DefiningEnd Theoria
DefiningEnd Theoria
DefiningEnd Theoria
Abstract
In this paper I present a new definition of endurance. I argue that the three-
definitions of endurance and perdurance in that the theories of three- and four-
though both definitions are expressed within the same broad language, some of
the terms of that language have subtly different meanings within the context of
underlying theoretical similarities, and yet also that there are some subtle
differences in the way each theory understands some of the terms of mereology,
that allows us to see clearly what lies at the heart of the debate between these
1 Introduction
For some time now, there have been two main competitors when it comes to
is the thesis that persisting objects have only spatial dimensions. Thus since our
world is a world in which there are three spatial dimensions, in our world
* With many thanks to David Braddon-Mitchell and Mark Colyvan for helpful discussion of
these issues.
2
hand, is the view that persisting objects have both spatial dimensions and a
temporal dimension. Since our world is a world with three spatial dimensions
and one temporal dimension, this is the view that persisting objects are four-
The three-dimensionalist holds that all objects are wholly present whenever
they exist, and persisting objects, which exist at more than one time, are wholly
dimensionalism holds that objects persist through time by being only partly
present at each moment at which they exist, that is, by having a temporal part
present at each time at which they exist. Thus objects persist by perduring,
While three-dimensionalism has been considered the standard view, and four-
dimensionalism the new kid on the block, of late some serious allegations have
has argued that the only plausible way to define endurance entails that
presentism is true. That is, it entails that the only ontologically real time is the
present. And Theodore Sider3 holds that there is no coherent way to define
endurance such that the definition will hold for composite objects. These are
1 Of course, there is a further issue as to whether our ordinary linguistic terms refer to these
perduring objects, which is the standard view, or whether our terms refer only to temporal
parts, and claims about the past and future are made true in virtue of the existence of the
relevant temporal counterparts. On the latter view, while it is true that objects perdure, it is not
true that the everyday objects of our ontology persist by perduring. Rather, they persist by
having the relevant temporal counterparts. This view is defended by Sider, T. (2001). Four-
dimensionalism: an ontology of persistence and time. Oxford University Press. Nothing in this paper
hangs on this distinction.
2 Merricks, T. (1999). “Persistence, Parts and Presentism.” Nous 33(3): 421-438.
3 Sider, T. (2001). chp 3.
3
the debate between the three and four-dimensionalist cannot even get off the
between these two views, that many four-dimensionalists believe that this is the
case. While a lively and profitable exchange between these two views existed
this would be cold comfort given that Merricks’ definition commits the three-
and argue that this definition does not face any of the problems considered.
2 Definition Difficulties
be wholly present, all of them existing at every time at which they exist, and to
be strictly identical at each of those times.4 This suggests that we could define
ID: An object O endures through interval T iff for any two times t and t’
perdurance. We can see how this is supposed to work with ID. The perdurantist
holds that at each time at which a persisting object O exists, it is a distinct part
of O that exists at that time. Thus if O persists through T, and t1 and t2 are
instants in T, then O-at-t1 is a distinct object from O-at-t2: each of these objects
are distinct temporal parts of O. Thus if O perdures it does not meet the
definition ID.
4 Cf.
Wiggins, D. (1968). "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time." Philosophical Review 77:
90-95; Baker, L. R. (1997). "Why Constitution is not Identity.” Journal of Philosophy 94: 599-621;
Johnston, M. (1992). "Constitution Is Not Identity.” Mind 101: 89-105.
5 Merricks, T. (1995). “On the Incompatibility of Enduring and Perduring Entities.” Mind 104:
523-41.
5
The problem with ID though, is that it can be read in a way that is compatible
with perdurantism. For the perdurantist holds that “O” refers to the entire four-
dimensional object, and not the temporal part O-at-t1. The four-dimensional
identical to itself at those times. Thus understood in this sense, it is true that O
The problem here, points out Merricks6 is that to say that an object has only
spatial extension is to say that while not all of an object’s parts exist at one point
in space, all of its parts do exist at one time. Thus it seems that to say that an
object is not temporally extended is to say that all of that object exists at a time,
and that seems to be no more than to say that it is wholly present at every time
define what it is to exist at a time, and what it is to exist at a time for the three-
exists.
