often equated with
deconstruction and also with postmodernism in general, but, as Macey further explains, it can
also be seen as a strand within everything from “New Historicism” to postcolonial theory.
Macey D (2000) 364-365. The common core of these tendencies can be described as “a
reluctance to ground discourse in any theory of metaphysical origins, an insistence on the
inevitable plurality and instability of meaning, a distrust of systematic scientificity and the
abandoning of the Enlightenment project.” See Macey D (2000) 364-365.
86
See Rockhill G & Watts P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 2. As Rockhill and Watts
explains, Rancière cannot be described as either a structuralist or post-structuralist theorist,
the dominant theoretical movements of his time and context. Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.)
(2009) 2. Firstly, Rancière rejects the characteristic structuralist distinction between science
and ideology suggested by his former teacher Althusser (and which will be discussed in detail
below) and he also forcefully declared his distance from post-structuralists such as Gilles
Deleuze and Jean-Francois Lyotard. Rockhill and Watts further elucidates that Rancière has
been interested from the very beginning in developing a research agenda that broke with the
dominant intellectual paradigms of his student years, specifically structuralism. Rockhill G &
Watts P (eds.) (2009) 2. As mentioned, he also did not follow the lead of his poststructuralist
compatriots or “the philosophers of difference” as he describes them. See Tanke J (2011) 9.
There are a variety of different markers that distinguishes his work from that of post-
structuralists. These markers as Rockhill and Watts articulately summarises include: “his
aversion to compulsive textualism (visible in the general lack of quotations and his allergy to
etymology), his angst-free relationship with Hegel, his general indifference toward
phenomenology, his lack of deference to ethico-religious forms of alterity, his criticisms of the
ethical turn in politics, his disregard for the supposed spectres of metaphysics and the project
of deconstruction, and his intense commitment to history that has led him beyond the
canonical writers of the philosophic tradition”. See Rockhill G & Watts P in Rockhill G & Watts
P (eds.) (2009) 2.
87
See Bosteels B “Rancière’s Leftism, Or, Politics and Its Discontents” in Rockhill G & Watts P
(eds.) (2009) 160.
88
As above.
89
As above.
32
work
does
not
fit
comfortably
within
identifiable
intellectual
movements
that
makes
it
of
such
interest
today.
Rancière
has
developed
a
distinct
project
with
his
own
conceptual
framework
and
reading
and
writing
strategies.
His
work
maintains
a
sharp
polemical
edge
as
he
regularly
critically
engages
with
prevailing
assumptions
and
their
underlying
framework.
It
has
been
argued
that
he
is
a
thinker
of
dissensus
who
constantly
undermines
what
is
taken
to
be
the
solid
footing
of
previous
philosophic
work.90
Hallward
explains
that
some
of
the
most
consistent
aspects
of
his
thinking
are
the
affirmation
of
a
fundamental
inconsistency
and
instability
of
experience
as
well
as
a
refusal
of
any
gesture
of
authority
or
theoretical
mastery
that
seeks
to
categorise
and
maintain
experience
by
limiting
it
to
conventional
categories
or
disciplines.91
This
can
be
directly
related
to
the
difficulty
of
theoretically
positioning
Rancière’s
thought:
Rather
than
abandoning
philosophy
in
favour
of
another
discipline,
the
practice
of
writing
that
Rancière
develops
questions
the
protocols,
conventions
and
limits
which
would
allow
history,
philosophy,
political
philosophy
or
aesthetics
to
maintain
themselves
as
stable
categories.92
Rancière
states:
My
problem
has
always
been
to
escape
the
division
between
disciplines,
because
what
interests
me
is
the
question
of
distribution
of
territories,
which
is
always
a
way
of
deciding
who
is
qualified
to
speak
about
what.93
Below
I
elaborate
on
Rancière’s
relationship
with
Louis
Althusser.
2.2.2
Rancière
and
Althusser
Rancière
began
his
career
as
a
participant
in
Althusser’s
reading
group
on
Karl
Marx’s
Capital
that
was
held
between
January
and
April
1965
at
the
École
Normale
Supérieure
(ENS),
Rue
d’Ulm
in
Paris.
Tanke
notes
that
the
broader
environment
in
which
Rancière
began
his
career
was
marked
by
the
social
and
political
radicalism
which
grew
up
during
and
after
the
Algerian
war
and
which
resulted
in
90
See Tanke J (2011) 9.
91
See Hallward P “Jacques Rancière and the Subversion of Mastery” Paragraph: A Journal of
Modern Critical Theory (2005) 26.
92
James I (2012) 111.
93
Tanke J (2011) 9.
33
the
revolutionary
events
of
May
1968,
which
will
be
discussed
below.94
Rancière’s
intellectual
beginnings
can
be
situated
within
the
milieu
of
theoretical
and
structuralist
Marxism
of
which
Althusser
was
the
most
prominent
and
leading
proponent
at
the
time.95
The
influence
of
Althusser
on
the
French
philosophical
scene
of
the
1960’s
cannot
be
overestimated.
In
1948,
upon
passing
his
aggregation
in
philosophy,
Tanke
notes
that
Althusser
was
awarded
a
position
as
agrégé
répétiteur
at
ENS.96
As
one
of
Althusser’s
subsequent
roles
was
to
prepare
students
for
their
own
aggregation
in
philosophy,
he
participated
in
the
intellectual
formation
of
many
who
would
become
France’s
most
distinguished
intellectuals
in
the
twentieth
century.97
Althusser
also
played
a
crucial
role
in
opening
the
ENS
up
to
new
theoretical
perspectives,
such
as
linguistics,
Levi-‐
Strauss’
structural
anthropology
and
the
readings
of
Sigmund
Freud
pioneered
by
psychoanalyst,
Jacques
Lacan.98
Etienne
Balibar
has
stated
that
Althusser
made
the
ENS
“a
centre
for
philosophy
that
was
living
and
not
academic”
and
compared
the
atmosphere
to
“a
proper
philosophical
life”
in
the
sense
that
the
ancients
would
have
understood
it.99
Tanke
further
explains
that
Rancière
himself
fondly
recalled
the
“intellectual
dynamism”
centred
on
Althusser
and
credits
the
differences
he
articulated
with
phenomenology
as
offering
“a
kind
of
liberation
from
university
culture.”100
Althusser
made
the,
by
now,
famous
assertion
that
he
was
rereading
Karl
Marx
“as
a
philosopher”.101
He
contended
that
Marx’s
early
and
mature
works
were
separated
by
an
“epistemological
break”.102
Davis
explains
that
at
the
beginning
of
the
1960’s
Althusser
advanced,
by
way
of
a
series
of
journal
articles,
an
original,
94
As above.
95
As above.
96
Tanke J (2011) 10.
97
As above.
98
Tanke J (2011) 10.
99
As above.
100
As above.
101
Davis O (2010) 2.
102
As above.
34
albeit
idiosyncratic,
reading
of
Marx.103
His
reading
was
based
on
the
radical
break
between
Marx’s
early
ideological
writings
and
his
more
mature
scientific
project
of
Capital.104
This
break
is
also
known
as
the
science/ideology
distinction.105
Very
simply
put,
ideology
embodied
for
Althusser
all
those
forms
of
ideas,
understandings,
beliefs
and
values
which
allow
individuals
to
collectively
function
in
a
given
socio-‐economic
world
and
which
work
to
sustain
the
relations
of
power
and
domination
which
underpin
that
socio
economic
order.106
In
this
context,
personal
beliefs
or
attitudes
(religious
values
or
shared
social
discourse
for
example)
are
seen
to
be
a
function
of
ideology
and
part
of
the
process
in
which
individuals
are
“interpellated”
as
the
subjects
of
ideology.107
Importantly,
much
of
what
can
be
regarded
as
philosophy
or
political
theory
is
also
a
product
of
ideology,
which
is
an
imaginary
construct
or
relation
that
conceals
actually
existing
constructs
and
relations.108
James
notes
that
as
opposed
to
ideology,
Althusser
proposed
his
specific
understanding
of
Marxist
science.109
Althusser
contended
that
Marx’s
early
writings
were
tainted
by
their
reliance
on
the
vocabulary
of
German
Idealism
that
prevented
the
development
of
a
scientific
understanding
of
social,
political
and
economic
reality.110
Therefore,
according
to
103
As above.
104
As above.
105
Tanke J (2011) 11. See Althusser L & Balibar E Lire Le Capital (1968).
106
James I (2010) 114.
107
As above. “Interpellation” refers to the mechanism that produces subjects in such a way
that they recognise their own existence in terms of the dominant ideology of the society that
they live in. See Macey D (2000) 203. In French it is commonly used to mean, “being taken in
by the police for questioning” or it can also refer to questioning a minister of parliament. See
Macey D (2000) 203. Macey mentions that Althusser’s basic illustration of the mechanism
exploits the sense of “questioning” or “haling”. See Macey D (2000) 203. An individual
walking down the street is hailed by a police officer- “Hey, you there!” and turns round to
recognise the fact that he is being addressed. In doing so, that individual is constituted as
subject. According to Althusser the idea of interpellation demonstrates that subjects are
always already products of ideology and thus subverts the idealist thesis that subjectivity is
primarily self-founding. See Macey D (2000) 203. See also Althusser L Lenin and Philosophy
and Other Essays (1971) trans. Brewster B.
108
As above.
109
James I (2012) 114. For Althusser, as James explains, scientific knowledge is not ideology,
attitude or opinion. It is a theoretical practice that identifies the actually existing structures
which, behind the veil of ideological appearance, underpin social, economic and historical
forms. James I (2012) 114.
110
Davis O (2010) 2.
35
Althusser,
as
Tanke
elucidates,
the
later
works
belonged
to
a
fundamentally
different
“problematic”,
the
term
he
used
for
the
general
conceptual
framework
in
which
concepts
gain
their
meaning
and
applicability.111
He
argued
that
all
sciences
begin
with
a
phase
in
which
the
world
is
understood
from
a
perspective
positioned
around
human
nature
and
concrete
particular
facts;
and
it
is
only
after
an
epistemological
break
with
this
early
phase
that
abstract
and
so-‐called
proper
scientific
conceptual
knowledge
of
the
world
become
possible.112
Althusser
contended
that
Marx’s
work
after
1845,
specifically
Capital,
was
not
continuous
with
his
work
of
the
early
period,
but
rather
constituted,
as
Davis
explains,
a
radical
break
with
it.113
He
suggested
that
Capital
was
a
theoretical
revolution
and
that
it
made
possible
knowledge
of
the
world
as
it
really
is.
This
he
termed
“Marxist
science”.
Marx’s
early
work,
by
contrast,
represented
an
inferior,
pre-‐
scientific
form
of
understanding
that
he
accordingly
termed
“ideology”.
Ideology
attempted
to
explain
the
world
in
terms
of
human
nature
and
could
therefore
also
be
characterised
as
“humanist”
and
“anthropological”.114
Belief
in
“the
break”
is
a
hallmark
of
Althusserianism.
Davis
explains
that
non-‐Althusserian
Marxists
tend
not
to
think
that
there
is
such
a
pronounced
rupture
or
break,
although
many
would
acknowledge
that
there
is
a
discernable
movement
away
from
explanation
in
human
terms
toward
more
abstract,
theoretical
formulations.115
Tanke
notes
that
in
For
Marx,
Althusser
suggested
that
Marx’s
thought
could
be
categorised
according
to
the
following
schema:
1840-‐44:
early
works,
1845:
the
works
of
the
break,
1845-‐57:
transitional
works,
1857-‐83:
mature
works.116
The
science/ideology
distinction
is
central
to
nearly
all
Althusser’s
thought
and
much
of
his
work
consisted
in
properly
separating
the
scientific
notions
from
the
remnants
of
idealism
that
he
thought
hampered
or
limited
Marx’s
thought.117
An
example
of
the
more
humanist
writings
can
be
seen
in
111
Tanke J (2011) 11.
112
Davis O (2010) 2.
113
As above.
114
Davis O (2010) 2. See Althusser L & Balibar E (1970) 17.
115
As above.
116
Tanke J (2011) 12. See Althusser L (1971) 40.
117
As above. As Tanke explains, according to Althusser, the rupture must be continually
produced if Marx’s thought was no to lapse into the speculative thought that preceded it.
36
Marx’s
early
account
of
the
way
in
which
factory
workers
are
alienated
by
their
work.
These
writings,
as
Tanke
explains,
centred
on
the
human
worker
and
the
way
in
which
his
work
gave
rise
to
feelings
of
being
divided
from
himself
and
from
his
fellow
workers
as
well
as
from
the
object
that
he
is
producing.118
“Alienation”,
in
this
early
sense,
is
a
form
of
unhappiness,
a
psychological
feeling
of
being
divided
from
oneself.119
As
Davis
illuminates,
the
first
nine
chapters
of
Capital
on
the
other
hand,
begins
with
a
very
abstract
exposition
of
economic
concepts
such
as
“commodity”,
“value”
and
“labour”.120
The
logic
of
Marx’s
approach
here
suggests
that
these
concepts
are
necessary
if
the
underlying
mechanisms
that
account
for
the
real
basis
of
feelings
of
alienation
are
to
be
understood.121
Therefore,
as
Davis
elucidates,
in
Capital,
the
alienating
effects
of
work
can
only
be
understood
properly
in
terms
of
the
structure
of
the
economic
relations
in
the
society
in
question.122
These
relations
are
not
immediately
accessible
however.
They
cannot
be
perceived
or
discerned
by
the
factory
worker,
as
he
or
she
requires
a
developed
theoretical
understanding
of
the
underlying
economic
processes
and
structures.123
Marx
was,
according
to
Althusser,
a
voracious
and
remarkably
perceptive
reader.124
Althusser
suggested
that
Marx,
in
Capital,
could
be
seen
as
undertaking
See Tanke J (2011) 12. Activating this break therefore involved scratching Marx’s corpus of
concepts such as “labour”, “alienation”, “consciousness”, “species-being”, and the vague
anthropology they refer to. Tanke J (2011) 12. Althusser can be read as attempting to
distance Marxism from the humanist platform espoused by the French Communist Party and
he also worked to undermine its attempt to find common ground with socialists, social
democrats and the Catholic left. Tanke J (2011) 12. His strategy involved distancing Marx from
his predecessors. He, for example, as Tanke explains, opposed the interpretation applied by
Marx and Engels themselves, according to which historical materialism would be Hegelianism
in inverted form. Tanke J (2011) 12-13. Althusser contended that readers should take seriously
the famous thesis of Marx (XIth on Feuerbach) in which philosophy was condemned for only
having merely interpreted the world.
118
Tanke J (2011) 13.
119
Davis O (2010) 3.
120
As above.
121
As above.
122
As above.
123
As above.
124
As above.
37
two
distinctive
types
of
reading.125
The
second
type
of
reading
is
the
reading
that
interested
Althusser.
Davis
explains
this
type
of
reading
in
the
following
way:
Althusser
suggested
that
when
Marx
reads
the
work
of
the
economist
Adam
Smith
for
example,
Marx
discerned
that
Smith’s
theory
had
hit
upon
a
correct
answer
to
a
question
which
Smith
himself
had
not
known
how
to
formulate,
but
which
Marx
was
able
to
pose
openly
and
explicitly.126
Marx
started
by
handling
as
questions
what
bourgeois
political
economists
saw
as
solutions.
As
Davis
notes,
his
method
consisted
of
working
through
the
blind
spots
in
their
writings
in
order
to
supply
concepts
for
the
economic
phenomena
that
they
left
unexplained.127
Marx,
for
example,
applies
the
name
“surplus-‐value”
to
what
Smith
could
think
of
only
as
profit,
rent
and
interest.128
While
Marx
was
not
the
first
to
isolate
this
concept,
Althusser
contends
that
he
was
the
first
to
handle
it
properly,
using
it
to
reconstruct
“the
causal
nexus
to
which
it
belongs”.129
Tanke
explains
that
after
identifying
“surplus-‐value”
as
the
key
explanation
of
capital,
Marx
used
it
to
elaborate
the
entirety
of
the
capitalist
mode
of
production,
which
is
itself
viewed
as
a
historically
variable
system
of
effects.130
Importantly,
for
Althusser,
this
understanding
of
the
mode
of
production
is
what
allowed
Marx
to
describe
capitalism’s
distinct
form
of
structural
causality,
or
the
manner
in
which
the
capitalist
system
is
determined
by
“the
reciprocal
functioning
of
economic,
political,
ideological
and
scientific
components”.131
The
scientificity
of
Marx’s
analysis
thus
results
from
the
“identification
of
a
concept-‐problem
and
the
rigorous
analysis
of
the
causal
system
to
which
it
belongs”.132
Althusser
termed
125
See Althusser L & Balibar E (1970) 19-21.
126
Davis O (2010) 3.
127
As above.
128
Tanke J (2011) 13.
129
As above.
130
As above.
131
As above.
132
As above. It should be mentioned here that Rancière’s marked difference from
structuralism and post-structuralism can also be seen in his approach to writing and reading.
Rancière describes his break from Althusser in terms of a shift away from a hermeneutic
reading of texts towards a more affirmative view of language. He moved away from a critique
based on the “Saussurian distinction between la langue and la parole”, the distinction
between underlying, unconscious structures and the cultural, social, political and other texts
that are determined by those structures. See Arsenjuk L “On Jacques Rancière” Fronesis
38
this
type
of
reading
“symptomatic”
and
in
doing
so
he
aligned
Marx
with
a
kind
of
psychoanalyst
whose
therapy
comprised
of
helping
the
analyst
to
formulate
the
problem
that
lies
beneath
the
surface
manifestation
that
is
his
or
her
symptom.133
In
other
words,
to
read
Marx
“as
a
philosopher”
meant
reading
his
text
as
a
psychoanalyst,
taking
what
it
says
on
the
surface
to
be
a
mere
symptom
of
its
underlying
meaning.134
Althusser’s
intention
was
to
explicitly
theoretically
formulate
this
underlying
meaning
of
the
philosophy
of
Marx,
which
he
thought
was
implemented
but
not
stated
explicitly
in
Capital.
He
thereby
applied
Marx’s
form
of
reading
to
his
own
work.135
Davis
explains
that
Marx’s
philosophy,
according
to
Althusser,
was
a
theory
of
history
as
ultimately
determined
by
relationships
of
material
production.136
This
theory
is
also
sometimes
called
“dialectical
materialism”.137
Althusser
described,
as
Tanke
explains,
the
symptomatic
method
of
reading
as
“restoring
to
the
text
its
unconscious”.138
Symptomatic
reading
conceives
of
a
theoretical
text
as
“the
necessary
combination
of
sightings,
lacks
and
oversights
whose
relationships
it
attempts
to
make
explicit”.139
It
begins
with
“present
terms,
identifies
the
absent
concepts
upon
which
the
text
nevertheless
relies,
and
attempts
to
reconstruct
the
mechanism
their
interactions
bespeak”.140
With
respect
to
Capital
this
involves
attending
to
those
analyses
that
exploit,
but
do
(2005) 1. This comes down to a distancing from any kind of reading based on suspicion of the
meaning of texts towards embracing an approach that is more affirmative of the surface of
text itself. Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 1-2. It will hopefully become clear later that for Rancière
the surface of texts does not hide what is underlying, but becomes a scene on which the
creativity and effectiveness of language games and speech acts are demonstrated. In
Rancière’s approach speech acts are not understood as ideological artefacts, but precisely as
acts or political gestures that are in themselves capable of reconfiguring the situation in which
they are enunciated. See Arsenjuk L “On Jacques Rancière” Fronesis (2005) 1. Published in
English on 2007/03/05 available online at Eurozine Journals www.eurozine.com/ articles/2007-
01-01-arsenjuk-en.html (accessed 28-12-2014).
133
Davis O (2010) 3.
134
As above
135
As above.
136
As above.
137
As above.
138
Tanke J (2011) 14.
139
As above.
140
As above
39
not
explicitly
articulate
philosophical
concepts.
The
symptomatic
reading
of
Capital
therefore
“attempts
to
reconstruct
the
theoretical
problematic
to
which
it
belongs,
while
distinguishing
it
from
the
ideological
problematic
from
which
it
departs”.141
The
project
of
dividing
a
line
between
science
and
ideology
is
the
obligation
that
Althusser
assigns
to
philosophical
practice:
Philosophy
represents
people’s
class
struggle
in
theory.
In
return
it
helps
the
people
to
distinguish
in
theory
and
in
all
ideas
(political,
ethical,
aesthetic
etc.)
between
true
and
false
ideas.142
It
is
important
to
note
that
Althusser
could
not
imagine
a
society
without
ideology.
As
Tanke
further
explains,
even
a
classless
society
will
rely
on
it
for
achieving
social
integration.143
It
is
therefore
necessary
for
philosophy
to
separate
the
truth
of
economic,
political
and
scientific
practices
from
their
so-‐called
mystifications.144
As
Tanke
elucidates,
philosophy
is
class
struggle
in
theory
to
the
extent
that
it
prevents
knowledge
from
being
exploited
by
bourgeois
tendencies.145
Philosophy
has
for
Althusser
an
indispensable
part
to
play
in
politics:
the
education
of
those
immersed
in
the
economic
sector.146
Althusser,
as
mentioned,
applied
Marx’s
symptomatic
mode
of
reading
to
his
own
major
text
in
Reading
Capital
and
in
doing
so
Althusser
claimed
to
be
formulating
Marx’s
philosophy
in
theoretical
terms.147
Davis
states:
The
understanding
of
Marx’s
philosophy
thus
obtained
from
Capital
was
to
be
supplemented
by
an
analysis
of
revolutionary
struggle:
like
Marx’s
masterwork,
revolutionary
movements
were
thought
to
be
practical
enactments
of
Marxists
philosophy
in
which
it
was
Althusser’s
self-‐
appointed
task
to
read
the
theory.
For
Althusser,
books
and
revolutionary
movements
alike
were
deemed
susceptible
to
his
eclectic
mix
of
self-‐
assertingly
philosophical
and
notionally
psychoanalytic
analysis.148
Davis
further
notes
that
the
attraction
of
Althusser’s
enterprise
for
Rancière
and
a
whole
generation
of
activists
on
the
Left
can
partly
be
explained
by
the
political
141
As above.
142
See Althusser L (1971) 21.
143
Tanke J (2011) 14.
144
As above.
145
As above.
146
Davis O (2010) 4.
147
As above.
148
Davis O (2010) 4.
40
climate
of
the
time.149
During
the
1960’s
it
became
clear
to
most
that
the
Soviet
Union
under
Stalin
had
become
a
brutally
oppressive
police
state.
Althusser’s
objective
was
to
find
in
Marx’s
thinking
the
principle
of
a
theoretical
understanding
of
Marxism’s
aberrations.
It
was
suggested
that
only
a
correct
understanding
of
the
true
meaning
of
Marx’s
philosophy
could
serve
as
a
reliable
guide
to
political
action
and
as
a
safeguard
against
those
aberrations.150
Revolutionary
political
practice
without
the
correct
theory
was
felt
to
be
“doomed
to
the
short-‐sighted
pursuit
of
ill-‐understood
goals”.151
Althusser’s
theory
further
held
a
particular
appeal
to
activists
on
the
Left
who
were
also
intellectuals
as
it
seemed
to
transcend
the
distinction
between
theory
and
practice
by
redefining
the
kind
of
intellectual
work
undertaken
in
lecture
halls
as
a
form
of
political
action,
or
“theoretical
practice”.152
Rancière:
“We
found
in
Althusser’s
work
the
idea
that
intellectuals
could
have
a
different
role,
one
other
than
cultural
consumption
or
ideological
reflection:
real
involvement
as
intellectuals
in
transforming
the
world”.153
The
fact
that
this
was
a
false
hope
and
that
theoretical
practice
was
“something
of
a
sleight
of
hand”,
as
Davis
describes
it,
only
became
clear
to
Rancière
after
the
events
of
May
1968,
which
shall
be
discussed
below.154Althusser’s
approach
therefore
promised
Marxist
intellectuals
a
significant
role
in
the
revolution
as
intellectuals.
Importantly,
as
Davis
further
explains,
it
also
set
the
interpretation
of
Marx’s
work
free
from
the
authority
of
the
French
Communist
Party
(FCP)
whose
support
of
Stalin
in
the
fifties
lead
to
a
forceful
de-‐Stalinisation
in
the
sixties.155
With
this,
the
party’s
commitment
to
violent
revolutionary
struggle
had
transformed
into
support
for
the
pursuit
of
social
change
through
democratic
means.156
The
most
damaging
to
the
party
was
their
support,
during
the
Algerian
War
of
Independence,
for
the
Socialist
Prime
minister
Guy
Mollet’s
1956-‐Bill
that
granted
special
powers
to
the
governor
of
149
Davis O (2010) 5.
150
As above.
151
See Davis O (2010) 5.
152
Davis O (2010) 6.
153
Rancière J (1974) (passage translated by Davis O (2010) 6).
154
Davis O (2010) 6.
155
As above.
156
As above.
41
Algeria
thereby
effectively
establishing
a
police
state
and
by
doing
so,
seriously
compromising
revolution
and
liberation.157
As
Davis
notes,
it
was
therefore
no
surprise
that
the
idea
that
Althusser’s
theory
could
free
the
interpretation
of
Marx
from
the
interpretive
authority
of
the
party
was
attractive
to
leftist
activists,
activists
who
positioned
themselves
to
the
left
of
the
FCP.158
As
noted
by
Rancière,
“Marx’s
theory
belonged
to
nobody
but
his
readers
and
their
only
duty
was
to
it
[…]
Everyone
could
read
Marx
and
see
what
followed.
All
that
was
required
was
for
them
to
approach
the
text
through
the
discipline
of
science”.
159
However,
as
Davis
further
mentions,
the
practice
proved
to
be
less
emancipatory
than
many
students
had
hoped
for.
Behind
the
discipline
of
science
lay
another
form
of
authority,
that
of
pedagogical
authority.160
And
as
shall
be
seen
later,
with
the
discussion
of
Joseph
Jacocot
in
Rancière’s
book,
The
Ignorant
School
Master,
this
is
highly
problematic
for
Rancière
and
key
elements
of
his
theory,
especially
his
conception
of
equality,
can
be
seen
as
a
reaction
to
the
idea
of
pedagogical
authority
experienced
by
him
during
these
years.161
This
pedagogical
authority
was
related
to
the
fact
that
the
art
of
symptomatic
reading
was
not
open
to
all.
Apart
from
investment
of
effort
and
attention
it
required
instruction.
As
stated
by
Althusser
“[w]e
need
something
quite
different
from
an
acute
attentive
gaze;
we
need
an
educated
gaze”.162
Davis
explains
that
Marxist
science
had
been
set
free
from
the
authority
of
the
party,
to
become
dependent
on
the
authority
of
the
pedagogue.163
This
is
why
Rancière’s
repudiation
of
Althusser
is
entitled
“Althusser’s
Lesson”
and
why,
as
Davis
further
notes,
at
key
junctures,
it
frames
Rancière’s
argument
against
Althusser
as
an
argument
against
pedagogy.164
For
Rancière,
Althusserianism
is
“fundamentally
a
157
Davis O (2010) 6.
158
As above.
159
As above. See Rancière J (1974) 20 (passage translated by Davis O (2010) 6).
160
Davis O (2010) 7.
161
Rancière J (1991).
162
Althusser L (1970) 27.
163
Davis O (2010) 7.
164
As above.
42
theory
of
education”
and
“every
theory
of
education
strives
to
maintain
the
source
of
the
power
it
seeks
to
shed
light
on”.165
Althusser
suggested
that
only
by
a
correct
understanding
of
theory
would
a
political
practice
that
avoided
the
so-‐
called
aberrations
of
Stalinism
and
the
compromises
of
democratic
socialism
be
possible.166
For
Rancière,
Althusser’s
investment
in
the
privileged
position
of
the
pedagogue
meant
that
it
would
never
be
time
for
his
students
to
fulfil
the
promise
of
political
action:
“It
followed
from
the
logic
of
Althusserian
discourse
that
the
moment
would
never
come:
the
antagonistic
struggle
of
empirical
politics
would
never
allow
philosophy
the
opportunity
to
conclude”.167
Although
Althusserianism
seemed
to
be
at
the
forefront
of
progressive
Left
discourse,
as
Davis
highlights,
Rancière
came
to
the
conclusion
that
it
functioned
in
accordance
with
a
“pedagogical
temporality
of
delay”.168
The
time
to
act
would
therefore
never
come;
the
inequalities
that
were
to
be
eliminated
would
always
remain
in
place.
Rancière
viewed
Althusserianism
as
an
“endlessly
procrastinating
process
of
instruction”.169
It
served
only
to
emphasise
the
inequality
between
the
instructed
and
those
unschooled
in
Marxist
science
and
therefore
the
importance
and
authority
of
the
teacher.
It
should
also
be
mentioned
that
Althusserianism
asserted
itself
at
a
time
when
higher
education
in
France
was
subject
to
an
intense
debate
that
ultimately
culminated
in
the
liberation
of
curricula,
the
creation
of
several
new
universities
and
an
influx
of
students
from
backgrounds
traditionally
under-‐represented
in
French
Universities.170
As
Tanke
explains,
the
changes
eventually
put
in
place
were
largely
the
result
of
the
demands
made
by
students
throughout
the
1960’s
and
it
was
in
this
sense
that
Althusserianism
functioned
as
a
call
to
order
addressed
to
students.171
During
this
time,
students
were
questioning
the
university’s
position
165
Rancière J (1974) 104.
166
Davis O (2010) 7.
167
Rancière J (1974) 104.
168
Davis O (2010) 7.
169
As above.
170
Tanke J (2011) 17-18.
171
As above.
43
within
the
capitalist
system.172
They
were
politicising
forms
of
instruction
as
well
as
the
power
relations
inherent
in
traditional
pedagogy.173
Althusserianism
attempted
to
“defuse
these
institutional
critiques
by
shifting
the
investigation
from
the
forms
of
power
at
issue
in
the
student-‐teacher
relationship
to
a
discussion
about
the
content
of
courses
themselves”.174
The
science/ideology
distinction
transformed
debates
about
social
functions
and
procedures
into
assessment
of
whether
or
not
the
knowledge
was
properly
materialist.
However,
Althusserianism
masked
the
novelty
of
student
demands,
displacing
critique
of
practices
into
the
realm
of
ideas.
Not
only
did
this
gesture
forestall
a
serious
reckoning
with
institutionalised
forms
of
domination,
it
quietly
laid
the
groundwork
for
a
pedagogical
space
in
which
philosophy
could
be
awarded
pride
of
place.175
In
Rancière’s
view
the
idea
that
Althusserianism
allowed
its
supporters
to
claim
that
theory
itself
was
class
struggle,
amounts
to
a
shell
game
in
which
the
revolution
continually
“recedes
behind
the
endless
development
of
science”.176
Rancière
has
explained
that
the
book-‐length
publication
of
Althusser’s
Lesson
in
1974
was
made
pressing
by
a
renaissance
of
Althusserianism,
attempting
to
recapture
the
events
of
May
‘68.177
The
book
describes
how
Althusser’s
“theoreticist”
assumptions,
predicated
upon
a
sharp
divide
between
those
who
think
and
those
who
act
forecloses
possibilities
of
human
emancipation.178
Throughout
the
book,
Rancière
rejects
any
conception
of
philosophy
premised
on
the
idea
that
some
are
capable
of
thought
while
others
are
not.179
As
will
be
demonstrated
later,
this
notion
or
idea
becomes
central
to
Rancière’s
politics.
For
Althusser,
revolutionary
education
“must
have
a
rigorously
defined
object,
unfold
with
a
carefully
defined
methodology,
and
be
officiated
over
by
those
172
As above.
173
As above.
174
As above.
175
As above.
176
As above.
177
Tanke J (2011) 18.
178
As above.
179
As above.
44
possessing
specialised
training”.180
Tanke
mentions
that
Althusserian
students
were
famous
for
their
insistence
that
the
“theoretical
formation”
was
a
precondition
for
political
militancy.181
The
science/ideology
distinction
institutes
a
division
into
the
sphere
of
practices,
separating
the
learned
from
those
absorbed
by
ideology.
This
secures
the
necessity
of
scholars
in
general
and
university
theoreticians
in
particular.
For
Rancière,
as
mentioned,
this
attitude
reserves
a
place
for
philosophy
at
the
top
of
the
division
of
labour.
Rancière:
“The
challenge
is
clear:
it
is
a
question
of
saving
philosophy,
and
‘Marxist
philosophy’
in
particular,
as
the
business
of
university
specialists”.182
And
as
Tanke
explains
[l]ike
its
Platonic
forbearer,
Althusserianism
presents
itself
as
indispensable
for
discerning
between
true
and
false
ideas,
that
is,
the
directives
of
science
and
the
petit-‐bourgeois
tendencies
threatening
to
take
hold
of
the
worker’s
movement.
It
is
here
that
philosophy
finds
its
justification,
for
as
long
as
men
and
women
misjudge
the
shadows
in
the
cave
wall,
they
will
require
philosophers
to
guide
their
politics.183
Philosophy
therefore
struggles
on
behalf
of
the
non-‐ideological
concepts
produced
by
science,
using
them
to
clarify
political
thought
and
action.
Tanke
further
explains
that
theory’s
“clear-‐sightedness”
is
predicated
upon
its
conscious
removal
from
the
spheres
of
economic
and
political
practice.
It
provides
those
engaged
with
the
reality
of
what
they
cannot
see
because
of
their
position
within
the
division
of
labour.184
What
was
therefore
alarming
for
Rancière
was
that
Althusserianism
requires
the
masses
to
wallow
in
ideology.185
Althusser
opposed
any
practices
of
what
can
be
called
“auto-‐emancipation”.186
He
assumed
that
popular
movements
are
limited
by
degrees
of
incapacity,
therefore
requiring
the
formation
of
a
theoretical
avant-‐
garde.187
For
him,
the
class
struggle
unfolds
transparently
and
therefore
relies
180
Tanke J (2011) 19.
181
As above.
182
Rancière J (1974) 35.
183
Tanke J (2011) 20.
184
As above.
185
As above.
186
As above.
187
As above.
45
upon
science
to
clarify
its
stakes.188
Tanke
explains
that
Rancière,
in
contrast,
assumes
that
practices
are
relatively
evident
to
those
engaged
in
them.189
He
even
suggests
that
economic
exploitation
and
political
domination
require
little
explanation
to
those
who
are
subjected
to
it.
He,
as
will
be
elucidated
in
the
discussion
of
his
mature
politics
below,
turns
his
critical
efforts
against
those
discourses
that
benefit
from
postulating
truths
in
an
effort
to
redistribute
the
field
of
capacities.190
Davis
explains
that
for
Althusser,
the
Marxist
truth
of
things
does
not
lie
on
the
surface
waiting
to
be
discovered
by
the
attentive
reader.191
It
is
rather,
as
Davis
further
explains,
the
educated
reader,
schooled
in
the
art
of
symptomatic
reading
that
delves
beneath
the
surface
in
order
to
find
and
formulate
the
latent
188
As above.
189
As above.
190
As above. It should be mentioned that although it has rightly been remarked that
Rancière’s reaction against Althusserianism borders on the extreme, as Davis notes, it is also
multifaceted. Davis O (2010) 12-13. Davis identifies four aspects of Althusserianism, which he
argues are preserved in Rancière’s project. Davis O (2010) 12-13. For the purposes of my
discussion I refer to the aspect with regards to Rancière’s style. Davis explains two marks that
can broadly be termed Althusser’s philosophical style that are reflected in Rancière’s work.
Davis O (2010) 12-13. According to Davis, Althusser, by reading Marx “as a philosopher” and
thereby, as he put it, “redressing one hundred and twenty years of censorship by silence
within the university”, provided a model for displacing philosophy which is echoed by
Rancière in the 1970’s when Rancière, as lecturer in philosophy at Vincennes, used the
academic freedom accorded to him to immerse himself and his student Alain Faure in the
archives of the nineteenth century French worker’s movement and read them “as
philosophers”. See Davis O (2010) 12-13. For all Althusser’s rhetoric of disciplinary rigour and
systematicity, he also offered an early lesson in ”indiscipline” or “anti-disciplinarity”. For
Davis, the intellectual and political potential of this approach is demonstrated in an
unparalleled fashion in Rancière’s work. Davis O (2010) 12-13. Davis further explains that the
second vestige of Althusser’s philosophical style exhibited in Rancière’s work is what has
been called Althusser’s “declarative” conception of philosophy, which Rancière adopted to
some extent. Davis O (2010) 12-13. The philosopher’s task is to “present his theses”. Some of
Rancière’s more schematic work, for example his assertion of the separation between politics
and the police order that will be explained later in this chapter, or the periodisation of the
history of literature and art, exhibits, according to Davis, a decidedly Althusserian inclination
for declaring the existence of lines of demarcation and seeing what follows. Davis O (2010)
12-13. Davis argues that these observations are in no way an argument of Rancière’s work as
derivative of Althusser’s in any reductive sense. Davis O (2010) 12-13. Rather, he demonstrates
that the relationship between the two thinkers is more involved than cursory readings would
suggest. See Davis O (2010) 12-14.
191
Davis O (2010) 13.
46
theoretical
question.192
The
specialists
in
symptomatic
reading,
namely,
the
Althusserian
intellectuals
engaged
in
this
work
of
theoretical
practice,
would
then
instruct
the
proletariat,
the
ordinary
men
and
women,
in
correct
political
action.193
The
intellectual
thus
stands
in
a
“one-‐way
pedagogical
relationship”
to
the
proletariat.194
The
public
is
condemned
to
spontaneous
practice,
rather
than
being
engaged
in
real
revolutionary
action.
Rancière
states:
The
“masses”
make
history,
no
doubt
about
it,
but
not
just
any
masses:
those
which
we
educate
and
organise.
They
only
make
history
if
they
first
understand
that
they
are
separated
from
it
by
a
thick
layer
of
“dominant
ideology”
by
all
of
those
stories
the
bourgeoisie
tell
them
and
which,
stupid
as
they
are,
they
would
always
swallow
hook,
line
and
sinker
if
we
weren’t
there
to
teach
them
how
to
tell
good
ideas
from
bad
ones.195
Thus,
Althusserianism
is
for
Rancière
a
condescending
philosophy,
which
protects
the
social
privilege
of
those
institutionally
associated
with
it.
As
Davis
notes,
the
tone
in
the
passage
above
is
almost
visceral.
Rancière’s
response
to
Althusserianism
is
less
of
a
critique
and
rather
almost
a
“violent
allergic
reaction”.196
Rancière’s
approach,
as
will
be
discussed
later,
is
founded
upon
the
assumption
of
radically
equal
capacities.
Central
to
his
thesis
is
that
one
cannot
start
with
inequality
and
work
progressively
towards
its
elimination.
Equality
in
Rancière’s
approach
is
a
“presupposition,
an
axiom,
or
it
is
nothing”.197
Rancière
contends
that
politics
is
not
hampered
by
a
lack
of
knowledge,
the
mal-‐
information
of
the
marginalised
classes
or
the
inopportunity
of
the
moment,
but
rather
by
the
failure
to
embody,
in
advance,
the
equality
we
want
to
bring
into
a
context.198
For
him,
nothing
is
more
troubling
than
the
contention
that
the
world
is
divisible
on
the
basis
of
intellectual
capacities,
the
fact
that
some
can
draw
lines
and
erect
hierarchies,
whether
between
theory
or
practice,
or
between
science
and
ideology,
intellectuals
and
workers.199
192
As above.
193
As above.
194
As above.
195
Rancière J (1974) 34 (passage translated by Davis O (2010) 13).
196
Davis O (2010) 13.
197
Rancière J The Philosopher and His Poor (2004) 223.
198
Davis O (2010) 14.
199
As above.
47
Rancière,
as
a
student
of
Althusser,
initially
contributed
to
Reading
Capital.200
The
contribution
entitled
“The
Concept
of
Critique
and
the
Critique
of
Political
Economy
from
the
1844
Manuscripts
of
Capital”
followed
immediately
after
Althusser’s
prefatory
essay.
Rancière’s
contribution
was
a
compliant
rehearsal
of
Althusserian
doctrine.
As
Davis
mentions,
Rancière’s
contribution
is
extreme
in
its
Althusserian
orthodoxy
because
it
emphasises
the
opacity
of
the
world
to
ordinary
perception
and
because
it
holds
that
only
symptomatic
reading
can
result
in
a
reliable
understanding
of
the
world.201
It
is
important
to
mention
that
Rancière’s
transition
from
compliant
student
to
outspoken
critic
of
Althusser
did
not
happen
in
a
vacuum.
Mao’s
Cultural
Revolution
that
was
at
its
height
in
the
period
between
1965
and
1968,
and
the
near
revolution
in
France
in
May
’68,
both
applied
pressure
on
young
Althusserians.202
The
Cultural
Revolution
questioned
the
social
and
institutional
privilege
accorded
to
scholars,
teachers
and
bureaucrats
by
virtue
of
their
knowledge
and
education,
whilst
May
’68
began
as
a
student
revolt
and
it
questioned
the
power
and
processes
of
pedagogy.
May
’68
saw
students
and
factory
workers
engage
in
revolutionary
action
without
guidance
from
the
FCP.203
On
the
contrary,
the
FCP
was
instrumental
in
ending
it.
In
this
context
Althusserian
science
and
the
FCP
became
redundant.
Rancière:
“Althusserianism
met
its
death
on
the
barricades
of
May
along
with
many
other
ideas
of
the
past”.204
Althusser,
however,
did
not
seem
to
realise
this.
As
Davis
notes,
even
before
publishing
his
excoriating
repudiation,
Althusser’s
Lesson,
Rancière
had
already
written
a
sceptical
book
and
an
article
in
which
he
described
200
See Davis O (2010) 4. Davis notes that Rancière’s essay followed at least within the first
edition of 1965. Davis O (2010) 4. The textual history of Rancière’s piece reflects his
relationship with Althusser. The second French edition at the end of 1968 contained only
Atlhusser’s and Balibar’s contributions. Davis O (2010) 4. In his preface to that edition,
Althusser rather insultingly remarks that the new edition is “improved” (p xii) and that the
omissions in no way damage the integrity of the interpretation of Marx’s works being put
forward. Davis O (2010) 4. In 1973, Althusser and his publisher wanted to reprint the first
edition in its entirety. Rancière requested that his contribution be preceded by a prefatory
autocritique, but Althusser refused. Davis explains that the autocritique was published
separately. Davis O (2010) 4.
201
As above.
202
Davis O (2010) 20.
203
As above.
204
As above.
48
Althusser’s
work
as
“reactionary”
and
labelled
his
own
contribution
to
Reading
Capital
as
“rustic”
because
of
the
crudeness
with
which
it
reproduced
Althusserian
dogma
about
the
epistemological
break.205
Rancière
presented
Althusser’s
Lesson
as
an
exasperated
reaction
to
his
former
teacher’s
failure
to
take
in
the
broad
lessons
of
May
’68.206
Rancière
complained
that
Althusser’s
“Response
to
John
Lewis”
written
in
1973,
a
counterattack
against
the
British
communist,
simply
restated
in
more
accessible
language
the
same
ideas
he
had
advanced
eight
years
before,
as
though
May
‘68
had
changed
nothing.207
Rancière’s
break
with
Althusser
was
therefore
in
part
because
of
their
different
views
on
the
significance
of
the
events
of
May
1968.
Rancière
has
explained
that
his
Althusserian
perspective
began
to
fall
apart
when
9
million
people
struggled
and
went
on
strike
across
France,
without
the
support
of
parties
or
trade
unions.208
For
Rancière
“a
whole
system
of
certainties
was
shaken”.209
Tanke
explains
that
the
events
indicated
that
it
was
time
to
revisit
the
tenets
of
Marxism
as
articulated
by
Althusser.
May’68
had
arguably
demonstrated
the
capacity
of
workers
and
students
to
instigate
and
organise
protests
without
the
guidance
of
Marxist
intellectuals.
It
had
in
fact
happened
and
popular
revolt
was
eminently
possible
without
correct
theoretical
understanding.210
For
Rancière,
Althusserianism’s
overemphasis
on
acquiring
scientific
rigorous
understanding,
“risked
suppressing
[struggle]
in
the
endless
meantime,
the
social
and
institutional
hierarchies
through
which
pedagogical
power
is
exercised”.211
Althusserian
analysis
was
out
of
feeling
with
the
new
forms
of
politics
brought
forth
by
May
‘68.
In
order
to
demonstrate
the
eclipse
of
Althusserian
Marxism,
Rancière
juxtaposed
it
to
the
experiences
of
workers
at
the
LIP
watch
factory
in
France.
Tanke
explains
that
these
workers,
upon
learning
of
plans
for
the
205
As above.
206
As above.
207
See Althusser L Résponse à John Lewis (1973) as referenced in Davis O (2010) xx.
208
Davis O (2010)
209
Tanke J (2011) 20.
210
Davis O (2010) 15.
211
As above.
49
termination
of
a
number
of
their
colleagues,
forcibly
occupied
their
plant.212
Rather
than
simply
striking,
these
workers
continued
the
production
and
sale
of
watches
under
the
slogan
“[i]t
is
possible:
we
make,
we
sell,
we
pay
ourselves!”213
Tanke
notes
that
what
followed
were
experiments
in
self-‐management
that
gripped
the
imagination
of
the
French
public.214
In
simple
economic
terms,
workers’
control
produced
greater
profits
than
those
of
management.
Because
of
the
refusal
of
traditional
channels
such
as
labour
unions,
the
event
is
often
claimed
as
part
of
the
political
legacy
of
May
’68.215
This
was
at
the
time
when
Althusser
wrote
his
famous
“Reply
to
John
Lewis”,
affirming
most
of
his
original
theses.
These
workers
articulated
their
struggle
in
the
following
terms:
“The
economy
is
in
service
of
man,
man
is
not
in
the
service
of
the
economy”.216
“Man”
according
to
Rancière
did
not
function
as
a
lure
to
lead
workers
back
into
the
darkness
of
ideology,
but
rather
as
a
means
of
resisting
hierarchy.217
“Man”
is
the
political
name
by
which
workers
opposed
the
powers
exercised
over
them,
with
its
extension
refuting
the
division
on
which
their
bosses
rely.218
The
question
is
not
for
Rancière
whether
the
name
is
of
bourgeois
derivation,
“but
whether
it
can
be
made
to
serve
the
self-‐emancipation
of
the
people”.219
For
Rancière,
the
Althusserian
equation
of
“Man”
and
his
rights
with
bourgeois
humanism
is
rash,
as
a
brief
history
of
the
workers’
movement
demonstrates.220
The
events
at
the
watch
factory
closely
resemble
demonstrations
of
equality
that
will
become
central
to
Rancière’s
politics,
demonstrations
that
use
a
name
of
sufficient
generality,
“man”,
which
facilitates
in
the
creation
of
a
polemical
scene.221
The
workers
asserted
themselves
against
a
distribution
in
which
they
had
little
part
and
the
name
allowed
for
the
elaboration
of
a
site
of
struggle
where
the
goal
was
212
Tanke J (2011) 20.
213
Tanke J (2011) 21.
214
As above.
215
As above.
216
As above. See Rancière (1974) 157.
217
As above.
218
As above.
219
As above.
220
Tanke J (2011) 21-22.
221
As above.
50
to
determine
who
was
and
who
was
not
covered
by
it.222
The
use
of
such
names
provides
an
opportunity
to
engage
in
politics,
altering
current
relations.
The
LIP-‐
workers’
experiment
asserts,
as
Tanke
highlights,
that
a
world
free
of
hierarchal
divisions
is
possible.223
For
Rancière,
they
demonstrated
that
the
time
in
which
intellectuals
instructed
people
about
what
they
can
and
cannot
do
had
passed.
Rancière’s
exploration
in
the
mid-‐1970’s
of
the
archives
of
the
French
workers’
movement
that
will
be
discussed
later,
was
driven
by
a
desire
to
refute
the
Althusserianism
claim
that
“the
workers
need
our
scientific
knowledge”
by
showing
that
workers
had
time
and
again
not
only
organised
meaningful
political
revolt,
but
also
understood
their
circumstances
and
their
position
in
the
world.224
According
to
Davis,
this
understanding
was
in
no
sense
inferior
to
Marxist
science.225
His
work
in
the
archives
affirmed
his
belief
that
the
Althusserian
understanding
of
the
relationship
between
Marxist
intellectual
work
and
revolutionary
struggle
was
incorrect.
In
his
book
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
Rancière
explores
the
relationship
between
intellectual
work
and
revolutionary
struggle
in
the
work
of
Marx,
tracking
its
reappearance
in
the
work
of
Jean-‐Paul
Sartre
and
Pierre
Bourdieu
as
well
as
its
prehistory
in
Plato’s
model
of
the
ideal
state.226
In
this
book,
Davis
explains
that
Rancière
insinuates
by
suggestive
juxtaposition
that
the
scientific
strand
identified
within
the
Marxist
tradition,
in
Marx,
Sartre,
Bourdieu
and
Althusser,
is
rooted
in
a
specific
relationship
between
power
and
knowledge
first
elaborated
in
Plato’s
ideal
state
in
Republic.227
Importantly,
in
Rancière’s
subsequent
work,
Plato,
as
Davis
discerns,
is
enemy
number
one
against
whom
his
politics
of
radical
equality
and
true
democracy
will
be
defined.228
I
will
elaborate
more
on
this
point
in
the
following
chapter.
222
As above.
223
As above.
224
As above. See chapter 3.
225
Davis O (2010) 15.
226
Rancière J (2004).
227
Davis O (2010) 15-16.
228
See chapter 3.
51
At
this
stage
it
is
important
to
further
mention
that
in
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor,
Rancière
reaches
the
conclusion
that
Marx
“alternately
disparaged
and
idealised
the
workers
of
his
day”.229
Rancière
was
struck
by
the
way
Marx
and
Engels
often
distanced
themselves
from
the
working-‐class
activists
of
their
day,
even
going
as
far
as
to
contemptuously
refer
to
some
of
them
in
private
as
“jackasses
hungry
for
new
ideas
but
unable
to
engage
with
them
other
than
by
feeding
them
like
animals”.230
As
Davis
clarifies,
Marx,
in
Rancière’s
view,
is
guilty
of
a
condescending
view
of
even
the
most
overtly
politicised
members
of
the
working
class
as
intellectually
incapable.231
Rancière
juxtaposes
Marx’s
contempt
towards
the
workers
of
his
day
with
his
commitment
to
a
theoretical
position
that
states
that
the
future
lies
with
the
proletariat
-‐
“a
new
class
which
is
strictly
not
a
class
but
which
would
emerge
with
the
growth
of
industrialisation
from
the
dissolution
of
existing
classes,
including
the
working
class
as
it
was
then”.232
As
Davis
explains,
Rancière’s
point
was
not
that
Marx’s
private
remarks
to
Engels
about
certain
workers
contradict
the
theoretical
claims
of
his
work.233
Rather,
Marx’s
private
contempt
seems
disconcertingly
consistent
with
certain
kinds
of
public
theorising
and
also
helps
to
illuminate
it.
Workers,
as
they
actually
are
in
the
here
and
now,
“are
the
brut
embodiment
of
a
future
that
they
are
incapable
of
understanding”.234
All
the
nobility
of
humanity
may
shine
on
the
brows
of
Parisian
workers
who
meet
for
study,
but
the
commodity
itself
presents
a
more
obtuse
face.
It
does
not
have
written
on
it
that
it
is
the
sign
of
the
division
of
labour
that
marks
it
as
the
property
of
capital,
except
in
the
form
of
hieroglyphics
that
cannot
be
read
by
workers
who
wear
on
their
brows
the
sign
of
a
people
both
chosen
and
condemned.235
As
Davis
further
notes,
the
identified
“germs”
of
Althusserian
scientism
were
actually
already
present
in
Marx’s
conflicted
view
of
workers
who
embody
a
229
Davis O (2010) 17-18.
230
As above.
231
As above.
232
As above.
233
As above.
234
Davis O (2010) 16.
235
Rancière J (2004) 75.
52
future
that
they
cannot
know.236
Rancière
also
draws
attention
to
the
way
in
which
Marx
may
be
said
to
“police”
the
proletariat,
particularly
in
The
Eighteenth
Brumaire.237
He
is
concerned
with
distinguishing
the
true
proletariat
from
their
degenerate
close
cousins,
the
common
criminals,
colonial
fortune-‐seekers
and
Bohemians,
referred
to
as
the
“lumpenproletariat”
in
the
Marxist
tradition.238
Rancière’s
question
is
as
follows:
“what
exactly
are
we
to
make
of
an
abstract
theory
of
the
revolutionary
proletarian
future
if,
from
the
outset,
it
is
accompanied
by
a
view
of
large
numbers
of
workers
in
the
present
as,
at
best,
constitutionally
unable
to
grasp
the
political
reality
of
their
own
situation
and
at
worst,
asinine
and
degenerate?”239
Davis
further
notes
that
Rancière,
although
he
by
no
means
offers
a
systematic
and
complete
genealogy
of
Marxist
“scientism”,
does
succeed
in
pointing
to
an
uneasy
combination
within
the
tradition
of
a
theory
of
proletarian
future
with
condescendingly
reductive
views
of
concrete
workers
in
the
present
and
their
limited
capacity
to
understand
themselves
and
their
world.240
Marx
therefore
assumes
that
were
it
not
for
the
intervention
and
contribution
of
intellectuals
and
their
“generously
extended
pedagogical
helping
hand”,
the
proletariat
would
be
incapable
of
an
understanding
necessary
for
the
accomplishment
of
their
historical
role,
namely,
revolution.241
Rancière’s
target
is
scientism
as
manifested
in
the
idea
that
the
proletariat
are
incapable
of
understanding
their
political
function
without
the
pedagogical
assistance
of
bourgeoisie
intellectuals.
For
Rancière,
May
’68,
amongst
other
happenings,
prove
this
was
a
convenient
fiction.
Further,
[s]cientism
is
associated,
for
Rancière,
not
just
with
a
privileging
of
the
social
position
of
intellectuals
but
also
with
an
indefinite
deferral
of
the
realisation
of
equality:
for
Marx,
just
as
for
Althusser,
with
his
pedagogy
of
delay,
the
time
to
enact
the
egalitarian
future
would
always
be
after
the
knowledge-‐deficit
of
the
student-‐proletariat
had
been
corrected
[…]
in
other
words,
never
now.242
236
Davis O (2010) 16.
237
Davis O (2010) 17.
238
As above.
239
As above.
240
As above.
241
Davis O (2010) 18.
242
As above.
53
And
it
is
this
scientism
that
privileges
some
and
decides
who
can
think
and
who
cannot
think,
who
can
act
and
under
what
circumstances,
as
well
as
the
fact
that
equality
is
infinitely
deferred
by
it,
that
Rancière
reacts
against
for
most
of
the
rest
of
his
intellectual
life.
After
he
distanced
himself
from
Althusser
and
criticised
the
tenets
of
Althusserianism,
he
engaged
with
questions
around
history,
historical
agency,
education
and
pedagogy.243
I
elaborate
on
these
engagements
in
the
next
chapter.
It
is
these
engagements
that
gave
rise
to
his
“mature
politics”.244
In
the
next
section
I
discuss
the
five
elements
or
moments
of
Rancière’s
mature
politics.
243
The main works that can be mentioned here is The Names of History: On the Poetics of
Knowledge trans. Melehy H (1994), The Nights of Labor: The Worker’s Dream in Nineteenth-
Century France trans. Drury J (1989), The Ignorant Schoolmaster: Five Lessons in Intellectual
Emancipation trans. Ross K (1991) and The Philosopher and His Poor trans. Drury J (2003).
244
Davis mentions that Rancière’s political work, or mature politics, responded to two
countervailing pressures. See Davis O (2010) 99. In global terms, the collapse of the
communist regimes in or shortly after 1989 inspired some philosophical and political
commentators to declare “the end of history” and “the end of politics”. (The “end of history”
refers to a book written in 1992 by Francis Fukuyama (The End of History and The Last Man) in
which he declares that the advent of Western liberal democracy may signal the endpoint of
humanity’s sociocultural evolution and the final form of human government. Western liberal
democracy therefore signals the end point of mankind’s ideological evolution as this form of
government becomes universal. In general it refers to political and philosophical concepts
that suppose that a particular political and economic or social system may develop that
would constitute a final form of human government. In different forms Georg Wilhelm
Friedrich Hegel, Karl Marx, Vladimir Solovyov and Fukuyama have posited this idea.) Davis
explains that during the same time in France, there was a resurgence of interest in political
philosophy, particularly by, neo-Aristotelians and followers of Hannah Arendt and it went
hand in hand with the idea that “ideological” or emancipatory questions could be put aside
and the political could be rethought in ethical terms of how to best “live together”. Davis O
(2010) 99. See also in general Beasley JP A Prehistory of Rhetoric and Composition: New
Rhetoric and Neo-Aristotelianism at the University of Chicago 1947-1959 (2007). Rancière’s
determination, in Disagreement, as will be discussed later, to refute Aristotle’s assumption
that the political could be deduced from the properties of human beings, language and the
power to reason, was motivated, in no small measure, according to Davis, by the popularity of
neo-Aristotelian conceptions of politics at that time. Davis O (2010) 99. Rancière, in his mature
politics, goes much further than attacking a single philosopher’s conception of politics and he
sets his sights instead on political philosophy as a whole, which he argues is flawed and
conservative because of the fact that it is unable to accept and think through the
consequences of the basic fact that any social order is contingent. See Davis O (2010) 99.
Davis explains that Rancière suggests that political philosophy cannot help but to always look
for the most rational social arrangement and what it fails to see is that any and “every social
arrangement is inherently irrational and ultimately provisional”. Davis O (2010) 99. Rancière
goes as far as suggesting that the ambition of the longstanding tradition of political
philosophy is to dispense with politics all together. Davis explains that the intellectual mood
54
2.3
The
Mature
Politics
2.3.1
The
Police
In
order
to
explain
Rancière’s
alternative
vision
of
politics,
it
is
necessary
to
start
with
an
explanation
of
his
conception
of
“the
police”,
“policing”
or
“the
police
order”.
Rancière
states
in
Disagreement:
Politics
is
generally
seen
as
a
set
of
procedures
whereby
aggregation
and
consent
of
collectivities
is
achieved,
the
organisation
of
powers,
the
distribution
of
places
and
roles
and
the
systems
for
legitimising
this
distribution.
I
propose
to
give
this
system
of
distribution
and
legitimisation
another
name.
I
propose
to
call
it
the
police.245
Rancière,
in
the
quote
above,
is
describing
mainstream
politics,
or
politics
as
we
have
come
to
know
it,
namely,
the
hierarchal
administration
of
society
that
governs
its
citizens
in
the
name
of
welfare.246
Rancière,
however,
defines
this
as
“the
police”.
On
this
description,
as
Chambers
elucidates,
the
actions
of
parliaments
and
assemblies,
the
decisions
of
courts,
the
work
of
politicians
and
bureaucratic
efforts
are
all
classified
under
the
non-‐political
heading
of
“the
police”,
“policing”
or
“the
police
order”.247
It
is
important
to
note
that
the
police
order
does
not
only
refer
to
state
institutions,
but
also,
as
Davis
explains,
include
private
institutions
and
an
array
of
social
and
cultural
practices
and
arrangements.248
Therefore,
it
does
not
only
refer
to
the
institutions
and
processes
of
governing,
organisation
and
the
representation
of
communities,
but
it
also
includes
the
exercise
of
power
on
different
levels
of
society
as
well
as
the
of the 1990’s with talk of “the end of politics” and the return to political philosophy was a
fitting trend to accompany what Rancière had already discerned operating in French politics
since the early 1980’s. Davis O (2010) 99. That is, the development and advancement of the
idea that the aim of politics is consensus. Importantly, as Davis elucidates, Rancière, in a
characteristic emphatic reversal, claims that consensus is not the aim of politics, but the
negation of politics: “consensus politics”, as will become clearer later, is effectively the
transformation of politics into management, a transformation which Rancière also associates
with the increasing power of elites and experts trained to undertake this managerial task.
Davis O (2010) 99-100.
245
Rancière J (1999) 28.
246
May T “There are no queers: Jacques Rancière and post-identity politics” Borderlands
(2009) 3.
247
Chambers S “Jacques Rancière and the problem of pure politics” European Journal of
Political Theory (2011) 306.
248
Davis O (2010) 76.
55
way
in
which
social
roles
are
distributed
and
legitimated.249
Rancière,
in
order
to
explain
the
broad
nature
of
the
term,
states
the
following:
[I]t
is
an
order
of
bodies
that
defines
the
allocation
of
ways
of
doing,
ways
of
being,
and
ways
of
saying,
and
sees
that
those
bodies
are
assigned
by
name
to
a
particular
place
and
task.
It
is
an
order
of
the
visible
and
sayable.250
Rancière’s
reference
to
“an
order
of
the
visible
and
sayable”
connects
with
what
he
calls
the
“distribution
or
the
partition
of
the
sensible”
(la
partage
du
sensible).
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
glosses
over
a
central
point
of
Rancière’s,
namely,
the
aesthetic
dimension
of
politics.251
The
notion
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
will
form
an
integral
part
of
this
chapter
and
I
believe
that
it
is
one
of
the
most
interesting
and
valuable
facets
of
Rancière’s
political
formulations.
I
therefore
explain
and
analyse
the
notion
fully
at
a
later
stage.
At
this
stage
it
should
be
mentioned
that
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
the
police
are
two
closely
related
and
interrelated
terms.
The
police,
as
Tanke
explains,
is
the
means
by
which
a
society
enforces
its
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
the
general
laws
distributing
lines
of
sight,
forms
of
speech
and
estimations’
of
people’s
or
bodies’
capacities.252
Put
simply,
for
the
purposes
of
this
section,
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
indicates
a
specific
picture
of
the
world
and
the
police
order
is
that
which
(through
different
mechanisms
and
procedures
of
domination
and
prescription)
enforces
that
picture
of
the
world.
249
As above.
250
Rancière J (1999) 29. Rancière demonstrates the link between his use of the term and the
work of Michel Foucault in the quote above. Foucault argues that “the police includes
everything” to the extent that any police order determines hierarchal relationships between
human beings as well as to the extent that it sets up relationships between “men and things”.
It thus also constitutes a material order. See Foucault M “Omnes et Singulatum” The Tanner
Lectures on Human Values (1979). Davis has mentioned that Rancière draws on an older and
wider sense of the term “police” than the familiar one of a repressive state organ. Davis O
(2010) 76-77. He rather draws on one closer to that identified by Foucault in the seventeenth-
and eighteenth-century writings as synonymous with the social order in its entirety. Davis O
(2010) 76-77. Despite his reference to Foucault, Davis claims that the opposition between
“the police” and “politics” that Rancière describes and the renaming of what is normally
thought of as politics as “policing” is a twisting of the ordinary usage of both of the terms
which blurs their proper meanings and dramatises the conflict between them. According to
Davis, Rancière works with a more open, creative and less disciplined view of the normal
usage of these terms. See Davis O (2010) 76-77.
251
As above.
252
Tanke J (2011) 45.
56
The
quote
mentioned
above
indicates
that
the
police
or
policing
should
be
understood
broadly.
The
police
enforce
the
framework
of
how
things
are.
It
hierarchises,
it
orders
and
regulates.
It
allocates
roles,
occupations,
norms
of
communication
and
display.
It
determines
modes
of
being,
seeing
and
saying,
it
affixes
ranks
and
values
and
continually
reinstates
the
legitimacy
of
social
hierarchy
as
well
as
its
own
domination.253
Its
role,
as
Tanke
notes,
is
to
maintain
the
status
quo
and
to
delimit,
in
advance,
the
sphere
of
politics.254
It
indicates
who
is
capable
of
speaking
and
what
they
are
able
to
say
and
also
what
can
become
a
matter
of
political
dispute.255
The
police
order
assigns
individuals
to
particular
positions
in
society
and
assumes
that
their
way
of
thinking
and
behaving
will
follow
from
those
positions.
In
other
words,
the
police
order
assumes
that
people
have
different
capacities
and
are
accordingly
destined
to
occupy
different
positions
in
society.256
Todd
May
describes
the
police
order
as
any
order
of
hierarchy.257
May
notes
that
within
a
specific
police
order
or
order
of
hierarchy
there
are
those
who
benefit
and
those
who
do
not,
or
those
who
benefit
more
than
others.258
Rancière
has
called
it
“those
who
are
counted
and
those
who
are
not”.259
The
way
in
which
we
understand
the
counted
and
uncounted
is
crucial
to
understanding
police
orders.
The
counted
and
uncounted
should
not
be
understood
as
or
reduced
to
a
single
class
division.
As
May
elucidates,
societies
function
with
a
number
of
hierarchies,
such
as
racial
hierarchies,
economic
hierarchies,
sexual
hierarchies,
gender
hierarchies,
religious
hierarchies
and
so
forth.260
Who
is
therefore
among
the
counted
and
who
is
among
the
uncounted
depends
on
the
hierarchy
one
is
looking
at.
The
concept
of
the
police
can
therefore
be
utilised
in
a
fluid
way.
Not
253
Stoneman E “Appropriate indecorum: Rhetoric and aesthetics in the political theory of
Jacques Rancière” Philosophy and Rhetoric (2011) 143.
254
Tanke J (2011) 45.
