J ctt1ws7wbh 5
J ctt1ws7wbh 5
J ctt1ws7wbh 5
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
This content is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives
4.0 International License (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0). To view a copy of this license, visit
https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/.
ANU Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to New
Directions for Law in Australia
I. Introduction
The anarchist Peter Kropotkin began his 1886 pamphlet Law and
Authority by describing the tendency of law to proliferate so that it takes
over every aspect of social life:2
when ignorance reigns in society and disorder in the minds of men, laws
are multiplied, legislation is expected to do everything, and each fresh law,
being a fresh miscalculation, men are continually led to demand from it
what can proceed only from their own education and their own morality.
11
If there was too much law for Kropotkin in 19th century Europe I don’t
like to imagine what he would have made of modern nation states and the
legal effects of globalisation. (Indeed the phenomenon of ‘juridification’
has been much analysed in the later 20th and early 21st centuries.3) In some
ways Kropotkin’s underlying image of law was not completely unlike the
image held by 19th and 20th century liberal thinkers. This image was of
a law with its own sphere, a law with a conceptual limit beyond which
people could organise their lives as they saw fit. Beyond law’s sphere
of regulation lay freedom and the private sphere. Kropotkin’s agenda was
to reduce and eventually eliminate law – he concludes his pamphlet with
the words ‘no more laws! No more judges!’4 The more moderate concern
of many other writers who also adopt the image of a limited law and
an outside or non-regulated area of freedom and privacy has been and
continues to be where to draw the line of legal intervention, and how
to improve the limited law to make it more efficient and consistent, less
obscure, and in tune with current social values.
The idea of a limited sphere of law and a non-legal sphere of freedom
was tested repeatedly throughout the 20th century, often in conjunction
with an appreciation of the disseminated nature of power. The image of
a limited law was, for instance, revealed to be incoherent in the 1980s by
feminist writers such as Frances Olsen and Katherine O’Donovan who
pointed to the many ways in which law shapes the conditions for social
life and structures legal subjects and their relationships.5 Law is not neutral
as regards social order, but rather creates, normalises and replicates social
life. At the same time, by perpetuating the idea that abstract individualism
is gender-neutral and race-neutral, and that the person is a natural
rather than constructed feature of social life, law obscures its own role
in producing social relations. As feminists argued, beyond law was not
freedom but, rather, a pervasively normalised and legally inflected social
and private life. As Margaret Thornton wrote in the 1990s, ‘For women,
neither the polity nor the market have been realms of freedom or self-
realisation, but realms of hostility’.6
3 See, in particular, Jurgen Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action Vol 2 (Beacon Press, 1987)
356–73.
4 Kropotkin, above n 2, 34.
5 Frances Olsen, ‘The Family and the Market: A Study of Ideology and Legal Reform’ (1983)
96 Harvard Law Review 1497; Katherine O’Donovan, Sexual Divisions in Law (Weidenfeld and
Nicholson, 1985).
6 Margaret Thornton, ‘The Cartography of Public and Private’ in Margaret Thornton (ed), Public
and Private: Feminist Legal Debates (Oxford University Press, 1995).
12
7 Austin Sarat, ‘“The Law is All Over”: Power, Resistance, and the Legal Consciousness of the
Welfare Poor’ (1990) 2 Yale Journal of Law and the Humanities 343.
8 Ibid. 378.
13
as more pervasive and less cohesive, a dispersed set of practices and values,
not necessarily emanating from a single place, and experienced and
performed differently by different groups of people.
Where does law reform sit in an image of law which is ‘all over’, as Sarat’s
respondent said, and where different groups of people have quite different
views of what law is and how it operates? I’d like to address this question
in three parts. First, by reference to the familiar notion that law reform is
about changing doctrinal law so that it better suits the social conditions of
the times. Second, by thinking about the idea that law reform can equally
address a changing concept of law. Third, by looking at changes in the
social and cultural conditions which underpin law.
In this image, society usually goes along within the constraints set in
place by the law. Social life is the water which flows through the form
preserved by law. There is no sense in this image that the characteristics of
the river as a whole have been formed by the flow of water; rather, the flow
is determined by the solid surfaces maintained by the law. Law reform
9 Alfred Thomson Denning (Baron), ‘The Universities and Law Reform’ (1949) 1 Journal of the
Society of Public Teachers of Law 258.
