Carl Schmitt and The Sacred Origins of Law PDF
Carl Schmitt and The Sacred Origins of Law PDF
Carl Schmitt and The Sacred Origins of Law PDF
Mika Ojakangas
Each of the elements has thus found its partisan, except earth—
earth has found no supporter.
Aristotle, De Anima
. Hereafter, I translate Recht (French droit) as “law” and Gesetz (loi) as “statute.”
. Carl Schmitt, Der Wert des Staates und die Bedeutung des Einzelnen (Munich: C.
H. Beck, 1914), p. 79.
. Carl Schmitt, Über die Drei Arten des rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens, 2nd ed.
(Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1993), p. 24.
. On the “founding rupture” as the metaphysical core of Schmitt’s legal and political
34
Telos 147 (Summer 2009): 34–54.
doi:10.3817/0609147034
www.telospress.com
Carl Schmitt and the Sacred Origins Of Law 35
theory, see Mika Ojakangas, A Philosophy of Concrete Life: Carl Schmitt and the Political
Thought of Late Modernity (Bern: Peter Lang, 2006).
. Schmitt, Über die Drei Arten, p. 23.
. Carl Schmitt, State, Movement, People, trans. Simona Draghici (Corvallis, OR:
Plutarch Press, 2001).
. There are of course exceptions to this rule. See, e.g., Gopal Balakrishnan, The
Enemy: An Intellectual Portrait of Carl Schmitt (London: Verso, 2000), pp. 191–200; G. L.
Ulmen, “The Concept of ‘Nomos’: Introduction to Schmitt’s ‘Appropriation/Distribution/
Production’,” Telos 95 (Spring 1995): 39–52; Wolfgang Palaver, “Carl Schmitt on Nomos
and Space,” Telos 106 (Winter 1996): 105–27; Bruno Bosteels, “The Obscure Subject:
Sovereignty and Geopolitics in Carl Schmitt’s The Nomos of the Earth,” South Atlantic
Quarterly 104 (2005): 295–305; Carlos A. Otero, “From the Nomos to the Meridian,”
South Atlantic Quarterly 104 (2005): 381–88; Mitchell Dean, “Nomos: Word and Myth,”
in Louiza Odysseos and Fabio Petito, eds., The International Political Thought of Carl
Schmitt: Terror Liberal War and the Crisis of Global Order (London: Routledge, 2007),
pp. 242–58; Panu Minkkinen, “Hostility and Hospitality,” No Foundations: Journal of
Extreme Legal Positivism 4 (October 2007): 53–60.
36 Mika Ojakangas
Mother Earth
According to Schmitt, nomos is not something that we create by will (deci-
sionism) or by reason (normativism) but something that grows naturally.
The measures given by nomos are natural measures. This is not to say,
however, that Schmitt’s turn would have been a turn to Scholasticism and,
hence, to traditional Catholicism. The natural measures that Schmitt has
in mind are not measures of a divinely ruled cosmos, in which the human
being participates through the highest part of his reason. Schmitt’s natu-
ral measures are telluric rather than cosmological. They do not descend
from heaven, but ascend from the earth. For Schmitt, this is related to
the nature of man as a terrestrial being (Landwesen). In the beginning of
Land and Sea (1942), Schmitt writes: “Man lives, moves and walks on
the firmly grounded Earth. It is his standpoint and his base [Boden]. He
derives his point of view from it, which is also to say that his impressions
are determined by it and his world outlook is conditioned by it. Earth-
born, developing on it, man derives not only his horizon from it, but also
his poise, his movements, his figure and his height.” Yet man is not a ter-
restrial among terrestrials for Schmitt. In The Nomos of the Earth (1950),
he explains what kind of terrestrial man is: he is a cultivating terrestrial.
