Russi Social Contract
Russi Social Contract
Russi Social Contract
CHRISTOPHER D. WRAIGHT
Continuum International Publishing Group
The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane
11 York Road Suite 704
London SE1 7NX New York NY 10038
JC179.R88W73 2008
320.1’1–dc22
2008014322
Preface vii
1. Context 1
2. Overview of Themes 9
3. Reading the Text 19
Book I 19
Book II 52
Books III and IV 89
4. Reception and Influence 120
Notes 129
Further Reading 132
Index 135
This page intentionally left blank
PREFACE
vii
PREFACE
viii
CHAPTER 1
CONTEXT
1
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
2
CONTEXT
3
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
he travelled widely during his eventful life, driven from place to place
by a passionate, inquiring mind (or, at times, the displeasure of those
whom he had offended). His intense, sometimes baffling preoccupa-
tions and opinions caught the imagination of many of his contem-
poraries, while being equally capable of rousing violent opposition.
Rousseau was a profoundly divisive figure, both for the revolutionary
ideas expressed in his various writings, and for the erratic conduct of
his personal affairs and relations. Indeed, the relationship between
his constantly evolving thought and his turbulent private life is always
close, making it more than usually useful to have at least a cursory
understanding of the latter before attempting to engage with the
former.
The richest source of information on Rousseau’s life is his remark-
ably frank autobiography, The Confessions, a huge and at times
thoroughly entertaining account of his personal and intellectual
development. There are also a number of works written at the end of
his life, some shrill and self-justificatory, others reflective and insight-
ful. Together, they reveal a man endlessly preoccupied with the
thorniest questions of human relations: What is the fundamental
nature of people? How best may their social affairs be organized?
What prevents them from fulfilling their proper potential? While his
autobiographical writings are often harsh on the failings of others to
conform to his exacting answers to those questions, he is no less
judgemental about his own shortcomings. At his worst, Rousseau
can come across as paranoid and self-obsessed; at his best, he is capa-
ble of commenting with a rare clarity and perceptiveness on human
frailty and its capacity for improvement. These are the themes which
animate his most important books, not least The Social Contract,
written fairly late in his life in 1762, and which is principally respon-
sible for his reputation as a political philosopher.
An interest in political questions seems to have been with him from
a very early age. Rousseau was born in Geneva in 1712, then an
independent city state run along republican lines originally set down
by the Protestant theologian John Calvin. In contrast to the heredi-
tary monarchies which then ruled over most of Europe, Geneva was
governed by a group of legislative councils drawn from the citizens
of the city. Although the system was less genuinely representative
than perhaps originally intended (eligible ‘citizens’ actually made up
a relatively small proportion of the population), many Genevois were
both acutely conscious and proud of their republic’s distinctive
4
CONTEXT
5
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
6
CONTEXT
7
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
8
CHAPTER 2
OVERVIEW OF THEMES
9
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
10
OVERVIEW OF THEMES
HUMAN NATURE
It is common in political philosophy, when attempting to start from
first principles, to appeal to the set of conditions obtaining in a
so-called ‘state of nature’. Rousseau’s predecessors, Thomas Hobbes
and John Locke, had made much of this device. As Locke puts it,
The idea behind this is to try and get at the way things were, or may
have been, prior to the rise of an ‘unnatural’ civilization. For some
philosophers, the state of nature may be treated as a matter of his-
torical fact – a real phase of historical social development which can
be theorized about; for others, it may merely be a useful device to
introduce some ideas about the relationship between people as they
are and people as they might be. In both cases, one intention behind
introducing the idea of a state of nature is to try and construct a pic-
ture of what people are like in themselves; that is, before the
meddlesome effects of formal education, law and convention have
altered things irretrievably.
Rousseau is no exception to this. Indeed, he felt that others who
had made recourse to such a device had not gone far enough: in imag-
ining a state of nature, they had merely come up with a more basic
version of the society they already inhabited.4 His ambitions were
more radical: he thought it was possible to have a clear sense of what
people were like ‘in themselves’, and to trace how modern forms of
civilization had distorted this original character. These days, even
with much greater knowledge of the far past than Rousseau pos-
sessed, we might be quite cautious about speculating on the moral
character and intentions of those living in pre-civilized times. It is
very difficult to imagine what the inner lives of such people could have
been like, especially given the paucity of written evidence. Rousseau,
11
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
12
OVERVIEW OF THEMES
13
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
14
OVERVIEW OF THEMES
15
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
16
OVERVIEW OF THEMES
17
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
18
CHAPTER 3
BOOK I
The ideas Rousseau expounds in The Social Contract were originally
envisaged as part of a planned larger work to be called ‘Political
Institutions’. However, Rousseau abandoned his intentions for this
more ambitious scheme, and The Social Contract remains his most
complete work on politics and political philosophy. It is also his most
famous and widely read book, the one on which his reputation as a
thinker and writer is chiefly based. Despite this, it is relatively short
and compact, and much of the important content is compressed into
the first two books of the four-book whole. On the surface it is decep-
tively easy to read, and major ideas are expressed in a concise manner
which is refreshingly different from some other more ponderous
works of political philosophy. However, this very concision can hide
real difficulties in interpretation. As we shall see, it can occasionally
be difficult to see what Rousseau means by some of the core terms he
advances, even when he himself seems to think their significance must
be readily apparent. As a result, there is by no means complete agree-
ment among Rousseau scholars on the best interpretation of such
sometimes elliptical ideas. Nonetheless, within the comparatively
brief text, there is a wealth of original and provocative thought, much
of which continues to exercise political theorists in our own time.
In what follows, the intention is to give a comprehensive overview
of the important themes and ideas of The Social Contract, as well as
an introduction to some of the controversies and difficulties they
throw up. As we have seen from a consideration of Rousseau’s life
and early political writings, the subject of a just and equitable society
was never far from his thoughts. His frequent dismay at the problems
19
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
20
READING THE TEXT
21
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
22
READING THE TEXT
This is Rousseau in full, polemic flow, and illustrates the extent of the
‘chains’ which he thinks bind members of unjust societies. Having
sketched such a grim scenario, however, he then confidently claims
that he has the solution: a means of turning oppressive political insti-
tutions into genuinely legitimate instruments of a benign society.
Before moving on to this, though, he spends a few chapters consider-
ing the nature of some of the social orders he thought exhibited such
destructive features clearly. By exposing their weaknesses, he hopes
to bolster the case for his own, reformed political system, the outline
of which has yet to be revealed.
23
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
24
READING THE TEXT
25
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
relatively little recourse should they dislike the way things are going.3
In a similar vein, Aristotle argued in his political philosophy that
certain classes in society are inherently more suited to rule than
others. Some are born for slavery, others to be masters. In a manner
reminiscent of the familial analogy, Aristotle argues that some
elements of society are simply incapable of making sensible use of
complete freedom, and must therefore be guided by those more fitted
to the task.4
Rousseau rejects the idea that there are inherently two classes of
people: those fit to rule and those destined to be ruled. To character-
ize things in such a way is, for him, similar to describing the ruled as
cattle and the rulers as shepherds. It is true that, as a result of custom
and tradition, it may seem as if some social groups are destined for
one fate or another. However, this is to get things the wrong way
round. If slaves are held in slavery for long enough, then even they
will come to see that as their natural state. Indeed, some may end up
thinking it justified, and perhaps take some degree of satisfaction
from their lowly station. But that is not because they were fitted to
that role prior to society’s influence; instead, it is society that has
moulded them into the state which only subsequently seems natural
for them. We might think of the ‘Stockholm Syndrome’ phenomenon
for an extreme example of this: the tendency some people have to
identify with their oppressors even in very stressful and abusive
situations.
Rousseau’s argument against a natural hierarchy of groups within
society is very brief. It may seem as if he has given hardly any atten-
tion to it. However, it is worth bearing in mind here our earlier
discussion of human nature and psychology. In Rousseau’s reading
of them, Aristotle and his ilk assume that people have a certain set of
capacities before entering the social order, and the state should orga-
nize itself around those differing capacities. However, for Rousseau,
society itself is responsible for altering people’s basic psychology and
motivations. The point of making his suppositions about the state of
nature is partly to make this notion clear. And if that account is at all
persuasive, then it is consistent of him to reject the notion that
certain groups within society ought, from the very beginning, to be
accorded more rights than others. For him, the apparent suitability
of some for slavery and others for finery is a symptom of an unjust
society, not a reason for its establishment. The idea that there is
an inherent hierarchy among people, the rulers and the ruled, is
26
READING THE TEXT
27
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
28
READING THE TEXT
Slavery (4)
Having dismissed the ideas of natural authority and the rule of the
strongest, Rousseau concludes that the only basis for a just society is
one founded on a covenant: an agreement between all members of
the society to live under rules they all agree on.
In what comes later, he will outline the exact form of covenant
which he feels generates the optimal political order. Before that, how-
ever, he feels compelled to dismiss an alternative version. The
inspiration for the discussion comes, once again, from Grotius, who
claims that ‘a people may give itself to a king’. In other words, the
covenant may take the form of a populace deciding to give up their
freedom to an individual who will then rule over them. Rousseau
considers perhaps the most extreme example of this, which is slavery.
He begins the chapter by considering whether a covenant of this sort
provides a more satisfactory basis for society than those already
discussed. He also discusses a slightly different case: whether enslav-
ing a population as a result of a war between rival states can ever
be justified. Unsurprisingly, both questions are answered in the
negative. Some of the reasons he gives, however, develop a little
further the psychological background we have already covered.
