(David Ingram) First Language Acquisition Method
(David Ingram) First Language Acquisition Method
(David Ingram) First Language Acquisition Method
*c;
David Ingram
Department of Linguistics
The University of British Columbia
CE
For my mother,
Mary Strailman
Contents
Preface Page ix
1 Introduction 1
Further reading 4
PART I FOUNDATIONS 5
The history of child language studies 7
2.1 The period of diary studies (18761926) 7
2.2 The period of large sample studies (1926-1957) 11
2.3 The period of longitudinal language sampling (1957 to
present) 21
Further reading 30
Stages of language acquisition 32
3.1 Some possible meanings of ‘stage’ 32
3.2 Some proposals on stages of acquisition 38
3.3 Descriptive vs. explanatory stage 54
Further reading 57
Explanation and language acquisition 59
4.1 Introduction 59
4.2 Child Language vs. Language Acquisition 60
4.3 A theory of acquisition 63
4.4 Theoretical assumptions about language acquisition 69
4.5 Sources of variation among children 77
Further reading 80
PART I1 MILESTONES 81
5 The period of prelinguistic development 83
5.1 Introduction 83
5.2 Infant speech perception 84
5.3 Infant speech production 96
vii
viii CONTENTS
5.4 Early cognitive development 115
5.5 The linguistic environment 127
Further reading 137
6 The period of single-word utterances 139
6.1 The definition of word acquisition 139
6.2 Early word comprehension and production 140
6.3 The explanation of early word meaning 155
6.4 Pragmatic and grammatical development 160
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 178
6.6 The linguistic environment 219
Further reading 231
7 The period of the first word combinations 234
7.1 Defining the period of the first word combinations 234
7.2 Grammatical development: an overview 236
7.3 The grammatical analysis of early word combinations 261
7.4 Current theoretical approaches 302
7.5 The methodology of grammatical analyses of children 332
Further reading 337
8 The period of simple sentences: phonological and semantic
acquisition 340
8.1 Introduction 340
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 341
8.3 The further development of word meaning 394
Further reading 432
9 The period of simple sentences: acquisition of grammatical
morphemes 435
9.1 Introduction 435
9.2 Morphological acquisition in English: a descriptive overview 439
9.3 The acquisition of Aux in English questions 454
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 465
9.5 Cross-linguistic morphological acquisition 493
9.6 The explanation of morphological acquisition 499
9.7 Linguistic input and grammatical acquisition 506
Further reading 513
10 Concluding remarks 516
Bibliography 519
Further reading
There have been several introductory texts on the study of language
acquisition of children. The two most used ones appear to be Dale (1976)
Language development: structure and function, and de Villiers & de Villiers
(1978) Language acquisition. A recent book of chapters contributed by
different authors is Language acquisition, edited by Fletcher and Garman
(1979’2nd edn 1986). Still another recent book, Oksaar (1983) Language
acquisition in the early years, has been translated into English from the
original German of 1977. A recent text from a Piagetian perspective is
Language development from birth to three by Anisfeld (1984). Earlier
efforts at a text include McNeill (1970a), Menyuk (1971), Cazden (1972),
and Bloom & Lahey (1978). There is also a highly readable introduction
contained in Clark & Clark (1977).
Part I
Foundations
2 The history of child language studies
The field of child language acquisition is one that has gone through several
changes over the years in both the methods and the theoretical orientation
used. It is my belief that an understanding of the field requires an initial
exposure to its history. My impression is that the field has lost this
perspective and that many investigators are unaware of its rich literature.
This chapter, then, is designed to provide a historical overview that will
discuss the evolution of current methods, descriptive findings, and theoreti-
cal perspectives. It will proceed by discussing three major periods of child
language studies. These periods are identified by the dominant method in
each. They are:
1. The period of diary studies (1876-1926)
2. The period of large sample studies (1926-1957)
3. The period of longitudinal studies (1957-present)
For each period we will look at the major studies, the methodological
approach, the most general findings, and the theoretical orientation.
While there was this view of the child, little effort went toward specifying
the actual principles used by the child to construct a language system.
While the dominant method of this period was the parental diary, this
does not mean that diary studies ended with 1926. Rather, other methods
came along and joined the diary approach. There have been numerous
diary studies conducted since 1926, and the best ones in English have
appeared since then. Clearly, the most cited is the four-volume work by
Leopold (1939-49) on his daughter Hildegard from birth to age 2 years.
While Hildegard acquired both English and German, most discussion has
centered on Hildegard’s acquisition of English. Perhaps the next most
detailed book is that of Lewis (1936, 2nd edn 1951) who reported on the
early language of a boy referred to as ‘K’. Both these books are full of
detailed observations. The most recent major diary is probably that of
Smith (1973) on his son A’s phonological development. The most novel
diary is that of Weir (1962), who tape-recorded the presleep monologues of
her son Anthony from 2;2 to 2;4. Rich diary studies exist for other languages
as well, e.g. French (GrCgoire 1937, 1947), Russian (Gvozdev 1949), and
Polish (Zarqbina 1965).
The studies that are reported on later in the book will sometimes show all
these uses of diary data.
In any research project, the first step is an in-depth review of the
literature. In acquisition, we have one additional step, the careful evalu-
ation of available diaries for relevant data. One of the skills needed for the
study of language acquisition, then, is the ability to extract data from diary
studies. To do it requires careful reading and evaluation of the diaries
relevant to one’s interest. For example, we need to assess the parent
observer’s qualifications to observe certain aspects of language. It is difficult
to get reliable phonological data, for instance, from a diarist with no
phonetic skills; and the semantic study of early word meaning is of dubious
value when we are only given word lists, with little mention of errors of
usage. We are constantly rejecting or overlooking certain aspects in search
of those points of importance.
There is no doubt that the difficulty of pulling out relevant data from a
2.2 The period of large sample studies (1926-1957) 11
Table 2.1 A summary of Axel Preyer’s language at 1;5, taken from
Table VI in Ingram (1978), itselfa summary of Preyer (1889).
Production: only two words since 1;l; ‘atta’ which meant ‘going’ and ‘heiss’ (hot).
Comprehension: (a) since 1;1, responds correctly to: ‘where is papa? Mama?’
(b) consistently understands the following words: ‘clock, ear, shoe, chair,
shoulder, foot, forehead, chin, nose, blow, beard, hair, hat, meat, eye, arm,
hand, cheek, head, mouth, table, light, cupboard, flower’.
(c) obeys the following verbs: ‘run, kick, lie down, cough, blow, bring, give,
come, kiss’.
diary has led to either total avoidance of the approach or emphasis on just
one or two highly reliable sources. We would like to argue, however, that
the gains are worth the effort. For one thing, the diaries usually provide a
comprehensiveness that is impossible to replicate starting from scratch. The
collection of daily observations for one or more children for up to several
years is a tremendous undertaking. One can benefit from a parent
observer’s years of effort in a few hours of reading. Second, children vary
greatly and it may only be the occasional child who shows a particular
pattern. An examination of a cross-section of diaries may reveal one such
child, and provide clues for what to look for in seeking another for careful
study.
Let us look at an example of how useful data can be extracted from a diary
record. It is a common observation that children seem to comprehend more
than they produce. What is the database for this observation? Preyer (1889)
is an early study that provides explicit data on this point. In Ingram (1978),
I extracted linguistic data from this diary on Preyer’s son Axel as part of a
general discussion of the relation of language and cognition. Table 2.1 here
summarizes the data from Table VI of Ingram (1978) on Axel’s comprehen-
sion and production at age 1;5.
We can see that Axel has around 50 items in his comprehension while
only producing two words. As far as his production goes, Preyer observes
(p. 131): ‘Characteristic for this period is the precision with which the
various moods of feeling are expressed, without articulate sounds, by means
of the voice. . .’ The general findings that might be classified as the conven-
tional wisdom on language acquisition are based on data such as these.
Table 2.2 Some general characteristics of some of the major large sample
studies conducted between 1926 and 1957
Smith (1926) 124 children between 2 and 5; Length of sentences and general
one-hour conversations aspects of sentence development
McCarthy (1930) 140 children between 1;6 and 4;6 Length of sentences and general
50 sentences each aspects of sentence development
Day (1932) 160 children between 2;O and 5;O Study of language in twins
50 sentences each
Fisher (1934) 72 children between 1;6 and 4;6 Study of gifted children
three-hour samples
Davis (1937) .
173 singletons, 166 twins, alI‘ - Comparison of twins with
between 5;6 and 6;6 singletons
50 sentences each
Young (1941) 74 children between 2;6 and 5;5 Comparison of lower- and
six hours of conversation middle-class children
Templin (1957) 430 children between 3;O and 8;O Length of sentences and general
50 sentences each aspects of sentence development
Smith’s (1926) results on vocabulary growth, for example, are still cited
today (e.g. Dale 1976:174) as the norms for English, and Templin (1957)
remains the most common reference for norms of articulatory development
(e.g. Ingram 1976a).
The study of sentence length is of particular interest. In the period of
diary studies, Stern & Stern (1907) had developed stages of acquisition that
were based on the observation that children’s sentences get increasingly
longer. Nice (1925) developed her own stages of sentence length (see
further Chapter 3) that used an explicit measure which she called the
‘mean sentence length’. This was calculated by counting the number of
words in each sentence of a child’s language sample and calculating the
average number of words per sentence. This measure was used in virtually
every study done during this period. In fact, in McCarthy’s (1954) major
review of this period, there is an extensive table that gives the mean
sentence length from several studies across several ages.
The other emphasis of these studies was to apply the results on these
three general areas to different groups of children. The first studies were
concerned with normal children, e.g. Smith (1926), McCarthy (1930), and
Wellman ef al. (1931). Soon, however, other groups were analyzed, e.g.
twins (Day 1932; Davis 1937), gifted children (Fisher 1934), and lower-class
children (Young 1941). This natural development can be traced to the fact
that most of these studies were conducted by students or colleagues of Smith
and McCarthy. Madorah Smith was at the University of Iowa and one series
of research came out of there, published in the University oflowa Studies in
Child Welfare. Dorothea McCarthy was at the University of Minnesota and
2.2 The period of large sample studies (1926-1957) 15
Table 2.3 A summary of the methodological design of Templin (1957)
Tests: (1) Articulation - 176 sounds tested in selected words ages 3;O-S;0,with separate
word test for those 6;O-8;0.
(a) 3;O-5;0 repeated words after the examiner or spontaneously identified
pictures.
(b) 6;O-3;0 read the text words or repeated them after the examiner.
(2) Discrimination - pairs of syllables were spoken by the examiner and children
had to judge them as ‘same’ or ‘different’.
(a) 3;O-5;0used pairs of real words of objects that were identifiable (59 pairs,
e.g. ‘keys’ to ‘peas’).
(b) 6;O-8;0 used pairs of nonsense syllables (50 pairs, e.g. [sa vs. za].
(3) Sentence development- 50 utterances were elicited and transcribed on site using
toys and picture books.
(4) Vocabulary - receptive vocabulary was assessed through standardized tests.
(a) 3;O-5;0Ammons Full-Range Vocabulary Test
(b) 6;O-8;0 Seashore-Eckerson English Recognition Vocabulary Test.
noticeable drop in their number since 1957. Perhaps the major one since
then has been Olmsted’s (1971) study on the phonological development of
100 children.
1. Child innately vocalizes, and can recognize sounds which are similar and which are
different. He develops the habit of repeating a familiar speech sound, e.g. [da].
2. When someone such as the mother produces a word similar to one of his babblings, e.g.
‘doll’, he will imitate it with his closest speech form, e.g. [da].
3. The mother’s use of ‘doll’ in the context of dolls will lead the child to associate the sounds
with the event of seeing the doll. The sight of the doll becomes a stimulus for saying [da].
4. The habit of saying [da] in specificcontexts, e.g. seeing one’s doll after one’s bath, will lead
the child to say [da] in that context when the doll is absent. That is, speech becomes
displaced.
5 . His successful attempts at speech are reinforced, leading him to adult-like pronunciation.
His imperfect attempts are lost.
there is a one-to-one relation between the conditioning of the child and its
word acquisition. We can see if the child acquires words in comprehension
and production separately at first and only later simultaneously. Or, for
word meaning, we can compare the use of a child’s word to the contexts in
which it was first taught. Throughout the book, we will emphasize the
importance of developing testable theories of acquisition.
A third aspect of Bloomfield’s view is that it appears to be focussed on
pronunciation and early word use. How does he account for the child’s
acquisition of grammar? Here Bloomfield has less to say. He has no theory
that explains how the syntax of the language is acquired, although he does
make mention of the role of analogy in historical change (p. 275). He does,
however, emphasize the role of correction by the parent. For example, he
says (p. 31): ‘if he says Daddy bringed it, he merely gets a disappointing
answer such as No! You must say “Daddy brought it”.’ This does not tell us
how the child establishes the grammar for the correct utterance, but it
proposes that parents must do a tremendous amount of language teaching.
As we shall see later, this prediction is not borne out by current evidence.
The major attempt during this period to explain language acquisition is
that of Skinner (1957). As pointed out in its Preface, the book covers his
research from 1934 to 1955. It is the culmination of his theoretical work
during these years and it is ironic that it was published the same year as
Templin’s study. These two works constitute two of the reasons I place the
end of this period in 1957. Skinner’s proposals are an elaborate develop-
ment of the basic notions of stimulus, reinforcement, and association,
introduced above. They do include, though, some attempts to account for
the learning of syntax. To oversimplify: the structure of a sentence consists
of a chain of associations between the words in the sentence. Suppose, for
example, that the child knows the words ‘dog’ and ‘run’, and hears them in
the sentence ‘The dog is running.’ The child may imitate this as ‘dog run’ and
be positively reinforced or rewarded. The word ‘dog’ becomes a response
by the child to some stimulation, say seeing a dog run; and ‘dog’ in turn
becomes a conditioned stimulus for the word ‘run’. The development of
grammar for the child, then, is the learning of a set of associations between
words that can lead to classes of words. A grammar will be a set of classes
that occur in a predicted serial order, based on these associations.
