A History of The Histories of Econometrics
A History of The Histories of Econometrics
A History of The Histories of Econometrics
The understanding procedure. Another sort of question that the scientist has to
answer is: why did it happen? Why did this situation exist? Why did the events
follow the course they did? The answer to these questions constitutes the
rational part of the investigation. By the power of his mind the scientist tries to
bring some reasonable order into the happenings and the things he observed.
Introduction: 1985
- February 20: Minolta releases world's first autofocus single-lens reflex camera;
- March 4: The Food and Drug Administration approves a blood test for AIDS, used
- November 20: Microsoft Corporation releases the first version of Windows; and
- Franco Modigliani receives the Nobel prize for “for his pioneering analyses of
However unique and special these events are, they do not necessarily make 1985 a
special year.
- August 19: At the Fifth World Congress of the Econometric Society, for the first
speakers were David F. Hendry, Edward Leamer and Christopher Sims. Adrian R.
Pagan (1987) was discussant and Angus Deaton was chairing this session.
- December 17-18: Two-day symposium to mark Joop Klant’s retirement from the
presented (de Marchi 1988) were ‘An appraisal of Popperian methodology’ by Daniel
M. Hausman, ‘The natural order’ by Klant, ‘Ad hocness in economics and the
Popperian tradition’ by D. Wade Hands, ‘Popper and the LSE economists’ by Neil de
Marchi, ‘The case for falsification’ by Terence W. Hutchison, ‘John Hicks and the
Roy Weinraub, ‘The case for pluralism’ by Bruce J. Caldwell, ‘Thick and thin
Association, a Joint Session with the History of Economic Society was held on ‘First
Forays Into the History of Economics’1. The papers presented at this session were:
1
This is how it was announced (AEA 1985, 907). According to Morgan this is probably a misprint, it
should be ‘Econometrics’ instead of ‘Economics’.
- December 30: At the same AEA Meeting, another Joint Session with the HES was
held on ‘Popper and the LSE Economists’. The papers presented at this session were:
‘Popper and the LSE’ by de Marchi (1988a), ‘Ad hocness in economics’ by Hands
Lawrence A. Boland were discussants and Weintraub was presiding this session.
Three other relevant events of 1985 were the publications of Weintraub’s book
General Equilibrium Analysis and Michael McAleer, Pagan and Paul A. Volker’s
article ‘What will take the con out of econometrics?’3, and the foundation of
Phillips was not only the founder of Econometric Theory but also its editor since its
first issue published in 1985 till today. The first issue contains an extensive Editorial
explaining the editorial policy objectives of this journal. It is remarkable that to four
the subject's early scholars. In its present stage of evolution, the subject of
econometrics is still visibly rooted in the historical tradition that slowly took
shape in the early years of this century, which gained definite form in the work
Haavelmo and the research of the Cowles Commission during the 1940s, the
latter very largely under the inspiration of Marschak and Koopmans. Many of
2
This is also the title of his D.Phil. (Oxon) Thesis defended in 1988.
3
This was a response to Leamer (1983).
3
us have much to learn from this historical tradition and from the talents,
of articles that explore the nature of this historical tradition, examine the
evolution of econometric thought from its foundation research, and study the
[…] These in-depth interviews will offer the opportunity of a wide ranging
insights into the evolution and the present state of econometric research.
more about the human side of research discovery and come to understand the
genesis of the subject’s main ideas from some of its finest minds. Most
particularly, those readers who have not had the benefit of personal contact
with some of our leading econometricians may now have the opportunity to
hear their voices, not only on matters concerned with their own research, but
and will encourage them to make the fullest use of their own talents. (Phillips
1985, 4)
These are many facts to show that in 1985 there was close mutual interaction of
4
continued till today: In 2006 a new Palgrave series Handbook of Econometrics was
Strikingly, this volume starts with a (historical) overview (by Aris Spanos) of
different approaches “that should encourage though, discussion, and perhaps some
textbooks” and two on the history of econometrics (by Richard W. Farebrother and
Summer Meeting of the Econometric Society at Duke University in June 2007 had –
for the first time – a session on the history of econometrics, organised by Weintraub.