Rousseau begins by asking whether it makes any sense for a person
to sell his or her freedom to another in exchange for other benefits
29
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
30
READING THE TEXT
31
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
32
READING THE TEXT
was greatly influenced by the example of the English Civil War, where
it seemed to him that having a very powerful monarchy was preferable
to the alternative of chaos and warfare. Even if such a view is authori-
tarian, it is certainly not obviously or inevitably a recipe for slavery.
So, in considering alternatives to his own, yet to be announced
theory, is Rousseau guilty of the ‘straw man’ fallacy: setting up
implausible rival theories and ignoring better versions in order
that his own account may appear superior? To some extent, yes.
If Rousseau’s purpose in listing the weaknesses of alternative politi-
cal models was to eliminate all other possibilities but his own, then he
has left potential gaps. However, it would be very difficult to reject
every possible variation of an authoritarian or non-covenantal polit-
ical theory, and, in a relatively brief work such as The Social Contract,
probably counter-productive. After all, there is a limit to how persua-
sive it is to list the defects of political models in the hope of settling
on something else by default.
So, being a little charitable, we might view Rousseau’s strategy in
the following light: in the opening chapters, he has considered and
rejected some influential theories of social organization (at least in
his own time), and in such a way as to limit the remaining possibili-
ties. He has not dismissed every permutation of these theories by any
means, but he has used his rejection of them to enhance the accept-
ability of two core notions: that a legitimate society is based on some
form of covenant, and that the quality of freedom is essential if the
participants in the covenant are to count as genuine partners. In the
following three chapters, these notions are given some concrete shape.
As we shall see then, a Hobbesian-type society such as the one we
have sketched here would be incompatible with Rousseau’s account,
since it turns out that any diminution of an individual’s freedom in
favour of another is rejected. To see how this radical idea will be
developed, we will have to turn now from Rousseau’s negative views
on rival political philosophies to the positive exposition of his own.
33
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
34
READING THE TEXT
35
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
36
READING THE TEXT
37
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
We’ll see, as we progress, that there are a number of points where the
satisfaction of both criteria is questionable. But for now we should
allow Rousseau a little more space to flesh out the bones of his pro-
posal, before returning to assess how plausible it is.
38
READING THE TEXT
39
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
40
READING THE TEXT
certainly hard to see how this squares with his original objective: to
come up with a form of political association which provides security
while still preserving as much freedom as an individual has in the
state of nature. From the discussion so far, it may well seem that
nothing of the sort has been achieved, and Rousseau has done no
more than create a whole community of slaves, all of whom have
derogated their rights to a vague and nebulous ‘general will’, the basis
of which is still very unclear. Indeed, this might seem even worse
than a society based on natural authority or force of the strongest,
since at least in those scenarios some people retained their freedom to
act in their own best interests. If Rousseau’s account is to strike us as
all coherent and credible, then we should want to know a lot more
about the workings of the general will. Likewise, if he is to convince
us that his system meets the goal of guaranteeing freedom and human
flourishing, then we should want to hear more about how being
‘forced’ to act in accordance with the will of the sovereign could con-
tribute to that objective.
Thankfully for us, Rousseau does say more about each issue. The
first chapters of Book II contain more detail on the general will and
how it is discovered and acted on, but he first spends a little time dis-
cussing his particular conception of freedom, to which we now turn.
41
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
profound and lasting benefit. In doing so, their lives become more
significant, and freer, than they would have done otherwise.
Here then are some initial reasons why Rousseau’s state, by his
own account, succeeds in guaranteeing human freedoms despite the
apparently draconian powers of the sovereign. Once again, in order
to make this plausible, we must bear in mind the psychological under-
pinnings to his social theory. To recall, Rousseau believes that the
quality of compassion plays a privileged role in human dealings.
A psychologically healthy individual will be motivated by a benign
self-interest modified by a natural desire to help others when they are
suffering. Only when such instincts are perverted by poorly con-
structed societies does this urge become subsumed by the strident
demands of malign amour-propre, and beneficent self-interest turns
into malignant self-love. When the possibility of providing mutual
assistance to our fellow citizen is dimmed by the pressures of ubiqui-
tous selfishness and patronage, our moral imagination becomes
limited, and we are increasingly subject to an inward-looking desire
to please ourselves. Though our actions may be unconstrained by
any external force, a more satisfying and significant mode of living
has been denied us. As a result, we are less free, and the opportunity
to fulfil our true human potential has been taken away.
Though we are as yet still waiting for a more precise account of
how Rousseau’s ideal community wards against these dangers, it
should be at least reasonably evident in which direction his thought
is headed. Since in his civil society every decision is made by all mem-
bers, and is also binding on all members, there is a clear reason for
each individual to think about how their actions bear on the entire
community. As there will never be a case where a citizen can pass
laws which only affect other people, each will be more inclined to
consider the broader implications of any proposal. By doing so, they
will bind themselves more closely with the interests of the entire
group, rather than sticking slavishly to their own. Presumably, the
beneficial effects of thinking in such a way will become increasingly
apparent as time goes on and the community flourishes. It is there-
fore perfectly proper that dissenters from the general decisions of the
group should be bound to accept the sovereign’s will, since they are
but part of a project which holds the promise of ennobling and
uplifting all of its members. In time, even they might come to recog-
nize the enormous benefits of being part of such an association, even
if in the short term their individual will has been frustrated.
42
READING THE TEXT
43
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
they are able to carry out what they wish to do at any given time.
If they are prevented from doing so, for any reason, then their liberty
has been taken away. Now, there may still be many instances when
it is right for a political power to restrict such negative freedom.
If someone wanted to murder people indiscriminately, then there
would be plenty of justification for curtailing their freedom to act.
However, in such a case, there would be no claim that the act of
curtailing the murderer enhances their freedom; instead, it is accepted
that in some cases an individual’s freedom should be limited. In the
absence of extenuating circumstances, negative freedom is a some-
thing to be protected and encouraged, but there may be limits to this
if the benefits of freedom impede other social goods, such as per-
sonal security. A classically liberal position, using the notion of
negative freedom, might be constructed along the lines that an indi-
vidual should be free to do what they wish, so long as their actions do
not lead to others being directly harmed.
It is clear that, at least in the rough form articulated here,
Rousseau’s political system does not guarantee negative freedom
thus construed. The Social Contract dictates that each member gives
up their individual right to act as they choose in favour of the general
will of the community. The sovereign may choose to coerce any one
of its members just if the member has a divergent view from the
general will. In addition, Rousseau argues that such a state of affairs
is consistent with the freedom of every individual in the community
being enhanced, rather than diminished. His position is much closer
therefore to Berlin’s idea of ‘positive’ freedom. Here, the central idea
is that an individual is more (positively) free the more opportunities
they have to enhance their life and pursue objectives which lead to
beneficial outcomes. A good society should act to ensure that its
citizens have as wide and as healthy a range of choices as it can.
According to the proponent of positive freedom, it is insufficient
simply to remove unnecessary constraints from an individual; instead,
they should be helped to take advantage of potentially beneficial
situations they might otherwise have no access to. A commonplace
example is that of forcing children to go to school. Much of the time,
children would prefer not to be in the classroom, and if unconstrained
by rules and the threat of punishment would probably opt to go else-
where. But if they were allowed to do this whenever they chose, their
opportunities in later life would be severely curtailed: they might lose
the freedom to pursue a good career due to a lack of skills, and be
44
READING THE TEXT
45
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
Property (9)
Before moving on to his more detailed discussion of the powers of
the sovereign and the nature of the general will, Rousseau spends a
little time to outline how the notion of property functions in his ideal
community. That he does so just after his account of civil freedom is
no accident: for many theorists both before and after Rousseau, the
concepts of liberty and property go very closely together. The right
to own property is seen by some as a fundamental pillar of freedom,
and by others as a tool for oppression and inequality. In Rousseau’s
argument, the nature of property is somewhat parallel to the nature
of freedom. In the same way that an individual moves from an unsatis-
factory ‘natural liberty’ in the state of nature to a fulfilling ‘civil
liberty’ via The Social Contract, they move from simply having ‘pos-
sessions’ in the state of nature to obtaining a genuine form of legal
property in the civil state, backed by the underwriting power of the
sovereign. The way in which Rousseau thinks this works, given his
earlier insistence that every individual gives up all their rights to
everyone else in The Social Contract, is somewhat complex.
He starts by re-emphasizing that when a person enters The Social
Contract, they give up everything to the community: their person,
their rights and their goods. However, it is important to note in what
sense they give up their material possessions: interestingly, they do
46
READING THE TEXT
47
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
48
READING THE TEXT
49
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
So the state itself, from its perspective, has no more title to the goods
of all than does an individual over their possessions in the state of
nature. By contrast, the individual citizen within Rousseau’s state has
a greater purchase on the possessions within their trusteeship, since,
as he has argued, this is underwritten by the whole community acting
in concert.
This is an odd point to make. Presumably, Rousseau is aiming to
quell worries over the potential abuse of individual rights by the state –
after all, in his account the right of occupancy is a weaker right than
that established by The Social Contract, with important limitations
placed on it. But despite this qualification, it is still clear that, in
every important sense, the state genuinely owns the property held in
trust by every member of the community. There is still no obvious
reason why the sovereign power could not simply decide, in accord-
ance with the general will, to disinherit its members, or simply take
things from them whenever it wished.
This is an analogous objection to the one we raised earlier with
respect to freedom. Rousseau has outlined a system which he claims
brings great benefits, but which also places (apparently) enormous
power in the hands of the sovereign, and seems to generate no safe-
guards against abuse of that power. If the individual lacks tools with
which to ward off capricious or unjust behaviour, then there must be
some other reason why the sovereign cannot simply ride roughshod
over the interests of any one of its members. And, as intimated
earlier, Rousseau feels he does have such reasons. These pertain to
the unique nature of the general will: he will aim to demonstrate how
this concept, properly understood, constrains the sovereign from
acting partially or unjustly and ensures that each individual within
the state will be free in the best possible sense. In order to see how this
mechanism will work, we must now turn, at last, to his exposition of
the workings of the sovereign in Book II.
