Kritik Der Practischen Vernunft Critique of Practical Reason
Kritik Der Practischen Vernunft Critique of Practical Reason
Kritik Der Practischen Vernunft Critique of Practical Reason
Having mastered epistemology and metaphysics, Kant believed that a rigorous application
of the same methods of reasoning would yield an equal success in dealing with the
problems of moral philosophy. Thus, in the Kritik der practischen Vernunft (Critique of
Practical Reason) (1788), he proposed a "Table of the Categories of Freedom in Relation to
the Concepts of Good and Evil," using the familiar logical distinctions as the basis for a
catalog of synthetic a priori judgments that have bearing on the evaluation of human action,
and declared that only two things inspire genuine awe: "der bestirnte Himmel über mir und
das moralische Gesetz in mir" ("the starry sky above and the moral law within"). Kant used
ordinary moral notions as the foundation ffor a derivation of this moral law in his
Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals) (1785).
We begin with the concept of that which can be conceived to be good without
qualification, a good will. Other good features of human nature and the benefits of a good
life, Kant pointed out, have value only under appropriate conditions, since they may be used
either for good or for evil. But a good will is intrinsically good; its value is wholly self-
contained and utterly independent of its external relations. Since our practical reason is
better suited to the development and guidance of a good will than to the achievement of
happiness, it follows that the value of a good will does not depend even on the results it
manages to produce as the consequences of human action.
Kant's moral theory is, therefore, deontological: actions are morally right in virtue of
their motives, which must derive more from duty than from inclination. The clearest
examples of morally right action are precisely those in which an individual agent's
determination to act in accordance with duty overcomes her evident self-interest and
obvious desire to do otherwise. But in such a case, Kant argues, the moral value of the
action can only reside in a formal principle or "maxim," the general commitment to act in
this way because it is one's duty. So he concludes that "Duty is the necessity to act out of
reverence for the law."
According to Kant, then, the ultimate principle of morality must be a moral law
conceived so abstractly that it is capable of guiding us to the right action in application to
every possible set of circumstances. So the only relevant feature of the moral law is its
generality, the fact that it has the formal property of universalizability, by virtue of which it
can be applied at all times to every moral agent. From this chain of reasoning about our
ordinary moral concepts, Kant derived as a preliminary statement of moral obligation the
notion that right actions are those that practical reason would will as universal law.
Consider, for example, the case (#2 in the text) of someone who contemplates relieving a
financial crisis by borrowing money from someone else, promising to repay it in the future
while in fact having no intention of doing so. (Notice that this is not the case of finding
yourself incapable of keeping a promise originally made in good faith, which would require
a different analysis.) The maxim of this action would be that it is permissible to borrow
money under false pretenses if you really need it. But as Kant pointed out, making this
maxim into a universal law would be clearly self-defeating. The entire practice of lending
money on promise presupposes at least the honest intention to repay; if this condition were
universally ignored, the (universally) false promises would never be effective as methods of
borrowing. Since the universalized maxim is contradictory in and of
2|Page
itself, no one could will it to be law, and Kant concluded that we have a perfect duty (to
which there can never be any exceptions whatsoever) not to act in this manner.
On the other hand, consider the less obvious case (#4 in the text) of someone who lives
comfortably but contemplates refusing any assistance to people who are struggling under
great hardships. The maxim here would be that it is permissible never to help those who
are less well-off than ourselves. Although Kant conceded that no direct contradiction would
result from the universalization of such a rule of conduct, he argued that no one could
consistently will that it become the universal law, since even the most fortunate among us
rightly allow for the possibility that we may at some future time find ourselves in need of
the benevolence of others. Here we have only an imperfect duty not act so selfishly, since
particular instances may require exceptions to the rule when it conflicts either with
another imperfect duty (e.g., when I don't have enough money to help everyone in need) or
a perfect duty (e.g., if the only way to get more money would be under a false promise).
Kant also supposed that moral obligations arise even when other people are not
involved. Since it would be contradictory to universalize the maxim of taking one's own life
if it promises more misery than satisfaction (#1), he argued, we have a perfect duty to
ourselves not to commit suicide. And since no one would will a universalized maxim of
neglecting to develop the discipline required for fulfilling one's natural abilities (#3), we
have an imperfect duty to ourselves not to waste our talents.
These are only examples of what a detailed application of the moral law would entail,
but they illustrate the general drift of Kant's moral theory. In cases of each of the four sorts,
he held that there is a contradiction—either in the maxim itself or in the will—involved in
any attempt to make the rule under which we act into a universal law. The essence of
immorality, then, is to make an exception of myself by acting on maxims that I cannot
willfully universalize. It is always wrong to act in one way while wishing that everyone else
would act otherwise. (The perfect world for a thief would be one in which everyone else
always respected private property.) Thus, the purely formal expression of the categorical
imperative is shown to yield significant practical application to moral decisions.
Although he held that there is only one categorical imperative of morality, Kant found it
helpful to express it in several ways. Some of the alternative statements can be regarded as
minor variations on his major themes, but two differ from the "formula of universal law"
sufficiently to warrant a brief independent discussion.
Kant offered the "formula of the end in itself" as: "Act in such a way that you treat
humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of another, always at the same time
as an end and never simply as a means." This places more emphasis on the unique value of
human life as deserving of our ultimate moral respect and thus proposes a more personal
view of morality. In application to particular cases, of course, it yields the same results:
violating a perfect duty by making a false promise (or killing myself) would be to treat
another person (or myself) merely as a means for getting money (or avoiding pain), and
3|Page
violating an imperfect duty by refusing to offer benevolence (or neglecting my talents)
would be a failure to treat another person (or myself) as an end in itself. Thus, the Kantian
imperative agrees with the Christian expression of "The Golden Rule" by demanding that
we derive from our own self-interest a generalized concern for all human beings.