We then have the notion of “wholly present” left undefined. Ned Markosian7
WP: An object x is wholly present at t just in case (a) x exists at t and (b) it is
not the case that there is a y such that y is a temporal part of x at some
x exists at, but only at t. (3) x overlaps every part of y that exists at t.9
(b) it is not the case that there is a y such that y is a temporal part of x at
The difficulty with this definition is that endurance is defined in terms of the
negation of perdurantism. This is problematic for two reasons. The first is that
some endurantists hold that the very notion of a temporal part is incoherent, 10
or that although in some very abstract sense they understand the notion of a
temporal part, they can make no sense of the idea that objects are composed of
7 Markosian, N. (1994). “The 3D/4D Controvery and Non-Present Objects.” Philosphical Papers
23: 243-49.
8 The definition is framed in terms of an instantaneous temporal part t, but it can easily be re-
stated to include extended temporal parts. In Zimmerman, D. (1996). “Persistence and
Presentism.” Philosophical Papers 25: 115-126, Zimmerman suggests the following, beginning
with a definition of an extended temporal part where T and T* range over intervals and t and t*
over instants.
x is a temporal part of y throughout T = df (i) x exists during and only during T; (ii) for every
subinterval T* of T, there is a z such that (a) z is part of x, and (b) for all u, u has a part in
common with z during T* iff u has a part in common with y during T*; and (iii) y exists at
times outside of T.
Then we would define wholly present as:
x is wholly present at t=df (i) x exists at t; and (ii) it is not the case that there is a y such that
either (a) for some t* such that t ≠ t*, y is a temporal part of x at t* or (b) for some T which does
not include t, y is a temporal part of x during T.
9 Sider, T. op cit pg 60.
10 Cf. Thomson, J.J. (1983). "Parthood and Identity Across Time." Journal of Philosophy 80: 201-
220.
7
temporal parts.11 One who holds either of these views, justly or not, clearly
would not want to define endurance in terms of the absence of temporal parts.
to be the more intuitive, “folk friendly” view, and a view that significantly pre-
terms of the negation of perdurance, then this significantly undercuts the idea
that there was any clear, coherent view about persistence prior to a perdurantist
account being constructed. If it turned out, for instance, that the only way we
not the case that the theory of special relativity is true, then this would be good
grounds to conclude that there was no clear understanding of absolute
simultaneity prior to the formulation of relativity theory. The point is that prior
temporal part, and thus if there was some conception about the way objects
persist, it clearly could not have been in terms of the absence of temporal parts.
conception, and so perhaps it will turn out that it is not possible to define
endurance in a way that does not refer to the posits of perdurantism. This
would certainly not imply that three-dimensionalism is not the more intuitive
view, or that it is in some way inferior to perdurantism. Still, I think that all
things considered it would be better if the endurantist could state her thesis in a
way that does not involve the mention of temporal parts. In that case we can, at
11 Van Inwagen, P. (2000). “Temporal Parts and Identity Across Time.” The Monist 83(3) 437-459.
van Inwagen writes: “Since I understand all the worlds, I understand ‘Lewis-part”andknow
what Lewis-parts are. In a way. In the same way as the way in which I should understand talk
of “propertyless objects” if I were told that “propertyless object” meant “object of which
nothing is true.”...But I should hardly care to say that I know what someone was talking
about...who talked of them in a way that suggested that he supposed there were such things.” p
445.