SUMMARY
It may be helpful at this stage to have a brief recapitulation of the
main themes we have covered.
Rousseau’s aim is to devise a political system which preserves
the freedom found in the state of nature while avoiding the material
dangers of such a state. He considers a number of current political
theories, each dependent on the idea of a certain group (or an
50
READING THE TEXT
STUDY QUESTIONS
1. What are the chief strengths and weaknesses of the three politi-
cal systems Rousseau rejects, in his own account? Are his reasons
for dismissing them valid ones?
2. How does humanity progress from the state of nature into the
state of society, according to Rousseau? Is his description of the
changes a compelling one?
3. What are the essential features of Rousseau’s social model, as
outlined in Book I? What are the potential benefits and pitfalls
of such a system?
4. What are the principal differences between ‘natural liberty’ and
‘civil liberty’, as outlined by Rousseau? What are the advantages
and disadvantages of each conception?
51
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
BOOK II
In Book II, Rousseau concentrates on making the nature of the
sovereign clearer, and also expanding on the currently nebulous idea
of the general will. By doing so, he hopes to show that the worries we
have about the apparently unfettered powers of the sovereign can be
met. He also has points to make about the practicalities of govern-
ment, some of which will be discussed in more detail in Book III, and
much to say about the law and its proper application. In doing so, he
introduces the character of the lawgiver, a figure which has seemed to
many commentators the most confusing aspect of his entire system.
By the end of the book, however, he has advanced the bulk of the
legislative basis of his political system, and we will be in a much
better position to judge the success of it.
52
READING THE TEXT
would break the essential feature of Rousseau’s social order: that all
members of the community participate to an equal level in the delib-
erations of the sovereign, and all are bound to an equal level by its
decisions. If a group of members of the state decided that they were
somehow more fitted to govern the community than others, and
seized the role of determining the general will and acting on it
(whether by force or the agreement of all others), then the social
order would degenerate into the kind of stratified society which
Rousseau is trying to avoid. In such a scenario, all the individual
members of the state would have given up their freedoms, but only a
subset of them would have retained the power to shape the direction
of the community. And this, of course, is just another version of
Grotius’s scenario of a people choosing to give up their freedom to a
monarch (or oligarchy), which Rousseau has already rejected.
It is important to note here that Rousseau is not claiming that no
powers at all can be delegated from the sovereign downwards. On a
practical level, it would be very difficult to run a society if everything
had to be decided by an assembly of all its members. As we shall see,
many of the practical decisions affecting the community are in fact
taken by the government, which is a subordinate level of administra-
tion. The sole task of the sovereign is to determine the general will,
and to act according to its dictates. However, once this claim has been
made we are likely to want to know more from Rousseau about how
such labour is divided up. What makes one issue a matter for the sov-
ereign, and another a matter for government? In other words, which
kinds of issues require attention to be paid to the general will, which
ones can be left for subordinate administrative bodies to sort out?
Rousseau’s answers to this give us more clues to the nature of the
general will and how it must operate. He begins by claiming that the
sovereign, as well as being inalienable, is also indivisible. This is a very
similar idea to the one just considered, but this time refers directly to
the issue of separation of powers, a discussion which Rousseau would
have been familiar with from the writings of Locke.8 In many politi-
cal systems in both our own time and Rousseau’s own, the sovereign
power of a nation is divided into several elements. Most commonly,
these are the executive (the body charged with implementing laws
and policies), the legislature (which formulates the laws themselves)
and the judiciary (which adjudicates on the correct application or
transgression of such laws). In Rousseau’s account, there is no such
division of the sovereign power. The sovereign only has one job: to
53
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
determine what the general will is, and pass regulations in accordance
with its dictates. When this process is followed correctly, the regula-
tions which emerge may properly be called ‘laws’. If any subdivision
of the state (i.e. the government, or an individual) passes its own
regulations, then even though they may be in some sense binding,
they are merely ‘decrees’.
This conception of the role of the sovereign cuts across many more
familiar schemes of national administration. For example, as Rousseau
points out, the act of declaring war is commonly held to be a funda-
mental prerogative of the sovereign body of a nation. However, in his
own political system, all the sovereign does is pass laws in accordance
with demands of the general will. According to Rousseau, the deci-
sion to go to war is properly understood as the implementation of a
law. So waging war is not a genuine function of the sovereign: if
Rousseau’s ideal community were to decide to do such a thing, then
the decision would rest with some other administrative element of it.
Of course, it is likely that the sovereign would have the job of passing
laws to determine under what circumstances wars may be declared, or
when they are forbidden, etc. The point is that the sovereign body has
no role in acting upon those laws: that is a task which must be carried
out by a different element of the society.
So we are beginning to get a clearer picture of the role and limits
of sovereign power in Rousseau’s scheme. First, it is necessary that
every action of the sovereign is performed when it is functioning as a
whole: there can be no delegation of this role to groups composed of
less than all members of the community. Second, the sovereign is
limited to passing laws, not enacting them. If either of these condi-
tions is broken, then the actions of the sovereign (or elements therein)
may no longer be considered legitimate. This is because, as we already
know, the legitimacy of the sovereign body comes from the fact that
it is fully representative, and also that its dictates apply to all mem-
bers of the community. In due course, Rousseau has quite a lot to say
about what happens when nations succumb to corruption of the
proper function of sovereignty, but for now he is concerned to delin-
eate the sovereign’s function and its associated powers. And it should
be clear that such moves are partly designed to address some of the
worries about the apparently unfettered powers of the sovereign we
raised earlier. As the sovereign power is in the business of simply
making laws, not acting upon them, it is not within its remit to
perform some kinds of malfeasance directly, such as arbitrarily
54
READING THE TEXT
55
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
acted upon, it holds the promise of charting a path for the state which
protects both freedom and security. Any decision made by the sover-
eign which has as its object a part of the community, rather than the
whole of it, cannot have emerged from a proper application of the
general will. And here the notion of the general will seems to be
referred to by Rousseau in a slightly different way. Rather than being
the term for a motivation we all have individually, it seems to be the
standard or guide against which the sovereign assesses its options.
When conceived thus, Rousseau seems to regard the general will as
something uniquely possessed by the people acting together, a con-
cept which is only actualized through the activities of the sovereign
itself. As he puts it,
56
READING THE TEXT
57
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
the sovereign to impotence. For these reasons, he rejects the idea that
the general will is best understood as a unanimous vote by the sover-
eign body. Indeed, he explicitly contrasts the ‘will of all’ with the
general will, claiming that although the entire populace can never be
corrupted, they can be misled or work from faulty information.
If a unanimous verdict is too ambitious a standard for the sover-
eign to work to in every case, then perhaps a simple majority of
the voting members is enough. In a footnote at the beginning of
Chapter 2, Rousseau seems to indicate that this is an acceptable basis
for determining the general will, and explains that unanimity is not
required for a decision to reflect the general will as long as all votes
are counted and no-one is excluded from contributing to the process
(SC, II, 2n). But we must be careful here. Rousseau still wants to
claim that the general will is in some way a reflection of the will of
the community as a whole. As we shall see shortly, the kind of major-
ity voting system based on competing parties which we are familiar
with in our own democratic societies is not a suitable model. He is
instead keen to preserve the idea that the ‘will of all’ forms the basis
of the general will, even if the two notions are not quite the same
thing. In a rather baffling passage, he attempts to clarify the relation-
ship between the two notions thus:
There is often a great difference between the will of all [what all
individuals want] and the general will; the general will studies only
the common interest while the will of all studies private interest,
and it is indeed no more than the sum of individual desires. But if
we take away from these same wills the pluses and minuses which
cancel each other out, the balance which remains is the general
will. (SC, II, 3)
58
READING THE TEXT
59
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
60
READING THE TEXT
61
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
62
READING THE TEXT
63
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
64
READING THE TEXT
65
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
readily apparent. In the first two chapters of Book IV, he adds a series
of comments on the general will which make this optimism clear:
Why does Rousseau think that matters are so clear-cut, and the pos-
sibility of error so distant? As we will see, this comment is somewhat
at variance with claims he makes in Book II, which we will consider
below, about the need for the guiding hand of a benign lawgiver. But
in advance of that, there are some reasons for his optimism that the
properly constituted sovereign assembly will tend to find the dictates
of the general will evident and obvious.
The first is his familiar insistence on the natural goodness of people
in their unadulterated, pre-civilized state. To recall, for Rousseau, it
is primarily the actions of poorly constituted societies which alienate
people from their healthy instincts towards self-preservation and
compassion. In the absence of the distorting drives of malign amour-
propre, people will generally perceive what is good and healthy for
them, free from the distractions of the need to maintain a social
station. Under the conditions of The Social Contract, they are free to
maintain this benign and uncluttered disposition within a properly
ordered society, and so retain their clear view of the right course of
action to take in order to preserve the social good. As Rousseau is
fond of claiming, each individual in their role as a citizen member of
the sovereign has become a constituent part of a single willing entity.
Just as each individual in their role as a discrete entity has a clear
vision of what is needed for their own body, so the sovereign has a
clear vision of what is needed to sustain and guide the state. Rousseau
further claims that the simplest intellects are best at retaining this
natural instinct for the best route to successful self-preservation.