255
As above.
256
Davis O (2010) 78.
257
May T Borderlands (2009) 4.
258
As above.
259
Rancière J (1999) 6. In the section that explains the notions of the “miscount and the
wrong" below, I elaborate fully on the idea of the counted and uncounted.
260
May T Borderlands (2009) 4.
57
all
oppression
occurs
along
a
single
register.
May
highlights
that
the
police
does
not
refer
to
a
single
or
particular
hierarchy,
but
to
the
various
and
different
hierarchies
that
govern
societies.
Therefore,
“[i]t
is
entirely
possible
for
one
to
be
a
member
of
the
uncounted
in
one
part
of
the
police
order
and
among
the
counted
in
another
part”.261
Further,
not
all
orders
of
hierarchy
are
equally
oppressive
or
dominant.
Thus,
as
Rancière
states
as
a
further
indication
of
the
term’s
fluidity,
“[t]here
is
a
worse
and
a
better
police”.262
Tanke
explains
that
the
police
monopolises
interpretations
in
an
attempt
to
create
a
single
direction
for
the
movement
of
society.263
It
therefore
refers
to
a
series
of
assumptions
that
structure
life
in
common.264
It
is
a
specific
interpretation
that
attempts
to
strip
the
given
order
of
things
from
its
litigious
character.265
It
primarily
has
to
do
with
the
logic
of
inequality
that
creates
forms
of
inclusion
and
exclusion.
It
distributes
bodies
and
voices,
define
what
is
seen
and
unseen
and
draws
boundaries
such
as
those
that
exists
between
the
public
and
the
private.266
Policing
attempts
to
co-‐opt,
manage,
contain,
and
undermine
any
dispute
about
the
excluded
within
the
community.
Tanke
explains
further
that
police
operations
include
the
selective
framing
of
issues
by
mainstream
news
organisations,
the
management
of
economic,
cultural
and
existential
insecurity
and
the
transformation
of
political
names
or
subjects
like
“the
people”
or
“the
workers”
into
socio-‐economic
identities.267
The
police
order
can
also
be
described
as
that
which
enforces
the
perceptual
configuration
of
society.268
What
is
sayable,
visible,
understood,
who
counts
and
who
doesn’t?
It
maintains
the
more
or
less
“automatic
perception
of
status,
identity,
position
and
entitlement”.269
With
its
close
relation
to
the
distribution
of
the
sensible,
Tanke
explains
that
the
police
261
As above.
262
Rancière J (1999) 30-31.
263
Tanke J (2011) 46.
264
As above.
265
As above.
266
As above.
267
Tanke J (2011) 45.
268
As above.
269
As above.
58
order
ultimately
concerns
the
material
ground
of
communicability,
intelligibility
and
sensibility.270
It
maintains
the
operations
that
set
the
limit
of
what
is
conceivable
and
possible
in
a
specific
time
and
place.
It
should
be
mentioned
further
that
Rancière’s
formulation
of
the
notion
of
the
police
helps
to
explain
some
of
his
opinions
or
arguments
when
it
comes
to
our
current
perception
of
politics.
He
encourages
us
to
question
that
the
notion
of
governance
is
about
the
management
of
a
shared
and
unequal,
prosperity
and,
more
radically,
he
opposes
the
equation
of
politics
with
the
state.
Rancière
attributes
the
weakness
of
contemporary
politics
to
the
politics
of
what
he
terms
“consensus”.
I
elaborate
shortly
on
the
meaning
of
consensus
in
order
to
introduce
the
notion.
Thereafter,
I
turn
to
Rancière’s
definition
of
politics.
Consensus
is
the
means
by
which
the
police
attempt
to
prevent
the
emergence
of
political
subjects
or
what
Rancière
calls
“the
demos”.271
Consensus
aims
to
avoid
the
demos’
politicisation
by
distributing
the
various
parts
of
a
community
without
remainder.
As
the
absence
of
politics,
it
attempts
to
render
invisible
and
inaudible
those
discourses,
issues,
individuals,
and
groups
that
would
tear
open
the
self-‐
evidence
of
the
police
by
giving
voice
to
their
exclusion.272
Consensus,
through
the
mechanisms
of
the
police,
holds
forth
that
everyone
in
the
community
has
been
fairly
counted
or
taken
into
regard.
Consensus,
as
will
become
clearer
later,
is
not
the
goal
of
politics
for
Rancière;
it
is
rather
the
sensible
distribution
that
politics
must
overcome.273
Rancière
has
in
the
same
vein
referred
to
our
time
as
a
“consensual
time”
to
indicate
that
the
logic
of
depoliticisation
is
becoming
more
sophisticated
and
politics
itself
more
difficult.274
Rancière
has
set
his
conception
of
politics
in
opposition
to
a
specific
consensus
prevalent
today:
“The
discourses
ascendant
since
the
fall
of
the
Berlin
Wall
that
270
As above.
271
Rancière J (1999) 9.
272
Tanke J (2011) 45.
273
As above.
274
Rancière J Chroniques Des Temps Consensuels (2005) 7-10 as quoted in Tanke J (2011) 46.
59
attempt
to
legitimate
the
unrestricted
reign
of
the
market”.275
This
form
of
consensus
employs,
as
Tanke
explains,
a
particular
series
of
operations
to
convert
democratic
struggles
into
a
series
of
managed
conflicts.276
Tanke
further
explains
that
consensus
exploits
the
cover
of
political
realism
as
a
doctrine
that
“justifies
war,
social
hierarchies
and
economic
inequalities
by
invoking
necessity”.277
For
Rancière
“[r]ealism
is
the
absorption
of
all
reality
and
all
truth
in
the
category
of
the
only
possible
thing”.278
According
to
Rancière,
the
type
of
political
realism
present
today
is
the
ideology
that
claims
that
it
is
beyond
ideology.
An
ideology
that
would
have
us
believe
that
it
is
possible
to
base
government
on
a
pragmatic
estimation
of
human
nature,
the
laws
of
the
market
and
the
global
situation:
We
witness
a
version
of
realism
whenever
leaders
exploit
the
imperatives
of
modernisation,
economic
necessity,
or
notions
such
as
the
“post-‐9/11
world”
to
justify
unpalatable
decisions.
Realism
gains
traction
by
promoting
itself
as
the
efficient
alternative
to
the
chimeras
of
democracy.
[...]
They
encourage
citizens
to
become
reasonable
in
their
demands
and
to
acknowledge
the
contingencies
of
the
globalised
world,
asking
us
to
be
content
with
what
we
have,
and,
in
lean
times,
to
give
back
some
of
our
“privileges”.279
Realism
is
therefore
one
form
of
police
operations
that
attempt
to
put
an
end
to
politics.
It
is
one
of
the
discourses
that
attempt
to
convince
us
that
the
existing
world
is
the
only
one
possible.
It
also
presents
itself
as
the
only
rational
choice
in
the
management
of
common
life.
Tanke
argues
that
in
instances
where
realist
discourse
is
employed,
for
example,
to
undermine
pension
funds,
lower
wages,
deny
people
healthcare,
or
limit
democracy,
it
typically
promises
a
future
in
which
prosperity
and
security
will
offset
these
short-‐term
inconveniences.280
Rancière
asks;
“what
is
more
utopian
than
a
schema
whose
goal
continually
recedes
into
the
future?”281
The
meaning
of
consensus
will
hopefully
become
even
clearer
as
the
different
aspects
of
Rancière’s
politics
are
explained.
At
this
stage,
I
can
add
that
consensus
has
to
do
with
the
agreement
of
political
parties
and
social
partners
within
a
given
community
about
the
common
interests
of
that
275
Tanke J (2011) 46.
276
As above.
277
As above.
278
Rancière J (1999) 132. See also Tanke J (2011) 46.
279
Tanke J (2011) 47.
280
As above.
281
Rancière J Aux bords du Politique (1998) 56-59.
60
community.
Moreover,
it
has
to
do
with
agreement
about
what
is
given
or
self-‐
evident
in
a
specific
context.
These
“givens”
are
objectified
to
the
extent
that
they
can
no
longer
lend
themselves
to
a
dispute;
they
are
not
open
to
litigation
or
contestation.
It
is
against
this
type
of
contemporary
consensus
or
realism
that
Rancière
conceptualises
his
definition
of
politics.
Consensus
results
from
and
relies
upon
the
police
operations
that
enforce
roles,
places
and
positions
as
well
as
ways
of
doing,
seeing
and
saying
that
delimit
the
boundaries
of
the
perceptible,
thinkable
and
possible
and
see
that
those
boundaries
persist.282
For
Rancière,
it
is
politics
functioning
upon
equality
that
can
protect
the
possible
as
possible.
With
the
police
in
mind,
I
now
turn
to
Rancière’s
definition
of
politics.
2.3.2
Politics/Equality
I
propose
to
reserve
the
term
politics
for
an
extremely
determined
activity
antagonistic
to
policing:
whatever
breaks
with
the
tangible
configuration
whereby
parties
and
parts
or
lack
of
them
are
defined
by
a
presupposition
that,
by
definition,
has
no
place
in
that
configuration-‐
that
of
the
part
that
has
no
part
[...]
political
activity
is
always
a
mode
of
expression
that
undoes
the
perceptible
divisions
of
the
police
order
by
implementing
a
basically
heterogeneous
assumption
[...]
an
assumption
that
at
the
end
of
the
day,
itself
demonstrates
the
sheer
contingency
of
the
order,
the
equality
of
any
speaking
being
with
any
other
speaking
being.283
Politics
is
the
undoing
of
the
police
order
through
a
presupposition
of
equality.284
Rancière
conceptualises
politics
around
the
concepts
of
equality,
contingency
and
antagonism.285
It
is
always
dissensual
and
polemical.
Importantly,
“[p]olitics
is
the
activity
which
turns
on
equality
as
its
principle”.286
In
order
to
make
sense
of
Rancière’s
politics,
I
firstly
address
two
aspects
described
by
Rancière
in
the
opening
quote
above,
namely,
the
equality
of
speaking
beings
and
the
heterogeneous
assumption
that
needs
to
be
implemented.
The
presupposition
of
equality
is
the
presupposition
of
the
equality
of
all
speaking
beings:
282
Tanke J (2011) 47.
283
Rancière J (1999) 29-30.
284
May J “Jacques Rancière and the ethics of equality” SubStance (2007) 24.
285
As above.
286
Rancière J (1999) XI.
61
There
is
an
order
in
society
because
some
people
command
and
others
obey,
but
in
order
to
obey
an
order
at
least
two
things
are
required:
you
must
understand
the
order
and
you
must
understand
that
you
must
obey
it.
And
to
do
that,
you
must
already
be
the
equal
of
the
person
who
is
ordering
you.287
According
to
this
conceptualisation,
equality
must
be
presupposed
on
the
basis
of
the
equality
of
anyone
capable
of
hearing
and
understanding
an
order.
It
is
the
presupposition
of
those
who
have
no
part
in
the
police
order.
May
explains
that
this
presupposition
belongs
to
anyone
who
acts
in
terms
of
it,
when
a
person
or
persons
decide
to
assert
himself/herself/themselves
in
the
name
of
his/her/their
own
equality.288
By
presupposing
equality,
subjects
undo
the
classifications
of
the
police
order.289
Equality
therefore
undoes
the
classifications
by
which
some
give
orders.
May
notes
that
the
equality
of
every
speaking
being
lies
at
the
heart
of
democratic
politics
for
Rancière.290
This
equality
is
found
within
the
fact
that
the
person
who
understands
the
order
is
equal
to
the
one
who
issues
it.
People
can
communicate
with
one
another
and
conduct
their
lives
on
the
basis
of
these
communications,
but
“one
may
be
in
a
position
that
permits
one
to
give
orders,
but
that
position
is
never
justified
by
any
inequality
between
those
who
give
orders
and
those
who
receive
it”.291
The
heterogeneous
assumption
that
Rancière
refers
to
in
the
quote
mentioned
above
is
exactly
the
equality
of
all
speaking
beings.
This
is
the
heterogeneous
assumption
that
politics
postulates
against
the
police.
Police
orders
work
on
the
assumptions
that
some
are
to
give
orders
and
some
are
to
receive
them.
May
further
notes
that
racial,
gender
and
class
distinctions
for
example
are
grounded
in
the
police
assumption
that
there
is
inequality
between
those
who
can
order
the
lives
of
others
and
those
who
have
287
Rancière J (1999) 16.
288
May T SubStance (2007) 24.
289
May T SubStance (2007) 25.
290
As above.
291
May T Borderlands (2007) 5. Equality in this sense is an irreducible fact of social existence
that can never entirely be effaced. Rancière does not argue that humans are essentially equal.
He doesn’t have to. He instead argues that all attempts to justify inequality are incoherent.
See Tanke J (2011) 56. Rancière states that “in order for authority to be more than arbitrary
force, it must inevitably give reasons. This process of supplying reasons undermines the claims
on behalf of inequality for when it attempts to explain the hierarchies it would erect, inequality
presupposes equality”. See Rancière J (1991) 46-49.
62
no
part.292
In
other
words,
the
simple
act
of
understanding
a
command
can
become
an
occasion
for
staging
a
counterdemonstration
of
equality.
For
Rancière,
in
principle,
every
social
arrangement
is
therefore
open
to
disruption
by
egalitarian
politics.293
It
should
be
mentioned
here
that
May
explains
that
when
one
presupposes
equality
a
contradiction
comes
into
play.294
Political
action
brings
out
into
the
open
the
fact
that
elites,
especially
those
in
democratic
societies,
on
the
one
hand
believes
in
equality,
whether
this
belief
is
ontological
(in
the
sense
that
for
politics
it
is
important
for
people
to
be
considered
equal)
or
normative
(in
the
sense
that
all
human
beings
should
be
treated
equally)
and
on
the
other
hand
believes
in
inequality.295
This,
as
May
further
elucidates,
does
not
necessarily
refer
to
a
belief
in
inequality
per
se,
but
rather
to
a
commitment
to
hierarchies
and
dominations
of
the
police
order,
which
implies
inequality.296
This
is
the
belief
that
it
is
permissible
to
distribute
certain
roles
to
certain
people,
i.e.
by
approving
of
the
hierarchal
police
order
they
hold
the
principle
of
inequality.
Politics
introduces
the
assumption
that
every
speaking
being
is
equal
to
every
other.
Heterogeneity
functions
on
two
levels
within
this
assumption.
Firstly,
equality
is
posited
against
inequality.
It
challenges
the
right
of
those
positioned
to
give
orders.
As
May
notes:
Those
who
fail
to
have
a
part
do
not
do
so
because
of
some
lack
they
possess.
They
find
themselves
where
they
are,
not
because
it
is
right
that
they
be
there,
but
because
the
police
order
just
happened
to
place
them
there.
It
could
well
have
been
that
they
were
placed
elsewhere,
better
positioned
in
the
police
order,
and
the
order
would
be
no
worse
off
for
that.297
The
second
level
on
which
heterogeneity
functions
in
Rancière’s
formulation
is
the
contingency
of
the
order
itself.
If
every
speaking
being
is
equal
to
every
other
speaking
being,
then
the
fact
that
some
have
a
part
and
others
do
not
is
purely
292
As above.
293
As above.
294
May T SubStance (2007) 28-29.
295
As above.
296
As above.
297
May T Borderlands (2009) 5.
63
contingent.
Having
a
part
is
therefore
not
naturally
justified.298
This
does
not
mean
that
people
are
never
to
delegate
authority,
but
delegation
itself
presupposes
participation
of
the
delegators
and
presupposes
their
equality.299
Police
orders
that
divide
along
various
registers
refuse
to
recognise
the
contingency
of
their
distributions.300
Such
distributions
or
divisions
are
taken
as
justified
and
even
natural.
Politics
positing
the
equality
of
speaking
beings,
as
May
elucidates,
gnaws
away
at
the
supposedly
natural
order.301
Politics
concerns
equality
and
equality
arises
when
the
traditional
mechanisms
of
what
are
usually
called
politics
are
put
into
question.302
Rancière
states:
Politics
only
occurs
when
these
mechanisms
are
stopped
in
their
tracks
by
the
effect
of
a
presupposition
that
is
totally
foreign
to
them
yet
without
which
none
of
them
could
ultimately
function:
the
presupposition
of
equality
of
anyone
with
everyone.303
It
should
be
mentioned
here
that
Rancière
derives
his
conception
and
understanding
of
equality
from
the
notion
of
the
equal
intelligence
of
people
postulated
in
his
work
on
pedagogy.
His
specific
understanding
of
equality
is
developed
in
his
book
The
Ignorant
Schoolmaster
in
which
he
engages
with
the
ideas
of
the
historical
figure
of
Joseph
Jacocot.304
This
engagement
is
central
to
298
As above.
299
As above.
300
As above.
301
As above.
302
May T in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 108.
303
Rancière J (1999) 17. To illustrate the above-mentioned point, Rancière has frequently
referred to the account of the plebeian revolt around Menenius Agrippa, who served as the
patrician ambassador to the plebs occupying Aventine Hill. See Rancière J (1973) 9. He
explains how, in an attempt to restore order to the city, Menenius resorted to the familiar
fable of the body politic with hierarchal divisions of labour. Menenius explained that everyone
has a place, and without patrician command the plebeian body will starve. Rancière highlights
that the problem with his explanation is that it had to be spoken. He was addressing a group
of addressees capable of understanding. Rancière: “The principle of superiority is ruined if it
has to be explained to inferiors why they are inferior”. See Rancière J (1973) 9. A command,
Tanke notes, presupposes that it can be understood, cutting across the relationship of
dissimilarity from which it is articulated. Tanke J (2011) 57. Rancière: “There is no service that
is carried out, no knowledge that is imparted, no authority that is established without the
master having, however little, to speak ‘equal to equal’ with the one he commands or
instructs”. Rancière J (1973) 9. This can also be seen as Rancière’s response to Aristotle’s
partitioning of the logos, namely that there is no meaningful distinction between perceiving
and possessing reason. See Rancière J (1973) 9. See also Tanke J (2011) 57.
304
Rancière J (1991).
64
Rancière’s
understanding
of
politics
and
equality.
Because
of
its
centrality
and
importance,
as
mentioned
in
the
introductory
chapter,
I
dedicate
a
section
to
it
in
the
next
chapter.
That
discussion
should
enable
an
even
deeper
understanding
of
his
formulation
of
equality.
In
this
section,
I
ensue
with
a
general
discussion
of
his
politics
and
the
role
of
equality
therein.
What
should
be
made
clear
at
this
stage
is
that
not
every
disruption
of
the
police
order
is
worthy
of
the
name
of
politics.305
Tanke
explains
that
Rancière
reserves
this
term
for
actions,
speech
situations,
manifestations,
practices,
arguments,
and
even
works
of
art
and
literature
that
inscribes
equality
into
police
divisions
of
inequality.306
He
states
that
“[n]othing
is
political
in
itself
[…]
for
the
political
only
happens
by
means
of
a
principle
that
does
not
belong
to
it:
equality”.307
Therefore,
only
the
supposition
of
equality
allows
for
speech,
action
and
organisation
to
break
from
the
police.
Without
equality
such
operations
are
categorised
under
the
heading
of
non-‐political
competition
between
parts.308
Rancière:
What
makes
an
action
political
is
not
its
object
or
the
place
where
it
is
carried
out,
but
solely
its
form,
the
form
in
which
the
confirmation
of
equality
is
inscribed
in
the
setting
up
of
a
dispute,
of
a
community
existing
solely
through
being
divided.309
Thus,
politics
entails
the
enactment
of
equality
(the
equality
of
speaking
beings),
through
the
staging
of
a
scene
of
dissensus
or
conflict,
within
a
police
situation
of
inequality.
Put
differently,
politics
is
that
which
ruptures
orders
of
domination,
legitimacy
and
distribution
through
people
enacting
their
equality
within
an
unequal
police
order.310
305
Tanke J (2011) 51.
306
As above.
307
Rancière J (1999) 33.
308
Tanke J (2011) 51.
309
Rancière J (1999) 32.
310
Davis explains that Rancière’s opposition between the police and politics and the
renaming of what is normally thought of as politics as policing is a twisting of the ordinary
usage of both terms and which blurs and dramatises their proper meanings. See Davis O
(2010) 76. This twisting and dramatising is, as will become clearer later, characteristic of
Rancière’s politics. See Davis O (2010) 76.
65
Stoneman
highlights
that
politics
in
Rancière’s
sense
does
not
derive
from
a
priori
truths
about
knowledge,
human
nature
or
social
interaction.311
It
is
not
a
function
or
form
of
government
and
it
neither
ensures
nor
establishes
socio-‐economic
order.312
Politics
is
a
dissensual
activity
that
consists
only
in
demonstrating
equality
in
order
to
break
with
the
“tangible
configuration”
of
the
police
order
as
Rancière
puts
it
in
the
quote
mentioned
in
the
beginning
of
this
section.
The
type
of
equality
that
Rancière
holds
forth
is,
as
Stoneman
mentions,
not
something
to
be
attained,
preserved
or
balanced
against
competing
factors.313
Equality,
understood
in
this
way,
names
an
assumption
that
political
subjects
must
presuppose
on
their
own
account
and
demonstrate
through
their
own
actions.314
Equality
is
therefore
not
given
by
a
social
order,
nor
is
it
claimed,
it
is
practiced,
verified.315
In
this
regard,
May
has
usefully
described
Rancière’s
conception
of
equality
as
an
“active
equality”,
a
form
of
equality
that
the
oppressed
presume,
declare
and
verify
for
themselves
and
which
is
to
be
distinguished
from
equality
as
conventionally
understood
as
“passive
equality”
which
is
given
by
those
in
power.316
Equality
cannot
be
given.
The
police
order
or
given
hierarchal
social
arrangement
is
symbolically
disrupted
by
an
equality
that
is
presupposed
and
antagonistic.317
Politics
is
the
subversion
of
hierarchy
by
way
of
introducing
a
scene
of
dissensus
into
the
inegalitarian
partitions
or
orderings
of
the
police.
It
ruptures
the
logic
that
presupposes
inferiority
and
superiority.318
As
Stoneman
further
highlights,
it
disorders
the
coherence
of
any
distribution
of
places,
roles
and
parts
given
by
the
police.319
311
Stoneman E Philosophy and Rhetoric (2011) 129.
312
As above.
313
As above.
314
As above.
315
Rancière J (1991) 88.
316
See May T The Political Though of Jacques Rancière (2008).
317
Stoneman E Philosophy and Rhetoric (2011) 129.
318
Stoneman E Philosophy and Rhetoric (2011) 135.
319
Stoneman E Philosophy and Rhetoric (2011) 136.
66
Further,
it
can
be
stated
that
politics
is
also
not
the
assertion
of
personal
autonomy.
One
does
not
emancipate
oneself
politically
by
oneself.320
The
practice
of
democracy
is
a
matter
of
community
and
of
“membership
in
a
single
world
which
can
only
be
expressed
in
adversarial
terms,
a
coming
together
which
can
only
occur
in
conflict”.321
It
is
an
assumption
made
together.
May
notes:
To
engage
in
a
democratic
politics,
in
the
politics
of
equality
is
not
simply
to
say,
or
act
as
though
one
were
saying
“we
are
all
equal
now”.
It
is
to
structure
the
past
in
light
of
equality.
To
act
democratically
is
to
always
have
been
equal.
The
democratic
political
subject
creates
itself
in
the
moment
of
its
struggle,
but
the
presupposition
of
its
struggle
is
ascribed
to
a
past
that
justifies
it
retrospectively.322
Within
the
presupposition
of
equality,
political
subjects
are
not
asking
to
be
merely
“included”.
The
presupposition
of
equality
is
demonstrating
the
fact
that
political
subjects
have
always
been
equal.323
It
is
important
to
mention
that
since
the
practice
of
politics
occurs
in
a
situation
of
the
inegalitarian
classifications
of
the
police
order,
by
breaking
with
that
order,
politics
can,
in
Rancière’s
conception,
be
more
or
less
effective
in
creating
change.324
But,
as
warned
by
Ross,
we
ought
not
to
confuse
social
effects
with
the
existence
of
politics.325
It
is
not
in
the
consequences
but
in
the
acting
out
of
the
presupposition
of
equality
that
politics
occurs.
Ross
notes:
Unconcerned
with
the
duration
or,
for
the
most
part,
with
measuring
any
social
effects
or
usefulness
such
events
might
have-‐
and
supremely
unconcerned
with
institutions-‐
Rancière’s
thought
has
produced
disappointment
for
readers
looking
for
a
prescription
or
a
program
for
action
or,
for
that
matter,
a
celebration
of
time
spent
“in
the
trenches”,
so
to
speak,
the
temporality
of
militant
organising.326
Politics
begins
and
ends
in
a
scene
of
dissensus
or
police
conflict.327
Ross
eloquently
explains
further:
320
Rancière J On the Shores of Politics (1995) 49 trans. by Heron L.
321
As above.
322
May T (2008) 71.
323
As above.
324
As above.
325
Ross K “Historicizing Untimeliness” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 29.
326
As above.
327
May T (2008) 71.
67
Politics
is
an
event
that
cannot
be
predicated
any
more
than
its
end
can
be
apocalyptically
announced.
It
is
always
circumstantial,
local
and
entirely
contained
in
its
singular
manifestations.328
It
therefore
does
not
carry
on
indefinitely,
but
only
exists
through
enacting
equality
by
means
of
a
scene
of
dissensus
within
a
particular
police
order
and
it
is
only
within
the
moment
of
dissensus
and
undoing
of
the
classifications
of
the
police
order
that
it
exists.
Politics
in
Rancière’s
definition
of
it
is
rare,
it
is
temporal
and
it
is
localised.
It
is
an
activity
of
the
moment
and
always
provisional.329
Enactments
of
equality
also
re-‐enacts
what
Rancière
calls
“the
distribution
of
the
sensible”
which
I
mentioned
in
the
previous
section
and
explain
below.330
The
division
or
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
both
an
order
of
intelligibility
and
an
order
of
distribution.
The
order
of
distribution
constitutes
division.
Some
can
speak,
others
cannot,
some
have
their
voice
heard
or
have
greater
say
and
others
do
not.
Politics
is
a
partition
in
this
division
of
the
sensible
that
only
ever
institutes
yet
another
order
that
is
itself
open
to
egalitarian
challenge.331
Politics,
therefore,
as
Dillon
eloquently
explains,
is
itself
this
never-‐ending
polemical
intrusion
of
equality
into
specific
historical
orders
(distributions
of
the
sensible).332
In
other
words,
politics
takes
place
within
the
police
order.
The
encounter
between
politics
and
the
police
is
never
final
or
definitive
and
never
“produces
a
new
stage
of
history”.333
It
is
always
a
renegotiation
of
the
police
order
that
we
must
live
in.334
Democratic
politics,
enacted
by
the
presupposition
of
the
equality
of
speaking
beings,
can
only
renegotiate
or
reconfigure
the
police
order.
The
practice
of
equality
occurs
in
the
context
of
a
particular
hierarchy
in
a
particular
police
order.
As
mentioned,
nothing
guarantees
that
politics
will
create
change.335
According
to
Rancière,
equality’s
“verification
becomes
‘social’,
causes
it
to
have
328
Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 29.
329
Davis O (2010) 79.
330
Dillon M “A Passion for the (im)possible: Jacques Rancière, equality, pedagogy and the
messianic” European Journal of Political Theory (2005) 431.
331
As above.
332
As above.
333
Chambers S European Journal of Political Theory (2011) 307.
334
As above.
335
May T in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 116.
68
real
social
effect,
only
when
it
mobilises
an
obligation
to
hear”.336
Politics
is
a
process
and
“[i]t
is
the
emergence
of
a
collective
subject
acting
under
the
presupposition
of
its
equality,
an
acting
that
disrupts
a
particular
police
order”.337
It
should
be
emphasised
further
that
the
police
and
politics
are
closely
related.
Rancière
elucidates:
If
the
distinction
between
politics
and
the
police
can
be
useful,
it
is
not
to
allow
us
to
say:
politics
is
on
this
side,
police
is
on
the
opposite
side.
It
is
to
allow
us
to
understand
the
form
of
their
intertwinement.
We
rarely,
if
ever,
face
a
situation
where
we
can
say:
this
is
politics
in
its
purity.
But
we
ceaselessly
face
situations
where
we
have
to
discern
how
politics
encroaches
on
matters
of
the
police
and
the
police
on
matters
of
politics.338
Further,
the
idea
that
we
should
not
confuse
change
with
politics
does
not
mean
that
for
Rancière
political
change
is
merely
unimportant.
As
may
reiterates,
it
is
of
the
highest
importance
for
Rancière.339
But,
we
must
distinguish
the
existence
of
politics
from
its
effectiveness.340
If
we
do
not
“we
risk
missing
it
in
the
moment
of
its
happening,
and,
on
the
other
hand,
ascribing
it
where
it
does
not
exits”.341
Politics
and
equality
as
described
by
Rancière
upsets,
it
ruptures
and
breaks
apart.
Hallward
emphasises
that
equality
does
not
refer
to
a
place,
but
to
the
placeless
or
the
out
of
place,
not
to
a
class,
but
to
the
unclassifiable
or
the
out
of
class.342
The
essence
of
equality
is
not
so
much
to
unify,
but
as
to
declassify,
to
undo
the
supposed
naturalness
of
orders
and
replace
it
with
controversial
figures
of
division.
Equality
is
the
power
of
the
inconsistent,
disintegrative
and
ever-‐
played
division.343
Rancière’s
politics
postulate
the
presumptions
of
a
disruptive
equality
against
the
advocates
of
an
orderly,
hierarchical
inequality.
Rancière’s
most
general
effort
has
always
been
“to
explore
the
various
resources
of
displacement,
indistinction,
de-‐
336
Rancière J (1995) 86.
337
May T in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 116.
338
Rancière J “The Method of Equality: An Answer to Some Questions” in Rockhill G & Watts
P (eds.) (2009) 287.
339
May T in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 116.
340
As above.
341
As above.
342
Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 141.
343
Rancière J (1995) 32-33.
69
differentiation
or
de-‐qualification
that
are
available
in
any
given
field”.344
And
the
tool
for
this
displacement
or
indistinction
is
equality.
In
his
formulation
of
equality
Rancière
attempts
to
defend
the
idea
that
the
notion
of
politics
should
be
reserved
for
democratic
forms
of
organisation,
communication,
practice,
and
action.
Democracy
in
the
Rancièrian
framework
is
necessarily
a
destabilising
and
disruptive
force.
Politics
is
distinguishable
from
other
ways
of
ordering
the
community
by
its
most
basic
element,
equality.
Without
equality
therefore,
distributions,
operations,
and
discourses
partake
of
the
opposite
of
politics,
namely
the
police.
The
police
employ
a
fundamentally
different
logic
than
politics
and
the
opposition
is
sometimes
explained
by
Rancière
in
terms
of
“worlds”
in
order
to
highlight
the
fact
that
the
police
and
politics
are
essentially,
although
closely
related,
different
orientations
toward
the
community.345
“Doing”
politics
is
placing
the
two
worlds
or
logics
in
conflict
by
creating
spaces
where
the
two
can
be
opposed
and
the
police
hierarchies,
however
provisionally,
overturned.
The
political,
according
to
Rancière,
is
the
third
space
of
contestation,
an
indeterminate
and
always
shifting
meeting
point
between
politics
and
the
police.346
It
is
further
important
to
mention
that
equality
relies
upon
its
demonstration.
Tanke
explains
that
Politics
is
about
generating
obligations
to
recognise
the
existence
of
a
shared
world
through
the
creation
of
polemical
sites
where
equality
can
be
verified.347
Equality
follows
from
demonstration,
both
in
the
logical
and
performative
sense.348
It
resides
in
demonstrating
that
the
demonstrators
are
political
subjects
and
that
their
arguments
count
as
political
arguments.
This
notion
of
demonstration
is
closely
related
to
Rancière’s
argument
that
politics
is
about
redistributing
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
As
mentioned,
344
Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 141.
345
Tanke J (2011) 51. See for example “Who is the subject of the Rights of Man?” South
Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 297-310 at 304 where Rancière describes politics as “putting two
worlds in one and the same world”.
346
As above.
347
Tanke J (2011) 59.
348
As above.
70
I
will
discuss
this
notion
fully
at
a
later
stage.
At
this
stage
it
should
suffice
to
mention
that
the
demonstration
of
equality
is
necessary
to
create
the
conditions
in
which
others
recognise
the
import
of
equality.349
These
demonstrations
or
actions
create
a
shared
world
where
one
was
previously
denied
and
they
are
significant
for,
as
Tanke
notes,
they
overturn
the
exclusionary
partitions
of
the
police.350
Therefore,
demonstrations
create
possibilities
to
begin
to
take
part
or
participate.
Equality
requires
a
polemical
demonstration,
a
case
or
verification.
Equality
as
demonstration
is
closely
related
to
Rancière’s
idea
of
politics
as
dissensus.
Dissensus
has
to
do
with
“disputing
subjects
and
litigious
objects”.351
Politics
opposes
consensus
by
means
of
dissensus.
Tanke
notes
further
that
dissensus
is
the
means
by
which
the
given
situation
is
deprived
of
its
self-‐evidence
and
subjected
to
dispute.
He
states
that
“[d]issensus
is
the
process
of
politics
itself
in
that
it
is
the
activity
of
countering
the
police
distributions
of
the
sensible
with
the
egalitarian
supplement”.352
Dissensus
breaks
open
an
interpretation
of
sense
thought
to
be
undisputable,
whether
it
be
through
polemics,
demonstrations,
strikes,
speech,
poetic
activities,
or
the
definition
of
new
capacities.353
If
consensus
promotes
the
obviousness
of
the
status
quo,
politics
as
dissensus
opposes
it
by
postulating
another
world:
Dissensus
operates
on
space
and
time
in
order
to
create
a
new
terrain
for
confrontation.
It
is
the
action
of
creating
a
stage
upon
which
one
can
appear
equal.
It
sketches
the
outline
of
a
different
world
and
forces
us
to
reconsider
it
alongside
our
own.
Politics
is
the
activity
of
holding
in
conflict
the
world
of
the
police
and
the
one
defined
under
the
assumption
of
equality.
Dissensus
consists
in
making
apparent
fundamentally
heterogeneous
ways
of
parcelling
out
capacities
and
parts.354
349
As above.
350
Tanke J (2011) 60.
351
Tanke J (2011) 61.
352
Tanke J (2011) 62.
353
As above.
354
Tanke J (2011) 62- 63. According to Tanke it is for this reason that Rancière speaks of
politics as “made up of the relationships between worlds” and not simply conflicts over
power. Tanke J (2011) 62- 63. As he explains, for Rancière the concept of power has outlived
its usefulness. Tanke J (2011) 62- 63. It was formerly an instrument for problematising aspects
of existence erroneously believed to be apolitical. It provided resources for critiquing
phenomena as diverse as education, urbanism, the framing of life in the media and the ability
of class, race, gender and heteronormative privileges to perpetuate themselves. For
Rancière, it sustains the thesis that “everything is political” and therefore ends politics. See
Rancière (1999) 31-32 & 118.
71
Politics
as
dissensus
means
that
police
distributions
are
never
secure
and
can
be
continually
contested
by
those
who
as
subjects
question
its
objects,
parameters
and
partitions.
Before
explaining
Rancière’s
notion
of
the
political
subject,
I
reiterate
the
most
important
points
discussed
above.
Politics
is
an
antagonistic
activity,
which
inscribes
equality
into
police
situations
of
inequality.
Its
aim
is
to,
on
the
basis
of
a
universal
equality
(the
equality
of
speaking
beings),
disrupt
particular
hierarchal
arrangements
so
as
to
reconfigure
the
police
order
that
we
must
live
in.
Equality
is
central
in
Rancière’s
conception
of
politics.
Political
subjects
presuppose
it
on
their
own
and
it
is
an
equality
that
is
demonstrated
and
manifested
in
order
to
generate
obligations
within
a
specific
police
order.
Politics
occur
in
a
scene
of
dissensus,
which
is
the
setting
up
of
a
scene
or
a
stage
where
equality
can
play
itself
out.
It
lays
bare
the
contingency
of
police
meanings,
rejecting
police
definitions.
The
police
order
is
concerned
with
titles
and
roles,
classification
and
identification.
Politics
is
concerned
with
not
only
breaking
with
the
established
framework
of
the
police,
but
importantly;
with
opening
up
the
possibility
of
reconfiguring
the
police
order
itself.
If
the
police
order
is
concerned
with
prescribing
what
is
thinkable
and
perceptible,
the
political
subject
is
concerned
with
instituting
breaches
so
that
other
meanings
and
directions
are
possible.
In
the
section
below
I
explain
Rancière’s
notion
of
the
political
subject.
2.3.3
The
Political
Subject
Politics,
as
mentioned,
involves
dissensus.
It
is
the
disruption
and
reconfiguration
by
a
political
subject
of
the
given
order
of
domination
and
the
political
subject,
in
Rancière’s
terms,
only
emerges
and
comes
to
exist
through
the
act
of
politics.355
To
engage
in
politics
is
not
to
discover
a
subject
of
politics,
it
is
rather
to
create
one.356
Before
the
scene
of
dissensus,
before
the
enactment
of
equality
there
is
no
political
subject.
Political
subjectivity
happens
alongside
and
through
the
355
Rancière J (2010) 31.
356
May T (2008) 71.
72
enactment
of
equality.
To
become
a
subject
is
therefore,
as
May
explains,
one
side
of
the
coin.357
The
other
side
is
the
creation
of
dissensus.
Rancière
states
that
“[i]t
consists
of
creating
a
stage
around
a
specific
conflict
on
which
the
equality
or
inequality
as
speaking
beings
of
the
partners
in
conflict
can
be
played
out”.358
One
becomes
a
subject
by
“rejecting
the
classification
of
the
police
order
and
one
does
that
by
acting
and
speaking
in
a
way
that
demonstrates
equality
that
runs
counter
to
the
inequality
of
the
classifications
of
the
police
order”.359
Equality
cannot
be
received,
but
only,
as
mentioned,
practiced
or
verified
by
the
political
subject.
As
May
further
notes,
Rancière
might
argue
that
equality
cannot
be
received,
because
to
receive
it,
is
already
to
be
less
than
equal
to
those
who
bestow
it.
Democratic
politics
is
politics
of
the
formation
of
subjects.360
Rancière
states:
Politics
is
not
the
exercise
of
power.
Politics
ought
to
be
defined
in
its
own
specific
mode
of
action
that
is
enacted
by
a
specific
subject
and
that
has
its
own
proper
rationality.
It
is
the
political
relationship
that
makes
it
possible
to
conceive
of
the
subject
of
politics,
not
the
other
way
around.361
Therefore,
there
is
no
sphere
of
pre-‐constituted
subjects.
There
are
no
pre-‐given
interests,
classes
or
struggles.362
Interests,
classes
and
struggles
arise
because
a
group
of
people
decide
to
make
itself
a
subject
by
demonstrating
their
equality.
Rancière
explains
it
in
the
following
way:
Politics
does
not
happen
just
because
the
poor
oppose
the
rich.
It
is
the
other
way
around:
politics
causes
the
poor
to
exist
as
entity.363
Rancière
does
not
mean
here
that
nobody
is
poor
before
the
emergence
of
politics.
What
come
into
existence
are
not
poor
people,
but
the
poor,
a
collective
subject
taking
action
by
challenging
the
police
order’s
presupposition
of
the
inequality
of
poor
people.364
In
order
to
describe
the
political
subject
as
Rancière
357
As above.
358
Rancière J (1999) 51.
359
May T (2008) 71.
360
As above.
361
Rancière J (2010) 27.
362
As above.
363
Rancière J (1999) 11.
364
May T Borderlands (2009) 7.
73
envisions
it,
it
is
important
to
introduce
the
concept
of
“subjectivisation”,
“subjectivation”
or
“subjectification”:
By
way
of
subjectification
I
mean
the
production
through
a
series
of
actions
of
a
body
and
a
capacity
for
enunciation
not
previously
identifiable
within
a
given
field
of
experience,
whose
identification
is
thus
part
of
the
reconfiguration
of
the
field
of
experience.365
Subjectivation
is
a
production
that
arises
through
collective
action.
It
does
not
give
rise
to
collective
action
and
does
not
pre-‐exist
it.
It
also,
as
May
notes,
doesn’t
arise
from
collective
action
as
a
consequence.
Subjectivation
rather
arises
through
collective
action,
within
it
and
alongside
it.366
What
therefore
arises
is
a
we.367
Where
there
were
once
individuals,
within
the
moment
of
politics,
a
subject
of
collective
action
comes
to
exist
when
the
members,
recognising
one
another
in
solidarity,
confront
the
police
order
on
the
basis
of
equality.368
But
what
then
distinguishes
politics
from
any
group
taking
action
in
its
own
name?
Let’s
say
in
the
name
of
women,
homosexuals
or
black
people?
Importantly,
subjectivation
should
not
be
understood
as
a
process
of
identifying,
but
rather
as
one
of
declassifying.
May
states:
A
democratic
politics
rejects
the
hierarchy
of
the
police
order
not
in
the
name
of
particular
identities,
but
in
the
name
of
equality,
the
equality
of
speaking
beings.369
The
process
of
subjectivation
is
not
a
process
of
adding
a
new
police
category,
but
a
process
of
undercutting
police
categories.
It
does
not
merely
give
us
a
new
name
that
can
be
added
to
the
existing
names
in
the
police
order.370
Rancière
argues
that
“[t]he
essence
of
equality
is
in
fact
not
so
much
to
unify
as
to
declassify,
to
undo
the
supposed
naturalness
of
orders
and
to
replace
it
with
365
Rancière J (1999) 35. It seems that these terms are used interchangeably in the English
translations of Rancière’s books as well as in the various works of authors who write about the
process of subjectivation. See for example the index of words in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.)
(2009) 352.
366
May T Borderlands (2009) 7.
367
As above.
368
As above.
369
As above.
370
As above.
74
controversial
figures
of
division”.371
Identification
imposes
qualities,
usually
qualities
already
associated
with
the
police
order.372
Subjectivation
is
not
blackness
or
the
feminine,
for
example,
or
any
other
particular
content
for
that
matter.
The
underlying
meaning
is
equality
and
only
equality.373
The
following
important
question
has
been
formulated
in
this
regard:
Is
the
concept
of
equality
shorn
from
any
type
of
identity
capable
of
supporting
politics
directed
at
specific
hierarchal
conditions?374
Or
put
differently,
don’t
we
need
the
specific
content
of
identity
in
order
to
struggle
against
the
identity
imposed
by
the
police
order.
May
answers
this
question
in
the
following
way
and
I
quote
him
at
length:
Rancière’s
politics
does
not
deny
that
people
in
struggle
see
themselves
as
having
particular
identities.
What
is
at
issue
is
how
the
politics
defines
itself
or
at
least
how
its
unfolding
reveals
it
to
be.
We
might
put
the
point
this
way:
an
identity
may
be
motivating
for
political
actors,
and
it
may
structure
the
way
they
act,
but
what
is
politically
relevant
for
a
democratic
politics
does
not
have
to
do
with
any
of
that.
It
only
has
to
do
with
whether
the
presupposition
of
equality
is
in
play:
that
is,
whether
the
action
taken
is
reasonably
seen
as
an
expression
of
that
presupposition.
[...]
What
is
at
stake
is
not
the
preservation
of
identity
but
the
equality
of
those
who
seek
to
live
as
they
see
fit.
[...]
It
is
the
politics
of
those
who,
regardless
of
[let’s
say
for
example]
their
sexual
orientation,
see
one
another
as
fellow
members
of
a
police
order
that
can
incorporate
and
co-‐opt
almost
anything
into
its
operation:
anything,
of
course,
except
equality.375
Gabriel
Rockhill
has
defined
Rancière’s
political
subject
as:
neither
a
political
lobby
nor
an
individual
who
seeks
adequate
representation
for
his
or
her
interests
and
ideas.
It
is
an
empty
operator
that
produces
cases
of
political
dispute
by
challenging
the
established
framework
of
identification
and
classification.376
The
established
framework
of
identification
and
classification
is
of
course
the
police
order.
“Identity”
is
therefore
not
a
term
usually
associated
with
Rancière’s
work.
In
fact,
he
is
highly
critical
of
identity,
specifically
the
way
in
which
it
371
Rancière J (1995) 37.
372
May T Borderlands (2009) 7.
373
As above.
374
May T Borderlands (2009) 12.
375
May T Borderlands (2009) 14-15.
376
Rockhill G “Glossary of Technical Terms” in Rancière J (ed.) The Politics of Aesthetics
(2004) 90.
75
operates
within
and
becomes
identical
to
the
distribution
and
classifications
of
the
police
order.
It
is
for
this
reason
that
it
might
be
apt
to
describe,
as
Rockhill
does,
Rancière’s
political
subject
as
an
“empty
operator”.377
In
this
regard,
Rancière
states
the
following:
For
me
politics
is
never
a
question
of
identity;
it
always
stages
a
gap
[un
ècart].
When
one
says
“we
are
the
people”,
I
would
say
precisely
that
“we”
and
“the
people”
is
not
the
same
thing;
politics
takes
place
in
the
gap
between
the
two.
[…]
For
me
politics
is
the
constitution
of
a
theatrical
and
artificial
sphere
[…]
A
political
subject
is
a
type
of
theatrical
being,
temporary
and
localised.378
It
should
be
mentioned
that
the
notion
of
verifying
equality,
or
presupposing
it,
encompasses
the
idea
that
one
is
acting
“as
if”
one
is
an
equal
and
the
idea
of
creating
a
scene
of
dissensus
relates
to
the
idea
of
building
a
stage
from
where
to
demonstrate
one’s
equality.
This
notion
of
acting
“as
if”
shall
be
discussed
in
more
detail
later,
when
discussing
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
Rancière
uses
a
number
of
theatrical
metaphors
in
order
to
explain
his
politics
and
it
is
from
within
this
formulation
that
he
conceptualises
the
political
subject,
not
according
to
any
type
of
identity,
but
according
to
the
enactment
of
equality,
through
the
process
of
subjectivation.
The
people
“does
not
constitute
a
type
of
group;
it
is
not
a
mass;
it
is
purely
the
name
of
an
act
of
subjectivisation”.379
In
order
to
understand
Rancière’s
political
subject,
we
need
to
make
a
distinction
between
the
identities
forced
upon
people
in
the
police
order
and
the
political
subjects
that
break
from
these
allocations.380
It
is
only
through
the
elaboration
of
bodies
and
voices
not
identified
within
the
police
order
that
politics
take
place.
This
is
what
Rancière
means
when
he
states
in
the
above-‐mentioned
quote
that
politics
involves
“actions
of
a
body
and
a
capacity
for
enunciation
not
previously
identifiable
within
a
given
field
of
experience,
whose
identification
is
thus
part
of
377
As above.
378
Citton Y “Political Agency and the Ambivalence of the Sensible” in Rockhill G & Watts P
(2009) 129-130.
379
As above.
380
Tanke J (2011) 67.
76
the
reconfiguration
of
the
field
of
experience”.381
The
political
subject
is
a
class
that
belongs
to
no
one
in
particular
and
thus
potentially
to
everyone.382
The
process
of
subjectivation
contains
two
closely
related
moments;
firstly,
the
moment
of
disidentification
where
the
subject
tears
away
from
the
identities
and
interests
as
defined
by
the
police.383
In
other
words,
the
moment
when
an
individual
actively
challenges
their
position
within
the
dominant
order.
And
the
second
moment
entails
a
creation
of
new
subjectivities
in
excess
to
the
parts
already
identifiable
within
the
police
order.384
These
subjectivities
revolve
around
“impossible
identifications”
or
names
that
do
not
belong
to
anyone
in
particular.
Tanke
elucidates:
Strictly
speaking,
these
subjectivities
cannot
be
inhabited
by
the
person
or
group
making
the
identification;
however,
they
provide
the
means
for
escaping
the
policed
identities
that
limit
individuals.385
The
impossible
identification
allows
a
subject
to
extend
beyond
itself,
redefining
capacities
and
insisting
upon
commonality
with
others.386
In
“Politics,
Identification
and
Subjectivization”
Rancière
refers
to
an
impossible
identification
as
“an
identification
that
cannot
be
embodied
by
he
or
she
who
utters
it”.387
Rather
than
erasing
the
difference
between
one
subject
and
another,
impossible
identifications
take
“the
difference
between
voice
and
body”
to
generate
otherwise
unimaginable
political
effects.388
Rancière
states:
“We
are
the
wretched
of
the
earth”
is
the
kind
of
sentence
that
no
wretched
of
the
earth
could
ever
utter.
Or,
to
take
a
personal
example,
for
my
generation
politics
in
France
relied
on
an
impossible
identification-‐
and
identification
with
the
bodies
of
Algerians
beaten
to
death
and
thrown
into
the
Seine
by
the
French
police,
in
the
name
of
the
French
people,
in
October
1961.
We
could
not
identify
with
those
Algerians,
but
we
could
question
our
identification
with
the
“French
people”
in
whose
name
they
were
murdered.
That
is
to
say,
we
could
act
as
political
subjects
in
the
interval
or
381
Rancière J (1999) 35.
382
Tanke J (2011) 67.
383
Tanke J (2011) 67.
384
As above.
385
As above.
386
As above.
387
Rancière J October (1992) 67.
388
Parker A “Impossible Speech-Acts: Jacques Rancière’s Erich Auerbach” in Rockhill G &
Watts P (eds.) (2009) 256.
77
gap
between
two
identities,
neither
of
which
we
could
assume.
That
process
of
subjectivisation
had
no
proper
name,
but
it
found
its
name,
its
cross
name,
in
the
1968
assumption
“We
are
all
German
Jews”-‐
a
“wrong”
identification,
an
identification
in
terms
of
the
denial
of
an
absolute
wrong.389
Therefore,
to
identify
with
the
Algerian
people
is
impossible.
It
was
impossible
to
identify
with
their
lives
and
suffering
under
the
existing
regime,
yet
neither
was
it
possible
to
identify
with
the
French
in
whose
name
they
had
been
killed.
But,
as
Rancière
states,
“we
could
act
in
the
interval
between
two
identities”,
hence
the
slogan
“We
are
all
German-‐Jews”
whilst
most
of
the
demonstrators
were
not
themselves
German
Jews.
Therefore,
what
is
staged
by
the
political
subject
is
not
an
identity,
but
the
gap
between
two
identities.
The
idea
of
subjectivation
will
become
clearer
later
with
the
discussion
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
with
illustration
of
some
of
the
examples
that
Rancière
uses.
At
this
junction
it
should
be
made
clear
that
political
subjectivity
is
about
reconfiguring
the
police
order
by
creating
new
identities,
capacities
or
bodies.
It
is
therefore
a
claim
to
equality
that
rejects
the
allocations
of
the
police
order
and
appeals
to
identifications
that
are
new
to
the
police
order
and
that
holds
the
potential
to
reconfigure
the
order.
Subjectivation
is
the
process
of
straying
from
one’s
“natural”
position
given
by
the
police
order,
under
the
heading
of
equality,
in
order
to
create
new
capacities
or
bodies.
The
example
that
Rancière
uses
and
mentioned
above
is
complex
and
contains
multiple
nuances.
But,
ultimately,
for
the
purposes
of
this
section,
Rancière
stipulates
that
subjectivation
is
never
simply
about
the
assertion
of
identity
but
always
also
about
the
refusal
of
an
identity
imposed
by
others,
by
the
police
order,
and
it
therefore
involves
an
impossible
identification,
which
places
the
subject
between
identities.390
The
subject
strays
from
the
police
order
identity
and
then
has
to
identify
with
something
else,
an
identification
that
undercuts
the
police
order
and
therefore
doesn’t
exist
within
the
given
police
order.
Because
of
the
fact
that
it
doesn’t
exist
within
the
police
order,
it
is
an
impossible
identification,
so
to
speak.
The
discussion
of
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny
in
the
next
chapter
will
illustrate
in
more
389
Parker A in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 257.
390
Davis O (2010) 42.
78
detail
in
what
way
impossible
identifications
can
be
made.
Impossible
identifications,
at
this
juncture,
can
be
said
to
involve
names
belonging
to
no
one
in
particular
because
they
are
not
simply
the
reiteration
of
police
identities.391
The
particular
name
is
not
the
important
thing
in
question.
Rather,
it
is
how
that
name
manifests,
the
content
it
is
given
and
the
way
in
which
it
used
to
disrupt
police
order
identities.
Because
it
is
not
merely
a
confirmation
of
the
categories
of
the
police
order,
the
subject
is
between
identities,
between
a
police
identity
and
an
impossible
identity.
At
this
stage,
it
should
therefore
suffice
to
say
that
dissensual
politics
prefers
polemics,
discord
and
confusion
to
the
identities,
places
and
capacities
of
the
police
order.
This
definition
is
intimately
related
to
Rancière’s
view
of
politics
as
disruptive,
as
that
which
attempts
to
break
apart
the
police
order’s
logic
and
to
reconfigure
the
order.
Politics
and
political
subjectivity
is
about
mixing
identities,
spaces
and
places
of
the
police
order.
It
is
about
challenging
the
police
order’s
account
of
things
by
demonstrating
something
different
to
the
police
order
and,
not
merely
disrupting
it,
but
opening
up
the
possibility
of
reconfiguring
the
order
itself;
and
equality
is
the
vehicle
of
this
demonstration.
It
is
further
important
to
mention
that
subjectivation
has
a
complex
relation
to
time
and
it
relates
to
the
time
of
politics.
Subjectivation
is
“self-‐creation”
and
a
people
in
struggle
become
subjects
when
they
act
out
of
a
collective
sense
of
their
equality.392
However,
although
the
sense
of
one’s
equality
is
bound
to
the
struggle
itself,
it
is
projected
backwards
in
time.
May
explains:
Thus
equality
is
not
simply
that
presupposition
which
ascribes
social
congregation
in
the
last
instance
to
the
community
of
speaking
beings
as
to
a
principle
necessarily
forgotten;
for
it
is
manifested
in
the
recurring
rupture
which,
by
projecting
the
egalitarian
presupposition
back
to
a
point
anterior
to
itself,
endows
it
with
social
significance.393
391
Tanke J (2011) 67.
392
May T (2008) 71.
393
May T (2008) 72.
79
The
political
subject
is
therefore
the
subject
that
acts
“as
if”
it
has
always
been
equal
within
a
particular
dissensus
or
instance.
Or
more
to
the
point,
the
political
subjects
act
as
if
it
has
always
been
a
political
subject
within
a
particular
dissensus.
Before
explaining
the
notions
of
“the
wrong
and
the
miscount”,
it
should
be
reiterated
that
one
becomes
a
political
subject
within
a
specific
scene
of
dissensus
by
rejecting
police
classifications
and
identities
as
well
as
the
allocations
of
ways
of
doing,
seeing,
saying
and
being
that
the
police
order
states
should
follow
from
these
classifications
or
identities.
It
is
about
rejecting
the
“natural”
position
given
by
the
police
order
as
well
as
the
implicit
police
order
assumptions
about
that
position.
There
are
no
pre-‐constituted
political
subjects
that
are
regarded
as
qualified
to
participate
in
politics.
It
is
through
the
construction
of
a
“we”
that
speaks
in
and
through
equality
that
a
political
subject
is
constituted.
As
shall
become
clear
later,
for
Rancière,
unimaginable
political
effects
can
be
generated
by
the
process
of
subjectivation,
by
the
process
of
speaking
to
the
gap
between
identities
and
by
identifying
with
the
impossible.
The
wrong
and
the
miscount
further
elucidates
Rancière’s
political
subject.
I
turn
to
these
notions
below.
2.3.4
The
wrong
and
the
miscount
It
was
mentioned
in
the
previous
section
that
subjectivation
is
as
much
a
struggle
for
recognition
of
the
political
existence
of
subjects
as
it
is
for
the
identification
with
a
new
category.
The
notions
of
the
miscount
and
the
wrong
serve
to
further
elucidate
this
idea.
Rancière,
in
order
to
explain
his
formulation
of
the
“structural
miscount”,
looks
back
at
democracy
in
ancient
Athens.
Democracy
emerged
after
Solon’s
reforms
of
594
BCE
abolished
enslavement
for
indebtedness.394
Davis
explains
that
this
led
to
the
emergence
of
a
class
of
citizen
called
the
demos
or
394
Davis O (2010) 80. See also Rancière J (1999) 9.
80
the
people.395
The
demos
lacked
all
of
the
traditional
attributes
thought
necessary
for
active
involvement
in
the
political
process
or
public
sphere,
such
as
noble
birth,
wealth
or
moral
excellence.
Yet,
they
nevertheless
claimed
not
only
to
participate
in
the
political
process,
but
also
to
be
on
equal
footing
with
those
thought
to
have
the
right
to
participate
in
politics.396
Their
claim
is
a
response
to
what
Rancière
calls
the
“wrong”
(le
tort).
This
refers
to
the
fact
that
they
are
denied
a
legitimate
part
in
society,
or
the
right
to
legitimate
political
participation.397
Aristotle
describes
the
members
of
the
demos
as
those
who
had
“no
part
in
anything”.398
Their
political
existence
was
essentially
denied.
For
Rancière
the
demos
is
a
prime
example
of
a
political
subject.
Rancière
states
that
the
demos
is:
An
excessive
part-‐
the
whole
of
those
who
are
nothing,
who
do
not
have
specific
properties
allowing
them
to
exercise
power
[...]
Democracy
is,
properly
speaking,
the
symbolic
institution
of
the
political
in
the
form
of
the
power
of
those
who
are
not
entitled
to
exercise
power-‐
a
rupture
in
the
order
of
legitimacy
and
domination.
Democracy
is
the
paradoxical
power
of
those
who
do
not
count:
the
count
of
the
unaccounted
for.399
“The
part
of
those
who
have
no
part”
(la
part
des
sans-‐part)
occurs
alongside
“the
count
of
the
uncounted”
(le
compte
des
incomptes).400
The
demos
becomes
the
very
subject
of
politics
and
Rancière
uses
Aristotle’s
formulation
in
order
to
explain
the
notions
of
the
wrong
and
the
miscount.
The
demos
is
the
political
subject
inasmuch
as
it
is
capable
of
exceeding
and
thereby
undermining
the
police’s
accounting.401
The
demos
therefore
have
no
recognised
existence
within
the
social
hierarchy
of
the
police
order.
They
do
not
count
and
they
have
not
been
counted.
Policing
therefore
also
denotes
a
specific
way
of
counting.402
An
aspect
of
the
police
order
has
counted
all
the
parts
of
the
community.
Policing
is
not
just
a
way
of
counting
the
actual
groups
that
make
up
the
social
whole,
it
is
also
a
way
of
counting
that
excludes
the
possibility
of
any
remainder
to
that
395
Davis O (2010) 80.
396
As above.
397
As above.
398
As above.
399
Davis O (2010) 81. Rancière J in Panagia D Diacritics (2000) 124.
400
Tanke J (2011) 43.
401
As above.
402
Chambers S European Journal of Political Theory (2011) 307.
81
order.403
As
Davis
explains,
the
police
must
count
it
all.
The
demos
is
therefore
the
part
“that
has
no
part”,
“the
unaccounted
for”.
Politics
occurs
when
the
demos
appears
through
the
enactment
of
equality,
by
the
construction
of
a
scene
of
dissensus.404
Whereas
the
police
define
the
community
as
unified
and
whole,
politics
consists
of
contesting
the
very
definition
of
community.405
It
demonstrates
that
there
has
been
a
fundamental
“miscount”
and
insist,
through
the
enactment
of
the
equality
of
speaking
beings,
that
there
is
another
ac/count
of
the
city.406
For
Rancière,
the
hierarchy
of
a
specific
social
order
is
based
on
the
basic
injustice
of
the
wrong
or
this
miscount.
The
demos’
claim
to
equality
is
therefore
also
an
assertion
of
their
existence
outside
of
the
police’s
accounting.
Their
egalitarian
claim
seeks
to
highlight
the
contingency
of
the
police
order’s
hierarchy,
which
is
a
hierarchy
based
on
a
basic
injustice,
the
fundamental
miscount
or
wrong
of
their
non-‐existence.407
Therefore,
politics
cannot
be
other
than
antagonistic
or
disputatious,
because
it
is
the
expression
of
a
basic
disagreement
with
a
police
order
that
recognises
neither
the
claim,
nor
the
existence
of
the
part
that
has
no
part.408
The
police
order
assumes
that
there
is
no
part
of
those
who
have
no
part.
And
the
struggle
for
equality
is
the
struggle
for
the
very
existence
of
the
part
of
those
who
have
no
part
as
subject.
Equality
exists
through
the
inability
of
any
political
order
to
count
the
shares
of
the
community
or
the
communal
parts
and
distribute
the
common
between
them
on
the
basis
of
some
“harmonious
geometrical
governance”
or
what
Rancière
refers
to
as
an
arkhe
(a
principle
of
justice
or
the
good
for
example).409
Because
403
As above.
404
As above.
405
As above.
406
Tanke J (2011) 43.
407
Davis O (2010) 81.
408
As above.
409
Arsenjuk L “On Jacques Rancière” Fronesis (2005) 1-2. (Published on 2007/03/05 and
available online at Eurozine Journals www.eurozine.com/ articles/2007-01-01-arsenjuk-en.html
(accessed 28-12-2014). Rancière states: “An arkhe is two things: it is a theoretical principle
entailing a clear distribution of positions and capacities, grounding the distribution of power
between rulers and ruled; and it is a temporal beginning entailing that the fact of ruling is
anticipated in the disposition to the rule and, conversely, that the evidence of this disposition
is given by the fact of its empirical operation”. Rancière J (2010) 51. For Rancière the
82
there
is
no
arkhe
or
perfect
principle
or
transcendental
truth
according
to
which
the
parts
of
the
community
can
be
regarded,
there
is
a
fundamental
wrong
done
during
any
type
of
counting.410
The
equality
of
speaking
beings
is
irreducible
to
any
political
order
and
thus
never
instituted
as
such.
Arsenjuk
notes:
It
is
an
equality
which
presents
itself
only
through
a
declaration
of
a
wrong
committed
by
the
count
of
the
community
parts-‐
it
is
thus,
an
equality
which
exists
through
what
it
denies.411
Equality
needs
to
be
axiomatically
assumed
through
the
declaration
of
the
wrong.412
This
equality
is
of
course
simply
the
equality
of
anyone
with
everyone
else,
or
the
equality
of
speaking
beings.
It
demonstrates
the
absence
of
the
arkhe,
of
a
proper
principle
or
the
sheer
contingency
of
the
social
order.413
The
political
subject
demonstrates
not
merely
the
lack
of
proper
principle,
“but
the
principle
that
there
is
lack
of
a
proper
principle”.414
Politics
is
the
process
that
authorises
the
exercise
of
power
by
those
with
no
sanctioned
authorisation
or
authority.
Politics
is
the
process
that
founds
the
power
to
govern
other
people
on
nothing
other
than
“the
absence
of
foundation”,
on
nothing
other
than
the
absence
of
the
arkhe.415
existence of a wrong pre-sets philosophy with the effect of another kind of equality, “one that
suspends simple arithmetic without setting up any kind of geometry. This equality is simply
the equality of anyone with anyone else: in other words, in the final analysis, the absence of
arkhe, the sheer contingency of any social order”. Rancière J (1999) 15. According to
Rancière, it is this contingency that the existence of politics makes manifest and that political
philosophy has sought to domesticate and placate by suturing politics to a certain extra-
political principle. Rancière J (1999) 15. Arsenjuk explains that this takes on three forms:
Firstly, “archi-politics”; this refers to Plato and the attempt to tie politics to a communitarian
rule, to subsume politics under the logic of a strict and closed distribution of parts and the
establishment of a social space which is homogenously structured and thus leaves no space
for politics to emerge. Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 3-4. Secondly, “para-politics”; this refers to
Aristotle and the attempt to reduce political antagonism to mere competition, negotiation
and exercise of an agonic procedure, or, to draw the political subject into the police order as
just one more of its many parts. Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 3-4. Lastly, “meta-politics”; this
refers to Marx and the understanding of political antagonism as a displaced manifestation of
“true” antagonism, which is socio-economic, or, politics that can only happen with the
promise of its self-abolishment or the destruction of the political theatre that is necessary for
the direct administration of the socio-economic sphere. Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 3-4. See
Rancière J (1999) 61-93.
410
As above.
411
As above.
412
As above.
413
As above.
414
As above.
415
Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P (2009) 146.
83
For
Rancière
democracy
is
a
radical
paradox
and
it
is
indeed
the
paradox
of
politics
itself.
It
is
a
paradox
“[b]ecause
the
institution
of
politics
seems
to
provide
an
answer
to
the
key
question
as
to
what
it
is
that
grounds
the
power
of
rule
in
a
community”.416
And
democracy
provides
an
answer,
but
it
is
an
astonishing
one:
namely,
that
the
very
ground
for
the
power
of
ruling
is
that
there
is
no
ground
at
all”.417
Rancière
thinks
of
politics
in
the
form
of
encounter.418
Politics
opposes
the
logic
of
“the
supplementary”
(that
there
is
another
part)
with
the
logic
of
the
police
logic
of
saturation
(all
is
counted).
The
police
take
for
granted
that
there
are
only
the
existing
parts
of
society
and
that
each
of
them
has
been
given
its
due,
its
common
share.