8
The idea that an object lacks temporal extension if not all of its parts exist at one
point in space, but all of its parts do exist at one time, suggests another way to
define the notion of wholly present. For the idea of being wholly present is the
idea that all of an object is present. Implicitly then, the notion of wholly present
invokes the notion of parthood: for surely if all of an object is present, then all of
its parts must be present. This suggests the following definition of ‘wholly
present’:
WP1: An object x is wholly present at a time just in case all of its parts are
Both Sider and Merricks consider this definition of ‘wholly present’. Sider
rejects the definition on the grounds that it fails for any object that loses or gains
parts over the course of its existence. Given what we know about microphysics,
it follows that no composite object would ever be wholly present, and thus
would not endure. Merricks draws the somewhat different conclusion that this
is true, then all of an object’s parts are present at every time at which it exists: it
only exists in the present, and in the present, all of its parts are present. We
have already noted, however, that it would be best for the three-dimensionalist
faced, then, with the prospect of being unable to define endurance either in
3 Siderian Suggestions
Sider considers another way to define wholly present, suggesting the following:
9
We can see that this definition of strongly wholly present bears a striking
wholly present at all times in its life just in case at all times at which x exists, it
has all and only the same parts at each of those times. Thus if we were to define
endurance as follows:
which it exists.
it will again turn out that the only objects that endure are objects that either
have no spatial parts, (simples) or which neither gain nor lose spatial parts
hold the view that only simples endure, this leads Sider to suggest E2:
E2. An object x endures iff it is possible that x is strongly wholly present for
suppose t and t* are temporal instants within T. Now suppose that at t there is
temporal instant. Then there is some part of x that exists in T and which is not
Still, E2 is not inconsistent with the idea that objects perdure, but have no
longer than an instant, it may not be a great deal longer! So it could still be that
persisting objects are the fusions of extended temporal parts, and thus are not
wholly present whenever they exist. But the three-dimensionalist does not just
want to rule out the existence of instantaneous temporal parts, she wants to
show that objects are in fact wholly present at every moment at which they
exist. Thus E2 is too weak.
z.
11
One criticism the endurantist might level against E3 is that it is too weak. Many
endurantists hold that mereological universalism, is false.14 They hold that there
is no object composed of Lincoln and my dog. Call this putative object Log. It
might be argued that the intuition behind the notion of “wholly present” is one
that would rule out the existence of Log. For there is a long period of time after
Lincoln dies, and before my dog is born, during which no parts of Log exist. So
how can we think that Log is wholly present? There are those endurantists who
will think that any definition of endurance that allows that Log endures, is in
some fundamental way failing to capture the intuition that drives three-
dimensionalism.
E3, however, allows that Log can endure. For although Lincoln and my dog do
not exist at the same time, it is possible that they exist throughout the same time
interval, and that throughout that interval they are mereologically constant.
Thus there is some x such that it is possible that everything that is at any time in
T part of Log, exists and is part of Log at every time in T. Hence Log endures.
Those endurantists for whom the mere thought of Log brings on a severe case
of hives, may argue that if E3 allows that Log endures, this is sufficient reason
present for some interval of time T, and there is actually some proper part
According to this definition then, an object endures only if it is possible that all
of its parts exist throughout T, and if at least one of its parts is actually part of
14 Cf.Wiggins, D. (1980). Sameness and Substance. Oxford: Blackwell Press. and Van Inwagen, P.
(1987). “When are Objects Parts?” Philosophical Perspectives 1. Metaphysics: 21-47.
12
that object throughout T. This would rule out cases such as Log as enduring.
For there will be no part of Log, that is part of Log at all times at which Log
The endurantist, however, might think that this definition is too restrictive,
since she might hold that there could be objects that persist over a sufficiently
long period of time that none of the parts of the object at the beginning of its life
are parts of it at the end of its life. Thus E4 would seem to result in the
out that what determines whether an object persists, is whether or not it has
some particular part at each time it exists. Thus if it is true that in the space of
seven years all of the atoms that compose me have been completely replaced,
then by this definition I endure, and thus persist, only for seven years, and then
I cease to exist. Even more oddly, I might persist for the time I do in virtue of
having one particular atom A as a part: when that atom ceases to be part of me
after seven years, I suddenly cease to exist. Surely though, in general we do not
want to say that an object ceases to exist because it loses some small part.
present for some interval of time T and there are actually no temporally
contiguous pairs of intervals I and I- that occur in L, such that none of the
According to this definition, all that is required for an object to endure is that
contiguous intervals, there is some part that overlaps both intervals. This
15 Two partsoverlap just in case there is some sub-part that is a part of each.
16This bears some similarity to physical continuity theories in for example personal identity
where identity across time is analysed as bearing the ancestral of the sharing a part relation.