As is apparent from even as brief an account as this, Skinner allows for
very little innate language structure. This point of view, so prevalent during
this period, was attacked heavily by linguists in the next period who
emphasized the hierarchical complexity of language. Nonetheless, behav-
iorism has continued on through today although most of the research has
been on associations between words apart from syntax. There is a major
work by Mowrer (1960) to account for language in behaviorist terms, and an
2.3 The period of longitudinal language sampling (1957 to present) 21
early attempt by Jenkins & Palermo (1964) to develop Skinner’s ideas on
how syntax could be acquired without resorting to innate linguistic prin-
ciples. An important question, which we will return to in later chapters, is
the following. The attempt to account for early two-word utterances by
imitation and word association is possible, although it becomes subject to
massive difficulties as an attempt to explain more complex, adult-like
language. When, in the development of language, does the child show
language structure that is too complex to be explained by simple principles
of association and imitation?
Children (age
Investigator range in months) Sampling schedule
Braine (1963a) Andrew (19-23) parental diary of all multi-word utterances pro-
Gregory (19-22) duced. For Steven, there were tape-recordings for
Steven (23-24) four hours over a four-week period (12 sessions.)
Miller & Ervin (1964) Susan (21- ) initially weekly in 45-minute sessions; later every
Lisa (24- ) two months for 2 or 3 sessions for 4-5 hours.
Christy (24- ) Sampling over a two-year period.
Harlan (24- )
Carl (24- )
Bloom (1970) Eric (19-26) eight hours over three or four days, every six
Gia (19-27) weeks.
Kathryn (21-24)
There are two major arguments put forth for this position. One follows
from the fact that language is highly creative. We continually produce
sentences that we have never heard before, and our grammar can
potentially generate an infinite number of sentences. If the child learned
language using rote learning and imitation, we could never account for the
rate of acquisition that occurs. By a very young age, children are capable of
producing a range of sentence structures that is nearly comparable to that of
the adult. It is argued that this ability could not be attained without highly
complex innate ability. Second, the language the child hears is ‘degenerate’
in the sense that it does not provide the child with the information necessary
to acquire linguistic structure. Take, for example, the sentence ‘Is the boy
who left happy?’ It consists, among other things, of a moved auxiliary ‘is’
that agrees in number with a noun phrase ‘the boy’, which in turn is
modified by a relative clause ‘who left’. There is nothing in the phonetic
string of the sentence, [1~6abxhulcfthaepi],that tells the child about the
structure, or the nature of possible rules that move constituents. This kind
of knowledge about the possible structure of the language is part of the
child’s Universal Grammar.
Another example of this can be given in reference to our earlier
discussion of the acquisition of the meaning of the word ‘doll’ (cf. Table
2.4). Bloomfield proposed that the child learns this by pairing the vocali-
zation of ‘doll’ in the context of the object doll. What stops the child from
thinking ‘doll’ means ‘a doll seated’, or ‘a pink thing’, etc., in fact an almost
infinite range of possibilities? There will need to be some innate limitations
on what ‘doll’ could mean in that context, these being restrictions on
possible relations between cognitive and semantic categories (cf. Jacken-
doff 1983).
Within nativism, we suggest that there are two possible positions, the
maturationist vs. the constructionist. These two views have to do with the
way in which the principles of Universal Grammar became available to the
child. The maturationist view, which can be assigned to Chomsky, states
that the principles are released or become available to the child at some
genetically determined time. They could come quite early, like the ability to
walk, or later, like puberty. The constructionist view, on the other hand,
does not allow linguistic behavior to change due to maturation, but rather
accounts for all changes by a building up of structure. What occurs later
does not replace what occurred earlier, but rather builds upon it. The
constructionist view, then, is a more restricted view of development in that
it allows less change over time than a maturationist view. The point will be
returned to in detail in Chapter 4.
The constructionist view has been most clearly articulated in psychology
by Piaget (e.g. Piaget 1971). It focusses on the importance of determining
2.3 The period of longitudinal language sampling (1957 to present) 27
sequential stages of development. Piaget (1971) has discussed the fact that
his view is nativist, but emphasizes that it is nativism with a focus on
development. For example, he states (p. 16): ‘one still needs to explain in
detail how, in the field of knowledge as in that of organic epigenesis, this
collaboration between the genome and the environment actually works’.
Much of the research on language acquisition done in this period seems to
have a constructionist slant, although it is not always explicitly articulated.
The distinction between these two views can be used to isolate what
appear to be two distinct fields of language acquisition that have evolved in
the last decade or so. So far, we have used the terms ‘child language’ and
‘language acquisition’ interchangeably. Wasow (1983:191), however, has
preferred the following distinction:
There has been, for some years now, a fairly sharp split in the field of
developmental psycholinguistics between what I will call researchers
in ‘child language’ versus those in ‘language acquisition’. Child
language research is concerned primarily with what children say; that
is, it focusses on the data. The central concern of most child language
research is on data collection and classification, with correspondingly
close attention to data collection techniques, and relatively little
concern for abstract theoretical issues. Language acquisition special-
ists . . . regard child language data as interesting only to the extent that
it bears on questions of linguistic theory.
Henceforth, I’ll use this distinction by Wasow, and use capitals when doing
so, Le. Child Language vs. Language Acquisition.
It is now possible to characterize the theoretical approach of the
longitudinal studies cited above. They can be called part of Child Language
in that they focus on the data, and are concerned with data collection
techniques. They also, however, have a theoretical orientation that tends to
be constructionist, that is, they attempt to determine stages of acquisition
that follow from the analysis of data. Wasow (1983) comments on this in a
footnote (p. 91), stating that this kind of theorizing tends to be inductive,
Le. ‘the hypotheses are generated from patterns observed in the corpora’.
Wasow makes one further point about the theoretical work in Child Lan-
guage. He states that its hypotheses are local, i.e. investigators ‘posit
strategies for dealing with particular phenomena at a specific stage of
development, rarely attempting to relate to general issues in linguistic
theory’ (p. 191). For purposes of reference, I’ll call those people who
pursue Child Language in this fashion psycholinguists.
The field of Language Acquisition, on the other hand, starts with
linguistic theory and then turns to questions of language acquisition. It
considers language development in two ways. One, it views theories of adult
28 THE HISTORY OF CHILD LANGUAGE STUDIES
Further reading
Bibliographies
The first bibliography on language acquisition was that of Wilson (1898)
which covers much of the period of diary studies. The next is that of Leopold
(1952). This is a very useful reference source which gives brief descriptions of
many of the studies. For example, on Taine (1877), he states (p. 94): ‘The
famous philosopher’s observations of his two children . . . originality of the
child emphasized too much . . .’; and on Chamberlain & Chamberlain (1904,
1905, 1909): ‘interesting case study of daughter to 3;11, mostly third year.
Careful observers; selected observations, not systematic, but thorough.
“Phonetic” transcription unsatisfactory, but improves somewhat as the study
progresses’ (p. 15). Slobin (1972) is an updating of Leopold’s bibliography.
Slobin deletes Leopold’s brief descriptions, and also some of the earlier refer-
ences. It is important, therefore, to double-check Leopold (1952) with regard
to the earlier literature. Besides adding new references, Slobin also provides
appendices specifically on non-English studies. He also provides three valu-
able indices: 1, according to language spoken by child (44 language groupings
are given); 2, according to content of reference (e.g. babbling, phonology,
syntax); and 3, content of reference according to language spoken by child,
that is, cross-listing the first two. The most recent bibliography is Abraham-
sen (1977). Abrahamsen has selected over 1500 entries in the literature that
she felt were relevant to child language research as of 1977. The organization
is topical, with the main divisions as follows: I: general resources; 11: syntac-
tic development; 111: semantic development; IV: grammar; and V: phono-
logy and orthography. All references are for English (so that Slobin 1972
remains the primary reference for non-English studies) and the studies
thought to be most important are set apart with asterisks.
Readers
There are currently three books of selected readings. Bar-Adon & Leopold
(1971), Ferguson & Slobin (1973), and Bloom (1978). Bar-Adon & Leopold
is the richest for selectionsfrom early researchers. It contains a selection from
Taine (1877) and Darwin (1877) as well as items from other diary works.
Ferguson & Slobin concentrate on non-English studies and provide the only
translations available for some of these, particularly for some important ones
in Russian. Bloom (1978) concentrates on recent work in English although
there are selections from the work of M. Smith (e.g. Smith 1933).
Suggested reading
A feel for the nature of the research done during each of these three periods
can be obtained by reading a sampling of each. A minimum introduction
Further reading 31
would be the following: Taine (1877), Templin (1957:3-18) ‘I: Introduction,
11: The experiment’, Brown (197351-9) ‘The study of Adam, Eve, and
Sarah’. The earliest form of the behaviorist view can be found in Bloomfield
(1933:2&37). Bar-Adon & Leopold’s book (1971) Child language. A book
of readings contains selections from several early works; each selection is
preceded by a brief explanation which helps to set the work in its place in
history.
3 Stages of language acquisition
The word ‘stage’ is possibly the most used term in language acquisition.
The literature is rich with its use, and an article or book rarely comes
along without its appearance. Unfortunately, few people attempt to define
the way in which they are using it. In one respect this is understandable.
Unlike other technical terms, stage is part of our everyday vocabulary,
and we have grown up using it. It is easy to use it with the misleading
assumption that our hearer understands the word in the same way that we
do.
In a scientific enterprise such as language acquisition, however, we need
to be careful to define what requirements we set in order for a stage to be
proposed. As will be shown, there are various ways in which the term can
be used, each with different implications. We need to define ‘stage’ in
order to describe the facts of child language, and these facts are a
necessary data base for the explanation of different stages. Careful analy-
sis of the use of ‘stage’ is crucial to the constructionist view, since we
ultimately want to use stages of acquisition as evidence for a theory of
language acquisition.
This chapter will discuss ‘stage’ by first looking into some of the ways in
which it can be used. Next, it will provide a general review of the stages of
acquisition that have been put forward in the literature. Lastly, it will return
to ‘stage’ and define it in two ways, distinguishing between descriptive and
explanatory stages of acquisition.
32
3.1 Some possible meanings of ‘stage’ 33
certain height, say 5 feet 6 inches. We could then say that she is at the ‘5 foot
6 inch’ stage, meaning she will not change any more. There are less obvious
linguistic examples where we can use stage in this sense. For one, we could
describe a child who is severely retarded, and whose language is perman-
ently arrested at a point where only one-word utterances are used. We could
say that the child is at the ‘one-word’ stage where ‘stage’ refers to a behavior
that is permanently halted at a point on the continuum. Another linguistic
example, which is common, is to use ‘stage’ to refer to the attainment of the
adult behavior on some linguistic feature, such as the use of relative clauses.
This use of ‘stage’ sounds insightful, but does not say much more than does
the continuity requirement above.
A third use of ‘stage’, one that approaches common use, is to add a third
restriction to the two already mentioned, i.e. a transition requirement. The
transition requirement restricts ‘stage’ to cases where the behavior that has
plateaued is expected to change again at some later time. A child who is at
the thumb-sucking stage under this use is a child who has reached some
maximal use of thumb sucking, and will continue on for some time until it
drops. A drop in rate, of course, is not the only direction in which the
change may occur, although it is the most common use. We could have a
plateau, and then an increase. It is common in learning a new skill, for
example, that there is an increase in ability, followed by a plateau, followed
by an increase. The period of the plateau can be referred to as a stage. In
learning to juggle, we may eventually move on to four balls, but our ability
is limited to three balls for the time being. A linguistic example would be the
mean length of the child’s utterances. We might find that the child’s
utterances have been increasing steadily, but that for several weeks their
mean length has been constant, say around three words per utterance. We
could then say the child is at the ‘three-word’ stage, meaning that there is a
temporary halt at this point.
Our third definition of ‘stage’ is a static one, in that it describes a time
when no change has occurred. We can shift this perspective, and instead
limit ‘stage’ to a point where there is active change. In learning, there are
occasions when the changes that occur seem more rapid than others. In
physical growth, these are those periods when the child is said to be
‘shooting up’; in language, these are those periods when the child seems to
.have made a breakthrough and makes rapid progress. In these changes,
there is a sudden increase in use that then remains constant. This can be
captured by adding an acceleration requirement. A ‘stage’, then, is a period
of rapid acceleration in the development of a linguistic ability that will end
in a plateau, i.e. a steady rate of use (possibly final acquisition) afterwards.
A linguistic example is the way children acquire words in production. At
first there is a slow period of growth from around l ; O to 1;6, and then a rapid
3.1 Some possible meanings of ‘stage’ 35
spurt in the size of the child’s vocabulary. We could refer to this spurt as a
stage of acquisition. Figures 3.1-4 show each of these possible uses of
‘stage’ in terms of how they would appear upon. measurement.
general stages. Each stage consists of a cluster of behaviors that are related
by general principles. Uzgiris & Hunt (1975), however, have argued against
these general stages, and say that we can only discuss stages of specific
behaviors such as imitation or knowledge of the spatial relations of objects.
In language, we could reject the idea of general stages of acquisition and
concentrate on the stages of specific topics, like the stages of acquiring the
meaning of ‘cat’, or the stages in learning how to pronounce a sound like /t/.
It is common, however, to see researchers go beyond single behaviors
and to use ‘stage’ to refer to the relations between behaviors. The simplest
relation that can hold would be where one behavior has succeeded another.
Let us call this a succession requirement and such a stage a ‘succession
stage’. Imagine someone who likes to dabble in crafts and spends one year
doing painting, and the next year doing pottery. H e has gone through two
such stages, a ‘painting stage’ and a ‘pottery stage’. Or, there are certain
reflexes that infants show for a short time and then lose: these could each be
considered a stage. In language acquisition there is a period of time where
children will overextend the meanings of their words, for example calling all
four-legged animals ‘dog’; it lasts from around 1;6 to 2;6. This behavior
could be isolated and referred to as the ‘overextension stage’.