‘Upright and simple men’ are the most difficult to deceive or trick
because they have insufficient complexity in their wants and needs to
be capable of subversion. The society of The Social Contract respects
this simple, direct goodness, and through the agency of such ideal
66
READING THE TEXT
67
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
68
READING THE TEXT
69
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
and the social order will in effect cease to be that governed by The
Social Contract, and will degenerate into a version of the rule of the
strongest. There could never be a separate body charged with prevent-
ing this happening, since the sovereign is the supreme author of the
state’s laws. Moreover, there is only so much one could do to prevent
people, having been shown a better way of living, opting to reject it all
and return to a partial, grasping alternative. As long as a majority
within the sovereign has sufficient sense of community and respect
for the general will to vote down those who wish to place their indi-
vidual aims ahead of it, the society will preserve itself.
So, according to Rousseau, the sovereign is a self-regulating entity.
There is no external body overseeing its activities: either it acts prop-
erly, and the society will prosper, or it doesn’t, and the experiment of
The Social Contract has failed. As he remarks at the end of his pas-
sage on voting in Book IV:
70
READING THE TEXT
power, and making clear its role as a legislative body, Rousseau turns
his attention to the nature of law itself. Unhelpfully for the reader
seeking reassurance that the state really is a benign institution, his
first argument is for the right of the community to impose the death
penalty on those who defy its laws. In the provocatively cold terms
into which he is liable to slip from time to time, Rousseau announces
the situation thus:
If a prince says to [a citizen]: ‘It is expedient for the state that you
should die’, then he should die, because [. . .] his life is no longer
the bounty of nature but a gift he has received conditionally from
the state. (SC, II, 5)
At this point, the liberal critic may be liable to throw their hands up
and despair. Isn’t the very purpose of the state to preserve life? If the
individual surrenders their liberty to a body which can take it away
seemingly with impunity, in what sense could they be considered as
free as they were before entering into The Social Contract?
Rousseau at least seems to acknowledge that his position requires
more than the cursory justification he is sometime inclined to give his
contentious points. He starts by addressing the counter-argument
that a person cannot relinquish to the state that which they have no
right to in the first place. It was commonplace in Rousseau’s time to
hold that a person had no right to take their own life, since this was a
gift from God. So if an individual has no powers to take their own
life, how could they transfer such a power to the state to enact? This
point may have less force now than it did in the time Rousseau was
writing, since it seems less obvious to many in the modern world that
a person does not have the right to take their own life, even if such an
act is generally to be deplored and counselled against. But Rousseau
meets the objection not by imputing a natural right to suicide to the
individual (which could in theory be transferred to the state), but by
claiming that the risk of death is one which is rational for an individ-
ual to take on when passing from the state of nature into the civil
state. Suppose I wish to eliminate the possibility that my life will be
endangered by murderers (who may be roaming freely in the perilous
state of nature). On that basis, I enter civil society on the promise
that it will be free of murderers. If I were then to become one myself
I could have no complaint when my own life becomes forfeit as a
result. When becoming a party to The Social Contract I take on the
71
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
risk that I may become a victim of the stringent rules which attracted
me to it in the first place. But because the risk of death is much lower
in civil society than it is in nature, it is still a gamble worth taking.
Now Rousseau is surely right to say that an individual wishing to
derive the benefits of a society should abide by the rules of that soci-
ety, even if the penalties for transgression may in principle be turned
on them. But it doesn’t necessarily follow that capital punishment
is an outcome which it would be always rational to accept as a risk.
If it were the case that the only way to rid a society of murderers were
to execute all such killers when they are discovered, then Rousseau’s
argument may have some force. But if a society were capable of gen-
erally safeguarding against murder without recourse to capital
punishment, then taking on the risk of being killed by the state is
unreasonable. Since I have not transferred the right to take my own
life explicitly to the state in the terms of The Social Contract (accord-
ing to Rousseau), the rightness of capital punishment becomes a
pragmatic question: if it is necessary for the maintenance of the
state’s beneficial protective powers that it has the right to kill its
citizens, then it is a rational choice for the citizen to accept the risk of
state-sanctioned execution in exchange for such protection. But this
is assumed, rather than argued-for, in the text. We might be very
sceptical that the state needs the power to execute its citizens in order
to maintain the security of the populace as a whole, at least without
being given more reason for this claim.
Rousseau’s second argument in favour of the death penalty is
somewhat different. If an individual violates a law which the sover-
eign has formulated then they are to be understood as breaking the
terms of The Social Contract. As such, they have placed themselves
outside the limits of the state, and should be treated by it as a foreign
entity. Depending on the severity of the crime committed, Rousseau
recommends that they either be deported or executed. Later in the
same chapter his tone seems to soften a little, and he claims that fre-
quent use of such powers by the state indicates weakness or laxity,
and that no person should be put to death if there is a less severe way
of dealing with the problem of their opposition to the sovereign’s
pronouncements. Nonetheless, he leaves the reader in no doubt that
the power of the state over an individual is complete, even to the
extent that it may legitimately take their lives.
Rousseau’s insistence on this point is rather puzzling. Up until
now, we have been considering the powers of the sovereign. As we
72
READING THE TEXT
have seen, this body is charged with passing laws of a general nature
which govern the basic direction and principles of the state. Given
that the actual enacting of the death penalty is incompatible with this
(in that it singles out a single individual or group for punishment), it
cannot fall to the sovereign to carry out this burden. Indeed, Rousseau
claims that the sovereign body cannot itself execute an instance of
capital punishment: instead, that function must fall to a subordinate
level of government. As yet, we know very little of the other organs
of power aside from the sovereign, and so the reason for his insertion
of this issue here is a little unclear. Moreover, the question of capital
punishment seems somewhat redundant in the wider explanatory
scheme. On the face of it, everything Rousseau has said thus far
would be just as compatible with a society which abjured state-
sanctioned killing. As such, we may feel that Rousseau’s arguments
here are ill-founded, and do nothing to advance the acceptability of
his general scheme. If anything, they are likely to undermine the
plausibility of his overall project for little reward, and so we should
not regard them as being in any way essential to the wider scheme.
In the following chapter, thankfully, Rousseau moves on to more
familiar ground. Having once again explained the social pact and the
social order it gives rise to, he proposes to say a little more about the
kinds of laws it must pass in order to preserve itself. He starts by con-
sidering the idea of ‘natural law’. This is the idea that there is justice
inherent in things, which by the application of reason or knowledge
of God’s will we are capable of perceiving. According to such a legal
tradition, a law may be considered more or less just depending on
how closely it conforms to the underlying natural order from which it
derives its power. Rousseau does not dispute the first part of this, and
is happy to accept that a divine creator is the source of all natural law,
and that the activities of reason are in principle capable of enabling
people to act in accordance with it. Nonetheless, true to form, he does
not believe that the great mass of people will follow such dictates with
any regularity. If they did, then the state of nature would no doubt
remain a benign place and the necessity for civil society would be
obviated. There would be in fact no advantage to an individual in fol-
lowing a lawful path within the state of nature, since those around
them who do not will gain considerable power at their expense.
The great advantage civil society brings to this situation is that all
the people who are subject to the laws are themselves the authors of
them. By participating in the process of sovereignty, each member of
73
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
74
READING THE TEXT
But even he seems to think, from time to time at least, that this
analogy does not quite guarantee things will reliably work out for the
best. In a remarkable passage, Rousseau voices some of the very
objections we have raised earlier in our discussion on the discernment
of the general will, and seems to concede that they are entirely valid:
How can a blind multitude, which often does not know what it
wants, because it seldom knows what is good for it, undertake by
itself an enterprise as vast and difficult as a system of legislation?
[. . .] The general will is always rightful, but the judgement which
guides it not always enlightened. [. . .] Individuals see the good and
reject it; the public desires the good and does not see it. (SC, II, 6)
75
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
76
READING THE TEXT
77
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
their lives more closely in accordance with it, but they have not explic-
itly considered the argument in its raw state, nor formally acquiesced
to its truth. Similarly, we can see the same effects at work in music,
drama and literature: Dickens does not argue that generosity and
charity are virtues to be imitated; instead, he attempts to show the
reader, through the sufferings of Scrooge, that the selfish receive their
just deserts in the end. This method of showing by analogy or exam-
ple is a very widespread technique in social education, and is obviously
instrumental in passing moral attitudes to children.11
It is this form of persuasion that the lawgiver must resort to in
order to shape the society towards the right end. But he does not do
so simply by appealing to emotions; rather, in Rousseau’s account he
is to present himself as a kind of interpreter of the divine will, such
that the people believe his wisdom is that of the gods. Not everyone
can pull such a trick off: for the unskilled practitioner, the attempt
will end in ignominy when the ruse is uncovered. A dishonest pre-
tender who attempted to pull the wool over people’s eyes for no
higher purpose may succeed in the short term, but could only ever
string together a community of the weak-minded, and the resultant
social order would not last long. The lawgiver has two important
attributes which prevent this fate happening to him. First, he has the
genuine interests of the multitude at heart: through his supernatural
forbearance, he is able to dupe the entire prospective community with
only the potential reward of seeing them elevated into a superior
state of social harmony to motivate him. Second, he has the skills of
rhetoric and persuasion needed to convince even the stoutest and
most upright of people that his recommendations are genuinely of
divine origin, and risks no uncovering of his mission or exposure of
the deception.
The object of all this chicanery is to encourage the populace, which
would otherwise be prey to the divergent ambitions of their individ-
ual wills, to consider themselves part of a shared project, one in which
they can genuinely feel themselves a part, and which they have no
reason to stymie by pursuing a partial set of interests. For Rousseau,
this is in the end the copper-bottomed guarantee that the sovereign
of his proposed state will refrain from abusing its position of abso-
lute power. Instead of external sanctions, the populace will be led by
the lawgiver to feel themselves as a single entity with a single set of
goals and objectives, and will willingly be sculpted into a united cor-
porate block, free of dissension and willing only the common good.