10 Ibid. 258.
14
11 John Gava, ‘The Rise of the Hero Judge’ (2001) 24 UNSW Law Review 747; J D Heydon,
‘Judicial Activism and the Death of the Rule of Law’ (2004) 10 Otago Law Review 493; Michael Kirby
‘“Judicial Activism”? A Riposte to the Counter-Reformation’ (2005) 11 Otago Law Review 1.
12 See Mari Matsuda, ‘When the First Quail Calls: Multiple Consciousness as Jurisprudential
Method’ (1988) 11 Women’s Rights Law Reporter 7, 8.
15
neutrality vis-à-vis social power, engaging from a position that does not
accept its neutrality has been very difficult. This has led to a good deal of
caution among all critics of state law about whether and how to engage
with law and law reform: What can be expected of law reform? Does
engaging with law simply legitimate its exclusion of alternative knowledges?
How can values of care be imported into doctrinal law? How can the
experiences of marginalised others be incorporated into the assumed
knowledge of law? How can legal subjects be reconstructed as relational
rather than atomistic? How can entrenched biases in the operation of
law be addressed? How can we even commence the ‘horizontal dialogue’
that Irene Watson has spoken of between modern Australian colonial law
and the first, original, law of this country?13 The very form of positivist
law seems to prevent anything but ad hoc change which may, of course,
accumulate into something larger over time, but it is a very slow process.
13 Irene Watson, ‘What is the Mainstream? The Laws of First Nations Peoples’, see Ch 18, this
collection.
14 See, in particular, Frederick Schauer, ‘The Path-Dependence of Legal Positivism’ (2015) 101
Virginia Law Review 957, 960–69.
15 W Morrison, Jurisprudence: From the Greeks to Post-modernism (Cavendish, 1997) 227; see
also, discussing Bentham, Schauer, above n 14, 960–69; Tom Campbell, The Legal Theory of Ethical
Positivism (Dartmouth, 1996).
16
16 H L A Hart, ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morality’ (1958) 71 Harvard Law
Review 593, 596.
17
18
22 On ‘embodied imagining’, see Judith Grbich ‘The Body in Legal Theory’ (1992) 11 University
of Tasmania Law Review 26.
23 Patricia Ewick and Susan Silbey, ‘Conformity, Contestation, and Resistance: An Account
of Legal Consciousness’ (1992) 26 New England Law Review 731.
24 Robert Cover, ‘Nomos and Narrative’ (1983) 97 Harvard Law Review 4; see also Robert Post,
‘Who’s Afraid of Jurispathic Courts: Violence and Public Reason in Nomos and Narrative’ (2005) 17
Yale Law Journal of Law and the Humanities 9.
19
I don’t have a very clear answer to these questions, but my sense is that the
more traditional attitudes to law reform have substantially changed and
are now more in keeping with an expansive and even experimental view
of what law is. I would make a couple of observations.
First, critical and sociolegal approaches add support to using an evidence-
based approach to reform rather than an approach based on abstract
rationality. Empirical sociolegal evidence is very significant in this
context, as are efforts (discussed below) to read or interpret legal doctrine
in ways which accommodate both diversity of values and diversity of
life experiences. Second, a more disseminated image of law is perhaps
more receptive to efforts to test successor legalities in and around the
edges of state law. In some contexts, state law itself can become an
experimental space for new ideas about law. One could cite, for example,
so-called ‘alternative’ practices of law, such as non-court-based dispute
resolution or Indigenous sentencing courts which introduce values of
negotiation, accommodation, recognition of the other, and legal plurality
into the practice and meaning of law. At the margins of or beyond state
law, examples might include truth and reconciliation commissions and
efforts to mobilise civil society in justice initiatives, such as the Women’s
International War Crimes Tribunal and other people’s tribunals.25
These instances draw on state legality but also deliberately eschew it in
the interests of (in part) taking law beyond its self-defined boundaries.
They are of course indicative of a two-way process or oscillation between
practice and theory:26 new practices help to generate new theory, which
in turn widens the possibilities for further new practices.
