Tamil Nadu National Law University: Course Syllabus Jurisprudence
Tamil Nadu National Law University: Course Syllabus Jurisprudence
Tamil Nadu National Law University: Course Syllabus Jurisprudence
JURISPRUDENCE
Jurisprudence is a broad philosophical discipline which both clarifies as well as evaluates key legal
concepts, values and institutions. It forms the theoretical background that justifies Law, as well
as lays down the normative standards through which law can be tested. As such, it is a part of the
central core of legal education across law schools.
In the past few years however, the study of Jurisprudence has undergone a sea of change. Earlier,
Jurisprudence was taught out of standard textbooks like Salmond and Paton and was aimed at
training law graduates to “think like a lawyer” through an exposition of legal concepts as applied
by the courts. This approach, as per the legal theorist Ronald Dworkin, “produced only the
illusion of legal progress, and left the genuinely important issues of principle in the law
untouched”. Today, Jurisprudence has evolved into a more conceptual discipline which deals
with questions such as: ‘What is Law?’ ‘What is the connection between Law and morality?’ and
‘Is capital punishment justified?’ It seeks to ensure that law students truly understand the
philosophical basis of legal systems and the role of Law in society. This course adopts this latter,
more modern approach to studying jurisprudence. Structured around six fundamental issues in
legal theory - law, rights, causation, punishment, property and promises- this course will form the
theoretical foundations on which students can build upon the rest of their legal education.
Course Objectives
To understand the definitional scope as well as the philosophical basis of key legal
concepts such as law, rights, causation, punishment, property and promises.
To understand the connections between the theory of law and its professional practice,
and to apply abstract insights to real-world problems.
To introduce students to key debates and ideological positions in legal theory; to
encourage them to evaluate and arbitrate between these positions.
To encourage students to engage with theoretical texts and write critically about
philosophical issues
Learning Outcomes
Teaching Methods
The course will run every day from Monday to Saturday for 55 minutes.Students are expected to
come to class prepared to ask questions about what they have read, to evaluate the material, and
to express their own reasoned views on controversial issues.
This introduction introduces the major trends, positions and schools of jurisprudence through a
close examination of Fuller’s classic thought experiment - the Speluncean explorers case. The
case will be used as an anchor for the course, to understand the most important problems in
legal theory and to elucidate jurisprudential concepts such as positivism, natural law, the
separation thesis and interpretation. Through it and the real case of R. v. Dudley and Stephens,
we will also illustrate the practical importance of legal theory, and the profound impact that one's
jurisprudential ideology can have on one's view of the law. At the end of this unit, we hope to
understand the point of studying jurisprudence as well as have a general indication about its
scope.
Compulsory Readings:
1. Fuller, Lon. “The Case of the Speluncean Explorers”. Harvard Law Review 62.4
(1949): 616-645.
2. Eskridge, WN. “The Case of the Speluncean Explorers: Twentieth Century
Statutory Interpretation in a Nutshell”.
3. Suber, Peter. The Case of the Speluncean Explorers: Nine New Opinions. 1st ed.
London and New York: Routledge, 1998. pp. 33-54, 62-70, 77-88.
4. R v. Dudley and Stephens ( 1884) 14 QBD 273.
5. U.S. v. Holmes. Circuit Court, E. D. Pennsylvania. 26 F.Cas. 360 (1842)
6. Williams, Glanville. "A Commentary on R. v. Dudley and Stephens." Cambrian
L. Rev. 8 (1977): 94.
Additional Readings:
Additional Readings:
Law MODULE 2
One of the most pressing issues evident from the Speluncean explorers case is the indeterminacy
of ‘Law’. What is ‘Law’ ? How do we differentiate “Law” from the orders of a thug to pay
ransom money or the prohibitions imposed on a child by a doting parent? A second issue
evident in the Fuller’s hypothetical is the problem of unjust and unfair laws. What is the
relationship between Law and Morality? Do we have a duty to obey amoral laws? Were the
persecution instruments enacted by the Nazi government “Law”? This unit deals with historical
and contemporary thought on both these issues. It also briefly introduces legal scepticism-
theories which argue that the attempt to understand the nature of law is either impossible,
illusory or incorrect.
What is Law?
Compulsory Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
1. Gale, Susan Gaylord. "A very German legal science: Savigny and the
historical school." Stan. J. Int'l L. 18 (1982): 123.