The session was a success: “The history session was well attended and the discussion
was lively. Although the audience was almost entirely practitioners rather than
historians” (Hoover 2010, 20). An outcome of this discussion was that the editors of
HOPE and the session participants started to consider whether it would be useful and
on the history of econometrics to see who the earlier contributors were and whether
they were still active to find out whether a critical mass of historians would be
interested “to turn up the heat and bring the history of econometrics back to the
forefront of the field” (Hoover 2010, 19). Surveying the literature it soon became
clear that the interest in the history of econometrics arose from within econometrics
itself, and that its histories are mainly written by econometricians. Only a few papers
5
on econometrics were written by historians of economics. According to Weintraub
modern work in economics. That is, the history of economic thought should
But he only rectified this scandal partly; his own study was on the history of
Twenty-five years after this scandal, the situation has not really improved. Although
Journal of the History of Economic Thought and in HOPE, the number of articles
So, on the one hand, one can be pleased that the histories of econometrics are at least
written by the econometricians themselves, but on the other hand, this leads therefore
history can be used to delineate econometrics, that is, to set its disciplinary boundaries,
with respect to its aim, its methods, its scientific values, etc. The risk is that history is
4
He mentions, however, “some work in England by Mary Morgan, sponsored by the Social Science
Research Council and guided by Professor David Hendry” (140).
6
used to legitimize set boundaries, while actually these boundaries should be
histories are written from the perspective of econometrics as a separate science, and
so they are constructed separate from the histories of connected disciplines like
delineating history has also a blind spot for applied research where disciplinary
boundaries are usually blurred, but also a blind spot for what is happening outside the
geographic areas of appointed founding fathers. Most histories give the impression
the rest of the world. The conference aim was to rectify these historiographic biases
by inviting contributions to these issues; the subsequent chapters are a result of this
invitation.
Chart Session
Another goal of the conference was to gain some understanding of the historical
A way to deal with these questions was to take the advantage that the HOPE
conferences would be held at Duke University where several of the 1985 characters
had and have their (temporary) home office. The original idea was to have a ‘witness
seminar’ with the 1980s witnesses. A witness seminar is a seminar “where several
people associated with a particular set of circumstances or events are invited to meet
7
together to discuss, debate, and even disagree about their reminiscences” (Tansey
1997). Because a witness seminar’s dynamics depends on its focus on a “particular set
a seminar. The main question was to investigate what happened in the 1980s with
event, so it would be hard to know what to focus on. Nevertheless we decided to have
a collective-memory stimulating session with the Duke people (currently called the
HOPE Group) and the conference participants, and not to call it a ‘witness seminar’
but a ‘chart session’ instead:5 Morgan and Boumans had prepared several charts to
stimulate the participant’s memories.6 These ‘charts’ showed diagrams and graphs of
The surprising result of this session7 was that after a warming-up stage participants
started to call several events that appeared to be important catalysers for several works
on the history of econometrics. This is the reason why we started above with listing
the 1985 events. It seems that for this kind of oral history, whether you would want to
Two events of the 1980s episode turned out to be crucial: The very early (8:00am)
Sunday morning session on ‘First forays into the history of econom[etr]ics’ was very
5
The whole session was video-recorded and is available [Paul: ?].
6
Because of the ash clouds spit out by the Iceland volcano Eyjafjallajökull, Morgan and Dupont-
Kieffer were not able to attend physically, they participated via the internet.
7
For writing this introduction we benefitted a lot of the reminiscences shared by the participants (in
order of sitting): Hoover, Jim Wible, Weintraub, Eric Chancellier, Aiko Ikeo, Robert Dimand, Gilbert,
Hsiang-Ke Chao, Charles Renfro, Allin Cottrell, Qin, Daniela Parisi, John Aldrich, Jeff Biddle, Tom
Stapleford, Bernardo Coelho, Sofia Terlica, Alain Marciano, de Marchi, Paul Dudenhefer, and (online)
Morgan and Dupont-Kieffer. This chapter is a reflection of this session.
8
well attended and brought de Marchi and Gilbert to the idea of having the papers of
this session published in the Oxford Economic Papers (1989), of which Gilbert had
been general editor from 1979 to 1988. As elected vice president of the History of
Economics Society, de Marchi had the responsibility to concoct three sessions for the
AEA meetings. Coats (1987, 62) mentioned this session explicitly: “Incidentally, the
Economics Society session organized by Neil de Marchi at the December, 1985 AEA
meeting – is one of the most exciting current developments in the subject, for it
promises not only to enhance our knowledge and understanding but also to widen the
professional audience and support for the history of economics.” The other event was
the 1989 Capri conference (see below) where several of the characters involved in this
Is Econometrics Science?