13
proposal too rules out punctuate objects such as Log, since in such cases there
overlaps both intervals: all those intervals during which no parts of the object
exist.
It might be argued that the advantage of E5 is that it more truly captures the
universalism might be false. Perhaps Log does not exist. Whether universalism
answer to the question “what objects exist”? The thesis of endurance, however,
is a thesis about how objects persist, not which objects exist. Many three-
the idea that objects are wholly present whenever they exist.17 We ought not,
as to rule out certain objects as enduring. For this will either rule out the
some accept, or it will force those who accept universalism to concede that at
least some objects persist but not endure. Those who believe in Log, for
instance, but hold that objects persist by being wholly present, would either
have to reject E5, or conclude that Log persists by perduring, though some
other objects persist by enduring. I submit, then, that we should not at this
which objects exist, and should thus define endurance in a broad way.
With this criticism rejected then, it seems that we might be able to accept E3 as a
(and thus of course E3) seems to fail to capture the endurantist intuitions
implicit in the notion of “wholly present.” For it turns out that objects endure in
virtue of it being possible that they persist through time in a particular way,
rather than in virtue of how they actually persist. The endurantist, after all,
began by claiming that objects persist by being wholly present whenever they
exist. But almost all of the objects of our day to day ontology fail to be actually
accepts E3, she ought more properly to say that objects endure by having the
But this seems to tell us little about the way objects actually persist, other than
that it is possible that objects have identity of parts over time. For in a world
part of O at t’. This, of course, is precisely what perdurantism rules out. Still,
here we have a conceptual claim about what is possible, not about what is
actual. Indeed, matters are a little more dire than Sider acknowledges. Given
E3, it will be true that O endures in world w just in case there is some world z
then O does not perdure in z. This means that O endures in the actual world
just in case there is some possible world z in which O does not perdure. So it
looks like endurantism is true in the actual world just in case perdurance is not
necessarily true.
Of course, this is not quite right. It could be that there is some world w in which
objects are strongly wholly present, and yet none of the objects in w might have
counterparts of, or be trans-world identical to, any actual objects. Then it would
not follow from the existence of w, that the actual world is an enduring world.
If we think though, that for any actual object O there does exist some strongly
actual world just in case perdurance is not necessarily true. This would be
series of distinct temporal parts. For the fact that O’s counterpart is strongly
We might think though, that there is really no problem here. For just as we
might reject the sort of flexible counterpart relation that allows that there is a
reject the claim that any actual perduring object could have a strongly wholly
present counterpart. Though prima facie there might be reasons to suppose that
And perhaps there are reasons to embrace something like this claim. E3
requires that some actual object O endures only if there is some counterpart of
its existence. It is not at all clear though, that it is even logically possible that
actual objects have counterparts that are mereologically constant: for perhaps it
is an essential property of some or all actual composite objects that they change
16
over time. In that case there is reason to suppose that no actual composite object
I think these considerations add a good deal of weight to rejecting E3. For
unclear why she should be committed to the idea that it is possible that
any actual object have a strongly wholly present counterpart, then it is certainly
impossible that any actual perduring object has a strongly wholly present
counterpart. Thus our earlier problem evaporates. However, since it will turn
out to be impossible that any actual object endures, E3 will certainly be
E2 fares better on this score. For E2 requires only that some actual object O
some interval of time T. Since interval T could be of very short duration, it is not
obvious that any actual object O should fail to have a counterpart that is
strongly wholly present through some interval T. Suppose that in the actual
world some person P perdures. Then suppose that there is a world w1 in which
there exists an object that is almost an intrinsic duplicate of P, call it P1, except
that are strongly wholly present through some interval T, however, we are
brought back to our original problem that an actual object O can endure solely
definition of endurance.