While some behaviors may drop out, many appear for a first time,
develop over time, and stay in the child’s repertoire of behaviors. We can
then add a co-occurrence requirement, Le. a requirement that a stage is
defined as the point at which at least two behaviors exist together. For
example, there is a time from around l ; O to 2;O when children use
single-word utterances such as ‘mama’. From 1;6 to 2;O these occur along
with some usage of two-word combinations such as ‘see mama’, ‘my
cookie’, etc. We can talk about a ‘two-word stage’ as the period when one-
and two-word utterances co-occur. This kind of stage can be called a
‘co-occurrence stage’. The name of each stage can be assigned by labeling it
according to the dominant or new behavior that appears. In the above
example, the label ‘two-word stage’ is taken from the new behavior.
Suppose that one-word utterances are dominant (Le. more frequent) from
1;6 to 1;9, and that two-word utterances are dominant from 1;9 to 2;O. If we
used the dominant behavior as the label, then only the ldtter time period
would be called the ‘two-word stage’.
There are two further kinds of use of ‘stage’ that can be distinguished. We
will add a third requirement to succession and co-occurrence, which we will
call the principle requirement. This requirement states that a stage only
exists if we propose a principle that accounts for the co-occurrence of the
behaviors. For example, children walk and pronounce their first words
around the same time. It is not likely, however, that we would want to refer
to these two as a stage, since there seems to be no causal relation between
3.1 Some possible meanings of ‘stage’ 37
E
t Principle A
them, that is, their co-occurrence is correlational. Other behaviors may look
similar enough that we may propose a principle to relate them.
The addition of the principle requirement leads to two further kinds of
stage. One kind is what we shall call an ‘implicational stage’. This stage
occurs when the principle we propose to relate behaviors is such that the
occurrence of one behavior necessarily implies the occurrence of the other.
For example, we could propose that children acquire general phonological
features before more specific ones. This claim implies by logical necessity
that the stage in which the child acquires the difference between /p/ and /t/
will follow the stage in which children distinguish between /p/ and /1/
(assuming that class features like [k sonorant] are more general than place
features like [k alveolar]).
38 STAGES OF LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
The second is what we shall call a ‘principle stage’. This occurs when the
behaviors being explained are such that one does not by necessity imply the
other. For example, children appear to begin to play symbolically with
objects, as in pretending that a block of wood is a car, around the same time
that they begin to acquire language (see Part 11, Chapter 6). Piaget has
proposed that these two behaviors are related by a general principle which is
that the child has developed the symbolic function. This could be referred to
as the ‘symbolic stage’ of development. The stage would be named for the
principle that underlies the behaviors. Figures 3.5-3.8 present a graphic
representation of these possible definitions of stage.
As hopefully is obvious by now, there is a multiplicity of ways in which
‘stage’ can be used. The student of language acquisition will probably find
all the above uses and more when reading works in the field. The above
discussion was provided to present the difficultieswith the term. Section 3.2
will provide an overview of the better-known attempts to describe stages of
language acquisition, and section 3.3 will attempt to limit our use of the
term in future work.
Preliminary stage (first year) This stage consists of three behaviors: (i) babbling, (ii)
unintelligible imitation, (iii) preliminary understanding.
First period (1;O-1;6) The child acquires a small number of sounds with special meanings,
which express the ideas of an entire sentence. There is, however, no evidence that the child
understands grammar.
Second period (1;6-2;O) The child realizes that everything has a name, with: (i) a sub-
sequent spurt in word acquisition, (ii) questions about the names of things. Soon after, the first
multi-word utterances appear, first hesitantly, then more fluently.
There are three stages of vocabulary growth:
(a) substance - increase in nouns;
(b) action - increase in verbs;
(c) relation and distinction - increase in qualifying and relational words.
Third period (2;O-2;6) Sentences become well-formed in that they contain words for the
major grammatical relations, like ‘subject and object’. The acquisition of inflections begins,
and may last for years. Syntax consists of the loose linking of words together where word order
may vary. The range of questions expands.
Fourth period (2;6 on) The simple juxtaposition of words in syntax is replaced by
hierarchical structure and the acquisition of embedded or subordinate sentences. The
acquisition of some grammatical morphemes still continues. The child’s questions now include
those of time and causality.
The insight into the relation between sign and import which the child
gains here is something fundamentally different from the simple
dealing with perceptions and their associations. And the demand that
some name must belong to every object, whatever its nature, we may
consider as a real - perhaps the child’s first - general thought.
(P. 165)
42 STAGES OF LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
Another feature of the period is that the word spurt may occur first in
comprehension, only later to be evidenced in production. Recall that
Gunther asked for the names of things several months before his productive
word spurt. Presumably his receptive vocabulary was increasing greatly
during this time, although Stern does not say much about it.
Stern goes on to analyze the nature or categorization of the vocabulary
developed during this period and beyond. He proposes three stages:
(a) substance stage
(b) action stage
(c) relation and attribute stage
Since he did not attribute classes of this type to the first period (at least not
in their adult form), we can presume that the Principle of the Linguistic Sign
also contains some guidelines on how to classify. These three stages appear
to be ‘co-occurrence stages’ (Figure 3.6) focussing on new behaviors that
enter the child’s language. In the substantive stage, most of the words are
referring to nominals, i.e. the names of things. Later, in the action stage,
terms for actions enter the vocabulary and grow. These are a new behavior
that co-occur with the nominals. Unfortunately, Stern does not give us
much information on how the stages progress, or what principle or
principles determine them. Nor does he tell us how to classify words into
these categories - a potential problem, given the holistic meaning of the
child’s utterances.
The above developments all refer to vocabulary. A second major
characteristic of the second period is the onset of multiword utterances.
Although he is not very explicit, Stern appears to want to separate these
from the milestones in vocabulary, i.e. the vocabulary spurt and the onset of
multiword utterances co-occur, but they are not caused by the same
principle. The latter appears to occur later than the former, so that we could
interpret from this sequence that the Principle of the Linguistic Sign is a
necessary, but not sufficient, cause of multiword speech. Since they bear
this relation, we can do one of two things, either treat the two separately, so
that the vocabulary is in the second period, when the syntax (Le. one-word
sentences) is still in the first, or treat them as both in the same period, but
define the second period as one composed of two principles, the Principle of
the Linguistic Sign followed by the principle that leads to early word
combinations. We will assume that Stern takes the latter course, although
this is not obvious from his writing.
We can look at the cause of the early multiword combinations and their
structural properties, but as for the cause, again we have to search a bit for
Stern’s position. Three potential causes can be located. One is that the
child’s cognitive advances are so great that the child needs more language
3.2 Some proposals on stages of acquisition 43
structure: ‘The general cause of all this working-up is a certain “language
famine”. For normally the wealth of experiences and the need of expression
grows far more quickly than the supply of forms of words. . .’ (p. 161). That
is, the child’s needs to express itself lead it to seek or develop new, more
complex expression. Another possible cause could be the child’s com-
prehension, which is in advance of production. Stern comments that his
children understood multiword utterances during the last months of pro-
ducing one-word sentences. For example, Hilde at 1;4showed understand-
ing of ‘Touch your nose with your foot’ one month before her first
multiword utterances in production. The third possible cause is the child’s
growing imitative ability. Stern distinguishes between direct imitation,
which comes immediately after hearing, and indirect imitation, which is
delayed or internal. He states (p. 155): ‘with increasing age direct imitation
. . . falls more and more into the background and leaves indirect imitation to
do most of the work’. If these three aspects come to be coordinated, as the
three factors at the end of Stern’s preliminary stage, then we can say that
their interaction leads to early multiword speech.
Stern is very reluctant to give these first multiword utterances any
structure. Rather, he sees them as loosely juxtaposed, initially in the form
of successive one-word sentences:
It is true that these word collections were not all so fluently spoken as
are our sentences; their characteristic rather was a jerky utterance
(often interspersed by pauses) of the isolated words; in such a case it is
really more a question of a short chain of one-word sentences as: Hilde
- cocaa (come Hilde, the cocoa is here), ater - dolly (Father look, I
have a dolly). It is only by degrees that such loose juxtapositions pass
into the firm union of a really coherent sentence. (P. 166)
Stern has little specific to propose on the structure of these non-syntactic
combinations, except that they are somewhat limited in their creativity. For
example, he states at one point: ‘For a year the words the child uses are fixed
forms only’ (p. 168).
The first major gains in syntax occur in the thirdperiod around 2;O. There
are two major grammatical changes: (i) the onset of the acquisition of
inflections, and (ii) the combination of words by syntactic rules, not just
juxtaposition. He does not cite a specific cause, but implies it is a principle
that leads the child to syntax: ‘The two-year-old child begins to acquire all
this in the different forms of inflection (declension, conjugation, com-
parison) fairly simultaneously, so that, in reality, we are dealing with united
psychic progress along the whole line’ (p. 168). Let us call this the Principle
of Syntactic Structure, one which directs the child to formulate rules of
sentence structure within the restrictions of Universal Grammar and some
44 STAGES OF LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
theory of acquisition. The fact that Stern believes the source of this principle
is internal is clear from the following remarks:
Now, it can be readily understood that, in spite of great individual
differences in speech-development, certain regularities in the sequence
ofspeech-capabilities are to be found in the child, for general laws of
mental growth are at work here, and it is the consequence of these that
every phase acquires the necessary supply of words and phrases . . .
Since many of these laws act more or less independently of the kind of
speech that influences the child or of any other conditions of environ-
ment, it is evident how strong must be the part played by the inner
faculty and its gradual growth in the development of the child’s speech.
(P. 158)
Despite these innate abilities, the child’s development is still quite slow.
It takes children several years to complete the acquisition of inflections.
Also, the increase in sentence length with greater productivity around age
2-3 years still goes through a great deal of non-fluent production. He gives
the following sequence from Hilde (1;lO) as a request for her mother to go
get some pickles (p. 169):
(3.1) Mama. Want pickies. Room. Wanty pickies. Back. Dada, mama fetch.
Also, the child will move certain words to the sentence-initial or final
position in order to give them prominence. Regarding inflectional develop-
ment, there is just one mechanism that is proposed to account for the child’s
development, the ability to use analogy. This mechanism shows up in other
discussions around this time, as in Jespersen (1922). The child will notice
the regular inflections and apply them to irregular forms, e.g. ‘drinked’ for
‘drunk’ or ‘badder’ for ‘worse’. There is no discussion of how the child
unlearns these, or of how the child’s syntactic rules change over time. Given
the lack of a major syntactic theory at the time, however, this is not
surprising.
Stern’s fourth period starts from around 2;6. It is marked by three
changes. The first is the appearance of subordinate sentences. At first, the
complementizers, relative pronouns, and adverbials that mark the subord-
inate clause may be absent. For example, at 2;6 Gunter said the sentence
in (3.2a) with the meaning of (3.2b) (as translated from German):
(3.2) a. Mother say, builded has Gunter
b. I want to tell mother what Gunter has been building
At 3;O Hilde used each of the sentences in (3.3), again translated from
German (p. 171):
3.2 Some proposals on stages of acquisition 45
(3.3) a. indirect question I will look in the kitchen and ask if she is coming
here
b. temporal clause Will whip the doll till it hurts her
c. causal clause That moves so today because it is broken
d. conditionalclause You’ll get no bread and butter if you’re so
naughty
e. final clause You must take away the beds so that I can get
out
f. consecutiveclause Dolly has disturbed me, so that I could not
sleep
While these may appear around 2;6, their acquisition will vary from type to
type and may take up to 5;O to be acquired. For example, he cites hypo-
thetical conditional clauses as quite late. He gives the following example
(p. 171) from Gunter, which was used at 4;8 in reference to a friend who
had an operation: ‘If he were (not) cut at once, then he had died.’
Stern, as earlier, does not discuss the principle behind this, nor its relation
to the earlier syntactic development of the third period. Since it is given as a
separate account, we will assume it is a separate principle, and shall call it
the Principle ofSubordination. Further, we will assume that the Principle of
Syntactic Structure is a necessary precursor. In this sense, Stern’s fourth
period is a ‘co-occurrence stage’ labeled for the new behavior that has
appeared (Figure 3.6).
A second and apparently independent change of the fourth period con-
cerns the use of questions. Up until now, the child has asked concrete ques-
tions like ‘what?’ and ‘where?’. Now, the child begins to use the more
abstract questions of ‘why?’ and ‘when?’. These early ‘why’ questions can
be quite persistent, as is evidenced by the following dialogue between Hilde
and her mother at 3;7 (p. 172):
(3.4)
Child: What is he eating?
Mother: Fish.
Child: Why does he eat fish?
Mother: Because he is hungry.
Child: Why doesn’t he eat rolls?
Mother: Because we don’t give him any.
Child: Why don’t we give him any?
Mother: Because bakers only make rolls for people.
Child: Why not for fishes?
Mother: Because they haven’t enough flour.
Child: Why then haven’t they enough?
Mother: Because not enough corn is grown.
46 STAGES OF LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
Stern does not discuss the principle behind these changes either, We can
isolate it as separate one from those discussed earlier and for reference
purposes call it the Principle of Derivational Morphology.
Stern’s stages capture behavioral milestones that are described by other
diarists during this historical period. There are some attempts to relate
these behaviors to each other through the proposal of unifying principles,
although this is not done consistently. Some behaviors are related and
others simply co-occur.
3.2 Some proposals on stages of acquisition 47
Table 3.3 The basic measures used by Nice (1925)for Jive stages of
language acqukition
Stages
Measures
1 2 3 4 5
Period
Stern’s term Nice’s term Brown’s term
position, he discusses the performance factors which may restrict the child
from showing this ability. He also looks into the performance factors that
may help the child discover the structure of the adult language, for example,
guidelines such as paying attention to the ends of words. There is, however,
little attention to the principles that would be part of Universal Grammar
and used to construct a grammar, i.e. a set of linguistic rules.