78
READING THE TEXT
79
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
evolution of the state clash with this objective of equality? The very
fact that he has extra information about the goals of the society
which are unknown to the majority seems to give him an edge, and
the fact that he surreptitiously pushes the entire populace in a direc-
tion of his choosing apparently undermines one of Rousseau’s core
ideas, that there are no classes of people more fitted to rule by nature
than others.
These are serious objections to the figure of the lawgiver. As pre-
sented in the text, he does seem to be an individual of almost comical
super-powers, who also stands uncomfortably apart from the general
spirit of communal equality which vitiates Rousseau’s political
scheme. Arguably, however, these apparent absurdities can be
addressed by reconstructing Rousseau’s thoughts somewhat, albeit at
the price of modifying his most colourful claims for the lawgiver’s
powers. The important feature to observe is that the lawgiver’s role is
principally to guide the populace from the state of nature into civil
society. Once this state has been achieved, it is not necessarily the
case that his role continues in the same form thereafter. When the
masses have been enlightened, there is no longer a need for an indi-
vidual lawgiver, since the society as a whole will have come to see
themselves as a single entity with shared goals and goods, and under
such conditions the sovereign will much more reliably pick out and
act upon the general will. As such, Rousseau’s objective of equality
within the state of The Social Contract is maintained: though the
populace needs to be kick-started by the god-like lawgiver, once they
have moved into the correct institutional framework, and have the
right set of motivations, the lawgiver can melt once more into the
crowd, his work done. Thereafter, we might suppose that things have
as good a chance as they ever will of proceeding smoothly, with all
constituents of the state on a genuinely equal basis and operating
from an appropriately enlightened platform.
Similarly, the somewhat outrageous claims for the abilities of the
lawgiver can perhaps be modified slightly with little loss. A more
sober vision of the situation might be this. The transition from the
state of nature to civil society is hard. Even though the long-term
benefits of such a shift are considerable, such distant rewards will be
difficult to appreciate for most, and the likelihood is that, in the
absence of an exceptional leader, the transition will never be made.
However, from time to time, such geniuses do emerge. Lycurgus
would be a key example for Rousseau, but there are plenty of other
80
READING THE TEXT
81
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
82
READING THE TEXT
83
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
84
READING THE TEXT
that means that some are stuck with the status quo, at least until such
time as their capabilities evolve.
This qualification risks ruining much of the appeal of Rousseau’s
project, at least if the criteria for transformation are too high
or demanding. In the remainder of Book II, he outlines what these
must be. An important first consideration is the size of the commu-
nity. For Rousseau, small states are better than large ones, since,
among other things, the former are much better at sustaining
the sense of community and shared purpose which the lawgiver
inculcates. Even in the modern world, where rapid and easy commu-
nication is widespread, it is easy to see why this consideration is
important for Rousseau. The sovereign body, composed of all mem-
bers of the state, needs to meet and deliberate in order for the general
will to be enacted. This would be difficult in a large and diffuse
nation, whereas in a small one such problems are less acute. Moreover,
in an environment where each citizen has a reasonable chance of
knowing most of the others, or at least being familiar with the
circumstances which affect them all, then the lawgiver’s urgings will
seem more plausible.
A second and more important consideration is the cultural homo-
geneity of the populace. For Rousseau, the only people who are
capable of being given laws (in the proper sense) are those who have
already been bound together in some form of covenant or union, but
who have not developed a legal system of the normal sort. In other
words, they must have some kind of prior means of self-identification,
but must not have advanced far enough along the road of civilization
to have allowed poorly constituted practices to crystallize. In addi-
tion to these major considerations, Rousseau also thinks that a host
of other factors conspire to frustrate the efforts of the lawgiver, such
as too many riches (or too much poverty), too much cohesion (or too
little) and bellicosity (or feebleness). At the end of the passage where
many of these criteria are laid down (SC, II, 10), he seems at his most
pessimistic about the possibility of his reforms, and implies that the
only country in Europe of his time capable of meeting his conditions
is Corsica.14
Even if we take this pessimism with a pinch of salt (elsewhere he
is much more phlegmatic), it certainly seems the case that, for
Rousseau, the lawgiver must pick his subjects carefully, and there is
no guarantee that every nation has what it takes to enter into a legiti-
mate and equal contractual social arrangement. Of all the various
85
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
things which must be in place, the most important is the prior sense
of community and shared union: it is this which the lawgiver can
work on to help the community move smoothly into Rousseau’s
institutional framework. But this insistence on an existing sense of
being bound together raises the second area of difference with what
has gone before. To recall, one of Rousseau’s objections to Grotius’s
idea that a nation could be formed when a group of individuals
decided to give themselves up to a monarch was that the individuals,
by the act of coming together and deliberating towards a common
goal, had already become a people, and the presence of a monarch
was therefore otiose. And yet, it seems that a precondition of
Rousseau’s own political system is that there is something like a
shared sense of community already in place. His earlier implication,
that the state of The Social Contract emerges from a previous
poorly formed set of institutions in which malign amour-propre has
taken its toll, now seems to have been replaced by the idea that the
lawgiver must intervene in the earlier stages of social development,
before bad practices have gone too far. Indeed, in a characteristic
sound bite, he confidently announces that ‘nations, like men, are
teachable only in their youth; with age they become incorrigible’
(SC, II, 8).
These inconsistencies are irritating, and together have the effect of
undermining confidence in the rigour of Rousseau’s vision. We are
left at the end of Book II with considerable uncertainty over the pre-
cise sequence of events required to turn a body of people into the
ideal civil society, or the exact set of circumstances under which such
a transformation can occur. However, given Rousseau’s promise to
deal with men ‘as they are’, perhaps we should not be too surprised
that his ambitious project oscillates somewhat between the harsh
practicalities of the real world and the more rarefied air of theoreti-
cal state-building. What these final chapters of Book II do give us is
a recognition by Rousseau of the practical challenges involved in
applying his scheme to the vagaries and imperfections of the real
world. In the following two Books, he does have a little more to say
about all of these issues, but the bulk of his political project at the
fundamental level – the setting out of the basic principles of his soci-
ety – has now been laid out. So we should turn to a summary of the
ideas we have covered so far, and see if a convincing political scheme
has emerged.
86
READING THE TEXT
SUMMARY
Rousseau has described a society in which every member surrenders
their individual freedom to the community as a whole. They do this
in order to gain the security of being part of a larger entity, and to
escape the dangers of the state of nature and the inequality of poorly
constituted social orders. As a citizen, they are then bound by the
laws emanating from the sovereign body, and have no reserved rights
with which to challenge or reject such laws. But they are also a mem-
ber of the sovereign, and thus have a say in how those laws are
drafted. Since all fellow citizens are also in the same situation, Rous-
seau believes that the body will respect the safety and interests of its
members in a more reliable way than an alternative system relying on
a constitutional separation between the rulers and the ruled.
The laws the sovereign passes are by their nature general: they may
not pinpoint individuals or interest groups either positively or nega-
tively. Properly formulated, these laws will also reflect the general will
of the community. This notion is derived from the collected individ-
ual wills of all the members of the sovereign body through a rational
consideration of the best outcome for the state as a whole. When the
sovereign body votes, the matter is settled. In such a situation, if
the sovereign is acting appropriately, then the resultant statement
of the general will be a reliable, impartial guide to the continued
prosperity of the society.
However, it is possible, even likely, that the sovereign may misinter-
pret the general will, or choose to ignore it. In order to prevent this
eventuality, the community must be so constituted that its members
learn to cultivate a genuine sense of a shared enterprise, and are
taught to equate their own interests with that of the state. There is no
guarantee that such vision will be possible in every nation. It may be
necessary for a person of great vision to guide the rest of the mem-
bers of the state towards that realization. In this case, the qualities
needed by such a person would be remarkable, and the populace also
of an appropriately receptive nature to benefit from their instruction.
Should all unfold thus, however, then each constituent individual will
benefit from an enjoyment of ‘civil liberty’, and be free of the chains
that formerly bound them. The deliberations of the sovereign will be
reliable, and the resultant social order will guarantee both freedom
and equality.
87
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
Such is, in very brief outline, the scheme we have been discussing.
It is by no means a complete statement of Rousseau’s political views:
we have yet to consider his conception of the subordinate level of
government at all (which is the subject of Book III, the largest
division of The Social Contract), and there are further important
ideas expressed in Book IV. Nonetheless, we are perhaps for the first
time able to return to the two questions we raised in the previous
chapter concerning the acceptability of his political vision:
With regard to the first issue, we may feel that, at least as laid down
in the text of The Social Contract, there are areas where Rousseau’s
thought is more than a little opaque. Certainly, many of his critics
have been quick to write it off as a hopeless muddle. Nonetheless, it
has seemed to other more sympathetic readers that there is a coher-
ent narrative there to be picked out, especially if one takes the time
to develop a proper appreciation of Rousseau’s psychological theory
and the motivation behind it. In this guide we have generally
followed the order of chapters as they are found in the text itself, and
it seems to me that, for all its pockets of fog, there is a vision running
through The Social Contract which remains reasonably consistent,
and which generates a political scheme which one can engage with
fruitfully. There is of course much controversy over the correct (or
perhaps most coherent) interpretation of the general will, and the
unhappy brevity of Rousseau’s descriptions of its derivation from
the will of all must be counted as a major blow to the credibility of
the project. We will return to some of these issues in the final chapter
of this book.