The reason for the convergence of econometrics, history of economics and philosophy
of science in the 1980s is the accusation in the 1970s of the econometrics’ inability to
meet the high expectations of the 1950s as producer of reliable predictions and policy
published in 1980, the same year in which Sims’ ‘Macroeconomics and Reality’ was
published in Econometrica, the article in which his VAR approach was introduced.
9
What started as a critique of John Maynard Keynes (1939) on Jan Tinbergen’s first
League of Nations volume (1939) soon became a more general debate about the role
the late 1930s by the League of Nations to perform statistical tests on business-cycle
theories. The results of this study were published in a two-volume work, Statistical
achieved, based on three case studies. Keynes’s (1939) critique was that the technique
of multiple correlation analysis which had been adopted by Tinbergen was solely a
The implication was that if the economic theorist does not provide the modeler with a
complete set of causal factors, then the measurement of the other causal factors will
be biased. Moreover, Keynes argued that some significant factors in any economy are
was the assumed linearity of the relations between these factors. He also noted that the
determination of time-lags and trends was too often based on trial and error, and too
little informed by theory. And last but not least was the problem of invariance: would
the relations found also hold for the future? These questions remained central to the
subsequent debate.
Taking into account all of these concerns and Tinbergen’s responses to them, Keynes
came to the conclusion that econometrics was not yet a scientific approach:
No one could be more frank, more painstaking, more free from subjective bias
10
human qualities go, whom it would be safer to trust with black magic. That
there is anyone I would trust with it at the present stage or that this brand of
persuaded. But Newton, Boyle and Locke all played with Alchemy. So let him
model”, which, according to him consisted of: using an incomplete set of determining
factors (omitted variables bias), building models with unobservable variables (such as
expectations), estimated from badly measured data based on index numbers, obtaining
spurious correlations from the use of proxy variables and simultaneity, being unable
forms not knowing the appropriate dimensions of the regressors, mis-specifying the
dynamic reactions and lag lengths, incorrectly pre-filtering the data, invalidly
Hendry admitted that “It is difficult to provide a convincing case for the defence
alchemy since many of his criticisms remain apposite” (Hendry 1980, 402). The ease
11
econometric method suggests alchemy, but according to Hendry, the scientific status
There are two issues that are of particular interest here. Firstly, Hendry in the need of
saying something about what science is, referred to and used mainly Popperian
literature: Chalmers 1976, Popper 1968, 1969 and Lakatos 1974, but also mentions
Kuhn (1962). Secondly, research for this paper was financed in part by a grant
(HR6727) from the Social Science Research Council (SSRC) to the Study in the
History of Econometric Thought at the LSE. This grant was also used to finance
Morgan’s PhD research on the history of econometrics which she, in 1979, had just
Harry Johnson and Roy Allen sold me their old copies of Econometrica, which
went back to the first volume in 1933. Reading early papers such as Haavelmo
ideas and ignored the evolution of our discipline. Dick Stone agreed, and he
had lost her job at the Bank of England when Margaret Thatcher abolished
Soon afterwards, Qin started to study the more recent history of econometrics through
to about the mid-1970s, which led to her PhD thesis in 1989, supervised by Hendry,
8
She finished her PhD in 1984. Her 1990 book originated from this thesis.
9
In 1983, the Social Science Research Council had changed into Economic and Social Research
Council.
12
Gilbert and Stephen Nickell.10 This interest in the history of econometrics also led to
a series of seminars at Nuffield to discuss history with John Aldrich, Gilbert, Morgan
Hendry referred to Keynes’s usage of the term alchemy to discuss the scientific nature
see Hendry 1980, 388). This characterization is based on a story by Carl F. Christ
(1967, 155):
I once had an urgent letter to dictate and, the Economics Department secretary
This story was probably the motivation for Leamer (1983) to contribute to the debate
about the scientific character of econometrics under the title: “Let’s take the con out
of econometrics”.11
Leamer’s paper is very much about the “myth” of science that empirical research is
10
Morgan and Aldrich were her thesis examiners. Her 1993 book originated from this thesis.