4 A New Definition
when uttered at any temporal location. Even at time t when spatial part P is not
part of O simpliciter just if it is timelessly true that P is part of O. But the three-
false relative to the temporal location at which it is uttered.19 So why should the
just if it is timelessly true? After all, the endurantist does not believe that there
exist any four-dimensional objects that are composed of non-present parts. She
19 Though of course it will be timelessly true that “P is part of O at t”, even though it is not
timelessly true that P is part of O.
18
holds that P is part of O at any time t just in case P exists at t, and P is part of O
at t.
We could say then, that ‘P is part of O simpliciter’ is true at any time t just in
case P exists at t, and P is part of O at t. This would capture the idea that for the
endurantist, all of an object’s parts are present at each time at which it exists,
without ruling out the possibility of objects changing parts over time. This
very same proposition ‘P is part of O simpliciter’ would at one time be true, and
propositions without also embracing the A theory of time. If so well and good,
for the endurantist might not wish to be committed to that particular piece of
the very same object O can be both wholly red and wholly blue: there is no
contradiction so long as O is red at one time, and blue at another. The magic is
“all in the tense”. It is difficult to see though, how appeal to tensed propositions
So let us put aside the panacea of tensed truth and consider how the analogous
20 A defender of this view includes Van Inwagen, P. (1990). “Four-Dimensional Objects.” Nous
24: 245-255.
21 Defenders of which include Haslanger, S. (1989). “Endurance and Temporary Intrinsics.”
Analysis 49: 119-125; Johnston, M. (1987). “Is There a Problem about Persistence?” The
Aristotelian Society Supp 61: 107-135. pp 113-115; Lowe, E.J. (1988). “The Problems of Intrinsic
Change: Rejoinder to Lewis.” Analysis 48: 72-77.
19
the having of those properties such that an object is red-at-t1 or red t1ly.
Although perhaps it turns out that red is not intrinsic22 on this account,
endurantists still typically seem to think that such properties are good
deservers of the everyday notion of being red. That is, they think that everyday
statements of the ‘O is red’ kind are rightly analysed in terms of O being red-at-
tn or red tnly for some appropriate n.
for an object to count as being red at that time in the usual sense in which we
having red t1ly at every time at which it exists, including times at which O is not
red.23 For clarity, consider the adverbialist account more closely. Suppose that
at t1 O is red, at t2 O is red, and at t3 O is blue. At t1, O has the property of being
red t1ly; it also has the property of being red t2ly and blue t3ly. The advantage
enduring object can instantiate the very same property at different times, but
simply in a different manner. The red instantiated at t1 is supposed to be the
manner at t2. But notice that the manner in which blue is instantiated at t1 is
exactly the same manner in which it is instantiated at t3: namely the t3ly
manner. So if O is blue just in case O instantiates blue in a tnly manner, then O
What the adverbialist needs to say is that there are a range of “metaphysically
basic” properties which are the temporally relativised properties of being, for
22 Atleast according to Lewis and other advocates or perdurantism. See Lewis, D (1986). On The
Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell pg. 204.