Politics
claims
the
opposite,
that
there
is
a
wrong
done
in
the
existing
count
of
the
community,
that
there
is
the
part
of
those
who
have
no
part
and
it
is
through
constructing
a
scene
of
dissensus
in
which
the
existence
of
the
wrong
is
verified.
It
is
also
then
through
the
axiomatic
assumption
or
presupposition
of
equality
that
the
political
subject
is
born.419
Further,
the
part
of
those
who
have
no
part
has
to
be
staged
because
it
is
not
a
part
identifiable
or
recognisable
within
the
police
order,
as
such
an
“impossible
identification”
is
necessary.420
The
demos,
the
people,
appear
as
the
exception
that
stands
in
for
the
whole
and
has
the
effect
of
disrupting
existing
identifications
by
separating
the
community
parts
from
its
places.
For
Rancière
there
are
no
privileged
political
actors,
no
inherently
political
object;
there
is
no
proper
political
content.
Because
of
the
fact
that
politics
occurs
within
the
police
order
and
it
shares
its
objects
and
its
content
and
happens
against
its
background,
politics
is
a
matter
of
form:
Anything
can
become
political
(the
strike,
the
demonstration,
the
workplace)-‐
if
it
breaks
with
the
logic
of
negotiation
between
the
existing
parts
of
social
entities,
stop
being
the
site
of
determination
of
the
proper,
an
becomes
a
scene
of
an
encounter
between
the
logic
of
the
police
and
the
416
As above.
417
Rancière J (2010) 50.
418
Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 15.
419
Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 4.
420
As above.
84
axiomatic
assumption
of
equality,
a
subjectivisation
of
a
wrong
and
the
disidentification
of
the
communal
parts
from
themselves.421
It
has
been
noted
that
the
idea
of
the
wrong
or
le
tort,
derived
from
the
word
“torde”,
a
verb
that
Rancière
frequently
uses,
means
to
wring
or
to
twist.422
This
indicates
that
the
wrong
is
torsion
or
twisting
of
the
equality
underpinning
all
human
relationships.
Social
inequality
is
therefore
a
wronging
or
wringing
of
the
primordial
equality
on
which
inequality
relies.423
Politics
name
these
twists.
It
disrupts
the
supposed
naturalness
of
the
initial
count
with
the
emergence
of
the
demos,
whose
emergence
also
manifests
the
wrong.424
The
emergence
of
the
demos
impacts
on
the
entire
community
for
the
reason
that
it
cannot
begin
to
take
part
without
altering
the
ordering,
count
and
distribution
of
parts
constituted
at
its
expense.425
The
logic
of
the
arkhe,
mentioned
above,
attempts
to
turn
the
arbitrariness
of
the
social
into
something
natural
and
it
is
the
emergence
of
the
demos
that
makes
its
arbitrariness
manifest.
The
essentially
groundless
nature
of
human
community,
along
with
any
natural
equality
that
might
exist
is
covered
over
by
a
“geometric
equality”
that
attempts
to
supress
the
emergence
of
the
demos,
by
claiming
it
doesn’t
exist.426
The
emergence
of
the
demos
therefore
turns
the
consensual
community
into
a
litigious
one;
where
the
community
was
the
sum
of
its
parts,
the
emergence
of
the
demos
separates
the
community
from
itself.427
421
As above.
422
Tanke J (2011) 52.
423
As above.
424
As above.
425
As above.
426
Tanke J (2011) 54.
427
Rancière states: “Politics exist whenever the counts of parts and parties of society is
disturbed by the inscription of a part of those who have no part. It begins when the equality
of anyone and everyone is inscribed in the liberty of the people. This liberty of the people is
an empty property, an improper property through which those who are nothing can purport
that their group is identical to the whole of the community. Politics exists as long as singular
forms of subjectification repeat the forms of the original inscription of the identity between
the whole of the community and the nothing that separates it from itself- in other words, the
sole count of its parts. Politics ceases wherever this gap no longer has any place, wherever
the whole of the community is reduced to the sum of its parts with nothing left over”.
Rancière J (1999) 306.
85
It
should
further
be
noted
that
the
wrong
does
not
simply
precede
and
therefore
determine
political
subjects.428
This
would
mean
finding
the
equivalent
of
an
arkhe
of
politics.
The
situation
is
a
bit
more
complicated.
Arsenjuk
explains
that
the
declaration
of
the
wrong
that
marks
the
beginning
of
politics
happens
within
the
police
order.429
The
police
order
is
by
its
definition
the
order
of
the
non-‐existence
of
the
wrong.
The
wrong
can’t
therefore
simply
precede
its
declaration.
The
wrong
does
not
simply
precede
the
appearance
of
the
subject.430
Not
only
does
the
political
subject
appear
within
the
police
order,
but
also
the
wrong
itself:
The
declaration
of
a
wrong
is
therefore
never
simply
a
statement
of
an
already
existing
fact.
Politics
is
not
the
countering
of
facts
with
other
facts.
The
existence
of
a
wrong
is
not
a
fact.
The
declaration
of
the
wrong
consists
rather
in
the
break
with
the
logic
of
the
factual.431
In
a
strict
sense
then
the
declaration
of
a
wrong
is
impossible
due
to
the
fact
that
the
wrong
does
not
precede
such
a
declaration.
Nevertheless,
the
declaration
occurs.
It
happens
through
an
“enunciation
that
retroactively
changes
the
conditions
of
its
own
possibility”.432
As
Arsenjuk
aptly
notes,
the
birth
of
the
political
subject
through
the
declaration
of
the
wrong
thus
involves
“a
kind
of
free
gesture
or
an
anarchic
that
authorises
itself
through
a
retroactive
presupposition
of
its
own
existence”.433
Rancière’s
analysis
of
the
Greek
experience
allows
him
to
describe
the
encounter
between
politics
and
the
police
as
a
specialised
form
of
class
struggle.434
As
Tanke
notes,
this
is
not
to
say
that
politics
is
in
any
way
about
the
contest
over
goods
within
a
society.435
In
the
Greek
experience,
the
rich
attempt
to
put
an
end
to
politics
by
insisting
upon
the
fundamentally
just
nature
of
the
distribution
of
the
police
order.
The
poor
on
the
other
hand,
who
embody,
according
to
Rancière,
“nothing
other
than
politics
itself”
attempt
to
reconfigure
the
police
distribution
428
Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 4.
429
As above.
430
As above.
431
As above.
432
As above.
433
As above.
434
Tanke J (2011) 52.
435
As above.
86
so
that
they
can
take
part.436
Politics
is
the
means
by
which
the
part
that
has
no
part,
through
the
declaration
of
a
wrong,
“contest
the
categories,
divisions,
identifications
and
means
of
social
integration
that
attempt
to
consign
them
to
non-‐existence”.437
Rancière
makes
it
clear
that
political
conflict
does
not
involve
an
opposition
between
groups
with
different
interests
that
has
an
equal
share
or
equal
right
to
participate
in
politics.438
The
count
of
the
unaccounted
is
relegated
by
the
police
order
to
that
which
is
not.
Politics
forms
an
opposition
between
logics
that
count
the
parties
and
parts
of
the
community
in
different
ways.439
In
conclusion
and
to
clarify,
the
whole
of
the
community
is,
according
to
the
police,
a
perfect
“fittingness
of
functions,
places
and
ways
of
being”.440
Everyone
has
his
or
her
place
and
function.
This
can
even
include
the
poor,
or
those
that
are
excluded.
The
point
is
that
the
police
have
named
them
or
counted
them.
And
with
this
naming
all
the
assumptions
about
what
the
poor
or
the
excluded
can
be
or
do
is
established.
The
police
count
the
community
as
the
sum
or
totality
of
this
“fittingness”
of
empirical
parts,
each
part
bearing
particular
qualifications
for
membership.
These
parts
or
groups
are
defined
by
differences
in
birth,
by
different
functions,
locations
and
interests
and
by
their
“dedication
to
specific
modes
of
action,
in
places
where
these
occupations
are
exercised”.441
The
police
say
what
there
is
and
what
there
is
not
and
politics,
through
the
declaration
of
the
miscount,
disturbs
this
entire
arrangement.
The
demos
therefore
brings
politics
into
existence
through
the
manifestation
of
the
wrong
and
is
therefore
the
subject
of
politics
in
two
senses,
namely:
“It
is
the
agent
whose
emergence
turns
the
consensual
community
into
a
litigious
one,
and
its
existence
as
a
potential
part-‐taker
is
the
very
object
of
confrontation”.442
436
As above.
437
As above.
438
Rancière J (2010) 35.
439
As above.
440
As above.
441
As above.
442
Tanke J (2011) 52.
87
The
miscount
and
the
wrong
can
mean
different
things
in
different
contexts.
Simply
put,
it
refers
to
the
attempt
to
make
manifest
the
fact
that
there
is
nothing
natural,
or
that
there
is
no
principle
that
can
justify
the
existing
structure
of
the
community’s
hierarchies,
parts,
groups
and
positions.
On
the
contrary,
this
structure’s
existence
is
based
on
a
fundamental
miscount,
or
wrong.
The
central
point
that
Rancière
attempts
to
make
with
regards
to
these
specific
notions
of
the
wrong,
the
miscount
and
the
demos
can
be
further
explained
by
his
use
of
the
term
“disagreement”.
Rancière
has
stated
that
politics
“has
the
rationality
of
disagreement
as
its
very
own
rationality”.443
Disagreement
here
does
not
refer
to
simple
differences
of
political
outlook.
Disagreement
“has
clearly
not
to
do
with
words
alone.
It
generally
bears
on
the
very
situation
in
which
speaking
subjects
find
themselves”.444
As
James
explains,
Rancière’s
concern
is
the
concrete
and
material
situation
or
conditions
from
which
people
are
able
to
speak
and
from
which
their
voices
can
be
heard
and
understood.445
It
refers
to
content
as
well
as
position.
As
will
become
clear
later,
disagreement
is
a
function
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
which
divides
up
space
and
place,
sites
and
the
perspectives
of
a
shared
world.
As
such,
disagreement
cannot
simply
be
a
matter
of
discursive
differences,
but
it
rather
concerns
the
ground
of
intelligibility
and
communicability
upon
which
such
differences
may
be
articulated
in
the
first
place.446
Rancière
states
that
disagreement
is
less
concerned
with
arguing
than
with
what
can
be
argued,
the
presence
or
the
absence
of
a
common
object
between
X
and
Y.
It
concerns
the
sensible
presentation
of
this
common
object,
the
very
capacity
of
the
interlocutors
to
present
it.447
Disagreement
is
therefore
not
just
a
difference
in
opinion
or
misrecognition,
nor
is
it
misunderstanding.448
It
therefore
concerns,
as
James
further
notes,
fundamentally
divergent
ways
of
understanding
and
encountering
any
object
of
disagreement
as
well
as
the
relative
possibilities
of
expression
and
443
James I (2010) 120.
444
Rancière J (1999) XI.
445
James I (2012) 121.
446
As above.
447
Rancière J (1999) XII.
448
As above.
88
communication
that
are
available
to
those
who
may
be
party
to
the
disagreement.449
The
essence
of
an
unequal
order
lies
in
the
unequal
distribution
of
material
conditions,
situations
and
positions
which
determine
possibilities
of
active
participation.
James
states:
This
means
that
the
things
which
may
be
disputed
in
Rancière’s
understanding
of
disagreement
are
not
disputed
by
parties
who
have
an
equal
say
in
the
dispute,
nor
an
equal
position
from
which
to
shape
its
terms.450
Politics,
with
disagreement
as
its
rationality,
therefore,
does
not
just
relate
to
the
contestation
of
a
disputed
object
but
also
to
the
status
and
position
from
which
parties
can
speak
and
make
themselves
heard.
451
This
is
why
the
political
subject
is
formulated
as
“the
part
that
has
no
part”.
They
have
no
part
in
the
sense
that
they
are
not
afforded
an
equal
position
to
participate
and
speak
from.
Politics,
through
the
miscount
and
the
wrong,
demonstrates
or
makes
manifest
the
unequal
distribution
of
speaking-‐positions
and
the
contingency
thereof.
Before
turning
to
the
concept
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible,
it
is
necessary
to
state
that
politics
is
therefore
about
the
part
that
has
no
part;
the
demos
that
must
make
manifest
their
existence
as
political
subject
within
a
particular
scene
of
dissensus
or
context.
Rancière
uses
the
Greek
experience
and
the
definition
of
the
demos
in
order
to
show
that
questions
of
politics
and
political
participation
rely
on
prior
decisions
about
what
will
be
a
political
argument
and
who
will
be
able
to
qualify
for
participation
in
what
circumstances.
The
demos,
therefore
449
James I (2012) 121.
450
As above.
451
As above. As James elucidates, for Rancière the activity of politics of disagreement
concerns the inequality of material conditions which determine the possession or otherwise
of a voice or logos. James I (2012) 122. In this context, politics cannot simply be party politics
because political parties already participate, have a voice and are assigned a place within the
social order. James I (2012) 122. Nor, as James further explains, can politics be the more or
less competent management of economic forces and resources since this too is a matter for
those who are already accounted for and have been given a privileged role within the order
of society. James I (2012) 122. Not, for the same reason, can politics be the management of
competing interests within a shared political, legal and juridical framework. Rancière wants to
underline that politics properly speaking is not an activity, which is pursued on the basis of
any consensus, constitutional or institutional or on the basis of shared norms or protocols.
See James I (2012) 122.
89
represents
the
groundlessness
of
any
political
title,
the
fact
that
these
decisions
are
contingent
and
that
there
is
a
different
way
of
counting.
The
part
that
has
no
part
also
serves
to
illustrate
the
notion
that
politics
is
at
once
the
entering
into
a
realm
of
perceptibility
and
visibility.
Other
than
being
the
presupposition
of
equality
through
the
process
of
subjectivation,
by
declaring
a
wrong
against
the
classifications
of
the
police
order,
politics
is
also
about
redistributing
the
sensible.
2.3.5
The
Distribution
of
the
Sensible
Politics
is,
before
all
else,
an
intervention
in
the
visible
and
sayable.452
Rancière
has
stated
that
“[t]here
never
has
been
any
aestheticization
of
politics
in
the
modern
age
because
politics
is
aesthetic
in
principle”.453
And
“[p]olitics
is
aesthetic
in
that
it
makes
visible
what
had
been
excluded
from
a
perceptual
field,
and
in
that
it
makes
audible
what
use
to
be
inaudible”.454
Politics
is
for
Rancière
fundamentally
a
matter
of
expression
and
therefore
of
aesthetics.
Police
orders
are
also
“regimes
of
expression
and
they
determine
what
is
expressible
on
the
basis
of
a
“partition
(or
sharing
out)
of
the
perceptible”.455
Rancière
argues
that
the
struggle
of
politics
is
always
an
aesthetic
struggle
for
a
new
partition
of
what
can
be
called
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.456
As
Ross
affirms,
aesthetics,
in
this
formulation,
should
be
understood
in
its
widest
sense,
not
only
as
perceptibility,
but
also
sensibility.457
Politics
is
demonstrated
and
expressed
and
within
and
through
it
that
the
political
subject
appears.
Politics
is
a
political
aesthetic
countering
of
the
presentations
and
representations
of
the
police
order.458
As
mentioned,
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
comprises
of
a
certain
picture
of
the
world
and
the
police
order
comprises
of
the
mechanisms,
procedures
and
functions
that
enforces
this
picture.
The
police
order
is
therefore
the
means
by
452
Rancière J (2010) 37.
453
Rancière J (1999) 58.
454
Rancière J (2004) 226.
455
Ross D “Politics and Aesthetics, or, Transformations of Aristotle and Bernard Stiegler”
(2009) Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture available at
www.transformationsjournal.or/journal/issue_19/artivle_032.shtml(accessed2014/12/0).
456
As above.
457
As above.
458
As above.
90
which
a
society
enforces
its
distribution
of
the
sensible.
The
police
maintain
the
operations
that
set
the
limit
of
what
is
thinkable,
possible
and
conceivable
and
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
describes
or
defines
the
thinkable,
possible
and
conceivable
within
a
specific
context.
Policing
further
denotes
an
ordering
of
the
parts
of
society,
which
is
an
ordering
“that
invents
a
range
of
communicative
and
behavioural
norms
that
is
then
distributed
on
the
basis
of
a
body’s
nature,
function
and
occupation”.459
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
therefore,
as
mentioned,
comes
down
to
the
perceptual
configuration
of
society.460
What
is
sayable,
what
is
visible,
what
is
understood,
who
counts
and
who
doesn’t?
It
is,
more
or
less,
as
mentioned,
our
“automatic
perception
of
status
identity
and
entitlement”.461
In
this
regard,
the
French
formulation
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
becomes
helpful.
Tanke
explains
that
the
word
partage
has
two
elements
or
senses
that
is
easily
lost
in
the
English
translation.462
Partage
has
a
double
meaning,
namely,
separation
and
community,
dividing
and
sharing.463
In
the
first
sense,
“it
describes
how
partitions
and
divisions
of
the
sensible
is
seen
and
unseen,
audible
and
inaudible,
how
certain
objects
and
phenomena
can
be
related
or
not,
and
also,
who,
at
the
level
of
subjectivity,
can
appear
in
certain
times
and
places”.464
It
denotes,
as
Tanke
further
explains,
a
general
distribution
of
bodies
as
well
as
an
implicit
estimation
of
what
they
are
capable
of
in
what
times
and
in
what
places.465
It
therefore
divides
up
and
separates
spheres,
people,
places
and
times.
The
second
sense
of
partage
indicates
that
these
distributions
are
shared.466
It
indicates
a
sharing
of
the
sensible
that
refers
itself
to
the
principles
and
forms
of
relation
that
are
part
of
the
community
or
common
world.
It
therefore
denotes
the
parcelling
out
of
spaces
and
times
to
create
a
shared
459
Stoneman E Philosophy and Rhetoric (2011) 43.
460
Tanke J (2011) 2.
461
As above.
462
As above.
463
Bosteels B “Rancière’s Leftism, Or, Politics and Its Discontents” in Rockhill G & Watts P
(eds) (2009) 170.
464
Tanke J (2011) 2.
465
As above.
466
As above.
91
world.467
As
Tanke
further
highlights,
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
of
great
significance
to
Rancière.468
Its
distinctions
and
divisions
anticipate
what
is
thinkable
and
possible.469
Tanke
eloquently
explains
that
it
provides
a
picture
of
the
world
of
what
can
be
conceived,
discussed
and
disputed
and
what
can
be
conceived,
discussed
and
disputed
in
turn
structures
what
presents
itself
as
thought
and
as
possibility
for
further
thought.470
The
sensible
provides
courses
of
action,
forms
of
relation
and
what
may
be
regarded
as
new
thought
for
sensible
configuration.471
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
thus
ultimately
defines
the
field
of
possibility
and
impossibility
within
a
specific
context
or
community.472
In
French,
the
word
sense
means
at
once,
sense,
meaning
and
direction.473
Politics
is
a
redistribution
of
the
sensible
and
to
redistribute
the
sensible
means
to
bring
into
question
both
the
obviousness
of
what
can
be
perceived,
thought
and
done,
as
well
as
the
distribution
of
those
thought
capable
of
perceiving,
thinking
and
doing.474
With
his
formulation
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible,
Rancière
is
interested,
as
Tanke
further
explains,
in
the
sense
that
is
made
of
sense.475
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
connotes
to
the
meanings
that
are
made
of
what
appears
to
our
senses.476
The
task
of
politics
is
that
of
introducing
breaches
so
that
other
meanings
and
directions
are
created.477
The
police
order,
enforcing
the
distribution
of
the
sensible,
ultimately
concerns
the
material
ground
of
communicability,
intelligibility
and
sensibility
and
politics
concerns
the
contestation
of
this
material
ground.478
467
As above.
468
Tanke J (2011) 2-3.
469
As above.
470
Tanke J (2011)
471
Tanke J (2011) 2-3.
472
As above.
473
As above.
474
Sellberg K “Sublime gender transposition: The reformed platonism of Jacques Rancière’s
aesthetics as queer performance” Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture 2011
www.transformationsjournal.or/journal/issue_19/artivle_032.shtml (accessed 2014/12/06).
475
Tanke J (2011) 2.
476
Tanke J (2011) 22.
477
Tanke J (2011) 2.
478
Tanke J (2011) 49-50.
92
Citton
mentions
that
the
partition
or
distribution
of
the
sensible
has
become
something
of
a
household
name
in
France.479
With
this
phrase
or
formulation
Rancière
refers
to
the
most
basic
system
of
categorisation
through
which
we
perceive
and
intuitively
classify
the
data
provided
to
our
senses.480
Citton
explains
the
usefulness
of
the
formulation
by
highlighting
that
it
has
been
adopted
by
literary
critics,
philosophers,
theorists
of
aesthetics
as
well
as
sociologists,
who
all
seem
to
find
in
the
formulation
a
way
of
expressing
what
they
always
wanted
to
express.481
Indeed,
many
scholars
have
been
seduced
by
the
phrase
as
its
role
hinges
between
politics
and
aesthetics
and
it
proves
to
be
extremely
helpful
as
it
allows
one
to
dig
tunnels
under
disciplinary
frontiers.482
For
Citton,
it
sets
up
an
interface
through
which
various
approaches
can
interact
and
shed
light
on
each
other
and
it
offers
a
foundational
common
ground
on
the
basis
of
which
one
can
root
and
articulate
various
reflections.483
It
unites
discussions
on
philosophy,
479
Citton Y in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 120.
480
As above.
481
As above.
482
As above.
483
As above. Rockhill explains that Rancière has formulated an alternative conception of the
relationship between art and politics. Rockhill G “The Politics of Aesthetics: Political History
and the Hermeneutics of Art” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 200-201. Instead of searching for
a definitive solution of the long-standing problem of the connection between art and politics,
he attacks the guiding assumption on which the problem is based: “that art and politics are
separate domains in need of being linked together”. See Rockhill G in Rockhill G & Watts P
(eds.) 200-201. Rather, with the notion of the distribution of the sensible, Rancière sums up his
position, namely, that art and politics are consubstantial insofar as they both organise a
common world of self-evident facts of sensory perception: “In fact, the very delimitation and
definition of what are called art and politics are themselves dependent upon a distribution of
the sensible regime of thought and perception that identifies them as such”. See Rockhill G
in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 200-201. Rancière states: “[A]rt and politics are not two separate
realities about which it might be asked if they must be put in relationship to one another.
They are two forms of distribution of the sensible tied to a specific regime of identification”.
See Rancière J Le Destin Des Images (2003) 19. It is argued that since the late 1990’s,
Rancière has put forth one of the most powerful accounts of aesthetics. See Rockhill G in
Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 200-201. Instead of taking art to be historical and attempting to
unveil its fundamental essence he maintains, as Rockhill and Watts elucidates, that there is no
“art in general” but only historically constituted “regimes” that establish a given distribution
of the sensible and determine the framework of possibility for artistic production and
theoretical reflection on art. Rockhill G & Watts P Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 9.
93
politics,
art,
aesthetics,
and
cinema,
all
of
which
are
conceived
of
as
practices
of
creating,
distributing,
contesting
and
redistributing
the
sensible
world.484
When
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
viewed
through
the
lens
of
human
capacity
or
action,
some
data
is
perceived
and
selected
as
relevant
by
people,
while
other
data
is
rejected
as
irrelevant
or
ignored.485
As
Citton
further
elucidates,
each
time
this
happens,
agents
inherit
a
specific
social
configuration
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible,
which
they
can
transmit
as
it
has
been
transmitted
to
them,
or
which,
following
the
encounter
with
this
data,
can
lead
them
to
modify
it
at
a
minute
or
sometimes
more
dramatic
level.486
The
reconfiguration
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
appears,
within
Rancière’s
formulation,
as
the
founding
moment
of
political
subjectivation:
Whether
I
stand
in
front
of
a
work
of
art
or
am
involved
in
a
social
movement,
the
possibility
of
politics
rests
on
such
a
moment
when
I
am
led
to
reconfigure
the
partage
du
sensible
I
have
inherited
from
the
majoritarian
norms
(along
with
its
blind
spots,
its
denial
of
rights,
and
its
hierarchy
of
privileges).487
When
it
comes
to
the
concept
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible,
aesthetics
should
be
understood,
as
mentioned,
in
an
expanded
sense.
It
should
include
484
Tanke J (2011) 1-2.
485
Citton Y in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 123 & 313.
486
As above. Citton further theorises the distribution of the sensible as active in the sense that
theatrical politics draws on our capacity to repartition, alter lines and blur borders. Citton Y in
Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 131-137. Citton reminds that we should not forget that we can only
do so from within a certain given or inherited configuration of the partage du sensible or “a
state of things that pre-exists and largely predetermines our possible work of
reconfiguration”. Citton Y in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 131-137. Before taking place toward
other people, the re-presentation takes place within us. This is what is active in Rancière’s
formulation according to Citton. Citton Y in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 131-137. He refers to
the process of thought within which certain data perceived by our sensory apparatus get to
be considered as relevant, and make it to the point where they become a deciding factor in
the determination of our future behaviours, while other comparable data gets lost along the
way. Citton Y in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 131-137. And it is in this process that we become
agents, political or otherwise. The selective re-presentation appears as a way to mange a
situation of excess. There are too many data in our sensory input for us to give an exhaustive
account of all features. Not everything can count and any given state of things carries excess.
See Citton Y in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 131-137.
487
As above.
94
factors
such
as
time
and
space
that
structure
the
way
in
which
things
appear.488
The
way
in
which
the
given
world
or
the
sensible
is
defined
through
the
partitioning
of
space
and
time
is
political
because
it
sketches
the
boundaries
of
what
is
sensible,
intelligible
and
possible.
The
redistribution
of
the
sensible
is
about
invalidating
the
current
distribution
of
space
and
time.489
It
is
about
undermining
the
space
and
time
prescribed
by
the
police
order.
As
mentioned,
the
noun
le
partage
from
the
verb
partager,
means
both
to
share
out
and
divide
up.490
It
therefore
simultaneously
suggests
the
sharing-‐out
and
the
dividing-‐up
of
the
sensory
or
the
sensible
world.491
The
sharing-‐out
and
dividing-‐up
can
be
understood
in
terms
of
a
system
of
[a]
priori
forms
determining
what
presents
itself
to
sense
experience.
It
is
a
delimitation
of
spaces
and
times,
of
the
visible
and
invisible,
of
speech
and
noise,
that
simultaneously
determines
the
place
and
the
stakes
of
politics
as
a
form
of
experience.
Politics
revolves
around
what
is
seen
and
what
can
be
said
about
it,
around
who
has
the
ability
to
see
and
the
talent
[…]
to
speak,
around
the
properties
of
spaces
and
the
possibilities
of
time.492
Further,
the
nature
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
makes
it
seem
as
self-‐
evident.
The
redistribution
of
the
sensible
is
about
disputing
that
which
is
given,
it
is
a
division
put
in
the
common
sense.493
Rancière
states:
[Politics]
is
a
subversion
of
a
given
distribution
of
the
sensible.
[…]
The
subversion
implies
the
reframing
of
a
common
sense.
A
common
sense
does
not
mean
a
consensus
but,
on
the
contrary,
a
polemical
place,
a
confrontation
between
common
senses
or
opposite
ways
of
framing
what
is
common.
[…]
Politics
is
a
polemical
form
of
reframing
of
common
sense.494
And
it
is
up
to
political
subjects,
presupposing
their
equality,
to
reframe
the
given
distribution
of
the
sensible.495
To
become
the
subject
of
politics
is
to
make
oneself
488
Tanke J (2011) 5.
489
Tanke J (2011) 25.
490
Davis O (2010) 91.
491
As above.
492
Rancière J (2004) 13. As Kristin Ross notes, Rancière prefers to think about time in terms of
the way it gives form to relations of power and inequality and how its denaturalisation
shatters those relations. See Ross K in in Rockhill G & Watts P (2009) (eds.) 18.
493
Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 304.
494
Rancière J “The method of Equality: An Answer to Some Questions” in Rockhill G & Watts
P (2009) (eds.) 277.
495
It should be mentioned, as Rockhill explains, that some of Rancière ’s more recent work
offers a slightly more nuanced position that remained somewhat peripheral in his earlier work
95
appear
where
there
had
previously
been
only
categories
and
indeed
categories
that
rendered
one
or
one’s
experience
invisible.496
Politics
is
an
aesthetic
phenomenon;
it
makes
something
appear
that
had
not
been
there
before,
namely,
the
part
of
those
who
has
no
part.497
Politics
therefore
disorders
the
coherence
of
any
distribution
of
roles
and
places
and
parts.
As
May
notes,
it
disidentifies
bodies
from
their
police
order
nature
and
their
ends.498
It
interrupts,
through
the
part
that
has
no
part,
the
symbolic
partitions
that
mark
some
as
unseen,
unheard
and
of
no
account.499
Politics
has
to
do
with
aesthetic
performances
that
create
spaces
for
disagreement.
As
mentioned
in
the
previous
section,
Rancière
often
refers
to
politics
and
the
police
in
terms
of
worlds.
He
states
in
Disagreement
that
politics
is
bringing
two
worlds
together,
the
world
in
which
all
speaking
beings
are
regarded
as
equal
and
the
world
in
which
they
are
not.500
Politics
may
therefore
be
regarded
as
an
“aesthetic
operation
of
world-‐
when it comes to politics and the distribution of the sensible. See Rockhill G in Rockhill G &
Watts P (2009) (eds.) 201-202. Instead of simply juxtaposing a consensual distribution of the
sensible and dissensual acts of political subjectivisation, Rancière increasingly uses the term
politics to refer to both distributions and redistributions of the sensible order. See Rockhill G
in Rockhill G & Watts P (2009) (eds.) 201-202. Because of the more detailed account of the
conjunction of politics, Rancière has been led to break down “a strict opposition between an
established order and intermittent moments of destabilisation”. See Rockhill G in Rockhill G
& Watts P (2009) (eds.) 201-202. The distribution of the sensible, more recently, refers to both
of these elements: “This distribution and redistribution of places and identities, this
delimitation and re-delimitation of spaces and times, of the visible and invisible, of noise and
speech constitutes what I call the distribution of the sensible”. Rancière J Malaise Dans
L’esthètique (2004) 38 (passage translated by Rockhill G). A similar change is visible in his
definition of politics: “[Politics is] the configuration of a specific space, the delimitation of a
particular sphere of experience, of objects established in common and coming from a
common decision, of subjects recognised as capable of designating these objects and
arguing about them”. See Rancière J Malaise Dans L’esthètique (2004) 37 (passage translated
by Rockhill G). Rockhill further explains that Rancière is emphasising the police process in
politics and the dissensual elements in the distribution of the sensible. See Rockhill G in
Rockhill G & Watts P (2009) (eds.) 201-202. He therefore breaks down the rigid opposition
between stable structures and intermittent acts of reconfiguration. Politics is a distribution of
the sensible insofar as every distribution presupposes at least the potential for redistribution.
See Rockhill G in Rockhill G & Watts P (2009) (eds.) 201-202.
496
Tanke J (2011) 3-4.
497
May T (2008) 71.
498
As above.
499
As above.
500
Rancière J (1999) 30.
96
disclosure”.501
It
transforms
perceptual
limitations
to
reveal
an
equality
of
bodies,
capacities
and
voices.
Tanke
has
mentioned
that
they
key
question
for
any
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
to
know
whether
it
is
founded
upon
equality
or
inequality.502
A
division
is
always
a
division
into
parts
and
it
is
essential,
in
Rancièrian
terms,
to
determine
the
metric
according
to
which
this
division
takes
place:
“Whether
it
is
the
distribution
of
parts,
objects,
the
arts,
or
the
relationship
between
speech
and
visibility,
these
operations
define
worlds
that
are
either
compatible
or
incompatible
with
equality”.503
Therefore,
the
primary
goal
of
any
analysis
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
thus
to
determine
whether
equality
is
present
or
not.
It
is
interesting
to
note
that
Tanke
reads
Rancière
’s
writings
as
initiating
a
twofold
movement
with
respect
to
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.504
In
the
first
instance,
it
offers
what
Tanke
calls
a
“topographical
analysis”
of
the
sensible.
This
form
of
analysis
should
be
seen
as
sidestepping
the
so-‐called
“hermeneutics
of
depth”.505
This
refers
to
interpretations
that
are
premised
upon
meanings
thought
to
reside
below
the
surface
of
texts,
political
arrangements
and
artistic
forms.506
If
one
is
to
explain
it
in
Rancièrian
terms,
beside
from
such
interpretations’
theological
residue,
depth
hermeneutics
establishes
the
pedagogical
space
of
the
master,
the
one
who
knows
the
true
meaning
of
things
and
is
gracious
enough
to
impart
it
to
others.507
As
we
will
see,
with
reference
to
Joseph
Jacocot
that
will
be
discussed
below,
the
hermeneutics
of
depth
is
problematic
for
Rancière
as
it,
along
the
lines
of
scienticism,
divides
the
world
into
two:
minds
capable
of
detecting
in
words
and
forms
their
correct
meaning
and
those
who
are
dependent
upon
others
for
such
discoveries.
In
Tanke’s
reading,
the
topographical
analysis
sticks
to
the
surface
of
things.508
It
offers
a
description
of
the
relationship
between
elements
and
the
501
Stoneman E Philosophy and Rhetoric (2011) 146.
502
Tanke J (2011) 2.
503
As above.
504
Tanke J (2011) 3.
505
As above.
506
As above.
507
Tanke J (2011) 3.
508
As above.
97
common
world.509
This
form
of
analysis
does
not
claim
to
strike
upon
the
ultimate
or
correct
meaning
of
these
forms.
The
point
is
rather
to
try
and
indicate
“how
they
appear,
the
logic
of
their
relations,
the
conditions
of
their
historical
possibility,
the
meanings
they
have
been
given
and
the
overall
picture
they
give
rise
to”.510
The
sensible
world
is
itself
shared
and
these
elements
are
detectable
on
the
surfaces
of
texts,
images
and
political
arrangements.511
Because
of
this,
topographical
analysis
employs
a
supposition
opposed
to
the
hermeneutics
of
depth,
namely;
“it
credits
its
addressees
or
readers
with
being
already
in
possession
of
capacities
for
making
sense
of
sense”.512
The
analysis
is
thus
framed
inter-‐subjectively
according
to
Tanke.513
The
second
instance,
or
moment
that
Tanke
detects,
is
evaluating
these
arrangements
in
terms
of
the
version
of
the
possible
that
they
define.514
Rancière
attempts
to
analyse
how
the
constitution
of
a
sensible
given
(whether
in
philosophical
discourses,
political
arrangements
and
artistic
practices)
defines
forms
of
openness
or
closure.
Rancière’s
work
can
be
viewed
as
a
series
of
interferences
designed
to
break
apart
and
undermine
the
sense
of
inevitability
attached
to
many
forms
of
intellectual,
political
and
artistic
labour.515
The
second
movement
is
therefore
an
intervention
into
the
sensible
configuration
of
our
common
world
designed
to
create
space
for
the
implementation
of
equality.516
Further,
it
becomes
important
to
explain
Rancière’s
509
As above.
510
As above.
511
As above.
512
As above.
513
Tanke J (2011) 3-4.
514
As above.
515
As above.
516
As above. Ross argues that beginnings, or points of departure is more important for
Rancière than for most thinkers and he likes to begin by throwing things into reverse. Ross K
in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 20-21. For example, if one looks at Rancière along the lines of
culture; he doesn’t begin with culture (conceived of as one’s proper allotment in symbolic
capital or culture conceived of as a set of consoling rituals). Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P
(eds.) 20-21. He, as Ross explains, rather begins with emancipation. Ross K in Rockhill G &
Watts P (eds.) 20-21. The concept of culture “whether one applies it to knowledge of the
classics or to the manufacture of shoes, has the sole effect of effacing this movement of
subjectivisation that operates in the interval between several nominations and its constitutive
fragility”. See Rancière J The Names of History: On the Poetics of Knowledge (1994) 98. The
concept of culture thus presupposes an identity tied to a way of speaking, being and doing
that is itself tied to a situation, a name, body, assigned to a place, a life station. Ross K in
98
use
of
theatre
within
his
notion
of
politics,
the
power
of
language
and
speech
within
the
context
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
the
argumentative
and
logical
character
of
equality
that
seeks
to
redistribute
the
sensible.
I
address
these
points
below
before
concluding.
Rancière’s
conception
of
equality
is
illuminated
by
his
use,
metaphorically
and
literally,
of
theatre.517
Here
aesthetics
again
come
into
play
and,
as
Hallward
explains,
rather
than
a
principle
of
order
or
distribution,
Rancière
presents
equality
as
a
“pure
supposition
that
must
be
verified
continuously
-‐
a
verification
or
an
enactment
that
open
specific
stages
of
equality,
stages
that
are
built
by
crossing
boundaries
and
interconnecting
forms
and
levels
of
discourse
and
spheres
of
experience”.518
Hallward
explains
that
every
subject
plays
or
acts
in
the
theatrical
sense.519
Every
political
subject
is
first
and
foremost
“a
sort
of
local
and
provisional
theatrical
configuration”.520
The
thematic
of
the
stage
is
all
pervading
in
Rancière’s
work.
In
the
mid-‐1970’s
Rancière
already
adopted
the
view
that
rather
than
a
matter
of
“popular
savagery”
or
“historical
necessity”,
revolt
is
“a
staging
of
reasons
and
ways
of
speaking”.521
Rancière
went
on
in
Disagreement
to
define
politics
as
a
matter
of
Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 20-21. Culture, as Ross further notes, is “inherently functionalist
and non-contingent” in Rancière’s terms. Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 20-21. With
reference to Arlette Farge and her discussion of the anti-ethnological dimension of Rancière’s
work on history, the following might be discerned, according to Ross: “If a space (territory or
terroir) is the point of departure for an analysis, whether it be the space of the region, ghetto,
island or factory, the people’s voices, their subjectivities, can be nothing more than the
naturalised, homogenised expressions of those spaces”. Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.)
20-21. Rancière’s project could be said to be a different kind of cultural studies, an anti-
identitarian one: “A cultural study where the concept of culture has been banished form the
outset and identitarian matters twisted into a fluid and unscheduled non-system of significant
misrecognitions”. See Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 20-21.
517
Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 141.
518
As above. See Rancière J “The Thinking of Dissensus: Politics as Aesthetics” paper
presented at the conference “Post-structuralism and Radical Politics” Goldsmiths College,
London (16-17 September 2003) available at http://homepages.gold.ac.uk/psrpsg/confe-
rence/fidelity/html(accessed2014/12/16).
519
As above.
520
Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 141.
521
Rancière J Les Scenes Du Peuple (2003) 10 as referenced in Hallward P in Rockhill G &
Watts P (eds.) 142.
99
performing
or
playing,
in
the
theatrical
sense
of
the
word,
the
gap
between
a
place
where
the
demos
exists
and
a
place
where
it
does
not
[…]
Politics
consist
in
playing
or
acting
out
this
relationship,
which
means
first
setting
it
up
as
theatre,
inventing
the
argument,
in
the
double
logic
and
dramatic
scene
of
the
term,
connecting
the
unconnected.522
In
this
regard,
Rancière
has
also
referred
to
the
example
of
an
ordinary
act
of
policing,
namely,
the
instruction
to
“move
along
now,
there
is
nothing
to
see
here”.523
If
the
police
order
denies
that
there
is
anything
to
see,
politics
creates
a
spectacle
or
something
to
see.
Politics
entails
transforming
this
space
of
“moving-‐
along”
into
a
space
of
the
appearance
of
the
subjects.524
Politics
is
in
this
sense
creative
and
dramatic.525
Moreover,
it
is
axiomatically
theatrical
since
the
emergence
of
a
subject
is,
for
Rancière,
always
also
the
emergence
into
the
realm
of
perception,
visibility
and
audibility.
As
Davis
states,
“it
is
a
manifestation”.526
Political
subjectivation
resembles
acting
because
it
involves
pretending
that
you
are
something
you
are
not
in
order
to
become
it;
pretending
to
be
an
equal
participant
within
the
political
process
from
which
you
are
in
fact
excluded.
And
within
the
act
of
demonstration,
the
political
subject
or
the
demos,
previously
unaccounted
for,
appears
within
the
realm
of
perception
or
the
current
distribution
of
the
sensible.
Importantly,
the
notion
of
speech
is
intimately
linked
to
Rancière’s
politics
and
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
Rancière
states:
522
Rancière J (1999) 88. Hallward terms Rancière’s politics as theocracy and discusses seven
reasons why Rancière’s politics is theatrical, namely, “it is spectacular”, “it is artificial”, “it
privileges multiplicity over unity”, “it is disruptive”, “its performance is contingent”, “it tends
toward improvisation” and “it operates within a liminal configuration”. See Hallward P in
Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 146-157.
523
Davis O (2010) 86.
524
As above.
525
As above. Hallward, as mentioned, has described Rancière’s politics as “theatocracy”. See
Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 140-157. The term derives originally from Plato
who famously excluded theatre from his ideal city in Republic. This was not because of the
immoral content of plays, but rather because the theatre was a dangerous place of
semblance where actors are doing two things and being two people at the same time.
Theatre therefore challenges the metaphysical organising principle of Plato’s autocratic and
hierarchal state, namely, the principle of specialisation according to which people can only do
or become one thing. Rancière’s deep-level connection and engagement with Plato will be
discussed within chapter 3 below.
526
Davis O (2010) 86.
100
[P]olitics,
in
fact,
is
not
the
exercise
of
power
and
the
struggle
for
power.
It
is
the
configuration
of
a
specific
space,
the
parcelling
out
of
a
particular
sphere
of
experience,
of
objects
we
take
to
be
shared
and
stemming
from
a
common
decision,
of
recognised
subjects
able
to
designate
these
objects
and
to
discuss
them.
Man,
Aristotle
says,
is
political
because
he
can
speak
and
thereby
share
notions
of
just
and
unjust,
whereas
animals
have
only
the
ability
to
voice
pain
and
pleasure.
But
the
question
is,
who
has
the
power
of
speech
and
who
has
only
a
voice?
Politics
happens
[subjects]
demonstrate
that
their
mouths
can
articulate
speech
that
states
shared
realities
and
not
just
a
voice
that
signifies
pain.
This
arrangement
and
rearrangement
of
places
and
identities,
the
parcelling
and
reparcelling
out
of
spaces
and
times,
of
the
visible
and
the
invisible,
of
noise
and
speech,
constitute
what
I
call
the
sharing
of
the
sensible.527
When
Rancière
asks
in
the
above
quote
“who
has
the
power
of
speech
and
who
has
only
voice?”
he
points
to
the
fact
that
when
people
sometimes
try
to
voice
their
grievances
or
claims,
there
is
a
tendency
for
their
speech
not
to
be
heard
as
rational
argument.528
Part
of
the
wrong
or
the
miscount
is
that
there
is
a
presumption
that
no
account
will
be
taken
of
the
complaints
of
the
part
of
those
who
have
no
part.
As
Davis
notes,
this
does
not
mean
that
these
complaints
are
understood
and
then
disregarded.529
Rather,
in
a
more
fundamental
sense,
they
are
not
heard
as
meaning-‐bearing
language
or
speech
that
is
politically
relevant.530
Rancière
is
not
referring
to
inaudibility
and
invisibility
in
a
straightforward
way.
The
question
revolves
around
whether
or
not
a
group
in
question
is
thought
to
be
capable
of
participation
in
the
life
of
the
community
as
a
whole,
a
question
of
that
group’s
share
in
“the
definition
of
the
common
of
the
community”.531
Rancière
uses
the
aesthetics
of
politics
to
express
the
idea
that
questions
of
partaking
rely
on
prior
decisions
about
what
will
be
interpreted
as
logically
formed
human
speech
and
what
will
be
construed
as
animal
noise.532
He
illustrates
the
aesthetic
dimension
of
politics
by
making
recourse
to
the
double
sense
of
logos,
which
in
Greek
means
both
speech
and
account:
527
Rancière J Malaise Dans L’esthètique (2004) 37-38 passage translated by Méchaoulan E.
See Méchaoulan E “Sophisticated Continuities and Historical Discontinuities, Or, Why Not
Protagoras?” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) 55.
528
Davis O (2101) 90-91.
529
As above.
530
As above.
531
Rancière J (199) 36.
532
Tanke J (2011) 49.
101
Politics
exists
because
the
logos
is
never
simply
speech,
because
it
is
always
indissolubly
the
account
made
of
this
speech:
the
account
by
which
a
sonorous
emission
is
understood
as
speech
capable
of
enunciating
what
is
just,
whereas
some
other
emission
is
merely
perceived
as
noise
signalling
pleasure
or
pain,
consent
or
revolt.533
Rancière
is
therefore
highlighting
here
that
logos
is
at
once
speech
and
a
distribution
of
speech
positions.534
Domination
and
oppression
follows
from
the
refusal
to
acknowledge
someone’s
full
possession
of
speech,
which
is
the
basic
requirement
for
political
participation.
As
Tanke
explains,
the
aesthetics
of
politics
indicates
that
before
being
about
the
negotiation
of
interests,
the
community
relies
upon
judgments
about
what
constitutes
speech,
who
is
capable
of
possessing
it,
what
the
appropriated
places
for
it
are
and
what
can
be
addressed
as
a
political
issue.535
Politics
revolves
around
the
use
that
is
made
of
the
distinction
between
speech
and
noise.
Politics
contests
the
general
aesthetic
framework
in
which
distinctions,
such
as
the
distinction
between
full
and
partial
possession
of
speech,
operate:
It
consists
of
forcing
an
opposing
side
to
acknowledge
not
only
the
demands
for
inclusion
but
also
the
speech
of
those
making
the
demands.536
In
order
to
explain
this
line
of
thinking,
Rancière
refers
to
a
number
of
Aristotle’s
and
especially
Plato’s
formulations.
These
are
important
references
and
I
discuss
them
in
full
when
discussing
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny
in
the
next
chapter.
Rancière
has
a
specific
view
of
language
that
can
be
described
as
a
poetical
account
of
language.
It
is
based
on
a
rereading
of
Plato’s
critique
of
writing
in
Phaedro.537
Plato
views
the
written
word
or
what
he
calls
the
“orphan”
word
as
always
supplementary
to
the
communal
order.538
As
Arsenjuk
highlight,
the
written
word
can
liberate
itself
from
a
situation
in
which
the
roles
of
both
the
addresser
and
the
addressee
are
established.539
The
limits
of
what
is
sayable
are
strictly
determined
within
specific
orders
of
power.
Anyone
can
appropriate
the
533
Rancière J (1999) 22-23.
534
Tanke J (2011) 50-51.
535
As above.
536
As above.
537
Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 1-3.
538
As above.
539
As above.
102
written
word.
It
is
not
the
same
for
the
spoken
word
however.
The
spoken
word
is
tied,
for
Plato,
as
Rancière
states,
to
the
“logic
of
the
proper”.540
The
written
word
on
the
other
hand
presents
excess.541
It
is
unexpected
and
inexhaustible
in
its
relation
to
a
world
of
distributed
tasks
and
roles
and
speech
that
belong
to
individuals
and
groups
in
the
communal
order.542
Excessive
words
or
words
of
excess
over
the
existing
distribution
of
the
sensible
represents
the
egalitarian
power
of
language,
which
Rancière
calls
“literarity”.543
These
words
can
disturb
the
existing
circuits
of
meanings
and
places
of
enunciation.544
Humans
are
political
animals
for
Rancière
for
two
reasons,
firstly,
because
they
have
the
power
to
put
more
words
into
circulation
(useless
words,
supplementary,
unnecessary
words
that
go
beyond
rigid
designation)
and,
secondly,
because
that
ability
is
unceasingly
“contested
by
those
who
claim
to
speak
properly
or
correctly”.545
The
words
used
within
the
moment
of
politics
become
significant.
Words
or
phrases
can
intervene
within
a
specific
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
can
as
such
create
or
mobilise
the
moment
of
politics.
Rancière
argues
that
politics
connects
individuals
with
the
entire
community
by
announcing,
for
example,
“we,
the
workers
of
the
world”.546
Tanke
aptly
and
very
importantly
highlights
that
for
Rancière,
political
speech
relies
upon
poetic
world-‐opening
devices,
such
as
“we
are
the
workers
of
the
world”.
These
enunciations
fashion
collective
subjects,
a
“we”,
a
people
or
the
demos.547
The
logic
of
equality
uses
expansive
political
names:
540
As above.
541
As above.
542
As above.
543
As above.
544
As above.
545
As above. See also Rancière J (1999) 59. If one for example looks at the name “the
proletariat”, the classical name for the part of those who have no part in a capitalist society,
Rancière claims that this word, when it appeared in the struggles of the nineteenth century,
did not really express a working-class culture. Rancière J (1999) 59. It is not that it functioned
as a representation of a social class or that it identified a part of the existing population. It
rather functioned as a “useless” word, unrecognisable as a valid category from the
standpoint of the police order. It is an artifice, which enabled a declaration of a wrong, the
naming of the part that has no part. See Arsenjuk L Fronesis (2005) 1-3.
546
As above.
547
Tanke J (2011) 65.
103
The
poetic
moments
of
politics
are
the
creative
linguistic
actions
that
challenge
the
divisions
between
capacity
and
incapacity,
between
rulers
and
ruled,
between
those
with
and
those
without
a
part.548
The
poetics
of
politics
is
about
the
invention
of
names
for
a
collective.
These
names
are
usually
names
with
sufficiently
generality,
recognisable
within
the
current
distribution
of
the
sensible.
But,
the
invention
occurs
in
making
new
connections
or
configurations
with
regards
to
these
names,
giving
them
new
content
as
well
as
using
them
to
make
impossible
identifications.
For
Rancière,
concepts
can
be
used
as
tools
“to
displace
existing
topographies
and
undermine
consensual
regimes
by
thinking
through
the
far
side
of
the
police”.549
The
poetics
of
politics
invents
new
names
and
identities
and
the
point
is
also
to
invent
arguments.
Davis
explains
that
one
of
the
aspects
of
subjectivation
is
that
it
has
an
argumentative
dimension
to
it.550
The
argumentative
characteristic
of
subjectivation
highlights
Rancière’s
insistence
on
struggles
that
involve
language
and
rational
argument,
especially
in
his
historical
work.
In
his
book
On
the
Shores
of
Politics
he
places
a
strong
emphasis
on
the
logical
and
argumentative
character
of
revolt
by
referring
to
what
he
terms
the
“syllogism
of
emancipation”.551
The
example
he
discusses
of
such
a
syllogism
of
emancipation
is
a
strike
by
Paris
tailors
in
1833,
protesting
against
their
employer’s
refusal
to
entertain
their
demands
for
better
pay,
shorter
working
hours
and
improved
working
conditions.
Davis
explains
that
they
invented
their
argument
by
using
a
clause,
or
syllogism,
from
the
preamble
of
the
Charter
of
1830
that
resulted
from
the
July
Revolution,
namely
“all
the
French
are
equal
before
the
law”.552
Three
premises
seemed
to
contradict
this
clause
according
to
Rancière.553
Firstly,
the
refusal
to
entertain
the
workers’
demands
meant
that
they
were
not
treated
as
equal,
secondly,
confederations
of
workers
and
employers
alike
were
illegal
and
yet
only
workers
were
pursued
by
authorities
and
thirdly,
no
less
a
representative
of
the
law
than
the
public
prosecutors
gave
a
speech
in
which
he
asserted
that
workers
were
not
548
As above.
549
Rockhill G & Watts P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 12.
550
Davis O (2010) 84.
551
As above.
552
As above.
553
Davis O (2012) 85.
104
equal
members
of
society.554
As
Davis
further
highlights,
it
could
be
argued
that
the
Charter
had
always
been
understood
as
an
aspiration.555
But,
this
was
not
the
approach
adopted
by
the
tailors.556
They
demanded
that
the
three
premises
be
reconciled
with
the
clause
or
that
the
clause
be
changed
to
something
like
“not
all
the
French
are
equal
before
the
law”.557
The
charter
therefore
employed
in
an
effort
to
create
logical
argument.
For
Rancière,
the
charter
served
as
a
basis
for
the
practical
verification
of
equality
as
part
of
a
logical
and
argumentative
demonstration
of
equality.
However,
it
should
be
mentioned
with
regards
to
the
logical
and
argumentative
aspect
that
Rancière
does
not
conceive
of
politics
as
simply
a
debate
between
subjects
who
disagree
and
negotiate
over
specific
issues.
For
him,
as
mentioned,
the
subjects
are
wronged
in
such
a
fundamental
way
as
to
place
in
doubt
their
very
existence
as
subjects,
their
capacity
to
participate
in
the
debate
and
whether
their
arguments
are
understood
as
rational
arguments
by
other
parties.558
Further,
in
his
analysis
of
the
strikes
of
the
1830’s
Rancière
elucidates
the
workings
of
equality.
Rancière
refers
to
the
charter
as
“a
most
peculiar
platform
of
argument”.559
The
tailors
acted
as
if
they
have
always
been
equal
and
they
demanded
that
the
charter
should
be
rectified
to
reflect
their
situation
or
that
the
conditions
of
their
situation
must
be
changed.
In
this
regard,
political
subjects
are
those
who
make
visible
the
fact
that
they
belong
to
a
shared
world
that
others
do
not
see
and
importantly:
554
As above.
555
As above.
556
As above
557
As above. As Davis highlights, the declaration of equality in the Charter and similar legal
and political declarations or instruments are, for Rancière, a powerful resource. Davis O (2010)
85. But they are only powerful resources “if they are taken up confidently with a view of
verifying them, rather than regarded as optimistic aspirations or illusory descriptions of
reality”. Davis O (2010) 85. According to Davis, Rancière is far from being a disillusioned
skeptic about formal declarations of equality in legal and constitutional documents, unlike
Marx, for instance that saw rights as mere expressions of the interests of the bourgeois
property-owning class. Davis O (2010) 85. Rancière is not naïve enough to think that such
documents can somehow magically produce the equality that they declare, but he does insist
then that they can serve as a basis for a practical verification of equality as part of a logical
argumentative demonstration. See Davis O (2010) 85.
558
As above.
559
Davis O (2010) 86.
105
The
worker
who
puts
forward
the
public
nature
of
a
“domestic”
wage
dispute
must
demonstrate
the
world
in
which
his
argument
counts
as
argument
and
must
demonstrate
it
as
such
for
those
who
do
not
have
the
frame
of
reference
enabling
them
to
see
it
as
one.
Political
argumentation
is
at
one
and
the
same
time
the
demonstration
of
a
possible
world
in
which
the
argument
could
count
as
argument
[…]
It
is
the
construction
of
a
paradoxical
world
that
puts
together
two
separate
worlds.560
The
workers
must
stage
equality
and
they
must
pretend
it
already
exists
in
order
to
create
it.
They
must
not
only
demonstrate
their
argument,
but
also
demonstrate
a
common
world
of
argument.
Davis
elucidates:
The
worker
subject
that
gets
included
on
it
as
speaker
has
to
behave
as
though
such
a
stage
existed,
as
though
there
were
a
common
world
of
argument-‐
which
is
eminently
reasonable
and
eminently
unreasonable,
eminently
wise
and
resolutely
subversive,
since
such
a
world
does
not
exist.561
Rancière
detects
through
his
analysis
that
creative
linguistic
actions,
poetic
devices
and
expansive
political
names
or
syllogisms
can
disclose
possibilities
for
the
demonstration
of
arguments
and
the
worlds
in
which
they
count
and
therefore
also
disclose
possibilities
for
reconfiguring
sensible
distribution.
2.4
Conclusion
Rancière’s
experiences
under
Althusser
resulted
in
him
distancing
himself
from
any
notion
of
politics
that
function
to
maintain
social
and
institutional
hierarchies
through
the
exercise
of
pedagogical
power.
The
idea
that
some
can
not
only
instruct
others
on
how
to
politically
revolt,
but
can
also
help
them
in
fully
understanding
their
own
conditions
and
position
within
the
world
became
untenable
for
Rancière.
The
concept
of
the
truth
of
Marxist
science
against
all
the
falsehoods
of
ideology
served
only
to
classify
people
into
those
who
need
scientific
knowledge
and
those
who
can
impart
it.
Scientism
infinitely
defers
political
struggle
and
equality
whilst
maintaining
the
status
quo.
For
Rancière,
the
events
of
May
’68
made
the
ideas
that
he
came
to
adopt
under
Althusser
questionable.
He
gleaned
from
it
the
possibility
of
an
equality
embodied
in
advance
and
the
events
only
affirmed
the
problematic
relationship
between
560
Rancière J (2010) 38-39.
561
Davis O (2010) 87.
106
knowledge
and
power
that
he
later
reacted
against.
For
him
this
relationship
represented
nothing
more
than
a
form
of
legitimisation
of
current
roles,
what
he
would
later
refer
to
as
the
police
order.
Rancière
highlights
in
his
mature
politics
that
what
we
normally
perceive
as
politics
comes
down
to
policing,
or
the
suppression
of
politics.
Governance,
organisation
and
the
representation
of
communities
as
well
as
the
exercise
of
power
on
different
levels
of
society,
rather
than
facilitating
struggle,
legitimates
current
ways
of
doing,
being
and
saying.
Rancière’s
conception
of
the
police
is
a
fluid
concept
indicating
the
mechanisms
and
procedures
that
enforce
the
broad
systems
of
domination
in
a
specific
context.
The
police
order
help
to
maintain
hierarchies,
it
allocates
and
regulates.
It
indicates
who
is
capable
of
speaking
and
what
they
are
able
to
say
in
what
time
and
in
what
place.
The
police
order
embodies
consensus,
holding
forth
a
form
of
realism
that
tells
us
that
the
police’s
way
is
the
only
possible
way.
It
objectifies
matters
to
such
an
extent
that
they
can
no
longer
be
contested.
They
become
self-‐evident
and
not
open
to
dispute.
Against
the
police
Rancière
postulates
politics.
A
specific
form
of
demonstration
that
runs
counter
to
policing.
It
implements
the
assumption
of
the
equality
of
speaking
beings
in
order
to
undo
the
workings
of
the
police
order.
Equality
presupposed,
from
the
outset,
confronts
the
police
with
its
own
contingency.
Equality
is
central.
What
makes
something
political
is
not
its
object
or
the
place
within
which
it
is
carried
out,
it
exists
solely
in
the
form
of
an
equality
that
is
declared,
demonstrated
and
presupposed.
Equality
cannot
be
given
by
governments
and
it
cannot
be
preserved,
attained
or
balanced
against
other
principles.
It
is
practiced
and
verified.
Politics
therefore
exits
solely
in
the
enactment
of
equality
by
means
of
a
scene
of
dissensus.
It
does
not
carry
on
indefinitely.
It
exists
in
and
through
the
demonstration
of
dissensus.
It
is
rare,
temporal
and
localised.
It
does
not
necessarily
effect
change.
It
institutes
a
breach
within
a
specific
police
order
that
divides
a
specific
distribution
of
the
sensible
that
is
itself
open
to
egalitarian
challenge.
Politics
and
the
police
order
are
therefore
not
perfectly
identifiable
or
pure
enactments
or
systems.
They
are
107
interrelated,
intertwined
and
fluid
and
the
point
is
to
discern
where
politics
actually
happen,
where
and
when
it
encroaches
on
the
police
and
where
and
when
police
matters
encroach
on
politics.
The
meeting
point
between
politics
and
the
police
is
always
shifting.
Politics,
through
the
declaration
of
equality
disorders,
upsets,
breaks
apart
and
ruptures.
Its
power
is
division
and
inconsistency.
The
police
order
is
by
its
very
nature
an
order
of
unequal
ordering
and
the
equality
of
speaking
beings
therefore
becomes
a
tool
for
displacement
and
declassification.
It
breaks
open,
through
dissensus,
interpretations
thought
to
be
incontestable.
In
Rancière’s
formulation
of
the
political
subject,
it
becomes
clear
that
the
subject
of
politics
only
exists
through
and
within
the
process
of
subjectivation.
A
political
subject
exists
and
ends
within
the
moment
of
politics.
It
is
politics
that
declares
equality
that
makes
it
possible
to
conceive
of
the
subject
of
politics
and
not
the
other
way
around.
The
political
subject
too,
is
localised
and
temporal.
The
process
of
subjectivation
is
the
process
whereby
a
subject
rejects
the
classification
of
the
police
order.
It
undercuts
police
categories.
It
is
not
simply
the
process
of
adding
a
new
police
category
to
the
existing
police
categories.
Rancière,
as
mentioned,
is
highly
critical
of
identity,
especially
the
way
in
which
it
becomes
identical
to
the
classifications
of
the
police
and
all
the
assumptions
implicit
in
police
categories.
Politics
is
never
a
question
of
identity;
it
is
a
question
of
working
within
the
gaps
between
identities,
of
dividing
a
police
identity
from
itself,
of
complicating
and
overturning
it.
The
first
moment
of
subjectivation
is
the
disidentification
with
police
categories
and
the
second
is
the
creation
of
new
identities
or
of
giving
new
content
to
identities-‐
confusing
and
disrupting
the
identities
within
the
police
order.
In
the
next
chapter
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny
will
demonstrate
how
impossible
identifications
tear
people
away
from
police
order
designated
places.
The
process
of
subjectivation
whereby
subjects
identify
with
new
categories
also
encompasses
the
struggle
for
the
existence
of
political
subjectivity
as
such.
Rancière
demonstrates
this
by
his
equation
of
the
political
subject
with
the
demos
in
Athenian
democracy.
The
demos
as
collective
were
regarded
as
not
having
the
108
necessary
attributes
for
involvement
in
politics.
Policing
also
denotes
a
specific
way
of
counting
the
community.
The
police
order’s
way
of
counting
excludes
the
possibility
of
remainder.
However,
the
police’s
way
of
counting
is
based
on
a
structural
miscount.
The
demos
lays
bare
this
miscount
or
wrong
of
their
non-‐
existence
as
political
subject.
Politics
therefore
has
to
be
disputatious
or
antagonistic
as
it
expresses
a
basic
disagreement
with
the
recognitions
of
the
police
order.
When
the
equality
of
speaking
beings
is
postulated,
it
discloses
that
the
ground
for
the
power
of
ruling
is
that
there
is
no
ground
at
all.
The
miscount
and
the
wrong
are
employed
by
Rancière
to
demonstrate
that
politics
is
about
disagreement.
Disagreement
involves
the
concrete
and
material
conditions
from
within
which
people
are
able
to
speak.
It
illustrates
that
politics
is
not
the
participation
of
parties
that
have
an
equal
say
from
within
the
context
of
equal
positions.
At
the
heart
of
a
political
dispute
there
is
conflict
over
what
constitutes
reason,
what
is
a
legitimate
object
of
political
discussion,
and
what
it
means
to
be
a
political
subject.
This
is
why
Rancière’s
states
that
politics
is
first
and
foremost
about
the
existence
of
politics.562
Politics
is
not
about
the
management
of
competing
interests
within
shared
political,
legal
or
juridical
frameworks.
That
is
the
police
order.
Politics
is
therefore
not
an
activity
pursued
on
the
basis
of
any
consensus,
constitutional,
institutional
or
on
the
basis
of
shared
norms.
Politics
consists
of
a
radically
more
fundamental
manifestation.
Politics
is
about
the
part
that
has
no
part
in
anything,
the
demos
that
is
according
to
the
police
not
within
the
realm
of
visibility
and
perceptibility.
The
demos
as
political
subject,
struggles
in
order
to
enter
into
this
realm,
to
essentially,
appear.
Rancière
therefore
demonstrates
that
the
police
order
determines
speaking
positions
and
politics
is
not
about
struggling
within
the
already
existing
realm
of
determined
positions.
Rather,
it
is
about
a
radical
egalitarian
call
that
disputes
and
opens
up
the
foundational
and
structural
beliefs
that
holds
claim
to
the
correct
way
of
counting.
Because
of
the
fact
that
politics
radically
disputes
the
framework
of
speaking
positions
it
is
also
always
an
562
Rancière J Dissensus: On Politics and Aesthetics (2010) 35.
109
intervention
into
the
visible
and
sayable.
It
is
an
intervention
into
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
It
is
in
this
sense
that
politics
is
aesthetics.
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
as
the
perceptual
configuration
of
society
shapes
what
is
visible,
audible
and
what
object
and
phenomena
can
be
related
in
what
times
and
spaces.
As
the
regime
of
possibility
and
impossibility,
it
determines
sense,
meaning
and
direction.
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
has
become
a
popular
concept.
It
can
not
only
be
described
as
an
idea.
It
is
also
a
way
of
describing,
a
way
of
mapping,
of
viewing
and
of
bringing
together
and
taking
apart
everything
that
we
experience
through
our
sense.
Rancière
postulates
a
type
of
topographical
analysis
that
attempts
to
trace
the
distribution
of
the
sensible,
its
logic
and
relations;
the
conditions
and
the
possibilities
it
gives
rise
to.
The
sensible
is
a
certain
picture,
a
way
of
framing
things
and
politics
intervenes
in
this
picture,
and
it
subverts
its
message,
its
narrative
and
form.
If
the
police
order
enforces
the
fact
that
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
has
specific
perceptual
limitations,
politics
confronts
it
with
expansion.
The
thematic
of
the
stage
permeates
Rancière’s
work.