11
“Con” must have the meaning of “a swindle in which you cheat at gambling or persuade a person to
buy worthless property”, like con in “con man”: “a man who cheats or tricks someone by means of a
confidence trick”. So to take the con out of something is taking the tricks away. We thank Morgan for
her to understand this phrase. McAleer, Pagan and Volker (1985) has a similar interpretation.
13
problem of nonexperimental settings (usual the case in economics) compared to
(Leamer 1983, 33). Traditional econometrics seems not to admit this “experimental
belt’ which protects certain hard core propositions from falsification” (34). So,
But also “the false idol of objectivity has done great damage to economic science”
(36). If we want to make progress, according to Leamer, “the first step we must take is
logical conclusion based on facts, but because “the sampling distribution and the prior
distribution are actually opinions and not facts, a statistical inference is and must
opinion held by all, or at least held by a set of people you regard to be a close
14
It is thus the task of the econometrician to withhold belief until an inference is shown
approach and the VAR approach, respectively, leading to the debates of the mid 1980s.
Beside the already mentioned symposium at the Fifth World Congress of the
Econometric Society, according to Dale J. Poirier (Hendry, Leamer and Poirier 1990),
these debates took place at sessions of the North American Summer Meeting in June
1986 at Duke University, and the Australasia Meeting in August 1988 at the
Daniel McFadden, John W. Pratt, Eugine Savin and Sims as panelists and John
methodology with Dennis S. Aigner, Clive W.J. Granger, Leamer and M. Hashem
discussions” (172), Poirier (Hendry, Leamer and Poirier 1990) organized a “dialogue”
This Methodenstreit fits nicely in a longer tradition of debates about the most
These well-known debates are all strikingly related to econometric methodology. The
15
advantage of debates is that they are often less technical and so receive more attention
Delineation of Econometrics
This worry about developing an econometric methodology that can help to prevent
debate, is not so different from the motivation of the founding fathers of econometrics
to design a program for turning economics into a science.12 The beginnings and its
Ragnar Frisch, who first coined the term econometrics in his very first paper in
economics ‘Sur un problème d’économique pure’ (1926), the term means the
discipline which, for the lack of a better name, may be called econometrics.
pure economics, as far as possible, into a science in the strict sense of the word.
(Frisch 1971)
In his first Editorial of the newly established journal Econometrica, Frisch (1933)
12
See Bjerkholt and Qin (2011a) for a more detailed history of the founding of the Econometric
Society with the aim of “scientization” of economics.
16
Its definition is implied in the statement of the scope of the Society, in Section
nationalistic bias. Its main object shall be to promote studies that aim at a
It is apparent that the underlying motivation for this “new discipline”, from its
Presumably, this is the reason Frisch and Tinbergen were awarded the first Nobel
Prize in economics. As is well known, the Nobel Prize in economics is not a real
Nobel prize but the Central Bank of Sweden Prize in Economic Science in Memory of
Alfred Nobel instituted at the tercentenary celebration of the Swedish Central Bank.
The Central Bank approached the Nobel Foundation and the Royal Swedish Academy
of Science (the awarding authority for the prizes in physics and chemistry) for
agreement on the conditions and rules for the prize. “There was, however, a certain
scepticism towards the new prize idea among some natural scientists in the Academy
– partly because of a general reluctance to extend Nobel prizes to new fields, partly
17
enough to warrant a prize of this kind on an equal footing with prizes in ‘hard
sciences’ like physic and chemistry” (Lindbeck 1985, 37-38). Because of this
skepticism it is interesting to see that the first prize was awarded to two founders of
econometrics: “Their aim has been to lend economic theory mathematical stringency,
and to render it in a form that permits empirical quantification and a statistical testing
of hypotheses. One essential object has been to get away from the vague, more
This was, however, not the only way econometrics was originally delineated. While
designing its program, Frisch together with Charles Frederick Roos and Irving Fisher
were also drawing a list of potential charter members for the Econometric Society in
formation. The list consisted of 28 names from 11 countries (Divisia 1953, Bjerkholt
kind of delineation, it is remarkable that from its first issue in 1933 onwards (till the
Francesco Fuoco, William Stanley Jevons*, Hans von Mangoldt, Johann Heinrich
13
Luigi Amoroso, L. v. Bortkiewicz, A.L. Bowley, T.N. Carver, Gustav Cassel, J.B. Clark, J.M. Clark,
C. Colson, F. Divisia, G.C. Evans, Mordecai Ezekiel, Corrado Gini, J.M. Keynes, Hans Mayer, H.L.
Moore, Jacques Moret, Bertil Ohlin, Warren M. Persons, A.C. Pigou, Umberto Ricci, Jacques Rueff, H.