23 Unless you believe in ineliminably tensed propositions.
20
instance, red-at-t or red tly. At every time at which an enduring object exists, it
instantiates all of the relativised properties that it will ever instantiate: this is
what makes it true that enduring objects are strictly identical over time. But is
not sufficient for an object to count in the everyday sense as being blue at some
time, that it exemplifies blueness in some manner at that time. Rather, everyday
manner at a time other than t, and the everyday sense of having a property in a
tly manner at t, let us call this latter having a property simpliciter. Having the
property of blue t3ly at t3 is having the property of being blue simpliciter. Of
course, this is not a usual use of the term ‘simpliciter’, since the property of being
t3, though, the everyday claim ‘O is blue’ is true in an unqualified way, though
instantiated at t3. That is, the ordinary English sense of having a property is
property that is qualified. So let us say that ‘O is blue simpliciter’ is true at some
time t just if at t, O is blue in a tly manner. Then the difference between being
blue and being blue simpliciter marks the difference between being merely blue
But wait. If O is blue simpliciter at t3 and O is not blue simpliciter at t1, then it
simpliciter’ not as a proposition in the narrow sense, but rather, that as picking
proposition of being red t1ly at t1. If O is red simpliciter at t2, then ‘red
simpliciter’ picks out the proposition of being red t2ly at t2. For any property P,
being red simpliciter names a relation between a time and having the property
of being red in a particular temporal way. Thus the property of being red
simpliciter is a different property at t1 than it is at t2. Thus there is no
contradiction in saying that the very same object O is red simpliciter at t1 and is
not red simpliciter at t3. For it is not that there is some one property of being red
simpliciter that O has at t1 but lacks at t3. Rather, we can see ‘red simpliciter’ as
The question then is why is it that instantiating red t1ly at t1 and instantiating
red t2ly at t2 both deserve to be called instantiating ‘red simpliciter’? For it might
example. If this is so, then why think that there is anything in semantically in
common between the propositions picked out by ‘red simpliciter’? One way to
we might think of as being the “Kripke intension”. If water in the actual world
24 Frank Jackson uses the terminology of an A intension, while David Chalmers uses the
terminology of a primary intension. For more on two dimensional semantics see Jackson, F.
(2004). “Why we need A-intensions.” forthcoming in Philosophical Studies; Braddon-Mitchell, D.
(2004). “Mastering Meaning” forthcoming in Philosophical Studies;; Chalmers, D. (2004). “The
Foundations of Two Dimensional Semantics” forthcoming in Philosophical Studies;.
22
is H20, then considered counterfactually ‘water’ picks out all and only H20 in all
other worlds. On the A intension we consider what terms pick out in worlds
considered as actual. If the actual world is one in which a clear potable liquid of
somewhat different chemical composition than H20 exists, then ‘water’ refers to
statements such as ‘is red simpliciter’ at different times rather than different
out different redness properties at different times. But in both cases there exists
as we began with the idea that there is, for the endurantist, some
that does not capture our everyday sense of having a property, so too we can
modified way that does not capture our everyday sense of having a part. For
suppose that there is some object O that is at t1 composed of A and B, and at t2
composed of A and C. Then we can say that at t1 O has part A and B t1ly, and
has part A and C t2ly. So there is some technical sense in which O has part C at
t1. But this sense clearly does not conform to the everyday sense of having a
part or to the sense in which the endurantist affirms that objects are not
tly manner, so too we want to say that the everyday sense of having a part is
these two senses we can say that the everyday sense will be known as having a
true at any time t iff at t, P is part of O tly. This allows us to define endurance as
follows:
E*: An object endures iff it exists at distinct times, and is wholly present at
tly.
This definition captures the core endurantist intuition that in some sense all of
an enduring object’s parts are present whenever it exists. So our object O at t2
has parts A and C simpliciter but does not have part B simpliciter. That is, in the
everyday sense of ‘part’ B is not part of O at t2. So O is not a four-dimensional
object. For at t2, it has no parts that exist at times other than t2.