2. Robert E. Rodes, Jr., On the Historical School of Jurisprudence,
49 American Journal of Jurisprudence 165 (2004)
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
1. Pound, Roscoe. "Law in books and law in action." Am. L. Rev. 44 (1910): 12.
2. Ehrlich, Eugen, and Nathan Isaacs. "The sociology of law." Harvard Law
Review 36.2 (1922): 130-145.
3. David Nelken 'Ehrlich’s legacies: Back to the future in the sociology of law’,
in Marc Hertogh ed Living Law, Hart 2009 pp 237-272
Additional Readings:
1. Dennis Galligan, Law in Modern Society, OUP 2007 pp 6-19, 28-38 50–63.
2. Ehrlich, Eugene. Fundamental principles of the sociology of law. Transaction
Publishers, 1962.
3. Stone, Julius. "Social dimensions of law and justice." (1966).
Compulsory Readings:
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
1. Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus, and Leslie Green. The concept of law.
Oxford University Press, 2012. Chapter 5,6.
2. Dworkin, Ronald M. "The model of rules." The University of Chicago Law
Review 35.1 (1967): 14-46.
Additional Readings:
1. Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus, and Leslie Green. The concept of law.
Oxford University Press, 2012. Introduction. Postscript.
2. Shapiro, Scott J. "The ‘Hart-Dworkin’ debate: A short guide for the
perplexed." Ronald Dworkin 22 (2007): 49.
3. Dworkin, Ronald. Taking Rights Seriously. (Harvard University Press, 1978).
Chapters 2 & 3.
4. Coleman, Jules. ‘Beyond Inclusive Legal Positivism’, Ratio Juris, 22(3) 2009.
5. Dworkin, Ronald. "Hart's postscript and the character of political
philosophy." Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24.1 (2004): 1-37.
6. Dworkin, Ronald. Law’s Empire. (Belknap Press, 1986).
7. Raz, Joseph. Practical reason and norms. OUP Oxford, 1999.
8. Gardner, John. "Some types of law." (2007).
Compulsory Readings:
1. Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus, and Leslie Green. The concept of law.
Oxford University Press, 2012. Chapter 7.
2. Fuller, Lon L. "Positivism and fidelity to law: A reply to Professor Hart."
Harvard law review (1958): 630-672.
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
1. Devlin, Patrick Baron. Morals and the criminal law. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1965. (Extracts)
2. Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus, and Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart. Law,
liberty, and morality. Stanford University Press, 1963. (extracts)
3. Dworkin, Ronald. "Lord Devlin and the enforcement of morals." The Yale
Law Journal 75.6 (1966): 986-1005.
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Reading:
Additional Reading:
Legal Scepticism
Compulsory Readings:
1. Oliver W. Holmes, Jr., “The Path of the Law,” 10 Harvard Law Review
457 (1897)
2. Karl Llewellyn, “A Realistic Jurisprudence -- The Next Step,” 30
Columbia Law Review 431 (1930)
3. Alf Ross, “Tu-Tu,” 70 Harvard Law Review 812 (1957)
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
Rights MODULE 3
One of the concepts invoked by Justice Tattling in the Speluncean Explorers case is the “Right”
to life. “Rights” are often used to limit the power of the Law over an individual. For example,
one might say that the State cannot make a law asking me to be silent, since it violates my ‘Right’
to free expression. This unit explores the meaning and basis for the concept of rights. Starting
with Hohfeld’s classical exposition of the language of rights- this unit clarifies key issues in
understanding ‘Rights’ - What are Rights? What is their purpose? Are rights ‘given’ or are they
‘inherent’? How do we justify “exceptions” or “restrictions” to rights?
Additional Readings:
Compulsory Readings:
1. Kramer, M., Simmonds, N., and Steiner, H., 1998, A Debate Over Rights,
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Introduction. “The Modern Will Theory”,
“The Interest Theory of Rights”.
Additional Readings:
1. Kramer, M., and Steiner, H. 2007, “Theories of Rights: Is There a Third Way?”,
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 27: 281–310.
2. Van Duffel, S., 2012, “In Defense of the Will Theory of Rights”, Res Publica, 18:
231–31.
3. MacCormick, N., 1977, “Rights in Legislation”, in Hacker, P., and Raz, J. (eds.),
Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Honour of H.L.A Hart, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1977, pp. 189–209.