Schultz, J. Schumpeter, E. Slutsky, T. de Pietri Tonelli, Gustavo del Vecchio, Harald Westergaard and
W. Zadadski.
14
The names with an asterisk have also their photograph printed in Econometrica. In issue 2.4 (1934)
there is also a “specimen” printed of Walras’ correspondence.
18
Gerhard Tintner (1953) used this strategy of appointing forerunners as one of the
means to “define” econometrics. These were Gregory King, William Petty’s Political
From 1939 onwards, articles on “founding fathers” were published whenever the
Colson*, Georges Darmois, François Divisia, Luigi Einaudi, I. Fisher, Eraldo Fossati,
Frisch*, Yehuda Grunfeld, Leif Johansen, Keynes, Oskar Ryszard Lange, Ta-Chung
Liu, Moore*, Hans Peter, Roos, Henry Schultz*, Joseph A. Schumpeter*, Eugen
attention and awareness died more or less out in the 1960s. Note, for example, that
Econometrica didn’t pay any attention to the fact that its first editor Frisch and
Tinbergen received the very first Nobel Prize in economics in 1969. As we saw earlier,
mathematical theory of political economy” which was published in the Journal of the
Statistical Society of London, for two reasons: firstly, “with the purpose of
discovering such forgotten works and memoirs” and secondly, “in the hope that
19
suggestions may be thereby elicited for its extension and correction” (398).15 The list
published this list with a translation of Jevons’ call for extensions and corrections in
the Journal des Économistes. The lists were sent around for further “completion”
and other published writings” in the second edition of his Theory of Political
Economy [1879]. This list contained 146 publications. In the preface to this edition, he
writers must be mathematical so far as they are scientific at all, because they
treat of economic quantities, and the relations of such quantities, and all
quantities and relations of quantities come within the scope of the mathematics.
According to Jevons, the list could be decomposed into four distinct classes. A first
class of publications are of those “who have not at all attempted mathematical
second class contains those “who have abundantly employed mathematical apparatus”,
but, misunderstood “its true use, or being otherwise diverted from a true theory” (xxv).
The third class contains those “who, without the parade of mathematical language or
20
quantitative ideas” (xxv). The most important class, however, is the fourth class of
those “who have consciously and avowedly attempted to frame a mathematical theory
of the subject, and have […] succeeded in reaching a true view of the Science”
(xxviii). These are: Jules Dupuit, Cournot and Walras. But a “truly remarkable
discovery in the history of this branch of literature” (xxxii) was Hermann Heinrich
Gossen.16
Fisher had selected out of Jevons’ 1888 list “those 50 which are either undoubtedly
method” (Fisher 1892, 120). To this list a second list was added with 66 publications
Wealth.
This tradition was also continued in Econometrica by the editorial aim of organizing
surveys of “the significant developments within the main fields that are of interest to
the econometrician” (Frisch 1933, 3). The idea was to have four surveys each year,
one of each on the following fields: 1) general theory, 2) business cycle theory, 3)
16
In the third edition (1888), a list of books was added by Jevons’s wife Harriet Ann Jevons. This list
contained 196 writings.
21
Tinbergen on field (1); Alvin H. Hansen and Herbert Tout, and Tinbergen on (2); Paul
Lorenz, Horst Mendershausen, Paul R. Rider, Roos and W. A. Shewhart on (3); and C.