Indeed,
politics
is
about
staging
a
scene
of
dissensus,
presupposing
equality,
creating
it
where
it
isn’t,
inventing
arguments
and
worlds
in
which
these
arguments
count.
Political
subjects
are
local,
provisional
and
theatrical
configurations
that
act
as
if
they
are
equal
in
unequal
police
distributions.
They
create
syllogisms
or
use
words
in
order
to
build
a
stage
on
which
their
equality
can
be
played
out.
In
reflecting
on
voice
within
the
framework
of
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics,
it
becomes
clear
that
politics
is
the
very
struggle
for
voice.
The
police
order
enforces
a
specific
regime
of
sensible
distribution
that
determine
who
has
the
power
of
voice
and
who
has
not.
Politics
is
the
process
by
which
those
whose
speech
is
seen
as
noise
declare
themselves
as
equal
participants
with
equal
voice.
The
police
order
determines
the
forms
that
a
speech-‐act
can
take,
its
place
and
time.
As
the
basic
system
through
which
we
perceive
and
intuitively
classify
and
process
information,
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
creates
the
framework
that
determines
the
possession
or
otherwise
of
political
voice.
In
Rancièrian
terms
110
political
voice
or
the
notion
of
having
political
voice,
can
be
aligned
with
speech
as
opposed
to
noise,
which
cannot
appear
within
the
sensible
distribution
of
the
police
order.
Rancière
makes
it
clear
that
politics
concerns
realms
of
visibility,
intelligibility
and
perceptibility.
The
possession
of
political
voice
is
conditioned
upon
the
possibility
of
appearance
within
these
realms.
This
is
why
politics
can
be
described
as
a
conflict
over
voice,
over
who
has
it
in
what
times
and
spaces.
As
such,
political
voicing
occurs
upon
entering
or
appearing
within
a
specific
framework
of
thinking
and
interpretation.
However,
this
is
not
appearing
or
entering
into
a
framework
of
perception
in
any
straightforward
way.
Political
voicing
opens
up
the
possibility
of
the
reconfiguration
of
the
sensible
realm
itself.
In
a
Rancièrian
sense,
political
voicing
radically
disputes
the
current
configuration
by
confronting
it
with
an
alternative
configuration.
Political
voicing
occurs
within
the
context
of
a
political
subject
that
challenges
the
sensible
distribution
of
the
police.
Matters
of
politics
and
political
voicing
are
in
this
way
aesthetic.
Voicing
is
the
moment
wherein
the
properties
of
space,
the
possibilities
of
time,
the
formation
of
identities
and
locales
are
thought
of
in
another
way.
When
considered
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
politics,
political
voice
is
not
about
claims
for
inclusion,
or
for
that
matter
identity.
It
is
about
the
employment
of
universal
equality
in
order
to
displace,
divide
and
redistribute.
As
mentioned,
politics
discloses
(through
staging
a
dissensus,
acting
equal,
inventing
arguments
and
syllogisms
and
supplementary
words)
a
different
world.
Political
voice
is
therefore
that
which
must
reveal,
through
demonstration,
a
different
way
of
thinking,
doing,
seeing,
saying
and
interpreting.
In
the
context
of
Rancière’s
politics,
political
voice
involves
creation.
Politics
consists
of
creating
spaces
and
times
in
which
the
demonstration
of
equality
can
take
place.
At
this
juncture
it
can
already
be
gleaned
from
his
formulations
that
it
is
the
invention
of
worlds,
words,
arguments
and
linguistic
configurations
that
blur
the
well-‐ordered
partitions
of
voice
and
silence.
The
discussion
of
Rancière’s
engagements
with
certain
historical
figures
in
the
next
chapter
as
well
as
the
engagement
with
Spivak
after
that,
will
serve
to
further
shed
light
on
the
notion
of
political
voice.
My
aim
is
for
a
more
complete
111
picture
of
voice
to
emerge
during
these
explorations.
At
this
stage,
what
further
emerges,
when
considering
voice
against
the
background
of
the
problems,
difficulties
or
the
lack
of
political
voicing
or
political
visibility
of
many
South
African
women,
is
that
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
becomes
a
valuable
formulation.
The
distribution
of
the
sensible,
as
mentioned,
has
become
a
popular
concept
and
tool
for
analysis
across
a
variety
of
disciplines.
It
is
not
only
a
concept
that
describes
a
specific
regime
of
thinking
and
interpretation,
but
it’s
also
a
way
of
tracing
and
mapping
the
various
sensible
distributions
that
determine
the
possibilities
and
perceptual
limitations
of
voice.
This
way
of
describing
a
given
framework
allows
for
the
identification
of
mechanisms,
procedures
and
ways
of
thinking
that
supress
or
reveal
the
content,
form
and
times
and
spaces
of
speech,
voicing
or
enunciation.
Political
arrangement,
power
relations
and
social
hierarchies
within
society
are
conceived
of
as
practices
of
creating,
distributing
and
contesting
the
sensible
world.
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
names
these
practices
and
as
such
provides
a
basis
from
where
to
intervene
in
the
structures
that
render
some
issues,
individuals
and
discourses
inaudible
and
invisible.
It
therefore
provides
a
useful
foundation
from
where
various
reflections
can
take
place.
It
should
further
be
mentioned
that
Rancière’s
formulation
of
the
police
order
and
of
the
notion
of
consensus,
highlights
the
fact
the
legal
and
institutional
mechanisms
of
government
and
even
more
broadly;
the
shared
norms
and
protocols
within
a
community
cannot
give
rise
to
political
activity,
properly
speaking.
Rather,
these
mechanisms
and
shared
norms
give
rise
to
a
specific
logic
or
orientation
towards
the
sensible
world.
As
mentioned
in
the
introductory
chapter,
from
one
perspective
the
specific
issues
facing
many
South
African
women,
especially
the
levels
of
sexual
violence
and
contexts
of
poverty,
are
addressed
through
various
legal
and
political
mechanisms
and
tools.
It
was
mentioned
that
in
this
regard
a
paradox
emerges:
Women’s
issues
and
broader
gender
challenges
are
within
the
public
realm,
but
they
themselves,
as
bodies
and
beings,
are
somehow
beyond
the
realm
of
care,
with
many
living
in
abject
poverty
and
in
constant
fear
of
sexual
violence.
When
it
comes
to
gender,
South
Africa
has
112
one
of
the
most
progressive
legislative
and
policy
frameworks
in
the
world.
However,
it
would
seem
that
either
the
voices
of
many
women
cannot
be
heard
to
the
extent
that
their
material
and
concrete
contexts
are
meaningfully
transformed,
or
these
issues
can
to
a
certain
extent
not
even
be
formulated.
When
viewed
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics,
it
becomes
clear
that
specialised
policy
and
law
as
well
as
consensual
activism
and
awareness
becomes
part
of
the
mechanisms
of
the
police
order.
The
sexual
violence
perpetrated
against
many
women
as
well
as
their
socio-‐economic
marginalisation
has
been
taken
into
account
by
the
police
order.
“Women”
have
been
counted
and
their
issues
named.
There
can
be
no
doubt
about
the
fact
that
the
strides
made
by
government
through
policy
and
legal
frameworks
in
order
to
promote
gender
equality
were
and
remain
important,
on
a
practical
as
well
as
a
symbolic
level.
However,
Rancière’s
formulation
of
the
police
order
allows
us
to
ask
to
what
extent
these
mechanisms
contribute
in
maintaining
the
status
quo.
These
frameworks,
mechanisms,
procedures
and
discourses
that
surround
the
particular
problems
that
many
women
face,
also
serve
to
confirm
the
notion
that
government
is
aware
of
these
pressing
issues,
that
it
has
done
a
lot
and
that
it
is
doing
what
it
can,
affirming
that
they
are
being
addressed.
This
results
in
the
closing
off
of
alternative
conversations
surrounding
these
issues,
establishing
a
discourse
of
pragmatic
management.
Moreover,
the
ineffectiveness
of
measures
and
laws
with
regard
to
these
problems
might
be
explained
by
the
fact
that
it
would
seem
that
government
is
less
concerned
about
actually
reducing
the
number
of
rapes
and
improving
the
living
conditions
of
the
majority
of
women,
than
showing
that
they
are
tirelessly
engaged
in
the
effort.
Further,
because
of
the
progressive
frameworks
that
are
established,
the
issues
of
the
socio-‐
economic
deprivation
of
many
women
as
well
as
the
continuing
sexual
violence
perpetrated
against
them
are
selectively
framed
and
interpreted.
They
are
therefore
only
viewed
through
and
along
the
lines
of
these
frameworks,
limiting
other
possible
perceptions
and
possibilities
of
voice.
Progressive
policy
frameworks
as
well
as
activism
within
the
public
and
private
realms
of
society
serve
to
limit
democracy
to
a
certain
extent.
The
widespread
awareness
and
consensual
activism,
together
with
specialised
policy
and
legislation
effectively
113
neutralises
these
issues.
When
we
have
societal
consensus
(coupled
with
the
managerial
efforts
of
government)
over
the
fact
that
the
highly
patriarchal
cultures
in
the
country
needs
to
be
transformed
and
the
suffering
of
many
women
need
to
be
alleviated,
these
problems
become
part
of
the
most
interior
logic
and
workings
of
the
police
order
and
they
therefore
essentially
lose
their
capacity
for
litigation,
for
dispute,
for
contestation,
for
discussion
and
controversy.
As
mentioned,
the
specific
legislative
and
policy
directives
of
the
South
African
government
as
well
as
societal
activism
in
general
are
exemplary.
These
efforts
cannot
be
lamented.
However,
Rancière’s
description
of
politics
and
the
police
order
allows
us
to
ask
what
different
frameworks
and
understandings
are
available.
His
formulations
points
the
question
of
how
certain
issues
can
become
intelligible,
visible
and
perceptible
to
the
extent
that
it
declares
a
wrong
or
manifests
in
a
struggle
for
equality.
These
postulations
therefore
point
to
a
different
visibility
than
the
visibility
involved
in
consensual
frameworks.
They
point
to
the
possibility
of
a
different
voicing
that
can
frame
certain
issues
in
such
a
way
so
as
to
politicise
them
or
open
them
up
to
dispute
or
contestation
again.
Rancière’s
politics
reminds
of
the
fact
that
the
police
order
through
consensus
refers
to
a
topography
of
the
visible,
of
what
is
possible
and
what
can
be
thought.
Political
voice
does
not
form
part
of
this
topography.
It
forms
part
of
dissensus.
Dissensus
has
two
primary
operations;
firstly,
it
questions
who
counts
as
subjects
worthy
of
taking
part
in
politics
and
secondly,
what
constitutes
an
object,
or
the
possible
topic
of
politics.
Dissensus
therefore
multiplies
“litigious
objects
and
disputing
subjects”
as
Rancière
puts
it.563
It
questions
a
society’s
definitions
of
competence,
forms
of
relation,
and
divisions
of
labour.
The
potency
of
dissensus
is
that
it
politicises
issues,
objects
or
subjects
thought
not
to
be
political,
ever
or
anymore.
When
it
comes
to
the
precariousness,
complexity
and
difficulty
of
issues
surrounding
voicing
as
it
relates
to
many
South
African
women,
Rancière’s
politics
points
to
the
creation
of
a
new
terrain
for
confrontation.
It
becomes
clear
that
the
most
urgent
issues
that
many
South
African
women
face
are
within
the
563
Rancière J (1999) 118.
114
current
distribution
of
the
sensible,
but,
they
appear
(they
are
only
audible,
visible
and
intelligible)
in
a
specific
way.
As
such
these
problems
also
essentially,
disappear.
In
the
face
of
disappearance,
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics
points
to
the
fact
that
a
dissensual,
radically
egalitarian
political
voicing
can
re-‐open
the
space
in
which
they
can
again
be
thought.
In
the
next
chapter
I
discuss
the
figures
of
Gabriel
Gauny
and
Joseph
Jacocot
as
figures
that
overturned
sensible
distributions.
These
discussions
further
serve
to
explain
Rancière’s
work
around
politics
and
they
also
further
serve
to
make
sense
of
voice.
They
allow
for
a
deeper
understanding
of
Rancière’s
formulation
on
politics
and
therefore
political
voice.
Jacocot
illustrates
the
power
of
equality
and
Gauny
demonstrates
the
power
of
identifications
that
redistribute
the
times,
spaces
and
places
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
115
CHAPTER
3
Radical
Intellectual
Equality
and
the
Reconfiguration
of
Work’s
Space
and
Time
3.1
Introduction
In
the
previous
chapter
I
explained
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics
and
reflected
on
the
notion
of
political
voice
through
the
lens
of
his
formulations.
Against
the
background
of
the
complexities
and
difficulties
of
political
voice
or
visibility
as
it
pertains
to
many
women
within
the
South
African
context
,
I
discussed
in
what
way
the
mechanisms
of
government
and
consensual
activism
can
be
thought
of
when
viewed
in
the
frame
of
Rancière’s
conception
of
politics.
I
suggested
that
the
operations
of
government
and
activism,
rather
than
opening
issues
of
silencing
to
litigation,
dispute
and
contestation,
to
a
certain
extent
contributes
to
the
disappearance
of
some
of
the
most
pressing
issues
that
many
South
African
women
face.
These
operations,
rather
than
giving
rise
to
political
voicing,
create
a
discourse
of
pragmatic
management.
It
was
mentioned
in
the
introductory
chapter
that
the
discussions
of
Joseph
Jacocot
and
Gabriel
Gauny
in
this
chapter
will
allow
for
an
even
deeper
or
better
understanding
of
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics.
In
this
regard
it
should
be
mentioned
again
that
Rancière’s
work
can
be
said
to
represent
three
stages.
The
first
stage
was
his
critique
of
the
main
tenets
of
Althusserian
theory
starting
from
the
early
1970’s.
The
second
stage
involved
questions
of
education,
pedagogy,
history,
historiography
and
historical
agency.
From
these
engagements
he
formulated
his
mature
politics
that
represents
the
third
stage
of
his
work.
The
previous
chapter
therefore
involved
the
first
and
third
stages.
The
discussion
of
Joseph
Jacocot
and
Gabriel
Gauny
in
this
chapter
involves
the
second
stage
of
his
work.
As
mentioned,
the
discussions
around
these
historical
figures
that
Rancière
engages
with
serve
to
illuminate
some
of
his
most
important
arguments.
In
many
ways,
Rancière’s
research
into
these
figures
not
only
crystallised
his
objections
to
Althusserianism,
but
also
allowed
him
to
properly
formulate
his
work
on
politics.
116
The
way
in
which
Rancière
engages
with
these
figures
as
well
as
the
arguments
that
he
formulates
on
the
basis
of
them,
demonstrates
two
important
elements
of
his
work
namely;
the
political
potency
of
equality
and
the
reconfiguration
of
the
space
and
time
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
I
therefore
find
it
necessary
to
shed
light
on
Rancière’s
work
in
this
regard.
It
provides
significant
insight
into
his
thinking.
A
further
aim
of
this
chapter
can
be
described
as
involving
ways
in
which
to
approach
the
notion
of
voice
or
moments
of
voicing
in
the
context
of
the
difficulties
surrounding
the
voice
of
many
South
African
women
set
out
in
the
first
chapter.
What
becomes
important
here
is
the
way
in
which
Rancière
mobilises
these
historical
figures
in
order
to
refute
certain
dominant
lines
of
thinking
in
specific
contexts.
The
way
in
which
these
historical
figures
are
staged
has
itself
the
political
effect
of
expanding
perception
and
reframing
what
is
thinkable.564
Therefore,
apart
from
providing
further
insight
into
Rancière’s
thinking
on
politics,
the
figures
and
discussions
in
this
chapter
also
represent
a
way
of
engaging
with
and
writing
about
moments
of
political
voicing.
These
discussions
therefore
serve
to
suggest
different
angles
or
places
from
where
to
think
through
and
how
to
write
about
the
notion
of
political
voice
within
the
context
of
a
Rancièrian
understanding
of
politics.
The
question
that
arises
is,
when
making
sense
of
voice,
how
are
we
to
engage
with
and
approach
the
notion
political
voice?
In
this
regard,
I
suggest
that
Rancière’s
engagement
with
the
figures
of
Joseph
Jacocot
and
Gabriel
Gauny
is
suggestive
of
some
important
considerations,
which
I
explain
below.
I
firstly
discuss
the
figure
of
Joseph
Jacocot
explored
in
his
book
on
pedagogy,
The
Ignorant
Schoolmaster
in
order
to
explain
Rancière’s
conception
of
equality
that
is
so
central
to
his
notion
of
politics.565
I
also
discuss
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny
discussed
in
his
book
The
Nights
of
Labor.566
The
discussion
of
Gauny
occurs
564
Ross K “Historicizing Untimeliness” in Rockhill G & Watts p (eds.) (2009) 24-25.
565
Rancière J (1991).
566
Rancière J (1989).
117
alongside
a
discussion
of
certain
aspects
of
Plato
that
Rancière
engages
with
and
criticises
in
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor.567
I
individually
introduce
these
discussions
in
the
sections
below.
3.2
Joseph
Jacocot
Rancière’s
reflections
on
equality
and
pedagogy
were
formulated
in
his
book
The
Ignorant
Schoolmaster.568
As
mentioned,
an
analysis
of
Rancière’s
reflections
on
the
figure
of
Joseph
Jacocot
will
allow
for
a
deeper
understanding
of
the
type
of
equality
that
he
postulates.
Davis
notes
that
Badiou
and
May
have
both
rightly
insisted
that
the
radical
conception
of
equality
that
Rancière
formulates
in
his
book
on
Jacocot
is
one
of
the
most
important
defining
and
original
features
of
his
work
and
has
implications
far
beyond
the
field
of
pedagogy.569
It
becomes
clear
in
his
discussions
of
Jacocot
that
his
reflections
on
equality
and
politics
are
rooted
in
his
explorations
of
what
it
means
to
learn
and
teach.
Rancière’s
account
of
pedagogy
and
equality
also
echoes
his
earlier
concerns
with
Althusserianism.
The
Ignorant
Schoolmaster
is
profoundly
sceptical
of
the
professed
interests
of
educational
institutions
in
equality.570
As
stated,
Althusserianism,
for
all
its
promises
of
correct
revolutionary
practice,
seemed
to
Rancière
to
come
down
to
“a
pedagogy
of
delay”.571
The
moment
of
the
revolution
is
infinitely
postponed
and
in
the
meantime
the
social
and
institutional
privileges
of
pedagogues
are
strengthened.572
It
was
in
the
figure
of
Jacocot
that
Rancière
found
a
way
to
react
to
some
of
his
concerns
around
Althusserianism.
He
also
found
in
Jacocot
a
way
in
which
to
conceptualise
his
highly
original
description
of
equality.
Whilst
much
of
Jacocot’s
anti-‐method
of
teaching
remains
vague
in
Rancière’s
account,
it
is
important
to
note,
as
Davis
highlights,
that
Rancière
does
not
devise
567
Rancière J (2003).
568
Rancière J The Ignorant Schoolmaster: Five Lessons in Intellectual Emancipation (1991)
trans. Ross K.
569
Davis O (2010) 27.
570
Davis O (2010) 29.
571
As above.
572
See section 2.2 above.
118
a
“new
curriculum
or
a
pedagogical
programme”.573
Jacocot’s
pedagogical
experiment
rather
provides
a
new
understanding
of
the
nature
of
equality.574
According
to
Davis,
the
book
offers
“an
emancipatory
reconfiguration
of
the
idea
of
the
lesson”.575
For
May,
Rancière
puts
into
question
the
distance
between
teacher
and
taught
subjects,
knowledge
and
non-‐knowledge
and
the
knowing
master
and
the
ignorant
masses.576
Before
explaining
Rancière’s
exploration
of
Jacocot,
it
should
be
mentioned
that
in
his
telling
of
Jacocot,
Rancière’s
voice
mingles
thoroughly
with
that
of
Jacocot’s.
May
explains
that
the
book
works
assiduously
to
avoid
any
type
of
commentary
and
it
also
shies
away
from
any
devices
that
would
separate
the
author
and
subjects
or
readers.577
In
this
regard,
May
explains
that
Rancière
employs
the
present
tense
throughout
the
book
and
avoids
phrases
such
as
“Jacocot
says”.578
Rancière
also
fully
adopts
Jacocot’s
vocabulary.
Swenson,
for
example
notes
that
the
key
terms
such
as
émancipation,
explication
and
abrutissement
are
all
Jacocot’s
usages
and
Rancière
gives
the
responses
Jacocot
gave
to
the
objections
he
encountered.
579
As
Swenson
further
explains,
the
small
number
of
authors
referred
to
are
all
contemporaries
whom
Jacocot
liked
to
read
and
the
primary
citations
are
largely
drawn
from
Jacocot
himself,
his
detractors,
and
his
defenders.580
As
Swenson
notes,
“there
is
no
moment
at
which
Rancière
leaves
Jacocot’s
circle”.581
Davis
notes
that
the
book
is
a
philosophical
tale
that
offers
material
resistance
to
easy
conceptual
analysis.582
He
argues
that
[g]iven
Jacocot’s
suspicion
of
explanation,
it
is
appropriate
that
-‐
because
of
its
complex
conceptual-‐material
texture
-‐
this
is
an
especially
difficult
book
573
Davis O (2010) 29.
574
As above. Fénelon F Les Aventures de Télémaque published anonymously in 1699 and
reissued by Fénelon’s family in 1717. Davis explains that the story fills out a gap in Homer’s
Odyssey, recounting the educational travels of Telemachus, son of Ulysses, accompanied by
his tutor, Mentor, who is revealed at the end of the story to be Minerva, the goddess of
wisdom. Davis O (2010) 29.
575
As above.
576
May T “Rancière in South Carolina” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 111.
577
As above.
578
As above.
579
Swenson J “Style indirect libre” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 266.
580
As above.
581
As above.
582
Davis O (2010) 29.
119
to
explain.
[It]
is
a
skillfully
crafted
material
object,
a
textured
work
of
art
and
artifice,
as
well
as
a
book
of
ideas.583
Thus,
it
becomes
difficult
to
fully
capture
Rancière’s
engagement
with
Jacocot.
I
therefore
do
not
propose
to
fully
explain
Rancière’s
exploration
and
the
implications
thereof,
but
rather
to
shed
some
light
on
the
most
important
arguments
that
Rancière
puts
forth
through
his
analysis
of
Jacocot.
Joseph
Jacocot
(1770-‐1840)
was
an
artilleryman
in
the
Republican
Armies
and
a
partisan
from
the
French
Revolution.
The
Bourbon
Restoration
forced
him
into
exile
and
it
was
while
he
was
in
exile
that
he
obtained
a
teaching
position
at
the
University
of
Louvain
in
Flanders.
He
had
to
teach
French
to
a
group
of
Flemish
students.
The
only
problem
was
that
Jacocot
did
not
speak
a
word
of
Flemish
and
his
students
did
not
speak
a
word
of
French.
This
would
normally
present
a
problem
when
it
comes
effective
teaching.
However,
as
Davis
explains,
Jacocot
devised
a
plan
so
as
to
not
be
exposed
as
a
fraud.584
He
came
upon
a
bilingual
copy
of
Télémaque,
Fenelon’s
praised
portrayal
of
the
wanderings
of
Telemachus.
He
asked
his
students
to
learn
the
French
by
comparing
it
to
the
Flemish
and
his
desperate
attempt
at
teaching
“yielded
unexpected
results”.585
After
some
time,
the
students
were
not
only
able
to
read
the
French
text,
but
they
could
compose
essays
on
its
meaning.
Rancière
states:
583
As above. In Rancière’s account of him, Jacocot may be seen as emphasising the
“materiality of the subjects” he is teaching and conversely the ideality, or intellectuality, of so-
called “manual” labour. See Davis O (2010) 28-29. One of the principles of Jacocot’s method
for Rancière, is to establish a relation of equivalence between knowledge and the materials
worked upon by the labourer: “Each citizen is also a man who makes a work, with the pen,
with the drill, or with any other tool” (Rancière J The Ignorant Schoolmaster (1991) 108). The
intention, as Davis mentions, is to also persuade the manual worker who thinks learning is
something he is unable to do that he is already exercising the same human intellect in his
work. See Davis O (2010) 28-29. To understand Telemachus takes no special gift, or no gift
more special than the intellect, which he is already using in his work. As will be explained,
with regards to Rancière’s discussion in The Nights of Labour, this undermines the
assumption underlying the Platonic social hierarchy, which placed pedagogues in superior
positions and posits occupations. For Rancière, no one person is especially suited or destined
for writing books any more than any other is for making shoes. This notion carries over into
the style in which The Ignorant Schoolmaster is written, in the sense that it “weaves a
complex conceptual-material web”. See Davis O (2010) 28-29.
584
Davis O (2010) 29.
585
As above.
120
He
had
given
no
explanation
to
his
students
on
the
first
elements
of
language.
He
had
not
explained
spelling
or
conjugations
to
them.
They
had
looked
for
the
French
words
that
correspond
to
words
they
knew
and
the
reasons
for
their
grammatical
endings
themselves.586
Students
were
therefore
learning
without
Jacocot’s
instruction
and
he
soon
employed
this
method
of
so-‐called
“non-‐teaching”
to
other
subjects
in
which
he
was
not
proficient,
such
as
law,
piano
and
painting.587
As
Tanke
explains,
non-‐
teaching
somehow
allowed
Jacocot
to
see
what
is
often
concealed
in
traditional
pedagogical
practices
namely,
that
one
does
not
learn
by
internalising
the
knowledge
of
another,
but
through
the
exercise
of
one’s
own
faculties.588
What
he
learned
was
ways
of
removing
obstacles
to
student’s
abilities
so
that
they
can
eventually,
with
time,
make
their
own
discoveries.589
From
his
experiences
Jacocot
draws
the
conclusion
that
people
are
equally
intelligent
or
they
have
equal
mental
capacities.
For
Jacocot,
the
problem
of
education
is
not
that
people
have
different
levels
of
intellectual
abilities,
but
as
Swenson
notes,
that
some
attend
closely
to
what
they
are
doing
and
others
do
not.590
There
are
therefore
no
natural
divisions
that
prevent
people
from
achieving
academic
success.
One
only
has
to
engage
with
the
material.591
Jacocot’s
experiences
led
him
to
conceptualise
a
pedagogical
theory
of
radical
intellectual
equality,
affirming
that
all
people
are
in
possession
of
equal
mental
capacity.
Rancière
states:
The
duty
of
Joseph
Jacocot’s
disciples
is
thus
simple.
They
must
announce
to
everyone
in
all
places
and
all
circumstances,
the
news,
the
practice:
one
can
teach
what
one
doesn’t
know.592
Jacocot’s
experiences
also
led
him
to
general
scepticism
about
the
function
and
effectiveness
of
explanation.
Rancière
states
the
following:
Explanation
is
not
necessary
to
remedy
an
incapacity
to
understand.
On
the
contrary,
that
very
incapacity
provides
the
structuring
fiction
of
the
explicative
conception
of
the
world.
It
is
the
explicator
who
needs
the
incapable
and
not
the
other
way
around;
it
is
he
who
constitutes
the
586
Rancière J (1991) 4-5.
587
As above.
588
Tanke J (2011) 35.
589
As above.
590
Swenson J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 111.
591
As above.
592
Rancière J On the Shores of Politics (1995) 101.
121
incapable
as
such.
To
explain
something
to
someone
is
first
of
all
to
show
him
he
cannot
understand
it
by
himself.
Before
being
the
act
of
the
pedagogue,
explication
is
the
myth
of
pedagogy,
the
parable
of
a
word
divided
into
knowing
minds
and
ignorant
ones,
ripe
minds
and
immature
ones,
the
capable
and
the
incapable,
the
intelligent
and
the
stupid.593
For
Jacocot,
“all
people
are
virtually
capable
of
understanding
what
others
have
done
and
understood”.594
Everyone
has
the
same
intelligence
and
differences
in
knowledge
are
simply
matters
of
either
opportunity
and/or
motivation.
Hallward
explains
that
on
the
basis
of
this
assumption,
superior
or
having
more
knowledge
than
another
ceases
to
be
a
necessary
qualification
of
the
teacher,
just
as
the
process
of
explanation
ceases
to
be
an
important
part
of
teaching.595
The
usual
supposition
of
education
systems
is
that
it
should
function
in
such
a
way
that
it
eventually
furthers
social
justice
and
equality
between
people.596
Jacocot
however,
as
Tanke
explains,
begins
with
the
assumption
of
intellectual
equality
and
seeks
to
establish
a
different
type
of
pedagogy
on
the
strength
of
this
assumption.597
Over
time
Jacocot
defended
his
method
and
came
to
oppose
traditional
pedagogy
on
its
grounds.
Tanke
further
clarifies
that
in
order
to
maintain
the
position
that
people
are
equally
intelligent
what
is
required
is
the
refusal
to
accept
that
intellectual
inequality
is
the
explanation
for
why
some
do
better
than
others
or
why
some
achieve
greater
academic
success
than
others.598
Intelligence
needs
to
be
separated
from
its
material
effects.
He
explains
that
it
is
obvious
that
some
do
better
than
others,
that
some
are
more
successful
than
others
and
more
quickly
successful
when
it
comes
to
the
tests
and
trails
put
forth
by
educational
institutions.599
But
this
cannot
necessarily
and
should
not
be
described
in
terms
of
intelligence.
For
Tanke,
the
question
that
Rancière
puts
forth
with
regards
to
Jacocot
is
the
following:
“How
are
we
to
move
seamlessly
from
material
facts
to
593
Rancière J (1991) 6-7.
594
Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 144.
595
As above.
596
As above.
597
May T in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 111.
598
Tanke J (2011) 36-37.
599
As above.
122
the
immaterial
of
the
mind?”600
For
Jacocot,
the
juncture
between
thought
and
expression
must
be
affirmed
in
order
to
do
so.601
As
Tanke
elucidates,
thought
is
prior
to
language
and
all
communication
is
first
and
foremost
the
will
to
communicate
sentiments
by
means
of
arbitrary
signs.602
It
is
therefore
possible
to
contend
that
intellectual
activity
is
equal
because
of
the
fact
that
communication
is
sometimes
difficult
and
it
is
within
the
process
of
communication,
articulation
and
expression
that
problems
may
arise.
What
is
therefore
preferred
is
a
different
explanation
for
why
some
students
learn
faster
than
others.
Tanke
explains
that
dissimilar
results
should
rather
be
attributed
to
different
intensities
of
will.603
As
Tanke
further
elucidates;
the
claim
is
not
that
all
academic
works
are
equal
in
quality,
but
rather
that
they
do
not
originate
from
two
different
natures.604
Rancière
states:
There
aren’t
two
sorts
of
minds.
There
is
inequality
in
the
manifestations
of
intelligence,
according
to
the
greater
or
lesser
energy
communicated
to
the
intelligence
by
the
will
for
discovering
and
combining
new
relations;
but
there
is
no
hierarchy
of
intellectual
capacity,
emancipation
is
becoming
conscious
of
this
equality
of
nature.605
And
I
will
not
say
that
one’s
faculties
are
inferior
to
other’s.
I
will
only
suppose
that
the
two
faculties
haven’t
been
equally
exercised.606
Jacocot
named
his
method
“universal
teaching”
and
it
basically
involves
the
natural
method
by
which
one
learns
through
comparing
of
two
facts.607
Tanke
explains
that
a
student
must
identify
a
fact,
relate
it
to
something
else
and
then
relate
or
recount
the
connection
between
the
two.608
In
order
to
do
this,
no
explanation
is
needed:
600
As above.
601
As above.
602
As above.
603
As above.
604
As above.
605
Rancière J (1991) 27.
606
Rancière J (1991) 50.
607
Tanke J (2011) 37.
608
As above.
123
All
that
is
required
is
the
confidence
to
venture
forward
into
a
world
of
unconnected
facts,
the
will
to
focus
the
intelligence
and
the
courage
to
find
the
language
to
communicate
one’s
adventure.609
In
his
pedagogical
experiment,
Jacocot’s
role
as
teacher
was
reduced
to
the
relentless
and
continuous
questioning
of
students
to
ensure
that
they
apply
themselves
to
the
task
at
hand.610
When
there
were
performances
of
uneven
achievement,
the
teacher’s
role
is
not
to
use
these
performances
to
rank
the
students
by
intelligence
or
capacity,
but
rather
to
see
weakness
as
evidence
of
a
lack
of
application
to
the
task.
Davis
notes
that
when
students
protested
that
they
cannot
do
better,
or
cannot
perform
the
task
at
all,
the
teacher
was
to
become
“an
intractable
master”,
as
stubborn
as
possible.611
Jacocot
therefore,
according
to
Davis,
took
the
protests
of
students
as
false
modesty.612
A
typically
response
from
Jacocot
was:
You
must
begin
to
speak.
Don’t
say
that
you
can’t.
You
know
how
to
say
“I
can’t”.
Say
in
its
place
“Calypso
could
not”,
and
you’re
off.
You’re
off
on
a
route
that
you
already
knew,
and
that
you
should
follow
always
without
giving
up.
Don’t
say:
“I
can’t”.
Or
then
learn
to
say
it
in
the
manner
of
Calypso,
in
the
manner
of
Telemachus,
of
Narbal,
of
Idomeneus
[…]
you
will
never
run
out
of
ways
to
say
“I
can’t”,
and
soon
you
will
be
able
to
say
everything.613
The
ignorant
teacher
is
therefore
someone
who
validates
the
efforts
of
students
and
provides
them
with
continuous
encouragement,
always
keeping
students
on
track
to
their
intellectual
emancipation.614
Tanke
states:
The
master
compels
the
student
to
make
greater
effort,
to
draw
more
connections,
to
recognise
deeper
patterns,
and
to
communicate
the
results
more
elegantly.
He
does
not
for
all
that
tell
the
student
what
to
think
about
what
he
finds.
He
simply
provides
the
occasion
for
the
student
to
discover
his
own
capacity.615
609
As above.
610
Davis O (2010) 27.
611
As above
612
As above.
613
Rancière J (1991) 24 as quoted in Davis O (2010) 27.
614
Tanke J (2011) 37.
615
Tanke J (2011) 38.
124
Tanke
further
explains
that
universal
teaching
refuses
to
employ
“explication”,
which
is
the
process
whereby
a
teacher
clarifies
and
explains
text.616
Explication
supplements
a
text
with
commentary
that
is
designed
to
make
the
meaning
of
the
text
clearer
or
apparent.617
During
the
process
of
explication,
as
Tanke
notes,
the
assumption
exists
that
the
text
will
not
be
properly
understood
without
the
teachers’
intervention.618
The
process
therefore
continuously
reveals
what
a
student
would
not
have
gathered
without
assistance.619
For
Rancière,
explication
institutes
a
relationship
between
intelligence
and
intelligence,
thereby,
as
Tanke
notes,
convincing
a
student
of
the
inferiority
of
her
own.620
What
is
learned
in
this
process
is
that
one’s
intelligence
relies
upon
another’s
and
in
Rancière’s
view
the
intelligence
of
the
student
is
subordinated
and
the
relationship
is
termed
“stultification”.621
As
Tanke
further
explains,
the
process
whereby
the
mind
realises
its
own
powers
without
the
reliance
on
another’s,
is
known
as
“emancipation”
and
emancipation
is
opposed
to
stultification.622
Stultification
therefore
convinces
the
student
that
he
is
dependent
on
the
intelligence
of
others
whilst
emancipation
enables
him
to
discover
what
he
is
capable
of.623
Rancière
through
his
exploration
of
Jacocot
is
contesting
the
belief
that
nature
has
distributed
the
gifts
of
the
mind
unequally:
What
sustains
the
positions
of
educators,
to
say
nothing
of
the
social
order,
if
not
the
notion
that
some
are
not
capable
of
thinking
as
well
as
others?624
Universal
teaching
postulates
the
presupposition
of
intellectual
equality
and
as
Tanke
further
explains,
the
presupposition
of
intellectual
equality
is
a
hypothesis
in
search
of
proof.625
The
point
is
shifting
the
terms
of
the
debate
and
Tanke
notes
that
whilst
it
might
be
difficult
to
establish
the
presupposition
definitively,
it
616
As above.
617
Tanke J (2011) 37.
618
As above.
619
As above.
620
As above
621
As above.
622
Tanke J (2011) 38.
623
As above.
624
Tanke J (2011) 36.
625
As above.
125
is
a
belief
that
is
legitimate
to
hold.626
Rancière
explains,
“our
problem
isn’t
proving
that
all
intelligence
is
equal.
It
is
seeing
what
can
be
done
under
that
presupposition”.627
Davis
argues
that
at
times
Jacocot’s
method
might
be
viewed
as
an
elaborate
form
of
“autodidactism”,
the
process
whereby
a
learner
struggles
alone
with
the
content
of
a
text,
while
the
teacher
at
most
seeks
to
keep
the
student
focussed
with
relentless
questioning.628
Jacocot’s
method
is
further
viewed
by
Rancière
as
a
radical
critique
of
the
Enlightenment
model
of
progressive
pedagogy.
For
Rancière,
Jacocot
derives
the
“mad”
notion
that
all
intelligence
is
equal
and
that
this
equality
is
a
presupposition
that
requires
demonstration
and
not
a
goal
that
needs
to
be
attained
[…]
he
derives
the
notion
that
the
ideals
of
progress
and
the
progressive
moment
are,
in
and
of
themselves,
principles
of
inequality
as
a
social
end
and
entrusting
certain
education
“experts”
with
the
task
of
reducing
the
effects
of
the
clash
between
an
“equality
to
come”
with
existing
inequality
means,
in
short
to
institute
inequality
as
principle
whose
reproduction
is
infinite.629
According
to
Davis,
Rancière’s
thoughts
around
Jacocot
can
therefore
be
seen
as
an
early
challenge
to
the
progressivism
which
took
hold
of
the
nineteenth
century
and
which
still
dominates
thinking
about
education
and
social
inequality
today.630
According
to
Rancière:
An
enormous
machine
was
revving
up
to
promote
equality
through
instruction.
This
was
equality
represented,
socialised,
made
unequal,
good
for
being
perfected-‐
that
is
to
say,
deferred
from
commission
to
commission,
from
report
to
report,
from
reform
to
reform
until
the
end
of
time.
Jacocot
was
alone
in
recognising
the
effacement
of
equality
under
progress,
of
emancipation
under
instruction.631
It
should
further
be
noted
that
Rancière’s
assumption
of
equal
intelligence
amounts
too
much
more
than
merely
the
idea
to
have
the
utmost
of
faith
in
the
626
As above.
627
Rancière J (1991) 46.
628
Davis O “The radical pedagogies of François Bon and Jacques Rancière” French Studies
(2010) 183.
629
Panagia D “Dissenting words: A conversation with Jacques Rancière” Diacritics (2000) 122.
630
Davis O (2010) 30.
631
Rancière J (1991) 134.
126
abilities
of
students.632
Davis
argues
that
it
implies
a
profoundly
different
understanding
of
the
relationship
between
student
and
teacher.633
The
teacher’s
role
is
to
place
the
student
in
a
position
or
situation
from
which
they
can
only
escape
by
using
their
intellect.634
Universal
teaching
therefore
involves
somewhat
of
a
paradox:
“[I]f
emancipation
is
something
which
can
never
be
given,
but
only
taken,
to
teach
is
to
construct
a
serious
of
puzzles
from
which
the
student
can
only
escape
by
seizing
knowledge”.635
Universal
also
teaching
involves
relentless
questioning
in
an
attempt
“to
expose
non-‐sequiturs
and
obscurities”.636
For
Davis,
Jacocot’s
aversion
to
explanation
is
sometimes
exaggerated
to
the
limits
of
plausibility.637
He
radically
marks
his
stance
from
any
type
of
common-‐sense
thinking
about
education.638
However,
as
further
explained
by
Davis,
his
suspicion
of
explanation
is
not
incoherent.
It
should
rather
be
understood
in
institutional
and
political
terms.639
In
his
view,
when
students
are
taught
in
a
“normal”
way
by
being
led
from
imperfect
or
incorrect
explanations
to
less
imperfect
or
correct
ones,
this
promotes
intellectual
dependency
and
endorses
the
sense
of
intellectual
inequality
which
is
crucial
to
the
survival
of
the
institution
and
the
maintenance
of
the
status
quo.640
Therefore,
Davis
explains,
the
intellectual
inequality
that
is
produced
by
institutions
is
thought
of
by
Rancière
in
relation
to
other
forms
of
social
inequality.641
According
to
Rancière
it
rationalises
the
division
of
society
into
those
who
are
born
to
think
and
govern
and
their
intellectual
inferiors
in
intelligence
that
are
fit
only
to
follow
instruction.642
Educational
institutions
therefore
seem
to
instil
a
sense
of
intellectual
and
political
inequality
through
processes
such
as
marking
and
examinations
as
well
as
632
Davis O French Studies (2010) 184.
633
As above.
634
As above.
635
As above.
636
As above.
637
As above.
638
As above.
639
As above.
640
As above
641
As above.
642
As above.
127
through
the
subtext
of
the
everyday
interactions
between
student
and
teacher,
rather
than
instilling
a
sense
of
capability.643
Jacocot
also
argues
that
even
though
the
aim
of
ordinary
pedagogy
is
to
bring
about
greater
equality
between
student
and
teacher
by
way
of
a
series
of
incrementally
more
sophisticated
explanations,
it
is
unacceptably
slow.644
It
is
a
hierarchal
approach,
which
misunderstands
the
process
of
learning
and
the
reality
of
human
intellect.645
For
Jacocot,
one
can
obtain
better
results
by
assuming
from
the
outset
that
students
are
the
intellectual
equals
of
their
teacher.646
Davis
explains
that
when
a
teacher
presumes
that
a
student
is
equal
in
intelligence
it
enables
the
student
to
retranslate
his
expression
of
incapacity
into
the
very
knowledge
of
which
he
thought
himself
incapable.647
This
is
the
key
point
about
Jacocot’s
method.648
Alain
Badiou
has
formulated
the
following
two
theses
with
regard
to
this
point:
1. Under
the
condition
of
a
declared
equality,
ignorance
is
the
point
at
which
new
knowledge
can
emerge.
2. Under
authority
of
an
ignorant
master,
knowledge
can
be
a
space
for
equality.649
As
Davis
notes,
the
radical
conception
of
equality
that
Rancière
derives
from
Jacocot
is
that
equality
must
be
presupposed,
from
the
outset,
within
the
pedagogical
encounter;
it
is
an
equality
that
must
be
declared
and
verified
within
that
encounter.650
This
line
of
thinking
of
course
permeates
Rancière’s
politics.
Equality
is
active
and
must
be
assumed
and
put
to
the
test.
It
is
further
important
to
mention
that
the
method
of
universal
teaching
is
essentially
anti-‐institutional.
Jacocot
was
deeply
sceptical
of
all
attempts
to
translate
universal
teaching
into
any
type
of
hierarchical
social
arrangement.
He
643
Davis O French Studies (2010) 188.
644
As above.
645
As above.
646
Davis O (2010) 25.
647
As above.
648
Davis O (2010) 27.
649
Badiou A in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 42.
650
Davis O (2010) 27.
128
therefore
rejected
the
possibility
of
the
incorporation
of
universal
teaching
into
organised
frameworks.
As
Tanke
eloquently
puts
it,
“for
Jacocot,
its
institutionalisation
will
be
its
betrayal”.651
As
Tanke
explains,
Jacocot
insists
on
the
pedagogical
being
a
site
for
the
realisation
of
equality
and
institutions
inevitably
function
by
establishing
hierarchies
and
inequality.652
However,
this
is
not
a
call
to
anarchism.653
Rancière
emphasises
that
Jacocot’s
students
were
more
than
ready
and
willing
to
engage
in
political
argument,
but
they
realised
that
its
rhetoric
is
often
competition
for
supremacy
and
that
moments
of
reason
are
far
and
few
in
between.654
For
Rancière
it
is
rather
about
the
fact
that
“every
institution
is
an
explication
in
social
act,
a
dramatisation
of
inequality”.655
Further,
Télémaque
was
necessary
within
Jacocot’s
experiment.
The
text
allowed
Jacocot
to
distance
himself
from
his
intelligence
and
knowing,
thereby
allowing
students
to
discover
their
own
intellectual
capabilities.
According
to
the
approach
of
radical
intellectual
equality
the
teacher
no
longer
distributes
knowledge
to
the
student,
but
he
rather
encourages
the
student
to
acquire
knowledge
for
him
or
herself
through
an
encounter
with
a
written
text
or
some
other
demonstration
or
example
from
that
field
of
knowledge.656
Télémaque
formed
the
bond
between
Jacocot
and
his
students
and
Jacocot’s
role
amounted
to
nothing
more
than
continuously
pointing
students
back
to
the
text.
Davis
notes
that
“the
schoolmaster
can
be
ignorant
because
the
text
it
savant”.657
Therefore,
when
Jacocot
radicalised
his
experiment
by
teaching
more
subjects
that
he
didn’t
know
anything
about,
the
text
or
other
example
from
that
field
is
what,
according
to
Davis,
saves
the
ignorant
schoolmaster
from
absurdity.658
Télémaque,
or
its
651
Tanke J (2011) 40.
652
As above.
653
Davis O (2010) 29.
654
Davis O (2010) 28-29.
655
Rancière J (1991) 105.
656
Davis 28-29.
657
Davis O French Studies (2010) 183.
658
As above.
129
equivalent,
allows
pedagogy
to
be
simultaneously
egalitarian
and
meaningful
as
“the
teacher
and
the
student
are
equal
before
the
book”.659
Tanke
explains
that
universal
teaching
works
on
the
assumption
that
knowledge
is
simply
there
for
the
taking,
based
on
the
model
of
primary
language
learning.660
It
is
always
a
matter
of
learning
a
language,
or
using
a
familiar
tool.661
Anything
can
serve
as
a
starting
point.
The
idea
that
thought
is
before
language
allows
us
to
transform
knowledge
into
creative
activity:
[W]e
speak
as
poets
when
we
recount
the
mind’s
adventure
with
imperfect
signs.662
According
to
Rancière/Jacocot,
the
most
important
virtue
of
intelligence
is
poetry,
understood
in
a
broad
sense.663
Tanke
explains
that
for
Jacocot
and
Rancière,
knowledge
consists
in
drawing
connections
and
inventing
language
in
which
we
can
communicate
these
findings.664
Rancière
states
that
[i]n
the
act
of
speaking,
man
doesn’t
transmit
his
knowledge,
he
makes
poetry;
he
translates
and
invites
others
to
do
the
same.
He
communicates
as
artisan:
as
a
person
who
handles
words
like
tools.665
Communication
is
therefore
a
double
creation
and
it
consists
of
translating
to
signs
one’s
own
experience
of
navigation.666
Jacocot
and
Rancière
contend
that
the
artist
can
probably
more
readily
discover
the
language
of
equality
than
university
professors,
because
“[t]hey
renounce
the
tyranny
of
the
fixed
message,
creating
instead
spaces
for
play,
reciprocal
engagement
and
negotiated
meaning”.667
659
As above.
660
Tanke J (2011) 39.
661
Rancière J (1991) 65 & 5-6.
662
Tanke J (2011) 39.
663
As above.
664
As above.
665
Rancière J (1991) 65.
666
Tanke J (2011) 39.
667
Tanke J (2011) 39.
130
Ultimately,
Rancière’s
work
and
exploration
of
Jacocot
seeks
to
demonstrate
the
power
of
declarations
of
equality,
intellectually
and
politically.
Ross
eloquently
reiterates
the
role
of
equality
in
the
context
of
Jacocot
and
I
quote
her
at
length.
At
the
heart
of
the
pedagogical
relation
is
the
representation
of
inequality
as
evolutionary
epistemology:
the
people
who
can
never
catch
up
with
the
enlightened
elite,
or
who
can
never
be
completely
modern.
People
who
are
trapped,
without
knowing
it,
at
one
stage
along
the
trajectory
of
progressive
time,
and
who
are
destined
to
remain
there,
imprisoned
in
this
other
time,
that
of
the
child,
or
that
of
the
primitive.
But,
inequality
can’t
be
gradually
whittled
away,
just
as
equality
is
not
a
goal
to
be
one
day
attained,
nor
arrived
at
by
dint
of
a
series
of
concessions
made
by
the
state.
Short-‐
circuiting
the
temporality
of
pedagogy
makes
equality
a
point
of
departure,
the
point
of
departure,
an
axiom
anterior
to
the
constitution
of
a
particular
staging
of
politics
and
which
makes
such
a
staging
possible.
Rather
than
being
the
criteria
that
determines
how
long
it
will
take
for
society
as
it
is
to
become
society
as
it
might
or
should
be,
equality
as
an
axiom
enables,
thought,
experiment,
invention.668
For
Rancière,
the
idea
that
students
learn
on
their
own
means
that
the
hierarchal
ordering
and
policing
of
society
is
constantly
undermined
by
the
absolute
equality
that
characterises
the
human
intellectual
and
always
insures
a
potential
for
true
political
intervention.
What
does
it
mean
to
presuppose
people
are
equally
intelligent?
In
short,
it
has
to
do
with
the
ability
of
people
to
shape
their
own
lives.669
In
this
regard
May
states
that
[s]urely
there
are
things
that
others
can
teach
us.
But
we
are
capable
of
cobbling
those
teachings
together
into
a
meaningful
whole,
and
far
more
capable
of
teaching
ourselves
many
of
those
things
than
the
hierarchal
order
in
which
we
live
would
lead
us
to
believe.670
The
employment
of
equality
allows
for
previously
supressed
capacities
to
emerge
and
the
presupposition
of
equality
is
a
destabilising
force.
Equality
can
disrupt
any
notion
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
It
is
not
given,
or
claimed,
but
practiced
and
verified.
Assuming
radical
intellectual
equality
bolsters
capacities
previously
denied
or
not
recognised
and
allows
those
deprived
or
silenced
voices
the
ability
to
reconfigure
the
sensible
configuration.671
In
the
conclusion
I
elaborate
on
668
Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 26.
669
May T in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 111.
670
As above.
671
Tanke J (2011) 36-37.
131
Jacocot’s
equality
as
it
pertains
to
voice.
Below,
I
turn
to
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny.
3.3
Gabriel
Gauny
in
The
Nights
of
Labor
and
Plato
in
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
There
is
no
point
waiting
for
some
moment
in
the
future
when
everyone
has
the
leisure
to
be
by
turns
a
shepherd,
a
fisherman
and
a
critic
at
nightfall
[…]
the
time
is
now
for
us
to
break
the
chains
of
the
working
day
in
which
and
against
we
struggle,
the
time
to
win
for
ourselves
the
body
and
soul
of
philosophical
leisure.672
Tanke
mentions
that
one
of
the
major
political
legacies
of
May
‘68
was
to
disrupt
the
boundaries
thought
to
exist
between
manual
and
intellectual
labour.673
The
boundaries
between
manual
and
intellectual
labour
became
of
great
interest
to
Rancière.
His
work
of
the
1970’s
around
Althusserianism
can
be
viewed
as
an
attempt
to
displace
the
representational
mechanisms
through
which
intellectuals
attempted
to
guide
political
movements.674
And
the
disruption
of
the
boundaries
between
manual
and
intellectual
labour
became
central
to
this
displacement.
His
concern
in
this
regard
sent
him
into
the
archives
of
the
French
workers’
movement.
He
would
remain
there
for
ten
years.
This
experience
was
essential
to
the
formation
of
many
of
Rancière’s
central
notions,
especially
those
pertaining
to
politics
as
the
redefining
of
partitions
of
the
sensible
world.
The
insights
he
gathered
in
the
archives
continue
to
define
his
thought
and,
as
Tanke
mentions,
its
spirit
shapes
his
general
approach
to
political
and
philosophical
questions.675
Rancière’s
archival
work
resulted
in
the
publication
of
The
Nights
of
Labor:
The
Worker’s
Dream
in
Nineteenth-‐Century
France
in
1981
and
The
Philosopher
and
his
Poor
in
1983.676
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
can
be
viewed
as
a
companion
to
The
Nights
of
Labor.
The
latter
charts
the
history
of
workers
who
refused
to
live
their
lives
according
to
the
prescriptions
of
work
and
therefore
their
strict
identities
as
672
Rancière J Louis-Gabriel Gauny: Le Philosophe Plébéien (1983) 17 as quoted in and
translated by Davis O (2010) 160.
673
Tanke J (2011) 22.
674
As above.
675
As above.
676
Rancière J (1989) & (2004).
132
workers.
The
former,
as
Davis
notes,
investigates
the
means
by
which
philosophy
has
locked
up
workers
through
discourses
about
their
nature.677
For
Rancière,
philosophy
has
historically
defined
itself
against
those
people
engaged
in
manual
labour,
arguing
for
its
superiority
and
powers
of
discernment
against
those
supposedly
lacking
the
time
for
thought.
Both
of
the
books
therefore
interrogate
the
idea
that
thinking
is
a
luxury
of
a
few.
In
this
section,
I
discuss
the
historical
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny
that
Rancière
explores
in
his
book,
The
Nights
of
Labor.
Before
focussing
on
Gauny
and
Rancière’s
engagement
with
him,
I
outline
Rancière’s
engagement
with
Plato
in
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor.
When
it
comes
to
the
relationship
between
power
and
knowledge
and
intellectual
and
manual
labour,
Plato
becomes
an
important
critical
focus
for
Rancière.
An
outlining
of
Rancière’s
main
concerns
with
regards
to
Plato
becomes
important
as
it
allows
for
a
proper
appreciation
of
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny.
Rancière,
at
times,
directly
link
Gauny’s
actions
and
words
with
Plato’s
assumptions
in
order
to
show
that
the
latter
is
unfounded.
The
analysis
of
Plato
is
further
central
to
Rancière’s
thinking
as
it
directly
relates
to
the
notion
that
some
are
capable
of
thinking
and
others
are
not
or
that
some
are
destined
for
contemplation
and
others
for
work.
It
therefore
becomes
important
to
shortly
outline
some
arguments
made
by
Plato.
3.3.1
Plato
Davis
explains
that
for
Rancière
Plato’s
idea
of
the
city
in
Republic
is
a
political
model
of
“philosophical-‐pedagogical
tyranny”.678
The
Republic
is
a
treatise
on
677
Tanke J (2011) 22.
678
Davis O (2010) 18. Davis outlines the way in which Rancière’s positive account of
intellectual equality originated from his radicalisation of the critique of pedagogy in
Althusser’s Lesson to encapsulate Marx as well as Sartre and Bourdieu as thinkers in the
French Marxist tradition. Rancière’s work in the archives bolstered his belief that an
Althusserian understanding of the relationship between Marxist intellectual and revolutionary
struggle was wrongheaded. See Davis O (2010) 18-25. Davis explains that in The Philosopher
and his Poor, he returns to explore the contours of this motif in Marx’s work and its
reappearance in that of Jean-Paul Sartre and Pierre Bourdieu and its prehistory that he finds
in Plato’s ideal state (Davis O (2010) 18-25). In this book, Rancière argues by suggestive
juxtaposition that the scientific strand identified within the Marxist tradition (in Marx, Sartre
133
government
as
well
as
a
treatise
on
education
in
which
the
educated
rule
and
in
turn
educate
their
successors.
Plato
allows
for
three
social
classes
in
his
ideal
city
namely;
workers,
who
fulfil
the
material
needs
of
a
society
as
a
whole,
a
military
class
of
soldier-‐guardians
and
a
governing
class
of
philosopher-‐kings.679
Rulers
must
be
trained
in
order
to
ensure
that
they
have
acquired
the
necessary
knowledge
to
rule.
As
Davis
explains,
in
this
society,
government
is
a
product
of
a
selective
education
system
and
the
preserve
of
experts.680
It
is
a
self-‐perpetuating
system
because
of
the
fact
that
philosopher-‐kings
must
educate
their
successors
and
those
whom
education
is
offered
to
are
preselected
from
among
the
children
of
parents
in
the
military
and
the
ruling
classes.681
The
children
of
workers
are
not
normally
educated
for
government.
According
to
Plato,
the
hierarchy
of
classes
corresponds
to
a
hierarchy
of
human
character
types.
Davis
explains
that
the
assumption
is
that
in
members
of
the
working
class,
appetitive
desires
such
as
hunger
and
sexual
satisfaction
will
predominate,
whilst
in
the
classes
of
warrior-‐
guardians
and
philosopher-‐kings,
reason
and
honour
will
prevail
over
appetitive
desire.682
It
is
not
difficult
to
see,
considering
Rancière’s
intense
aversion
to
destined
positions
within
the
police
order,
why
Plato,
at
times,
becomes
Rancière’s
enemy
number
one.
As
Davis
elucidates
further,
Plato
is
quite
aware
that
the
assumption
of
the
hierarchy
of
human
character
types
is
exactly
that,
an
assumption.683
However,
he
suggests
that
it
should
be
taught
as
fact
and
in
order
to
argue
this,
he
takes
recourse
in
the
myth
of
three
metals.684
According
to
this
myth,
there
are
three
and Bourdieu, as well as Althusser), is rooted in a certain conception of the relationship
between power and knowledge first elaborated in Plato’s autocratic model of the ideal city in
Republic. It should be mentioned that I do not discuss Rancière’s engagement with Jean-Paul
Sartre and Pierre Bourdieu as an outline of the engagement with Plato will suffice in order to
contextualise Gabriel Gauny properly and in order to demonstrate Rancière’s contentions in
this regard. For general discussions on these theorists and Rancière’s engagement with them
see Davis O (2010) 18-25 and Tanke J (2011) 28-35.
679
As above.
680
As above.
681
As above.
682
As above.
683
As above.
684
As above.
134
races
of
people
in
the
hierarchal
relationships
of
society,
namely,
bronze,
silver
and
gold
races
that
correspond
to
the
three
social
classes.
The
myth
suggests
that
children
will
be
born
with
roughly
the
same
mix
of
metals
in
their
soul
as
their
parents.
The
main
function
of
the
selective
educational
system
outlined
by
Plato
is
to
deselect
or
to
disqualify
those
offspring,
so
that
the
racial
purity
of
the
classes
is
preserved.685
The
greatest
threat
to
this
system
is
the
social
climber,
“the
parvenu”
or
the
worker
with
ideas
above
what
his
station
requires.686
Davis
notes
that
there
is
of
course
nothing
especially
outlandish
about
Rancière’s
commentary
on
Plato.687
However,
what
makes
Rancière’s
criticisms
significant
is
where
he
repeatedly
places
the
emphasis,
namely,
on
the
fact
that
there
is
absolutely
no
rational
basis
for
Plato’s
elaborate,
autocratic
hierarchy.688
The
section
on
Plato
is
titled
“Plato’s
Lie”,
indicating
that
the
entire
system
rests
on
a
lie,
myth
or
founding
fiction.
Plato
was
disturbed
by
the
so-‐called
“amateurishness”
of
Athenian
democracy.689
He
rather
opted
for
aspects
of
the
Spartan
model
of
war-‐state
ruling
over
a
largely
submissive
population
that
provided
for
the
material
needs
of
the
state
as
a
whole.690
In
Plato’s
ideal
model
there
is
a
hierarchy
of
specialists
in
which
each
class
would
do
only
one
thing.
The
shoemaker
will
only
make
shoes
and
the
farmer
only
grow
crops
and
shoes
and
crops
will
be
exchanged
for
the
good
of
all.691
Plato
claims
that
only
by
devoting
all
our
time
to
one
activity,
an
activity
for
which
our
birth
equips
us,
can
the
best
results
be
achieved.
And
so
it
follows
that
workers
do
not
have
time
to
do
anything
but
work.
Rancière
doesn’t
find
the
claim
about
innate
character
traits,
nor
the
claim
about
the
time
required
for
perfecting
a
skill
persuasive.692
Rancière
acknowledges
that
685
Davis O (2010) 19.
686
As above.
687
As above.
688
As above.
689
As above.
690
As above.
691
As above.
692
As above.
135
Plato
is
merely
making
an
assumption
that
specialisation
is
the
only
way
to
achieve
the
best
results.
Workers,
it
is
assumed,
are
not
able
to
do
more
than
one
thing
at
a
time.
For
Rancière,
this
assumption
about
the
worker
translates
into
an
arbitrary
prohibition:
“the
simple
prohibition
against
doing
anything
else”.693
For
Plato,
the
climber
who
“trespasses”
on
the
role
or
the
position
of
others
lies
at
the
root
of
injustice
and
for
him,
justice
means
staying
put.694
Rancière
finds
it
significant
that
Plato,
through
introducing
the
myth
of
the
three
metals,
admits
to
the
arbitrariness
of
the
distinction
between
those
who
rule,
those
who
are
capable
of
philosophy
and
the
rest
of
the
multitude
or
the
workers
that
is
not
suited
for
for
thinking.695
For
Davis,
the
originality
in
Rancière’s
reading
lies
not
in
what
he
says
about
Plato
in
isolation,
but
rather
in
his
argument
by
way
of
“parataxis”
between
Plato
and
the
reputedly
progressive
work
of
philosophers
such
as
Marx,
Jean-‐Paul
Sartre
and
Pierre
Bourdieu.696
These
thinkers
are
therefore
tainted
by
association
according
to
Davis.697
For
Rancière,
all
four
have
in
common
the
construction
of
a
group
he
calls
“the
poor”
which
is
also
the
proletariat,
the
workers
or
the
dominated
class
who
are
constitutively
incapable
of
thought.698
Rancière
suggests
that
similar
reasons
are
advanced
in
each
case
693
As above.
694
As above.
695
See Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 276.
696
As above.
697
As above. Davis notes that with regard to Sartre, Rancière concentrates on his later work
that involves the question of the relation between workers and the Communist Party (Davis O
(2010) 22-25). According to Sartre, workers are unable to think for themselves and need the
Party because they do not have time and are too tired. Rancière thus aligns Sartre with the
Platonic argument for “specialisation”. See Davis O (2010) 22-25. In suggesting that workers
are too tired to think, Sartre unwittingly recreates the Platonic ban on doing more than one
thing. He also, according to Rancière, articulates Marx’s assumption that people make
history, but they do not know they do so. See Davis O (2010) 22-25. It should be mentioned
that Rancière’s point is not that Sartre’s concern for workers is disingenuous, but rather that
his emphasis on the worker’s inevitable tiredness deprives the worker of the power of
thought. As Davis explains, for Rancière, what Sartre is ultimately doing is denying his tired
poor the same capacity for “self-directing intellectual freedom”, which he as philosopher
exercises. For a more detailed discussion, see Davis O (2010) 20-22. Davis notes that
Rancière’s dispute with Bourdieu’s work on pedagogy and aesthetics is more involved than
his engagement with either Marx or Sartre. Davis accurately summarises Rancière’s
engagement with Bourdieu. See Davis O (2010) 22-25.
698
As above.
136
and
that
these
reasons
are
all
similarly
unfounded.699
More
importantly,
in
each
case
“the
philosopher”
is
dependent
on
“his
poor”
who
cannot
think
for
themselves.700
Marx’s
proletariat,
for
example,
are
held
up
as
the
embodiment
of
a
common
future.
However,
Davis
explains,
the
proletariat
are
constitutively
unable
to
understand
that
future
and
their
role
in
it.701
Such
knowledge
must
be
introduced
by
intellectuals,
who
stand
in
a
relationship
of
mutual
independence
to
their
specific
“poor”.702
In
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor,
Rancière
calls
for
the
recognition
of
the
equal
capacity
of
all
for
what
Davis
terms
“sophisticated
self-‐
understanding
and
self-‐performance”;
an
understanding
that
goes
far
beyond
conservative
thinking
such
as
that
captured
by
the
idea
that
the
worker
must
do
one
thing
at
a
time.703
Rancière’s
biggest
concern
in
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
is
the
underestimation
of
understanding
and
imagination
of
those
people
or
“poor”
on
whose
behalf
certain
philosophers
speak.
As
we
have
seen
with
his
discussion
on
Jacocot,
Rancière’s
conception
of
radical
intellectual
equality
is
a
reaction
against
pedagogical
power.
It
is
after
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
that
he
radicalises
his
critique
of
the
assumption
that
some
think
and
others
do
not
into
a
pedagogy
of
equal
intellectual
capacities.
Rancière
seeks
to
refute
the
idea
that
workers
should
perform
only
those
functions
that
supposedly
correspond
with
their
natures.704
Some
people
are
thought
to
be
naturally
capable
of
thought
and
others
are
destined
only
for
work.
Some
have
gold
in
their
souls,
others
silver
and
bronze.
Tanke
mentions
that
the
style
and
terrain
of
The
Philosopher
and
his
Poor
is
very
different
than
The
Nights
of
Labor.705
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
is
a
critique
of
philosophy
that
attempts
to
show
that
philosophical
thought,
in
order
to
demonstrate
its
difference
from
and
superiority
of
other
practices,
denies
the
poor
capacities
for
thought.706
In
699
As above.
700
As above.
701
As above.
702
As above.
703
Davis O (2010) 19.
704
Tanke J (2011) 28.
705
Tanke J (2011) 27-28.
706
As above
137
this
book,
Rancière
argues
that
philosophy
locks
up
the
poor
because
it
is
interested
in
preserving
its
own
purity.707
Tanke
explains
that
the
book
traces
the
form
that
philosophy
assumes
when
partitions
the
world
on
the
basis
of
supposedly
distinct
natures.