It is through cultivation of land that man sows the seeds of the fundamen-
tal measures of his collective existence, the just measures of his order
and orientation—that is to say, his nomos: “Every ontonomous [onto-
nome] and ontologically just judgement derives from the land.” All in all,
Schmitt argues, there is no law without a connection to the earth: “Law is
bound to the earth [erdhaft] and related to the earth.”10 The earth is the ori-
gin of all justice (Gerechtigkeit). It is itself “infinitely just” (allgerecht).11
This means that everything unrelated to the earth, everything uprooted
and deterritorialized, is unjust. The name Schmitt gives to this unjustness
is nihilism. To the extent that nomos signifies, according to Schmitt, the
unity of order (Ordnung) and concrete location (Ortung), nihilism desig-
nates order that is fundamentally and definitively separated from such a
. Carl Schmitt, Land and Sea, trans. Simona Draghici (Washington, DC: Plutarch
Press, 1997), p. 1.
. Carl Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus Publicum
Europaeum, trans. G. L. Ulmen (New York: Telos Press, 2003), p. 45.
10. Ibid., p. 42.
11. Ibid.
Carl Schmitt and the Sacred Origins Of Law 37
reason, Schmitt argues, the sea has no law.17 The sea has no law because
it has no “character” in the original sense of the Greek word, charassein:
to engrave, to scratch, to imprint.18 Although the riches of the sea (fishes,
pearls, and other things) are won by the hard work of human labor, the sea
does not give them off according to an inner measure of sowing and reap-
ing. Moreover, no lasting lines can be engraved onto the surface of the sea:
“Ships that sail across the sea leave no trace.”19 Finally, the sea cannot be
delineated by fences, enclosures, walls, and houses. Therefore, the mea-
sures of order and orientation of human life do not show themselves on
the open sea: “On the waves, there is nothing but waves.” On the sea there
is no law but mere disorientation.20 To be sure, Schmitt admits that the
question concerning man’s proper element is not so simple, because man
is “not a creature wholly conditioned by his medium [Umwelt].”21 In fact,
man can go so far as to “change himself into a new form of his historical
existence, in virtue of which he readjusts and reorganizes himself.”22 This
does not imply, however, that Schmitt would be a relativist in his under-
standing of the elements. “Man is a terrestrial” means that he should also
remain bound to the earth. From Schmitt’s perspective, there is something
perverse in man’s “thrust seawards,”23 not to mention in his thrust airward
and even toward the element of fire, which are the more recent elements
of human activity.24 Only the element of earth can serve as the genuine
foundation for the authentic order of nomos.
Land Appropriation
Yet the cultivation of land is not Schmitt’s final word as regards the
appearance of the just order and orientation. According to him, even the
nomads have their law (nomos), although they do not cultivate land. More-
over, this law is based on the very same primeval act as the law of the
25. According to Schmitt, the nomads also appropriate their lands, although only
provisionally. See Carl Schmitt, “Nomos—Nahme—Name,” appendix in The Nomos of
the Earth, p. 341.
26. On appropriation as Ereignis, see Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, pp. 39, 45,
48, and 83.
27. Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, p. 48.
28. Ibid., p. 48; see also pp. 47, 45 (translations modified).
29. Ibid., p. 81.
30. Carl Schmitt, “Appropriation/Distribution/Production: An Attempt to Determine
from Nomos the Basic Questions of Every Social and Economic Order,” appendix in The
Nomos of the Earth, p. 329.
31. ”So Joshua came suddenly upon them with all his people of war” and “smote
them, until they left none remaining.” Joshua 11:7–8.
40 Mika Ojakangas
The Visible
Schmitt is nowhere very clear as to how to distinguish the improper and
the proper land-based order. Yet, we already have some clues. Unlike deci-
sionism, which focuses on conscious personal decision, “concrete order
thinking” emphasizes the concrete institutional order of a community.