Before leaving Brown, there is one last point that needs to be addressed,
i.e. his view of development before his five stages. He does discuss briefly
his ideas on the period of single-word utterances which precedes the five
stages. He sees this period as pre-grammatical, i.e. as not having any of the
structural properties of Stage 1. Thus, Brown gives this period’s utterances
a lean interpretation, as does Stern. Since Brown switches to a rich
interpretation for Stage I, however, he needs to propose a marked qualita-
tive change between the two. He needs to give single-word utterances a lean
interpretation because he bases much of his inference on early structure on
the child’s use of word order.
3.2.4 Summary
The three proposals of stages of acquisition given above provide some
preliminary facts about the child’s early linguistic behavior. They also
reflect the style of language acquisition research reported in Chapter 2. The
54 STAGES OF LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
Further reading
General literature
The literature on general stages is surprisingly restricted, with the efforts of
Stern, Nice, and Brown constituting three of the major attempts. The
proposals of all three are in a form that is readable for the beginning
student; specific readings are: Stern (1924: 143-70), Nice (1925), and
Brown (1973:632). In Part 11, we will consider one other approach for
early grammar proposed by Halliday (1975). Two other general attempts
are not in English. One is that of Kaczmarek (1953) in Polish; the only
discussion of this in English is a brief treatment in Bar-Adon & Leopold
(1971:133-4). Interestingly, there appears to be a rich literature on acqui-
58 STAGES OF LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
4.1 Introduction
In Chapter 1it was stressed that language acquisition is an area of study that
crosses a variety of disciplines. Because of this, the goals of investigators
vary tremendously, and, thus, the extent and domain of explanation sought.
As already noted, much of the research in the field has led to descriptive
observations. This has been the consequence in some cases of an atheoreti-
cal orientation, or else of a belief that theorizing must follow from a strong
data base. Much of the work of those in education or in language disorders
is descriptive in nature, with the primary goal of establishing norms of
acquisition. This is a useful practical goal, yet it does not take us very far in
understanding why acquisition proceeds as it does. Much of the data from
the diaries of linguists also lacks attempts at extensive explanation. As
N. V. Smith (1982) has said somewhat facetiously (p. 471): ‘by providing a
plethora of factual observations, it [child language: DI] offers a rich field for
the taxonomist and anecdotalists’.
So far I have addressed the issue of explanation in two contexts. In
Chapter 2, I presented the theoretical orientation of the three major
historical periods in the study of child language. It was pointed out that each
of these three periods had its own theoretical orientation, with the nativism
of the last period being divided into constructionism and maturationism.
These two were contrasted with behaviorism, which assigned very limited
innate ability to the child. In the last chapter, I dealt with the question of
stages of acquisition and finished with the suggestion that our ultimate goal
in determining stages is to limit ourselves to explanatory stages, i.e. changes
in the child’s ability that can be accounted for by principles that themselves
are testable.
In the present chapter, I treat explanation in more depth, as a framework
for the rest of the book. First, returning again to the distinction between
Child Language and Language Acquisition, I discuss the way each differs in
its approach to explanation in language learning. I will argue that each
needs to adjust its approach in the direction of the other to improve upon
59
60 EXPLANATION AND LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
fact, as we will see, true.) If so, our theory of acquisition will contain the
lexical principle and the generalization principle, and it will need to specify
the conditions under which the one yields to the other.
These two principles are still not sufficient to account for the acquisition
of the adult rule of plural formation. The child could conclude that there
are two forms of the plural for ‘foot’, these being ‘foots’ and ‘feet’. Wexler
& Culicover (1980), who have led the research into principles of language
acquisition, propose the uniqueness principle to make this last step. The
principle, in its most general form, will tell the child to select only one of
the above forms, the one that is used in the child’s linguistic environment.
As with the other principles, we will leave its exact formulation open.
These three principles, the lexical principle, the generalization principle,
and the uniqueness principle, are examples of the kinds of principles that
will be part of the theory of acquisition that attempts to explain morpholo-
gical acquisition.
An example of a principle of acquisition in the area of syntax is the
principle discussed in Chomsky (1975:32). There, he presents the sen-
tences in (4.2), where sentence (4.2b) is the correct question form of
(4.2a) :
(4.2) a. The man who is tall is in the room
b. Is the man who is tall in the room?
c. * Is the man who tall is in the room?
(4.2b) is the result of the rule in English of Subject-Auxiliary Inversion
which moves the auxiliary to the front of questions. Chomsky refers to this
rule as a structure-dependent rule, meaning that it requires a structural
analysis of the sentence to apply it. It moves the auxiliary of the main
clause. The rule would be structure-independent if it ignored structure, and
simply said ‘move the first auxiliary’. If the rule were such, it would
produce the ungrammatical (4.2c), where the first auxiliary is the ‘is’ in the
relative clause ‘who is tall’.
Chomsky goes on to claim (with no evidence cited) that children never
form questions like (4.2~).The reason is that the child has a principle
which we shall call the principle of structure-dependent rules which blocks
the child from ever having a rule that is structure-independent.
The only reasonable conclusion is that UG contains the principle that
all such rules must be structure-dependent. That is, the child’s mind
. . . contains the instruction: Construct a structure-dependent rule
ignoring all structure-independent rules. The principle of structure-
dependence is not learned, but forms part of the conditions for
language learning. (Chomsky 1975:32-3)
4.3 A theory of acquisition 67
We see this as a principle of language acquisition. The corresponding
principle of UG is that all rules in language are structure-dependent. Such a
principle restricts a possible rule of language, but it does not restrict the
child from using structure-independent rules at some early point in acqui-
sition. To do this, we need the separate principle of structure-dependent
rules.
As with our earlier principles, this one will need to be revised in the face
of acquisition data. Like Baker (1979), Chomsky has no data to support his
claim about what children do, apart from experience in hearing children
speak. Elsewhere (Ingram 1985a) we have pointed out examples where
children do seem to form a structure-independent rule before a structure-
dependent one. One example concerns the acquisition of the English rule of
Subject-Verb Agreement. This rule operates in English to make a verb
agree in number with its subject, as shown in (4.3):
(4.3) a. The man is in the room
b. The men are in the room
We could formulate two forms to the rule, one structure-independent, the
other structure-dependent. These two are stated in (4.4):
(4.4) a. structure-independent rule: a verb agrees in number with a pre-
ceding noun
b. structure-dependent rule: a verb agrees with its subject
Sentences like (4.5) show why the rule for adults is structure-dependent, in
that (4.a) and (4.b) are ungrammatical because the verb is agreeing with the
preceding noun instead of with its subject:
(4.5) a. * Which balls are the boy throwing?
b. * Which ball is the boys throwing?
c. Which balls is the boy throwing?
d. Which balls are the boys throwing?
I am currently studying the acquisition of Subject-Verb Agreement in
English, using sentences like those in ( 4 3 , asking young children to judge
sentences as either ‘good’ or ‘silly’, using the technique of metalinguistic
awareness. Interestingly, early results indicate that younger children will
accept sentences like (4.5~)and (4.5d) as bad. That is, the younger children
are using the structure-independent rule of (4.4a), rather than the adult
structure-dependent rule. In Ingram (1985a), I suggest that we need
another principle to precede the principle of structure-dependent rules.
This principle, which I shall call here the principle of linear sequence, states
that the child should first establish rules based on structure-independent
linear order, such as ‘precede’ or ‘follow’. This principle yields to the one
68 EXPLANATION AND LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
other position can argue that the child restructures later, so that the first
adjective+noun structures are different from the later ones. The child will
only reanalyze ‘the red dog’ later on. One reason why Adjective Preposing
does not exist might be that the child has not yet heard enough relative
clauses to formulate the correct version of the rule. Another possibility is
that the ability to embed sentences has not yet matured, and needs time to
do so. Major restructuring will occur, whether as a result of hearing the
appropriate input or as a result of a maturational event. In all cases, the
child language data are explained, and hence are irrelevant to the adult
analysis.
Under the maturationist positions, the goals of Language Acquisition are
limited. Under the strong inclusion hypothesis, it becomes a field con-
cerned with performance factors. Under the restructuring hypothesis, it
focusses on one of two things. For one, it can document when children hear
specific sentence structures in acquisition. Part of this task also involves
determining the amount of time necessary with a particular structure before
a principle necessary to acquire it is triggered. That is, what is the necessary
trigger experience? Some research on this question can be found in Nelson
(1981). The other area is to determine the relative times when principles
mature. The strong inclusion hypothesis, of course, assumes early release of
the principles, as its program of research will be concerned to prove the
existence of adult principles as early as possible. The restructuring hypo-
thesis, however, will allow for later appearance, so it will be concerned with
relating the appearance of each of the principles in time.
It may turn out, ultimately, that the maturationist view is correct, and
that we need to limit the goals of language acquisition in the ways just
described. It is possible, however, to restrict the extent of restructuring in
ways that will allow acquisition data to play a role in linguistic theory. This is
possible if we take a constructionist view of acquisition. In its simplest form,
constructionism proposes that a rule at any particular stage always adds to
or builds upon the earlier forms of a rule. The final form of the rule in the
adult grammar will result from the final addition to the rule. This view
restricts change, in that the rule at stage n+l can never be qualitatively
completely different from stage n.
This position can be exemplified in our discussion of Adjective Prepos-
ing. Acquisition data indicate that the first structures are of the form
+
adjective noun as in ‘red dog’. If there is evidence that this is productive (a
point to be returned to), we can propose a phrase structure rule to produce
it. Once proposed, however, it will always be a part of the child’s grammar.
The position does not allow the restructuring necessary to have Adjective
Preposing once the child is exposed to relative clauses. It does allow,
however, three other analyses of the relation between the two structures in
4.4 Theoretical assumptions about language acquisition 73
(4.6): (i) the two structures are generated separately, Le. there are no
principles of UG to relate them in the syntax; (ii) the adjective+noun
structures are of two kinds, those generated by a phrase structure rule only,
and those that result from Adjective Preposing; or (iii) the underlying
+ +
structure for all proposed adjectives is adjective noun relative clause,
and the Adjective Preposing rule moves an adjective from the relative
clause into an empty adjective category. The rule would be structure-
preserving in the sense of Emonds (1976). The adjective data in this case do
not dictate a simple solution, but they limit the range of possibilities.
There has been some extensive debate as to whether the correct approach
is constructionism or maturationism (e.g. Piattelli-Palmarini 1980),
although the debate has never been formulated quite in the form just given.
Here I would like to give two arguments for the selection of constructionism
over maturationism as the correct underlying theory of acquisition. The first
is an argument based on the potential contribution of each. If we select
maturationism, our view of acquisition research is limited to the goals
mentioned above. That is, it restricts the field to a highly descriptive
discipline. If we select constructionism, however, it expands the role of
acquisition to include a part of a theory of linguistic competence. All things
being equal, i.e. the internal arguments for one do not settle the issue ahead
of time, then the position that expands the scope of a discipline is preferable
to one that limits it. If constructionism is proven false, i.e. that it does not
lead to generalizations about the nature of linguistic competence, then we
will be no worse off than if we had chosen maturationism. If true, we will
add new data to linguistic theory.
The second argument concerns the testability of the two positions. As has
been argued before, the maturationist view is not testable, in that acquisition
data cannot be used either toprove or disprove it. Constructionism, however,
predicts that the principles it develops should lead to generalizations about
language that will be consistent with independent analyses of historical
change and linguistictheory. The inductive generalizations should play a role
much the same as that discussed for historical change in Lightfoot (1979).
The selection of a constructionist view leads us to our first assumption
about language acquisition that will underlie the discussion throughout the
book. It is summarized as follows:
The Constructionist Assumption: The form of the child’s grammar at
any point of change which we shall call stage n will consist of
+
everything at stage n plus the new feature(s) of stage n I .
This assumption adds to the other features of ‘stage’discussed at the end of
Chapter 3, namely that there has to be a change, and that a principle be
proposed to cause the change.
74 EXPLANATION A N D LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
Further reading
General literature
The basic ideas in this chapter were first expressed in Ingram (1985a). White
(1982) discusses explanation from a different perspective. Her major
assumption is that the child’s language at any stage of development is a
possible human language. This is a weaker assumption than the Construc-
tionist Assumption, but it forces linguistic theory to account for acquisition
data. Chomsky’s position can be found in Chomsky (1975). It was first
adapted to issues of learnability by Wexler & Culicover (1980). An
extremely critical discussion of the attempts to explain acquisition to date is
Atkinson (1982).
The following are suggested excerpts from the above: Chomsky
(1975:3-35), White (1982: chs. 1-3), Wexler & Culicover (198O:l-29),
Atkinson (1982:1-26).
Part 11
Milestones
5 The period of prelinguistic development
5.1 Introduction
Most generally, this is the period of the infant’s development that extends
from birth to the onset of the first word. The discussion of this period begins
with an attempt to define its boundaries more carefully.
At first glance, the selection of birth as the beginning of the study of the
infant appears uncontroversial. Even here, however, it is necessary to
realize that an arbitrary point on the continuum has been imposed. In a
more extensive study, it would also be desirable to explore the nature of the
infant’s prenatal development, for there are important issues concerning
the fetus’s physiological development, particularly regarding the auditory
system and the vocal tract. There are also the possible effects of in utero
auditory experiences. We assume, however, that birth represents the
infant’s readiness to begin the experiences we normally associate with
human development.
The other boundary of the period needs to be set by narrowing down
what we mean by the acquisition of the first word. As will be seen in
section 6.1, defining this milestone is no easy matter. Recall from Chapter 3
that Stern defined the end of prelinguistic development as the onset of the
first word in production. Throughout Part 11, however, I will begin
whenever possible with the child’s receptive ability. The end of this period,
therefore, will be marked by the onset of the first words in comprehension.
The description of prelinguistic development will concentrate on three
major areas of development. The first is the infant’s ability to perceive
linguistic stimuli. This is the area of infant speech perception, which is
defined as the ability to perceive speech before the recognition that such
speech conveys meaning. This ability will later be compared to child speech
perception, which refers to the perception of meaningful speech, or lan-
guage. Child speech perception, then, begins with the period of single-word
utterances. (I will use the term ‘infant’ for the first year of life, and ‘child‘
thereafter; this appears to be a common practice, with no theoretical
implications.)