Nature of Rights
Compulsory Readings:
1. Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom, Ch: 7 The Nature of Rights, (also
published in Mind, 1984).
2. Waldron, J., (ed.), 1984, Theories of Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Introduction.
3. Wenar, Leif (2005). “The Nature of Rights”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33:
223–252.
Additional Readings:
1. Hart, Herbert LA. "Are there any natural rights?." The Philosophical Review
64.2 (1955): 175-191.
2. Dworkin, Ronald M. (1981). “Is there a Right to Pornography?”, Oxford Journal
of Legal Studies, 1: 177–213
3. Wellman, Carl (1985). A Theory of Rights, Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.
4. Steiner, Hillel. "An essay on rights." (1994).
5. Singer, Joseph William. "The legal rights debate in analytical jurisprudence from
Bentham to Hohfeld." Wis. L. Rev. (1982): 975.
This unit deals with two issues which are central to the Speluncean Explorers case. Firstly, we
look at whether the explorers caused and were responsible for Whetmore’s death? We look at what
does it really mean to cause, and be responsible for a crime. Are insane individuals responsible for
their actions? Are children? Does failure to prevent a crime, cause a crime? In the second part,
we explore the question: if the explorers were responsible, should they be punished? Why should
there be punishment for a crime? How much punishment should be given for a particular crime?
Compulsory Readings:
1. Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus, and Tony Honoré. Causation in the Law. OUP
Oxford, 1985. Introduction. Conclusion.
2. Foucault, Michel, Alain Baudot, and Jane Couchman. "About the concept of the
“dangerous individual” in 19th-century legal psychiatry." International journal of
law and psychiatry 1.1 (1978): 1-18.
3. Fine, Cordelia, and Jeanette Kennett. "Mental impairment, moral understanding
and criminal responsibility: Psychopathy and the purposes of punishment."
International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 27.5 (2004): 425-443.
Additional Readings:
Additional Readings:
1. Ehrlich, Isaac. "Crime, punishment, and the market for offenses." The Journal
of Economic Perspectives 10.1 (1996): 43-67.
2. David Dolinko, “Retributivism, Consequentialism, and the Intrinsic Goodness
of Punishment,” Law and Philosophy. Vol. 16 (1997), pp. 507-528
3. Becker, Gary S. "Crime and punishment: An economic approach." The
economic dimensions of crime. Palgrave Macmillan UK, 1968. 13-68.
4. Menninger, Karl. "The crime of punishment." (1968).
5. Ehrlich, Isaac. "The deterrent effect of capital punishment: A question of life
and death." (1973).
6. Michael S. Moore, “Justifying Retributivism,” Israel Law Review, Vol. 27 (1993)
pp. 15-49
Property
Compulsory Readings:
Additional Readings:
1. Penner, James E. The idea of property in law. Oxford University Press, 1997.
Introduction. Chapter 4,10.
2. Merrill, Thomas W., and Henry E. Smith. "What happened to property in law
and economics?." The Yale Law Journal 111.2 (2001): 357-398.
3. Hart, Oliver, and John Moore. "Property Rights and the Nature of the Firm."
Journal of political economy 98.6 (1990): 1119-1158.
4. Waldron, Jeremy. "The right to private property." (1990).
5. Hughes, Justin. "The philosophy of intellectual property." Geo. LJ77 (1988):
287.
6. Murphy, Roberts & Flessas, Understanding Property Law, (Sweet & Maxwell
2004), excerpts
7. Demsetz, Harold. "Toward a theory of property rights."
8. Waldron, Jeremy. "Property, Justification and Need." Canadian Journal of Law
& Jurisprudence 6.2 (1993): 185-215.
Compulsory Readings:
Additional Readings:
1. Jones, D. H., 1966, “Making and Keeping Promises”, Ethics, 76: 287–296.
2. Raz Joseph, 2012, “Is there a Reason to Keep Promises”, No. 12-320, Research
Paper Series, Columbia University Public Law & Legal Theory, Columbia Law
School.
3. Zvi H. Triger, For the Love of Contract, 51 Tulsa L. Rev. 407 (2015)
4. Habib, Allen. "Promises." (2008).
5. Gregory Klass, George Letsas, Prince Saprai, Philosophical foundations of
Contract Law (OUP 2014), excerpts
6. Owens, David, 2006, “A Simple Theory of Promising”, Philosophical Review,
115(1): 51–77.
*****