Bresciani-Turroni, Jakob Marschak, Roos and Hans Staehle on (4). These surveys did
not only inform the reader of Econometrica about “significant developments”, but
also to promote new theories, tools or methodologies. This tradition came to an end
Besides the already mentioned histories, bibliographies and surveys there are several
contributions on the history of the Econometric Society by Divisia (1953) and Christ
(1983) and on the Cowles Commission by Christ (1952, 1977, 1985 and 1994),
The boiling points of interest in the history of econometrics were initiated by attempts
to delineate the discipline, that is, to define its boundaries, and to identify the proper
scientific approach. What we see is that this delineation is closely related to the
images of science adhered in each period of interest. For Jevons and Fisher a scientific
images playing a role in the methodological debates of the 1980s were those of Karl
Popper, Imre Lakatos and Thomas Kuhn. These science images in each period played
17
Phillips was the supervisor of Epstein’s (1984) Ph.D. Thesis “Econometric Methodology in
Historical Perspective”. “I started to develop serious questions about the general scientific status of
empirical econometrics. […] I felt it was important to explore the problem more deeply in the context
of the studies and methodological arguments developed by the researchers who were most influential in
shaping econometrics as we know today. To my surprise, I discovered a long history of substantive
debates over methodology that complements, and even extends, the critiques put forth recently by some
of the most respected modern practitioners” (Epstein 1987, v).
22
Weintraub’s (“long struggle of escape” to find the most appropriate)
historiography
discipline that studies these ideals. So, it seems obvious that a historiography focused
obviousness of this connection, it has not been investigated as much for econometrics,
as it has been done for mathematical economics: In his various publications of the
development of the work they evaluate” (140). For that reason he quoted Lakatos’s
history of science without philosophy is blind” (Lakatos 1971, 91). Influenced by the
philosophical views of that time, that is, of Kuhn and Lakatos, methodology should be
introduction to the special issue of the Oxford Economic Papers on the history and
methodology of econometrics:
In fact methodology is inquiry into why the accepted is judged acceptable. But
standards alter; and while methodology can be suggestive, its suggestions are
offered only on the basis of an understanding of past and current practice and
23
the reasons for it. Methodology thus shades imperceptibility into historical
But their philosophical framework itself was fixed, namely the developments were
sense” (5). The same applies to Weintraub’s (1985) historical study of General
have been distorted by the use of inappropriate models taken from the philosophy of
science that were developed to appraise work in physical sciences” (i), but
nevertheless he took for granted that Lakatos’s model of research programmes was
Lakatos, to be normative. He was quite explicit about this. Taking its cue from the
above paraphrase of Kant’s dictum, Lakatos’s (1971) paper on the history of science
intended to explain:
how the historiography of science should learn from the philosophy of science
and vice versa. It will be argued that (a) philosophy of science provides
knowledge; (b) two competing methodologies can be evaluated with the help
24
needs to be supplemented by an empirical (socio-psychological) ‘external
As a result “each internal history has its characteristic victorious paradigms” (93).
For Weintraub this was – a few years later – the main reason no longer to tell “the
story of twentieth century economics as the rise and fall, or the progress or
262). History should be done from “a perspective based not on asking of how science
should be done, but rather how it was and is done” (267). This is the so-called
Weintraub was not the only one among historians and philosophers of economics who
and Blaug, in 1989 on the island of Capri. The conference intended to investigate
to be an appropriate framework for analysing what economics is and is not like” (de
Marchi 1991, 1). This neutral phrased question turned out to be the geyser of a heated
conference volume (de Marchi and Blaug 1991). The conference organizers and
editors of the proceedings decided not to write a joint introduction but instead de
Marchi wrote the introduction and Blaug an ‘Afterword’. Where de Marchi (1991)
observed that the “tone” of many Capri papers contrasted “sharply” with the mood of
25
an earlier Lakatos conference held in 1974: “not a few participants displayed more
No one could possibly have predicted how the mixture of people collected at
Capri would react to our instructions but I was personally taken aback by what
to give Lakatos a further run for his money and of the 17 papers delivered at
the conference not more than five were unambiguously positive about the
One of the principal consequences of this conference was an increased interest among
turn.
But, as Weintraub rightly admits: there can be “no escape from ‘frameworks.’ There
is no view from nowhere, no platforms on which I, the historian, can stand apart and
aloof from the materials on which I work” (Weintraub 2002, 269). For his history of
distinction between what he calls the “body of knowledge” and the “image of
knowledge”.