Once again of course, we are faced with the difficulty that at t1 B is part of O
simpliciter and at t2 B is not part of O simpliciter. So it looks as though O has the
property of having a certain part at one time, and the property of lacking that
part at another time. And once again the analogous solution presents itself. Just
different property than having that part simpliciter at some other time. The
once again, there is no one property of having some part simpliciter that is
In what sense then, is this definition an indexicalist one? That is, what does it
I see it, this is a perfectly acceptable thing to say. It might be objected that in this
object which exists at t. But this is not so. Three- and four-dimensionalists alike
in supposing that O can exist at multiple times, including t, and then define
It is, however, not necessary to think of the definition in this way. When we ask
ourselves what is at t, the answer we can give is that it is the utterance ‘P is part
some other time, it may be true or false, and in either case, it will be true or false
about whether utterances are wholly present or partly whenever at their time of
definition tells us that at different times, the same utterance is made true by the
So E* captures the endurantist intuition that objects have all of their parts at a
time, without committing them to the view that objects are unable to lose any
parts, or to the view that presentism is true. For we can say that all of an object’s
parts simpliciter are present at t, and that the object is strictly identical with itself
over time without being compelled to say that the object exists only at t, or that
only spatial extension. The difficulty with that proposal is that to have no
temporal extension is to have all of one’s parts at the same time, but not at the
same place, and thus ultimately we were returned to the problem of defining
endures iff it has only spatial extension. For E* tells us that all of an object’s
parts simpliciter are had at a single time. Any parts that were parts of an object
at a previous time, or will be parts of an object at a future time, are not parts of
that object simpliciter. This tells us that the object has no temporal extension, for
The most significant benefits of E*, however, are that it does not commit the
endurantist to any questionable metaphysical views, nor to any views about the
scope of the endurantist claim. It does not entail that propositions are tensed,
nor does it entail the truth of presentism, nor that composition is restricted in
presentist, of course, it will be trivially true that all of an object’s parts simpliciter
are present whenever it exists, since those are the only parts that exist. Thus for
the presentist, the only properties or parts that an object has at t are the tly
objects exist?” nor the question “what temporal locations exist?”. E* does not
rule out the existence of temporally scattered objects, since it may still be true of
such objects that all of their parts simpliciter exist at each time at which they
exists. For instance, if we consider again Log, we can say that at t, all of Log’s
parts include a human body and at t’, all of Log’s parts include a canine body.
that all actual objects endure, or, more likely, that all nomologically possible
and actual objects endure, or even that all actual and possible objects endure. E*
tells us is that if this is a world where objects endure, then it is a world in which
might think that this is not very illuminating, and that we have learned nothing
new about endurance in formulating E*. I think there is both something true
27
and something false about this claim. On the one hand, it is true that an
adoption of E* does not alter the way in which the endurantist will approach
times. Indeed, most of what endurantists say will remain unchanged in the face
of this definition. In this sense then, it tells us nothing new. I do not see that this
is a wholly bad thing. For we should not expect a definition, even one that is
good one to the extent that it captures the relevant intuitions, is coherent, and
illuminates the way in which the position that it defines, is related to opposing
solve all of the problems at hand. That much of what the endurantist says will
remain unchanged, is evidence of the fact that the definition preserves the core
Furthermore, there is a clear sense, in which this definition sheds light on the
about how objects do persist in the actual world, not just how they might
persist in some possible world. It does not just tell us that actual objects are
such that it is possible that they have no temporal parts, rather, it tells us that
they do not have temporal parts. Although E* does not refer to temporal parts,
it does define endurance in terms of parthood, which not only captures the
endurantist intuition that objects are wholly present whenever they exist, but
parts. For it turns out that both endurantism and perdurantism are defined in
terms of the parthood relation. This allows considerable clarification of the
28
relation between these two views. Indeed, we can see that E* entails, and is
E#: An object endures iff it exists at distinct times and is wholly present at
iff (a) it exists at t and (b) it is not the case that there is a y such that y is a
too, E* entails E#. For if at t, O has no parts simpliciter that exist and are part of
O at times other than t, then it follows that O has no temporal parts.
It is a plausible feature of E* that it entails E#. For while it would be less than
with one another without the risk that the use of different terminologies results
allows us to see that the core of the debate lies in the different understanding by
each, of what it is to have a part simpliciter. It thus allows those who wish to say
that the views present radically different metaphysics, to explain why this is so,
and it provides the grounds for those who wish to claim that they are
6 Conclusion
more straightforward and illuminating. Debate between the two views becomes
possible once there is the common ground of a pair of definitions that each side
understands.
References
599-621.
Studies;
30
125.
Studies .
Thomson, J.J. (1983). "Parthood and Identity Across Time." Journal of Philosophy
80: 201-220.
Metaphysics: 21-47.
Wiggins, D. (1968). "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time." Philosophical
115-126