83
84 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGUISTIC DEVELOPMENT
Ability at birth none basic sounds all human speech sounds some or all sounds
Ability to perceive will never be perceived will only perceive them if will perceive all of them will perceive them at point
non-native speech sounds without experience part of basic sounds at which ability matures
during 1st year of life
Effects of linguistic determines entire course of determines the acquisition no role, therefore no no role, therefore no
experience child’s ability of non-basic sounds cross-linguistic differences cross-linguistic differences
in infant’s ability in infant’s ability
5.2 Infant speech perception 87
Until recent years, however, the testing of these predictions was only
logically possible. How is one to find out if a 4-month old infant, for
example, can hear or perceive the English fricative [J]? We certainly cannot
ask them, as we do adults. The ability to test these predictions requires new
and creative methods of investigation for use with infants. In the last 15
years there have been several major developments in the methods used to
test young infants that have enabled scientists to begin to test these theories.
The next section presents an overview of the most important methods that
have been developed.
Fully voiced: voicing begins through does not occur occurs as /b/ [b]
entire production of the consonant.
Partially voiced: voicing begins during occurs as lbl does not occur [b]
the articulation of the consonant.
Voiceless unaspirated: voicing begins at occurs as stop occurs as /p/ [p]
release of consonant. after lsl, e.g.
‘spa’
Voiceless aspirated: voicing occurs after occurs as /p/ does not occur [p”]
release of consonant. , e.g. ‘pa’
subjects with a string of speech and have them tell us what they hear,
perhaps through making phonetic transcriptions and providing phonetic
commentary. While difficult to do with adults, this is of course impossible to
do with infants. Consequently, we must select a highly restricted set of
auditory stimuli, usually single syllables differing in just one phonetic
dimension, for example [pa] vs. [ba]. The techniques outlined above will
enable us to see if infants hear the two sounds as the same or as different.
Given the need to control for the interference of other acoustic cues, most
of the stimuli used have been artificially made.
Probably the most frequently studied acoustic feature in infant speech
perception has been voice onset time, or VOT. VOT refers to the moment at
which voicing occurs in relation to the release of a prevocalic consonant.
Table 5.2 demonstrates the V0.T for labial stop consonants in English and
Spanish. While both of these languages contain consonants that are written
as ‘b’ and ‘p’, their phonetic properties are quite distinct. The Spanish
distinction is between a fully voiced and voiceless unaspirated stop whereas
the English one is between a partially voiced and a voiceless aspirated
consonant. In addition, English has the voiceless unaspirated allophone [p]
that only occurs after /s/ (see Ladefoged 1975 for details).
One reason that stop consonants have been studied is that VOT can be
manipulated in the phonetics laboratory. Another, more important, reason
is that we have clear evidence which shows how adults perceive these
consonants categorially. To see this, we need to look for a moment at how
VOT is measured. We can assign a zero at the point at which a consonant is
released, and measure a consonant’s VOT from that point in milliseconds
(msec). The voiceless unaspirated consonants in Table 5.2 will have a zero
VOT, since voicing in these begins at the point of release. Those consonants
90 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGUISTIC DEVELOPMENT
that have prevoicing (for example, fully voiced or partially voiced) will be
assigned minus VOT values, and those with voicing lag, e.g. voiceless
aspirated, will be assigned positive values. Experimentally, we can con-
struct artificial speech stimuli that differ systematically in their VOT values,
e.g. a [ba] will have a VOT of -10 msec, or a [pa] a VOT of +10 msec. We
can then play these artificial (or synthetic) consonants to adults and ask
them if they hear a /b/ or a /p/. If perception were continuous, speakers
should gradually begin to hear a /b/ as the minus values increase. Studies
like those of Lisker & Abramson (1967) show that this is not the case.
Around a VOT of +25, English speakers suddenly hear the stimuli as /pa/.
Before this, they hear them as/ba/. This result, which has been replicated, is
referred to as categorical perception.
We can study infants to see what specific acoustic parameters they can
perceive. One such parameter is VOT. Another aspect we can examine is
whether or not infants can perceive categorically as adults do. In 1971,
Eimas et al. published the results of an initial inquiry into both of these
issues. It has since become a classic study that initiated the field of infant
speech perception.
Eimas, Siqueland, Jusczyk & Vigorito (1971) This study was done to
examine two issues: (i) if infants can hear the difference between voiced
and voiceless stop consonants, and if so, (ii) if their discrimination is
categorical. To do this, they used the HAS with two groups of infants:
1-month olds and 4-month olds. There were 26 infants in each group, with
equal numbers of boys and girls.
The stimuli they used were synthetic speech sounds prepared at Haskins
Laboratories, the primary research center for much of the research on adult
perception of VOT differences. The stimuli were even prepared by Lisker
and Abramson, the investigators who reported categorical perception in
adults. There were six speech stimuli used, with VOT values of -20, 0,
+20, +40, +60 and +80 msec. The consonants in the first three of these are
perceived by adults as /b/, i.e. an English voiced consonant. The consonants
in the last three speech stimuli are perceived by adults as /p/. Recall from
above that English adults place the boundary for English /b/ vs. /p/
around +25 msec. The infants in both age groups were assigned to
experience one of three experimental conditions. In one condition, called
the 20 D condition, the infants were to hear the speech stimuli that had
VOT values of +20 and +40 msec. The ‘20’ represents the fact that the
stimuli differ by 20 msec in VOT and the ‘D’ refers to the fact that the
difference between the two crosses the adult boundary for categorical
perception, and thus the sounds are different. Another group of infants
was to experience two stimuli that were 20 msec apart in VOT, but which
5.2 Infant speech perception 91
20 D I
I
I
I
I
I 1
0
1‘- Y I
II
I
I
I
1
I
i\
I
-
I
I I
I I
1 I I
I I I
I I I
I I I
I I I I I Ill I I I hLLuhLu
B S 4 3 2 1 1 2 3 4 B 5 4 3 2 1 1 2 3 4 B S 4 3 2 1 1 2 3 4
Time (minutes)
Figure 5.1 The mean number of sucking responses per minute for three groups
of 4-month-old infants, taken from Eimas, Siqueland, Jusczyk & Vigorito (1971:
fig. 2).
were within an adult category. That is, if the infant heard these pairs as
adults do, they would sound the same. Thus, this was called the 20 S
condition, with ‘S’ for ‘same’. The two stimuli used for /b/ were -20 and 0,
and the two for /p/ were +60 and +80. Half the infants in condition 20 S
would hear the /b/ stimuli, and the other half would hear the /p/ stimuli. A
third group of infants was assigned to the control condition. These infants
would hear only one of the six speech stimuli, instead of two. This group was
needed to check that infants did not increase or change their sucking rate
even when no changes in stimuli were presented. There were eight infants
from each age group in each of the 20 D and 20 S conditions, and ten of
each in the control condition.
When the infants entered the laboratory, they were given a pacifier which
would record their sucking rate. At first, their sucking rate was recorded to
determine their normal (or baseline) rate. This was generally about 25 sucks
per minute. Next, the child would hear a stimulus item. The infant’s
increased sucking would result in an increase in the loudness and rate of the
stimulus. The infant would hear repeated instances of the sound until his
92 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGUISTIC DEVELOPMENT
Eilers, Gavin & Wilson (1979) This study was undertaken to compare the
speech discrimination ability of English and Spanish infants on pairs of
synthetic stops that differ in VOT. Recall from Table 5.2 that English and
Spanish differ in the VOT values for the voiced vs. voiceless distinction:
Spanish places the distinction in the prevoicing range, while English places
it later (around +25 msec). The researchers decided to present the infants
with pairs representative of the contrasts in both languages. If the Universal
Theory is true, the infants should hear both distinctions. If the Attunement
Theory is true, then the infants should do better on just that distinction in
their native language. For the latter situation to occur, however, one of the
distinctions will need to be a basic one, in the sense of Table 5.1, and the
other to be a non-basic one. The non-basic one should show the effects of
experience.
Like Eimas et al. (1971), Eilers, Gavin & Wilson used synthetic speech
stimuli prepared at the Haskins Laboratory. The pair selected to test the
English contrast of ha/vs. /pa/ have VOT values of + 10 and +40 msec. The
Spanish pair VOT values were -20 and +10 msec. The subjects were eight
Spanish and eight English infants, all between 6 and 8 months of age. They
selected older children than did Eimas et al. because they wanted to allow
for the possibility of experience having an effect.
Since the infants were older, they used the VRISD already discussed. The
infant sat on the mother’s lap and was entertained by the assistant while
speech stimuli were presented over a speaker. The infant was first con-
ditioned (see 2.2.2) to turn to look at the visual reinforcer (a toy animal)
94 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGUISTIC DEVELOPMENT
that would light up when the stimulus changed. In this study, the initial
conditioning was done with the pair [bit], [b~t].All the infants were able
to hear this pair and turned their heads toward the visual reinforcer when
there was a change from one to the other. Then they were presented with
the test stimuli. The infants were tested six times for each pair. Three
times the stimulus item changed, and three times it did not. A head turn
was scored as ‘correct’ when it coincided with a change in stimulus. The
infant was scored ‘wrong’ if he turned his head when the stimuli did not
change, or if he did not turn his head when the stimuli did change. An
infant was judged able to perceive a discrimination if he was correct five
out of six times.
There are two further details of the study that are worth emphasizing.
First, there is always the possibility that the mother or assistant might
unconsciously alert the infant to a sound change. To avoid this, both the
mother and assistant wore earphones and listened to music. Second, there
is the problem of judging what constitutes a head turn. The assistant and
experimenter, who watched through a one-way window, would judge
independently. If they felt that a head turn had occurred, they would push
a button. If both pushed their buttons, the electronic equipment would
then cause the visual reinforcer to light up. In this study, the assistant and
experimenter agreed 96 percent of the time on what constituted a head turn.
The measure used in the analysis was the percentage of correct head turns
on each pair of stimuli for each group of infants. The English infants were
correct 92 percent for the English pair, but only 46 percent for the Spanish
pair. When subjected to statistical analysis this difference proved to be
significant, i.e. greater than what would be expected due to chance
variation. The English infants, therefore, were better on the English
contrast. The Spanish infants, on the other hand, did well on both contrasts.
They got 80 percent correct on the Spanish pair and 86 percent on the
English pair, i.e. they did equally well on both pairs.
These results support the attunement theory if certain assumptions are
made. One is that the boundary for the English contrast needs to be a basic
contrast in languages, that is, one which all infants are born to discriminate.
Eilers, Gavin & Wilson (1979) suggest this, arguing that there are acoustic
reasons for this contrast being more salient. If so, this explains why the
Spanish infants were able to make this discrimination without any experi-
ence of hearing it. Another assumption is that the Spanish contrast is not a
basic contrast, and is therefore one which requires linguistic experience.
This will explain why only the Spanish infants were able to perceive this
contrast, while the English infants were not. This study, then, provides
suggestive evidence that experience may be necessary for certain less salient
speech discriminations.
5.2 Infant speech perception 95
Kent (1981: 106-7), citing the work of Goldstein (1979), gives four major
differences between the two: ‘(1)the infant’s tract is appreciably shorter,
(2) the pharynx is relatively shorter in the infant, (3) the infant’s tract is
wider in relation to its length, and (4) because the infant does not have
erupted dentition, the oral cavity is flatter than in the adult’.
One consequence of these structural differences is that the resonant cavi-
ties are quite different for speech production. The size of the oral cavity is
much more restricted than the adult’s, with the tongue filling most of it.
Further, the tongue’s movement is also limited by incomplete maturation of
its complex set of muscles. Besides a narrow oral cavity, the infant does not
yet have a pharyngeal cavity (the area behind the back of the tongue in the
adult). Lastly, the operation of the velum is designed so that the infant can
breathe predominantly through the nasal cavity. Kent points out that the
transition to possible oral breathing occurs around 6 months of age. Before
this, the infant’s vocalizations are thus highly nasalized.
These differences combine to demonstrate that the infant’s vocalizations
will be heavily influenced in the first six months by physiological properties
of the developing vocal tract. While these changes do not stop at age 6
months, the infant develops enough by then to produce sounds that are
more easily recognizable to adults as human speech sounds. I propose,
then, that the development of these sounds over the last half of the first year
of life will constitute the testing ground for the theories just outlined.
There have been proponents for variants of each of the possible theories
of early speech production. Possibly the first to gain popularity during the
period of diary studies was a form of the universal theory. Due to the restric-
ted capacities of the infant’s vocal tract (as just described), the infant will
begin with many velar-like vocalizations. Early diarists saw in these sounds
the exotic sounds of the diverse languages of the world being described by
the new discipline of descriptive linguistics. Ignorant of their physiological
determinants, the diarists would hear an assortment of sounds not heard in
their native languages. As these diverse sounds were compiled from more
and more diaries, they came to be an extensive list of non-native forms.
The expression of the universal theory is most often identified with the
Russian linguist Roman Jakobson. In 1941, Jakobson published in German
a book entitled Kindersprache, Aphasie, und allgemeine Lautgesetze, which
was translated into English in 1968 as Child language, aphasia, and phono-
logical universals. In this book, and in several of his other writings, Jakob-
son made the proposal that infants babble the wide range of sounds that
may occur in the languages of the world. This position resulted from his
review of a large number of diary studies on children acquiring different
languages - Jakobson himself never actually collected data from children
directly.
5.3 Infant speech production 99
The following lengthy extract, taken from his presentation at the Fifth
International Congress of Linguists in 1939, presents Jakobson’s basic views
on babbling:
During the babbling period the child easily produces the widest
variety of sounds (for example, clicks, palatalized, rounded or phar-
yngealized consonants, affricates, sibilants, etc.) almost all of which
he eliminates upon passing to the ‘few words’ stage . . . It is true that
some of these disappearing sounds are not maintained by the child
when they do not occur in the speech of those around him, but there
are other sounds which suffer the same fate despite their presence in
the adult speech, and the baby reacquires them only after much effort.
Such is frequently the case with velars, sibilants, and liquids.