From this perspective, nomos is not a proper nomos until it has become a
concrete institutional order. But how does the order become institutional-
ized? At first, we may assume it is institutionalized by those very “fences,
enclosures, boundaries, and walls” in which the orders and orientations
of human life become visible.46 Schmitt holds that there is no nomos
without such enclosures: “Every nomos consists of what is within its own
bounds.”47 But it is highly probable that the same rule that applies to the
notion of appropriation applies to Schmitt’s notion of enclosure as well:
although every nomos implies an enclosure, every enclosure is not neces-
sarily a nomos. Something more is needed, and if we examine Schmitt’s
argumentation carefully, we will find two additional notions that can be
considered significant.
The first notion is visibility (Sichtbarkeit). At the beginning of the
article, we saw that when the solid ground of the earth was delineated by
fences, walls, houses, and other human artefacts, the orders and orienta-
tions of social life became apparent (offenkundig) and the forms of power
and domination visible (sichtbar). It was also established that Schmitt
defined nomos as the immediate form in which the political and social
The Sacred
For Schmitt, the most essential constituent of the just order relates to the
justness of its origin (Herkunft).55 It is the original appropriation that must
be recognized as just. Without such recognition, nomos “would be noth-
ing more than the arbitrary right of the stronger.”56 What, then, makes
Joshua’s conquest or Heracles’ theft a founding event of genuine nomos?
On what grounds may appropriation be recognized as legitimate? For the
medieval jurists and theologians, for example, the source of the legiti-
macy of appropriation was usually agreement.57 This was also the opinion
of many early modern theorists of natural law: “There is no precept of
natural law to be discovered by which men are enjoined to make an appro-
priation of things, as that each man shall be allotted his particular portion,
divided from the shares of others.”58 It is naturally just to use things, they
59. See John Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge UP,
1960), bk. 2, ch. 5.
60. Schmitt, “Nomos—Nahme—Name,” p. 348.
61. Ibid., p. 349.
62. Ibid., p. 348.
63. Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, p. 70.
64. Ibid., p. 78. Hence, contrary to Arturo Leyte’s claim (“A Note on The Nomos of
the Earth,” South Atlantic Quarterly 104 [2005]: 292), according to which Schmitt “does
not realize that surrounding nomos, as well as polis but not the modern state, is a sense
of the sacred,” I argue that Schmitt realizes very well that nomos is surrounded by such a
sense: the sense of the sacred is the very reason why he wants to restore the ancient mean-
ing of nomos. In this respect, I agree with Carlos A. Otero: “The nomos can be thought of
only as sacred.” Otero, “From the Nomos to the Meridian,” p. 383.
46 Mika Ojakangas
sanctified in a name that cannot be put into question.71 Such a name can
only be a sacred name and, more particularly, a name that can be localized
in a concrete space.72
This also explains why Schmitt refuses to call modern territorial
states within fixed boundaries genuine land-bound orders. Even though
the modern state realizes the principle cujus regio, ejus religio (“whose
region, his religion”), thus localizing religion in space, metamorphoses in
the sphere of the Christian religion unraveled all the unifying effects of
this localization. With the rise of Protestantism, religion was transformed
into a matter of conscience of a private individual, which paved the way
for the withdrawal of the religious from politics. Hence, although religion
becomes localized in the modern state, it is simultaneously delocalized
since it is privatized, individualized, and depoliticized. This is also the
reason why Schmitt argues that there is an unbridgeable gap between the
heroes of the conquista and the modern state. The heroes of the conquista
belonged to a spiritual world of a medieval community—and the distance
that separates that world from the world of the state is enormous: only
the medieval community recognized divinity in public life, discernible for
instance in the divine right of kings as well as the divine right of estates
to resist an unlawful ruler.73 In the modern state, there is no place for such
divine rights. With this displacement, the “original and natural unity of
politics and religion” is necessarily destroyed.74 In the modern state, the
immemorial alliance of religion and power has come to an end. It is for this
71. In Joshua’s case the legitimization was clearly ex post facto, given the fact that
the passage of Genesis where God promises the land to Abraham’s descendants was written
centuries after Joshua’s conquest. On the other hand, nowadays it is generally held that
Israelites established their presence in Canaan by a piecemeal process rather than by a
conquest. Thus, Joshua’s very conquest (this “classic example”) is a mere myth represent-
ing a late reconstruction of Israel’s early history, intended to illustrate certain post-exilic
political and theological aspirations. See, e.g., John Strange, “The Book of Joshua: Origin
and Dating,” Scandinavian Journal of the Old Testament 16 (2002): 49–50.