The second issue, concerning the practical consequences of
Rousseau’s state, is similarly vexed. It does not help that such a soci-
ety has never been realized, leaving the question open as to how a
sovereign power constituted along Rousseau’s lines might actually
function. In looking to the real world, the most similar exemplars
have yielded verdicts as diverse as the motivations of Rousseau’s
many commentators. He may be seen as an advocate of progressive
88
READING THE TEXT
STUDY QUESTIONS
1. What are the key characteristics of the sovereign body? Why
must it have these attributes?
2. Give an account of the general will, paying attention to its
derivation from the will of all.
3. What constraints are there on the activities of the sovereign
power, according to Rousseau? Are these sufficient to prevent
the abuse of individual members of the state?
4. Describe the nature and function of the lawgiver in Rousseau’s
political scheme. How successful is the introduction of this
element in solving the problems presented by his theory?
5. In Rousseau’s view, what are the prior ingredients needed for a
people to be such that they are fit to receive laws? Why does
Rousseau insist on these qualities?
89
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
90
READING THE TEXT
91
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
told that the ideal situation for Rousseau’s community is the foster-
ing of a sense of shared vision and values, such that coercion will
over time cease to be the major driver of compliance with the sover-
eign’s decisions. If it were otherwise, then the promise of freedom,
the cornerstone of Rousseau’s system, seems to have become distant
once more. Rousseau is alive to this worry, and notes that the larger
and more powerful the government becomes, the more the tempta-
tion on the part of the magistrates will grow to abuse their role. The
solution to this is to ensure that the sovereign retains equivalent pow-
ers to strip the magistrates of their position should they fail to carry
out the laws diligently and impartially. Once again he illustrates this
point with examples taken from mathematical ratios, and comes up
with the ideal recipe for success: the size of the government should
always be the square root of the size of the sovereign. If these
proportions obtain, then the respective objectives of social compli-
ance and sovereign oversight will be as guaranteed as is possible, and
the state will be a harmonious one.
It is difficult to take Rousseau’s precise prescription here entirely
seriously. In particular, there seems little reason to accept his faith
that simple mathematical ratios will yield an ideal balance between
sovereign and government sizes with any reliability. However, his
point about the relative sizes and influence of the sovereign and gov-
ernment is important. If the magistrates become the true driver of
the community’s policies then the general will can no longer be said
to be animating the community as it should. On the other hand,
practicality demands that there be an effective executive arm to
ensure that every citizen complies with the just laws of the sovereign
assembly. The problem is how to balance those two important fac-
tors in such a way that the principles of the general will as outlined in
the previous two books are not violated.
A key difficulty is, as Rousseau notes, that the government will
tend to develop a sense of its own identity over time, and will increas-
ingly see itself as a separate body to the state considered in its entirety.
Once this happens, then the community is in danger of fracturing
into factions, and the entire social project is placed in jeopardy.
Rousseau characterizes the issue thus. Each member of the govern-
ment has three ‘wills’, or motivations. The first is their individual will,
which every member of the community possesses. The second is their
will as a magistrate, what Rousseau calls their ‘corporate will’. The
third is their general will. Unfortunately, in Rousseau’s estimation the
92
READING THE TEXT
93
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
94
READING THE TEXT
95
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
96
READING THE TEXT
97
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
98
READING THE TEXT
have been elected, and such elections have taken place within the
social order put in place by the lawgiver according to the proper
functioning of the general will, there is at least the hope that the
selected individuals will rule in a wise and beneficent manner.
As presented in the text, this situation may seem, once again, to be
rather optimistic. In addition, it may appear that this structure of
government fails to reflect Rousseau’s consistent goal of equality,
since a disproportionate amount of power is being wielded by a nar-
row group of individuals. However, two things should be remembered.
First, since the task of government is to enact the will of the sover-
eign, the magistrates only have those powers which are given to them
by the community as a whole. Though they have discretion over how
to implement the laws of the state, they have no power to change
them. Should their interpretation seem to the community to have
departed from the general will in a systematic way, then the sovereign
reserves the right to dissolve the government and reconvene it in
another form. So in the sense that Rousseau thinks is important, the
magistrates have no more rights than any other member of the state
– they are still bound by the dictates of the general will and are sub-
ject to the laws agreed upon in the sovereign assembly. Second, the
fact that the magistrates are elected under a system of suffrage
devised by the sovereign gives the best possible chance, in an imper-
fect world, that they will be fitted to the job. In many respects, the
model is similar to the kind of representative democracy we touched
on above. Though the electorate in Rousseau’s state may of course
choose their magistrates badly or maliciously, the chances that they
won’t are much higher than in the case of hereditary or ‘natural’
selection. In addition, for Rousseau, the envisaged electoral activity
takes place within a community which has had a strong sense of
shared purpose and vision inculcated by the lawgiver, which gives
extra reason to suppose that the citizens would make every effort to
select the right candidates for government.15
It is evident from the text that this form of elected aristocracy is by
far Rousseau’s preferred system of government. However, for com-
pleteness’ sake, he also discusses the third option, that of monarchy.
The principal advantage of this system, according to Rousseau, is
efficiency. Since a monarchical government is identical with a single
individual, executive procedures and deliberations can take place
quickly with minimal dissension. As all other officials of the govern-
ment owe whatever powers they have to the monarch, the lines of
99
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
100
READING THE TEXT
101
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
102
READING THE TEXT
103
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
104
READING THE TEXT
105
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
citizens will return to the sorry state from which they emerged. If this
is the best that can be hoped for under Rousseau’s political system,
then we may be inclined to doubt whether it is worth supporting. As
we noted earlier, an individual in the state of nature takes a calcu-
lated risk in relinquishing their individual freedom to the community:
the least they could be expected to demand in return is a guarantee
that the resultant state will be of a permanent nature.
In response to this, it could be argued that Rousseau is merely
being realistic. If he were to argue that the institutions of his ideal
state were by their very nature immortal and incorruptible, then we
could be forgiven for finding his whole project implausible. By
acknowledging that there is always the possibility that fallible citi-
zens will reject the opportunity of enjoying a better mode of existence,
Rousseau is simply reflecting historical and political realities. More-
over, there is no implication on his part that the lifetime of properly
constituted states is necessarily particularly short. If a genuinely
egalitarian social order could be established which would last, say,
for several generations, then that would be an achievement of consid-
erable merit, and an enterprise for which individuals would be
rational to take the risk of participating in. Understood thus,
Rousseau’s vision of an improved social order is not so much pessi-
mistic as simply bounded by a pragmatic awareness of the potential
for failure as well as success.
However, if this still seems too gloomy a prognosis to be convinc-
ing, then there is a hint in the final paragraph of Chapter 11 that the
inevitable decline of societies does not in fact result in a meaningless
succession of temporary periods of freedom amidst an otherwise
unremitting stretch of despotism. In a suggestive passage, Rousseau
remarks that properly constituted societies, even if they eventually
dissolve, leave behind a legacy of laws. Where such laws have been
determined by a sovereign acting in accordance with the general will,
they have considerable legitimacy, and may even command respect
once the sovereign itself has disappeared. If, after a period of anar-
chy or tyranny, a second justly constituted society emerges from the
wreckage, it may be able to build on the legacy of its predecessor. In
this way, each properly organized society has the potential to improve
and augment the achievements of its ancestors. In support of this,
Rousseau cites the esteem in which ancient laws are held (we may
assume he is referring to the Classical world), and the modified form
in which these have been taken on by successor civilizations. Over a
106
READING THE TEXT
very long period of time, punctuated by the rise and fall of various
societies, the best legal precedents are strengthened by their repeated
adoption. Though Rousseau does not explicitly say so, a reasonable
interpretation of this passage would be that humanity is capable of
progressing in an absolute sense, even if this involves the constant
establishment and rejection of a series of just social arrangements.
Just as the individual in the state of nature is able to learn from expe-
rience and modify the natural drive of amour de soi into a more
profound inclination to seek a richer and more fulfilling life, the
indication here is that Rousseau believes civilizations too are capable
of learning from history, and may retain the capacity to emerge the
stronger for having passed through periods where the wisdom of a
true egalitarian order has been temporarily forgotten.
107
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
108
READING THE TEXT
109
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
110
READING THE TEXT
111
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
112
READING THE TEXT
used in its most common sense, is the name given to the motivation
each individual has to act in the interests of the community as a
whole. We may also use the term to describe the decision actually
made by the sovereign assembly which reflects the best average of all
these general wills across the whole community. If the sovereign body
is acting correctly and the social institutions are functioning as they
ought, then these two senses of the general will are very close together:
the latter is simply a refinement of the former. However, as we have
seen, it is possible for even the best societies to dissolve over time. If
this happens, with any luck they will leave behind them a legacy of
law which may be picked up by successor nations. Over a very long
period of time, the practices which continually survive this process,
and which are repeatedly found to be beneficial and useful, garner a
certain authority of their own. Once this body of generally accepted
laws and practices reaches a certain level of maturity, it may become
appropriate to describe its most fundamental maxims as a kind of
‘universal’ general will. In much the same way that the deliberations
of the sovereign refine the will of all into the general will of the com-
munity, the process of advancement and decay which all states are
subject to refines the various general wills of past communities into
a set of standards which all nations may aspire to.
Such an interpretation is very speculative, and has been constructed
here on scant foundations. However, it does capture something of the
flavour of the general will as a standard or benchmark against which
healthy societies must attempt to measure up. Whether or not it accu-
rately reflects Rousseau’s thought here, it seems clear that he believes
the general will has some kind of existence or significance in isola-
tion from the actual willing of members of a sovereign body, and
that even when the conditions of the social contract have irretrievably
broken down, there still remains some sense in talking about the
dormant ‘general will’ of the state.