An important feature of Jakobson’s version of the universal theory is his
proposal for the transition from babbling to words. The universal theory as
stated earlier simply allows the infant to maintain the sounds that will occur
in the language, while dropping others. Jakobson, however, restricts these
sounds further by suggesting an abrupt discontinuity between babbling and
the first words. The latter will be constrained by a theory that predicts the
order of appearance of phonological oppositions. Only the sounds that
participate in the first phonological oppositions (or contrasts) will be
maintained. Other sounds that are part of the language being acquired,
however, will be lost temporarily only to be reacquired later. The details of
Jakobson’s theory of the emergence of phonological oppositions will be
presented in Chapter 6. Here the important point is that the infant is given
the ability to babble or produce all possible speech sounds. Jakobson’s
theory had a tremendous impact on the field of child language and has been
frequently cited as a fact about the infant’s babbling, even in recent years.
Since the advent of behaviorism, there have been several theoretical
proposals made that could be described as variants of an articulatory
learning theory. Examples of these can be seen in Skinner (1957), Mowrer
(1960), and Winitz (1969). The last contains a particularly in-depth review
and elaboration of such theories. Most generally, acquisition proceeds in
the following way. First, since the mother will occasionally vocalize while
feeding the infant, her vocalizations become associated with a primary drive
(feeding). Since the infant’s vocalizations sound similar to the mother’s,
they too acquire reinforcing properties. Further, the infant’s vocalizations
will be reinforced or rewarded by the mother, especially if they sound like
the mother’s. That is, the mother (or parents) will reward or encourage the
infant to produce vocalizations like the adult language (e.g. ‘mama’,
‘papa’). This leads the infant to imitate actively the speech he hears.
While such theories rarely discuss the acquisition of different languages,
100 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGUISTIC DEVELOPMENT
it seems that they predict potential linguistic variation. The infant’s need to
be reinforced for sounding adult-like suggests that the infant’s babbling will
soon begin to sound like the adult language, if only at first in general
features like rhythm and timing. If this is so, the infant’s babbling should
sound different from language to language. Further, there should not be
any use of non-native sounds in the infant’s later babbling or first sounds
since these would not be reinforced by adults. For these theories to work,
the infant’s motor speech development at the end of the first year should be
sufficient to allow the child to imitate specific adult sounds.
A version of the maturational theory can be found in Locke (1983). Locke
proposes that infants in all linguistic communities will show the appearance
of certain basic, or what he calls ‘repertoire’, sounds at biologically predeter-
mined times. There is, therefore, no effect of the linguistic community on
the infant’s vocalizations. He states (p. 84):
I will suggest that no genuine accommodations to the adult system will
be evident until the child reaches the systemic stage of phonological
acquisition, which probably occurs at some time after the first 50
words are in use.
He therefore predicts that the babbling of infants in different linguistic
communities will all be the same.
Locke’s theory, however, is not completely maturational. At the point
when phonological acquisition begins, presumably around the 50th word
produced, the child shifts to a different procedure. Locke says that ‘it seems
reasonable to ascribe the child’s articulatory progress for nonrepertoire
sounds to an environmental interactive process we might inelegantly term
learning’ (p. 87). I know of no one who has proposed a complete
maturational theory of speech production. We can of course hypothesize
one, which predicts that all sounds, not just basic or repertoire ones, occur
at approximately the same time for all children.
The refinement theory is basically a constructionist theory. That is, it
proposes that the infant will go through well-defined stages of vocalization
where the earlier stages provide the building blocks of later ones. To be
consistent with constructionism, these stages will also require interaction
with the environment for their development. A theory of this kind can be
found in the work of Oller (1980,1981). We will go through the details of his
theory in section 5.3.3. Generally, he outlines five stages of infant vocali-
zation which each contribute to the infant developing adult-like speech
production. He proposes four major parameters that develop: pitch and
voice quality, resonance, timing, and amplitude. The emergence of adult-
like speech does not appear reflexively, however, but as a result of the
infant’s exploration of his speech ability and selective imitation. Oller’s
5.3 Infant speech production 101
model, however, does not have a strong interactional component. He
believes that the infant in the first year is primarily focussing on the basic
inventory of speech abilities. Infants in different linguistic communities,
therefore, are all coming toward the same point and will sound similar to
one another. In this sense, Oller’s viewpoint is similar to Locke’s in regard
to predictions about cross-linguistic babbling. A more constructionist
model would predict some cross-linguistic differences, either in the later
babbling or at least in the structure of the early words.
Category Feature
I. Vowels (i) Onset: immediately after (i) Onset: when the discomfort
birth cries have already begun to
(ii) Limited mainly to sounds a, appear
a, e, e (ii) a wider range, much less well
(iii) Often nasalized defined in quality
(iii) very rarely nasalized
11. Early consonants The semi-consonant ti appears The back consonants y, x, g, k, r
early, followed by h, I, and 0
111. Later consonants The front consonants, almost The front consonants, both nasal
exclusively nasal: m, n and oral: m, n, p, b, t , d
two classic studies that constituted the primary references in the area for
several years, and then turn our attention to more recent work.
Subjects: Earlier studies (1941), based on 40 infants during first 10 days of life; small groups of
10 to 15 infants in the first six months.
Later studies (1946-1948) 95 infants in the first 30 months, originally to be visited
twice a month longitudinally; there was a significant attrition rate.
Method: Vocalizations were tape-recorded and transcribed. The sample for each child
consisted of all the vocalizations that occurred within 30 breath groups. Multiple
transcribers were used and reliability was claimed to be over 90%.
Measures: 1 . Simple frequencies' of the occurrence of vowel and consonant tokens
2. Simple frequencies' of vowel and consonant types
3. Ratios of token frequencies of vowels to consonants
4. Ratios of type frequencies of vowels to consonants
5. Type to token ratios, Le. how often were specific types used
6. Comparison of adult and child frequencies of occurrence.
~ ~ ~ ~
I All frequencies are given for each child's sample for 30 breath groups.
No. of subjects 62 80 75 64 62 62
No. of records 125 181 166 170 147 149
1 . Mean number (tokens)’ of
vowels 49 53 56 55 56 58
consonants 11 14 18 21 25 34
2. Mean number (types)’ of
vowels 5 7 7 8 8 9
consonants 3 5 5 7 8 1 0
Percentage of consonants
glottal, velar 98 90 87 75 53 41
dental, alveolar 1 6 5 12 26 36
labial 1 4 8 13 21 32
Percentage of vowels
front 72 61 62 63 62 62
central 25 26 24 20 17 16
back 2 14 14 17 21 22
include both crying and non-crying sounds: presumably the younger the
infant, the greater number of crying vocalizations were included. The
measures most frequently reported were frequency of vowels and con-
sonants, for both types and tokens, and various ratios between these
frequencies.
In Table 5.6 I give some of the data from the seven major studies between
1946 and 1949 that are behind the findings in Irwin’s work. This table
reflects four findings. First, vowel-like vocalizations are much more fre-
quent than consonant-like ones at the onset, and the number of vowel-like
segments remains constant over the year while the number of consonants
nearly triples. Second, the differences between vowels and consonants are
not so great when types are observed. In fact, by 7 to 8 months of age, there
are as many types of consonants as vowels in the infant’s vocalizations.
Third, the distribution of consonants reveals that virtually all of the
consonants up to 6 months are either glottal or velar. A shift begins at 6
months, however, so that by 12 months the majority of consonants are
either labial or dental/alveolar. Fourth, the data on vowels indicate that
back vowels are infrequent in the first months, but increase gradually
throughout the year.
Despite methodological problems, Irwin’s studies provide an extensive
body of data that in essence support and add to Lewis’s results. Together,
they present a picture of the young infant using a predominance of vowel-like
106 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGUISTIC DEVELOPMENT
vocalizations that sound like front or low vowels. Further, the early
consonantal productions are either velar or glottal. A shift towards more
back vowels and front consonants begins around 6 months of age. These
results were commonly cited in the literature over the subsequent years. Of
some consequence is the fact that these available data were quite in
opposition to the claim by, Jakobson (1941/68) that children babble all
possible sounds. Despite this, Jakobson’s position continued to be stated, in
the face of available findings.
Normal infant’s age Characteristic vocalization types Metaphonological characteristic of mature languages
~~ ~
syllable-like sounds, but the timing of the opening and closing of these
syllables is irregular and not particularly adult-like.
Around 4 months of age the expansion stage begins, a period char-
acterized by the addition of a range of vocalizations to the infant’s phonetic
inventory. These do not appear in any particular order, and the infant may
go through periods of concentration on one or the other. Table 5.7 lists
seven such sounds. Four of these are obvious from their labels: RSP
(raspberry), bilabial or labiolingual trills; SQ (squeal), high-pitched sounds;
GRL (growl), low-pitched creaky sounds (the opposite of squeals); YEL
(yell), high-amplitude or loud vocalizations. In any particular sample from an
infant at this stage, the occurrence of any of these may vary tremendously.
This is also true for another of the new sounds, IES, or ingressive-
egressive sequences. These are vocalizations that concentrate on varying
ingressive and egressive breathing.
The two other new vocalizations merit special attention. FRNs, or
fully-resonant nuclei, are vowel-like vocalizations that sound more like adult
vowels. They have stronger resonances than the QRNs. For Oller’s subject
L, they comprised less than 10 percent of the vocalizations between 4 and 5
months. However, when adjacent to consonant-like elements, they
accounted for 59 percent of L’s vocalizations. MB, or marginal babbling,
begins in this stage, but is infrequent, less than 5 percent of L’s vocalizations
between 4 and 8 months. Marginal babbling consists of ‘sequences in which
a closure of the vocal tract is opposed with an FRN’ (p. 98). These
sequences are not reduplicated like later babblings, and they do not have
regular timing to the syllables.
The canonical stage around 7 months is the one usually identified with the
onset of babbling. To distinguish the babbling at this time from the earlier
marginal babbling, Oller refers to canonical babbling, or BB. ‘BB includes
both consonant-like units and FRNs (vowels) in a timing relationship that
conforms to mature language restrictions’ (p. 98). Oller points out that the
onset of the stage is relatively sudden, and that many of these units are
reduplicated, e.g. [bababa], [dadada]. He distinguishes two kinds of
canonical babbling: reduplicated babbling (RB) and single-consonant bab-
bling (SCB), e.g. [ba]. At this stage the latter is as frequent as reduplicated
babbling.
The last stage of infant vocalization for Oller is the variegated babbling
stage. There are two new types of vocalizations that appear: VAR (varie-
gated babbling) and GIB (gibberish). Variegated babbling consists of
sequences of consonants and vowels that differ. These vocalizations appear
to overcome the restrictions on the earlier canonical babbling. Gibberish
refers to ‘phonetic sequences with contrasts of syllabic stress. In GIB, fully
canonical syllables occur in the same utterances with low-stressed, often
5.3 Infant speech production 109
slurred syllables that seem to have QRNs as nuclei’ (p. 99). These
sequences sound as though the infant is producing an adult sentence with no
recognizable words.
As just described, Oller’s stages are only co-occurrence stages in the
sense of Chapter 3, Figure 3.6, defined by the occurrence of new vocal
behaviors. Oller wants, however, to go beyond this and to describe these
stages as construction stages. That is, he wants the stages to build upon each
other toward adult-like speech. To do this, he outlines what he calls
‘metaphonological parameters’. There are four of these general parameters
that need to be developed and coordinated before adult-like vocalizations
can be achieved:
Pitch and voice quality parameter: the development of the control of
pitch is practiced through squeals and growls; the emerging ability to
control pitch is seen later in development through the pitch variations
found in variegated babbling and gibberish.
Resonance parameter: the development of the articulation of fully
resonant vowels. The frequent quasi-resonant nuclei of the first
months give way to fully-resonant nuclei in the later stages.
Timing parameter: the development of control over the breathing
cycle in order to produce smooth consonant-vowel transitions. The
emergence of reduplicated babblings initiates adult-like timing of
syllables.
Amplitude parameter: the development of the control of amplitude or
loudness. The concentrated use of yells is an example of manipulation
of this parameter.
Table 5.7 lists the development of these parameters over Oller’s five stages.
Oller’s stages are constructionist in that the earlier developments of these
four parameters build upon each other toward more adult-like speech. To
make these stages descriptive, in the sense of section 3.3, we also need to
propose causes for the changes the infant undergoes. Here we will consider
three possible causes: physiological change, maturational growth, and
intentional exploration.
We have already discussed the extensive physiological or structural
changes undergone during the first year of life. Kent (1981) has explored the
possibility that these changes may account for the stages described by Oller.
Table 5.8 gives the anatomical developments suggested by Kent as possible
causes of the infant’s vocalizations from birth to 6 months of age. Kent is
careful, however, not to conclude that these are the causes. He states
(p. 111):
Table 5.8 Parallels between Oller's first three stages of phonetic development and physiological development, from
Kent (1981: Table 1)
' 0-1 month quasi-resonant nucleus Nasal breathing and nasalized vocalization because of engagement of
phonation stage larynx and nasopharynx. Tongue has mostly back-and-forth motions and
nearly fills the oral cavity.
2-3 months quasi-resonant nucleus plus velar or Some change in shape of oral cavity and an increase in mobility of tongue;
GOO stage uvular constrictions but tongue motion is still constrained by larynx-nasopharynx engagement.
4-6 months fully resonant nuclei Disengagement of larynx and nasopharynx allows increased separation of
expansion stage oral and nasal cavities, so that non-nasal vowels are readily produced.
raspberry (labial) The intra-oral air pressure necessary for fricative-like productions can be
developed with some regularity because of larynx-nasopharynx
disengagement. Raspberry results from forcing air through lips, which
close after each air burst because of natural restoring forces.
squeal and growl Contrasts in vocal pitch are heightened perhaps because descent of larynx
into neck makes the vocal folds more vulnerable to forces of
supralaryngeal muscles.
yelling Better coordination of respiratory system and larynx, together with
prolonged oral radiation of sound, permit loud voice.
marginal babble Alternation of full opening and closure of vocal tract is enhanced by
larynx-nasopharynx disengagement.
