Capstone-Project-Text Skill Up
Capstone-Project-Text Skill Up
Capstone-Project-Text Skill Up
THE CUMULATIVE
REPRESENTATIO
N OF
UNCERTAINTY
By A.Tversky and D Kahneman
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Advances in Prospect Theory: .................................................. 2
Abstract ....................................................................................... 2
Theory ......................................................................................... 4
2. Experiment ........................................................................... 5
3. Discussion ............................................................................. 10
Theorem ...................................................................................... 0
Theorem ...................................................................................... 0
AMOS TVERSKY
DANIEL KAHNEMAN1
ABSTRACT
We develop a new version of prospect theory that employs
cumulative rather than separable decision weights and
extends the theory in several respects. This version, called
cumulative prospect theory, applies to uncertain as well as to
risky prospects with any number of outcomes, and it allows
different weighting functions for gains and for losses. Two
principles, diminishing sensitivity and loss aversion, are
invoked to explain the characteristic curvature of the value
function and the weighting functions. A review of the
experimental evidence and the results of a new experiment
1
*An earlier version of this article was entitled "Cumulative Prospect Theory: An
Analysis of Decision under
Uncertainty."
This article has benefited from discussions with Colin Camerer, Chew Soo-Hong,
David Freedman, and David
H. Krantz. We are especially grateful to Peter P. Wakker for his invaluable input
and contribution to the
axiomatic analysis. We are indebted to Richard Gonzalez and Amy Hayes for
running the experiment and
analyzing the data. This work was supported by Grants 89-0064 and 88-0206 from
the Air Force Office of Scientific
Research, by Grant SES-9109535 from the National Science Foundation, and by
the Sloan Foundation.
1
THEORY
Prospect theory distinguishes two phases in the choice process:
framing and valuation. In the framing phase, the decision maker
constructs a representation of the acts, contingencies, and
outcomes that are relevant to the decision. In the valuation phase,
the decision maker assesses the value of each prospect and
chooses accordingly. Although no formal theory of framing is
available, we have learned a fair amount about the rules that govern
the representation of acts, outcomes, and contingencies (Tversky
and Kahneman, 1986). The valuation process discussed in
subsequent sections is applied to framed prospects.
2. EXPERIMENT
An experiment was carried out to obtain detailed information about
the value and weighting functions. We made a special effort to
obtain high-quality data. To this end, we recruited 25 graduate
students from Berkeley and Stanford (12 men and 13 women) with
no special training in decision theory. Each subject participated in
2.1. PROCEDURE
The experiment was conducted on a computer. On a typical trial,
the computer displayed a prospect (e.g., 25% chance to win $150
and 75% chance to win $50) and its expected value. The display
also included a descending series of seven sure outcomes (gains
or losses) logarithmically spaced between the extreme outcomes of
the prospect. The subject indicated a preference between each of
the seven sure outcomes and the risky prospect. To obtain a more
refined estimate of the certainty equivalent, a new set of seven sure
outcomes was then shown, linearly spaced between a value 25%
higher than the lowest amount accepted in the first set and a value
25% lower than the highest amount rejected. The certainty
equivalent of a prospect was estimated by the midpoint between
the lowest accepted value and the highest rejected value in the
second set of choices. We wish to emphasize that although the
analysis is based on certainty equivalents, the data consisted of a
series of choices between a given prospect and several sure
outcomes. Thus, the cash equivalent of a prospect was derived
from observed choices, rather than assessed by the subject. The
computer monitored the internal consistency of the responses to
each prospect and rejected errors, such as the acceptance of a
cash amount lower than one previously rejected. Errors caused the
original statement of the problem to reappear on the screen. 3 The
present analysis focuses on a set of two-outcome prospects with
monetary outcomes and numerical probabilities. Other data
involving more complicated prospects, including prospects defined
by uncertain events, will be reported elsewhere. There were 28
positive and 28 negative prospects. Six of the prospects (three
nonnegative and three nonpositive) were repeated on different
sessions to obtain the estimate of the consistency of choice. Table
3 displays the prospects and the median cash equivalents of the 25
subjects. A modified procedure was used in eight additional
problems. In four of these problems, the subjects made choices
regarding the acceptability of a set of mixed prospects (e.g., 50%
chance to lose $100 and 50% chance to win x) in which x was
systematically varied. In four other problems, the subjects
compared a fixed prospect (e.g., 50% chance to lose $20 and 50%
chance to win $50) to a set of prospects (e.g., 50% chance to lose
$50 and 50% chance to win x) in which x was systematically varied.
(These prospects are presented in table 6.)