72. Undoubtedly, for Schmitt, the most favorite name for a sacred space was Rome:
“Raum and Rom are the same word.” Carl Schmitt, Ex Captivitate Salus (Cologne: Greven
Verlag, 1950), p. 90. All in all, space is not a geographical notion for Schmitt but rather
a mythopolitical one. In the foreword to The Nomos of the Earth, p. 38, Schmitt refers
to Johann Jacob Bachofen—whose studies in mythology had became very popular in
Germany during the interwar period—and writes: “The ties to mythological sources of
jurisprudential thinking are much deeper than those of geography.”
73. Schmitt, The Leviathan, p. 46.
74. Ibid., p. 10.
48 Mika Ojakangas
reason that Schmitt calls the modern state a machine, or the “first modern
mechanism in a grand style.”75 Its truth and justice do not reside anywhere
except for “its technical perfection.”76 Hence, although the modern state is
an enclosed territorial order, it is not an order that could endow men with
orientation, because its public personifications and laws lack divine legiti-
macy. In the modern state, to use Sophocles’ words, “laws of the land”
(nomous chthonos) are no longer woven together “with oath-bound justice
of the gods.”77 Without such weaving, there is no law. This, I believe, is
Schmitt’s final word on nomos, in that it alone explains why Schmitt con-
siders our contemporary situation “completely deteriorated [zersetzt].”78
Volksnomostheologie
In his article “Nomos—Nahme—Name,” Schmitt complains about the
reception of The Nomos of the Earth by a German specialist in interna-
tional law. According to Schmitt, this specialist radically misunderstood
his reference to the Marian image of the conquista. He scorned it as a
“Christian trimming.”79 But Schmitt does not explain how this image
should be understood. If my analysis is correct, Maria should be under-
stood as a historical example of a sacred name. Maria is not a trimming,
nor is she mentioned because she is a Christian figure. Maria is a name that
sanctifies appropriation and the order that follows it. Every genuine order
of nomos presupposes sanctification, and all genuine sanctification con-
cerns the question of origins. And, precisely due to its sacredness, nomos
is capable of endowing men with orientation. The sacred opens up a space,
a meaningful world, because it localizes and hence fixes a perspective that
is beyond subjective vacillations.80 The sacred fixation (sakrale Ortung),
thus, makes an order normative. Yet, for Schmitt, no fixation is absolute
or universal. Nomos is not only spatially localized but also historically
evolving and developing, to the extent that every nomos grows naturally
but also dies naturally. At some point, every nomos withers away, when
it loses its vitality based on its ties to a divine source. In Schmitt’s view,
the withering based on the loosening of ties with the divine means a crisis
of order and orientation. In his view, however, it does not mean nothing-
ness. A new nomos can also emerge from the depth of the crisis through
fierce battles (Ringen) of the old and new forces. Precisely in such battles,
understood as great historical events, “right measures and meaningful pro-
portions” (nomos) eventually originate.81
That said, it is obvious that this article is a contribution to the (in)famous
“theological twist” in Schmitt studies. However, my intention is not to
argue that Schmitt was a traditional Catholic, nor that his Catholicism was
a form of Christianity that rejects its roots in Judaism in favor of pagan
foundations. Rather, following Raphael Gross,82 I argue that there is a close
link between Schmitt’s notion of nomos and the German Volksnomos-
theologie developed by such ultra-nationalist (and eminently antisemitic)
Lutheran theologians as Wilhelm Stapel, Emanuel Hirsch, Friedrich
Gogarten, and Paul Althaus. Hirsch was a distinguished Lutheran church
historian, who during the Nazi regime not only joined the party but entered
the auxiliary of the SS as a supporting member. He had reviewed approv-
ingly three books by Schmitt in 1923 and 1924, yet indicated that Schmitt
had taken the wrong road by ignoring the notion of Gemeinschaft as the
point of intersection between theology and constitutional history.83 In his
own theology of Volksnomos, Hirsch argued that every community stands
on a threefold foundation of God-given horos, nomos, and logos, mean-
ing uncrossable boundary (horos), conditions of order, life, and thought
(nomos), and a “self-expressive” living spirit (logos). Moreover, he—like
his Lutheran colleagues—saw God’s hand in the elevation of Hitler to
power, and believed that the revolution introduced by National Socialism
represented a proper reintroduction of horos, nomos, and logos to Ger-
man life. The Nazis, Hirsch argued, are conscious of divine boundaries not
81. Carl Schmitt, “The New Nomos of the Earth,” appendix in The Nomos of the
Earth, p. 355. Schmitt repeats here the concluding words of Land and Sea, p. 59.