5.3 Infant speech production 111
Although a causal relationship has not been firmly established, the
evidence certainly invites the tentative conclusion that major disconti-
nuities in vocal behavior in the first year are related to significant
remodeling of the oropharyngeal anatomy. This is not to argue for a
physiologic-anatomic determinism of early vocalization, but merely
to stress the importance of physiologic and anatomic factors in
evaluating early vocal behavior.
Language
group Cultural attitude Reference
could answer, the mother responded (translations are mine): ‘He says
“girl”.’ To child: ’You say “little horsie” ’ (2 times). To experimenter: ‘Play.
He says “little horsie plays”.’ In a later paper, Pye (1986) has found similar
‘to say’ routines in other cultures, but with different purposes. For example,
they occur in Kaluli (Schiefflin 1979) as teaching devices for developing
language.
Another effect of the QuichC attitude toward their infants is that the
culture has no developed linguistic routines for interacting with infants. Pye
says (1983b:18): ‘QuichC parents spend their time working, not entertaining
their children. I did not observe (nor could I elicit) any traditional games or
songs which parents engaged in with their young children.’ This is in marked
contrast with English parents, for whom such routines abound. Several of
these routines have been subjected to careful study:
give-and-take games (Ratner & Bruner 1978)
peekaboo (Bruner & Sherwood 1976)
book reading (Ninio & Bruner 1978; Snow & Goldfeld 1983)
Given this contrast in cultural attitudes, it is striking that the studies just
cited seek to explain the onset of later language milestones by the
occurrence of these play routines.
In the rest of this section, I will be reviewing data primarily on the
language addressed to English infants. At this point, however, we should be
reminded that the results are for English-learning infants. Thus, generali-
zations will need to await more careful studies in other cultures.
130 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGVISTIC DEVELOPMENT
a This is a direct quotation from Kaye (1980a: 489-90) reorganized into the form of a table.
as Pye has claimed for QuichC parents. As we will see, English parents have
a very different view of their infant from QuichC parents. As you might
expect, English mothers (the parents in the studies to be discussed) do talk
quite a lot to their infants. That being so, the next question is the purpose of
this language. One possibility is that they are directly teaching them in the
sense of behaviorism, as discussed in section 2.2.3 in relation to Bloomfield.
Or, they could be involved in indirect teaching by presenting a model of
how the infants should talk. If so, we would expect that parents’ language
should be quite simple during the period of prelinguistic development,
possibly dominated by single-word utterances. This would be supportive
evidence of a claim that the child’s single-word utterances follow from such
modeling. Still another possibility is that parents reserve attempts to teach
children language until they show some evidence of acquiring language
during the period of single-word utterances. If this is so, then the language
used to the prelinguistic infant may look quite different from that used later.
To study these possibilities requires observing parents addressing chil-
dren at two time periods and comparing their language at each. Here we will
review two studies which have used this methodology: Snow (1977b) and
Kaye (1980a).
Snow (1977b) Snow conducted her study with the hypothesis that English
baby talk would begin to show features like those in Table 5.11 when
children were around 1year and beginning to use language. For example, it
was predicted that tutorial types of questions like ‘What’s that?’ or requests
would not be used before that time since they would serve no teaching
purpose.
5.5 The linguistic environment 133
To study this hypothesis, Snow collected longitudinal samples using
video- and audio-tapes from two mother-child dyads. The infants, Ann and
Mary, were firstborn daughters of middle-class English parents. The tapes
were 20 minutes long, and included a feeding session and a play session. The
ages of the samples were as follows (in weeks):
As can be seen, the samples are not exactly comparable, but they are
sufficiently close.
Snow’s quantitative analysis applied several measures to the mother’s
language in each of the above sessions. The main measures were MLU and
percentage of interrogative sentences. The results of both of these are
presented in figures, so no specific numbers are available. Neither figure
showed any abrupt changes during the second year of life. For both
mothers, MLU remained constantly around 4.0 throughout the samples.
This short MLU indicates that the complexity features of Table 5.11 are
probably part of baby talk even during the period of prelinguistic develop-
ment. The occurrence of interrogatives was also relatively constant, around
30 percent. Interestingly, the most frequent occurrence of interrogatives
was during the first session where these were around 40 percent for Mary’s
mother, and 60 percent for Ann’s. Snow concludes from this that the data
do not support the hypothesis that the features of baby talk in English are
used in response to the child’s needs for a simplified model of language.
There were other measures applied by Snow which did show change over
the study period. These were percentages of declaratives, imperatives, and
contentless utterances (for example, verses, songs, sound-play). Table 5.12
gives these percentages for those times when samples were available for
both girls. At first glance, these appear to support the hypothesis that baby
talk changes around 1 year. For example, we would expect a mother to use
more contentless utterances during the period of prelinguistic development
if she felt that the infant was not learning language at that time. Or, we
would expect the increase in imperatives when the child becomes able to
understand and follow them. These data, then, appear to provide some
support for the claim that English parents adjust their speech as their infants
begin to acquire language. Unfortunately, the data also lend themselves to
other interpretations. For example, we could claim that they show that the
134 THE PERIOD OF PRELINGUISTIC DEVELOPMENT
Age in weeks
Type of utterance 12-13 29 49-52 79-81
Imperatives
Ann 10 6 25 23
Mary 15 7 28 5b
Declaratives
Ann 9 22 29 35
Mary 19 13 29 38
Contentless
Ann 22 38 26 16
Mary 26 32 18 17
Kaye (1980a) The preliminary data on baby talk to infants in Snow’s study
has been expanded by a much larger study by Kaye (1980a). Kaye examined
the language addressed to 37 infants by 36 mothers, one mother having
fraternal twins. Samples of 4-7 minutes were videotaped when the children
were 6,13 and 26 weeks of age; samples of 22 of the mothers were compared
to later samples collected at 26 months and 30 months as reported in Kaye &
Charney (1981). While the infant sample sessions were small, they still
produced a large total sample of 13,574 utterances from the mothers.
136 T H E P E R I O D OF PRELINGUISTIC D E V E L O P M E N T
Kaye used six measures to analyze the mothers’ utterances. Here, we
shall look at four of them:
number of utterances per minute
words per utterance (an MLU measure)
percentage of phatic utterances
percentage of exact repetitions
The term phatic utterance requires an explanation. These are (p. 493): ‘a
class of one-word greetings, consisting of the following utterances: Huh,
Uhhuh, Right, Sure, OK, Yes, Yeah, Yeh, Yep, Yay, Hello, Howdy,
Hm, What, Well, Ah, Oh, and Ooh.’
Like Snow, Kaye does not find that speech adjustment waits until the
child begins to acquire language. His data indicate, however, that adults
speak even shorter utterances to infants than to children acquiring lan-
guage. The short MLU to infants (2.76), high percentage of phatic
utterances (21 percent) and exact repetitions (16 percent) show even
simpler language than that used later. To the 2-year-olds the mothers’ MLU
increased to 3.68, and though the percentage of phatic utterances is not
given, exact repetitions reduced to 3.8 percent. Kaye states (p. 497):
‘. . .the mothers said many two-word utterances, as well as one-word
utterances not in the phatic category (e.g. No, Hey, Lookit, and the baby’s
name)’. While the mothers’ speech adjustments to infants may not be
intended to provide a teaching model of language, the highly repetitive and
simple language presented does provide what should be a helpful model for
acquisition.
Kaye also noticed that there were important individual differences
between mothers. He does not give a detailed analysis, but does provide an
example of two mothers who were very different from each other. Here are
partial samples of the language of these two mothers (p. 503):
Mother 1 Mother 2
1. Comeon. 1. Is that a burp?
2. Talk. 2. Huh?
3. Talk to me. 3. Or are you going to get the hiccups?
4. Can you talk to me? 4. Huh?
5. (laugh) say something. 5. You going to get the hiccups?
6. Comeon. 6. Huh?
7. Talk. 7. Yeah.
8. Can you talk? 8. Hi there.
9. Can you say something? 9. You look like you’re just
10. Well, talk. concentrating too hard.
10. Roseann.
Further reading 137
Mother 1 was highly directive, and used a lot of imperatives and direct
requests; for example, she used 44 percent requests in the sample as
compared to 0 percent for Mother 2. She also had over twice as many exact
repetitions (15 percent vs. 6 percent for Mother 2). Mother 2, on the other
hand, had a more narrative style with few requests made to the infant. She
also had twice as many fragments like ‘huh?’ (utterances 2, 4, 6) than
Mother 1 (56 percent vs. 24 percent). Also, she was more apt to drop an
auxiliary verb in questions, as in utterance 5 , than Mother 1 (50 percent vs.
20 percent of all questions). When we return to the role of the linguistic
environment in later chapters we will examine more carefully the possible
effects of these individual differences.
Kaye concludes that the language addressed to infants reflects the
mother’s expectations of the infant. He agrees, then, with Snow that
English mothers perceive their infants as possible conversational partners.
He takes this one step further, however, by allowing for mothers to vary in
their perceptions of their infants. He states (pp. 504-5):
There are two points to be emphasized here. First, there are linguistic
differences that result from these different attitudes, as exemplified by
Mothers 1 and 2. The effects of these differences need to be observed.
Second, the kinds of perception will vary from culture to culture, as
mentioned in 5.5.1. We need to be careful not to draw universal conclusions
in this area of research based solely on work in English. Both of these issues
will be returned to in the next chapter.
Further reading
Infant speech perception
There is quite a large, and controversial, literature that has appeared since
1971. The bibliography in this chapter is a selection of some of the more
frequently cited works. Periodically, books have appeared containing
review papers of the field; the major ones are: Schiefelbusch & Lloyd (1974)
with reviews by Morse, Eimas, and Butterfield & Cairns; Yeni-Komshian,
138 T H E P E R I O D OF PRELINGUISTIC D E V E L O P M E N T
Kavanaugh & Ferguson (1980b) with reviews by Eilers, Kuhl, and A s h &
Pisoni; Schiefelbusch & Bricker (1981) with a review by Trehub, Bull, and
Schneider.
Cognitive development
There are numerous introductions to Piaget’s theory; a simple one can be
found in Ginsberg & Opper (1969), also in Piaget & Inhelder (1969). An
in-depth coverage is provided by Flavell(l963). The serious student should
take a look at Piaget’s own researches on sensorimotor development which
are contained in his three books on the topic (Piaget 1948,1952,1954). The
best treatment of Piaget in a language acquisition text is Anisfeld (1984).
Linguistic input
Like infant speech perception, infant-adult interaction has been an area of
active research in recent years. While there are several papers on the topic,
few focus on the linguistic aspects of the mother in relation to later
development and the theories discussed in 5.5. The cultural differences that
may occur can be seen in Schiefflin (1979). The summary of the English
view of the infant as a conversationalist can be seen in Snow (1977b).
Bruner (1975) presents a strong statement on the role of the parent.
6 The period of single-word utterances
Recall in Stern’s stages, the first period begins with the onset of single
word utterances in production, presumably through definition (iv) above.
Here, however, this period will be shown as beginning with the onset of
consistent understanding of adult words. Thus, I will use definition (i) to
establish the boundary between what is prelinguistic and what is linguistic.
Nothing of import should be made of it, however, since it is primarily a
descriptive decision. It will only be important within a theory of acquisition
which attempts to propose principles for the transition of one infant ability
to another.
Comprehension Production
No. of words acquired Mean age No. of words acquired
0 0;10(14)
20 0;11(15)
30 1 ;0(3)
40 1;0(19)
50 1;W
1;1(21) 0
1;3(6) 20
1;4(14) 30
1;5(16) 40
1;9(15) 50
sizes for Benedict’s subjects at 18 months were larger than those found by
Smith. Given differences of method and Benedict’s small sample, however,
one should not make too much of these differences.
Benedict’s results are particularly interesting when we go beyond the
general findings and look at individual children. Table 6.2 provides a
simplified view of her results for four of the eight subjects, comparing the
age at which specific numbers of words were acquired in comprehension and
production. It shows two aspects of the data: the relation between the sizes
of the comprehension and production vocabularies, and the rate of acqui-
sition in each.
The results show four apparently very different children. Michael shows a
relatively small gap between comprehension and production. When he has
100 words comprehended, he already has 20 words produced. David shows
an even smaller gap, with 40 words produced with only 80 comprehended.
Diana and Elizabeth have a wider gap, with the latter showing 150 words
understood before any words produced. Clearly, the gap between the sizes
of the child’s receptive and productive vocabularies can vary tremendously.
Even though Michael and David have small gaps between the vocabu-
laries comprehended and produced, their patterns of development are by
no means the same. Looking at the rate of acquisition, based only on the
first 50 words in each vocabulary, Michael acquires his first 50 words in
comprehension and production at about the same rate, which is approxi-
mately two days per word. David, on the other hand, acquired the first 50
words in comprehension five times faster than in production, with rates of
one day per word vs. five days per word respectively. Stated differently,
David acquired his comprehension vocabulary twice as fast as Michael did,
but his productive vocabulary twice as slowly. Regarding rate, Elizabeth
6.2 Early word comprehension and production 143
Table 6.2 The number of words acquired in comprehension (C) and
production (P), and the number of days per word for the first 50 words in
comprehension and production, for four subjects taken from Benedict
(1979)“
0;9 0
0;lO 20 0 0 0
0;11 30 30 20 0 30
1;o 80 0 60 40 1 40 0
1;l 80 50 20 50
1;2 100 20 150 0 30 80
1;3 30 20 80 40 100 20
1;4 50 30 30
1;5 40 50
1;6 50 40
1;7 50
Rate b 2.3 2.0 1.6 2.0 1.o 5.0 1.8 3.7
Vocabularies at specific ages are approximate in that the data were not presented in this
manner originally.
Mean number of days needed to acquire a new word.
is very similar to Michael, in that her rate of acquisition for the two
vocabularies is similar, around two days per word for each. Diana, on the
other hand, is more like David in that her rate of acquisition of receptive
vocabulary is twice as fast as her acquisition of productive vocabulary.