2.2. RESULTS
The most distinctive implication of prospect theory is the fourfold
pattern of risk attitudes. For the nonmixed prospects used in the
present study, the shapes of the value and the weighting functions
imply risk-averse and risk-seeking preferences, respectively, for
gains and for losses of moderate or high probability. Furthermore,
the shape of the weighting functions favors risk seeking for small
probabilities of gains and risk aversion for small probabilities of loss,
provided the outcomes are not extreme. Note, however, that
prospect theory does not imply perfect reflection in the sense that
the preference between any two positive prospects is reversed
when gains are replaced by losses. Table 4 presents, for each
subject, the percentage of risk-seeking choices (where the certainty
equivalent exceeded expected value) for gains and for losses with
low (p _< .1) and with high (p _ .5) probabilities. Table 4 shows that
form _> .5, all 25 subjects are predominantly risk averse for positive
prospects and risk seeking for negative ones. Moreover, the entire
fourfold pattern is observed for 22 of the 25 subjects, with some
variability at the level of individual choices. Although the overall
pattern of preferences is clear, the individual data, of course, reveal
both noise and individual differences. The correlations, across
subjects, between lighting functions. A review of the experimental
evidence and the results of a new experiment confirm a distinctive
fourfold pattern of risk attitudes: risk aversion for gains and risk
seeking for losses of high probability; risk seeking for gains and risk
aversion for losses of low probability. Expected utility theory reigned
for several decades as the dominant normative and descriptive
model of decision making under uncertainty, but it has come under
serious question in recent years. There is now general agreement
that the theory does not provide an adequate description of
individual choice: a substantial body of evidence shows that
decision makers systematically violate its basic tenets. Many
alternative models have been proposed in response to this
empirical challenge.
Note: The two outcomes of each prospect are given in the left-hand
side of each row; the probability of the second (i.e., more extreme)
outcome is given by the corresponding column. For example, the
value of $9 in the upper left corner is the median cash equivalent of
the prospect (0, .9; $50, .1). the cash equivalents for the same
prospects on successive sessions averaged .55 over six
different prospects. Table 5 presents means (after transformation
to Fisher's z) of the
correlations between the different types of prospects. For example,
there were 19 and 17
prospects, respectively, with high probability of gain and high
probability of loss. The
value of .06 in table 5 is the mean of the 17 x 19 = 323 correlations
between the cash
equivalents of these prospects.
Fig 1.
Fig 2.
2.3. INCENTIVES
3. DISCUSSION
Theories of choice under uncertainty commonly specify 1) the
objects of choice, 2) a valuation rule, and 3) the characteristics of
the functions that map uncertain events and possible outcomes into
their subjective counterparts. In standard applications of expected
utility theory, the objects of choice are probability distributions over
wealth, the valuation rule is expected utility, and utility is a concave
function of wealth. The empirical evidence reported here and
elsewhere requires major revisions of all three elements. We have
proposed an alternative descriptive theory in which 1) the objects of
choice are prospects framed in terms of gains and losses, 2) the
valuation rule is a two-part cumulative functional, and 3) the value
function is S-shaped and the weighting functions are inverse S-
shaped. The experimental findings confirmed the qualitative
properties of these scales, which can be approximated by a (two-
part) power value function and by identical weighting functions for
gains and losses. The curvature of the weighting function explains
the characteristic reflection pattern of attitudes to risky prospects.
Overweighting of small probabilities contributes to the popularity of
both lotteries and insurance. Underweighting of high probabilities
contributes
both to the prevalence of risk aversion in choices between probable
gains and sure things, and to the prevalence of risk seeking in
choices between probable and sure losses. Risk aversion for gains
and risk seeking for losses are further enhanced by the curvature
of the value function in the two domains. The pronounced
asymmetry of the value function, which we have labeled loss
aversion, explains the extreme reluctance to accept mixed
prospects. The shape of the weighting function explains the
certainty effect and
violations of quasi-convexity. It also explains why these phenomena
are most readily observed at the two ends of the probability scale,
where the curvature of the weighting function is most pronounced
(Camerer, 1992). The new demonstrations of the common
consequence effect, described in tables 1 and 2, show that choice
under uncertainty exhibits some of the main characteristics
observed in choice under risk. On the other hand, there are
indications that the decision weights associated with uncertain and
with risky prospects differ in important ways. First, there is abundant
evidence that subjective judgments of probability do not conform to
the rules of probability theory (Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky,
1982). Second, Ellsberg's example and more recent studies of
choice under uncertainty indicate that people prefer some sources
of uncertainty over others. For example, Heath and Tversky (1991)
found that individuals consistently preferred bets on uncertain
events in their area of expertise over matched bets on chance
devices, although the former are ambiguous and the latter are not.
The presence of systematic preferences for some sources of
uncertainty calls for different weighting functions for different
domains, and suggests that some of these
a. (Wakker, 1989a) Expected utility theory holds iff ~> satisfies TC.