Drawing everything together, Kant arrived at the "formula of autonomy," under which
the decision to act according to a maxim is actually regarded as having made it a universal
law. Here the concern with human dignity is combined with the principle of
universalizability to produce a conception of the moral law as self-legislated by each for all.
As Kant puts it,
A rational being must always regard himself as legislator in a kingdom of ends rendered
possible by freedom of the will, whether as member or as sovereign.
In this final formulation, the similarity of Kant's moral theory with his epistemology should
be clear. Just as the understanding in each of us determines the regulative principles of
natural science that all must share, so the practical reason in each of us determines the
universal maxims of morality that all must obey.
In fact, this final formula for the categorical imperative brings us back to the original
concept of the will itself as that which is good without qualification. At this point in the
argument, Kant can provide a more technical statement of its intrinsic moral value by
distinguishing between autonomy and heteronomy of the will.
A heteronomous will is one in obedience to rules of action that have been legislated
externally to it. Such a will is always submitting itself to some other end, and the principles
of its action will invariably be hypothetical imperatives urging that it act in such a way as to
receive pleasure, appease the moral sense, or seek personal perfection. In any case, the
moral obligations it proposes cannot be regarded as completely binding upon any agent,
since their maxim of action comes from outside it.
4|Page
Human Freedom
Here's another way of looking at it: Each case of moral action may be said to embody its
own unique instance of the antinomy between freedom and causal determination. For in
order to do the right thing, it must at least be possible for my action to have some real effect
in the world, yet I must perform it in complete independence from any external influence.
Morality requires both freedom and causality in me, and of course Kant supposes that they
are. I can think of myself from two standpoints: I operate within the phenomenal realm by
participating fully in the causal regularities to which it is subject; but as a timeless thing in
itself in the noumenal realm I must be wholly free. The trick is to think of myself in both
ways at once, as sensibly determined but intelligibly free.
Kant rightly confesses at the end of the Grounding that serious contemplation of morality
leads us to the very limits of human reason. Since action in accordance with the moral law
requires an autonomous will, we must suppose ourselves to be free; since the
correspondence of happiness with virtue cannot be left to mere coincidence, we must
suppose that there is a god who guarantees it; and since the moral perfection demanded by
the categorical imperative cannot be attained in this life, we must suppose ourselves to live
forever. Thus god, freedom, and immortality, which we have seen to be metaphysical
illusions that lie beyond the reach of pure reason, turn out to be the three great postulates
of practical reason.
Although the truth about ourselves and god as noumenal beings can never be
determined with perfect certainty, on Kant's view, we can continue to function as
responsible moral agents only by acting as if it obtains. Things could hardly have been
otherwise: the lofty dignity of the moral law, like the ultimate nature of reality, is the sort of
thing we cannot know but are bound to believe.
Kant's interest in moral matters was not exclusively theoretical. In Die Metaphysik der
Sitten(Metaphysics of Morals) (1797) he worked out the practical application of the
categorical imperative in some detail, deriving a fairly comprehensive catalog of specific
rules for the governance of social and personal morality. What each of us must actually will
as universal, Kant supposed, is a very rigid system of narrowly prescribed conduct.
5|Page
In Zum ewigen Frieden (On Perpetual Peace) (1795), Kant proposed a high-minded
scheme for securing widespread political stability and security. If statesmen would listen to
philosophers, he argued, we could easily achieve an international federation of independent
republics, each of which reduces its standing army, declines to interfere in the internal
affairs of other states, and agrees to be governed by the notion of universal hospitality.
The final component of Kant's critical philosophy found expression in his (Kritik der
Urteilskraft (Critique of Judgment)1790). Where the first Critique had dealt with
understanding in relation to reality and the second had been concerned with practical
reason in relation to action, this third Critique was meant to show that there is a systematic
connection between the two, a common feature underlying every use of synthetic a priori
judgments, namely the concept of purpose. In the last analysis, Kant supposed, it is our
compulsion to find meaning and purpose in the world that impels us to accept the tenets of
transcendental idealism.
In aesthetics, for example, all of our judgments about what is beautiful or sublime derive
from the determination to impose an underlying form on the sensory manifold. Like
mathematics, art is concerned with the discovery or creation of unity in our experience of
the spatio-temporal world. Teleological judgments in science, theology, and morality
similarly depend upon our fundamental convictions, that operation of the universe has
some deep purpose and that we are capable of comprehending it.
Kant's final word here offers an explanation of our persistent desire to transcend from
the phenomenal realm to the noumenal. We must impose the forms of space and time on all
we perceive, we must suppose that the world we experience functions according to natural
laws, we must regulate our conduct by reference to a self-legislated categorical imperative,
and we must postulate the noumenal reality of ourselves, god, and free will—all because a
failure to do so would be an implicit confession that the world may be meaningless, and
that would be utterly intolerable for us. Thus, Kant believed, the ultimate worth of his
philosophy lay in his willingness "to criticize reason in order to make room for faith." The
nineteenth-century German philosophers who followed him quickly moved to transform
his modest critical philosophy into the monumental metaphysical system of absolute
idealism.
http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/5i.htm
6|Page