For
Rancière,
philosophy
harbours
a
general
disdain
for
the
working
classes.708
Plato’s
belief
that
each
should
perform
the
social
function
that
best
suit
his
nature,
justifies
a
certain
separation
between
theory
and
practice.709
Tanke
explains
that
in
Republic,
philosophy
regulates
production,
determines
moments
for
reproduction,
decides
which
spectacles
are
appropriate
and
generally
assures
that
the
division
of
labour
remains
intact.710
The
philosopher
therefore
promotes
or
demotes
individuals
based
on
judgements
about
their
aptitudes.711
Rancière
describes
philosophy
as
a
form
of
thinking
that
forcefully
denies
its
birth
and
obsessively
guards
its
lineage.712
For
Rancière,
philosophy
is
characterised
by
a
fundamental
and
ultimately
unsustainable
desire
for
purity
and
this
desire
compels
it
to
structure
itself
in
such
a
way
that
it
is
separate
from
other
practices.713
As
Tanke
explains,
whilst
there
are
considerable
differences
between
the
thinkers
that
Rancière
discusses,
they
all
rely
on
a
“conceptualisation
of
the
poor
as
an
inert
mass
whose
passivity
is
the
sine
qua
non
of
its
would-‐be
representatives”.714
For
Rancière,
this
conceptualisation
is
merely
a
variation
of
the
Platonic
distribution.
The
actions
of
certain
philosophers
restrict
the
business
of
thinking.715
Workers
require
specialists
that
are
dedicated
to
their
cause
and
the
traditional
division
of
labour
is
affirmed.716
For
Rancière,
certain
thinkers
fail
to
think
of
a
radical
alternative;
the
joining
together
of
the
realms
of
practice,
707
As above
708
As above.
709
As above
710
Tanke J (2011) 29.
711
As above.
712
Tanke J (2011) 30.
713
As above.
714
Tanke J (2011) 31.
715
As above
716
As above
138
thought
and
equality.717
Rancière
finds
in
the
figure
of
Gabriel
Gauny
a
joining
together
of
these
realms.
Gauny
forceful
asserts
the
rights
of
the
imagination
-‐
as
a
right
that
is
not
only
available
to
philosophers,
but
rather
to
anybody
who
wants
to
practice
such
a
right.
3.3.2
Gabriel
Gauny
Rancière
began
his
archival
work
during
a
period
in
which
many
intellectuals
left
their
normal
milieus
in
order
to
meet
and
engage
with
workers.718
Certain
intellectuals
had
hoped
to
find
what
can
be
described
as
an
authentic
working
class
culture
uncorrupted
and
uncontaminated
by
Marxist
theses.719
As
Tanke
explains,
The
Nights
of
Labor
began
for
Rancière
under
the
assumption
that
it
was
possible
to
trace
a
coherent
body
of
discourses
from
the
history
of
the
workers’
movement
into
the
present.720
Tanke
further
mentions
that
Rancière
has
explained
that
he
intended
to
“counterpose”
the
workers’
voice
to
the
voice
of
its
would-‐be
representatives.721
However,
he
was
forced
to
abandon
the
initial
lines
of
his
project
for
the
reason
that
he
quickly
came
to
the
conclusion
that
no
such
culture
or
coherent
workers’
voice
existed.
Instead,
he
encountered
a
strange
hybrid
culture
in
which
workers
refused
to
behave
as
workers.722
This
resulted
in
a
study
that
followed
the
lives
of
a
few
remarkable
voices
that
wrote
poetry
and
essays
in
defiance
of
the
partitioning
of
their
lives
as
workers.
Rancière
states:
I
set
out
to
find
primitive
revolutionary
manifestoes,
but
what
I
found
was
texts
which
demanded
in
refined
language
that
workers
be
considered
as
equals
and
their
arguments
responded
to
with
proper
arguments.723
Tanke
elucidates:
717
As above.
718
Tanke J (2011) 22-23.
719
As above.
720
As above.
721
As above.
722
As above.
723
Rancière J “Preface to the Hindi translation of Nights of Labor” as referenced in Tanke J
(2011) 23 & 166.
139
Workers
did
not
simply
struggle,
as
a
certain
line
of
thought
would
expect,
nor
did
they
valorise
the
trades
they
were
compelled
to
adopt
out
of
economic
necessity;
they
founded
journals,
composed
poetry,
and
imitated
“bourgeois”
forms
of
aesthetic
contemplation.724
For
Rancière,
this
discovery
demanded
that
he
abandon
the
epistemology
of
Marxist
historiography:
In
many
cases,
we
have
a
tendency
to
interpret
as
collective
practice
or
class
“ethos”
political
statements
which
are
in
fact
highly
individualised.
We
attach
too
much
importance
to
the
collectivity
of
workers
and
not
enough
to
its
divisions;
we
look
too
much
at
worker
culture
and
not
enough
at
its
encounters
with
other
cultures.725
The
Nights
of
Labor
relays
the
tale
of
workers
in
the
aftermath
of
the
July
Revolution
of
1830
and
follows
their
traces
of
revolt
up
to
1848.
Their
story
is
weaved
with
poems,
stories
and
essays
published
in
various
journals.726
The
book
describes
the
personal
significance
and
meaning
that
these
associations
and
publications
had
for
many
workers.
As
Tanke
explains,
on
Rancière’s
telling,
it
was
precisely
the
speculative
dimension
of
these
publications
that
was
of
the
greatest
appeal
and
Rancière
makes
a
long
argument
against
the
discursive-‐practical
form
the
workers’
movement
assumed
in
the
second
half
of
the
nineteenth
century.727
Rancière’s
narrative,
at
that
time,
challenged
many
leftist
notions
about
the
supposed
dignity
of
labour.
He
demonstrated
that
workers,
rather
than
finding
manual
work
a
source
of
pride,
described
it
as
torment.728
However,
they
used
their
nights
[n]ot
to
simply
replenish
the
machines
that
would
report
to
work
the
next
morning;
they
engaged
in
creative
and
scholarly
pursuits.729
Rancière
insists
that
these
types
of
activities
can
hardly
be
seen
as
laying
the
foundations
for
the
European
workers’
movement.730
Far
from
affirming
anything
724
Tanke J (2011) 23.
725
Rancière J “The myth of the artisan: Critical reflections on a category of social history”
International Labor and Working-Class History (1983) 10.
726
Such the Christian Socialist journal L’Atelier and the various publications founded by
Fourierites, Saint Simonians and Icarians, most notably La Ruche populaire. See Tanke J
(2011) 24.
727
Tanke J (2011) 25.
728
As above.
729
As above.
140
like
a
proletarian
identity,
Tanke
explains
that
these
writings
and
the
very
activity
of
writing
itself,
was
a
means
of
refuting
what
is
taken
to
be
natural,
namely,
that
workers
have
little
time
for
anything
else.731
Their
activities
were,
in
the
Rancièrian
sense,
a
means
of
“disidentification”
from
police
order
identities.
These
activities
allowed
them
to
reject
their
assigned
positions
in
the
division
of
labour
through
the
assumption
of
capacities
they
were
not
thought
to
possess.
Further,
as
Tanke
explains,
Rancière,
instead
of
contending
to
know
in
advance
the
nature
of
the
object
of
his
study,
refuses
in
The
Nights
of
Labor
to
categorise
the
texts
composed
by
these
workers.732
He
therefore
deliberately
avoids
representing
their
voices,
allowing
the
workers’
texts
to
circulate
on
their
own,
without
correcting,
classifying
or
explaining
them.733
What
is
demonstrated
is
that
the
workers
engaged
in
political
discussions
and
speculations
about
alternative
social
conditions.734
They
challenged
their
economic
subordination
and
exclusion
from
political
life.
Tanke
explains
that
the
workers
also
immersed
themselves
in
complicated
aesthetic
forms.735
They
organised
readings,
composed
poems,
commented
upon
the
works
of
others
and
adopted
a
generalised
outlook.736
These
interests
demonstrate
the
myth
of
restricting
aesthetic
pursuits
to
the
leisure
classes:
These
activities
were,
in
a
very
real
sense,
a
struggle
over
the
delimitation
of
the
economy
of
pleasures.737
Rancière
states:
I
assumed
that
those
narratives
were
much
more
than
descriptions
of
everyday
experience.
They
reinvented
the
everyday.738
730
As above.
731
As above.
732
As above.
733
As above.
734
The Nights of Labor takes us through “poems composed by metal workers, letters written
by builders who dream of being artists, interior decorators which aspire to a bourgeois
aesthetics and newspapers written by carpenters in which they represent their work to
themselves and respond to the images of work by others”. See Pelletier C “Rancière and the
poetics of the social sciences” International Journal of Research and Method in Education
(2009) 242-243.
735
Tanke J (2011) 25.
736
As above.
737
As above.
738
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 274.
141
Rancière
took
particular
interest
in
a
man
named
Gabriel
Gauny.
Gabriel
Gauny
was
a
joiner
who
left
the
archives
of
his
intellectual
life.739
From
the
1830’s
to
the
1880’s
he
wrote
an
impressive
number
of
texts,
most
of
which
remains
unpublished.740
Rancière
focuses
on
a
specific
essay.
It
relates
to
Gauny’s
workday
as
a
floor
layer.
It
was
one
of
the
essays
published
in
one
of
the
numerous
newspapers
that
blossomed
during
the
French
revolution
of
1848.
It
came
out
as
a
contribution
to
a
collective
political
affirmation.
However,
Rancière,
instead
of
taking
on
the
“collective
meaning
in
a
revolutionary
context”,
emphasises
passages
that
focuses
on
“the
joiner’s
individual
experience
and
his
personal
appropriation
of
the
power
of
writing”.741
For
Rancière,
Gauny
embodied
a
distinct
form
of
aesthetic
political
action.742
He
laid
floors
in
bourgeois
interiors.
However,
he
was
also
“composing
a
system
of
principles
designed
to
convert
his
modest
resources
into
the
maximum
quotient
of
freedom”.743
Tanke
explains
that
Gauny
had
a
special
knack
for
disassociating
his
mind
from
the
torments
the
body
endured
on
the
job.744
Through
his
imagination
he
would
transport
himself
into
a
realm
of
contentment.745
Gauny
describes
the
labourer’s
aesthetic
attitude
in
a
specific
way,
thereby
redistributing
the
particular
distribution
of
the
sensible.
He
shifted
his
gaze
outside
of
the
space
and
time
of
work.746
Rancière
highlights
the
following
passage
by
Gauny:
Believing
himself
at
home,
he
loves
the
arrangement
of
a
room,
so
long
as
he
has
not
finished
laying
the
floor.
If
the
window
opens
out
on
a
garden
or
commands
a
view
of
a
picturesque
horizon,
he
stops
his
arms
and
glides
in
imagination
toward
the
spacious
view
to
enjoy
it
better
than
the
possessors
of
the
neighbouring
residences.747
739
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 273.
740
As above.
741
As above.
742
Tanke J (2011) 26.
743
As above.
744
As above.
745
As above.
746
As above.
747
As above. See Gabriel Gauny Le Philosophe plebeian 45-46. This passage is frequently
employed by Rancière in order to demonstrate the nature of aesthetics and its ability to free
bodies from specific distributions of the sensible.
142
Rancière
reads
in
this
passage
an
exceptional
aesthetic-‐political
performance.
He
states
the
following
and
I
quote
him
at
length:
The
tiny
shift
that
I
perceived
in
the
little
narrative
of
the
joiner,
and
that
I
decided
to
develop
as
a
large
theoretical
and
political
shift,
consists
in
stripping
the
argument,
in
order
to
set
forth
its
core.
The
schema
of
knowledge
and
ignorance,
reality
and
illusion,
actually
covers
up
a
mere
tautology:
people
are
where
they
are
because
they
are
where
they
are,
because
they
are
incapable
of
being
elsewhere.
This
matter
of
incapacity
must
be
stripped
of
its
“scientific”
disguise.
People
are
not
unable
because
they
ignore
the
reason
for
being
there.
They
are
unable
because
unable
means
the
same
thing
as
being
there.
The
point
is
that
those
who
have
the
occupation
of
workers
are
supposed
to
be
equipped
for
that
occupation
and
for
the
activities
that
are
related
to
it.
They
are
supposed
to
be
equipped
for
working,
not
for
peripheral
activities
such
as
looking
around
and
investigating
how
society
at
large
works.
This
is
what
a
distribution
of
the
sensible
means:
a
relation
between
occupation
and
equipment,
between
being
in
a
space
and
time,
performing
specific
activities,
and
being
endowed
with
capacities
of
seeing,
saying,
and
doing
that
“fit”
those
activities.
A
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
a
matrix
that
defines
a
set
of
relations
between
sense
and
sense:
that
is,
between
a
form
of
sensory
experience
and
an
interpretation
which
makes
sense
of
it.
It
ties
and
occupation
to
a
presupposition.748
In
the
section
from
which
the
above
quote
is
taken,
Rancière
refers
to
Plato
and
to
the
so-‐called
reasons
why
workers
must
stay
in
their
place.749
The
first
reason
is
that
workers
have
no
time
to
go
elsewhere,
because
of
the
empirical
fact
that
work
does
not
wait.
And
Rancière
indeed
regards
this
as
an
empirical
fact.750
The
second
is
that
God
mixed
iron
in
the
makeup
of
workers
and
he
mixed
gold
in
the
makeup
of
those
who
are
destined
to
deal
with
the
common
good.
The
second
reason,
of
course,
is
not
an
empirical
fact.
The
second
reason
provides
the
logos
that
“sustain
the
empirical
state
of
things
by
identifying
the
place
where
work
does
not
wait
with
the
place
where
universal
thinking
is
expected
to
stay,
the
place
of
the
particular”.751
The
inequality
of
the
social
ordering
has
to
rest
on
an
inequality
in
terms
of
nature.
This
is
what
Ranciere
says
the
logos
provide.752
But
importantly;
it
provides
it
in
the
guise
of
a
myth,
of
a
lie
about
what
“fitting”
748
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 275.
749
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 275-276.
750
As above.
751
As above.
752
As above.
143
means-‐
the
story
of
the
deity
who
mixes
gold,
silver
or
iron
in
souls.753
The
logos
is
therefore
a
mythos.
The
argument
is
a
story
and
the
story
an
argument:
“The
social
distribution
rests
on
the
circle
of
the
empirical
and
the
prescriptive”.754
The
reason
for
inequality
has
to
be
given
in
the
guise
of
a
story,
but
a
story
is
the
most
egalitarian
form
of
discourse.
Rancière
states
that
“it
makes
of
the
philosopher
the
brother
of
the
children
who
enjoy
stories
and
of
the
old
women
or
the
old
slaves
who
tell
them
stories”.755
Here,
Rancière
is
highlighting
the
contradiction
that
opens
up
the
possibility
of
the
affirmation
of
equality.
The
inequality
of
the
workers
has
to
be
explained
to
them
through
a
story,
which
they
understand
just
as
well
as
those
who
are
telling
the
story.
The
very
means,
by
which
their
inequality
is
established,
requires
the
equal
intellectual
capacity
to
understand
the
story.
Or
put
in
Rancière’s
political
terms,
in
order
to
obey
an
order,
you
must
understand
it,
making
you
equal
to
the
one
that
is
ordering
you.
Rancière
tells
us
that
[t]he
logos
must
be
represented
as
a
story.
And
the
story,
Plato
says,
has
to
be
believed.
In
order
to
understand
what
is
at
stake
in
the
“belief”
of
our
joiner,
we
have
to
define
what
it
means
to
believe.
Obviously,
Plato
does
not
demand
that
workers
have
the
inner
conviction
that
a
deity
truly
mixed
iron
in
their
soul
and
gold
in
the
soul
of
the
rulers.
It
is
enough
that
they
sense
it:
that
is,
that
they
use
their
arms,
their
eyes,
and
their
minds
as
if
it
were
true”.756
For
Rancière,
the
ordering
of
social
occupations
and
orderings
functions
within
this
“as
if”,
which
ties
it
to
a
belief.757
Inequality
in
this
setting
works
out
to
the
extent
that
one
believes
it-‐
“[b]ut
that
belief
can
be
conveyed
only
in
the
egalitarian
mode
of
the
story”.758
For
Rancière,
in
the
construction
and
the
writing
of
his
sensory
experience,
Gauny
implements
a
different
“as
if”;
and
this
“as
if”
overturns
the
whole
logic
which
753
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 276.
754
As above.
755
As above.
756
As above
757
As above.
758
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 277.
144
allotted
him
his
place.
However,
this
overturning
is
not
the
idea
of
the
freeing
power
of
awareness
of
his
domination.
The
jobber
frees
himself
by
becoming
less
aware
of
his
exploitation,
pushing
aside
its
sensory
grip.
He
therefore
frees
himself
by
nurturing
the
power
of
self-‐delusion.
As
Rancière
acknowledges,
Gauny
still
works,
he
still
works
for
the
benefit
of
others
against
his
own
employment
and
his
health:
But
this
counter
effect,
which
results
from
his
way
of
reframing
the
space
and
time
of
exercise
of
his
force
of
labour,
is
the
source
of
a
new
pleasure,
the
pleasure
of
a
new
freedom.759
Rancière
explains
it
in
the
following
way
and
I
quote
him
at
length:
The
objection
has
it
that,
whatever
our
joiner
may
believe
as
he
looks
through
the
window;
the
room
remain
the
possession
of
its
owner
and
his
force
of
labour
the
possession
of
his
boss.
The
equal
and
disinterested
pleasure
of
the
gaze
is
just
as
delusive
as
the
promises
of
equality
written
in
the
Declaration
of
Rights.
Both
are
expressions
of
false
equality
that
delude
him
and
block
the
way
that
leads
to
true
equality.
I
answer
that
the
claim
of
“true”
equality
dismisses
the
reality
of
the
operations
of
the
verification
of
equality.
It
dismisses
it
at
the
same
time
that
it
grasps
the
struggle
over
the
as
if
in
the
pincers
of
appearance
and
reality.
Appearance
and
reality
are
not
opposed.
A
reality
always
goes
along
with
an
appearance.
For
sure,
the
joiner
remains
in
the
world
of
domination
and
exploitation.
But
he
is
able
to
split
up
the
tautology
of
the
being-‐there.
He
is
able
to
locate
his
ownership
in
the
ownership
of
the
master
and
the
owner.
He
actually
builds
up
a
new
sensible
world
in
the
given
one.
A
verification
of
equality
is
an
operation
which
grabs
hold
of
the
knot
that
ties
equality
to
inequality.
It
handles
the
knot
so
as
to
tip
the
balance,
to
enforce
the
presupposition
of
equality
tied
up
with
the
presupposition
of
inequality
and
increase
its
power.
For
instance,
the
perspective
gaze,
that
has
been
long
associated
with
mastery
and
majesty,
can
be
assumed
and
verified
as
a
power
of
equality.
That
verification
contributes,
thus,
to
the
framing
of
a
new
fabric
of
common
experience
or
a
new
common
sense,
upon
which
new
forms
of
political
subjectivation
can
be
implemented.760
For
Rancière,
Gauny’s
demonstration
of
equality
is
what
is
meant
by
the
word,
emancipation.
It
is
a
subversion
of
a
given
distribution
of
the
sensible.
What
is
759
As above.
760
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 280. It is important to note here that Gauny
does not engage in politics proper as described in Rancière’s mature politics. He is not
involved in a collective affirmation of equality in the way in which Rancière describes politics.
That is why Rancière uses the words “upon which new forms of political subjectivation can be
implemented”; meaning that Gauny’s example is a redistributing of sensible time and place
from where politics can be established.
145
overturned
is
the
relationship
between
what
is
done
by
one’s
arms,
what
is
looked
at
by
one’s
eyes,
what
is
felt
as
sensory
pleasure
and
what
is
thought
of
as
intellectual
concern:
It
is
the
relationship
between
an
occupation,
the
space-‐time
where
it
is
fulfilled,
and
the
sensory
equipment
for
doing
it.
The
subversion
implies
the
reframing
of
a
common
sense.
A
common
sense
does
not
mean
consensus
but,
on
the
contrary,
a
polemical
place,
a
confrontation
between
opposite
common
senses
or
opposite
ways
of
framing
what
is
common.761
This
is
what
the
relationship
between
aesthetics
and
politics
means:
“Politics
is
a
polemical
form
of
reframing
of
common
sense”.762
And
in
that
sense,
it
is
an
aesthetic
affair.
In
this
context
Tanke
mentions
that
one
virtue
of
the
aesthetic
is
that
it
conducts
one
into
an
indeterminate
zone
where
the
destiny
of
class
is
thrown
off.763
It
neutralises
the
properties
thought
to
inhere
in
a
body;
transporting
it
into
a
world
where
the
distributions
of
places,
times
and
capacities
are
not
permanently
fixed.764
It
allows
sense
to
be
separated
from
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
The
platonic
assertion
that
“work
does
not
wait”
amounts
to
locking
up
workers
in
the
space
of
their
absence
of
time.765
And
the
experience
of
emancipation
consists
in
“locating
another
time
in
that
time,
another
space
in
that
space”.
766
Kristin
Ross
mentions
that
The
Nights
of
Labor
drew
attention
to
a
very
powerful
act
of
stealing
time.
She
explains
that
Rancière’s
study
relocated
workers
into
another
kind
of
time,
outside
the
temporal
regime
established
by
Marx.767
Rancière
demonstrated
that
Marx’s
workdays
were
actually
exceeded
by
nights
and
all
its
possibilities.768
Ross
notes
that
what
becomes
clear
is
that
Marx’s
own
perspective
(as
Rancière
also
puts
forth
in
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor)
was
closely
aligned,
not
to
that
of
the
worker,
but
rather
to
that
of
capital-‐
the
761
As above.
762
As above.
763
Tanke J (2011) 34.
764
As above.
765
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 282.
766
As above.
767
Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 23.
768
As above.
146
perspective
of
“the
production
of
surplus
value”.769
Gauny
does
not
fit
comfortably
in
the
framework
of
the
worker,
neither
Plato
nor
Marx’s.
He
rather
asserts
his
rights
to
the
imagination
against
temperance
and
beyond
the
context
of
proletarian
recruiters.770
Gauny
and
the
other
workers
used
their
Nights
to
engage
in
a
different
kind
of
labour,
the
labour
of
writing.
Tanke
eloquently
states:
Writing
for
them,
was
part
of
a
politics
of
world
opening.
It
was
not
simply
a
vehicle
for
giving
voice
to
their
grievances;
the
activity
itself
was
a
means
of
removing
themselves
from
a
sensible
order
in
which
they
had
little
part.
It
enabled
them
to
create
capacities,
and
there
with
the
new
space-‐time
configuration
in
which
to
attest
their
equality.771
According
to
Tanke,
the
act
of
writing
is
a
symbolic
and
practical
rupture
that
effaces
the
barriers
thought
to
exist
between
those
granted
the
luxury
of
thought
and
those
thought
to
be
held
captive
by
the
space-‐time
of
their
employment.772
Their
pleasure
of
writing
was
not
a
retreat
from
politics:
Theses
hard-‐won
bonuses
of
time
and
liberty
were
not
marginal
phenomena,
they
were
not
diversions
from
the
building
of
the
worker
movement
and
its
great
ideals.
They
were
a
revolution,
discreet
but
radical
nonetheless.773
The
aesthetic
attitudes
that
these
workers
assumed,
whether
in
writing
or
contemplating
a
view,
allows
them
to
move
away
from
their
habitual
identities-‐
the
identities
prescribed
by
police
order
categories
and
associations.774
Rancière
explains
how
the
identity
of
“worker”
became
something
very
different
in
the
construction
of
the
worker
poets:
For
a
long
time,
I
looked
for
a
“proper”
worker
[…]
in
the
corporatisation
of
crafts/cultures/forms
of
originary
identities.
This
did
not
work.
It
was
impossible
to
see
working
class
speech
constructing
itself
from
a
proper
body
emerging
from
its
proper
location.
What
instead
manifested
itself
was
a
speech
sought
to
drag
itself
away
from
these
incarnations,
no
longer
to
769
As above.
770
As above.
771
Tanke J (2011) 64-65.
772
As above.
773
Tanke J (2011) 64-65.
774
Tanke J (2011) 67.
147
speak
like
a
worker
but
to
subjectivise
itself
under
the
name
of
the
worker
in
the
space
of
common
speech.775
The
worker
poets
rejected
the
identities
that
were
stamped
on
their
bodies,
the
assumptions
made
about
their
capacities
and
the
“spatio-‐temporal
locales”
which
they
are
forced
to
occupy.776
Gauny,
in
a
very
real
sense,
was
not
waiting
for
some
point
in
the
future
to
take
for
himself
the
leisure
of
philosophical
contemplation.
He
did
not
wait
for
some
or
other
revolution
or
change.
Rather,
he
embodies
in
the
here
and
now
the
possibility
of
a
radical
reconfiguration
of
speech.
3.4
Conclusion
It
becomes
clear
that
the
figure
of
Joseph
Jacocot
allowed
Rancière
to
glean
a
specific
type
of
formulation
of
equality
that
he
would
later
articulate
within
his
mature
politics.
His
engagements
with
the
figure
of
Jacocot
opened
up
a
way
of
thinking
about
equality
as
a
destabilising
force.
The
lessons
of
education
and
universal
teaching
served
as
a
means
from
where
to
conceptualise
the
political
potency
of
equality
declared
and
axiomatically
assumed.
The
notion
of
radical
intellectual
equality
leaves
us
speculating
about
what
can
be
done
under
the
presupposition
of
equality.
In
a
very
real
way,
Jacocot’s
arguments
also
invokes
a
political
opportunity:
Essentially
what
an
emancipated
person
can
do
is
to
be
an
emancipator:
to
give,
not
the
key
to
knowledge,
but
the
consciousness
of
what
an
intelligence
can
do
when
it
considers
itself
equal
to
any
other
and
considers
any
other
equal
to
itself.777
Against
institutional
and
political
power,
equality
postulates
the
freedoms
of
invention,
poetry
and
thought.
We
see
the
same
type
of
invention
within
Rancière’s
politics-‐
the
invention
of
names
for
a
“we”,
the
construction
of
the
language
within
which
arguments
can
be
understood,
the
creation
of
worlds
and
scenes
of
dissensus.
Politics
is
about
new
words,
new
meanings
and
new
formulations
made
by
new
figures,
or
figures
previously
denied
the
capacity
for
775
Rancière J (2005) referenced in Pelletier C International Journal of Research and Method in
Education (2009) 242-243.
776
Tanke J (2011) 67.
777
Rancière J (1991) 39.
148
voice.
For
Rancière,
declarations
of
equality
hold
open
the
possibility
for
true
political
intervention
and
for
radical
redistribution
of
the
sensible.
Equality’s
function
is
to
reopen
the
space
for
politics,
for
contestation
and
redistribution.
In
Rancière’s
engagements
with
Jacocot
and
Gauny,
he
constantly
undermines
the
notion
that
some
can
think
and
think
better
than
others.
He
insists
on
displacing
distinctions
that
determine
who
can
think
and
speak,
who
can
impart
knowledge
and
who
has
time
for
philosophical
leisure.
When
these
distinctions
are
displaced,
possibilities
for
voice
are
created.
He
affirms,
over
and
over
again,
his
aversion
to
predestined
spaces,
places,
times
and
identities.
For
Rancière,
Gauny
becomes
a
figure
that
redistributes
the
sensible.
His
redistribution
involves
a
politics
of
new
forms
of
innovation
that
tears
bodies
and
voices
from
their
police
order
assigned
places,
thereby
freeing
up
time,
speech
and
expression;
acting
as
if
and
demonstrating
the
lessons
of
equality.
For
Rancière:
Such
lessons
can
be
found
everywhere.
It
is
possible
to
find
everywhere
new
examples
of
the
disjunctive
junction
between
being-‐there
and
the
reason
for
being-‐there.
It
is
possible
to
disentangle
in
every
case
the
“as
if”
which
is
involved
in
the
“that’s
the
way
it
is”.
From
this
point
on,
it
is
possible
to
imagine
a
method
of
equality
specifically
aimed
at
detecting
and
highlighting
the
operations
of
equality
that
may
occur
everywhere
at
every
time.778
Therefore,
for
Rancière,
equality
is
in
gestation
around
us
all
the
time
and
equality
makes
it
possible
to
redistribute
spatio-‐temporal
locales
and
identities;
equality
can
introduce
new
voices
into
the
sensible
mix.
It
was
mentioned
in
the
introduction
of
this
chapter
that
a
further
aim
of
the
chapter
is
to
suggest
ways
in
which
to
engage
with
and
write
about
the
notion
of
political
voice.
As
mentioned,
the
question
that
arises
for
me
is,
when
making
sense
of
the
notion
of
political
voice,
how
are
we
to
approach
and
think
about
voice?
When
reflecting
on
ways
in
which
to
think
through
voice
within
the
context
of
a
Rancièrian
politics
and
against
the
background
of
the
disconnect
or
difficulties
of
voice
of
many
South
African
women,
two
important
points
should
be
mentioned:
Firstly,
I
would
like
to
highlight
Rancière’s
choice
of
historical
778
Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 280-281.
149
figures
as
a
way
of
expanding
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
As
Ross
explains,
Rancière
chooses
marginal
characters
often
drawn
from
the
most
obscure
historical
archives.779
The
particular
actions
and
points
of
view
of
these
marginal
individuals,
when
reframed
and
restaged,
are
mobilised
by
Rancière
against
the
dominant
categories
and
lines
of
thought.780
These
readings
can,
along
the
lines
of
the
redistribution
of
the
sensible,
renegotiate
and
expand
perception
and
reconfigure
what
is
thinkable.
It
is
important
to
mention
that
from
a
Rancièrian
point
of
view,
these
individuals
are
not
used
as
spokespersons
or
sociological
representatives,
but
are
nevertheless
mobilised
to
serve
as
a
“diagnostic
of
the
contemporary
situation”.781
Each
person
retains
his
or
her
individual
singularity
and
historical
contingency.
Ross
further
mentions
that
Rancière
writes
against
generalisations,
systems
and
at
times
even
against
concepts.782
His
concern
is
first
and
foremost
with
what
specific
historical
actors
have
said
and
written
in
contingent
and
contextual
situations.783
Ross
further
highlights
the
fact
that
his
historical
figures
are
framed
like
literary
characters
in
order
to
refute
various
myths
and
ideologies.784
The
important
point
in
this
regard
is
that
writing
itself
becomes
a
way
of
politically
expanding
perception.
Rancière
has
termed
this
“literarity”,
which
refers
to
writing’s
ability
to
disrupt
the
organisation
of
society.785
Rancière
states:
The
democracy
of
writing
is
the
regimes
of
the
letter
which
is
free
for
anyone
to
take
up
for
themselves,
whether
to
make
their
own
the
life
of
779
Ross K “Historicizing Untimeliness” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 24-25.
780
As above. Further, the discussion of these characters also becomes important in order to
demonstrate Rancière’s method of engagement in a more general sense. As mentioned,
what is significant is the way in which he mobilises these historical figures so as to create
spaces for the implementation of equality within his writing. To an extent I employ the same
method of engagement in chapter 5. It is a method of equality that works between
disciplines, which I will elaborate on in the introduction of chapter 5.
781
As above.
782
As above.
783
As above. As mentioned, Ross explains that Rancière also offers a “peculiar and powerful
version of transdisciplinarity” (Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 24-25). His response
to fixed knowledges is not to combine different knowledges, but rather to use one to
undermine or contest another. In an effort to redistribute the sensible distribution of
discipline, he uses history against philosophy or literature against political theory for example.
See Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 24-25.
784
Ross K in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 24-25.
785
See Davis O (2010) 107-115.
150
heroes
or
heroines
of
a
novel,
or
to
become
a
writer,
or
as
a
way
of
joining
in
the
discussion
about
affairs
of
common
concern.
This
is
not
a
matter
of
irresistible
social
influence,
but
rather
of
a
new
division
of
the
sensory,
of
a
new
relationship
between
the
speech
act,
the
world
it
configures
and
the
capacities
of
those
who
inhabit
that
world.786
Therefore,
when
it
comes
to
making
sense
of
the
notion
of
voice,
the
way
in
which
we
approach
political
voice
and
write
about
political
voice
becomes
important
considerations
as
these
engagements
itself
form
part
of
a
topography
of
the
visible
and
sayable.
These
engagements
can
form
new
relations
between
the
visible
and
invisible,
audible
and
inaudible
and
voice
and
silence.
The
distribution
of
the
sensible
is
itself
a
regime
of
presentation
tied
to
a
specific
interpretation
and
as
such
the
interpretation
of
events
and
their
meaning
either
confirms
the
consensual
distribution
or
form
new
dissenting
interpretations
of
meaning.
Secondly,
the
engagements
above
highlight
what
can
be
described
as
the
fragility
and
difficulty
involved
when
it
comes
to
thinking
about
politics
and
political
voicing.
Rancière’s
project
around
Gabriel
Gauny
demonstrated
this.
He
started
with
the
assumption
that
it
was
possible
to
trace
a
coherent
political
worker’s
voice.
As
mentioned,
he
soon
abandoned
this
assumption,
as
what
he
found
was
voices
that
could
not
easily
fit
into
any
identifiable
category
of
worker.
Making
sense
of
voice
through
Rancière’s
framework
against
the
background
of
the
difficulties
and
complexities
surrounding
voicing
as
it
pertains
to
many
South
African
women
therefore
points
to
a
way
of
thinking
about
political
voice
that
doesn’t
seek
to
coherently
partition
highly
individualised
political
statements
or
moments
of
voicing.
Rancière
highlights
the
fact
that
political
voice
cannot
emerge
from
a
proper
body
in
its
proper
location,
tied
to
specific
forms
of
speech.
It
therefore
doesn’t
point
to
any
type
of
analysis
or
way
of
thinking
about
voice
that
seeks
to
trace
it
along
the
lines
of
established
categories.
The
suggestion
is
rather
a
rethinking
and
displacing
of
established
distinctions.
Joseph
Jacocot
and
Gabriel
Gauny
as
well
as
the
other
worker
poets
embody
for
Rancière
the
786
Rancière J Politique de la littérature (2007) 21-22 trans. Davis O (2010) 112.
151
transgression
of
boundaries
and
the
recasting
of
habitual
identities.
They
point
to
dissensus
and
to
vigilance
when
it
comes
to
the
openings
of
equality.
What
becomes
central
in
Rancière’s
engagement
with
Jacocot
is
that
equality
as
a
point
of
departure
creates
a
place
from
where
to
think
about
voice.
What
therefore
becomes
valuable
in
the
discussion
with
regards
to
Jacocot
is
the
question
that
he
opens
up
and
invites
us
to
contemplate,
namely,
what
can
be
done
under
the
presupposition
of
equality,
radically
declared?
Equality,
rather
than
affirming
occupations,
identities
and
coherent
orderings,
provides
a
space
from
where
new
forms
of
political
subjectivation
can
be
established.787
Thus,
when
making
sense
of
the
notion
of
voice,
Rancière’s
formulations
points
to
the
fact
that
the
way
in
which
we
approach
and
write
about
political
voicing,
is
itself
political
practice:
Democracy
is
first
of
all
the
invention
of
words,
words
with
which
those
who
do
not
count
make
themselves
count
and,
in
so
doing,
confuse
the
ordered
division
between
speech
in
silence
[…]788
787
See Rancière J in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 280.
788
Rancière J Politique de la littérature (2007) 53 trans. Davis O (2010) 114.
152
CHAPTER
4
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak:
“The
Subaltern
Cannot
Speak”
4.1
Introduction
As
mentioned
in
the
introductory
chapter,
the
main
aim
of
the
research
is
an
effort
to
understand
the
notion
of
political
voice.
In
the
previous
chapters,
I
explained
and
shed
light
on
Rancière’s
notion
of
politics
and
reflected
on
what
lines
of
thinking
for
political
voice
and
ways
of
approaching
political
voice
are
opened
up
by
his
work.
In
this
chapter
I
discuss
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”789
In
this
highly
influential
essay,
Spivak
engages
with
the
notion
of
political
speech.
As
will
be
explained,
her
focus
in
the
essay
is
mainly
on
the
possibility
of
the
political
voice
of
women
within
post-‐colonial
settings.
As
my
reflections
on
voice
take
place
against
the
background
of
the
precariousness
and
complexity
of
the
political
voice
of
many
South
African
women,
it
can
be
argued
that
engagement
with
Spivak’s
essay
becomes
necessary;
firstly,
because
of
the
fact
that
Spivak
rejects
the
possibility
of
the
political
voice
of
women
within
certain
conditions
and
secondly,
because
of
the
fact
that
the
essay
revolves
around
the
conditions
that
efface
the
voices
of
women
within
the
global
South.
As
will
become
clearer
in
the
discussion
below,
Spivak
answers
the
question
that
she
poses
in
the
title
of
her
essay
in
the
negative
and
she
attempts
to
trace
the
causes
of
the
economic
impoverishment
of
rural-‐based
women
of
colour
within
this
setting.
As
such,
her
analysis
becomes
relevant
to
the
plight
of
women,
especially
the
plight
of
economically
marginalised
black
women
within
the
post-‐
apartheid
South
African
context.790
Below,
I
introduce
Spivak
and
in
the
second
section
I
explain
the
main
arguments
formulated
in
her
well-‐known
essay.
From
there,
I
critically
reflect
on
her
essay
through
the
lens
of
the
politics
of
Jacques
789
Spivak S in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 271-313.
790
The consequences of Apartheid (as a system that strategically impoverished and politically
disempowered the black majority of the country) and highly traditional and patriarchal
cultures result in black women being the poorest of the poor. This is especially true for rural-
based women that have limited political agency and access to education and healthcare. See
for example Ruiters G (ed.) (2008).
153
Rancière.
The
aim
is
therefore
to
highlight
her
main
concerns
and
to
read
them
along
the
lines
of
Rancière’s
work
so
as
to
further
make
sense
of
and
contemplate
the
notion
of
political
voice.
The
aim
is
to
see
whether
Rancière’s
work
can
provide
different
possibilities
or
lines
of
thinking
when
it
comes
to
the
idea
of
subaltern
silencing.
To
what
extent
can
his
work
frame
Spivak’s
question
in
a
different
way,
or,
does
his
work
identify
moments
within
which
the
subaltern
can
speak?
Before
explaining
Spivak’s
main
essay,
I
shortly
introduce
her
in
order
to
contextualise
her
essay.
Spivak
has
been
described
as
an
unsettling
voice
in
literary
theory
and,
especially,
in
post-‐colonial
studies.791
Her
work
is
influenced
by
Marxism,
feminism
and
deconstruction
and
she
is
known
for
her
passionate
analyses
of
the
harm
done
to
women,
non-‐Europeans
and
the
poor
by
the
privileged
West.792
Spivak
also
persistently
questions
the
very
grounds
on
which
radical
critique
is
formulated.793
Morton
explains
that
Spivak’s
work
is
characterised
by
an
ongoing
attempt
to
find
a
critical
vocabulary
that
is
appropriate
to
describe
the
experiences,
voices
and
histories
of
individuals
historically
dispossessed
and
exploited
by
European
colonialism.794
As
Morton
further
highlights,
Spivak’s
consistent
focus
on
women,
the
working
class,
new
immigrants
and
post-‐colonial
subjects
has
led
her
to
791
Leitch VB, Cain WE et al (eds.) The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism (2010) 2193.
792
As above.
793
As above. As will be discussed below, Spivak criticises Gilles Deleuze and Michel Foucault
in her essay. In the context of feminism, Spivak has criticised western feminist thought for not
taking the lives and histories of “third world” women seriously in its account women’s
struggles against oppression. Spivak also challenged the universal claims of feminism to
speak for all women during the 1980’s, emphasising the importance of differences in race,
class, religion, citizenship and culture between women. See Morton S Routledge Critical
Thinkers: Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (2003) 75.
794
Morton S (2003) 45. Spivak often specifically focuses her attention on India in this regard.
Morton explains that Spivak’s literary criticism has greatly informed and influenced the
practice of reading literary texts in relation to the history of colonialism. See Morton S (2003)
45. She repeatedly emphasises that the production and reception of nineteenth-century
English literature in postcolonial nations as bound up with imperialism. See for example
Spivak GC A Critique of Postcolonial Reason: Towards a History of the Vanishing Present
(1999).
154
challenge
some
of
the
dominant
ideas
of
our
contemporary
era,
specifically
the
notion
that
the
western
world
is
somehow
more
civilised,
democratic
and
developed
than
the
non-‐western
world;
and
that
the
post-‐colonial
era
is
more
modern
and
progressive
than
the
earlier
historical
period
of
European
colonialism.795
For
Spivak,
the
damaging
effects
of
and
harms
done
through
European
colonialism
still
remains
and
did
not
simply
subside
or
stop
when
many
former
European
colonies
achieved
independence
in
the
second
half
of
the
twentieth
century.796
She
suggests
that
the
political
and
economic
structures
and
mechanisms
that
were
established
during
colonialism
continue
to
determine
and
shape
cultural,
political
and
economic
life
in
post-‐colonial
nations.797
Further,
Spivak
also
emphasises
how
anti-‐colonial
nationalism,
specifically
in
India,
assumed
a
bourgeois
character
and
therefore
in
many
ways
only
reproduced
the
social
and
political
inequalities
that
dominated
under
colonial
rule.798
Landry
and
Maclean
describes
Spivak’s
work
as
“following
a
complex
intellectual
trajectory
through
a
deeply
feminist
perspective
on
deconstruction,
the
Marxist
critique
of
capitalism
and
the
international
division
of
labour,
the
critique
of
imperialism
and
colonial
discourse,
the
critique
of
race
in
relation
to
nationality,
ethnicity
and
the
status
of
the
migrant
and
the
question
of
what
it
means
to
identify
with
a
nation
or
a
cultural
form
as
a
postcolonial
subject
in
a
neo-‐colonial
795
Morton S (2003) 1.
796
As above.
797
Morton S (2003) 1-2. These nations range from Ireland to Algeria, from India to Pakistan to
Jamaica and Mexico. Morton explains how the British Empire’s policies on education in India
encouraged educated, middle-class Indian subjects to internalise the cultural values of the
British (Morton S (2003) 1-2). The teaching of British cultural values to the upper middle class
in India was intended to instruct and enlighten the Indian middle class in the morally and
politically superior culture of the British Empire. By using these practices, the British tried to
persuade the Indian middle-class that colonial rule was in their best interest. Morton S (2003)
1-2. The teaching of English literature in colonial India therefore provided an effective,
though insidious way of executing the so-called civilizing mission of western imperialism.
Morton S (2003) 1-2. Spivak’s literary criticism, as mentioned, has specifically worked to
undermine the ideological function of English literature in the colonial context. She has
contended, for example, that “it should not be possible to read nineteenth-century English
literature without remembering that imperialism, understood as England’s social mission, was
a crucial part of the cultural representation of England to the English”. See Spivak GC “Three
Women’s Texts and a Critique of Imperialism” Critical Inquiry (1985) 243.
798
Morton S (2003) 2.
155
world”.799
Her
trajectory
has
gained
her
a
relatively
heterogeneous
international
audience
and
in
the
context
of
feminism,
Spivak
is
recognised,
as
among
the
foremost
feminist
critics
that
has
achieved
international
prominence.800
According
to
Landry
and
Maclean
she
is
one
of
a
few
who
can
claim
to
have
influenced
intellectual
production
on
a
truly
global
scale.801
Spivak’s
earliest
important
work
was
her
introduction
to
and
translation
of
Jacques
Derrida’s
Of
Grammatology,
the
first
of
Derrida’s
major
books
to
be
rendered
in
full
into
English.802
She
therefore
played
a
significant
role
in
799
Landry D & Maclean G (eds.) (1996) 3.
800
As above.
801
As above. Morton explains that in the context of feminism, Spivak has, for example,
questioned the idea of a global sisterhood between women, rather pointing to the complicity
of western feminism and imperialism in the oppression of women of colour. Morton S (2003)
2-4. She therefore expanded and complicated the critical terms and political objectives of
feminism in a way that is more sensitive to differences between women. Morton explains that
her continual interrogation of assumptions can make her difficult to read. Morton S (2003) 2-4.
She represents her work in complex language and style in order to interrogate to common-
sense assumption that clear, transparent language is the best way to represent silenced and
oppressed groups and individuals. Morton S (2003) 2-4. Rather, she suggests that the
opposite is true. The transparent systems of representation through which things are known
and understood are also systems that dominate and control people. Morton further explains
that her thought therefore emphasises the limitations of linguistic and philosophical
representation and their potential to mask real political and social inequalities. Rather than
simply presenting her arguments in inaccessible prose, Spivak’s writing carefully links
“disparate histories, places and methodologies in ways that refuse to adhere to the
systematic conventions”. See Morton S (2003) 2-4. Morton further argues that such a refusal is
not merely a symptom of academic fashion, but a conscious strategy employed to engage
the reader in critical interrogation of how we make sense of and understand literary, social
and economic texts after colonialism. Further, Spivak believes that theoretical writings should
be complex and flexible enough to reveal the complex and contradictory nature of social
relations. Morton S (2003) 2-4.
802
See Derrida J Of Grammatology (1976) trans. Spivak GC. Along with Spivak’s professor
Paul de Man, Derrida was one of the most prominent advocates of deconstruction. Jacques
Derrida can be described as the principal theorist of deconstruction. In 1967, three of his
works that lay the foundations of deconstruction was published and these works (Of
Grammatology, Writing and Difference and Speech and Phenomena) pushed Derrida to the
forefront of the philosophical stage. Derrida’s deconstruction is a strategy of critical analysis
in dialogue with the history of western philosophy. See Morton S (2003) 27-28. Commentators
struggle to define deconstruction because of the fact that it cannot be reduced to a method,
or defined as a theory with a clear set of objectives. See Morton S (2003) 27-28. Nevertheless,
some key points can be identified. Norris defines it as “the vigilant seeking out of those
“aporias, blindspots or moments of self-contradiction where a text involuntarily betrays the
tension between rhetoric and logic, between what it manifestly means to say and what it is
156
introducing
French
theory
into
North
American
and
British
literature
departments
between
1975
and
1982.803
Besides
introducing
the
influential
French
thinker
to
English-‐speaking
audiences,
it
has
been
argued
that
Spivak’s
“Translator’s
Preface”
set
a
new
standard
for
self-‐reflexivity
in
prefaces
and
introductions.804
Landry
and
Maclean
explains
that
it
addressed,
from
every
considerable
angle,
“the
question
of
the
preface”
and
what
it
meant
to
translate
and
explicate
the
work
of
Derrida.805
After
introducing
Derrida
the
scholar,
she
explored
the
question
of
preface
as
a
form
of
writing
and
an
occasion
or
event
in
writing,
with
particular
protocols
to
be
observed,
which
is
one
of
the
characteristic
gestures
of
deconstruction.806
Indeed,
Spivak
was
and
remains
heavily
influenced
by
deconstruction.
Morton
notes
that
Derrida’s
deconstructive
strategies
have
been
particularly
useful
to
postcolonial
intellectuals
such
as
Spivak
because
these
strategies
provide
a
theoretical
vocabulary
and
a
critical
conceptual
framework
from
where
the
very
philosophical
tradition
that
has
also
explained
and
in
many
ways
justified
the
nonetheless constrained to mean”. See Norris C Derrida (1978) 19. Derrida argues for
example that the process of making meaning, or signification, is structured in terms of how
signs differ from other signs; a thing is defined in relation to what it is not. This notion is
derived from Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure. Derrida takes this notion a step further
and emphasises how meaning is also perpetually deferred across a spatial and temporal axis,
so that a final point of stable meaning and knowledge is never reached in any signifying
system. He uses the word “différance” to demonstrate that signs are never fully identical to
the things they refer to- signs are structurally incomplete from the beginning and they require
additional or supplementary terms to complete them. See Morton S (2003) 27-28. Morton
explains that meaning is therefore radically unstable and “the need for supplementation to
compensate for the lack of original self-identity reveals how all signs are by definition
incomplete and lacking in identity or self-presence”. See Morton S (2003) 27-28. In this way,
Derrida’s thought radically undermines the authority and centrality of the western humanist
subject. See Morton S (2003) 27-28. Derrida also emphasises that the repression, exclusion
and erasure of “impossible” concepts such as différance are the very conditions of possibility
which ground and constitute philosophical meaning and truth. See Morton S (2003) 27-28.
803
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193.
804
Landry and Maclean argues that Spivak’s preface set a new standard to the extent that the
preface and her translation of it are by now considered required reading for any serious
Derridean scholar. See Landry D & Maclean G (eds.) (1996) 1.
805
As above.
806
As above.
157
subjection
of
non-‐western
societies
can
be
interrogated.807
Spivak,
specifically,
has
followed
the
Jacques
Derrida’s
thought
carefully
and
has
in
this
way
continually
emphasised
the
potential
usefulness
of
Derrida’s
work
for
making
critical
interventions.808
In
this
regard,
she
has
highlighted
how
deconstruction’s
interest
in
the
violence
of
traditional
hierarchal
binary
oppositions
(between
male
and
female,
the
west
and
third
world
for
example)
has
afforded
a
passage
from
literary
theory
to
radical
politics.809
Leitch
et
al
explains
that
Spivak
has
enjoined
feminism’s
involvement
in
the
silencing
of
women
to
a
Marxist
global
concern
with
the
political,
economic
and
cultural
oppression
of
non-‐white
people.810
This
resulted
in
a
serious
of
highly
significant
and
acclaimed
essays
that
contributed
to
setting
the
agenda
for
feminism
and
post-‐colonial
theory
in
the
1980’s
and
1990’s.811
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
was
arguably
her
best-‐known
essay
and,
as
Leitch
et
al
argues,
certainly
her
most
controversial
that
originated
from
that
decade.812
In
this
essay,
Spivak
answers
the
question
that
she
poses
in
the
title
in
the
negative.
She
suggests
that
the
most
oppressed
and
politically
invisible
individuals
and
groups
in
society
cannot
speak,
meaning
that
they
cannot
be
heard
by
dominant
political
frameworks
and
within
dominant
discourses
of
political
representation.
In
the
section
below
I
examine
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”813
807
Morton S (2003) 27.
808
As above.
809
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193. It should be mentioned here that in the context of
deconstruction, writing does not only refer to printed matter on a page, but to any text-
visual, vocal, cinematic, historical, social or political. See Morton S (2003) 27-28. Text is made
meaningful by a system of signs or code. Spivak, by emphasising how intellectuals are part of
the larger social text that they describe, reiterates the political consequences of all reading
practices. The radical challenge of the truth claims of western philosophy moves from textual
analysis of literature or philosophy to include economic and political texts, “thereby
questioning the opposition between philosophical or literary texts and the so-called real
world.” See Morton S (2003) 27-28.
810
As above.
811
As above.
812
Her suggestion that the subaltern cannot speak created much controversy, as it was
initially misinterpreted to mean that certain groups do not have any political agency or voice.
As will be demonstrated, this was not Spivak’s argument in her essay and is indeed a
misinterpretation. See Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193.
813
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 271-313.
158
4.2
The
Sexed
Subaltern
In
order
to
explain
Spivak’s
main
concerns
in
her
essay,
it
is
important
to
define
and
trace
the
term
“subaltern”.
According
to
the
dictionary,
as
Leitch
et
al
explains,
the
term
refers
to
a
person
holding
a
subordinate
position.814
Conventionally,
the
term
refers
to
a
junior
ranking
officer
in
the
British
army.815
The
Italian
Marxist
theorist
Antonio
Gramsci
was
the
first
to
theoretically
apply
the
term.
He
used
the
term
in
order
to
describe
the
unorganised
masses
that
must
be
politicised
for
the
workers
revolution
to
succeed.816
Gramsci
used
the
term
interchangeably
with
“subordinate”
to
denote
“non-‐hegemonic
groups
or
classes”.817
His
focus
was
specifically
on
organised
groups
of
rural
peasants
that
were
based
in
Southern
Italy.
For
Gramsci,
as
Morton
explains,
these
groups
had
no
social
or
political
consciousness
as
a
group
and
were
therefore
vulnerable
to
the
ruling
ideas,
culture
and
leadership
of
the
state.818
The
term
was
later
applied
in
the
1980’s
by
a
group
of
Indian
historians
that
called
themselves
“The
Subaltern
814
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2194.
815
As above.
816
Morton S (2003) 48.
817
As above. See also Gramsci A Selections from Prison Notebooks (1978) trans. Hoare Q &
Nowell Smith G. Antonio Gramsci was an Italian Marxist thinker and one of the principal
representatives of western Marxism. He was active in the Italian Socialist Party and then the
Italian Communist Party. Gramsci was arrested by Mussolini’s police in 1928 and spent the
rest of his life in prison. Macey notes that he produced thirty-three notebooks in prison, with a
selection published. Gramsci was the most important influence on the development of Italian
communism in the postwar period. See Macey D (2000) 165-166. One of his most important
theoretical developments was the concept of “hegemony”. Morton mentions that after the
failure of a worker’s revolution in Italy, Gramsci questioned the classic Marxist view that a
proletarian revolution was the natural consequence of the economic division of labour
between the worker and the capitalist and that ideology would somehow disappear once
capitalism was overthrown. Morton S (2003) 65. Gramsci rather emphasised that dominant
ideological institutions, such as political parties, the church, education, the media and
bureaucracy also play and important role in maintaining the relations of ruling and power.
Against the classis Marxist notion of ideology as false consciousness Gramsci proposed the
term “hegemony” which signified a more complex and flexible term to emphasise how
people’s everyday lives and identities are defined in an through dominant social structures
that are relatively autonomous of economic relations. Morton S (2003) 65. Morton further
explains that the crucial difference between classic Marxist accounts of ideology and
Gramsci’s definition of hegemony is that classic Marxist accounts of ideology as “false
consciousness” suggest and element of manipulation, deception and even coercion; whereas
hegemony depends on the consent and agreement of the individual. See Morton S (2003) 65.
818
As above.
159
Studies
Collective”.819
They
developed
the
term
in
order
to
define
the
“general
attribute
of
subordination
in
South
Asian
society,
whether
expressed
in
terms
of
class,
caste,
age,
gender
and
office
or
in
any
other
way”.820
Leitch
et
al
explains
that
the
term
held
particularly
rich
connotations
for
the
Indian
subcontinent
as
imperialism
was
often
considered
from
the
ambivalent
and
contradictory
position
of
the
subaltern,
“or
of
the
socially
subordinate
person
that
is
situated
within
a
complex
system
of
colonial
hierarchies”.821
For
the
Studies
Collective,
Gramsci’s
discussion
of
the
rural
peasantry
in
Southern
Italy
aptly
and
usefully
described
the
continued
domination
of
the
rural
peasantry
and
the
working
class
in
post-‐
independence
Indian
society.822
The
concern
of
the
group
was
that
India
achieved
political
independence
from
the
British
Empire
without
a
corresponding
revolution
in
the
class
system.823
The
Studies
Collective
attempted
to
retrieve
what
can
be
referred
to
as
a
history
of
subaltern
agency
and
resistance
from
the
perspective
of
the
people
rather
than
the
state.
They
thereby
appropriated
the
term
to
focus
their
attention
on
the
disenfranchised
and
economically
dispossessed
peoples
of
India.824
As
Morton
explains,
for
the
Studies
Collective,
elite
and
dominant
social
groups
traditionally
recorded
the
histories
of
the
rural
819
As above.
820
Morton S (2003) 49. Members of the collective include Shahid Amin, David Arnold, Partha
Chatterjee, David Hardiman, Ranajit Guha and Gyanendra Pandey.
821
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193.
822
As above. It is argued that Gramsci’s account provides a key theoretical resource for
understanding the conditions of the poor, the lower class and peasantry in India because of
the fact that he drew parallels between the division of labour in Mussolini’s Italy and the
colonial division of labour in India. Morton S (2003) 49. Gramsci also emphasised that the
oppression of the rural peasantry in Southern Italy could be subverted through an alliance
with the urban working class, or through the development of class-consciousness among the
peasants. Morton S (2003) 49. Gramsci’s account of the subaltern resembles Marx’s earlier
proclamation in the nineteenth century that the industrial working class in Europe carried the
future potential for collective social and political change. However, as Morton explains, unlike
Marx’s model of change, Gramsci stressed that the social and political practices of the rural
peasantry were not systemic or coherent in their position to the state. See Morton S (2003) 49-
50. And it is this lack of coherence that distinguished Gramsci’s notion of the subaltern from
the traditional Marxist perception of the industrial working class as unified and coherent.
Furthermore, it is argued that this lack of coherence when it comes to political identity in
Gramsci’s description of the subaltern is crucial to Spivak’s argument of the subaltern in the
post-colonial world that will be discussed below. Morton S (2003) 49
823
Morton S (2003) 48.
824
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2194.
160
peasantry
and
the
urban
working
class.825
Subaltern
histories
were
documented
in
the
archives
of
British
colonial
administrators
under
colonial
rule
and
were
later
rewritten
in
the
historical
reports
of
the
educated,
Indian
middle-‐class
elite
during
and
after
the
struggle
for
national
independence.826
Morton
elucidates:
The
historiography
of
Indian
nationalism
has
for
a
long
time
been
dominated
by
elitism
and
bourgeois
nationalist
elitism.
Both
originated
as
the
ideological
product
of
British
rule
in
India,
but
have
survived
the
transfer
of
power
and
have
been
assimilated
to
neo-‐colonialist
and
neo-‐nationalist
forms
of
discourse
in
Britain
and
India
respectively.827
Therefore,
the
historical
representation
of
various
lower-‐class
subaltern
groups
was
and
is
framed
in
the
terms
and
interests
of
the
ruling
power
and
dominant
social
classes.828
Morton
explains
further
that
the
British
historical
archives
rendered
the
lives
and
political
agencies
of
the
rural
peasantry
in
India
subordinate
to
the
larger
project
of
imperial
governance.829
Therefore,
in
the
elite
narratives
of
bourgeois
national
independence,
“the
localised
resistances
of
the
peasants
were
subordinated
to
the
larger
nationalist
project
of
decolonialisation”.830
The
Studies
Collective
thus
attempted
to
recover
the
histories
and
voices
of
subaltern
groups
before,
during
and
after
British
colonial
rule
in
India
by
critiquing
the
colonial
and
elite
representation
of
subalterns.831
Whilst
the
Studies
Collective
appropriated
the
term
to
denote
the
economically
disenfranchised
and
politically
disempowered
peoples
in
India,
Spivak
draws
on
the
nuances
of
the
term
in
her
essay,
insisting
that
the
subaltern
subject
is
“irretrievably
heterogeneous”.832
825
Morton S (2003) 49.
826
As above.
827
Morton S (2003) 50.
828
As above.
829
As above.
830
Morton S (2003) 50-51.
831
As above.
832
T Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2194. Leitch et al further explains that the term always
stands in an ambiguous relation to power in the sense that subalterns are subordinate to it,
but never fully consents to its rule. Subalterns therefore never adopt the dominant point of
view or vocabulary as expressive as its own identity. T Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2194.
161
In
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
Spivak
critically
engages
with
the
Subaltern
Studies
Collective.
Although
Spivak
highlights
the
important
points
and
achievements
of
the
Collective
in
their
work
of
recovering
the
histories
of
subaltern
groups,
she
criticises
them
on
two
points.
Firstly,
Spivak
argues
that
the
Collective’s
classic
Marxist
methodology
does
not
allow
them
to
read
the
history
of
women’s
resistance
in
India.833
Therefore,
as
Morton
explains,
although
Spivak
agrees
with
their
arguments
in
general,
she
argues
that
the
use
of
a
classic
Marxist
approach
to
social
and
historical
change
overlooks
the
lives
and
struggles
of
women
before,
during
and
after
India’s
independence.834
Further,
she
argues
that
anti-‐colonial
nationalist
leaders
originally
invoked
the
Marxist
model
of
historical
change
in
order
to
try
to
mobilise
the
subaltern,
but
it
clearly
failed
in
changing
the
economic,
political
and
social
circumstances
of
subalterns.835
Rather
than
a
classic
Marxist
definition
of
the
term,
Spivak
proposes
a
more
nuanced,
flexible,
post-‐Marxist
definition
of
the
subaltern;
“one
informed
by
deconstruction
and
that
takes
the
lives
and
histories
of
women
into
account”.836
Indeed,
gender
becomes
central
to
her
argument
on
the
subaltern.
For
Spivak,
“women’s
interception
[in
subalternity]
can
be
staked
out
across
strict
lines
of
definition
by
virtue
of
their
muting
by
heterogeneous
circumstances”.837
Therefore,
for
Spivak,
the
question
of
subalternity,
of
the
most
oppressed
groups
and
individuals,
cannot
be
conceived
of
only
in
terms
of
imperialistic
oppression
and
bourgeois
nationalism,
but
must
also
be
conceived
of
in
terms
of
gender
because
of
the
historical
and
persistent
patriarchal
oppression
of
women
through
various
mechanisms:
Within
the
effaced
itinerary
of
the
subaltern
subject,
the
track
of
sexual
difference
is
doubly
effaced.
The
question
is
not
of
female
participation
in
833
Morton S (2003) 47.
834
As above.
835
As above.
836
As above.
837
Morton S (2003) 50. The expansion of the term “subaltern” complicates the lower-class
associations of the term because it includes women from the upper middle class, as well as
peasantry and the sub-proletariat. Spivak’s crucial argument is however that the active
involvement of women in the history of the anti-British-colonial insurgency in India has been
excluded form the official history of national independence. Morton S (2003) 50.
162
insurgency,
or
the
ground
rules
of
the
sexual
division
of
labour,
for
both
of
which
there
is
“evidence”.
It
is,
rather,
that,
both
as
object
of
colonialist
historiography
and
as
subject
of
insurgency,
the
ideological
construct
of
gender
keeps
the
male
dominant.
If,
in
the
context
of
colonial
production,
the
subaltern
has
no
history
and
cannot
speak,
the
subaltern
as
female
is
even
more
deeply
in
the
shadow.838
Therefore,
the
dominant
point
of
view
holds
the
male
position
and
women
experience
marginalisation
in
India
by
virtue
of
patriarchal
discourses
of
religion,
family
and
the
state,
which
results
in
economic
disadvantage
and
gender
subordination.
The
sexed
subaltern
is
therefore
doubly
marginalised
and
in
the
shadow,
not
only
in
terms
of
race
and
economic
position,
but
also
in
terms
of
gender.
Spivak
therefore
expands
and
complicates
the
term.
For
Spivak,
the
term
should
be
flexible
enough
to
include
an
array
of
social
positions
and
to
denote
the
most
oppressed
and
invisible
constituencies
in
society.839
Her
insistence
on
a
nuanced
and
flexible
definition,
one
that
does
not
fall
prey
to
the
reductive
terms
of
strict-‐class
analysis,
relates
to
the
second
point
of
critique
with
regards
to
the
Studies
Collective.
Spivak’s
second
point
of
criticism
involves
her
concern
over
the
Collective’s
attempts
to
retrieve
a
subaltern
voice
or
consciousness,
or
put
differently,
to
recover
“the
will
of
the
subaltern”.840
For
Spivak,
such
an
approach
results
in
establishing
a
false
coherence
on
what
can
be
regarded
as
much
more
complex
and
differentiated
struggles
of
subaltern
groups.841
As
Morton
explains,
for
Spivak
there
is
a
risk
that
general
claims
or
theoretical
statements
made
on
behalf
of
disempowered
subaltern
groups
by
educated,
metropolitan
based
intellectuals
will
overlook
or
marginalise
the
crucial
differences
between
subaltern
groups
and
individuals.842
For
Spivak,
any
model
of
political
consciousness
will
paradoxically
838
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 287.
839
Morton S (2003) 47. Although Spivak, in the different versions of the essay and in numerous
interviews refer to different definitions of the term, she, as will be demonstrated later,
appropriates subalternity to encompass a range of different social positions that are not
predetermined by dominant political discourses
840
Morton S (2003) 53.
841
As above.
842
Morton S (2003) 46.
163
work
to
objectify
the
subaltern,
or,
“control
her
through
knowledge”.843
Indeed,
the
idea
of
speaking
for
disempowered
people
is
a
central
concern
for
Spivak.