In Chapters 4–7, Rousseau leaves his exposition of the general will
behind and spends some time explaining the virtues and vices of
ancient Rome. His purpose here seems to be to lend weight to the
arguments previously advanced on the rise and fall of civilizations.
In among a number of topics, he considers the best form of elections,
the potential rise of dictatorship, and various sorts of tribunals
established by the Romans to help arbitrate between different moral
and legal visions of society. To the modern reader, the discussion
may well seem of strictly historical interest only. Strangely, Rousseau
113
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
does not draw many explicit parallels between the Roman model and
his own social framework. It may be that he thought the links between
the two would be obvious, or simply that the insertion of such a
treatise would lend a certain gravitas to the argument of The Social
Contract. In any case, it demonstrates once again the indebtedness
Rousseau felt towards the example of the Classical world in formu-
lating his own political vision.
Of most interest in Book IV, however, is the final chapter on civil
religion. In this self-contained passage, Rousseau expounds his views
on the extent to which the state may have jurisdiction over its citizens’
religious beliefs. His conclusion is that, in the interests of the
common good, the state does have a role in regulating the beliefs
of its constituents, but that it is of a particular and restricted sort.
Rousseau’s stipulations here have seemed to his critics to present
another example of his totalitarian tendencies. To see how his thought
develops, and whether this criticism is justified, we will have to follow
his chain of reasoning throughout the chapter, which progresses from
a theory of the origin of religion, through a comparison of three
basic types, to a final verdict on what kinds of beliefs ought to be tol-
erated by the justly constituted state.
Rousseau starts by making some bold claims about the genesis of
religions. In the earliest days of civilizations, he claims, each tribe or
nation had their own god. To be a member of a certain nation was
more or less the same thing as believing in a certain god. As a result
of this, there were no religious wars in the sense that Europe was
familiar with, with different nations battling over the interpretation
of a common theology. Instead, it was understood that each nation
had its own deity, and every member of the polity owed allegiance to
that deity in the same way that they owed allegiance to the tribe.
Now, as we know, Rousseau places great store by citizens’ sense of
loyalty to and identification with the state, and believes that if this is
not present then the community cannot prosper. When the dictates
of religion and the nation are coexistent, there is no conflict between
the two. However, if the demands of religion separate from the
demands of the state, then the social fabric risks being damaged.
According to Rousseau, the rise of the monotheistic religions,
Christianity especially, exemplifies this process. The unique feature
of religions like Christianity is that they demand allegiance to a
spiritual realm which is clearly different from the citizen’s temporal
jurisdiction. The result is a conflict of allegiance on the part of every
114
READING THE TEXT
citizen between the state and the Church. In the case of the Catholic
Church, Rousseau claims, the separation is particularly acute, since,
for the French at least, the seat of spiritual authority is located in an
entirely different country.
Once he has given this historical sketch, Rousseau then goes on to
isolate three different kinds of religious belief. The first he calls the
religion of man, which seems to be an expression of the simplest kind
of reverence for the Supreme Being and the dictates of morality. As
we noted earlier, Rousseau is by no means in opposition to the idea of
a natural divine law, and appears to view the religion of man as a kind
of pure consciousness of this supernatural order. In its unadorned
state, the religion of man is less concerned with doctrine or ritual, and
more with fostering a sense of brotherhood on earth and an anticipa-
tion of the bliss awaiting in the afterlife. This simple devotional
sentiment is succeeded by the religion of the citizen, which is the pre-
Christian state we have just encountered. Here, the individual
awareness of the sanctity of the moral order is replaced by an elabo-
rate construction of rituals, dogma and legally sanctioned forms of
worship. Finally, this system is replaced by the religion of the priest.
This is the name Rousseau gives to a doctrine, like Christianity, which
has isolated itself from the interests and identity of the state and
which demands allegiance to a higher set of institutions.
For Rousseau, all three kinds of religious belief are inimical to the
smooth running of a justly constituted state. The religion of the
priest distracts citizens from the proper object of their loyalty and
diverts their energies elsewhere. Under such circumstances, the peo-
ple can no longer be relied upon to identify their interests with the
state, as required by the lawgiver, and will at best have their loyalty
split two ways. The religion of the citizen, while preserving a single
object of devotion among the citizenry, is little better, since it
promotes manifest falsehoods and empty dogmas. Finally, the reli-
gion of man is in some ways the worst of all, as it advocates an
unworldly conception of life and diverts the citizens away from the
concrete demands of their social duty. Rousseau complains that there
is nothing worse for the social spirit than having the attention of the
populace detached from the world and diverted to considerations of
the hereafter. In practical terms, therefore, every kind of religious
belief has poor consequences for Rousseau’s social objectives.
After such an analysis, one might expect Rousseau to advocate
atheism for the citizens of his ideal state. However, Rousseau believes
115
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
that atheists are the worst kind of people of all, since they (in his
account) can have no certain ground for personal morality. As a
result, atheists would be the most unreliable and least moral types of
citizens of all, and must not be tolerated in any justly conceived polit-
ical order. In the light of this, Rousseau’s response to the problem of
religious belief is therefore rather surprising. A ‘civil creed’ will be
drawn up which contains a small number of core beliefs. These are:
that there exists a supreme being which foresees and provides, that
there is an afterlife in which the just are rewarded and the unjust
punished, that the social contract and the laws emanating from its
institutions are sacred and inviolable, and that intolerance for any
other religious belief not in contradiction with these maxims is
forbidden. The penalty for failing to adhere to these maxims is either
deportation from the state or, in the most extreme case, execution.
Stated thus, Rousseau’s views on religion seem at once cynical and
repressive. In a manner reminiscent of the lawgiver’s aping of divine
authority, we might be wary of Rousseau’s apparent entirely prag-
matic dogma of the sanctity of the social contract and its laws. This
seems to be a purely artificial requirement of the creed, simply
inserted in order to maintain social cohesion and loyalty to the state.
Certainly, Rousseau does not argue for any genuine theological basis
for of his political model, and it seems to be inserted into the creed as
a matter of simple expediency. Moreover, the draconian punishments
meted out to any who refuse to publicly profess such a creed appear
repressive in the extreme. We are apt to think of religion as a matter
of personal conscience, and to respect the freedom of every individ-
ual to reach their own conclusion on such matters as the existence of
God and an afterlife. By making these subjects matters for the state,
Rousseau certainly seems to be breaking his promise to leave citizens
of the ideal state as free as they were before entering into it. The only
positive part of the scheme appears to be the requirement of toler-
ance for other religions, so long as the beliefs in question do not
contradict the basic maxims of the civil creed. Since Rousseau’s dog-
mas are very general, it would certainly be possible for some religions
to coexist with such a creed. However, many religious people would
reject the notion that the social contract, or any man-made political
arrangement, has the same level of sanctity as the belief in God or an
afterlife. Anyone who publicly professed such a thing would face
deportation from Rousseau’s state. Accordingly, even Rousseau’s
116
READING THE TEXT
SUMMARY
Having now covered the entire text of The Social Contract, it is per-
haps worth drawing some threads together. As we have discussed,
Rousseau’s political philosophy – his conception of the institutions
and laws best fitted to enabling people to live in a state of equality
and freedom – is founded on prior notions of psychology and a
vision of human nature. Without some understanding of these ideas,
his scheme loses much of its rationale. Of primary importance here
is Rousseau’s consistent worry about the potential of individuals to
prosper in a situation where their individual wills are placed together
in an environment of mutual and involuntary dependence. Of equal
importance is his belief that, if a way could be found to remove those
shackles of dependence, then the positive natural inclinations which
we all share may be harnessed in a more fruitful direction. The shape
of the society created by the social contract can only make sense if
viewed through this prism.
117
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
118
READING THE TEXT
STUDY QUESTIONS
1. What is the role of the government in Rousseau’s political
system? How does this relate to the role of the sovereign? Would
such a relationship function effectively?
2. What types of government are possible in Rousseau’s state, and
which have the most chance of success? Do you agree with
Rousseau’s diagnosis of the strengths and weaknesses of the
various systems?
3. What are the causes of social decline, according to Rousseau?
Are they convincing?
4. What are the reasons for Rousseau’s suspicion of religion? Does
his response adequately resolve the issue?
5. Taking The Social Contract as a whole, do you feel that Rousseau
succeeds in his mission of presenting a society where both free-
dom and equality are guaranteed?
119
CHAPTER 4
Such sentiments would have been shared by many Britons of the nine-
teenth century, for whom Rousseau was an exemplar of dangerous
continental extremism. Even during his own lifetime, Rousseau had a
peculiar ability to inspire both adulation and downright loathing.
There have been very few commentators then or since who have taken
a lukewarm position on his character and thought: he tends to strike
his readers either as a muddle-headed charlatan or a secular prophet
of signal importance and vision. What is beyond question is that, for
good or ill, The Social Contract and other writings by Rousseau have
profoundly influenced political theory and practice. In this chapter,
we will trace some of the historical responses to the text as well as
some more modern treatments.
POLITICAL RESPONSES
As we have seen in our discussion of his life and times, Rousseau
was quite capable of alienating even his closest supporters with
his erratic behaviour and accusations of conspiracy. He went from
120
RECEPTION AND INFLUENCE
121
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
This statement clearly derives from the idea of a general will, and the
notion that the law comes from all and applies to all. Indeed,
Robespierre was to claim that the dictates of his Committee of Public
Safety, a powerful instrument of control during the period when the
revolution degenerated into the ‘reign of terror’, were the very
embodiment of the general will. Clearly, Rousseau’s ideas permeated
deep into the consciousness of the Revolution.