82. See Gross, Carl Schmitt, pp. 51–59.
83. See John Stroup, “Political Theology and Secularization Theory in Germany,
1918–1939: Emanuel Hirsch as a Phenomenon of his Time,” Harvard Theology Review
80, no. 3 (1987): 338–39.
50 Mika Ojakangas
created by artificial reason but born in a “holy storm” that had come over
the Germans.84
As far as I know, however, Schmitt does not mention Hirsch in his
studies on the notion of nomos. Yet, he mentions his and Hirsch’s mutual
friend Stapel in The Nomos of the Earth: “I have great respect for the efforts
of Wilhelm Stapel and Hans Bogner, who have given nomos the meaning
Lebensgesetz.”85 Indeed, in his book Der Christliche Staatsmann (1932),
for instance, Stapel (a publicist, an editor of Deutsches Volksum, and also a
supporter of the Nazi regime) had defined Lebensgesetz-nomos as follows:
“Every Volk is hold together by a law of life, which corresponding to its
nature defines its inner and outer form, its cult, its ethos, its constitution,
and its law: by its Nomos.”86 But it was Bogner (Stapel’s friend and a
Hellenist, also mentioned by Schmitt) who had first identified nomos with
Lebensgesetz, that is, with the notion that had become very popular among
the right-wing nationalist intellectuals emphasizing the völkisch roots of
law during the 1920s.87 (Hence, Bogner’s innovation was not that he trans-
lated nomos as Lebensgesetz but that he identified the already existing idea
of the völkisch Lebensgesetz with the Greek nomos.) For the Greeks, Bog-
ner argues, nomos was that divine power that constituted and maintained
the order of life of the polis. It expressed the unity of Greek spirit and race,
determining their politics and war, their mores, language, and religion, at
least before it became “deteriorated” (zersetzt) by the Sophists!88 Bogner’s
definition of nomos, especially as it was presented in his book Die ver-
wirklichte Demokratie: Die Lehren der Antike (1930), thus paved the way
for the use of the notion in the ultra-nationalist Lutheran theology, which
previously had become known as the theology of the “orders of creation”
84. See Robert P. Ericksen, Theologians under Hitler: Gerhard Kittel, Paul Althaus
and Emanuel Hirsch (New Haven, CT: Yale UP, 1985), esp. pp. 151–53.
85. Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, p. 70n10. As far as I know, Bogner and Sta-
pel (the editor of Bogner’s books) never published anything together: Stapel just adapted
Bogner’s definition of nomos in his own writings.
86. Wilhelm Stapel, Der Christliche Staatsmann: Eine Theologie des Nationalis-
mus (Hamburg: Hanseatische Verlagsanstalt, 1932), p. 174. Quoted in Wolfgang Tilgner,
Volksnomostheologie und Schöpfungsglaube (Göttingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprecht, 1966),
p. 115.