25 Ustinia Dolgopol, ‘Redressing Partial Justice – A Possible Role for Civil Society’ in Ustina
Dolgopol and Judith Gardam (eds), The Challenge of Conflict: International Law Responds (Martinus
Nihjoff, 2006); Christine Chinkin, ‘Women’s International Tribunal on Japanese Military Sexual
Slavery’ (2001) 95 American Journal of International Law 335.
26 Davina Cooper, Everyday Utopias: The Conceptual Life of Promising Spaces (Duke University
Press, 2014).
20
Wittgenstein does not explicitly place law in his metaphor, but it might
be supposed that everyday knowledge about law is part of the flow, while
shared and presumed cultural knowledge is part of the riverbed – the
presupposed cultural knowledge would include the liberal and colonial
views of law as discrete, and as disconnected from social identity.
Philosopher Susan Hekman notes that philosophical theories that
differentiate between an epistemological background and everyday truths
are often extremely conservative, because they do not acknowledge that
cultural assumptions may change, and do not offer any ideas about how
to encourage such change.29 They simply rely on cultural background as
pre-given and immutable. She argues that Wittgenstein’s image holds
more potential for theorising and promoting change than most theories of
the background because it acknowledges that the riverbed may shift and
that it is not sharply divided from the everyday truths which it supports.
So how can cultural change be promoted? Cultural change does not occur
because people are presented with a logical argument as to why something
ought to be the case. It is much more incremental, and depends as much
21
on what are understood to be the criteria for truth within the cultural
background as it does on any new claim. As Hekman says, ‘feminist truth
does not make sense in the discourse of abstract masculinity’, and ‘we must
first alter the criteria of what it makes sense to say before we can proclaim
another “truth” and expect it to be heard’.30 To take a historical example,
claims for gender and racial equality could not be heard until presupposed
knowledge had shifted sufficiently for women and those of non-Caucasian
heritage to be regarded as people and equal citizens. Many cultural norms
still exist which make the resulting formal equality inadequate. Claims to
marriage equality still do not make sense to some people who see marriage
as necessarily heterosexual. There is no logic in this view but there is
a foundation – the foundation provided by a heteronormative cultural
background that still divides people into two sexes. In a quite different
sphere, it is still almost impossible for those educated within a Eurocentric
legal paradigm, with its obsessive taxonomies and entrenched distinctions,
to comprehend the relationality and connectedness of First Nations’
approaches to law. It seems almost beyond impossible for us to move past
human exceptionalism and separation to a view where people are seen as
fully part of the physical and natural world.
Hekman argues that changes in the cultural background essentially occur
by the emergence of new narratives and perspectives which decentre,
defamiliarise and eventually alter accepted knowledge.31 The trends I have
alluded to above, in relation to bringing different perspectives into doctrinal
law and understanding law itself in a more disseminated and less hierarchical
way, are themselves part of such a cultural change, as is the extensive
scholarship which challenges the accepted nature and limits of law.
One partial illustration of a contestation of the doctrine, concept and
cultural presuppositions of law is evident in the feminist judgments
projects, which have an English and Australian iteration, as well as several
others to come.32 The feminist judgments projects asked academic and
activist writers to provide an alternative feminist judgment to a case
chosen by the writer. Although all of the judgments were feminist, there
are of course many varieties of feminism, and also many ways in which
feminism can be brought to bear on particular issues. The objective in
30 Ibid. 438.
31 Ibid.
32 Rosemary Hunter, Clare McGlynn and Erika Rackley (eds), Feminist Judgments: From Theory to
Practice (Hart, 2010); Heather Douglas, Francesca Bartlett, Trish Luker and Rosemary Hunter (eds),
Australian Feminist Judgments: Righting and Rewriting Law (Hart, 2014).
22
***
In this chapter I have very artificially distinguished between the law
understood as substance, the law understood as concept, and the cultural
presuppositions which constitute the conditions for thinking and talking
about law and its concept. But of course – and as I hope will be clear
by now – these are artificial distinctions. Changing the content of law
over time may also change its shape and contours, and such changes are
also connected to shifts in cultural presuppositions. The riverbed is not
distinct from the river, and more importantly, the flow of the river is as
important as the banks and bed in influencing its overall shape and form.
23