In
her
engagement
with
the
Studies
Collective,
she
identifies
risks
attached
to
this
idea
and
she
expands
her
critique
to
post-‐colonial
intellectuals
and
in
the
beginning
of
her
essay,
engages
in
a
rigorous
critique
of
the
western
academy
in
general.844
Spivak
attempts
to
argue
that
post-‐colonial
critics
that
attempt
to
give
silenced
people
a
voice,
might
repeat
the
very
silencing
that
they
are
writing
against.845
Spivak
highlights,
for
example,
that
even
colonialists
thought
of
themselves
as
well
intentioned
and
in
this
regard
she
refers
to
the
British
outlawing
of
sati
under
843
See Morton S (2003) 56. In this regard Spivak uses the term “epistemic violence” in order
to demonstrate how western knowledge or epistemology has been used to justify “the
violent exercise of political and military force over non-western cultures”. Morton S (2003) 18-
19. The relationship between western knowledge and the violence of colonial dispossession
can best be illustrated by the following passage from Joseph Conrad’s Heart of Darkness:
“The conquest of the earth, which mostly means the taking away from those who have a
different complexion or slightly flatter noses than ourselves, is not a pretty thing when you
look into it too much. What redeems it is the idea only”. Conrad J Heart Of Darkness (1973)
10 as quoted in Morton S (2003) 19. Morton explains that Conrad’s correlation of the violent
exercise of colonial dispossession and the redemptive idea of imperialism as a civilising
mission illustrates the damaging effects that western knowledge continues to have on non-
western cultures. Morton S (2003) 19. For, in emphasising the moral and intellectual
superiority of western cultures, Europeans were able to justify the violent project of
imperialist expansion as a civilising mission. Morton S (2003) 19. Spivak also uses the term
“worlding” to refer to the way in which writing in general has provided a rhetorical structure
to justify imperial expansion. See Morton S (2003) 18. Spivak does not claim to avoid such
violence herself; rather she “self-consciously explores the structures of violence without
assuming a final settled position”. See Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193. The notion of
terra nullius can also be mentioned here in the context of the damage of colonialism. As
Morton explains, there are frequent historical references to colonial territories being
uninscribed or empty territories and references to indigenous people without culture, writing
or political sovereignty. Morton S (2003) 19. These descriptions of colonial territory as empty
and indigenous people as people without writings are persuasive metaphors employed to
justify colonial expansion. As Morton further notes these metaphors illustrate how people and
territory have been controlled, subjected, dispossessed and exploited through dominant
systems of western writing, textuality and knowledge. See Morton S (2003) 19.
844
Spivak specifically focuses on the writings of Michel Foucault and Gilles Deleuze and their
attempts of radical criticism involving the notion of a “sovereign subject”. See Spivak GC in
Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 271-272.
845
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193.
164
colonial
rule.846
Sati
is
the
Hindu
practice
of
widows
killing
themselves
on
their
husband’s
funeral
pyres,
in
other
words,
self-‐immolation.
While
the
British’s
intervention
can
be
said
to
have
saved
lives
and
may
have
given
some
free
choice
to
women
when
it
came
to
the
practice,
it
also
served
to
secure
British
power
in
India
and
to
underscore
the
difference
between
Indian
“barbarism”
and
British
“civilisation”.847
The
British
effectively
drove
Hindu
culture
underground.
It
was
denied
legitimacy
and
written
out
of
law.
Morton
notes
that
for
many
British
colonial
administrators,
the
practice
of
sati
epitomised
the
repulsive
and
inhumane
characteristics
of
Hindu
society.848
Therefore,
by
representing
sati
as
a
barbaric
practice,
the
British
were
able
to
justify
imperialism
as
a
civilising
mission
in
which
white
British
colonial
administrators
believed
that
they
were
rescuing
Indian
women
from
the
reprehensible
practices
of
a
traditional
Hindu
patriarchal
society,
or
in
Spivak’s
terminology,
the
British
were
“saving
brown
women
from
brown
men”.849
For
Spivak,
rather
than
defending
the
choice
and
agency
of
Hindu
women,
the
British
used
“the
body
of
the
widow
as
an
ideological
battleground
for
colonial
power”.850
Spivak’s
question
is
whether
intellectuals,
and
specifically
post-‐colonial
critics,
can
avoid
a
similar
condescension
when
they
try
to
represent
post-‐colonial
subjects,
or
oppressed
peoples
in
general?851
As
will
become
clear
later,
she
seems
doubtful.
By
using
the
example
of
sati,
Spivak
also
makes
an
important
point
with
regards
to
the
agency
of
women
or
the
possibility
of
the
subaltern
woman
“speaking”.
Spivak
considers
how
the
voice
of
Hindu
women
was
represented
in
descriptions
of
sati.
Morton
explains
that
in
terms
of
ancient
Hindu
texts,
the
practice
of
self-‐
immolation
is
coded
as
an
exceptionally
sacred
practice
or
pilgrimage,
rather
than
an
act
of
suicide.852
Suicide
was
strictly
forbidden,
but
was
permissible
as
stated
in
846
As above. Also See Spivak GC (1988) 298- 302.
847
As above.
848
Morton S (2003) 63.
849
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 296.
850
Morton S (2003) 63.
851
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193.
852
Morton S (2003) 62.
165
the
Dharmasastra
if
it
was
part
of
a
sacred,
religious
pilgrimage.853
This
pilgrimage
or
privilege
was
only
reserved
for
men.
However,
as
Morton
further
explains,
exception
was
made
for
the
practice
of
widow
sacrifice
or
sati
-‐the
practice
of
a
woman
physically
repeating
her
husband’s
death
in
a
sacred
place.854
Women
were
therefore,
within
this
context,
given
some
agency
by
patriarchal
Hindu
religious
practices.
They
could
perform
the
sacred
ritual
if
they
wished
to
do
so,
a
privilege
usually
only
reserved
for
men.
Spivak
argues
that
Sati
can
therefore
symbolise
an
exemplary
moment
of
woman’s
free
will
and
moral
conduct
as
the
practice
of
widow
self-‐immolation
is
not
prescribed
or
enforced
by
Hindu
religious
codes.855
It
can
therefore,
rather
than
being
interpreted
as
a
signifier
of
the
woman’s
moral
conduct
as
a
good
wife,
be
seen
a
signifier
of
her
own
desire.
It
is
this
sense
of
sati
that
was
lost
to
British
colonial
legislation.
The
colonial
representation
of
sati
therefore
overlooked
the
voice
and
agency
that
may
be
found
within
the
practice,
within
the
“choosing”
of
a
woman
to
enact
the
practice.
But,
interestingly,
the
agency
allowed
by
Hindu
religious
law,
is
the
agency
to
kill
oneself.
It
is
therefore,
as
Morris
explains,
a
self-‐negating
agency.856
In
other
words,
it
is
an
agency
that
recognises
women’s
non-‐identity.857
The
exception
made
for
women
thus
engenders
a
patriarchal
structure
of
domination
within
Hindu
religious
codes.858
It
can
also
be
argued
that
from
a
patriarchal
perspective,
women
did
not
necessarily
have
a
“free”
choice.
Hindu
women
were
expected
to
be
good
wives.
In
circumstances
where
she
inherited
her
husband’s
property,
it
might
have
been
expected
of
her
to
perform
sati
and
act
morally,
so
that
other
male
heirs
might
inherit
her
husband’s
property.
Here
her
voice
or
agency
is
ignored
by
Hindu
religious
expectations.
For
Spivak
then,
within
the
context
of
this
problematic,
it
is
hard
to
see
how
the
subaltern
as
woman
can
853
As above.
854
Morton S (2003) 62-63.
855
As above.
856
Morris R (ed.) Can the Subaltern Speak? Reflections on the History of an Idea (2010) 6.
Morris states that: “The entire ideological formation seems designed to foreclose the
possibility of woman acceding to the position from which she could actually speak- as
political subject”. See Morris R (ed.) (2010) 6.
857
As above.
858
Morton S (2003) 63.
166
speak.859
She
demonstrates
that
in
both
Hindu
and
British
discussions
of
widow
sacrifice,
the
voice
and
political
agency
of
women
is
effectively
repressed
from
official
historical
discourses
and
political
representation.860
Women’s
agency
or
voice
is
not
discussed
within
those
texts.
As
Morton
argues,
the
Hindu
religious
codes
as
well
as
the
British
constitution
of
the
widow
as
“passive
victim
of
patriarchal
violence”,
both
ignore
the
political
agency
of
the
subaltern
woman.861
It
is
within
this
context
that
Spivak
therefore
argues
that
the
sexed
subaltern
cannot
speak
because
of
the
fact
that
the
voices
of
subaltern
women
were
so
embedded
in
Hindu
patriarchal
codes
of
moral
conduct
and
the
British
colonial
representation
of
women
as
victims
of
a
barbaric
culture.862
This
results
in
subaltern
women’s
voices
being
impossible
to
recover.
There
is
nothing
that
remains
or
nothing
to
be
detected
in
terms
of
the
voices
of
the
women
within
this
context.
Their
voices
therefore
effectively
disappear
under
the
practices
of
patriarchy
and
imperialism.
Spivak’s
discussion
of
sati
also
operates
as
an
important
counterpoint
to
western
theories
of
representation
and
serves
to
argue
her
point
on
the
Studies
Collective’s
attempt
to
give
voice
to
the
subaltern.
Spivak
relates
the
desire
of
British
colonisers
to
“save
brown
women
from
brown
men”
to
the
desire
of
western
intellectuals
to
give
a
voice
to
the
oppressed.
As
Morton
explains,
she
claims
that
radical
intellectuals
can
paradoxically
silence
the
subaltern
when
claiming
to
represent
and
speak
for
their
experience,
in
the
same
way
the
colonialist
silenced
the
voice
of
the
widow
“choosing”
to
die.863
In
this
regard,
Spivak
engages
within
her
essay
in
a
severe
interrogation
of
those
western
writers
who,
at
the
time
of
Spivak’s
first
writing
of
the
essay,
were
attempting
to
produce
a
radical
critique
of
the
western
subject,
namely
Gilles
Deleuze
and
Michel
Foucault.864
Spivak
criticises
them
for
the
incapacity
to
recognise
the
non-‐universality
of
the
western
position
from
within
which
their
859
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 299.
860
Morton S (2003) 64.
861
As above.
862
As above.
863
Morton S (2003) 56.
864
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 4.
167
writing
takes
place
as
well
as
not
recognising
the
“constitutive
place
of
gender
within
the
formation
of
the
subject”.865
First,
it
should
be
explained
that
in
the
context
of
post-‐colonial
studies
and
the
political
struggle
for
national
independence,
Spivak
has
criticised
the
use
of
so-‐
called
“master
words”,
such
as
“the
colonised”,
“the
worker”,
and
“women”.866
Morton
explains
that
although
these
master
words
may
seem
to
provide
a
coherent
political
identity
for
disempowered
groups
in
order
to
struggle
against
an
oppressor,
they
do
not
do
justice
to
the
lives
and
histories
of
those
people
who
are
and
were
frequently
marginalised
and
oppressed
by
anti-‐colonial
national
independence
movements.867
Instead
of
using
these
master
words,
Spivak
suggests
the
word
“subaltern”
as
it
can
encompasses
a
range
of
different
subject
positions
that
are
not
predetermined
by
dominant
political
discourses.868
However,
as
mentioned
within
her
critique
of
the
Studies
Collective,
the
term
must
remain
flexible
enough
to
accommodate
different
social
identities,
without
falling
under
the
reductive
terms
of
strict-‐class
analysis.
Further,
according
to
Spivak,
theorists
and
advocates
of
political
transformation
have
looked
to
oppressed
peoples
as
a
potential
source
of
change
or
transformation.869
Marxists
speak
of
and
for
the
proletariat,
feminists
of
and
for
women
and
anti-‐colonialists
of
and
for
third
world
peoples
for
example.870
Spivak
reacts
against
what
she
sees
as
the
tendency
of
radical
politically
movements
to
romanticise
the
so-‐called
other
(for
instance,
as
Leitch
et
al
explains,
the
notion
that
third
world
people
should
lead
the
fight
against
multinational
global
865
As above. Morris refers here to “the subject of language, not only in the grammatical
sense, but also in the sense of having a voice that can access power”. See Morris S (ed.)
(2010) 4.
866
Morton S (2003) 45.
867
As above.
868
As above.
869
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2194.
870
As above.
168
capitalism).871
As
Leitch
et
al
further
elucidates,
to
assign
disempowered
people
certain
roles,
is
to
repeat
colonialism’s
violence,
which
views
non-‐European
people
as
important
or
relevant
only
to
the
extent
that
they
follow
western
scripts.872
Intellectuals,
who
romanticise
the
oppressed,
can
therefore
ironically
repeat
the
colonialist
discourse
that
they
want
to
critique.
In
the
context
of
Spivak’s
discussion
of
Deleuze
and
Foucault,
she
argues
that
the
use
of
master
words
is
essentialist.
It
assumes
cultural
solidarity
or
coherence
of
a
group
of
people
that
are
heterogeneous
in
nature
and
the
use
of
such
terms
by
intellectuals
puts
the
intellectual
in
the
role
of
a
transparent
medium
that
merely
represents
the
oppressed.873
In
order
to
elucidate
Spivak’s
critique
on
this
point,
it
should
be
mentioned
that
when
it
comes
to
specific
disempowered
groups
such
as
subalterns,
it
should
be
recognised
that
there
is
no
“pure”
subaltern,
or
for
that
matter
other.
The
other
always
exists
in
relation
to
the
discourse
that
would
name
it
as
other.874
Leitch
et
871
As above. The notion of the “other” in its most general sense refers to one pole of the
relationship between a subject and a person or thing defined or constituted as a non-self that
is different or other. See Macey D (2000) 229. In the context of postcolonial theory the term
refers to the discursive production of (an) other, which is a process that is characterised by the
way in which Europe produces an Orient-as other through the discourse of orientalism as
analysed by postcolonial theorist Edward Said. See Macey D (2000) 229. This has also been
described as “othering”. Europe functions as subject that asserts its control over the means
of communication and interpretation, and at the same time constitutes its colonial peoples
and nations as other. See Macey D (2000) 229. According to postcolonial theorist Homi
Bhabha the dominant discourse constructs otherness in an ambivalent way. Whilst it attempts
to construct the other as radically different from itself, it must also ascribe to the other an
element of its identity in order to valorise or justify the control it exerts. See in general Macey
D Dictionary of Critical Theory (2000) 285-286. See also Bhabha H The Location of Culture
(1994) and Said E Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient (1977). The notion of
“alterity” also refers to otherness. Originally formulated by Emmanuel Lévinas, in a
postcolonial context it refers to the process of becoming altern or different from the
dominant view. See also Macey D (2000) 229.
872
As above.
873
Morton S (2003) 45. Spivak refers to Deleuze and Foucault using terms such as “Maoist”
and “the workers struggle” to refer to collectives. Spivak in GC Nelson C & Grossberg L
(1988) 272.
874
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2193. French philosopher Michel Foucault originally
developed the study of “discourse”. In his view discourse is not simply a body of words and
sentences, but “the very structure in which the social world is constructed and controlled as
an object of knowledge”. Morton S (2003) 85. What is more, Foucault argues that “it is in
169
al
explains
that
Spivak
is
emphasising
the
fact
that
research
or
any
knowledge
acquirement
are
always
defining
the
“over
there”,
making
it
an
object
of
study,
something
that
knowledge
can
be
subtracted
from
and
“brought
back
here”.875
The
researcher
preserves
him-‐
or
herself
as
subject
and
any
discourse
is,
for
Spivak,
eventually
about
the
discoursing
agents
or
intellectuals
themselves.876
Leitch
et
al
explains
further
that
postcolonial
studies
are
a
feature
of
the
West’s
intellectual
tradition
and
therefore
relates
to
the
other
or
the
subaltern
with
what
can
be
called
a
hegemonic
vocabulary.877
If
viewed
in
this
way,
representing
the
subaltern
becomes
highly
problematic.
As
Lazarus
notes,
the
danger
is
thought
to
reside
in
the
fact
that
in
speaking
for
others
we
might
unintentionally
and
unwittingly
objectify
those
people
we
are
speaking
for
and
superimpose
our
own
elite
and
western
cognitive
maps
on
them
whilst
we
do
so
(it
is
of
course,
as
Lazarus
further
notes,
our
relative
privilege,
such
as
our
schooling
for
example,
that
has
put
us
in
a
position
to
do
so,
or
to
even
think
of
doing
so).878
discourse that power and knowledge are joined together”. See Foucault M The History of
Sexuality: An Introduction (1978) 100. The study of discourse can therefore not be separated
from the study of institutional power, discipline and domination of western societies. Morton
S (2003) 85. In Orientalism (1977) Edward Said expanded Foucault’s analysis of regimes of
discourse, power and knowledge in western societies by applying this model to what he calls
orientalism, or “colonial discourse”. Said, along the lines of Foucault, emphasised how the
will to know and understand the non-western world in colonial discourse is inseparable from
the will to power over that world. Morton S (2003) 85. Said argues that western colonial power
over the non-western “oriental” world is maintained in and through the discourses of the arts,
humanities and social sciences as well as through the more direct forms of domination such
as political rule and military repression. Colonial discourse analysis dissolves the simple
distinction between cultural texts and institutional or political discourses, rather pointing to
the fact that all texts that represent the colonial world are implicated in a structure of colonial
power and knowledge. Postcolonial theorist Robert Young explains: “Said’s deployment of
the concept of ‘discourse’ for his analysis of Orientalism enabled him to demonstrate a
consistent discursive register for particular perceptions, vocabularies and modes of
representation common to a wide variety of texts extending across the humanities and social
sciences- from travel accounts to history, from literature to racial theory, from economics to
autobiography, from philosophy to linguistics. All these texts could be analysed as sharing a
consistent colonial ideology in their language as well as their subject matter, a form of
knowledge that was developed simultaneously with its deployment and utilization in a
structure of power, namely colonial domination”. See Young R Postcolonialism: An Historical
Introduction (2001) 388. Also see Morton S (2003) 85.
875
As above.
876
As above.
877
As above.
878
Lazarus N The Postcolonial Unconscious (2011) 43.
170
What
is
more,
writing
about
the
subjectivity
or
the
will
of
the
subaltern
takes
place
within
dominant
discourses.
There
are
no
universal
frameworks
or
concepts
available
to
us
to
investigate
different
cultures.
These
investigations
always
take
place
within
structures
of
power
and
domination.
In
the
context
of
postcolonial
studies,
the
will
of
the
subaltern
is,
for
Spivak,
constructed
by
the
dominant
discourse
as
an
effect
of
elite
nationalism.879
This
discourse
effectively
contains
the
subaltern
within
the
grand
narrative
of
bourgeois
national
liberation
and
ignores
the
different
local
struggles
of
particular
subaltern
groups.880
And
within
the
broader
global
context,
Spivak’s
historical
and
political
analysis
describes
western
capitalism
and
colonialism
as
immensely
powerful
dominant
discourses.881
Leitch
et
al
argues
that
for
Spivak
the
whole
world
is
organised
economically,
politically
and
culturally
along
the
lines
of
western
discourses.882
Of
course,
no
discourse
can
completely
suppress
all
alternative
discourses.
Intellectuals
have
frequently
tried
to
create
counter-‐discourses
that
contest
dominant
discourses
in
order
to
connect
with
oppressed
people’s
struggles.883
However,
the
point
that
Spivak
attempts
to
make
is
that
although
dominant
western
discourses
aren’t
perfectly
aligned,
their
“multiplicity
generally
reinforces
rather
than
undercuts
the
marginalisation
of
non-‐white
people
and
the
dual
marginalisation
of
non-‐white
women”.884
Therefore,
it
is
not
possible
for
critics
or
intellectuals
to
write
about
colonial
subjects
without
sustaining
colonialism.
Post-‐
colonial
critics
therefore
write
from
within
the
same
power
structures
and
discourses
that
help
maintain
colonialism.
Research
is
always
in
a
way
colonial
and
879
Morton S (2003) 54.
880
As above. Spivak contends that local and particular struggles such as the role of Muslim
weavers in Northern India during the 1857 mutiny, the industrial action of Jute workers in
early twentieth century Calcutta, or the Adwah peasant rebellion of 1920 are ignored. See
Morton S (2003) 54.
881
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2195.
882
As above
883
For Spivak, postcolonial studies is another attempt to “liberate the other and to enable the
other to experience and articulate those parts of itself that falls outside what the dominant
discourse has constituted as its subjecthood”. See Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2194.
884
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2195.
171
the
political
and
economic
interests
of
the
west,
always
already
taint
knowledge
about
the
so-‐called
third
world.885
Spivak
refers
to
Sigmund
Freud
in
order
to
argue
some
of
her
points
on
colonialism.
Freud
helps
us
to
see
how
the
very
identity
of
whiteness
itself
is
created
in
part
through
the
self-‐proclaimed
benevolence
of
colonial
action.886
Freud
implicitly
cautions
against
the
idea
of
scapegoating,
or
creating
saviours.
Spivak’s
phrase
“white
men
are
saving
brown
women
from
brown
men”
serves
as
a
justification
of
colonial
interventions
if
white
men
are
taken
to
be
the
saviours
and
brown
men
are
scapegoated
as
the
oppressors
(of
brown
women).887
Postcolonialist
discourse
could
just
as
easily
scapegoat
white
men,
with
the
inevitable
consequence
of
presenting
either
brown
men
or
brown
women
as
the
saviours.888
Spivak
argues
that
Freud
can
aid
in
reminding
to
explore
the
dynamics
of
human
relationships
without
foreclosing
narratives
by
assigning
determinate
and
fixed
roles.889
It
is
along
these
lines
that
Spivak
remains
cautious
of
any
attempt
to
fix
and
celebrate
the
subaltern’s
distinctive
voice
“by
claims
that
the
subaltern
occupies
the
position
of
victim,
abjected
other,
scapegoat,
saviour
and
so
on”.890
This
is
one
of
the
reasons
why
Spivak
insists
in
defining
the
subaltern
flexibly;
to
such
an
extent
that
she
points
to
the
subaltern
as
that
which
inevitably
gets
excluded
by
and
from
all
systems,
defining
the
subaltern
as
“the
sheer
heterogeneity
of
decolonised
space”.891
I
will
return
to
this
point
below.
Spivak
is
postulating
the
argument
that
although
it
might
seem
as
an
obvious
goal
for
subaltern
groups
to
escape
their
exploitation
and
oppression,
the
historical
and
structural
conditions
of
political
representation
do
not
guarantee
that
the
interests
of
particular
groups
will
be
recognised
or
that
their
voices
will
be
885
As above.
886
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2196.
887
As above.
888
As above.
889
As above.
890
As above.
891
See Spivak GC A Critique of Postcolonial Reason (1999) 310.
172
heard.892
In
her
critique
of
Deleuze
and
Foucault,
she
starts
from
the
premise
that
the
structure
underpinning
aesthetic
representation
(in
artistic,
literary
or
cinematic
texts
for
example)
also
underpins
political
representation.
The
general
difference
between
aesthetic
and
political
representation
is
that
aesthetic
representation
tend
to
foreground
its
status
as
re-‐presentation.893
It
therefore
self-‐consciously
declares
itself
as
representation.
Morton
explains
that
for
Spivak
then,
the
problem
with
Deleuze
and
Foucault
is
that
they
efface
their
role
as
intellectuals
in
re-‐presenting
the
disempowered
groups
they
describe.
Spivak
compares
this
effacement
to
a
masquerade
in
which
the
intellectual
as
an
“absent
non-‐representer
[…]
lets
the
oppressed
speak
for
themselves”.894
Therefore,
despite
all
the
energy
that
Foucault
and
Deleuze
invest
in
showing
how
subjects
is
constructed
through
discourse
and
representation,
when
it
comes
to
real,
historical
examples
of
social
and
political
struggle,
they
fall
back
on
a
transparent
model
of
representation,
in
which
“oppressed
subjects
speak,
act
and
know
their
own
conditions”.895
Spivak
attempts
to
clarify
this
criticism
through
a
discussion
of
political
representation
in
Karl
Marx’s
Eighteenth
Brumaire
of
Louis
Bonaparte.
In
this
text,
Marx’s
offers
a
description
of
peasant
proprietors
in
nineteenth-‐
century
French
agrarian
society.896
He
argues
that
these
proprietors
did
not
collectively
represent
a
coherent
class
as
their
conditions
of
economic
and
social
life
prevented
them
from
having
class-‐consciousness.897
For
this
reason,
Spivak
argues
that
the
“absent
collective
consciousness
of
the
small
peasant
proprietor”
is
symbolically
depicted
by
a
political
representative
or
proxy
from
the
middle-‐
class,
who
speaks
on
their
behalf.898
For
Marx,
the
representation
of
the
peasant
proprietor
has
double
meaning,
which
in
German
is
distinguished
by
the
terms
darstellen
(representation
as
aesthetic
portrait)
and
vertreten
(representation
by
892
Morton S (2003) 57.
893
As above.
894
As above.
895
As above.
896
Morton S (2003) 57. See Marx K Surveys from Exile (1974) 239 trans. Fernbach D as
referenced in Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 275.
897
As above.
898
As above.
173
political
proxy).899
Spivak
argues
in
the
Deleuze-‐Foucault
conversation
that
the
two
meanings
of
representation
are
conflated
because
of
the
fact
that
in
the
constitution
of
disempowered
groups
as
coherent
political
subjects,
the
process
of
aesthetic
representation
is
subordinated
to
the
voice
of
the
political
proxy
who
speaks
on
their
behalf.
As
a
consequence
of
this
conflation,
the
aesthetic
portrait
–
symbolically
representing
disempowered
people
as
coherent
political
subjects-‐
is
often
taken
as
a
transparent
expression
of
their
political
desire
and
interests.900
What
is
important
is
that
Spivak
argues
that
the
act
of
rhetorical
conflation
can
have
potentially
damaging
effects
on
and
consequences
for
the
oppressed
groups
that
certain
intellectuals
claim
to
speak
for.901
In
Foucault
and
Deleuze’s
case,
these
groups
include
factory
workers
and
people
who
were
incarcerated
in
prisons
or
psychiatric
institutions
in
the
west.
For
Spivak,
when
this
model
of
political
representation
is
mapped
onto
the
third
world,
the
gap
between
aesthetic
and
political
representation
is
even
more
pronounced.902
Spivak
is
attempting
to
highlight
the
limitations
of
applying
European
theories
of
representation
to
the
lives
and
histories
of
disempowered
groups
in
the
third
world.
Unless
western
intellectuals
take
the
aesthetic
dimension
of
political
representation
into
account,
Spivak
argues
that
these
intellectuals
will
continue
to
silence
the
voice
of
subaltern
women.903
Spivak
calls
for
intellectuals
to
involve
themselves
in
a
project
of
“unlearning
our
privilege
as
our
loss”
in
order
to
strive
towards
having
an
ethical
relationship
with
the
subaltern.904
Unlearning
one’s
privilege
or
loss
involves
a
double
recognition;
firstly,
as
Landry
and
Maclean
explains,
it
requires
that
we
recognise
that
our
899
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 275-276.
900
See Morton S (2003) 57.
901
Morton S (2003) 58.
902
As above.
903
Intellectuals such as Benita Parry have accused Spivak of repeating the very silencing she
criticises. For Parry, Spivak effectively writes out “the evidence of native agency recorded in
India’s 200 year struggle against British conquest and the Raj” with the phrase “the subaltern
cannot speak”. Parry B “Problems in current theories of colonial discourse” Oxford Literary
Review (1987) 35.
904
Spivak GC The Post-Colonial Critic: Interviews, Strategies, Dialogues (1990) 9.
174
privileges,
whatever
they
may
be
in
terms
of
class,
race,
nationality,
gender
and
the
like,
prevents
us
from
gaining
a
certain
kind
of
Other
knowledge.
This
knowledge
is
not
simply
information
that
we
have
not
yet
received,
but
is
rather
knowledge
that
we
are
not
equipped
to
understand
by
reason
of
our
social
positions.905
To
unlearn
one’s
privilege
means
to,
on
the
one
hand,
work
hard
at
gaining
knowledge
of
others
who
occupy
spaces
that
are
most
closed
to
the
privileged
view
and,
on
the
other
hand,
it
means
attempting
to
speak
to
those
others
in
such
a
way
that
they
might
be
able
to
answer
back.
906
Spivak:
It
seems
to
me
that
finding
the
subaltern
is
not
so
hard,
but
actually
entering
into
a
responsibility
structure
with
the
subaltern,
with
responses
flowing
both
ways:
learning
without
this
quick-‐fix
frenzy
of
doing
good
with
an
implicit
assumption
of
cultural
supremacy
which
is
legitimised
by
unexamined
romanticisation,
that’s
the
hard
part.907
In
the
last
part
of
the
essay,
Spivak
invokes
the
story
of
Bhubaneswari
Bhudari,
a
young
middle-‐class
Indian
woman
who
took
her
own
life
in
her
father’s
apartment
in
Calcutta
in
1926.908
It
was
later
discovered
that
she
was
a
member
of
one
of
the
many
groups
involved
in
the
armed
struggle
for
Indian
independence.909
She
had
been
entrusted
with
a
political
assassination,
which
she
was
unable
to
do.
She
subsequently
committed
suicide
in
order
to
avoid
capture
by
the
British
colonial
authorities
and
to,
speculatively,
safeguard
the
members
of
her
group.910
Spivak
reads
Bhubaneswari’s
suicide
as
an
attempt
to
cover
up
her
involvement
in
the
anti-‐colonial
insurgency
movement
by
disguising
her
suicide
as
a
modern
example
of
sati.
Yet,
in
doing
so,
her
voice
and
agency
as
a
real
historical
woman
freedom
fighter
disappeared
form
the
official,
male-‐centred
historical
records.911
Technically,
her
suicide
did
not
conform
to
the
codes
of
sati
because
she
was
not
a
widow
and
the
suicide
did
not
take
place
in
the
sacred
site
of
the
husband’s
905
Landry D & Maclean G (eds.) (1996) 4.
906
As above.
907
“Sublatern Talk” Spivak GC in interview with Landry D & Maclean G in Landry D & Maclean
G (eds.) (1996) 288.
908
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 306-308.
909
Morton S (2003) 65.
910
As above.
911
As above.
175
funeral
pyre.912
However,
as
Morris
elucidates,
on
Spivak’s
account
Bhubaneswari
at
least
foreclosed
any
possible
that
her
suicide
might
be
interpreted
as
an
illegitimate
pregnancy
as
she
was
menstruating
at
the
time
of
her
suicide.913
For
Spivak,
there
is
no
question
that
Bhubaneswari
was
a
politically
committed
and
courageous
member
of
the
national
independence
struggle.
But,
she
argues
that
Bhubaneswari’s
attempt
to
rewrite
the
text
of
sati-‐suicide
is
a
“tragic
failure”
because
the
“subaltern
as
female
cannot
be
heard
or
read”
in
the
male-‐centred
terms
of
the
national
independence
struggle.914
Spivak
explains
that
supplementary
narratives
and
retellings
erased
Bhubaneswari’s
story.915
Her
exceptional
act
of
women’s
resistance
was
later
re-‐coded
as
a
case
of
an
illicit
love
affair
and
a
source
of
shame
for
the
subsequent
generations
of
her
family.916
Everyone,
including
her
own
family,
misunderstood
Bhubaneswari’s
suicide
and
no
one
in
India
seemed
interested
in
Spivak’s
return
to
and
reinterpretation
of
the
event
at
the
time
of
writing
the
essay.917
“Unnerved
by
this
failure
of
communication”,
Spivak
wrote
her
passionate
lament:
“the
subaltern
cannot
speak!”918
For
Spivak,
Bhubaneswari’s
suicide
is
not
an
example
of
an
Indian
women’s
inability
to
speak
within
western
discourse,
but
she
rather
shows
how
Indian
discourse
has
been
so
battered
by
colonial
history
that
it
too
offers
no
resources
for
successful
communication.919
Fifteen
years
later
Spivak
mentioned
that
her
remark
“the
subaltern
cannot
speak”
was
inadvisable
because
she
reminded
herself
that
“speaking”
always
occurs
within
the
nexus
of
actions
that
include
listening,
responding,
interpreting
912
It should be mentioned here that there is of course no way in which Bhubaneswari’s
intentions can really be proved, nevertheless, Spivak reads Bhubaneswari’s story as an
attempt to rewrite “the social text of sati-suicide in an interventionist way”. Spivak GC (1988)
307.
913
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 6.
914
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 307-308. See also Morton S (2003) 65-66.
915
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 307.
916
Morton S (2003) 66.
917
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2195.
918
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 307.
919
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2195.
176
and
qualifying.920
One’s
words
can
be
taken
up
in
a
number
of
possible
ways:
“The
ongoing
effects
of
an
utterance,
not
its
singular
expression
or
any
one
response,
produces
its
character
as
a
speech-‐act”.921
Spivak,
however,
remains
weary
of
all
representations
and
she
insists
on
the
inevitable
silences
in
all
discourses.922
She
still
seems
doubtful
that
political
speech
can
occur
within
certain
frameworks
and
she
also
still
reserves
the
term
“subaltern”
for
that
which
gets
excluded
by
systems
of
representation
or,
as
she
puts
it,
“the
sheer
heterogeneity
of
decolonised
space”.923
Before
concluding
this
point
should
be
discussed.
In
her
original
essay,
Spivak
appropriated
the
term
sublatern,
against
the
Subaltern
Studies
Collective,
to
refer
to
the
gendered
position
of
the
most
oppressed
individuals
within
Indian
society.
She
insisted
that
the
subaltern
should
be
understood
as
a
flexible
term
in
order
to
avoid
the
trappings
of
master
words
and
dominant
political
descriptions.
After
her
essay
and
in
the
different
and
abridged
versions
of
her
essay,
she
developed
and
expanded
the
term
in
order
to
affirm
and
explain
some
of
her
arguments
(presumably
because
of
the
impact
of
the
essay
as
well
as
the
praise
and
criticisms
that
the
essay
provoked).
She
has
given
several
definitions
of
the
term
in
subsequent
interviews
and
has
described
the
term
in
different
ways
in
her
writings
after
her
original
essay.924
920
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2196.
921
Leitch et al explains that Spivak recognises that much of the point of revisionist history or
of returning to instances of oppression, is to reactivate attempts at speaking that other forces
tried to obliterate and keep from having effects. See Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2196.
To deny this retelling as a form of speaking will hold on to a criterion of “authenticity” that
runs counter to Spivak’s whole argument about identity. For her the historian can sketch “the
itinerary of trace” that the silenced subaltern left. They should also mark the sites where the
subaltern was effaced and should delineate these discourses that did the effacing. See Leitch
V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2196.
922
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2196.
923
Spivak GC A Critique of Postcolonial Reason (1999) 310.
924
For example, “you have the foreign elite and the indigenous elite. Below that you will have
the vectors of upward, downward, sideward and backward mobility. But then there is a space
that is for all practical reasons outside those lines”. See Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L
(1988) 284. Another definition refers to the subaltern as “the part that remains most excluded
from the circuits and benefits of social capital”. See “Subaltern Talk” Spivak GC interview
with Landry D & Maclean G in Landry D & Maclean G (eds.) (1996) 288. See also “Interview
with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak: New Nation Writers Conference in South Africa” with De
Kock L in A Review of International English Literature (1992) 29-47.
177
Ultimately,
in
postcolonial
terms,
Spivak
uses
the
term
to
refer
to
everything
that
has
no
or
limited
access
to
cultural
imperialism.
The
term
has
developed
in
such
a
way
as
to
denote
something
of
a
non-‐speakingness.925
As
Morris
elucidates:
Subalternity
is
less
an
identity
than
what
we
might
call
a
predicament,
but
this
is
true
in
a
very
odd
sense.
For,
in
Spivak’s
definition,
it
is
the
structured
place
from
which
the
capacity
to
predicate
is
radically
obscured.926
This
results
in
the
idea
that
if
anyone
escapes
the
muting
of
subalternity,
she
ceases
to
be
subaltern
(something
that,
as
Morris
explains,
is
absolutely
to
be
desired
according
to
Spivak).927
Thus,
the
term
developed
to
denote
those
people
that
are
constitutively
beyond
or
outside
of
representation,
so
much
so
that
what
is
subaltern
has
“always-‐already
been
made
over,
not
only
translated
but
traduced,
not
only
appropriated,
but
expropriated”.928
This
has
resulted
in
some
criticism.929
Although
Spivak
has
attempted
to
refine
her
original
argument,
the
expansion
of
the
term
results
in
a
circuitry:
that
which
is
subaltern
cannot
speak
and
that
which
cannot
speak
is
subaltern.
In
Spivak’s
ultimate
formulation,
subalternity
as
a
singular
state
or
“a
position
without
identity
[…]
where
the
social
lines
of
mobility,
being
elsewhere,
do
not
permit
the
formation
of
a
recognisable
basis
for
action”
has
become
that
which
is
unrepresentable.930
Colin
Graham
has
described
it
as
“a
theoretical
site
of
disempowered
purity”.931
In
this
way,
subalternity
becomes
an
end
in
itself.
For
the
purposes
of
my
discussion,
I
read
the
term
“subaltern”
within
the
context
of
her
original
essay.
In
other
words,
I
read
the
term
to
refer
to
economically
oppressed
and
politically
marginalised
individuals,
irreducible
to
singular
analysis
and
as
including
an
array
of
social
positions
and
identities.
Spivak’s
most
important
and
significant
points
in
925
Landry D & Maclean G (eds.) (1996) 289.
926
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 8.
927
As above.
928
Lazarus N (2011) 144.
929
See for example in this regard Lazarus N (2011) 144-145.
930
Spivak GC “Scattered Speculations on the subaltern and the popular” Postcolonial Studies
(2005) 476.
931
See Graham C Deconstructing Ireland (2001) 106. See also Lehner S “’Dangerous Liaisons’:
Gender Politics in the Contemporary Scottish and Irish Imagination” in Gardiner M,
Macdonald G & O’Gallagher N (eds.) Scottish Literature and Postcolonial Literature:
Comparative Texts and Critical Perspectives (2011) 229.
178
her
original
essay
was
firstly,
her
warnings
against
describing
subalterns
along
the
lines
of
coherent
groups
in
ways
that
would
objectify
them
and
secondly,
reading
the
term
through
the
lens
of
gender
and
highlighting
the
silencing
of
women
by
way
of
heterogeneous
circumstances.
Spivak
suggests
that
we
should
engage
with
the
histories
and
social
texts
of
subalterns
through
careful
reading
strategies
and
deconstruction.932
Such
an
engagement
will
acknowledge
the
complicity
of
theory
with
its
object
of
critique
and
thereby
ensure
a
more
nuanced
and
ethical
engagement
that
does
not
objectify
or
romanticise
groups,
but
rather
seeks
to
trace
the
silences
and
exclusions
present
in
all
discourses.
4.3
The
Sexed
Subaltern:
Concluding
Remarks
In
her
discussion
of
sati
and
the
suicide
of
Bhubaneswari
Badhuri
as
well
as
the
surrounding
contexts
of
those
events,
Spivak
brilliantly
demonstrates
how
the
ideological
formations
of
those
events
seemed
designed
to
foreclose
the
possibility
of
woman
acceding
to
a
position
from
which
she
could
actually
speak-‐
or
have
a
voice
as
political
subject.933
Spivak
further
passionately
warns
against
the
dangers
in
any
attempt
to
speak
for
the
politically
invisible
and
disempowered.
With
regards
to
subalternity,
Spivak
insists
on
the
role
of
gender
within
its
formation
and
she
demonstrates
how
the
notion
of
subaltern
resistance
is
always
already
filtered
through
the
dominant
discourse
within
which
writing,
speaking
and
the
occurrence
of
voice
takes
place.
When
Spivak
states
that
the
subaltern
cannot
speak,
she
means
that
the
subaltern
cannot
be
heard
by
the
dominant
political
discourses
or
by
the
privileged
in
the
third
and
first
world.
Her
speech
or
voice
falls
short
of
fully
authorised
political
speech,
specifically
as
constrained
by
imperialist,
masculinist
colonial
and
postcolonial
structures
of
apprehension.
The
dominant
political
discourses
that
Spivak
discusses
in
her
essay
are
the
discourses
of
western
imperialism,
elite
representations
of
national
independence
in
India
as
well
as
masculinist
and
patriarchal
ideological
forms.934
932
See Morton S (2003) 40-42. See also Spivak GC 1(978) 201.
933
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 6.
934
The discourses of masculine hegemony and patriarchy becomes important within the
context of South Africa as South African women have traditionally and historically been
179
The
meaning
of
Spivak’s
contention
should
not
be
taken
out
of
context
to
mean
that
disenfranchised
peoples
have
no
agency.
Such
a
reading
will
be
contrary
to
the
situated
framework
that
she
establishes
in
her
essay.935
Morton,
for
example,
states
that
Spivak
would
certainly
not
want
to
deny
the
social
agency
and
lived
realities
of
disempowered
women.
What
Spivak
objects
to
in
the
early
research
of
the
Subaltern
Studies
Collective
is
the
idea
that
the
subaltern
“is
a
sovereign
political
subject
in
control
of
her
own
destiny”.936
The
crucial
point
for
Spivak
is
that
“speaking”
belongs
to
an
already
existing
structure
of
domination.
Further,
for
Spivak,
even
when
the
subaltern
“speaks”,
it
should
be
recognised
that
she
has
received
her
political
and
discursive
identity
within
historically
determinate
systems
of
political
and
economic
representation.937
Therefore,
such
a
speaking
is
also
already
an
effect
of
dominant
discourses
of
apprehension.
Ultimately,
Spivak’s
arguments
should
be
seen
as
valuable
in
enabling
an
investigation
of
what
conditions
obtrude
to
mute
the
speech
of
subaltern
women
and
render
their
speech-‐acts
or
voices
as
unimportant
to
those
who
occupy
dominant
patriarchal
spaces.938
It
can
therefore
be
said
that
Spivak
highlights
reasons
why
certain
phenomena
of
political
invisibility,
voicelessness,
or
difficulties
with
regards
to
political
voice
might
occur.
She
reminds
of
the
fact
that
“voice”
and
“speaking
politically”
are
filtered
through
dominant
discourses
that
might
serve
to
render
such
voices
as
subjected to highly patriarchal cultures. The prevalence of sexual violence and rape further
denotes the existence of hegemonic masculine orders and ways of life. Spivak’s analysis of
the way in which women are muted by different circumstances still remains relevant in the
context of gender oppression. Further, importantly, Morris notes that since the writing of
Spivak’s essay, much has changed. Morris highlights that the international division of labour
currently is organised to permit the effective exploitation of women and girl children in the
urban and rural peripheries (in sweatshops, factories, and brothels). The imperial project
today is mainly interested in liberating women for labour, which refers to “surplus value
extraction”. Human rights have often provided the alibi for this process. For Morris, we can
therefore be as cautious now of the promise for women’s salvation being proffered through
war and imperial domination as when Britain made the abolition of sati the mask and means
of its own imperialism. Morris (ed.) (2010) 7.
935
Morton S (2003) 60.
936
Morton S (2003) 53.
937
As above.
938
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 3.
180
politically
irrelevant
or
illegible.
There
is
no
guarantee
that
such
speech-‐acts
or
utterances
will
be
heard
within
dominant
discourses.
What
is
more,
even
when
the
subaltern
“speaks”,
her
discursive
identity,
as
mentioned,
renders
such
an
utterance
as
an
effect
of
the
dominant
political
and
economic
discourses.939
“She”
is
therefore
not
left
untouched
by
the
hegemonic
discursive
formations
that
surround
her.
Spivak
further
highlights
how
attempts
of
speaking
for
certain
people
might
serve
to
silence
their
voices
and
she
also
points
to
the
dangers
of
attaching
coherent
political
identities
to
heterogeneous
groups.
In
the
section
below,
I
reflect
on
Spivak’s
essay
through
the
lens
of
the
politics
of
Jacques
Rancière.
4.4
Subaltern
Equality
As
mentioned
in
the
introduction,
in
this
section
I
reflect
on
Spivak’s
essay
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
politics.
The
goal
here
is
not
to
embark
on
a
step-‐
by-‐step
comparison,
but
rather
to
critically
contemplate
some
of
Spivak’s
main
arguments.
As
Spivak’s
arguments
in
her
original
essay
result
in
her
concluding
that
subalterns
cannot
speak,
it
becomes
important
to
reflect
on
her
essay
so
as
to
understand
the
notion
of
political
voice
against
the
background
sketched
in
the
first
chapter.
Rancière
sees
people
voicing
political
claims
through
staging
a
scene
of
dissensus
on
which
their
equality
can
be
declared.
And
he
indeed
argues
that
people
in
various
circumstances
can
speak
politically
against
the
police
order
and
its
distributions
of
the
sensible.
I
therefore
aim
to
open
Spivak’s
claim
up
to
contestation
in
order
to
further
investigate
what
political
voicing
means.
The
first
point
that
can
be
mentioned
in
this
regard
relates
to
Spivak’s
criticism
of
the
use
of
master
words.
It
was
mentioned
above
that
Spivak
disparages
the
use
of
master
words
such
as
“women”
or
“the
worker”
for
example.
Her
criticism
with
regards
to
this
point
is
related
to
her
critical
engagements
with
the
Subaltern
Studies
Collective
and
her
warnings
against
objectifying
and
silencing
voices
by
939
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 204.
181
attaching
coherent
political
identities
to
individuals.
Such
objectification,
it
was
argued,
ignores
the
real
differences
between
people.
Rancière
is,
as
mentioned,
highly
critical
of
identity
and
specifically
identity
categories
associated
and
appropriated
by
the
police
order.
Therefore,
Rancière
and
Spivak
both
highlight
in
their
own
way
the
dangers
of
notions
of
identity
or
identity
categories.
However,
important
differences
need
to
be
highlighted.
Rancière
demonstrates
that
word
“worker”
for
example,
can
serve
as
the
name
under
which
people
can
subjectivise
themselves.
“Worker”
can
become
the
heading
under
which
subjects
can
tear
their
bodies
away
from
the
positions
assigned
by
the
police
and
its
representations
and
discourses.
Rancière
highlights
the
fact
that
people
in
struggle
sometimes
use
universal
syllogisms,
names
and
constructions
in
the
forming
of
a
“we”.
He
does
not
care
whether
“man”
for
example,
is
from
bourgeois
derivation
(in
colonialist,
imperialist,
or
patriarchal
terms
for
that
matter).
The
only
thing
that
matters
is
whether
it
can
serve
the
self-‐
emancipation
of
people.
The
point
is
how
and
if
subjectivation
occurs
through
equality
and
whether
it
redistributes
the
sensible
police
interpretations
of
the
name
that
the
“we”
goes
by.
Further,
such
theorisation
is
not
an
attempt
to
objectify
a
group
of
people.
Politics
and
the
political
subject
in
struggle
is
provincial,
localised
and
temporary.
The
struggle
of
the
demos
under
the
name
of
the
“we”
does
not
deny
the
real
differences
between
people,
but
rather
seeks
a
temporary
“coming
together”.
The
use
of
certain
master
words
in
a
process
of
subjectivation
and
in
the
redistribution
of
the
sensible
can
therefore
become
a
heading
under
which
equality
is
assumed,
practised
and
verified.
It
should
be
mentioned
that
although
Spivak
heavily
criticises
the
use
of
master
words,
she
did
however
concede
to
the
idea
of
“strategic
essentialism”.
“Essentialism”
refers
to
the
belief
that
certain
people
or
entities
share
some
essential
nature
that
secures
their
membership
within
a
category.
In
the
1980’s
essentialism
was
the
target
of
feminist
criticism
because
activists
recognised
that
182
generalisations
about
women
inevitably
excluded
some
women.940
Spivak
suggested
that
it
was
important
to,
in
some
instances,
strategically
make
essentialist
claims,
whilst
being
aware
that
these
claims
were
at
best
crude
generalisations.941
An
example
is
the
publicising
of
the
feminisation
of
poverty.
This
refers
to
the
way
in
which
employment
practices,
wages
and
social
policies
ensure
that
in
many
societies
women
make
up
the
majority
of
poor
adults.942
Of
course
not
all
women
are
poor,
but
in
order
to
battle
the
poverty
of
some
women,
strategic
essentialism
can
highlight
the
gendered
nature
of
economic
inequality.943
Although
Spivak
later
disassociated
herself
from
the
notion
of
strategic
essentialism
because
she
felt
that
it
had
“been
taken
as
an
excuse
for
just
essentialism
which
is
an
excuse
for
just
identitarianism”,
she
still
argues,
in
the
same
text,
that
strategic
essentialism
can
work
as
a
context-‐specific
strategy,
but
it
cannot
provide
long-‐term
political
solutions
to
end
oppression
and
exploitation.944
In
the
context
of
Rancière’s
politics
some
claims,
rather
than
being
“essentialist”
claims,
would
be
“universal”
claims
and
rather
being
long-‐term
solutions,
would
overturn
the
sensible
logic,
which
can
have
a
number
of
effects
on
the
police
order.
Although
I
agree
with
the
notion
that
essentialist
claims
can
serve
to
silence
or
exclude,
it
might
be
interesting
to
ask
in
what
way
theorising
in
this
regard
serve
to
close
off
opportunities
or
occasions
for
a
politics
of
equality.
The
theoretical
point
might
be
that
the
claim
of
equality
that
occurs
under
a
universal
heading
or
under
a
master
word
is,
as
mentioned,
localised
and
temporary.
It
is
within
a
particular
scene
of
dissensus.
Although
this
scene
might
occur
under
a
universal
heading,
the
point
of
politics
is
not
to
make
claims
about
the
universal,
but
rather
to
break
it
apart.
It
involves
problematising,
from
different
angles,
the
dominant
police
interpretations
of
such
master
words
or
headings.
The
point
is
exactly
to
reject
the
implicit
assumptions
made
about
this
category
or
identity,
to
940
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2194.
941
As above.
942
As above.
943
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2195.
944
Chakravorty P et al Conversations with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (2006) 64.
183
disidentify
and
to
reconfigure
the
identity
category
in
a
different
way.
An
impossible
identification
is
an
identification
that
cannot
be
embodied
by
the
person/peoples
who
is
identifying
and
as
such
cannot
signify
a
coherent
collectivity.
Master
words
or
headings
are
names
with
sufficient
generality,
already
recognisable
within
a
dominant
discourse
and
as
such
they
can
be
given
new
content
through
politics.
What
matters
are
the
poetical
linguistic
configurations
that
occur
alongside
names
or
headings;
demonstrating
logical
argument,
demonstrating
another
world.
The
fact
that
these
master
words
are
already
part
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
means
they
can
actually
help
with
the
demonstration
of
an
argument
and
the
world
in
which
that
argument
counts.
Its
recognisability
is
what
can
help
to
make
it
legible.
However,
this
heading
or
name
under
politics
is
exactly
what
doesn’t
become
a
coherent
collectivity.
Although
it
might
be
recognisable
within
the
current
police
order
or
distribution
of
the
sensible,
its
police-‐meanings
become
contested.
Through
Rancière’s
lens,
in
the
moment
of
politics,
this
name
is
made
up
of
impossible,
confusing
identifications
that
become
incoherent
and
they
therefore
involve
the
“indetermination
of
identities,
the
delegitimation
of
speaking
positions,
the
deregulation
of
divisions
of
space
and
time.”945
Further,
Political-‐being-‐together
is
a
being-‐between:
between
identities,
between
worlds
[…]
between
several
names
[…].946
The
relevant
question
is:
can
the
name
or
the
master
word
facilitate
in
the
creation
of
a
polemical
scene?
Another
very
important
point
that
Spivak
refers
to
in
her
analysis
of
subalternity
is
the
idea
that
speaking
politically
becomes
problematic
when
considering
the
dominant
political
discourses
within
which
such
a
speech-‐act
occurs.
Spivak
refers
to
the
imperialistic,
patriarchal
and
elite
nationalist
discourses
in
India
in
her
discussion
of
sati
as
well
as
the
death
of
Bhubaneswari
Bhaduri
that
served
to
silence
women.
These
discourses
therefore
served
to
foreclose
any
possibility
of
945
Rancière J Partage du Sensible (2000) 15 as quoted in Hallward P in Rockhill G & Watts P
(eds.) (2009) 144.
946
Rancière J (1999) 137-138.
184
women
within
that
context
actually
speaking
or
making
their
voices
heard.
After
considering
Rancière’s
thought,
what
can
be
mentioned
and
reflected
upon
is
the
idea
that
there
are
always
useless,
supplementary
words
at
our
disposal.
As
mentioned
no
discourse
can
ever
obliterate
all
alternative
discourses.
For
Spivak
however,
the
discourses
of
western
imperialism
and
masculinity,
although
not
perfectly
aligned,
mutually
reinforce
the
oppression
of
non-‐white
peoples
and
especially
non-‐white
women.
Along
the
lines
of
Rancière’s
theorising,
this
may
be
viewed
in
the
light
of
Rancière’s
point
that
politics
is
always
a
renegotiation
of
the
police
order
we
must
live
in.
All
we
can
do
is
to
attempt
to
renegotiate
the
sensible
distribution.
However,
and
this
is
an
important
point,
such
a
renegotiation
is
possible.
It
does
not
mean
that
people
cannot
politically
speak.
The
point
is
exactly
that
there
are
more
words
at
our
disposal
and
Rancière’s
examples
show
that
a
contradiction
within
the
dominant
discourse
can
mobilise
an
obligation
to
hear.
My
discussion
of
Olympe
de
Gouges
within
the
next
chapter
takes
this
argument
further
to
illustrate
this
point.
The
dominant
language,
manipulated,
handled
and
redistributed
can
open
up
the
space
for
equality
to
be
declared
and
for
the
redistribution
of
the
given.
People
or
political
speech
acts
in
Rancière’s
view
of
them
aren’t
just
simply
within
a
dominant
discourse.
The
point
is
that
they
can
be
between
dominant
identities,
spaces
and
places
and
it
is
within
the
“in-‐between”
that
equality,
verified,
might
occur.
Further,
it
is
exactly
maybe
instances
of
the
naming
of
all-‐encompassing
discourses
and
the
idea
that
everything
is
an
after-‐effect
of
such
discourses
that
can
result
in
local
and
particular
struggles
declaring
equality
and
unique
in
complexity,
not
being
detected.
It
theoretically
positions
people
within
discursive
formations
that
they
cannot
escape
from.
Further,
Spivak
is
indeed
correct
in
stating
that
there
is
no
guarantee
that
the
claims
of
certain
groups
of
people
will
be
heard.
The
struggles
and
voices
of
oppressed
and
invisible
constituencies
more
often
than
not
fall
short
of
fully
authorised
political
speech.
This
is
exactly
Rancière’s
point
with
regards
to
politics,
that
is,
that
there
have
been
prior
decisions
of
who
will
be
heard
within
what
times
and
what
spaces
and
that
politics
is
at
once
the
entering
into
a
realm
185
of
visibility,
audibility
and
perceptibility.
Politics
for
Rancière
doesn’t
occur
often,
but
the
possibility
of
a
universal
equality
is
in
gestation
around
us
all
the
time.
The
possibility
of
laying
the
contingency
of
the
prior
decisions
bare
is
always
there
and
this
might
be
exactly
Rancière’s
invitation;
not
to
romanticise
everywhere
what
we
see
as
the
subaltern
“speaking”,
but
rather
to
continuously
contest
the
lines
of
sensible
intelligibility.
Spivak
further
warns
against
the
dangers
of
representation
and
she
highlights
that
even
the
most
benevolent
efforts
at
representation
can
result
in
silencing
the
people
that
is
(or
would
be)
represented.
She
illustrates
this
point
masterfully
with
the
colonial
impulse
to
“save
brown
women
from
brown
men”
and
equates
this
desire
to
the
desire
of
post-‐colonial
intellectuals
to
speak
for
certain
groups
of
people.
Representation
is
also
highly
problematic
for
Rancière.
For
him
it
enforces
the
inferiority
of
the
people
that
must
be
represented
by
others
who
can
think
“better”
or
do
things
better.
Within
these
efforts
lies
a
presumed
inferiority
and
dependency
on
those
with
the
expertise
to
represent
and
to
engage
in
politics.
Combating
inequality
on
behalf
of
others
assumed
to
be
incapable
of
emancipating
themselves
simply
reproduces
the
logic
of
subordination
or
inferiority.947
Further,
Rancière
highlights
the
fact
that
certain
intellectuals
rely
on
a
conceptualisation
of
the
poor
as
an
inert
mass
whose
passivity
is
the
sine
quo
non
of
its
would-‐be
representatives
whilst
Spivak
reminds
of
the
limited
and
potential
harmful
effects
of
representation
or
of
intellectuals
speaking
for
disempowered
groups.948
The
point
is
that
for
Rancière,
representation
dramatises
the
world
in
a
certain
way,
locating
voices
and
bodies
in
certain
locales,
times
and
places,
thereby
implicitly
making
assumptions
about
their
capacities.
It
is
important
to
mention
that
for
Rancière
people
can
meaningfully
organise
political
revolt
and
understand
their
circumstances
and
their
world
without
the
instruction
of
intellectuals,
or
anyone
for
that
matter.
On
this
point
Spivak
and
Rancière
seems
to
have
certain
similarities
in
their
theorising.
However,
the
point
that
Spivak
makes
with
reference
to
Deleuze
and
Foucault
is
947
See Tanke J (2011) 36.
948
Tanke J (2011) 31. See also Rancière J (2004) 48.
186
that
even
when
people
“speak
for
themselves”,
something
that
Rancière
would
insist
upon,
they
have,
along
the
lines
of
post-‐structuralist
thought
(that
Spivak
remains
heavily
influenced
by),
received
their
discursive
identities
within
dominant
structures
of
domination.
In
the
context
of
her
essay,
the
voices
or
speech
acts
of
women
are
so
embedded
in
Hindu
patriarchal
codes
of
moral
conduct
and
British
colonial
representation
that
this
speaking
is
impossible
to
recover.
Rancière,
on
the
contrary,
does
not
view
speech
acts
as
ideological
artefacts
or
as
after
effects
of
dominant
discourses,
rather
he
takes
these
acts
on
the
surface
of
things,
as
an
act
that
can
reconfigure
the
situation
in
which
it
is
enunciated.
This
position
has
to
do
with
Rancière’s
rejection
of
post-‐structuralism
in
general.
Rancière
refuses
to
theorise
“the
subject”,
rather
focussing
on
the
process
of
subjectivation
as
the
process
of
making
other
or
impossible
identifications
in
the
precarious
temporality
of
politics.949
His
position
rather
points
to
temporary
and
unstable
subject
positions.
Rancière
rejects
notions
of
theorising
subjects
as
well
as
the
notion
that
speech
acts
are
effects
of
discourse
as
for
him
such
notions
contain
implicit
assumptions
about
the
capacities
of
people
and
who
and
what
can
appear
in
what
times
and
places;
and
what’s
more,
these
notions
can
produce
imposing
counter-‐discourses
of
subject
formation.950
949
The term “subject” is usually used in work deriving from continental philosophy, the
psychoanalysis of Jacques Lacan and the Marxism of Louis Althusser. See Macey D (2000) 203
& 368-369. It points towards all those descriptions of decentering that displace the source of
meaning away from “the individual” and towards structures, impersonal or unconscious
processes and ideology. See Macey D (2000) 203 & 368-369. For most of these theories the
individual is a product rather than a source of meaning. Rancière’s refusal to theorise the
subject is also closely related to his criticism of Althusserianism. Althusser uses “ the subject”
in a broadly similar way to Lacan (“the subject” is the subject of the unconscious and it is
therefore the subject that enters into the dimension of the symbolic which produces a
splitting or decentering of the subject by subordinating it to the laws of language). See
Macey D (2000) 203 & 368-369. For Althusser “the subject” does not exist prior to its
interpellation, but is summoned into its being by it. The process of interpellation refers to the
mechanisms that produces subjects in such a way that they recognise their own existence in
terms of the dominant ideology of the society in which they live. The idea of interpellation
demonstrates that subjects are always already the products of ideology. See Macey D (2000)
203 & 368-369.
950
See for example Dasgupta S “Words, bodies, time: Queer theory before and after itself”
Borderlands (2009) 1-20. In this article the author demonstrates in what way the critiques of
identity in the context of queer theory have served to created counter-discourses of subject-
formation.
187
Further,
as
Rancière
illustrates
with
his
discussions
of
Gauny
and
the
worker-‐
poets,
speech-‐acts
are
never
simply
straightforward
(whether
seen
as
a
discursive
product
or
not).
The
redistribution
of
the
sensible
is
not
just
about
an
utterance
that
is
heard
or
not
heard
as
political
speech.
It
is
rather
about
words,
bodies
and
actions
in
places
that
all
combine
polemically.
Gauny
best
illustrates
this
example
where
time
and
place
becomes
as
important
than
specific
utterances
or
speech-‐
acts.
The
worker
poets,
it
is
interesting
to
note,
borrowed
words,
images
and
speeches
from
the
elite
bourgeois
intellectual
discourse
of
their
time.
However,
the
manifestation
of
their
will
to
transgress
the
limits
of
the
discourse
that
would
see
them
as
workers
(with
only
time
to
work
and
their
bodies
incarnating
the
worker’s
revolution)
violates
the
very
“order
of
discourse”.951
Rancière
states
the
following
with
regards
to
their
writing:
By
stealing
away
to
wander
aimlessly
without
knowing
who
to
speak
to
or
what
to
speak
to,
writing
destroys
every
legitimate
foundation
for
the
circulation
of
words,
for
the
relationship
between
the
effects
of
language
and
the
positions
of
bodies
in
shared
space.952
The
worker-‐poets
with
their
borrowed
intellectual
words,
images
and
notions,
by
not
staying
put
and
simply
working
and
taking
pride
in
that
work,
but
by
writing;
acts
in
the
complete
opposite
to
the
discourse
that
would
name
them
as
workers.
The
idea
that
voices
are
so
embedded
in
the
discourse
that
would
oppress
them
and
produce
identities
(which
these
people
cannot
know,
but
cannot
help
to
manifest
with
their
words
and
actions)
comes
down
to
a
counter-‐discourse
that
would
lock
them
up
in
a
specific
distribution
of
the
sensible,
a
specific
“the
way
things
are”.
This
is
Rancière’s
objection.
The
worker
poets
borrow
words
and
images
and
speeches
and
notions
from
the
dominant
bourgeois
intellectual
discourse
or
paradigm,
effectively
taking
aspects
of
it
on,
but,
the
relationship
between
those
words
and
their
bodies
in
specific
(or
other)
times
and
places
reconfigures
and
destabilises
the
dominant
discourse
on
workers
completely.
Therefore,
for
Rancière
the
situation
is
more
complex
and
it
is
not
about
speech-‐
acts
or
voices
as
products
of
discursive
identities,
but
rather
about
the
“counter-‐
951
See Rancière J La Parole Ouvrière: 1830-1851 (1976) as reference in Dasgupta S
Borderlands (2008) 8.
952
Rancière J (2004) 13.
188
intuitive
relation
between
bodies
and
worlds”
or
the
“disembodiment
of
‘the
people’
from
the
discourse
that
produces
it”.953
It
should
be
mentioned
that
the
discussion
above
is
not
to
suggest
that
we
should
not
attempt
analyse
the
discourses
that
efface
the
possibility
of
speaking.
Indeed,
Rancière
states
that
the
distinction
between
the
police
order
and
politics
can
help
us
discern
how
politics
encroaches
on
matters
of
the
police
and
the
police
on
matters
of
politics.
We
can
understand
the
form
of
their
intertwinement.954
However,
such
theorising
should
not
create
counter-‐discourses
that
prescribe
who
can
do
what
in
what
times
and
places,
nor
should
it
diminish
the
complexity
of
matters
of
the
spatio-‐temporal
actions
of
bodies
that
disrupt
and
overturn
the
order
of
the
discourses
that
surround
them.
Another
point
that
can
be
discussed
with
regards
to
representation
is
Spivak’s
insistence
on
the
idea
that
representation
as
aesthetic
portrait
and
representation
by
political
proxy
should
not
be
conflated.
The
representation
of
people
as
coherent
subjects
should
not
be
taken
as
transparent
expressions
of
their
political
desires
and
interests.
With
regards
to
Rancière’s
politics,
Citton
makes
an
interesting
point.
He
argues
that
in
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics,
representation
does
occur,
but
it
is
the
political
subjects
themselves
who
is
involved
in
these
representations.955
Citton
elucidates:
Rancière
thus
answers
Gayatri
Spivak’s
question:
yes,
within
certain
historical
junctures,
the
subaltern
can
speak.
These
moments
are
relatively
rare
[…]
but
it
has
occurred
in
the
past
[…].
Subalterns
however,
in
Rancière’s
theatrical
politics,
never
speak
directly
for
themselves:
it
is
they
who
speak,
but
they
do
so
from
under
a
mask
that
they
have
painted
upon
their
face,
from
under
a
costume
they
have
collectively
designed
for
themselves,
on
a
carnivalesque
stage
they
are
building
with
each
of
their
interventions.956
Dasgupta S Borderlands (2009) 8.
953
189
Citton
therefore
refers
to
the
inner
distance
and
separation
between
the
representative
and
the
represented,
even
when
both
are
located
within
the
same
body.957
He
refers
to
the
persona,
or
the
acting
“as
if”
that
Rancièrian
political
subjects
stage
during
politics,
which
is
brought
on
by
the
making
of
impossible
and
paradoxical
identifications.
The
point
is
that
people
can
pose
as
things
they
are
not;
they
can
act
as
if
they
have
the
equality
they
have
not
and
according
to
Rancière,
as
mentioned,
what
is
staged
is
not
an
identity,
but
a
gap
between
the
“we”
and
“the
people”
in
whose
name
the
“we”
purports
to
speak.
From
one
point
of
view,
it
can
appear
that
Spivak’s
claim
that
the
subaltern
is
a
discursive
effect
removes
the
very
ground
for
effective
political
struggle.
Indeed,
Neil
Lazarus
argues
that
Spivak
is
not
really
concerned
with
“native
agency
[…]
but
[rather
with]
a
theory
of
the
way
in
which
the
social
and
symbolic
practice
of
the
disenfranchised
elements
of
native
population
are
represented
(or
rather
not
represented)
in
colonialist
elitist
discourse”.958
It
is
therefore
argued
that
what
Spivak
focuses
on
is
not
so
much
examples
of
the
struggles
of
people
or
groups,
but
rather
the
way
in
which
intellectuals
construct
groups
and
speaking
positions
and
it
is
within
this
context
that
the
subaltern
cannot
speak.