87. In Nazi Germany, Lebensgesetz became increasingly popular notion and it was
understood primarily in racial terms.
88. Hans Bogner, Die verwirklichte Demokratie: Die Lehren der Antike (Hamburg:
Hanseatische Verlagsanstalt, 1930). See also Tilgner, Volksnomostheologie, p. 114; Gross,
Carl Schmitt, p. 55.
Carl Schmitt and the Sacred Origins Of Law 51
(Shöpfungsordnungen) and which now wanted to give the idea of the Volk
as a God-given entity a more “refined” intellectual foundation.89 It also
became the intellectual foundation for Schmitt’s philosophy of nomos
conceived as a divinely sanctified law of growth.
To be sure, Schmitt also criticized Stapel and Bogner, but it is merely
the term Lebensgesetz that is problematic for him, not the basic meaning
they give to nomos. The reason why Schmitt rejects the notion of Lebens-
gesetz has to do with a linguistic degeneration of the terms Leben and
Gesetz, not with the idea it implies (law’s inseparability from life): Leben
has become a biological term, excluding other (especially spiritual) aspects
of life, whereas Gesetz expresses only the positivistic artifice of what is
enacted, not what grows naturally.90 But it is also true that Schmitt’s nomos
cannot be reduced to the Volksnomostheologie. Although the advocates of
the Volksnomostheologie similarly emphasized crisis, conflict, and battle
at the foundation of the development of nomos, unlike Schmitt they did
not pay attention to the “original” event of land appropriation. We cannot
find any interest in the thinking of “elemental orders” in their writings
either. Still, Schmitt’s mythopolitics of nomos would be quite incompre-
hensible without taking into account its engagement with the Lutheran
Volksnomostheologie, the theology that found the “primeval powers”
(Ursprungsmächte) of human existence in blood, soil, and the fate of the
nation.91
89. On the Volksnomostheologie, the theology of the “order of creation,” and their
historical background, see Tilgner, Volksnomostheologie. One of the basic ideas of the
theology of the “orders of creation” was that God manifests himself first in nature and
history and only secondarily in the gospel. Especially such natural-historical entities as
Volk and race are expressions of God’s will, and, therefore, to act against such holy entities
is sin—including universalistic aspirations and the mixing of races. See also Hans Tiefel,
“The German Lutheran Church and the Rise of National Socialism,” Church History 41
(1972): 326–36.
90. Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, p. 70n10.
91. See Tiefel, “The German Lutheran Church,” p. 332, quoting Gogarten.
92. Martin Ostwald, “Ancient Greek Ideas of Law,” in Philip P. Wiener, ed., Dic-
tionary of the History of Ideas, vol. 2 (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1973–74),
pp. 674–84; Martin Ostwald, Nomos and the Beginnings of the Athenian Democracy
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1969).
52 Mika Ojakangas
have had a great impact on the process that resulted in the conception of
nomos as a written statute. All in all, nomos played no major role in the
Greek language of law before the fifth century, although it otherwise was
a common word, usually designating a way of life. Before Solon, the two
most common terms for law were themis and dike. They were both much
more Schmittian than nomos ever was. They both designated more than
merely a set of legal rules by which right and wrong were determined;
rather, they formed a part of a social order that viewed them as having
existed from time immemorial and believed that they would continue to
exist without change, since the permanence of the order is guaranteed by
the gods.93 Hence, it was not the land-bound nomos, as Schmitt argues,94
but themis and dike that were replaced by thesmos, the term designating
law in the Solonian legislation. According to Schmitt, moreover, Solon’s
thesmoi were later called nomoi.95 This is true, but what Schmitt does not
notice is that thesmos as nomos no longer had the same meaning that it
had had in the Solonian legislation. Originally, thesmos had connotations
that could be associated with themis and dike: although Solon’s thesmoi
were written, writing was rather an accidental than an essential attribute
for them. Furthermore, although thesmos was not part of a universal order,
was never personified, and was always thought of as having had a begin-
ning in human time, it also meant institutional order. When nomos became
the technical term for law, all these connotations were displaced.