26
We may distinguish, broadly speaking, two sorts of questions concerning
every scientific discipline. The first sort are questions about the subject matter
of the discipline. The second sort are questions about the discipline qua
questions of the first sort, but usually not to answer questions of the second
The body of knowledge includes all those contents related to the subject matter of the
given discipline, these are its theories, facts, methods and open problems. The images
of knowledge include all claims about knowledge itself; they serve as guiding
principles; they pose and resolve questions that arise from the body of knowledge, but
are not part of and cannot be settled within the body of knowledge itself. These
second-order questions, for example, are: Which of the open problems of the
This division between the body and image of knowledge is not sharp and is
Moreover, changes in the body of knowledge may alter these answers. But these
answers are not exclusively determined by the body of knowledge; they may be
27
influenced by other, external factors as well. In turn, the image of knowledge plays a
decisive role in directing research and further determining the development of the
Corry’s motivation for this distinction is that the study of the interaction between
the realm of pure ideas, while avoiding dubious “strong” explanations that
mathematics is different from the other exact sciences: “mathematics is the only exact
science in which statements about the discipline may still be inside the discipline”
thinking about mathematics that is carried out strictly inside mathematics” (414), e.g.
proof theory. Images of knowledge are “all claims about mathematics that at a given
historical point are not an integral part of the mathematical body of knowledge” (414),
Hilbert’s list of problems of 1900” (414), it also includes the philosophy and history
of mathematics.
28
Using Corry’s categories to characterize the role of history in econometrics, it seems
contrast to mathematics, its is thinking about econometrics that is not an integral part
of the econometric body of knowledge but takes place where the body of knowledge
and the images of knowledge interact dynamically. Corry states that second-order
ancillary disciplines” (411), except mathematics due to its reflexive character, but
what we saw is that econometricians also address these questions, and that it has been
econometric evidence” (Hendry 1986, xi) in the 1980s, econometricians like Hendry
and Spanos felt the need to bridge the gap between the textbook econometric theory
techniques “in all their formal glory” and the ad hoc procedures empirical researchers
had to resort to: “Econometrics textbooks encouraged the ‘myth’ that the main
theoretical model and a menu of estimators (OLS, GLS, 2SLS, LIML, IV, 3SLS,
To set up a new methodology, the first section of the first chapter of Spanos’s (1986)
Hendry), starts with a “brief historical overview” to delineate its intended scope. Its
29
starting point is a “working definition” of econometrics: “Econometrics is concerned
with the systematic study of economic phenomena using observed data” (Spanos 1986,
3).
of the list of forerunners. According to Spanos’s history they are: Thomas Bayes,
Abraham De Moivre, Edgeworth, Ronald Aylmer Fisher, Francis Galton, Johann Carl
Friedrich Gauss, John Graunt, William Sealey Gosset, Edmond Halley, Reginald
Mitchell, Moore, Karl Pearson, Petty, Adolphe Quetelet, Schultz, Slutsky, Alfred
Russel Wallace, Herman O.A. Wold, Elmer J. Working, Philip G. Wright, George
Udny Yule. Only four persons survived the earlier Econometrica lists: Edgeworth,
Moore, Petty and Slutsky. Looking at this list, one can only but conclude that
Statistics because the data found in economics had unusual properties” (Granger 2006,
xi).
Spanos used for this brief history, beside the earlier works by historians of statistics
and probability theories: Cramer (1972), Maistrov (1974), Seal (1967), Stigler (1954),
and Stigler (1962), and by the philosopher of science Hacking (1975), also the then
30
more recent histories of econometrics: Hendry and Morgan (1995)18, Morgan (1982),
While Spanos and Tintner still rooted econometrics partly in Political Arithmetik of
Petty, Hendry and Morgan (1995, 4) cut that root of: “Econometrics emerged, not
from the long-lost seventeenth-century tradition of Political Arithmetik, but from the
the biometrics tradition which flowered at the end of that century”. The readings they
provided included only articles of six persons appearing on the Econometrica lists: I.
Twenty years after the publication of his textbook, Spanos (2006) choose Moore as
newly developed statistical tools of Galton, Karl Pearson and Yule could be
approach can be traced back to Moore (1911, 1914). (Spanos 2006, 16)
While Moore put econometrics on the wrong track, it was R.A. Fisher was who
contributed the most important ideas to the development of econometrics. Note that
R.A. Fisher did not appear on all former lists, except in Spanos’ own 1986 history.