In
her
essay,
she
insightfully
demonstrates
how
subaltern
women
have
no
discursive
space
from
which
to
speak
in
the
context
of
sati
and
the
suicide
Bhubaneswari
Bhaduri.
However,
she
goes
on
to
emphasise
that
not
only
is
there
no
discursive
space
that
can
emerge
from
which
the
subaltern
could
formulate
an
“utterance”,
but
also
that
“no
scene
of
speaking”
can
arise
for
the
subaltern
women
(the
example
that
she
usually
uses
are
economically
marginalised
third
world
women).959
It
is
within
this
regard
that
Spivak
has
been
criticised
for
contributing
in
the
silencing
of
third
world
women.960
From
a
Rancièrian
point
of
view
the
question
that
can
be
asked
is
to
what
extent
does
such
a
description
close
off
opportunities
for
the
detection
of
instances
of
the
verification
of
equality
and
to
what
extent
it
involves
making
957
As above.
958
See Lazarus N Nationalism and Cultural Practice in a Postcolonial World (1999) 112.
959
Shetty S & Bellamy E “Postcolonialism’s archive fever” Diacritics (2000) 25-48.
960
See for example Parry B Oxford Literary Review (1992) 27-58.
190
assumptions
about
the
bodies
of
people,
in
this
case
the
bodies
of
subaltern
women?
For
Rancière,
descriptions
that
lock
people
up
in
certain
discourses
and
that
sees
them
theoretically
positioned
within
a
specific
time,
place,
discourse
and
capacity,
is
as
damaging
as
the
objectification
or
romanticising
of
people
or
others.
Further,
as
mentioned
above,
Spivak’s
suggests
that
intellectuals
should
engage
with
the
social
texts
and
histories
of
subalterns
through
deconstructive
and
careful
reading
strategies
so
as
to
ensure
an
ethical
engagement.
Such
readings
can
help
us
to
refrain
from
the
objectification
or
romanticisation
of
subalterns.
From
a
Rancièrian
point
of
view,
this
will
only
serve
a
“discourse
of
mastery
and
the
logic
of
hidden
truths.”961
Spivak
will
become
here
“the
master
who
knows”
how
to
theorise
the
conditions
that
oppress
subalterns
and
how
to
put
forth
a
more
situated
articulation
of
particular
subaltern
histories.
And
it
is
these
particular
deconstructive
readings
that
will
do
justice
(as
much
justice
as
can
be
done)
to
the
lives
and
struggles
of
specific
subalterns,
especially
third
world
women.
What
becomes
apparent
here
is
again
a
notion
of
the
“the
way
things
are”.
It
can
also
be
asked
to
what
extent
this
theorising
serves
to
divide
the
world
up
into
people
that
can
do
deconstructive
readings
and
communicate
to
others
the
conditions
of
their
own
oppression
and
domination
and
those
that
must
be
told
about
their
own
conditions
of
oppression,
or,
those
who
know
how
to
ethically
engage
with
material
and
subaltern
peoples
and
those
who
do
not?
Although
Spivak’s
call
for
an
ethical
engagement
with
certain
materials
and
subaltern
struggles
is
well
intentioned
and
important,
Rancière’s
thought
might
be
able
to
add
an
extra
element
or
question
when
it
comes
to
the
engagement
with
social
texts
and
histories:
To
what
extent
it
is
thought
under
the
condition
of
an
egalitarian
maxim,
in
a
relationship
with
ignorance
so
as
to
open
up
and
create
new
space
for
equality.962
961
Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2000) 2.
962
See Badiou A “The Lessons of Jacques Rancière” in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2000) 48.
191
If
we
had
to
answer
the
question
that
Spivak
poses
in
the
title
of
her
essay
through
the
lens
of
Rancière
politics,
it
has
to
be
yes:
The
subaltern
can
speak;
temporarily,
rare
and
localised,
she
can
within
certain
circumstances
tear
words
from
her
body
in
other
spaces
and
times,
giving
incoherent,
confusing
and
paradoxical
content
to
names
of
sufficient
generality,
disembodied
from
the
discourses
that
produce
her.
For
Spivak,
the
subaltern
discursively
formed
and
as
effect
of
dominant
political
and
economic
discourse
cannot
be
“a
sovereign
political
subject
in
control
of
her
own
destiny”.963
For
Rancière,
the
subaltern
can
meaningfully
know
her
own
circumstances
and
conditions
and
have
“voice”
and
it
is
only
under
the
assumption
that
she
is
in
control
of
her
own
destiny
that
we
can
“take
seriously
the
equality
that,
at
various
points
in
history,
has
been
declared,
and
[…]
act
relentlessly
from
within
the
sensible
mode
of
being
that
challenges
the
distribution
of
the
sensible”.964
4.5
Conclusion
In
reflecting
on
the
notion
of
voice
against
the
background
sketched
in
the
first
chapter,
what
becomes
significant
in
Spivak’s
analysis
is
her
highlighting
of
the
discourses
of
masculinity
and
patriarchy.
She
emphasises
that
when
it
comes
to
the
voice
of
women,
especially
those
in
the
global
South
that
are
impoverished,
these
discourses
will
have
an
impact
on
whether
women
can
be
heard
politically.
Women
in
South
African
society
suffer
under
highly
traditional
and
patriarchal
cultures.
This
becomes
evident
when
considering
the
number
of
rapes
perpetrated
against
women
and
their
persistent
economic
inequality.
The
sensible
distributions
of
masculinity
and
patriarchy
point
to
South
African
women
truly
being
doubly
in
the
shadow.
What
therefore
becomes
valuable
in
Spivak’s
postulations
in
her
famous
essay
is
the
fact
that
she
highlights
that
when
it
comes
to
voice,
non-‐white
women
in
the
post-‐colonial
settings
experience
a
particular
set
of
difficulties.
More
recently,
Spivak
has
vocalised
her
criticism
of
global
963
Morton S (2003) 53.
964
De Boever A “Feminism after Rancière: Women in J.M. Coetzee and Jeff Wall”
Transformations (2011) “The Politics of Photography”.
192
developmental
policies
that
focus
on
women
in
the
so-‐called
third
world.965
Spivak
has
warned
against
the
rhetoric
of
United
Nations
declarations
on
women’s
rights
that
seem
to
confuse
access
to
global
telecommunications
and
the
right
to
bear
credit
with
women’s
political
empowerment
as
such.
For
Spivak,
the
rhetoric
on
women’s
rights
paradoxically
overlooks
the
poorest
women
of
the
South,
the
very
women
the
United
Nations
are
claiming
to
represent.966
It
is
argued
that
the
imperial
project
today
is
mainly
interested
in
liberating
women
for
labour,
which
refers
to
“surplus
value
extraction”.967
Human
rights
have
often
provided
the
alibi
for
this
process.968
Against
the
background
of
South
African
policy
directives
on
gender
equality
and
women’s
rights
these
arguments
become
significant.
Spivak’s
analysis,
just
as
Rancière’s
formulation
of
the
police
order,
helps
to
ask
to
what
extent
the
mechanisms
of
human
rights
and
gender
equality
contributes
to
the
maintenance
of
the
status
quo,
rather
than
contributing
to
the
creation
of
spaces
where
voices
can
be
revealed.
Ultimately
Spivak’s
essay
points
to
the
notion
of
a
gendered
muting
of
political
voice,
denoting
how
the
voices
of
women
within
certain
conditions
are
effaced
by
the
surrounding
discourses
of
the
police
order.
She
therefore
also
draws
our
attention
to
the
way
in
which
voice
hinges
on
the
practices
of
listening,
responding,
interpreting
and
qualifying.
She
also
underlines
the
dangers
and
problems
with
identity
categories
and
political
representation
and
the
fact
that
“speaking”
or
voice
already
belongs
to
an
existing
structure
of
domination
and
it
is
from
within
this
formulation
that
she
argues
that
the
subaltern
cannot
speak.
As
mentioned
above,
if
one
has
to
answer
the
question
of
whether
the
subaltern
can
speak
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
politics,
the
answer
would
be
yes.
A
reading
of
Spivak’s
essay
from
Rancière’s
perspective
opens
up
the
question
and
her
proposed
answer
to
contestation
and
dispute.
My
reading
of
Spivak’s
essay
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
politics
points
to
the
fact
that
the
subaltern
can
965
Morton S (2003) 138-139.
966
As above.
967
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 7.
968
As above.
193
speak
through
radical
forms
of
equality.
One
of
Spivak’s
important
points
in
her
essay
is
her
warning
of
the
use
of
master
words
or
identity
categories
that
can
serve
to
exclude
and
silence
others,
or
erase
the
differences
between
people
when
a
coherent
political
identity
is
attached
to
groups
of
individuals.
Rancière’s
formulations
demonstrate
how
certain
so-‐called
universal
names
for
a
“we”
can
become
a
heading
under
which
equality
is
declared.
It
can
become
a
name
under
which
people
can
tear
away
their
bodies
from
police
order
assigned
positions.
The
relevant
point
is
how
equality
manifests
under
these
headings
or
even
master
words.
Politics
is
rare,
temporary,
provincial
and
localised
and
rather
than
being
about
identity
or
the
name
under
which
equality
is
declared,
it
is
about
disidentification,
the
indetermination
of
identities
and
the
delegitimation
of
speaking
positions.
For
Spivak
the
presence
of
certain
conditions,
specifically
imperialist,
masculinist
and
patriarchal
discourses
means
that
these
discourses
mutually
reinforce
oppression
and
therefore
efface
the
possibility
of
women
speaking.
From
a
Rancièrian
point
of
view
one
might
react
by
stating
that
when
it
comes
to
voice,
we
can
only
renegotiate
the
police
order
and
its
distribution
of
the
sensible
that
we
must
live
in.
However,
the
possibility
of
the
declaration
of
equality
is
in
gestation
around
us
all
the
time
and
these
declarations
can
have
a
number
of
effects
on
the
police
order
and
in
certain
cases
mobilise
an
obligation
to
hear.
The
point
is
not
that
we
can
somehow
be
beyond
or
outside
of
the
limits
of
dominant
language
or
discourse,
but
rather
that
the
order
of
discourse
can
be
overturned.
The
dominant
discourse,
handled
correctly
and
manipulated
can
give
rise
to
paradoxical,
confusing
identities
in
the
in-‐between
of
names
and
worlds.
When
it
comes
to
the
possibility
of
voice,
the
question
is
not
simply
about
the
way
in
which
discourses
work
to
efface
voice,
but
rather
also
about
the
disembodiment
of
the
subaltern
from
the
discourses
that
produce
her.
Speech
acts
are
never
merely
ideological
artefacts
or
after
effects
of
the
dominant
discourse,
they
are
also
acts
that
can
renegotiate
the
situation
in
which
they
are
enunciated
-‐
the
way
in
which
words,
bodies,
actions,
places
and
times
combine
polemically
in
the
precarious
temporality
of
politics
can
renegotiate
the
sensible
of
a
situation.
From
a
Rancièrian
point
of
view,
the
assertion
that
subaltern
women
within
certain
conditions
and
junctures
cannot
speak,
is
to
lock
the
194
subaltern
up
in
a
counter
discourse,
in
a
position
where
she
is
defined
by
the
discourses
that
surround
her.
The
question
that
becomes
relevant
is
to
what
extent
such
a
theorising
closes
off
opportunities
for
a
politics
of
equality.
With
regards
to
the
reading
above,
it
should
be
mentioned
that
Rancière
should
not
be
read
as
to
suggest
that
if
we
just
look
hard
enough,
politics
and
declarations
of
equality
could
be
found
everywhere.
This
is
contrary
to
Rancière’s
project.
As
mentioned,
moments
of
politics
are
rare
for
Rancière.
The
moments
within
which
the
sensible
is
distributed
do
not
happen
every
day.
However,
it
is
possible.
Equality
has
been
declared
at
various
points
in
history
and
importantly:
Political
statements
[…]
produce
effects
in
reality.
They
define
models
of
speech
or
action
but
also
regimes
of
sensible
intensity.
They
draft
maps
of
the
visible,
trajectories
between
the
visible
and
sayable,
relationships
between
modes
of
being,
modes
of
saying,
and
modes
of
doing
and
making
[…]
They
thereby
take
hold
of
unspecified
groups
of
people,
they
widen
gaps,
open
up
space
for
deviations,
modify
speeds,
the
trajectories
and
the
ways
in
which
groups
of
people
adhere
to
a
condition,
react
to
situations,
recognise
their
images.969
Ultimately,
reading
Spivak’s
essay
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
politics
results
in
a
shift
in
the
question
that
she
poses
in
the
title
of
her
essay.
Rather
than
“Can
the
subaltern
speak?”
Rancière’s
politics
points
to
“If
the
subaltern
could
speak,
what
would
she
say?”
This
shift
does
not
represent
a
way
of
speaking
for
the
subaltern
or
coming
to
a
definitive
conclusion
about
what
she
would
say.
But,
rather
than
closing
off
possibilities
of
voice,
this
question
points
to
the
basic
spirit
of
Rancière’s
politics
namely,
the
assertion
of
the
rights
to
the
imagination
-‐
against
theoretical
limits.
In
the
next
chapter,
I
attempt
to
map
and
trace
some
redistributions
of
the
sensible.
The
figures
that
I
explore
blur
political
boundaries
and
overturn
their
distinctive
frameworks.
My
aim
is
to
contemplate
their
significance
and
meaning
as
a
way
of
thinking
through
political
voice.
969
Rancière J (2004) 30.
195
CHAPTER
5
Practicing
a
“Method
of
Equality”:
Reacting
Against
Sensible
Intelligibility
5.1
Introduction
In
this
chapter
I
discuss
some
examples
of
political
statements
and
historical
and
literary
figures.
The
discussion
of
these
examples
is
not
only
a
reaction
against
the
difficulties
surrounding
voice
outlined
in
chapter
one,
but
it
is
also
a
way
of
considering
further
possibilities
of
voice.
These
examples
can
be
regarded
as
declarations
of
equality
and
as
reconfigurations
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
The
examples
that
I
explore
are:
the
figure
of
Olympe
De
Gouges
that
Rancière
uses
to
illustrate
some
of
his
arguments
on
politics;
the
character
of
Lucy
in
J.M
Coetzee’s
novel
Disgrace;
the
figure
of
Bhaduri
Bhubaneswari
invoked
in
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”;
and
comments
and
political
statements
made
by
the
South
African
Shack-‐dweller’s
Movement.970
I
read
these
historical
and
literary
figures
and
statements
from
the
perspective
of
Rancière’s
politics
in
order
to
contemplate
their
meaning
and
significance
as
it
relates
to
the
idea
of
political
voice.
This
chapter
represents
a
way
of
thinking
through
the
theory
discussed
in
the
previous
chapters
and
I
also
discuss
these
figures
so
as
to
expand
certain
lines
of
thinking
or
to
form
new
relations
of
the
visible
and
sayable.
Writing
itself,
as
mentioned,
is
a
way
of
expanding
perception
and
these
discussions
therefore
become
a
way
of
disrupting
certain
forms
of
organisation
or
they
can
also
be
considered
as
a
way
of
making
use
of
a
democratic
writing
practice
as
explained
in
the
chapter
three.971
I
also
employ
or
practice
a
“method
of
equality”
along
the
lines
of
Rancière’s
description
of
politics.
Before
ensuing
with
the
exploration
of
the
literary
characters
and
figures,
I
shed
some
light
on
what
a
“method
of
equality”
entails.
970
Rancière J “Who is The Subject of the Rights of Man?” South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 103,
JM Coetzee Disgrace (1999), Abahlali baseMondjolo (South African Shack-dweller’s
Movement) (See Abahlali.org. (accessed 28/12/2014)), Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L
(1988) 313.
971
See section 3.4 above.
196
In
her
discussion
of
Rancière’s
argument
for
a
democratic
research
practice
in
the
context
of
methodological
debates
in
the
social
sciences,
Caroline
Pelletier
gives
some
direction
of
what
a
method
of
equality
might
look
like.972
She
indicates
how
Rancière’s
writings
frame
research
as
a
particular
kind
of
enterprise
namely,
to
make
visible
what
has
been
denied
and
to
argue
with
widely
used
systems
of
categorisation
in
order
to
enact
equality.973
In
his
writings
Rancière
aims
to
defend
the
possibility
of
politics
on
the
basis
of
the
equality
of
speaking
beings.974
Pelletier
explains
that
Rancière
has
critiqued
the
social
sciences
by
referring
to
what
he
calls
the
“aesthetics
of
knowledge”.975
He
discusses
the
ways
in
which
discourses
of
knowledge
or
discourses
that
claim
to
know
the
world
(including
research
accounts),
constitute
themselves
as
coherent,
valid
and
credible
972
Pelletier C International Journal of Research and Method in Education (2009) 253-248.
Published online 10 November 2009 available at Taylor and Francis Online-
www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/17437270903259741?journalCode=cwse20. The pages
referenced are the pages as cited within the online publication. Pelletier reviews the
significance of Rancière’s work for methodological debates in the social sciences. She
explores the implications of framing methodology as an aesthetic endeavor, rather than as
the applied technique of research. For Pelletier, what is at stake in this distinction is the
means by which research intervenes in a social order and how it assumes political
significance. Pelletier situates Rancière’s argument for a democratic research practice
organised around a “method of equality” in relation to openly ideological feminist
ethnography.
973
Pelletier C (2009) 4.
974
Pelletier C (2009) 3. Rancière’s position here, as Pelletier notes, is not relativistic in the
sense of all claims to knowledge being equally valid. It is rather a defense of the possibility of
politics on the basis of the equality of speaking beings. Making this equality visible means
interrogating the basis on which discourses legitimate themselves as epistemologically
superior to one another. Pelletier explains further that this is the basis of Rancière’s
accusation against the paradigm of social science, which defines its object of study in terms
of its social attributes (gender, ethnicity, occupation and so on) or position in the social order
(Pelletier C (2009) 3). This order is unequal precisely because it is an ordering. Therefore,
Pelletier explains, by defining its object in terms of its social attributes, social science restricts
its object of study to its social location and effectively denies the possibility of collectivity on
the basis of a lack of social attributes or on the basis of equality as Rancière defines it. See
Pelletier C (2009) 3. So-called “reflexive” social science discourses that address the problems
of “critical theory” by being aware of and announcing and recognising their own location in
the social order, simply reconfirms (from the perspective of Rancière) its hegemony, or its lack
of difference from itself. The solution is not to reflect on the sociological location of one’s
own position or scientific discourse, but rather by challenging the “equivalence established
between discourse and social location in both the object and the subject of study”. See
Pelletier C (2009) 3.
975
See Rancière J “Thinking between disciplines: An aesthetics of knowledge” Parrhesia
(2006) 1-12.
197
accounts
in
opposition
to
“ignorance
or
forms
of
ignorance”.976
As
Pelletier
explains,
Rancière
puts
forth
the
following
question:
When
knowledge
is
proffered,
what
form
of
ignorance
is
thereby
produced?977
Pelletier
asks
further:
When
social
science
research
accounts
claim
to
generate
scientific
knowledge
of
social
groups,
how
do
they
generate
a
category
of
research
accounts
that
are
non-‐scientific?978
What
role
is
therefore
ascribed
to
ignorance
or
non-‐science
and
under
what
condition
is
ignorance/non-‐science
transformed
into
knowledge?979
Pelletier
elucidates:
“[I]gnorance”
here
is
not
clearly
defined
in
terms
of
the
bad
thing
which
science
fights
to
eradicate,
but
is
instead
treated
as
a
necessary
corollary
of
knowledge
production
insofar
as
knowledge
implies
a
certain
relation
to
ignorance.980
In
this
regard,
Rancière
refers
to
two
traditions
that
created
the
occasion
for
him
to
develop
his
own
working
method
against
traditional
knowledge
production
and
research.
A
central
question
to
both
of
these
traditions,
as
Pelletier
explains,
is
how
can
someone
at
a
particular
time
and
place
perceive
their
world?981
One
way
of
answering
this
question
is
in
relation
to
ideology
as
described
in
Marxism,
which
refers
to
a
set
of
false
beliefs.
This
is
the
first
tradition.
I
elaborated
on
Rancière’s
objections
in
this
regard
in
the
second
chapter
of
this
research.
In
this
section,
I
focus
on
the
second
tradition,
or
second
way
of
answering
the
question.
The
second
tradition
refers
to
as
a
set
of
practices,
which,
post-‐Althusser,
bring
“about
false
judgments,
perceptions,
sensibilities
and
actions”.982
Pelletier
explains
that
in
the
latter
tradition
“false”
does
not
mean
untrue,
but
rather
refers
to
that
which
sustains
domination
or
dispossession.983
This
distribution
of
domination,
which
Rancière
traces
from
German
ideology
to
Pierre
Bourdieu’s
entire
corpus,
sees
that
people
are
characterised
as
having
only
certain
976
Pelletier C (2009) 5.
977
As above.
978
As above.
979
As above.
980
As above.
981
As above.
982
As above.
983
As above.
198
perceptions.984
These
perceptions
are
determined
by
their
place
in
society
and
by
their
incapacity
to
“see”
or
to
name/signify/know
their
place
within
the
social
order.
In
other
words,
“the
perceptions
are
determined
by
their
ignorance
of
the
means
and
fact
of
their
domination”.985
Pelletier
explains
that
within
this
critical
tradition
what
is
produced
is
precisely
the
ignorance
of
domination
and
its
corresponding
reasons.986
Pelletier
notes
that
what
the
social
order
therefore
produces
is
ignorance
of
how
the
social
order
really,
in
essence,
works.
To
make
this
claim
means
that
one
must
remove
oneself
from
that
social
order
or
extricate
oneself
from
the
source
of
ignorance.
This
is
how
Rancière
reads
Bourdieu’s
concept
of
reflexivity
for
example;
it
partitions
knowledge
from
ignorance
by
placing
knowledge
as
that
which
is
in
difference
to
the
social
order
and
then
claims
ignorance
as
the
object
of
knowledge.987
Pelletier
explains
that
Rancière
treats
Bourdieu’s
discourse
as
“performative”
rather
than
descriptive
in
the
sense
that
“ignorance
or
the
logic
of
practice
which
Bourdieu’s
discourse
posits,
exists
in
the
first
instance
as
a
product
of
that
discourse”.988
This
type
of
figuration
of
984
Pelletier explains that the second tradition that Rancière seeks to counter focuses not so
much on the incorporation of domination as on the finding of “a true and authentic popular
culture defined in terms of its autonomy from dominant values”. See Pelletier C (2009) 6. The
target of his readings in this tradition is social histories produced in the 1970’s and 1980’s,
which conceptualised a “working class culture in terms of resistance or agency”. See Pelletier
C (2009) 6. Celebrations of popular authenticity, he suggests, function as injunctions that
“popular people” should remain authentic to their own culture and by implication avoid
becoming tainted by middle-class “intellectualism”- or what he calls “exclusion by homage”.
See Rancière J (2004) xxiv. Pelletier explains that Rancière’s argument here suggests that
when “intellectual” readings by “popular people” are classified as “popular ventriloquism”
what is effectively claimed is the incapacity of “popular people” to think “authentically” (See
Pelletier C (2009) 6). Popular people are therefore granted their “own” domain of knowledge
and this is all for the better to preserve the domain of “intellectual knowledge” from
intrusions by non-scientists. See Pelletier C (2009) 6. Popular knowledge is therefore defined
in opposition to science. In other words, “it is constituted by ignorance of science”. See
Pelletier C (2009) 6. See also Rancière J (2004) xxiv and Bourdieu P (1991). As Davis explains,
Rancière’s dispute with Bourdieu’s work on pedagogy and aesthetics is extremely involved.
See Davis O (2010) 22-25. Rancière reacts against the sociologist’s self-interest and he is at
times unforgiving in his commentary in this regard. I do not explain his engagement with
Bourdieu here as it goes beyond the scope of explaining a method of equality. For a general
discussion on Rancière’s engagement with Bourdieu, see Davis O (2010) 22-25.
985
Pelletier C (2009) 5.
986
As above.
987
As above.
988
As above.
199
domination
creates
a
domain
of
knowledge
from
which
the
ignorant
are,
by
definition,
excluded.
Pelletier
explains
that:
Rancière
reads
the
modelling
of
ineluctable
social
reproduction
in
Bourdieu’s
discourse
not
as
a
description
of
the
state
of
affairs,
but
as
a
performative
securitisation
of
a
domain
of
knowledge.
Sociological
discourse
can
safely
critique
domination
whilst
“knowing”
it
can
never
change,
since
this
knowing
is
precisely
of
other
people’s
ignorance.989
Rancière’s
concern
is
that
this
tradition
claims
knowledge
of
“the
poor”
on
the
basis
of
“the
poor’s”
ignorance.
Or
as
phrased
by
Ross,
Rancière
points
to
the
fact
that
the
scientist
gives
himself
the
task
“of
speaking
for
those
who’s
presumed
ignorance
grants
[him
his]
domain”.990
This
notion
is
of
course
captured
by
the
title
of
Rancière’s
book
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor.
For
Rancière,
such
theorisation
is
effected
in
the
alignment
between
sensibilities
(judgments,
perceptions,
ways
of
doing,
being,
seeing,
saying)
and
social
location.
Therefore,
as
Pelletier
explains
further,
what
is
claimed
is
that
people
in
a
social
location
can
only
“be”
in
a
way
that
is
determined
by
their
social
location.991
This
ordering
establishes
“stable
relations
between
states
of
the
body
and
the
modes
of
perception
and
signification
which
correspond
to
them.”992
Pelletier
explains
further
that
this
ordering
sets
the
scene
for
a
dramatisation
that
ensures
that
a
certain
location
coincides
with
a
certain
type
of
thought.993
As
we
have
seen
in
the
previous
chapters,
Rancière
rejects
notions
of
determined
locales,
positions
and
times
that
correspond
with
specific
bodies
and
voices.
The
“aesthetics
of
knowledge”
refers
to
the
way
in
which
discourse
performatively
divides
the
world
into
people
who
speak
and
people
who
merely
ventriloquize,
people
who
can
think
the
social
order
and
people
who
can
only
obey
its
logic,
people
who
can
contribute
to
discussions
about
how
society
should
be
organised
and
people
who
are
too
caught
up
in
their
own
economic
occupation/culture
to
apply
themselves
authentically
to
the
affairs
of
society.994
989
As above.
990
Ross K “Introduction” in Rancière J (1991) xviii.
991
Pelletier C (2009) 5.
992
Rancière J Parrhesia (2006) 9.
993
Pelletier C (2009) 6.
994
Pelletier C (2009) 7.
200
Pelletier
explains
that
“knowing”
a
situation
of
domination
can
therefore
become
a
way
of
participating
in
it.995
What
is
submitted
in
this
distribution
of
knowledge
and
ignorance
is
the
idea
that
the
objects
of
science
(the
poor)
can
do
nothing
else
than
that
which
has
already
been
ordered
by
science
-‐
a
science
which,
as
Pelletier
explains,
is
precisely
a
knowledge
of
domination.996
Knowledge
is
therefore
aesthetic
in
that
a
research-‐based
account
dramatises
the
world
in
a
particular
way.997
It
constitutes
an
act,
a
way
of
configuring
and
dividing
the
domain
of
the
sensible.
Knowledge/scientific
statements
produce
effects
that
draft
maps
of
the
visible,
trajectories
between
the
visible
and
the
sayable,
relationships
between
modes
of
being,
modes
of
saying
and
modes
of
doing
and
making.998
The
question
that
arises
is
how
one
is
suppose
to
practice
equality
in
one’s
own
writing
without
establishing
this
type
of
relationship
between
ignorance
and
knowledge.
Firstly,
as
Pelletier
explains,
the
verification
of
equality
has
little
to
do
with
“respecting”
the
words
of
others
or
trusting
their
rationality
or
even
celebrating
their
existence.999
It
is
therefore
not
a
matter
of
being
faithful
to
the
content.
It
is
about
declassifying
words
and
re-‐ordering
the
way
in
which
words
take
on
meaning
through
a
category
or
body
to
which
they
are
assigned
in
the
social
order.1000
This
includes
the
time
and
place
of
utterances
and
the
activity
to
which
these
utterances
are
related.
Pelletier
elucidates:
It
is
about
reading/producing
words
against
the
guarantees,
or
modes
of
legitimation,
offered
by
the
social
location
of
the
speaker.
One
can
for
instance
treat
scientific
statements
as
literary
prose,
opinion
as
philosophy,
and
historical
words
as
speaking
in
the
present,
in
the
texture
of
the
historian’s
narration.1001
995
As above.
996
As above. It should be noted that Rancière’s disagreement with social history and
sociology is not with the quality of their research. Pelletier notes that he doesn’t highlight
shortcomings or contradictions in how some researches go by collecting data. It is rather the
way in which a discipline positions its own discourse in relation to other discourses and the
object of study. Pelletier C (2009) 9.
997
Pelletier C (2009) 9.
998
See Rancière J (2004) 39.
999
Pelletier C (2009) 8.
1000
As above
1001
As above.
201
Verifying
equality
therefore
involves
equality
as
action,
rather
than
as
the
consequence
of
that
action.1002
The
question
that
Rancière
puts
forth
according
to
Pelletier
is
what
makes
one’s
research
practice
political,
or
what
can
we
do
in
the
context
of
research
practices
in
order
to
open
up
the
possibilities
of
equality?
As
noted
by
Pelletier,
in
some
ways,
not
very
much.1003
One
can
enact
equality
in
one’s
own
writing.1004
This
would
involve
reconfiguring
the
field
of
knowledge
to
undo
the
partitions
that
divide
people
into
territories
of
competence
and
territories
by
which
people
are
assigned
certain
social
attributes.1005
Equality,
therefore,
has
to
be
figured
differently.
Rather
than
a
state
to
be
worked
towards,
Pelletier
elucidates
that
it
becomes
in
Rancière’s
politics
a
disruption
of
inequality.1006
Verifying
equality
can
also
be
concerned
with
“valorising”
certain
actions
namely,
those
actions
that
are
characterised
by
the
way
in
which
they
transgress
the
boundaries
of
categories.1007
Pelletier
notes
that
it
is
about
making
prominent
in
one’s
own
analytical
strategy
those
discursive
practices
which
lays
the
contingency
of
inequality
bare
and
which
demonstrate
and
reconfigure
ways
of
doing,
being
and
saying.1008
In
the
section
below
I
discus
Olympe
de
Gouges
that
Rancière
may
be
said
to
“valorise”.
From
there
I
attempt
to
valorise
or
describe
certain
characters
that
transgress
boundaries
and
disrupt
inequality
with
equality
in
the
South
African
context.
5.2
Olympe
de
Gouges
In
the
context
of
his
article
“Who
is
the
Subject
of
the
Rights
of
Man?”
Rancière
discusses
the
figure
of
Olympe
de
Gouges.1009
De
Gouges
was
a
woman
who
1002
Pelletier C (2009) 9.
1003
As above.
1004
As above.
1005
As above.
1006
As above.
1007
As above.
1008
As above.
1009
See Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 297. In this article, Rancière discusses De
Gouges in relation to a critique of Hannah Arendt. In her influential discussion of the plight of
stateless people in The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951) Arendt invokes “the right to have
rights” as the one true human right. Arendt observes that “the rights of man” or human rights
proved to be a mere illusion in the inter-war period where European states was forced to deal
202
with refugees who had been deprived of citizenship and who were for all intense and
purposes stateless. They did not belong to the community that they fled from and neither to
the community that they fled too. The idea of human rights therefore came apart at the very
moment when they were most needed, for it is only by virtue of citizenship that one could say
to have a claim to rights. For Arendt, these people were “people that lost all other qualities
and specific relationships except that they were still human”. See Arendt (1951) 297-198. The
plight of stateless people revealed that the modern conception of human dignity was a mere
abstraction. For Arendt, to live outside of a political community amounted to a deprived form
of existence in which individuals were thrown back on the giveness of their natural situation.
Andrew Schaap explains that in the exceptional inter-war period in which stateless people
had nothing left to appeal to except their rights as human beings, they were barely
recognisable as human. See Schaap A “Enacting the right to have rights: Jacques Rancière’s
critique of Hannah Arendt” European Journal of Political Theory (2011) 23-45 at 23. Schaap
explains that as a consequence of this experience, we became aware of a primordial human
right, a right more important than the rights to justice and freedom, namely, the right to
belong to a political community, which amounts to the right to politics. Schaap A European
Journal of Political Theory (2011) 23. Therefore, for Arendt, what was at stake were not
particular rights, but rather membership to a political community. Arendt’s analysis of the
perplexities of the rights of man or human rights provoked widespread debate in
contemporary political theory. In “Who is the Subject of the Rights of Man?” Rancière
criticises the problematic that Arendt established. For Arendt, the deprivation of citizenship
to a particular community means that a person has no means of redress; there is no basis on
which to claim “the right to have rights”. One is outside of legal structures, outside of politics
and outside of humanity because of the fact that for Arendt it is only by virtue of historical
institutions that we can be said to be human. Rancière argues that Arendt depoliticises
human rights as Arendt identifies the human with mere life and the citizen with the good life.
Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 297-299. For Rancière, Arendt establishes an aporia
when it comes to rights, as there is no basis, according to her, on which one can claim the
right to have rights. Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 298. This aporia is for Rancière
a product of the ontological presuppositions on which her analysis relies rather than being a
defining aspect of the actual experience of statelessness. See Rancière J South Atlantic
Quarterly (2004) 297. Rancière insist against Arendt (and her appropriation of Aristotle) that it
is a political mistake to deduce a conception of what it means to lead a fully human life from
an understanding of the human as a speaking animal. See Schaap A European Journal of
Political Theory (2011) 23-24. For Rancière, as discussed earlier, what counts as human speech
and as animal noise is a political question from the outset. Rancière rejects Arendt’s
conception of the political as a “world-disclosing public action through which individuals
reveal their humanness in the presence of equals”. See Schaap A European Journal of
Political Theory (2011) 23. Instead Rancière conceives of the political as the staging of a scene
of dissensus in which those who lack speech make themselves heard as political subjects. For
Rancière, the human in human rights does not correspond to a form of life. The human is a
litigious name, another heading under which equality can be confirmed. See Rancière J South
Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 299-304. Schaap explains that Arendt understands ordinary rights as
a precondition for politics since they institutionalise an artificial equality that is constitutive of
a public sphere, which is the sphere that politics takes place in. See Schaap A European
Journal of Political Theory (2011) 23-24. This is why the right to have rights amounts to the
right to politics. For Rancière, politics is contesting the political, it is about contesting what is
perceived as political and what is not, who has speech and who doesn’t, in what place and
time: “[…] Arendt views ‘the human’ in human rights ontologically as a life deprived of
politics, Rancière views ‘the human’ polemically as the dismissal of any difference between
203
during
the
French
Revolution
famously
stated
that
if
women
were
entitled
to
go
to
the
scaffold,
they
were
entitled
to
go
to
the
assembly.1010
Women
could
be
(and
were)
sentenced
to
death
as
enemies
of
the
Revolution
and
De
Gouges
used
this
point
to
demonstrate
that
there
was
at
least
one
instance
where
women’s
private
life
was
political.
Rancière
explains
that
“equal-‐born
women
were
not
equal
born
citizens”
because
they
could
not
fit
what
was
deemed
the
purity
of
political
life
of
the
time.1011
Women
belonged
to
the
domesticated
and
the
public
life
and
common
good
had
to
be
kept
apart
from
the
activities,
feelings
and
interests
of
the
private
life.1012
De
Gouges’
point
was
that
if
women
could
lose
their
lives,
sentenced
to
death
as
enemies
of
the
state
out
of
public
judgment
based
on
political
reasons,
then
their
private
life
(their
life
doomed
to
death)
was
political.
De
Gouges
was
the
author
of
the
text
The
Declaration
of
the
Rights
of
Women
and
the
Female
Citizen.
Rancière
states:
If,
under
the
guillotine,
they
were
as
equal,
so
to
speak,
“as
men”,
they
had
the
right
to
the
whole
of
equality,
including
equal
participation
to
political
life.1013
He
further
explains
that
the
lawmakers
of
the
time
could
not
even
hear
this.
Nevertheless,
it
could
be
enacted
in
the
construction
of
a
scene
of
dissensus
and
he
states
that:
A
dissensus
is
not
a
conflict
of
interests,
opinions,
or
values;
it
is
a
division
put
in
the
“common
sense”:
a
dispute
about
what
is
given,
about
the
frame
in
which
we
see
something
as
given
[...]
This
is
what
I
call
dissensus:
putting
two
worlds
in
one
and
the
same
world.1014
those who are qualified to participate in politics and those who are not”. See Schaap A
European Journal of Political Theory (2011) 23. Therefore, as Schaap further notes, for Arendt,
the sphere of implementation of rights is the public sphere or the sphere of citizenship. For
Rancière, politics is a process, the process of the enactment of equality and the sphere where
it takes place or when it takes place can be the very question of politics- the time and space
of politics is a political question. See Schaap A European Journal of Political Theory (2011) 23.
Politics is about the line that is drawn between the spheres of politics and so-called other
spheres. Politics is about the activity that brings into question where politics can take place
and by who it can be practiced. For a thorough and insightful discussion of Rancière’s
engagement with Arendt, see Schaap A European Journal of Political Theory (2011) 32-45.
1010
Rancière J The South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 303.
1011
As above.
1012
As above.
1013
Rancière J The South Atlantic Quarterly 304.
1014
As above. I have quoted this passage before, but quote it again so as to properly explain
Rancière’s point with regards to De Gouges.
204
A
political
subject
for
Rancière
is,
as
mentioned,
a
subject
with
the
capacity
to
stage
a
scene
of
dissensus.1015
As
a
woman
De
Gouges
had
no
qualification
to
make
the
claims
that
she
did.
She
was
not
a
party
with
equal
membership
to
the
political
table.
Yet,
she
made
the
claims.
She
therefore
presupposed
her
equality
in
making
political
claims.
De
Gouges
becomes
here
the
demos,
representing
the
part
that
has
no
part
according
to
the
police
order
or
according
to
the
sensible
distribution
of
women
as
private
beings.
By
constructing
a
scene
of
dissensus
(making
political
statements
which
she
is
not
qualified
to
do
and
authoring
the
declaration)
she
challenges
the
overall
distribution
of
the
sensible,
the
distribution
of
roles,
places
and
tasks.
De
Gouges
puts
together
what
Rancière
calls
“a
relation
of
inclusion
and
exclusion”.1016
She
is
excluded
from
political
participation,
yet
included
as
she
can
lose
her
life
on
political
grounds.
De
Gouges
therefore
demonstrates
and
highlights
a
contradiction
within
the
dominant
political
discourse
or
framework
of
the
given.
For
Rancière,
De
Gouges
was
not
merely
making
a
claim
for
inclusion.
Her
claim
rather
embodied
the
contradictions
of
the
police
order
arrangements
that
exclude
her.
She
mobilises
this
contradiction
within
the
dominant
discourse
of
the
time
and
handles
the
knot
of
this
contradiction,
disrupting
the
police
order
and
illuminating
its
contingency.
It
should
be
mentioned
here
that
although
De
Gouges
makes
her
claim
under
the
heading
of
“women”
and
she
does
this
as
a
woman
and
to
the
ends
of
women,
this
“identity”
operates
on
two
different
levels:
woman
is
both
associated
with
the
police
order
that
she
is
challenging
and
also
with
the
position
that
marks
this
challenge.1017
It
is
associated
with
both
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
also
with
its
redistribution.
It
is
associated
with
the
world
where
women
are
not
qualified
to
participate
in
politics
and
where
there
are
roles
and
tasks
and
places
1015
As above.
1016
As above.
1017
See Jooste Y “Thinking two worlds into one: The ‘distribution of the sensible’ and
women’s renegotiation” Stellenbosch Law Review (2013) 528-537.
205
designated
to
them
and
the
world
where
they
are
equal.1018
De
Gouges
can
here
be
located
as
being
in-‐between
identities
and
identifying
with
the
impossible
namely,
a
category
of
woman
that
does
not
yet
exist.
It
can
be
said
that
she
disidentifies
herself
from
the
category
of
woman
as
understood
and
seen
within
the
police
order
namely,
a
privatised,
non-‐political
designation
and
demonstrates
through
the
process
of
subjectification
(through
declaring
a
wrong
and
staging
a
contradiction)
another
category
of
woman,
identifying
with
the
impossible
somewhere
in-‐between:
It
is
the
measure
of
a
relationship
between
a
particular
social
group
identifiable
within
the
order
of
the
police
(woman
as
a
social
category
with
the
expected
set
of
tasks
to
perform
and
roles
to
assume)
and
the
ability
of
its
name
to
be
appropriated
by
anyone,
the
ability
of
its
name
becoming
the
inscription
of
a
wrong
(women
as
the
subject
of
a
political
struggle
as
the
name
with
which
the
declaration
of
a
wrong
takes
place).1019
As
Arsenjuk
notes,
for
Rancière,
politics
lives
off
the
difference
between
the
name
as
a
rigid
designation
of
a
social
entity
and
everything
that
goes
along
with
it
and
a
name
as
an
anonym
that
can
stand
for
the
equality
of
everyone.1020
Rancière
uses
De
Gouge
in
order
to
show
how
the
relationship
between
the
universal
and
particular
can
be
divided
anew.1021
Women
were
denied
the
rights
of
citizens
on
account
of
the
principle
that
states
that
citizenship
is
part
of
the
sphere
of
universality
while
woman’s
activities
belonged
to
the
sphere
of
the
particular
of
domestic
life.
Women
occupy
the
sphere
of
the
particular
and
as
a
result
they
could
not
be
included
in
political
life,
the
sphere
of
the
universal.
Against
this
statement
De
Gouges
made
her
argument
about
the
scaffold.
Her
argumentation,
for
Rancière,
blurred
the
boundaries
separating
two
realms
by
setting
up
a
universality
entailed
in
the
life
of
the
particular.
On
the
scaffold
1018
As above.
1019
Arsenjuk L “On Jacques Rancière” Fronesis (2005) 19-20. Published online 2007/03/05 and
available at Eurozine Journals www.eurozine.com/articles/2007-01-01-arsenjuk-en.html
(accessed 28-12-2014).
1020
As above.
1021
Rancière J (2010) 56-57.
206
everyone
was
equal:
women
were
“as
men”.1022
Men
and
woman
could
be
sentenced
to
death
for
treason
out
of
public
reasons:
This
is
what
a
democratic
process
entails:
creating
forms
of
subjectivation
in
the
interval
between
two
identities;
creating
cases
of
universality
by
playing
on
the
double
relation
between
the
universal
and
the
particular.1023
De
Gouges’
declaration
about
the
scaffold
can
be
seen
as
a
poetic
linguistic
device.
The
poetry
or
invention
is
within
the
making
of
new
connections
and
relations.
She
connects
the
life
of
the
body
that
can
die
on
grounds
of
political
reasons
with
the
right
to
participate
in
politics.
In
this
instance
she
connects
the
private
with
the
public
and
the
public
with
the
private,
dividing
these
two
notions
anew
and
blurring
and
confusing
the
boundaries
between
them.
Her
configuration
of
the
scaffold
and
the
private
life
further
indicates
a
demonstration
of
an
argument
as
well
as
the
world
in
which
that
argument
can
count-‐
she
invents
a
way
in
which
to
present
a
logical
argument
by
demonstrating
in
what
way
women
might
be
included
in
the
public
life.
In
the
text
“Who
is
the
Subject
of
the
Rights
of
Man?”,
Rancière
makes
an
interesting
point
with
regards
to
the
notion
of
rights
that
is
worth
discussing.1024
He
demonstrates
how
they
can
be
used
to
stage
a
scene
of
dissensus.
He
makes
the
following
point
with
regards
to
the
so-‐called
“subject
of
rights”:
The
subject
of
rights
is
the
subject,
or
more
accurately
the
process
of
subjectivization,
that
bridges
the
interval
between
two
forms
of
existence
of
those
rights.1025
The
two
forms
of
existence
that
he
refers
to
are
the
following:
Firstly,
rights
are
written
rights
or
inscriptions
of
a
community
as
free
and
equal.1026
They
are
incorporated
within
constitutions
and
international
treaties
and
standards.
As
such,
Ranciere
states,
these
rights
are
not
just
abstract
ideals
far
from
a
given
situation.1027
They
are
part
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible.
What
is
therefore
given
to
us
is
not
only
a
situation
of
inequality,
rights
are
also
an
inscription
or
a
1022
As above.
1023
As above.
1024
Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 302-303.
1025
Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 302.
1026
As above.
1027
As above.
207
“form
of
visibility
of
equality”.1028
Secondly,
the
rights
of
“Man”
are
the
rights
of
those
who
make
something
of
them-‐
of
this
or
that
inscription.
They
are
the
rights
of
those
who
use
their
rights
to
build
cases
for
verification
of
the
power
of
that
inscription.1029
For
Rancière,
it
is
not
only
a
matter
of
checking
whether
a
situation
confirms
or
denies
those
rights:
“The
point
is
about
what
confirmation
or
denial
means”.1030
“Man”
and
“citizen”
and
“human”
are
not
designated
collection
of
individuals.
They
are
political
names
or
surplus
names
that
set
out
a
question
or
a
dispute
about
who
is
included
in
their
count
and
accordingly,
freedom
and
equality
are
not
predicates
belonging
to
definite
subjects,
they
are
political
predicates
or
predicates
that
can
open
up
a
dispute
about
what
they
exactly
entail
and
whom
they
concern
in
which
cases.1031
Rancière
is
not
referring
here
to
a
court
process
or
going
through
the
necessary
legal
procedures
in
order
to
get
a
specific
outcome.
The
point
is
that
rights
can
be
politicised
or
made
political.
They
are
part
of
the
current
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
as
such
they
can
be
mobilised
in
a
process
of
subjectivisation.
They
can
open
up
a
dispute
or
a
dissensus
about
what
they
mean
and
who
should
be
included
in
their
count.
It
is
a
standard
inscribed
within
the
community,
not
as
an
ideal
or
as
something
to
measure
our
progress
against;
in
Rancière’s
terms
it
is
rather
an
example
that
can
be
utilised
in
the
verification
of
equality.
The
tailor’s
strike
of
1833,
discussed
in
chapter
two,
is
such
an
example.1032
The
strikers
claimed
that
either
their
working
conditions
should
change
or
the
French
Charter
of
Rights
should
be
changed
to
something
like
“not
all
the
French
people
are
equal
before
the
law”.
Rights
can
therefore
be
employed
to
make
new
connections
or
to
fashion
linguistic
formulations.
De
Gouges
made
such
new
connections
-‐
she
connected
the
particular
with
the
universal,
the
public
with
the
private
and
the
scaffold
with
the
assembly,
thereby
blurring
the
lines,
mobilising
contradictions
and
putting
two
worlds
into
one.
The
next
figure
that
I
discuss
is
the
figure
of
Lucy
in
J.M
1028
Rancière J South Atlantic Quarterly (2004) 303.
1029
As above.
1030
As above.
1031
As above.
1032
See section 2.3.5 above.
208
Coetzee’s
novel
Disgrace.
Lucy
may
be
said
to
live
out
the
idea
of
putting
two
worlds
into
one.
5.3
Lucy
In
J.M.
Coetzee’s
novel
Disgrace,
Lucy
is
a
white
lesbian
woman
who
lives
in
the
Eastern
Cape
province
of
South
Africa.1033
Lucy
makes
a
living
by
selling
flowers
at
the
local
market
and
by
taking
care
of
other
people’s
pets.
In
the
novel,
David
Lurie,
Lucy’s
father
comes
to
stay
with
her
after
he
has
resigned
from
his
teaching
job
in
Cape
Town
because
of
a
charges
involving
sexual
harassment.
One
morning
Lucy
and
David
take
the
dogs
that
are
in
Lucy’s
care
out
for
a
walk.
They
walk
pass
two
black
men
and
a
boy
and
when
they
get
back
to
the
farmhouse,
the
same
two
men
and
boy
are
waiting
for
them.
The
men
claim
that
they
come
from
Erasmuskraal,
where
there
is
no
electricity
or
water
and
they
ask
if
they
may
make
a
phone-‐call
as
the
sister
of
one
of
them
is
having
a
baby.
Lucy
allows
one
of
the
men
into
the
house,
but
when
the
other
immediately
follows
without
invitation,
David
knows
that
something
is
wrong.
David
makes
his
way
into
the
house
through
the
kitchen
as
the
front
door
is
locked
and
there
he
receives
a
hard
blow
to
the
head.
The
men
lock
him
in
the
bathroom
and
while
he
is
locked
up,
they
rape
Lucy.
They
are
robbed
and
all
except
one
of
Lucy’s
dogs
are
killed.
Before
taking
off,
the
men
douse
David
with
methylated
spirits
and
set
him
on
fire.
He
manages
to
extinguish
the
flames
with
water
from
the
toilet
bowl.
In
the
aftermath
of
the
horrific
attack,
a
disagreement
develops
between
David
and
Lucy.
David
wants
to
call
the
police
and
tell
them
what
happened.
Lucy
agrees,
but
she
does
so
on
the
condition
that
David
tells
his
side
of
the
story
and
1033
JM Coetzee Disgrace (1999). As Arne De Boever notes, much has been written on
Disgrace, especially within the branch of literary criticism called “ethical criticism”. Some of
this work has revolved around the ethical philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas and the challenge
to Levinas’ ethics that Disgrace puts forth. As De Boever notes, it can be argued that in the
novel, and arguably within Coetzee’s work in general, women occupy a problematic position.
De Boever attempts to read Lucy through Rancière’s politics so as to cast another light on the
aesthetic politics of Disgrace. See De Boever A “Feminism after Rancière: women in JM
Coetzee and Jeff Wall” Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture (2011) “Lucy’s Politics”
available at www.transformationsjournal .org/journalissue_19/article_032.shtml. See also
Jooste Y Stellenbosch Law Review (2013) 528-537.
209
only
his.
She
will
tell
the
police
what
happened
to
her.
The
police
take
Lucy
and
David’s
testimonies
and
during
hers,
Lucy
does
not
mention
anything
about
the
rape.
This
confuses
and
infuriates
David:
Lucy,
my
dearest,
why
don’t
you
want
to
tell?
It
was
a
crime
[…]
You
did
not
choose
to
be
the
object.
You
are
an
innocent
party
[…]
Can
I
guess?
Are
you
trying
to
remind
me
of
something?
[…]
Of
what
women
undergo
at
the
hands
of
men?1034
The
implicit
reference
to
his
trail
with
regards
to
the
sexual
harassment
scandal
in
Cape
Town
invokes
a
harsh
answer
from
Lucy:
This
has
nothing
to
do
with
you,
David.
You
want
to
know
why
I
have
not
laid
charge
with
the
police.
I
will
tell
you,
as
long
as
you
agree
not
to
raise
the
subject
again.
The
reason
is
that,
as
far
as
I
am
concerned,
what
happened
to
me
is
a
purely
private
matter.
In
another
time,
in
another
place,
it
might
be
held
to
be
a
public
matter.
But
in
this
place,
at
this
time,
it
is
not.
It
is
my
business,
mine
alone.1035
David
asks:
“This
place
being
what?”
and
Lucy
answers:
“This
place
being
South
Africa”.1036
De
Boever
notes
how
the
statement
made
by
Lucy
that
her
rape
is
a
private
matter
might
seem
profoundly
conservative
because
of
the
fact
that
she
is
affirming
women’s
association
with
the
private
life.1037
However,
Lucy’s
refusal
to
report
the
rape
happens
within
a
very
specific
context.
Many
commentators
have
read
her
statement
against
the
background
of
the
processes
of
the
South
African
Truth
and
Reconciliation
Commission
that
was
established
in
order
to
deal
with
transition,
reconciliation
and
forgiveness.1038
Victims
as
well
as
perpetrators
under
the
apartheid
regime
could
come
and
testify
and
tell
their
story.1039
The
TRC
1034
Coetzee JM (1999) 111
1035
As above.
1036
Coetzee JM (1999) 112.
1037
De Boever A Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture (2011) “Lucy’s Politics”. See
also Jooste Y Stellenbosch Law Review (2013) 533-534.
1038
See for example Boehmer E “Not saying sorry, not speaking pain: Gender implications in
Disgrace” Interventions: International Journal of Postcolonial Studies (2002) 342-351. See also
the Promotion of the National Unity and Reconciliation act 34 of 1995. The TRC was given the
task of dealing with issues of transition, reconciliation and forgiveness. The commission’s
assignment included addressing the trauma of the past, repairing trust and restoring
humanity, building a moral basis and new values for the South African society and legitimising
the new dispensation. The Truth and Reconciliation hearings were established as part of the
mandate of the TRC to get as complete picture as possible of the causes, extent and nature
of politically motivated gross violations of human rights.
1039
As above.
210
established
a
“culture
of
confession”
or
a
politics
of
confession.1040
In
response
to
this
politics
of
confession,
Lucy
does
not
tell
and
she
insists
on
women’s
association
with
the
private.1041
At
a
later
point,
Lucy
tells
David
after
he
brings
up
the
rape
again:
This
is
my
life.
I
am
the
one
who
has
to
live
here.
What
happened
to
me
is
my
business,
mine
alone,
not
yours,
and
if
there
is
one
right
I
have
it
is
the
right
not
to
be
put
on
trial
like
this,
not
to
have
to
justify
myself-‐
not
to
you,
not
to
anyone
else.1042
De
Boever
explains
that
Lucy
therefore
disclaims
the
right
that
she
has.
In
a
culture
of
sensible
distribution
of
confession,
she
chooses
“non-‐confession”.1043
Commentators
have
called
Lucy’s
association
with
the
private
life
a
revolutionary
position
when
considering
women’s
historical
exclusion
from
the
political
life
in
South
Africa.1044
Her
words
“not
to
be
put
on
trial
like
this”
also
arguably
refers
to
a
refusal
to
have
to
represent
what
occurred,
a
refusal
to,
as
De
Boever
notes,
stand
before
the
violence
that
consists
of
asking
for
accounts
and
justifications
to
the
police
and
courts
of
law.1045
De
Boever
describes
Lucy
as
challenging
several
distributions
of
the
sensible
that
are
at
work
in
Coetzee’s
novel.1046
She
challenges
the
historical
context
in
which
the
novel
is
situated
specifically,
the
aftermath
of
apartheid
and
the
problematic
and
complicated
relationships
between
black
and
white
people.
Lucy
announces
that
she
will
continue
to
live
on
the
farm
where
the
attack
took
place.
Her
decision
becomes
extremely
difficult
for
her
David
to
understand,
especially
after,
as
De
Boever
explains,
Lucy’s
black
assistant
Petrus
becomes
the
co-‐proprietor
of
Lucy’s
farm
through
a
land
transfer
that
aims
to
restore
land
to
the
native
South
African
black
population.1047
Lucy
stays
on,
deciding
to
become
a
“bywoner”
(a
poor
tenant
labourer
who
works
for
the
1040
De Boever A Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture (2011) “Lucy’s Politics”. See
also Jooste Y Stellenbosch Law Review (2013) 533-534.
1041
As above.
1042
Coetzee JM (1999) 133.
1043
De Boever A Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture (2011) “Lucy’s politics”.
1044
As above.
1045
As above.
1046
As above.
1047
As above.
211
landowner,
but
is
also
allowed
to
make
some
profit
for
him
or
herself).1048
In
order
to
give
Lucy
some
protection
Petrus
asks
via
David
to
marry
her.
To
her
father’s
surprise
she
accepts
the
proposal.
She
explains
that
he
is
not
offering
her
“a
church
wedding
followed
by
a
honeymoon
on
the
Wildcoast”,
but
rather
“an
alliance,
a
deal”-‐
“I
contribute
from
the
land
in
return
for
which
I
am
allowed
to
creep
under
his
wing.
Otherwise,
he
wants
to
remind
me,
I
am
without
protection,
I
am
fair
game”.1049
De
Boever
notes
the
following
and
I
quote
him
at
length:
What
Lucy
thus
realises
is
the
“impossible”
community
of
a
white
lesbian
woman
living
under
a
black
man’s
wing/
of
a
black
man
taking
a
white,
lesbian
woman
under
his
wing.
It
is
neither
the
future
for
South
Africa
that
her
father
imagined,
nor
the
one
that
Petrus
imagined.
Her
position
marks
instead
the
country’s
radically
“democratic”
future:
a
future
that
would
lie
beyond
the
established
framework
of
identification
and
classification-‐
race
(black/white),
gender
(male/female),
class
(owner/tenant),
and
sexuality
(straight/gay)-‐
in
which
South
Africa,
from
Lucy’s
perspective
,
is
caught
up.1050
Lucy’s
position
here
indeed
marks
a
radically
democratic
future
as
De
Boever
notes.
She
mixes
the
categories
and
blurs
the
sensible
boundaries
at
work
in
this
context.
Disgrace
also
realises
this
particular
politics
at
the
level
of
the
novel’s
aesthetic.1051
De
Boever
explains
that
Spivak
has
noted
that
the
novel
is
focalised
“relentlessly”
through
David
Lurie.
Spivak
draws
an
important
conclusion
about
the
aesthetic:
The
reader
is
provoked
for
he
or
she
does
not
want
to
share
in
Lurie-‐the-‐
chief-‐focaliser’s
inability
to
“read”
Lucy
as
patient
and
agent.
No
reader
is
content
with
acting
out
the
failure
of
reading
[...]
This
provocation
is
the
“political”
in
political
fiction,
the
transformation
of
a
tendency
into
crisis.1052
It
is
precisely
then
Lucy’s
internally
excluded
position
of
the
part
of
those
who
have
no
part
that
becomes
Disgrace’s
aesthetic.1053
The
novel
focuses
through
Lurie,
thereby
provoking
the
reader
to
counter-‐focalise
and
take
up
Lucy’s
cause.
1048
As above.
1049
Coetzee JM (1999) 203.
1050
De Boever A Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture (2011) “Lucy’s Politics”.
1051
As above.
1052
See Spivak GC “Ethics and politics in Tagore, Coetzee and certain scenes of teaching”
Diacritics (2002) 32.
1053
De Boever A Transformations: Journal of Media and Culture (2011) “Lucy’s Politics”.
212
While
Lucy
is
thus,
according
to
De
Boever,
“an
empty
operator”,
her
emptiness
“resists”,
“making
its
own
disappearance
impossible”.1054
De
Boever
further
interestingly
notes
that
the
closing
paragraph
in
Judith
Butler’s
book,
Antigone’s
Claim:
Kinship
Between
Life
and
Death,
almost
reads
like
a
summary
of
Rancière’s
political
subject.
I
think
it
is
worth
quoting:
Who
then
is
Antigone
within
such
a
scene,
and
what
are
we
to
make
of
her
words,
words
that
become
dramatic
events,
performative
acts?
She
is
not
of
the
human,
but
speaks
in
its
language.
Prohibited
from
action,
she
nevertheless
acts,
and
her
act
is
hardly
a
simple
assimilation
to
an
existing
norm.
And
in
acting,
as
one
who
has
no
right
to
act,
she
upsets
the
vocabulary
of
kinship
that
is
a
precondition
for
the
human,
implicitly
raising
the
question
for
us
of
what
those
preconditions
really
must
be.
She
speaks
within
the
language
of
entitlement
from
which
she
is
excluded,
particularly
in
the
language
of
the
claim
with
which
no
final
identification
is
possible.
If
she
is
human,
then
the
human
has
entered
into
catachresis:
we
no
longer
know
its
proper
usage.
And
to
the
extent
that
she
occupies
the
language
that
can
never
belong
to
her
she
functions
as
chiasm
within
the
vocabulary
of
political
norms.
If
kinship
is
the
precondition
of
the
human,
then
Antigone
is
the
occasion
for
a
new
field
of
human,
achieved
through
political
catachresis,
the
one
that
happens
when
the
less
than
human
speak
as
human,
when
gender
is
displaced
and
kinship
founders
on
its
own
founding
laws.
She
acts,
she
speaks,
she
becomes
one
for
whom
the
speech
act
is
a
fatal
crime,
but
this
fatality
exceeds
her
life
and
enters
the
discourse
of
intelligibility
as
its
own
promising
fatality,
the
social
form
of
its
aberrant,
unprecedented
future.1055
It
is
Lucy’s
insistence
on
distributing
otherwise
in
this
specific
material
and
spatio-‐
temporal
locale
that
allows
for
alternative
capacities
and
ways
of
being.
The
place
within
which
Lucy
positions
herself
is
exactly
where
she
shouldn’t
be
according
to
the
specific
context
and
it
is
exactly
this
place
that
holds
the
possibility
of
an
unprecedented
future.
Within
the
established
Apartheid-‐aftermath
framework,
she
locates
another
time,
an
impossible
time
that
points
to
different
relationships
and
she
also
lives
impossibly
within
this
time.
In
a
sense,
she
identifies
with
an
impossible
South
African
democratic
future
-‐
imagining
that
things
can
be
different
or
otherwise.
But,
Lucy
does
not
only
imagine
that
things
can
be
otherwise,
she
also
embodies
this.
She
stays
and
works
on
the
farm
as
labourer-‐
tenant,
married
to
the
black
Petrus.
Lucy
is
a
white
lesbian
woman
that
marries
1054
As above.
1055
Butler J Antigone’s Claim: Kinship Between Life and Death (2000) 82.
213
the
black
Petrus
for
“protection”.
If
she
is
married
to
a
local
man,
she
is
safe
from
rape
by
other
men.
It
is
therefore
not
only
the
refusal
to
report
the
rape
that
might
be
controversial,
but
also
the
undercurrent
of
this
arrangement
namely,
a
woman
that
is
now
married
to
a
man
and
therefore
becomes
his
property
and
as
such
cannot
be
sexually
used
anymore.
Lucy
thereby
enters
into
marriage
within
highly
patriarchal
terms.
She
tears
her
body
from
various
sensible
distributions.
Lucy
insists
on
another
account
and
she
thereby
defines
differently
and
acts
in
a
way
that
paradoxically
embodies
a
transformation
thought
to
have
not
yet
been
attained.
It
should
be
mentioned
here
that
some
readings
of
Disgrace
within
the
context
of
post-‐apartheid
thought,
rather
than
viewing
Lucy’s
actions
as
actions
that
represent
the
embrace
of
a
radical
reconfiguration
of
the
South
African
democratic
future,
reads
her
actions
as
highly
problematic
within
patriarchal
South
African
culture.1056
When
it
comes
to
Lucy’s
silence
and
passivity
in
her
refusal
to
report
the
rape
and
her
retreat
into
working
the
land
as
a
bywoner,
Lucy
can
be
seen
as
assuming
the
generic
and
stereotypical
position
of
woman
suffering
in
silence.1057
Lucy
serves
the
needs
of
others
and
Boehmer
asks:
“Is
reconciliation
with
a
history
of
violence
possible
if
woman
[…]
is
as
ever
biting
her
lip?”1058
When
it
comes
to
having
a
political
voice,
Lucy
can
indeed
be
read
in
some
instances
as
lacking
voice
and
although
refusal
to
speak
or
silence
can
establish
political
speaking
or
claims,
when
read
within
the
context
of
patriarchy
1056
See Boehmer E Interventions: International Journal of Postcolonial Studies (2002) 342-351.
See also Sanders M “Disgrace” Interventions: International Journal of Postcolonial Studies
(2002) 363-373.
1057
Van Marle et al explains that within the highly patriarchal traditional South African
landscape oppression through silence was one of the characteristic ways in which to keep
women in constrained political spheres. See Van Marle, De Villiers I, Beukes E M “Memory,
space and gender: Re-imagining the law” South African Public Law (2012) 570. As Van Marle
et al further explains, during the apartheid era women did not speak of the atrocities that
were done to them and when they did, they were silenced by the state and marked as liars
unsupported by family as their confessions brought shame to the family name (Van Marle, De
Villiers I, Beukes E M South African Public Law (2012) 570). The silence of women and
daughters also influenced the voices of all those around them. See Van Marle, De Villers I,
Beukes E M South African Public Law (2012) 570.
1058
Boehmer E Interventions: International Journal of Postcolonial Studies (2002) 351.
214
and
masculinity,
Lucy’s
silence
–
rather
than
pointing
to
political
voice
-‐
points
to
an
affirmation
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
and
its
cycles
of
female
domination.1059
As
illustrated
by
the
discussion
above,
I
read
Lucy
as
redistributing
a
certain
sensible
distribution
and
as,
to
a
certain
extent,
having
a
voice.
When
Lucy
in
no
uncertain
terms
declares:
“It
is
my
business
and
mine
alone”
she
is
not
silent,
she
is
not
biting
her
lip.1060
The
point
may
be
that
Lucy
resists
any
easy
readings.
She
is
silent
in
one
sense
and
she
speaks
in
another.
She
is
therefore
problematic
and
it
is
in
within
this
logic
that
she
redistributes
the
sensible
as
a
contradictory,
alternative
character
that
inhabits
an
in-‐between
space.
Rather
than
reading
Lucy
as
speaking
or
not
speaking,
as
having
a
voice
or
not
having
a
voice,
I
read
her
as
a
figure
of
division.