According to Ostwald, the last confirmed use of thesmos as a techni-
cal term for law in Athens is the prescription of a reenactment of Draco’s
law against tyranny in 511, reported by Aristotle.96 During the following
decades, nomos became the technical term for law, designating now a
written statute and nothing more. In other words, the deployment of nomos
93. According to Ostwald, themis (deriving from a stem meaning “place” and “estab-
lish”) is the wider concept of the two and defines those aspects of the social structure that
give order and regularity to the whole, whereas dike (whose etymology links it to a stem
meaning “show” and “point in a given direction”) usually describes the place assigned to
individuals within human society. Ostwald, “Ancient Greek Ideas of Law,” p. 675. Schmitt’s
Ortung, a key word in his philosophy of nomos, contains both of these significations.
94. Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, p. 75.
95. Ibid.
96. “There are the ordinances [thesmia] and ancestral principles of Athens: if any
person rise in insurrection in order to govern tyrannically, or if any person assists in estab-
lishing the tyranny, he himself and his family shall be disfranchised.” Aristotle, Athenian
Constitution, in Aristotle in Twenty-Three Volumes, vol. 20 (London: Heinemann, 1971),
16.10.
Carl Schmitt and the Sacred Origins Of Law 53
occurs simultaneously with the dissolution of the conception that law sig-
nifies the institutional order of polis. Therefore, although Schmitt notices
the change in the meaning of law during the classical period, this change
does not take place within the concept of nomos, as he claims. The change
took place when the Greeks replaced themis, first, by thesmos and, later
on, by nomos. Moreover, in Schmitt’s view, the change in the meaning
of nomos occurred as a consequence of the dissolution of polis,97 but it
is equally possible to argue that it was a precondition for the emergence
of the classical polis, at least if that is how we understand the democratic
Athens. The emergence of nomos as equivalent to law, designating written
statute, coincides, on this view, with the emergence of Athenian democ-
racy. It was democracy that saw it necessary to distinguish law from the
divinely legitimized order of things. In that respect, even the Solonian
thesmos appeared as non-democratic, since it was given from above and
excluded the notion of popular consent as its basis of legitimacy.
Hence, if we accept Ostwald’s analyses concerning the situation in
which nomos became the substitute for thesmos, we will recognize that a
much more important single factor than the Sophistic distinction between
nomos and physis or the dissolution of the polis was the appearance of a
democratic constitution. The positivist interpretation of law was the result
of a deliberate policy of democratic Athens.98 In Schmitt’s estimation, such
an interpretation, prevalent again today, testifies to a state of complete
deterioration, but, at the same time, we must remember that it also testi-
fies to the situation in which democracy has become the insurmountable
horizon. In such a situation, law cannot emanate from any other source
than from the will of the people, as Schmitt himself wrote in Constitu-
tional Theory. If we follow Schmitt, however, the will of the people has
to be understood in terms of what he calls secularization: the will of the
people in democracy is the exact equivalent to the will of God in theis-
tic theology. But today the will of the people is no longer a secularized
theological notion; it has ceased to be a substitute for God’s will. There is
nothing divine in people’s will, not even an imitation of the divine. To use
Schmitt’s words, it is the “sum of private opinions of each individual.”99
This means that law has become thoroughly profane as well, a mere tool
“devoid of all sacredness of content,” as Max Weber once said of modern
law.100 Schmitt experienced a “feeling of emptiness” before such law,101
and this was surely one of the reasons why he sought to “restore to the
word nomos its energy and majesty.”102 In today’s culture, where the feel-
ing of emptiness is cured by other and perhaps less majestic forces, such a
pursuit is but an anathema.
100. Max Weber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, trans.
Ephraim Fischoff et al. (Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 1978), 2:895.
101. Schmitt, “The Liberal Rule of Law,” p. 295.
102. Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, p. 67.