18
This “Readings in Econometric Thought”, as it was then titled, was expected to be published in 1986.
31
Conclusions
Corry’s distinction between the body and image of a science can so provide an
understanding of the history of econometrics and its own continuing struggle with its
that is, inclusive their perception of the views of the philosophers of science at a
relevant period, can help to clarify the development of econometrics. In other words,
understanding of the development of the image of science, which includes the history
be philosophical informed, which mean more precisely here that they need to be
Corry’s distinction between the body and image of knowledge does not only provide a
written in each period reflect the image of their discipline in that period. We saw that
forerunners. Cournot, Pareto and Walras do not appear in any current history of
econometrics. Each period has its own list of forerunners and founding fathers.
32
In the post-war period till the 1980s, history of econometrics was the history of
Cowles Commission econometrics. This only changed when in the 1970s the limits of
the Cowles program became visible and “young turks” like Hendry, Leamer and Sims
areas “before” and “beside” the Cowles program. Econometrics today is much more
attention for histories of statistics in relation to the history of econometrics and with a
more prominent role of R.A. Fisher. We leave it to future historians to delineate the
kind of econometrics that is reflected by this volume, we are simply too close to it to
see it.
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank the participants of the HOPE conference for their
contributions and comments, see footnote 8 for their names. We also would like to
thank Duo Qin for her many valuable comments and Marcel would like to thank Mary
Morgan in particular for the numerous amounts of conversations. We also would like
to thank Alain Pirotte and the external referees Spencer Banzhaf, Steven Durlauf,
References
917.
33
Bjerkholt, O. and D. Qin. 2011a. Teaching Economics as a Science: The Yale
, eds. 2011b. A Dynamic Approach to Economic Theory. London and New York:
Routledge.
Chalmers, A.F. 1976. What is this Thing Called Science? Queensland: University of
Queensland Press.
Econometrica 51.1:3-6.
Coats, A.W. 1987. Review Essay: History of Political Economy. The AEA and the
Cournot, A. [1897] 1927. Researches into the Mathematical Principles of the Theory
34
Cramer, H. 1972. On the History of Certain Expansions Used in Mathematical
de Marchi, N. and M. Blaug, eds. 1991. Appraising Economic Theories: Studies in the
21.1:1-30.
Theory 20.4:743-804.
2006).
12.2:119-138.
Skrifter 1.16:1-40.
35
. 1933. Editorial. Econometrica 1.1:1-4.
Gilbert, C.L. and D. Qin. 2006. The First Fifty Years of Modern Econometrics. In
Press.
Hands, D.W. 1988. Ad Hocness in Economics and the Popperian Tradition. In (de
Marchi 1988).
Hendry, D.F., E.E. Leamer, and D.J. Poirier. 1990. The ET Dialogue: A Conversation
Hendry, D.F., and M.S. Morgan, eds. 1995. The Foundations of Econometric Analysis.
Verlag.
36
Hoover, K.D. 2006. The Methodology of Econometrics. In (Mills and Patterson 2006).
42.1:19-20.
. [1879] 1957. The Theory of Political Economy, 5th edition, (1879 2nd edition, 1888
Keynes, J.M. 1939. Professor Tinbergen’s Method. The Economic Journal 49:558-
568.
Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8, edited by R.C. Buck and R.S. Cohen.
Dordrecht: Reidel.
Leamer, E.E. 1983. Let’s Take the Con out of Econometrics. American Economic
Review 79:31-43.
Lundberg, E. 1992. The Prize for Economic Science in Memory of Albert Nobel. In
37
McAleer, M., A.R. Pagan, and P.A. Volker. 1985. What Will Take the Con out of
Mills, T.C. and K. Patterson, eds. 2006. Palgrave Handbook of Econometrics, Volume
University Press.
Seal, H.L. 1967. The Historical Development of the Gauss Linear Model. Biometrica
54:1-24.
38
Spanos, A. 1986. Statistical Foundations of Econometric Modelling. Cambridge:
Century Medicine, vol. 1, edited by E.M. Tansey, P.P. Catterall, D.A. Christie,
S.V. Willhoft, and L.A. Reynolds. London: The Wellcome Trust. Also online
publication http://www.ucl.ac.uk/histmed/publications/wellcome_witnesses.
December:470-477.
39