Therefore,
the
possibility
of
political
voice
is
not
opened
up
by
the
fact
that
she
can
be
seen
as
having
a
voice
or
not
having
a
voice.
Rather,
it
is
opened
up
by
the
fact
that
she
can
be
read
as
both
and
neither.
5.4
Abahlali
baseMjondolo
Abahlali
baseMjondolo
is
a
social
movement
that
consists
of
South
African
shack-‐
dwellers.
The
movement
began
in
Durban
in
early
2005
and
it
is
the
largest
organisation
of
the
militant
poor
in
post-‐apartheid
South
Africa.1061
As
mentioned
in
the
introduction,
the
majority
of
South
Africans
live
impoverished
lives.
As
Selmeczi
notes,
the
inherited
apartheid
topography
results
in
the
spatial
and
1059
Refusal to speak can be read as a powerful instance of political subjectivity. Rather than
being seen as embodying passivity, refusal can be read as a counter-hegemonic action,
imbued with challenge and the beckoning of alternatives. See for example Van Marle K (ed.)
Refusal, Transition and Post-Apartheid Law (2009).
1060
Coetzee JM (1999) 111.
1061
See Abahlali’s official website: http//abahlali.org/a-short-history-of-abahlali-
basemjondolo-the-durban-shack-dwellers-movement/ (accessed on 20/12/2014). Instead of
explication and lengthy discussion, my aim here is to rather let these statements be read as is
so as to avoid speaking for or any implicit assumptions about the capacities of the
movement.
215
infrastructural
segregation
of
the
black
poor.1062
It
effectively
renders
them
spatially
and
materially
marginalised,
living
on
the
peripheries
of
the
national
cities.
Abahlali
has
practiced
numerous
forms
of
dissent
in
an
effort
to
transform
the
socio-‐economic
fate
of
the
poor
and
to
oblige
government
to
attend
to
their
plight.1063
The
majority
of
their
forms
of
dissent
and
efforts
have
been
defined
by
governmental
political
discourse
as
criminal
action.
1064
Members
of
the
movement
as
well
as
academics,
activists
and
journalists
have
produced
a
large
amount
of
research,
publications
and
various
other
forms
of
writing
on
the
movement
and
their
activities.1065
I
therefore
do
no
recount
their
whole
story
here.
It
is
also
important
to
mention
that
I
do
not
intend
to
speak
for
Abahlali
in
any
way.
The
movement
insists
on
a
protocol
that
interested
researchers
should
visit
them
and
talk
to
them-‐
“talk
to
us,
not
about
us”.1066
I
therefore
only
make
1062
See Selmeczi A “Dis/placing political illiteracy: The politics of intellectual equality in a
South African shack-dweller’s movement” Interface: A Journal for and about Social
Movements (2014) 230.
1063
As above. The movement began when a road blockage was organised in the Kennedy
Road settlement in protest to the sale of a piece of land to a local industrialist. The local
municipal counselor promised the shack-dwellers the land for housing. The movement grew
quickly and now has tens of thousands of supporters from more than 30 settlements around
the country. Within the last couple of years, more than 300 hundred of the members have
been arrested and subjected to police assaults, death threats and intimidation from local
ruling parties. The movement has tried to develop a sustained voice for shack-dwellers and
have marched to the offices of local councilors, police stations, municipal offices, newspapers
and the City Hall in Durban against governmental actions that have resulted in thousands of
people living on the street. The movement organised a successful boycott of the March 2006
local governmental elections under the slogan “No Land, No House, No Vote”. Abahlali have
also stopped evictions in a number of settlements, won access to schools and stopped the
industrial development of the land promised in Kennedy Road and forced numerous
government officials, offices and projects to visit Abahlali in the shanty towns. The movement
has struggled for land, housing, for an end to forced removals, access to education and the
provision of water, electricity, sanitation and health care. The movement has also set up
projects such as crèches, gardens, sewing collectives as well as support structures for people
living with HIV and AIDS.
1064
See Selmeczi A “Dis/placing political illiteracy: The politics of intellectual equality in a
South African shack-dweller’s movement” Interface: A Journal for and about Social
Movements (2014) 230-265.
1065
These engagements have included undergraduate essays, post-graduate theses, research
reports and work published in peer reviewed academic journals. See the list of publications
on Abahlali’s official website: http//abahlali.org/node/3204 (accessed on 20/12/2014).
1066
See http//abahlali.org/node/3204 (accessed on 20/12/2014).
216
use
of
literature
that
is
accepted
by
Abahlali.1067
I
also
explicate
as
little
as
possible
in
an
effort
to
let
the
movement’s
words
circulate
on
their
own.
The
point
is
not
to
represent
Abahlali
or
tell
their
story
for
them,
but
rather
to
attempt
to
practice
a
method
of
equality
that
valorise
words
and
instances
of
the
verification
of
equality.
It
has
been
argued
that
the
prevailing
political
discourse
sees
the
poor
black
majority
as
unable
to
practice
and
conceptualise
their
own
politics.1068
People
that
demonstrate
or
strike
are
often
seen
as
politically
illiterate.1069
As
mentioned,
the
spatial
order
of
apartheid
still
remains
and
most
people
are
left
to
live
in
spaces
of
infrastructural
decay.1070
In
their
discussion
of
the
municipal
practice
of
illegal
evictions,
Mark
Butler
and
Richard
Pithouse
have
stated
the
following:
[T]he
local
state
acts
in
a
systematically
criminal
manner
towards
its
poorest
residents
on
the
assumption
that
this
behaviour
is
within
the
norms
of
a
shared
social
consensus
amongst
the
social
forces
and
institutions
that
count.
That
elite
consensus
is
that
rights
formally
guaranteed
in
abstract
principle
should
not,
in
concrete
practice,
apply
to
the
poor.1071
Abahlali
has
struggled
in
various
forms
against
the
living
conditions
of
the
poor
and
the
manner
in
which
the
poor
are
dealt
with
by
the
state.
Most
of
their
efforts,
whether
in
the
form
of
marches,
strikes,
protests
or
demonstrations
have
been
received
by
government
as
criminal
and
violent
claims
to
service
delivery.
1067
I focus especially on the work of Anna Selmeczi who has written extensively on the
movement. See Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 230-
265. See also Selmeczi A “We are the people who do no count” Thinking the distribution of
the biopolitics of abandonment” PhD thesis at Central European University, March 2012.
1068
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 230.
1069
Selmeczi explores this point with regards to the protests of Abahlali baseMjondolo. She
argues that the contemporary spatio-political order of the South African “world class” city is
conditional upon constructing many South African lives as superfluous and disposable. See
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 230.The production
and abandonment of surplus people also depends on rendering them as improper political
subjects and dominant discursive conceptions further imply and reinforce conceptions of the
poor black majority as unable to think and practice their own politics as an illiterate group of
people. See Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 230.
1070
As above.
1071
Butler M & Pithouse R Lessons from eThekwini: Pariahs Hold Their Ground Against a
State that is Both Criminal and Democratic (2007) http://abahlali.org/node/984 (accessed on
28/12/2014).
217
Abahlali
contends
that
the
black
poor
majority
are
seen
as
less
than
equal
political
and
economic
subjects.1072
The
movement
has
in
many
ways
attempted
to
overturn
the
implicit
assumptions
of
their
demonstrations
as
criminal
acts:
They
say
we
committed
public
violence
but
against
which
public?
If
we
are
not
the
public
then
who
is
the
public
and
who
are
we?1073
By
asking
who
is
included
in
the
count
of
the
public,
this
statement
strikingly
disputes
the
criminality
often
associated
with
the
movement’s
actions.
On
this
logic,
the
movement
and
its
members
must
certainly
be
perceived
in
excess
to
the
public:
The
fact
that
our
minor
and
non-‐criminal
offences
are
treated
as
criminality-‐
as
public
violence-‐
shows
that
in
reality
we
are
not
included
in
the
definition
of
the
public
[…]
Therefore
we
have
to
rebel
just
to
count
as
public.1074
Here
the
movement
overturns
the
logic
that
sees
them
as
uncounted.
These
demonstrations
can
be
read
as
political
statements
that
“exist
because
those
who
have
no
right
to
be
counted
as
speaking
beings,
make
themselves
of
some
account.”1075
Tanke
has
argued
that
demonstrations
are
necessary
in
Rancière’s
conception
of
politics,
“demonstration
create
possibilities
for
the
part
of
those
who
have
no
part
to
begin
to
take
part”.1076
Demonstrations
can
therefore
impose
a
sensible
obligation
upon
others
to
recognise
the
rationality
of
the
arguments
of
the
demonstrators.1077
Whether
through
polemics,
strikes,
speech
scenes,
poetic
1072
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 235-236.
1073
Zikode S “The Third Force” in Yonk’ Indawo Umzabalazo Uyasimuvela: New York From
Durban: Durban Centre for Civil Society Research Reports (2013) as referenced in Selmeczi A
Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 235.
1074
Poni M “Public Violence” (2009) available at http://abahlali.org/node/5769 (accessed on
23/12/2014). As Selmeczi explains Abahlali has claimed on numerous occasions that
blockading roads is not violence: “violence is harm to human beings.” See Selmeczi A
Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 237. The members of the
movement often make the point that protests usually only turn violent after the police
intervenes: “Usually harm is only experienced when the police come. Before police come, no
harm happens, whether we sing and burn tires as part of our expression […] So, when we
burn tires, we sing our songs, the only thing we’re causing is traffic, which traffic always
happens by the way. And then, when police come, that’s where harm take place, and usually
we are the only victims”. See Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements
(2014) 237.
1075
Bosteels B “Rancière’s Leftism, or, Politics and its Discontents” in Rockhill G & Watts P
(eds.) (2009) 165.
1076
Tanke J (2011) 60.
1077
As above.
218
activities
or
the
definition
of
new
capacities,
equality
must
be
made
visible
or
it
must
manifest
in
the
declaration
of
a
wrong
so
as
to
break
open
an
interpretation
of
sense
thought
to
be
incontestable.1078
Dominant
discourse
has
also
often
seen
the
demonstrations
of
the
movement
as
“reactionary”,
“opportunistic”,
“anarchist”
and
“populist”.1079
They
have
been
condemned
for
vandalising
“already
existing
infrastructure
in
our
community”.1080
This
type
of
logic
with
regard
to
dissent-‐
that
includes
road
blockades,
trespassing
and
civil
disobedience-‐
is
becoming
more
and
more
prominent
within
the
new
South
African
constitutional
order.
It
is
indicative
of
a
reasoning
that
puts
forth
that
post-‐apartheid
freedom
and
equality
should
be
achieved
through
patient
organisation,
education
and
sustained
struggle.
The
implicit
consensus
is
that
in
our
constitutional
dispensation,
such
acts
are
criminal
and
there
is
a
refusal
to
acknowledge
certain
types
of
dissent
as
political
struggle.
The
movement’s
speech
is
in
some
cases
not
recognised
as
fully
authorised
speech:
We
have
discovered
that
our
municipality
does
not
listen
to
us
when
we
speak
to
them
in
Zulu.
We
tried
English.
Now,
we
realise
that
they
won’t
understand
Xhosa
or
Sotho
either.
The
only
language
that
they
understand
is
when
we
put
thousands
of
people
on
the
street.1081
Rancière:
[I]f
there
is
someone
you
do
not
wish
to
recognise
as
a
political
being,
you
begin
by
not
seeing
them
as
the
bearers
of
politicalness,
by
not
understanding
what
they
say,
by
not
hearing
that
it
is
an
utterance
coming
out
of
their
mouths.1082
Abahlali
has
also
been
made
out
to
be
“thoughtless”
in
their
actions.1083
They
maintain
however
that
although
they
have
chosen
a
different
form
of
struggle
(than
what
may
be
considered
as
acceptable
legal
and
political
routes),
it
doesn’t
1078
Tanke J (2011) 61.
1079
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 238.
1080
As above.
1081
Zikode S “Third Force” (2005) as referenced in Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal For and
About Social Movements (2014) 239.
1082
Rancière J (2001) 32.
1083
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 239.
219
mean
that
“we
did
not
come
to
this
campaign
after
careful
thinking”.1084
Further,
the
movement
has
not
only
sought
to
overturn
the
sensible
distribution
of
their
dissent
as
thoughtless,
but
has
also
resisted
dominant
allocations
of
the
poor
as
ignorant
and
in
need
of
education:
We
hear
that
the
political
analysts
are
saying
that
the
poor
must
be
educated
about
xenophobia.
Always
the
solution
is
to
“educate
the
poor”.
When
we
get
cholera
we
must
be
educated
about
washing
our
hands
when
in
fact
we
need
clear
water.
When
we
get
burnt
we
must
be
educated
about
fire
when
in
fact
we
need
electricity.
This
is
just
a
way
of
blaming
the
poor
for
our
suffering.
We
want
land
and
housing
in
the
cities,
we
want
to
go
to
university,
we
want
water
and
electricity-‐
we
don’t
want
to
be
educated
to
be
good
at
surviving
poverty
on
our
own.1085
After
a
fire
broke
out
in
a
settlement,
the
same
type
of
imposed
education
was
postulated
by
the
state:
After
the
fire,
people
were
basically
telling
us
to
teach
people
how
to
use
a
paraffin
stove
properly-‐
how
to
use
a
paraffin
stove
is
not
something
I
need
to
teach
to
the
people
who
have
used
them
all
their
lives!
Why
is
this
the
thing
they
think
must
be
taught
when
we
have
said
clearly
the
problem
is
that
we
are
excluded
from
getting
electricity.1086
Many
protests
and
forms
of
dissent
have
been
viewed
by
the
dominant
political
discourse
through
the
lens
of
the
pace
of
government’s
service
delivery.
Dissent
is
viewed
within
the
framework
of
the
immediacy
experienced
by
the
poor
that
cannot
grasp
the
complexities
of
government
processes
and
that
lack
understanding
of
the
patience
and
work
involved
in
long-‐lasting
and
proper
development:
Many
journalists
have
been
phoning
us
and
asking
if
our
“service
delivery
protest”
will
be
going
ahead
tomorrow.
We
appreciate
the
interest
of
the
media
but
we
really
want
to
stress
that
this
will
not
be
a
“service
delivery
protest”.
We
have
never
organised
“a
service
delivery
protest”.
[…]
The
language
in
which
people’s
struggles
are
turned
into
“service
delivery
protest”
is
a
language
that
has
been
imposed
on
our
struggles
from
the
outside-‐
it
is
not
our
language.
Of
course
we
are
struggling
for
land
and
housing,
water
and
electricity.
But
we
do
not
accept
the
limited
way
in
which
these
“services”
are
“delivered”.
Often
an
important
part
of
our
struggles
is
to
reject
the
way
that
services
are
delivered
[…]
We
are
struggling
for
the
full
recognition
and
realisation
of
our
humanity
in
a
1084
As above.
1085
Abahlali baseMjondolo “Statement of the Xenophobic Attacks in Johannesburg” (2008)
available at http://abahlali.org/node/3582 (accessed on 13/11/2014).
1086
Abahlali baseMjondolo and Rural Network Living Learning (2009) as referenced in
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 252.
220
society
that
denies
our
humanity
at
every
turn
[…]
To
call
our
struggles
“service
delivery
protests”
is
a
way
of
making
them
safe
for
our
oppressors
[....]1087
And
We
are
concerned
that
your
chief
of
staff
has
said
that
the
meeting
would
only
deal
with
“service
delivery
issues”
and
would
not
deal
with
“unrelated
issues”.
Since
when
was
democracy
about
service
delivery?
Since
when
was
human
dignity
about
service
delivery?
We
have
a
democratic
right
to
take
this
view
and
to
argue
for
it
when
we
engage
the
state.
In
fact
we
reject
the
whole
paradigm
of
“service
delivery”
[…]
Your
chief
of
staff
wants
to
confine
us
to
discussions
of
peripheral
importance
just
as
we
are
already
confined
on
peripheral
land
on
the
outskirts
of
the
city.1088
Abahlali
refuses
the
description
of
their
struggles
within
frameworks
that
can
neutralise
their
claims
or
contain
their
politics.
The
movement
lays
the
contingency
of
the
current
South
African
spatio-‐temporal
order
bare:
“We
know
that
we
are
not
supposed
to
be
living
the
way
we
do”1089
and
attempt
to
disrupt
any
form
of
intellectual
authority:
“We
always
say
that
the
fact
that
we
are
poor
in
life
does
not
make
us
poor
in
mind.”1090
Although
the
movement
has
continually
stated
that
they
are
“ordinary
men
and
women
[that]
insist
on
their
right
to
speak
and
be
heard
on
matters
that
concern
their
daily
lives”,
the
ruling
party
has
insisted
that
the
movement
is
ruled
by
a
“third
force”
of
leftist
intellectuals.1091
As
Selmeczi
confirms,
this
logic
postulates
a
fundamental
doubt
of
the
shack-‐dwellers’
capacity
to
theorise
and
conduct
their
own
struggle.1092
The
movement
has
established
the
“University
of
Abahlali
baseMjondolo”
by
declaring
that
the
shantytowns
are
places
of
“living
learning”.1093
The
movement
has
also
refused
knowledge
imparted
by
the
“politician-‐expert”
and
“charity-‐
1087
Abahlali baseMjondolo “Sutcliff’s Dirty Tricks Won’t Keep Us From Marching In Our City
Tomorrow” (2010) available at http://abahlali.org/node/6403 (accessed on 27/12/2014).
1088
Poni M quoted in Dear Mandela A film by Dara Kell and Christopher Nizza (2011) as
referenced by Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 248.
1089
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 248.
1090
Hlongwa M “The No Land, No House, No Vote Campaign Still On For 2009” (2007)
available at httpp://abahlali.org/node/510 (accessed on 12/12/2014).
1091
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 249.
1092
As above.
1093
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 255.
221
expert”
that
aim
to
“enlighten
the
dark
pockets
of
the
ignorant”.1094
Abahlali
notes:
We
are
supposed
to
suffer
silently
so
that
some
rich
people
can
get
rich
from
our
work
and
others
can
get
rich
having
conferences
about
having
more
conferences
about
suffering
[…]
We
must
even
be
invisible
when
people
are
getting
paid
to
talk
about
us
in
government
or
in
NGO’s.
Everything
is
done
under
our
name.1095
Here
Abahlali
can
be
said
to
indicate
something
of
Rancière’s
contention
that
some
knowledge
emerge
as
the
surplus
value
of
the
poor’s
labour:
“It
is
produced
by
them,
but
claimed
by
the
owners
of
the
means
of
production”.1096
Although
at
times
government
has
intentionally
sought
to
subvert
the
workings
and
actions
of
the
movement
by
way
of
arbitrary
evictions
and
arrests
(with
charges
usually
dropped
before
cases
reach
court)
and
intimidation
by
ruling
party
members,
the
movement
has
managed
to
sustain
protests
and
broader
public
engagement.
Their
membership
has
grown
to
tens
of
thousands
and
they
have
attracted
the
intention
of
activists
across
different
levels
of
civil
society.
The
movement
has
also
helped
numerous
members
of
their
community
and
has
demanded
response
from
various
governmental
institutions.
Against
prevailing
discourses
and
dominant
configurations
of
society
that
ensures
that
only
certain
classes
of
people
are
authorised
to
think
and
speak,
Abahlali
have
declared
that
they
do
think
and
speak.
To
say
that
“[e]veryone
speaks,
everyone
thinks”
is
more
subversive
than
it
sounds.1097
As
Hallward
elucidates,
thinking
“evades
regulation
and
contests
classification”.1098
To
think
is
therefore,
according
to
Hallward,
itself
to
subvert
any
rigid
distribution
of
places
and
roles.1099
1094
Selmeczi A Interface: A Journal for and about Social Movements (2014) 252.
1095
Hlongwa M “The No Land, No House, No Vote Campaign Still On For 2009” (2007)
available at httpp://abahlali.org/node/510 (accessed on 12/12/2014).
1096
Pelletier C (2009) 6.
1097
As above. Hallward P “Jacques Rancière and the Subversion of Mastery” Paragraph: A
Journal of Modern Critical Theory (2005) 26.
1098
As above.
1099
As above.
222
Before
concluding,
I
return
to
the
figure
of
Bhubaneswari
Bhaduri
that
Spivak
invokes
in
her
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
In
the
section
below
I
offer
a
short
and
different
reading
of
Bhubaneswari.
5.5
Bhubaneswari
Bhaduri
It
has
been
mentioned
that
the
tragic
figure
of
Bhubaneswari
Bhaduri
haunts
Spivak’s
famous
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”1100
Morris
explains
that
Bhubaneswari,
as
a
continually
misread
woman
with
an
impossible
story,
has
in
many
ways
accompanied
and
also
possessed
Spivak
in
her
own
effort
to
be
accountable
to
and
for
the
history
of
the
subaltern.1101
In
chapter
four
it
was
explained
that
Bhubaneswari
Bhudari
was
a
young
middle-‐class
Indian
woman
who
took
her
own
life
in
her
father’s
apartment
in
Calcutta
in
1926.1102
After
her
suicide
it
was
discovered
that
she
was
a
member
of
one
of
the
many
groups
involved
in
the
armed
struggle
for
Indian
independence.
She
had
been
entrusted
with
a
political
assassination,
which
she
was
unable
to
do.
She
subsequently
committed
suicide
in
order
to
avoid
capture
by
the
British
colonial
authorities
and
to,
speculatively,
safeguard
the
members
of
her
group.
Spivak
reads
Bhubaneswari’s
suicide
as
an
attempt
to
cover
up
her
involvement
in
the
anti-‐
colonial
insurgency
movement
by
disguising
her
suicide
as
a
modern
example
of
sati.1103
However,
Spivak
contends
that
her
voice
and
agency
as
a
real
historical
woman
freedom
fighter
disappeared
from
the
official,
male-‐centred
historical
records.
Technically,
her
suicide
did
not
conform
to
the
codes
of
sati
because
she
was
not
a
widow
and
the
suicide
did
not
take
place
in
the
sacred
site
of
the
husband’s
funeral
pyre.1104
However,
on
Spivak’s
account,
as
Morris
explains,
Bhubaneswari
at
least
foreclosed
any
possibility
that
her
suicide
might
be
1100
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 16.
1101
It should be mentioned here that Spivak later wrote that Bhubaneswari wrote a letter to
her grandmother. Spivak’s mother told her the story of Bhubaneswari and that is how she
came to research her as historical figure. See Morris R (ed.) (2010) 228.
1102
See section 4.2.
1103
As above.
1104
It should be mentioned here that there is of course no way in which Bhubaneswari’s
intentions can really be proved. Spivak offers a reading of Bhubaneswari’s story as an attempt
to rewrite “the social text of sati-suicide in an interventionist way”. See Spivak GC (1988) 307.
223
interpreted
as
an
illegitimate
pregnancy
as
she
was
menstruating
at
the
time
of
her
suicide.1105
For
Spivak,
there
is
no
question
that
Bhubaneswari
was
a
politically
committed
member
of
the
national
independence
struggle.
However,
Bhubaneswari’s
attempt
to
rewrite
the
text
of
sati-‐suicide
is
a
“tragic
failure”
because
the
“subaltern
as
female
cannot
be
heard
or
read”
in
the
male-‐centred
terms
of
the
national
independence
struggle.1106
Her
voice
was
“effaced
by
the
ideological
structures
of
imperial
masculinity
and
the
state”.1107
Spivak
explains
that
supplementary
narratives
and
retellings
erased
Bhubaneswari’s
story.1108
According
to
Spivak,
her
exceptional
act
of
women’s
resistance
was
later
re-‐
coded
as
a
case
of
an
illicit
love
affair
and
a
source
of
shame
for
the
subsequent
generations
of
her
family.1109
Spivak
was
disturbed
by
the
fact
that
everyone,
including
Bhubaneswari’s
own
family,
misunderstood
her
suicide
and
no
one
seemed
interested
in
Spivak’s
return
to
and
reinterpretation
of
the
event.1110
“Unnerved
by
this
failure
of
communication”,
Spivak
concluded
that
“the
subaltern
cannot
speak!”1111
Bhubaneswari’s
narrative
is
discussed
at
the
end
of
the
essay
and
Spivak
offers
Bhubaneswari
as
a
text
to
be
read.1112
As
mentioned,
since
her
initial
essay
Spivak
has
reminded
herself
that
speaking
always
occurs
within
the
nexus
of
actions
that
include
listening,
responding,
interpreting,
qualifying
and
so
on.
To
happen,
events
must
be
perceived
and
acknowledged
as
such.
Although
on
Spivak’s
reading
Bhubaneswari’s
suicide
was
a
tragic
failure,
she
certainly
redistributes
some
of
the
sensible
distributions
at
work
in
her
context.
She
was
a
female
member
of
an
anti-‐colonialist
struggle.
She
took
her
own
life
against
religious
codes.
And
she
committed
suicide
while
menstruating
so
as
to
rule
out
subsequent
narratives
of
illicit
pregnancy.
With
these
actions,
Bhubaneswari
1105
Morris R (ed.) (2010) 6.
1106
Morton S (2003) 65-66.
1107
Morris R (2010) (ed.) 7.
1108
See section 4.2 above.
1109
Morton S (2003) 66.
1110
Leitch V, Cain W et al (eds.) (2010) 2195.
1111
Spivak GC in Nelson C & Grossberg L (1988) 307.
1112
See footnote 992 above.
224
refuses
to
be
interpreted
in
a
certain
way.
Her
body
carried
the
signs
that
would
make
certain
masculinist
and
imperialist
interpretations
impossible.
Commentators
have
noted
how
Spivak’s
retelling
of
the
story
of
Bhubaneswari
on
numerous
occasions
has
transformed
the
private
family
secret
of
her
suicide
that
nobody
in
her
family
wants
to
talk
about
into
the
“public
political
archive
of
post-‐
colonial
studies”.1113
This
is
especially
accurate
if
one
considers
the
impact
of
Spivak’s
essay.
When
considered
along
the
lines
of
Rancière’s
politics,
a
different
lesson
can
be
gleaned
from
Bhubaneswari.
When
it
comes
to
the
retelling
of
Bhubaneswari,
Spivak
records
in
the
discourse
of
her
essay,
a
voice
that
is
phenomenally
impossible
as
a
historical
speech-‐act.1114
According
to
Spivak,
Bhubaneswari
has
no
place
from
which
to
speak.
And
it
is
from
within
this
juncture
that
a
different
political
future
might
be
opened
up:
The
alternative
telling
lies,
not
in
making
Bhubaneswari
speak,
but
rather
within
the
very
impossibility
of
her
having
a
voice.
For
in
recording
Bhubaneswari,
Spivak
does
“more
than
give
[her]
a
historical
identity”,
she
also
demonstrates
along
the
lines
of
a
Rancièrian
framework,
“how
a
politics
can
be
predicated
on
an
impossible
phenomenality
of
voice”.1115
Spivak
records
a
speech
event
that
is
impossible
and
it
is
from
within
this
recording
that
the
politics
of
voice
is
revealed.
5.6
Conclusion
1113
See Shetty S & Bellamy E “Postcolonialim’s archive fever” Diacritics (2000) 25-48.
1114
See Parker A in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 249. Parker discusses Rancière’s
discussion of Erich Auerbach’s Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature.
See Rancière J The Names of History: On the Poetics of Knowledge (1994) 29-30. Auerbach
discusses the New Testament and a specific instance where Tacitus records a speech of
Percennius in his writing. Percennius cannot speak for he is of the poor, he is a soldier. He
therefore has no place from which to speak, but Tacitus “lends him his tongue”. For Rancière,
it is exactly the fact that Tacitus records in his discourse the speech event that is impossible
that can point to a political future or politics: “By invalidating the voice of Percennius,
substituting his own speech for the soldier’s, Tacitus does more than give him a historical
identity. He also creates a model of subversive eloquence for the orators and simple soldiers
of the future” See Rancière J (1994) 29-30. I therefore use this line of thinking in Rancière’s
discussion of Auerbach and Parker’s eloquent relaying of Edward Said’s and Rancière’s
engagements with Auerbach in my contemplation on Spivak’s essay with regards to this last
point. Parker A in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 249-257.
1115
Parker A in Rockhill G & Watts P (eds.) (2009) 257.
225
The
figures
and
statements
discussed
above
represent
a
way
of
reacting
against
the
background
sketched
in
the
first
chapter,
specifically
the
complexities
and
difficulties
of
voicing
as
it
pertains
to
many
South
African
women.
Along
the
lines
of
employing
a
method
of
equality,
I
attempted
to
contemplate
moments
of
the
reconfiguration
of
the
sensible.
These
figures
and
related
statements
encompass
a
different
way
of
mapping
the
trajectories
of
the
visible
and
sayable.
A
method
of
equality
entails
reading
and
producing
words
against
guarantees
and
modes
of
legitimation.
It
entails
highlighting
verifications
of
equality
and
valorising
redistributions
of
the
sensible
order
so
as
to
give
rise
to
voicing
and
ways
of
voicing
thought
not
to
exist.
De
Gouges
mobilises
the
contradictions
of
the
contingent
police
order
that
surrounds
her
by
connecting
the
unconnected.
She
therefore
invents
an
argument
by
relating
facts
previously
unrelated.
She
handles
the
(im)possible
double
meanings
of
the
public
and
private,
the
universal
and
particular
and
inclusion
and
exclusion
in
a
way
that
mixes
descriptions
and
definitions
and
she
presupposes
equality
on
these
grounds.
Lucy
divides
the
distribution
of
places
and
roles
and
tasks
anew
by
refusing
to
follow
or
act
in
a
way
that
affirm
police
order
designations.
Her
redistributions
not
only
allow
her
to
tread
her
own
path,
but
also
open
up
the
possibility
of
another
time
and
place
within
the
located
time
and
place.
She
lives
an
impossible
transformation
by
contesting
the
lines
of
post-‐apartheid
sensibility
and
as
an
alternative
figure
of
division,
she
holds
open
the
possibility
of
voice.
The
statements
of
Abahlali
baseMjondolo
represent
a
refusal
to
simply
accept
the
distributions
of
the
dominant
political
discourse
that
sees
the
movement
as
ignorant
and
unable
to
understand
the
complex
mechanisms
of
governance.
They
rather
insist
that
their
voices
count
and
that
their
struggle
is
political
–
refusing
intellectual
and
consensual
authority
that
defines
what
people
should
and
should
not
do
and
who
should
think
and
not
think.
Within
their
demonstration
and
226
sustained
struggle
they
incite
and
represent
to
others
that
there
is
nothing
natural
about
their
position
within
the
societal
order.
Bhubaneswari
overturns
certain
readings
that
would
see
her
through
the
lens
of
masculinst
assumptions.
A
retelling
of
her
story
demonstrates
how
a
politics
can
be
thought
through
instances
of
impossible
voicing.
The
recording
of
non-‐speech
acts
invalidates
those
frameworks
that
would
see
them
as
noise
and
not
political
voice.
These
figures
and
statements
all
in
some
way
traced
and
mapped
redistributions
that
can
possibly
disclose
and
reveal
the
way
in
which
voice
is
freed
when
it
refuses
to
be
reduced
to
the
space-‐times
and
locales
of
sensible
configuration.
227
CHAPTER
6
Conclusion:
Retracing
the
way
Towards
the
Possibility
of
Voice
It
is
mentioned
in
the
first
chapter
that
this
thesis
involves
making
sense
of
the
notion
of
political
voice.
More
specifically,
it
involves
a
reflection
on
voice
through
the
lens
of
the
politics
of
Jacques
Rancière,
against
the
background
of
the
difficulties
surrounding
voicing
as
it
pertains
to
many
South
African
women.
It
is
also
mentioned
that
the
thesis
does
not
involve
formulating
concrete
steps
in
an
effort
to
go
forward.
Rather,
my
exploration
of
Rancière’s
work
on
politics,
against
the
specific
background
sketched
in
chapter
one,
comprises
of
a
journey
that
ultimately
points
me
to
new
insights
and
ways
of
understanding
the
notion
of
political
voice
as
well
as
the
way
in
which
political
voice
relates
to
my
discussion
of
women
and
the
specific
disconnect
that
comes
into
play
when
considering
some
of
the
most
pressing
issues
that
many
South
Africa
women
face.
As
explained
in
the
second
chapter,
Rancière
does
not
conceive
of
politics
along
social
conditions
or
identity
categories.
Rather,
what
matters
is
equality.
As
Clarke
confirms
with
regards
to
the
social
category
of
“women”
and
Rancière’s
thinking:
“[W]hile
[…]
disagreements
may
invoke
the
name
of
a
particular
social
category
(‘women’),
it
is
an
error
in
Rancière’s
view
to
understand
this
name
as
a
reference
to
a
prior
community
or
social
body”.1116
Indeed,
Rancière’s
thinking
on
politics
points
to
localised,
contextual
and
individual
thinking
and
theorising
and
my
exploration
here
opens
up
the
question
of
how
we
are
to
trace
new
topographies
of
the
visible
and
sayable
and
of
how
we
are
to
think
about
contexts
of
inequality
as
it
relates
to
many
women.
Such
thinking
does
not
require
an
expression
of
a
social
category
or
a
unified
self.
Rather,
it
requires
expressions
in
relation
to
equality,
in
relation
to
new
categories
and
identifications
and
in
relation
to
the
questioning
and
interrogating
of
gaps
between
universal
categories
and
lived
realities.
Rancière’s
politics
therefore
points
to
the
possibility
of
new
1116
Clarke C “Ranciere, Politics and the Social Question” in Davis O (ed.) (2013) 15.
228
configurations
of
voice
and
of
voicing
as
a
politicising
gesture.
In
order
to
conclude
in
the
section
below,
I
highlight
some
of
the
most
significant
lines
of
thinking
opened
up
by
my
reflection
on
voice.
In
exploring
Rancière’s
politics
by
way
of
the
concepts
of
“the
police
order”,
“politics/equality”,
“the
political
subject”,
“the
miscount
and
the
wrong”
and
“the
distribution
of
the
sensible”,
it
becomes
clear
that
within
a
Rancièrian
framework,
politics
is
the
very
struggle
over
or
for
voice.
Politics
is
the
process
that
breaks
apart
the
various
obstacles
that
confront
exercises
of
political
voicing.
Moments
of
political
voicing
runs
counter
to
the
police
order
and
the
various
categories
and
configurations
of
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
by
confronting
it
with
a
different
configuration.
Politics
radically
disputes
the
frameworks
that
determine
who
and
what
can
be
heard
and
seen
in
what
contexts.
The
possession
of
political
voice
is
conditioned
upon
the
possibility
of
appearance
in
realms
of
intelligibility,
perceptibility
and
visibility.
Voicing
becomes
the
moment
wherein
the
properties
of
space,
the
possibilities
of
time
and
the
formation
of
identities
and
locales
are
overturned.
Political
voicing
consists
of
inventing
worlds,
arguments
and
supplementary
names
and
identities.
When
analysing
Rancière’s
formulation
of
politics
against
the
background
of
the
disconnect
and
difficulties
of
voice
as
it
pertains
to
the
contexts
of
many
South
African
women,
the
notion
of
consensus
highlights
the
fact
that
legal
and
institutional
mechanisms
of
government
and
the
broader
protocols
of
the
community
cannot
give
rise
to
political
voicing
properly.
These
mechanisms,
rather
than
giving
rise
to
politics,
establish
a
discourse
of
pragmatic
management.
Further,
the
policy
and
legal
mechanisms
of
government
as
well
as
the
shared
norms
of
activism
give
rise
to
a
specific
logic
or
orientation
towards
the
sensible
world.
As
mentioned,
women’s
broader
issues
and
gender
challenges
are
within
the
public
realm,
but
they
themselves,
as
individuals,
bodies
and
beings,
are
somehow
beyond
the
realm
of
relevance,
living
in
abject
poverty
and
in
constant
fear
of
sexual
violence.
Many
women
cannot
therefore
politically
appear
or
be
visible
to
the
extent
of
their
concrete
contexts
being
transformed.
The
challenges
facing
South
African
women,
when
viewed
through
the
lens
of
the
police
order
becomes
issues
that
229
has
been
counted,
taken
into
account
and
named.
As
such,
they
are
neutralised
and
naturalised-‐
not
open
to
dispute
and
contestation,
litigation
and
controversy.
The
first
research
question
stated
in
chapter
one
of
the
thesis
is:
What
directions
for
thought
and
useful
lines
of
thinking
are
opened
up
by
an
exploration
of
the
work
of
Rancière?
I
argue
in
chapter
two
that
the
distribution
of
the
sensible
becomes
valuable
as
mechanism
and
concept,
as
idea
and
tool.
The
topography
of
the
visible
and
sayable
provides
a
ground
from
where
to
think
through
and
intervene
in
the
structures
that
set
up
the
well-‐ordered
partitions
of
voice
and
silence.
More
importantly,
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
allows
us
to
ask
to
what
extent
certain
mechanisms
and
societal
consensus
becomes
part
of
the
inner
logic
of
the
police
order
and
as
such
contributes
to
silencing.
Policy
and
juridical
frameworks
as
well
as
the
shared
norms
of
society
create
forms
of
inclusion
and
exclusion.
These
frameworks
produce
spaces
of
silence.
It
selectively
frames
and
interprets,
lending
an
air
of
inevitability
and
postulating
the
given
or
“the
way
things
are”.
In
chapter
three,
I
explain
the
fact
that
Rancière’s
formulations
on
politics
were
built
on
his
encounters
with
the
figures
of
Joseph
Jacocot
and
Gabriel
Gauny.
Radical
intellectual
equality
resulted
in
the
political
presupposition
of
equality.
Equality,
declared
from
the
outset,
is
a
destabilising
force
that
discloses
political
opportunities
of
emancipation
against
institutional
power
and
postulates
poetry,
invention,
thought
and
creation.
Equality
is
used
to
make
space
for
politics.
Gauny
and
the
other
worker-‐poets
displaced
distinctions
and
thereby
created
possibilities
for
voicing.
These
figures
displaced
predestined
spaces,
places,
times,
identities
and
in
this
regard
voicing
consists
of
a
radical
redistribution
of
spatio-‐
temporal
locales.
The
rejection
of
identities
stamped
on
bodies
by
dominant
discourses
reveals
a
space
where
voice
can
be
radically
reconfigured.
The
discussions
in
chapter
three
give
rise
to
the
question
of
how
we
are
to
approach
the
notion
of
political
voice
against
the
background
of
the
difficulties,
complexities
and
precariousness
of
voicing
when
it
comes
to
many
South
African
women.
Within
a
Rancièrian
understanding,
characters,
concepts
and
ways
of
writing
are
framed
in
such
a
way
so
as
to
refute
various
lines
of
thinking.
Writing
230
becomes
an
aesthetic-‐political
expanding
of
perception
that
can
divide
the
capacities
of
voice
and
silence
anew.
Within
Rancière’s
conception
of
politics
our
thinking
on
voice
and
our
writing
about
voice
highlights
the
fragility
of
voice.
It
was
mentioned
that
voice
cannot
emerge
from
a
proper
body,
in
its
proper
location
tied
to
specific
forms
of
speech.
It
cannot
be
traced
along
the
lines
of
established
categories.
Our
approaches
are
in
themselves
political
practices
and
therefore
require
dissensual
methods
that
invent
new
forms
of
sensible
structures
from
where
to
engage.
In
chapter
four
I
discuss
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak’s
essay
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
An
analysis
of
Spivak’s
essay
highlights
the
fact
that
women
in
the
global
South
are
confronted
by
a
particular
set
of
difficulties
when
it
comes
to
political
voicing.
The
discourses
of
masculinity,
patriarchy
and
imperialism
serves
to,
in
Spivak’s
analysis,
silence
the
voices
of
women.
Against
the
background
of
the
voices
of
South
African
women
Spivak
also
highlights
in
what
way
mechanisms
of
human
rights
and
gender
equality
serve
to
maintain
the
status
quo
rather
than
contributing
to
the
creation
of
spaces
where
voices
can
be
revealed.
Spivak
warns
against
the
dangers
of
representation
and
underlines
that
“speaking”
always
already
belongs
to
an
existing
structure
of
domination.
When
reading
Spivak’s
assertions
through
the
lens
of
Rancière’s
politics,
it
would
seem
as
if,
from
this
perspective,
the
subaltern
can
speak
through
radical
forms
of
equality.
Rancière’s
politics
emphasises
how
voicing
is
about
disidentification
and
the
delegitimation
of
speaking
positions.
Although
voicing
functions
within
the
police
order
that
we
must
live
in,
we
can
upset
the
order
of
the
police’s
discourse
and
mobilise
obligations
to
hear.
Equality
can
give
rise
to
paradoxical
confusing
identities
that
work
in-‐between
dominant
political
spheres,
names
and
spaces.
The
subaltern
is
confronted
by
dominant
established
frameworks
and
discourses
that
function
in
certain
circumstances
to
efface
voice,
but
voicing
can
occur
by
way
of
the
disembodiment
of
the
subaltern
from
the
discourses
that
produce
her.
Rancière’s
politics
points
to
the
question
of
how
we
close
off
opportunities
for
equality
in
our
theorising
and
shifts
the
point
of
focus
to
the
possibility
of
voices
declaring
equality.
231
In
chapter
five
I
attempt
to
trace
redistributions
of
the
sensible
as
a
way
of
further
reflecting
on
the
notion
of
voice.
Reacting
against
the
difficulties
surrounding
the
political
voicing
and
visibility
of
many
South
African
women
sketched
out
in
the
first
chapter,
I
explore
certain
figures
that
map
different
trajectories
of
the
visible
and
sayable.
Highlighting
verifications
of
equality
and
valorising
redistributions
of
the
sensible,
these
figures
give
rise
to
voicing
thought
not
to
exist.
De
Gouges
demonstrates
the
invention
that
is
characteristic
to
Rancière’s
political
subject.
Working
in-‐between
and
handling
double
meanings,
she
presented
a
political
case
for
women
to
be
counted
as
having
the
right
to
participate
in
politics.
Inventing
an
argument
and
the
ground
from
which
this
argument
counts,
De
Gouges
divides
the
parameters
of
inclusion
and
exclusion
anew.
Lucy
similarly
divides
anew
by
acting
and
speaking
in
a
way
that
point
to
another
time
and
place
and
another
way
of
living.
Lucy’s
voice
cannot
simply
be
located.
She
resists
easy
readings
and
as
such
becomes
an
alternative
figure
of
division.
The
political
statements
of
Abahlali
baseMjondolo
represent
a
declaration
of
equality
that
lays
the
contingency
of
inequality
bare.
Against
dominant
configurations
that
would
see
them
unable
to
understand
the
mechanism
of
government
and
governance,
Abahlali
sustains
struggle
and
engagement,
stating
that
they
also
think
and
that
they
cannot
easily
be
confined
to
the
peripheries
of
the
city.
The
discussion
of
Bhubaneswari
revealed
the
politics
of
voice.
A
different
reading
doesn’t
attempt
to
make
Bhubaneswari
speak,
but
rather
demonstrates
that
politics
work
between
the
lines
of
what
can
be
seen
and
interpreted
as
voice
and
what
cannot.
An
alternative
telling
therefore
reveals
an
impossible
voicing
that
maps
a
different
relation
between
voice
and
silence.
Continuously
working
against
the
grain
of
established
frameworks
of
visibility,
intelligibly
and
perceptibility,
Rancière’s
thinking
opens
up
a
different
framework
from
where
to
consider
what
it
means
to
speak.
He
invites
us
to
contemplate,
under
the
presupposition
of
equality,
new
ways
of
acting,
speaking
and
doing
in
order
to
displace
current
norms
of
voice.
Mapping
times,
places,
spaces,
232
capacities
and
sensible
distributions,
his
politics
implicitly
raises
the
question
of
how
we
are
to
continue
to
resist
the
established
formations
of
voice.
It
was
mentioned
in
chapter
one
that
Rancière’s
work
on
politics
is
but
one
way
in
which
to
imagine
the
notion
of
political
voice.
After
exploring
Rancière’s
formulations,
this
description
becomes
even
more
accurate.
In
the
context
of
Rancière’s
conception
of
politics,
implicit
in
the
notion
voice,
is
imagination.
Rancière
points
us
to
a
radical,
dissensual,
egalitarian
call
to
contest
the
very
definitions
of
what
it
means
to
have
a
voice.
Politics
is
the
process
of
inventing
a
voice.
We
always
have
invention
at
our
disposal;
invention
against
the
way
it
is,
against
inevitability
and
naturalisation,
against
the
mechanisms
of
silence
and
against
the
domain
of
the
impossible.
233
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Books
and
chapters
in
books
Althusser
A,
Rancière
J,
Macherey
P,
Balibar
E,
Establet
R
Reading
Capital
trans.
Brewster
B
London:
New
Left
Books
1970.
Althusser
L
Lenin
and
Philosophy,
and
Other
Essays
trans.
Brewster
B
London:
New
Left
Books
1971.
Althusser
L
Résponse
à
Jonh
Lewis
Paris:
Maspero
1973.
Althusser
L
For
Marx
trans.
Brewster
B
London:
The
Penguin
Press
1990.
Arendt
H
The
Human
Condition
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press
1958.
Badiou
A
“The
Lessons
of
Jacques
Rancière:
Knowledge
and
Power
after
the
Storm”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
30-‐51.
Badiou
A
Metapolitics
trans.
Barker
J
London:
Verso
2005.
Bosteels
B
“Rancière’s
Leftism,
Or,
Politics
and
Its
Discontents”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
158-‐176.
Butler
J
Antigone’s
Claim:
Kinship
Between
Life
and
Death
Columbia:
Columbia
University
Press
2000.
Cavarero
A
For
More
Than
One
Voice:
Toward
A
Philosophy
of
Vocal
Expression
trans.
Kottman
P
Stanford:
Stanford
University
Press
2005.
Citton
Y
“Political
Agency
and
the
Ambivalence
of
the
Sensible
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
120-‐139.
Chrisman
L
Postcolonial
Contraventions:
Cultural
Readings
of
Race,
Imperialism
and
Transnationalism
New
York:
Manchester
University
Press
2003.
Coetzee
JM
Disgrace
London:
Random
House
1999.
234
Davis
O
Jacques
Rancière
Cambridge:
Polity
2010.
Davis
O
(ed.)
Rancière
Now:
Current
Perspectives
on
Jacques
Rancière
Cambridge:
Polity
2013.
Deranty
J
&
Ross
A
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière
and
the
Contemporary
Scene
London:
Continuum
2012.
Derrida
J
Of
Grammatology
trans.
Spivak
GC
Baltimore:
John
Hopkins
University
Press
1976.
Douzinas
A
&
Gearey
C
Critical
Jurisprudence:
The
Political
Philosophy
of
Justice
Oxford:
Hart
Publishing
2005
Du
Toit
L
A
Philosophical
Investigation
of
Rape:
The
Making
and
Unmaking
of
the
Feminine
Self
Portland:
Routledge
2009.
Du
Toit
L
“Feminism
and
the
Ethics
of
Reconciliation”
in
Veitch
S
(ed.)
Law
and
the
Politics
of
Reconciliation
2007
185-‐214.
Foucault
M
The
History
of
Sexuality,
Volume
One:
An
Introduction
trans.
Hurley
R
Harmondsworth:
Penguin
1981.
Gardiner
M,
Macdonald
G,
O’Gallagher
N
(eds.)
Scottish
Literature
and
Postcolonial
Literature:
Comparative
Texts
and
Critical
Perspectives
Edinburgh:
Edinburgh
University
Press
2011.
Graham
G
Deconstructing
Ireland:
Identity,
Theory,
Culture
Edinburgh:
Edinburgh
University
Press
2001.
Gramsci
A
Selections
From
Prison
Notebooks
trans.
Hoare
Q,
Nowell
Smith
G
London:
Lawrence
and
Wishart
1978.
Hallward
P
“Staging
Equality:
Rancière’s
Theatrocracy
and
the
Limits
of
Anarchic
Equality”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
140-‐157.
Harasym
S
(ed.)
The
Postcolonial
Critic:
Interviews,
Strategies,
Dialogues
London:
Routledge
1990.
James
I
The
New
French
Philosophy
Cambridge:
Polity
2012.
235
Landry
D
&
Maclean
G
(eds.)
The
Spivak
Reader:
Selected
Works
of
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak
London:
Routledge
1996.
Lazarus
N
The
Postcolonial
Unconscious
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press
2011.
Lazarus
N
Nationalism
and
Cultural
Practice
in
a
Postcolonial
World
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press
1999.
Leitch
VB,
Cain
WE
et
al
(eds.)
The
Norton
Anthology
of
Theory
and
Criticism
New
York:
W.W
Norton
and
Company
2010.
Macey
D
Dictionary
of
Critical
Theory
London:
Penguin
Books
2000.
Madlingozi
T
“Good
Victim,
Bad
Victim:
Apartheid’s
Beneficiaries,
Victims
and
the
Struggle
for
Social
Justice
in
Van
Marle
K
&
Le
Roux
W
(eds.)
Law,
Memory
and
The
Legacy
of
Apartheid:
Ten
Years
After
AZAPO
v
President
of
SA
Pretoria:
University
of
Pretoria
Press
2007
107-‐126.
May
T
“Rancière
in
South
Carolina”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
105-‐
119.
May
T
The
Political
Thought
of
Jacques
Rancière:
Creating
Equality
Edinburgh:
Edinburgh
University
Press
2008.
Méchaoulan
E
“Sophisticated
Continuities
and
Historical
Discontinuities,
Or,
Why
Not
Protagoras?”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
55-‐66.
Morris
R
(ed.)
Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?
Reflections
on
the
History
of
an
Idea
Columbia:
Columbia
University
Press
2010.
Morton
S
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak
Portland:
Routledge
2003.
Parker
A
“Impossible
Speech-‐acts:
Jacques
Rancière’s
Erich
Auerbach”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
249-‐257.
Rancière
J
Aesthetics
and
its
Discontents
trans.
Cocoran
S
Cambridge:
Polity
2009.
236
Rancière
J
Disagreement:
Politics
and
Philosophy
trans.
Rose
J
Minneapolis:
University
of
Minnesota
Press
1999.
Rancière
J
Dissensus:
On
Politics
and
Aesthetics
Cocoran
S
(ed.)
London:
Continuum
2009.
Rancière
J
The
Emancipated
Spectator
trans.
Elliot
G
London:
Verso
2009.
Rancière
J
The
Flesh
of
Words:
The
Politics
of
Writing
trans.
Mandell
C
Stanford:
Stanford
University
Press
2004.
Rancière
J
The
Future
of
the
Image
trans.
Elliot
G
London:
Verso
2007.
Rancière
J
Hatred
of
Democracy
trans.
Cocoran
S
London:
Verso
2006.
Rancière
J
The
Ignorant
Schoolmaster:
Five
Lessons
in
Intellectual
Emancipation
trans.
Ross
K
Stanford:
Stanford
University
Press
1991.
Rancière
J
The
Names
of
History:
On
the
Poetics
of
Knowledge
trans.
Melehy
H
Minneapolis:
University
of
Minnesota
Press
1994.
Rancière
J
The
Nights
of
Labor:
The
Worker’s
Dream
in
Nineteenth-‐Century
France
trans.
Drury
J
Philadelphia:
Temple
University
Press
1989.
Rancière
J
On
the
Shores
of
Politics
trans.
Heron
L
London:
Verso
1995.
Rancière
J
The
Philosopher
and
His
Poor
trans.
Drury
J,
Oster
C,
Parker
A
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2003.
Rancière
J
The
Figures
of
History
trans.
Rose
J
Cambridge:
Polity
2012.
Rancière
J
The
Politics
of
Aesthetics:
The
Distribution
of
the
Sensible
trans.
and
introduced
by
Rockhill
G
(afterword
by
Žižek
S)
London:
Continuum
2004.
Rancière
J
The
Politics
of
Literature
trans.
Rose
J
Cambridge:
Polity
2011.
Rancière
J
Short
Voyages
to
the
Land
of
the
People
trans.
Swenson
J
Stanford:
Stanford
University
Press
2003.
237
Rancière
J
Moments
Politiques:
Interventions
1977-‐2009
trans
Foster
M
New
York:
Seven
Stories
Press
2009.
Rancière
J
Mute
Speech:
Literature,
Critical
Theory
and
Politics
trans.
Swenson
J,
introduced
by
Rockhill
G
New
York:
Columbia
University
Press
2011.
Rancière
J
Althusser’s
Lesson
trans.
Battista
E
London:
Continuum
2011.
Rancière
J
The
Aesthetic
Unconscious
trans.
Keates
D,
Swenson
J
Cambridge:
Polity
2009.
Rancière
J
The
Intellectual
and
His
People:
Staging
the
People
Volume
2
trans.
Fernbach
D
London:
Verso
2012.
Rancière
J
Chronicles
of
Consensual
Times
trans.
Cocoran
S
London:
Continuum
2010.
Rancière
J
Malaise
Dans
L’esthètique
Paris:
Galilée
1995.
Rancière
J
“The
Method
of
Equality:
An
Answer
to
some
Questions”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
273-‐288.
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009.
Rockhill
G
“The
Politics
of
Aesthetics:
Political
History
and
the
Hermeneutics
of
Art”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
195-‐215.
Ross
K
“Historicizing
Untimeliness”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
1-‐29.
Ruiters
G
(ed.)
Gender
Activism:
Perspectives
on
the
South
African
Transition,
Institutional
Culture
and
Everyday
Life
2008.
Said
E
Orientalism:
Western
Conceptions
of
the
Orient
Harmondsworth:
Penguin
1977.
Sibanda
S
“Not
Purpose-‐made!
Transformative
Constitutionalism,
Post-‐
Independence
Constitutionalism,
and
the
Struggle
to
Eradicate
Poverty”
in
238
Liebenberg
S
&
Quinot
G
(eds.)
Law
and
Poverty:
Perspectives
from
South
Africa
and
Beyond
2012
40-‐58.
Spivak
GC
“Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?”
in
Nelson
C
&
Grossberg
L
(eds.)
Marxism
and
the
Interpretation
of
Culture
Urbana:
University
of
Illinois
Press;
Basingstoke:
Macmillan
1988
271-‐313.
Spivak
GC
A
Critique
of
Postcolonial
Reason:
Toward
a
History
of
the
Vanishing
Present
Cambridge:
Harvard
University
Press
1999.
Spivak
GC
et
al
Conversations
with
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak
Michigan:
Seagull
Books
2006.
Swenson
J
“Style
Indirect
Libre”
in
Rockhill
G
&
Watts
P
(eds.)
Jacques
Rancière:
History,
Politics,
Aesthetics
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press
2009
258-‐271.
Tanke
J
Jacques
Rancière:
An
Introduction:
Philosophy,
Politics,
Aesthetics
London:
Continuum
2011.
Unger
R
The
Critical
Legal
Studies
Movement
Cambridge:
Harvard
University
Press
1986.
Van
Marle
K
(ed.)
Refusal,
Transition
and
Post-‐Apartheid
Law
Stellenbosch:
Sun
Media
2009.
Van
Marle
K
&
Motha
S
(eds.)
Genres
of
Critique:
Law,
Aesthetics
and
Liminality
Stellenbosch:
SUN
press
2013.
Walsh
D
Women’s
Rights
in
Democratizing
States:
Just
Debate
and
Gender
Justice
in
the
Public
Sphere
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press
2011.
Žižek
S
The
Ticklish
Subject:
The
Absent
Centre
of
Political
Ontology
London:
Verso
1999.
Articles
Boehmer
E
“Not
saying
sorry,
not
speaking
pain:
Gender
implications
in
Disgrace”
Interventions:
International
Journal
of
Postcolonial
Studies
(2002)
4
342-‐351.
Bohler-‐Muller
N
“Other
possibilities?
Postmodern
feminist
legal
theory
in
South
Africa”
South
African
Journal
on
Human
Rights
(2002)
18
614-‐629.
Botha
H
“Equality,
plurality
and
structural
power”
South
African
Journal
on
Human
Rights
(2009)
25
1-‐37.
239
Chambers
S
“Jacques
Rancière
and
the
problem
of
pure
politics”European
Journal
of
Political
Theory
(2011)
10
303-‐326.
Davis
O
“The
radical
pedagogies
of
François
Bon
and
Jacques
Rancière”
French
Studies
(2010)
LXIV
178-‐191.
Dasgupta
S
“Words,
bodies,
time:
Queer
theory
before
and
after
itself”
Borderlands
(2009)
8
1-‐20.
Dillon
M
“A
passion
for
the
(im)possible:
Jacques
Rancière,
equality,
pedagogy
and
the
messianic”
European
Journal
of
Political
Theory
(2005)
4
429-‐452.
Froneman
J
“Legal
reasoning
and
legal
culture:
Our
‘vision’
of
law”
Stellenbosch
Law
Review
(2005)
16
1-‐20.
Hafner-‐Burton
E
&
Ron
J
“Human
rights
institutions:
Rhetoric
and
efficacy”
Journal
of
Peace
Research
(2007)
44
379-‐383.
Hallward
P
“Jacques
Rancière
and
the
subversion
of
mastery”
Paragraph:
A
Journal
of
Modern
Critical
Theory
(2005)
28
26-‐45.
Harris
A
“Race
and
essentialism
in
feminist
legal
theory”
Stanford
Law
Review
(1990)
42
581-‐616.
Jooste
Y
“Thinking
two
worlds
into
one:
The
‘distribution
of
the
sensible’
and
women’s
renegotiation”
Stellenbosch
Law
Review
(2013)
24
528-‐537.
Kennedy
D
“Form
and
substance
in
private
law
adjudication”
Harvard
Law
Review
(1976)
1685-‐1778.
Klare
K
“Transformative
constitutionalism
and
legal
culture”
South
African
Journal
on
Human
Rights
(1998)
14
146-‐188.
Langa
P
“Transformative
constitutionalism”
Stellenbosch
Law
Review
(2006)
17
351-‐360.
Liebenberg
S
“Towards
a
transformative
adjudication
of
socio-‐economic
rights”
(2007)
Speculum
Juris
21
41-‐59.
May
T
“Jacques
Rancière
and
the
ethics
of
equality”
SubStance
(2007)
113
20-‐36.
May
T
“There
are
no
Queers:
Jacques
Rancière
and
post-‐identity
politics”
Borderlands
(2009)
8
1-‐17.
Moseneke
D
“The
Bram
Fischer
Memorial
Lecture:
Transformative
adjudication”
South
African
Journal
of
Human
Rights
(2002)
14
314.
240
Parry
B
“Problems
in
current
theories
of
colonial
discourse”
Oxford
Literary
Review
(1987)
9
27-‐58.
Pelletier
C
“Rancière
and
the
poetics
of
the
social
sciences”
International
Journal
of
Research
and
Method
in
Education
(2009)
32
267-‐284.
Pieterse
M
“What
do
we
mean
when
we
talk
about
transformative
constitutionalism?”
South
African
Public
Law
(2005)
20
155-‐166.
Rancière
J
“Politics,
identification
and
subjectivization”
October
(1992)
61
58-‐64.
Rancière
J
“Who
is
The
Subject
of
the
Rights
of
Man?”
South
Atlantic
Quarterly
(2004)
103
297-‐310.
Rancière
J
“Literature,
politics,
aesthetics:
Approaches
to
democratic
disagreement”
SubStance
(2000)
29
3-‐24.
Rancière
J
“Thinking
between
disciplines:
An
aesthetics
of
knowledge”
Parrhesia
(2006)
1
1-‐12.
Rancière
J
“The
myth
of
the
artisan:
Critical
reflections
on
a
category
of
social
history”
International
Labor
and
Working-‐Class
History
(1983)
24
1-‐16.
Roux
T
“Transformative
constitutionalism
and
the
best
interpretation
of
the
South
African
constitution:
Distinction
without
a
difference?”
Stellenbosch
Law
Review
(2009)
20
258-‐285.
Sanders
M
“Disgrace”
Interventions:
International
Journal
of
Postcolonial
Studies
(2002)
4
363-‐373.
Schaap
A
“Enacting
the
right
to
have
rights:
Jacques
Rancière’s
critique
of
Hannah
Arendt”
European
Journal
of
Political
Theory
(2011)
10
23-‐45.
Selmeczi
A
“Dis/placing
political
illiteracy:
The
politics
of
intellectual
equality
in
a
South
African
shack-‐dweller’s
movement”
Interface:
A
Journal
for
and
about
Social
Movements
(2014)
6
230-‐265.
Shetty
S
&
Bellamy
E
“Postcolonialism’s
archive
fever”
Diacritics
(2000)
30
25-‐48.
Spivak
GC
“Three
women’s
texts
and
a
critique
of
imperialism”
Critical
Inquiry
(1985)
12
243-‐261.
Spivak
GC
“Scattered
speculations
on
the
subaltern
and
the
popular”
Postcolonial
Studies
(2005)
8
457-‐486.
241
Spivak
GC
“Ethics
and
politics
in
Tagore,
Coetzee
and
certain
scenes
of
teaching”
Diacritics
(2002)
32
17-‐31.
Stoneman
E
“Appropriate
indecorum:
Rhetoric
and
aesthetics
in
the
political
theory
of
Jacques
Rancière”
Philosophy
and
Rhetoric
(2011)
44
129-‐149.
Van
Marle
K
“Lives
of
action,
thinking
and
revolt:
A
feminist
call
for
politics
and
becoming
in
post-‐apartheid
South
Africa”
South
African
Public
Law
(2004)
19
605-‐
628.
Van
Marle
K
“Transformative
constitutionalism
as/and
critique”
Stellenbosch
Law
Review
(2009)
20
286-‐301.
Van
Marle
K,
De
Villiers
I,
Beukes
E
“Memory,
space
and
gender:
Re-‐imagining
the
law”
South
African
Public
Law
(2012)
27
560-‐572.
Internet
sources
and
other
Interviews:
Panagia
D
“Dissenting
Words:
A
Conversation
with
Jacques
Rancière”
diacritics
(2000)
30
113-‐126.
Landry
D
&
Maclean
G
“Subaltern
Talk”
interview
with
Spivak
GC
in
Landry
D
&
Maclean
G
(eds.)
The
Spivak
Reader:
Selected
Works
of
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak
London:
Routledge
1996
288-‐297.
De
Kock
L
“Interview
with
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak,
New
Nation
Writers
Conference
in
South
Africa”
International
English
Literature
(1992)
23
29-‐47.
Internet
Sources:
Official
website
of
Abahlali
baseMjondolo:
Abahlali.org
Abahlali
baseMjondolo
“Statement
of
the
Xenophobic
Attacks
in
Johannesburg”
May,
2008
available
online
at:
http://abahlali.org/node/3582.
Abahlali
baseMjondolo
“Sutcliff’s
Dirty
Tricks
Won’t
Keep
Us
From
Marching
In
Our
City
Tomorrow”
March,
2010
available
online
at:
http://abahlali.org/node/6403
Arsenjuk
L
“On
Jacques
Rancière”
Fronesis
(2005)
19/20
available
online
at:
www.eurozine.com/articles/2007-‐01-‐01-‐arsenjuk-‐en.html.
242
Butler
M
&
Pithouse
R
“Lessons
from
eThekwini:
Pariahs
Hold
Their
Ground
Against
a
State
that
is
Both
Criminal
and
Democratic”
March,
2007
available
online
at
http://abahlali.org/node/984.
De
Boever
A
“Feminism
after
Rancière:
Women
in
J.M
Coetzee
and
Jeff
Wall”
Transformations:
Journal
of
Media
and
Culture
(2011)
19
available
online
at:
http://www.transformationsjournal.org/journal/issue_19/article
_03.shtml.
Hlongwa
M
“The
No
Land,
No
House,
No
Vote
Campaign
Still
On
For
2009”
March,
2007
available
online
at:
httpp://abahlali.org/node/510.
Poni
M
“Public
Violence”
2009
available
online
at:
http://abahlali.org/node/5769.
Rancière
J
“The
Thinking
of
Dissensus:
Politics
as
Aesthetics”
paper
presented
at
the
conference
Post-‐structuralism
and
Radical
Politics
Goldsmiths
College,
London
(16-‐17
September
2003)
available
at:
http://homepages.gold.ac.uk/psrpsg/conference
/fidelity/html.
Ross
D
“Politics
and
aesthetics,
or,
transformations
of
Aristotle
in
Bernard
Stiegler”
Transformations:
Journal
of
Media
and
Culture
(2009)
17
available
online
at:
http://www.transformationsjournal.org/journal/issue
_17/article_04.shtml.
Sellberg
K
“Sublime
gender
transposition:
The
reformed
Platonism
of
Jacques
Rancière’s
aesthetics
as
queer
performance”
Transformations:
Journal
of
Media
and
Culture
(2011)
19
available
online
at:
http://www.transformationsjournal.org/journal/issue_19/article
_032.shtml.
Snodgrass
L
“South
Africa:
A
dangerous
place
to
be
poor,
black
and
a
woman”
The
Conversation
September,
2015
available
at
http://theconversation.com/south-‐
africa-‐a-‐dangerous-‐place-‐to-‐be-‐poor-‐black-‐and-‐a-‐woman-‐47287.
Zikode
S
“We
are
the
third
force”
October,
2006
available
online
at:
Abahlali.org/node/17/
Dissertations:
Selmeczi
A
“We
Are
The
People
Who
Do
Not
Count:
Thinking
the
Distribution
of
the
Biopolitics
of
Abandonment”
PhD
thesis,
Central
European
University,
March
2012.
243