As a result of his alleged inspiration for a movement which quickly
became a byword for political repression, Rousseau has received
considerable criticism. The English conservative opponent of the
Revolution Edmund Burke called him an ‘insane Socrates’ for his
role in inspiring the excesses and brutality of the French Republic.6
122
RECEPTION AND INFLUENCE
123
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
124
RECEPTION AND INFLUENCE
125
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
126
RECEPTION AND INFLUENCE
the candid and tortured Confessions was most in tune with the
movement, but there are certainly aspects of The Social Contract
which prefigure important trends in Romanticism. Rousseau’s
continual appreciation of the natural goodness of people and the
usefulness of all their inherent drives and inclinations is the most
important feature in this regard.
So Rousseau’s influence in the history of ideas is somewhat com-
plex. Perhaps more so than any of his peers, his vision is difficult to
place neatly into any intellectual category. Like other great thinkers,
he occupies a position all of his own, and to align him too closely
with any intellectual tradition would risk misrepresenting the unique-
ness and vigour of his work. In the field of academic philosophy, he
has certainly been taken up as an inspiration by a diverse range of
figures. We have already touched briefly on Marx, but among those
others in debt to Rousseau is one of the giants of German philoso-
phy, Immanuel Kant, who seems to have drawn great inspiration
from Rousseau when formulating his own political philosophy, as
well as his extremely influential moral theory. According to Kant,
when considering the rectitude or otherwise of a given course of
action, it is the intention behind the action that is more important
than the consequences. The essential moral quality for an individual
to cultivate is a good will. Kant’s rules for determining right and
wrong actions in the light of this are quite complicated, but an impor-
tant aspect of them is this: an individual should act only according to
that maxim by which they can also will that the action would become
a universal law. In other words, the only right actions are those that
apply universally in the sense that everyone has a reason to assent to
them. Already in these words we can perceive something of an echo
of Rousseau’s conception of the general will. And elsewhere, Kant is
even more obviously in debt to Rousseau:
Here the inspiration from Rousseau’s idea that the only legitimate
kind of law comes from all and applies to all is clear.
In more recent times, Rousseau has continued to provide inspira-
tion for philosophers and political theorists. The most influential of
127
ROUSSEAU’S THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
these has been John Rawls, whose Theory of Justice has been credited
with reviving interest in political philosophy since its publication
in the 1970s. As his starting point, Rawls takes up a very similar ques-
tion to Rousseau: what mechanism can we use to determine a
universally binding set of fair principles of justice and governance,
given that all of us have different individual desires, abilities and
demands? The solution he adopts shares some important features of
Rousseau’s system. First, Rawls adopts the contractual model: the
promise of a fair society is made possible if the participants in some
sense agree to be bound by the laws. He also makes use of a proce-
dure analogous to the state of nature in Rousseau’s account, which
he calls the ‘original position’. This is a hypothetical state of affairs
prior to the establishment of the social order, the most important
feature of which is that each individual is subject to a veil of igno-
rance concerning their role and status in the future society. When
charged with making the contract to join together as a political unity,
therefore, they have no interest in making the conditions unequal,
since they do not know what position they will occupy. If the social
principles are such as to guarantee a high degree of equality, as least
as far as certain fundamental rights and goods are concerned, then
individuals will have a good reason to accept them. The similarity
between Rawl’s hypothetical basis for the state and Rousseau’s actual
decision procedure is striking, and he acknowledges his debt to the
idea of the social contract:
128
NOTES
1. CONTEXT
1
Grotius’s most influential book is The Laws of War and Peace. It is upon
this extensive treatise that his reputation as the father of international law
is based. His discussion of a populace giving up their rights to a ruler,
which Rousseau makes much of, is in Book III, Chapter 7 and onwards
(‘Of the Right over Prisoners’). A discussion of Rousseau’s relationship to
Grotius (and Hobbes) can be found in ‘Rousseau and the Friends of
Despotism’ in Ethics, Vol. 74, No. 1.
2
Rousseau, The Confessions, p. 20.
3
Rousseau, The Confessions, p. 327.
4
Rousseau, Reveries of the Solitary Walker, p. 27.
2. OVERVIEW OF THEMES
1
Rousseau is, at the least, ambivalent about the potential of women to
enjoy the same level of moral and intellectual development as men. In
Émile, the female counterpart of the eponymous protagonist, Sophie, has
a firmly supportive and subordinate function. In what follows, I shall
generally assume that Rousseau’s social and political theory applies to
both men and women, but it should be remembered that he would have
principally had men in mind when discussing potential citizens. For a fur-
ther discussion of this, see Wokler, Rousseau, pp. 100–102, and Dent,
A Rousseau Dictionary, pp. 248–249.
2
Rousseau, The Confessions, p. 377. At this stage, the work in question was
a more ambitious project called Political Institutions. This larger study was
never completed, and The Social Contract is a shorter compilation of
some of the central themes.
3
Locke, Two Treatises of Government, §4 (p. 116). See §§4–15 for a fuller
account of this, taking into account some objections. The contemporary
political philosopher John Rawls, in his influential A Theory of Justice,
also uses a variant of the idea of a pre-social state in his concept of the
‘original position’. See the final chapter of this book for a brief discussion
of this.
4
Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 161.
5
Rousseau does in fact remark on this difficulty in the Discourse on the
Origin of Inequality, and states that his claims should not be taken as
129
NOTES
historical fact, but as hypothetical conjectures. But it seems clear from the
detailed survey which follows that he does at least want his claims to be taken
seriously, and sees them as an accurate account of human psychology.
6
Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 188.
7
Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 184.
8
A critical appraisal of Rousseau’s account of the state of nature can
be found in J. C. Hall, Rousseau: An Introduction to his Political Philosophy,
pp. 28–73. See also Christopher Bertram, Rousseau and the Social
Contract, pp. 33–36.
9
Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 182 (n. 2).
10
Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 182 (n. 2).
11
This account of amour-propre is taken from Dent’s Rousseau: An Introduc-
tion to his Psychological, Social and Political Theory, especially pp. 70–72,
where there is a much fuller account of the notion and its role in Rous-
seau’s wider psychology. In what follows, I shall generally refer to
amour-propre in its malign or ‘inflamed’ sense in order to contrast it with
the wholesome amour de soi. The reader should be aware, however, that
not every reference to amour-propre in Rousseau’s oeuvre carries a neces-
sarily negative connotation. See also Dent and O’Hagan, ‘Rousseau on
Amour-Propre’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary
Volumes, Vol. 72, pp. 57–73.
12
The contemporary mathematician and historian Joseph Gautier
believed this, but Rousseau specifically rejected his suggestion. See Wokler,
Rousseau, p. 23.
1. WORKS BY ROUSSEAU
The text of The Social Contract in French, along with all Rousseau’s
other published works, may be found in the Oeuvres Complètes,
ed. by B. Gagnebin and M. Raymond (Paris: Éditions Gallimard).
Volume III, published in 1964, contains the full text of The Social
Contract, the Discourse on the Sciences and the Arts and the Discourse
on the Origin of Inequality. Volume I (1959) contains The Confessions
and the Reveries of the Solitary Walker, and Volume IV (1969)
contains Émile.
A separate edition of The Social Contract in French has been
published with an English introduction by C. Vaughan (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 1955).
There are a number of English translations of The Social Contract.
The one used throughout this guide has been by Maurice Cranston
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968). There is also an edition of The
Social Contract and Discourses translated by G. D. H. Cole, aug-
mented by J. H. Brumfitt, J. C. Hall and P. D. Jimack (London: Dent
Everyman, 1993). A more recent translation is found in The Social
Contract and Other Later Political Writings, ed. by Victor Gourevitch
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
Extracts from the Discourse on the Sciences and Arts and the
Discourse on the Origin of Inequality were taken from The Social
Contract and Discourses translated by G. D. H. Cole, augmented by
J. H. Brumfitt, J. C. Hall and P. D. Jimack (London: Dent Everyman,
1993). They are also available from The Discourses and Other Early
Political Writings, ed. by Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997).
Extracts from The Confessions were taken from the translation by
J. M. Cohen (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1953).
Extracts from Émile were taken from the translation by Allan
Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979).
132
FURTHER READING
The Extract from the Reveries of the Solitary Walker was taken
from the translation by P. France (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1979).
There is also an edition of Rousseau’s complete works in English,
currently in progress. At the time of writing, six volumes have been
released, which cover all of the works referred to in this guide, includ-
ing The Social Contract. See The Collected Writings of Rousseau, ed.
by R. D. Masters and C. Kelly (London: University Press of New
England, various dates).
2. BOOKS ON ROUSSEAU
There are numerous commentaries on Rousseau’s work and life
in general, and The Social Contract in particular. Some of the most
useful are:
Bertram, Christopher, Rousseau and the Social Contract (London:
Routledge, 2004)
Dent, Nicholas, Rousseau: An Introduction to his Psychological,
Social and Political Theory (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988)
Dent, Nicholas, A Rousseau Dictionary (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992)
Dent, Nicholas, Rousseau (Abingdon: Routledge, 2005)
Edmonds, David and Eidinow, John, Rousseau’s Dog: Two Great
Thinkers at War in the Age of Enlightenment (London: Faber &
Faber, 2006)
Gildin, Hilail, Rousseau’s Social Contract: The Design of the Argu-
ment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983)
Hall, J. C., Rousseau: An Introduction to his Political Philosophy
(London: Macmillan, 1973)
Miller, James, Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy (New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 1984)
O’Hagan, Timothy, Rousseau (London: Routledge, 1999)
Shklar, Judith, Men and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau’s Social
Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985)
Wokler, Robert, Rousseau (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995)
133
FURTHER READING
134
INDEX
135
INDEX
136