These results show that we have to be very cautious in applying the norms
of Table 6.1 to individual children. Further, the results in Table 6.2 reveal
that rate of acquisition and the gap between comprehension and production
are, to a certain extent, independent. Two general conclusions are: (i) the
rate of comprehension acquisition is the same as or greater than that for
production; and (ii) the gap between the two varies greatly, with a norm of
approximately 100 words understood at the time of the first words
produced.
1. Specific nominals: words that refer to only one exemplar of a category, but are not
necessarily limited to proper names, e.g. ‘Daddy’, ‘Coppy’ (name of pet).
2. General nominals: words which refer to all members of a category. It includes inanimate
and animate objects, and pronouns like ‘this’, ‘that’, ‘he’.
3 . Action words: words that elicit specific actions from the child or that accompany actions of
the child. It includes social-action games, e.g. ‘peekaboo’ and ‘what does doggie say?’;
event words, e.g. ‘eat’; locatives, e.g. ‘where’s -?’; general actions, e.g. ‘give’; and
action inhibitors, e.g. ‘no’, ‘don’t touch’.
4. Modifiers: words that refer to properties or qualities of things or events. It includes
attributes, e.g. ‘big’; states, e.g. ‘allgone’, ‘hot’; locatives, e.g. ‘there’; possessives, e.g.
‘mine’.
5 . Personal-social: words that express affective states and social relationships. It includes
assertions, e.g. ‘yes’, ‘no’, ‘want’; and social-expressive actions, e.g. ‘bye-bye’, ‘hi’,
‘nite-nite’.
Specific nominals 3 7 14
General nominals 38 17 51
Action words 4 6 13
Modifiers 2 6 9
Personal-social 1 12 8
Other 1 2 4
over time; general nominals increased in class size, while specific nominals
decreased:
Category No. of words acquired
1-10 21-30 41-50
Specific nominals (%) 24 14 9
General nominals (YO) 41 46 62
In addition, Nelson divided her children into two groups which differed in
their acquisition of these categories. These were called expressive and
referential children. As seen in Table 6.4, the expressive children had half as
many general nominals as the referential ones, but had many more
personal-social words - the referential children had very few of these.
There are at least two points that need to be discussed about this finding.
One is that while the children could be placed into these groups, their use of
these categories appeared to fall on a continuum. That is, except for a few
children at the extremes, children only tended toward one type or the other.
It may be that children may follow a normal distribution in the extent to
which they use general nominals or personal-social words. This is important
to state, since otherwise one may conclude that children fall neatly into one
category or another. Observe that we could set an arbitrary measure such as
saying that all children with 6 percent or more personal-social words are
expressive. If so, we have imposed a measurement sequence in the sense of
Chapter 4.
A second issue concerns the cause for this variation. In Chapter 4 we
explored three possible causes for variation. First, it could result from
performance differences, Le. that some children focus on naming while
others focus on self-expression. Nelson, in fact, seems to prefer an
explanation of this kind. A second cause could be the effect of the linguistic
environment. It is possible, for example, that some parents concentrate on
getting their children to learn names, while others allow them to concen-
146 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Table 6.5 Percentages of occurrence of words in three semantic categories
for the first 80 words in comprehension (C), and the first 50 words in
production (P), for eight subjects studied by Benedict (1979)
Specific nominals 24 30 17 19 11 17 15
General nominals 38 14 41 33 50 39 43
Action words 22 53 26 44 19 36 36
-
KEY
Comprehension o Specific nominals
.......... Production A General nominals
m Action words
. .**A.......-.A
-5a
m
50
....
9 A ..............
-)L
&.e-
40 ,
-$
m
c)
3 30
’CI
0 \ 0. .....
...............E
....‘-m.........
Y%
C
20
. ............
e,
2 ....““..Q........0
0..
$ 10
I I 1 I I , I
a more recent simple subject study, Hoek, Ingram & Gibson (1986) have
found a similar result.
Specific nominals“ ‘daddy’, ‘mommy’ (at least one proper name) 100
General nominals
Human” ‘baby’ 63
Non-humanh
food/drink ‘juice’ 67, ‘milk’, ‘cookie’ 56
‘water’ 44, ‘toast’ 39, ‘apple’, ‘cake’ 28
animals ‘dog’ 89, ‘cat’ 78, ‘duck 44, ‘horse’ 28
clothes ‘shoes’ 61, ‘hat’ 28
toys ‘ball’ 7 2 , ‘blocks’ 39
ve hicles ’car’ 72, ‘boat’, ‘truck’ 33
furniture ‘clock’ 39, ‘light’ 33
other ‘bottle’ 44, ‘key’ 33, ‘book’ 28
Action words“ ‘up’ 50, ‘sit’, ‘see’ 38
‘eat’, ‘down’, ‘go’ 25
Modifiers“ ‘hot’ 75, ‘allgone’, ‘more’ 38
‘dirty’, ‘cold’, ‘here’, ‘there’ 25
Personal-social words“ ‘hi’ 88, ‘bye(bye)’ 63, ‘no’, ‘yes(yeah)’ 50
‘please’, ‘thank-you’ 38
These are taken from Appendix A where Nelson gives the first 50 words for eight children.
These are taken from Table 8 where Nelson gives data for all 18 children.
Information like that in Table 6.7 is the first step in trying to determine
the nature of word meaning in young children. Besides knowing the specific
words children acquire, we need to look carefully at their contexts of usage.
This is, of course, no easy task. Most of the work in this area comes from
diaries and from the more recent studies which combine parental diaries
with naturalistic language sampling - even then our data are often incom-
plete. Some generalizable findings, however, have emerged.
As cited above, the earliest uses of words appear to be cases of
underextensions. Shortly after, however, there is evidence that the child’s
use of the word becomes generalized, not only to new appropriate
instances, but to inappropriate ones. For example, Braunwald (1978), in
her diary of her daughter Laura, provides the following data on the
production of ‘ball’:
(6.1) 1;0(9) picture of a ball in a book
1;0(9)-1;4 (i) a ball
(ii) round objects, e.g. grapefuit, orange, seedpod, door-
bell buzzer
(iii) request for the first and second servings of liquid in a
CUP
150 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Since six children each acquired 75 words, there was a total of 445 words
acquired. Of these, 149 or 33 percent were observed as being overextended.
The 149 words overextended occurred so 190 times, indicating that many
words were only overextended once. These data are quite important in
I
6.2 Early word comprehension and production 151
Table 6.8 Three types of overextensions, as defined by Rescorla (1980)
~~ ~
showing that overextensions only occur for a subset of the child’s vocabu-
lary, despite the fact that they are noticeable when they do happen. They
also reveal the difficulty in using unsystematic diaries to study over-
extensions, since such diaries tend to concentrate on unique or novel events
with no comments on more regular behaviors.
The analysis of semantic categories indicated that certain categories were
more likely to have words overextended than others. Words within cate-
gories that were overextended were as follows: letters 100 percent; vehicles
76 percent; clothing 62 percent. Only 28 percent of animal words were
overextended, which is interesting in that many of the examples of
overextensions in the diary literature are animal terms. There were 12
words in particular which were overextended: ‘baby’, ‘apple’, ‘car’, ‘truck’,
‘shoe’, ‘hat’, ‘dada’, ‘cheese’, ‘ball’, ‘cat’, ‘dog’, ‘hot’. These were words
which (i) were used by at least four children, and (ii) were overextended by
at least half of the children who used them. All but ‘cheese’ appear among
the first words acquired by English children in Table 6.7. These 12 words
were overextended 55 times, and thus represent 29 percent of the 190
overextended cases. Overextension, then, appears to be a salient character-
istic of a small part of the child’s lexicon.
Rescorla next divided overextensions into three types. These types were
labeled and defined as shown in Table 6.8. The categorical overextensions
are what we typically think of when we think of overextensions. These
occurred in 105 cases or 55 percent of the total number of overextensions.
152 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Table 6.9 Four patterns of associative complexes found by Rescorla (1980)
1 18 The associative complex occurred only for about one month, e.g., one
child used ‘baby’ for himself, his toys, other children, and for mother
and father when they pretended to cry. It only happened during the
first month of the word’s acquisition.
2 14 Use of the associative complex for a longer period of 2 to 4 months.
71% of these occurred after 1;3.
3 18 The associative complex developed gradually over time, with new
meanings added sequentially. For example, one child’s use of ‘daddy’
went through these stages:
(1;l-1;2) for her mother;
(1;3-1;4) for all fathers;
(1;41;5) pictures of men or animal fathers.
4 8 The associative pattern showed a mixed or complex temporal pattern.
Comprehension
(a) Age at 100th word comprehended 1;O(17) 1;0(26)
(b) Age at 200th word comprehended 1;3(24) 1;3(16)
(c) No. of days to acquire 200th word after 100th word
comprehended" 97 80
(d) Rate of acquisition (days per word) 0.97 0.80
Production
(e) Age at 50th word produced 1;5(2) 1;6(29)
( f ) No. of days between 50th word produced and 200th word
comprehended 38 103
(g) Estimated size of receptive vocabulary at time of 50 words
produced 239 words329 words
Table 6.12 Percentage of times each of four children in Shipley, Smith &
Gleitman (1969) would touch an appropriate toy in response to each of
three constructions
Structures
Subjects N (Yo) V N (Yo) VFN (Yo)
Mike 33 50 16
Karen 80 75 83
Linus 46 16 42
Jeremy 16 33 0
Mean 52 44 35
The data in Table 6.12, however, invite closer examination. Only one of
the children, Linus, shows the pattern for preferring N over VN (though
Karen has a slight preference), but he also prefers VFN over VN. Two
children, Mike and Jeremy, show a clear preference for VN over N. Despite
statistical tendencies, these data suggest that children at the end of the
period of single-word utterances are beginning to respond to VN and VFN
structures. That is, the data are suggestive of an emerging ability to process
VN structures. The following studies more directly address this possibility.
Miller, Chapman, Bronston & Reichle (1980) This account provides some
indirect evidence about the emergence of the understanding of two- and
three-term sentences by children. This study is summarized in Chapman
(1981a). As part of a general study on the development of cognition and
comprehension, Miller et al. tested comprehension on eight items, which
are given in Table 6.13. There were 12 children in each of the following age
groups: 10-12 months, 13-15 months, 16-18 months, and 19-21 months.
While there is no mention of the children’s language production, we will
assume that at least the first three groups were primarily children in the
period of single-word utterances.
Table 6.14 gives the number of children who passed a particular com-
prehension test item at least once. We can see at least four children in the
16-18 months group passed the items Possessor-Possession and Action-
Object. These results are consistent with results of Shipley, Smith &
Gleitman (1969), Huttenlocher (1974) and Sachs & Truswell (1978).
Interestingly, even in the 19-21 month group, only one child got an item
correct on the Agent-Action-Object structures. If Huttenlocher’s results
6.4 Pragmatic and grammatical development 167
Table 6.13 Eight comprehension items tested in Miller, Chapman,
Bronston & Reichle (1980) for 48 children between 10 and 21 months of
age, based on Chapman (1981a: Table 4)
are correct, these data suggest that it is not the number of words which is
important, but the function of these. Recall that Craig’s early success was
with structures of the form Action-Object-Recipient. Unfortunately,
Miller et af. did not test items of this kind.
Data suggest that children toward the end of the period of single-word
utterances begin to understand some structures which contain two or
three lexical items. Those that appear understood around this time are
Action-Object and Possessor-Possessed, and possibly Action-Object-
Recipient. No study yet has demonstrated sensitivity to word order or
grammatical morphemes. One general problem is the difficulty of testing
for children’s comprehension at this age. One possible methodology,
which has not yet been applied to this area, is the VRISD paradigm
discussed in section 6.2.2.
168 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Table 6.14 Number of subjectsa in Miller, Chapman, Bronston & Reichle
(I 980) to pass a comprehension item at least once, based on Chapman
(1981a: Table 5)
1. Person name 12 11 11
2. Object name 12 12 12
3. Action verb 4 9 10
4. Possessor-Possession 1 5 10
5. Absent person or object 2 4 8
6. Action-Object 1 5 8
7. Agent-Action 0 1 7
8. Agent-Action-Object 0 0 1
Halliday (1W5) Halliday kept a detailed diary of his son Nigel from 9 to 18
months. To study these data, he divided Nigel’s development into six-week
intervals that he labeled as Nigel (NL) 0 through 6. The actual ages for these
are as follows, in months:
170 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Table 6.16 Definitions for six functional concepts that underlie early word
use, according to Halliday (1975) and the number of words belonging to
each for samples NL 1 to 5
Utterance no.
Proto-word (and tone) Gloss Meaning
Instrumental
1. %--- (mid) ‘give me that’ initiation of a general demand
2. yi (high level) ‘yes I want that’ response to a general demand with object present
3. a: (high rise-fall) ‘yes I want what you just offered’ response to a general demand for a service or
nonvisible object
4. bwga(-) (mid) ‘I want some powder’ specific demand for powder
bug(-) (mid)
5 . tRa(-) (mid) ‘I want (to go and get) clock’ specific demand for clock
tR3(-)
Regulatory
6. a;3;J (mid) ‘do that (again)’ normal imitation of a general command
7. mi
j (wide; ff) ‘do that right now!’ intensified imitation of a general command
8. 5-- (low) ‘yes (let’s) do that’ positive response to a general command
9. 2 2 (midon both) ‘no don’t (let’s) do that’ negative response to a general command
10. 3--- ‘let’s go for a walk’ specific command to go for a walk
11. pwi---; pew (high level) ‘let me play with the cat’ specific command to play with cat
Interactional
12. na; an:a (high level) ‘Anna!’ greeting Anna
13. da; dada (high level) ‘Daddy!’ greeting Daddy
14. ?e: (longlow) ‘yes it’s me’ response to interaction
‘yes I see’
15. 0 (low) ‘don’t be cross with me’ response to regulation or reproof
16. a::da (high rise and mid fall) ‘look, a picture; you say what it is’ normal initiation of object-oriented interaction;
[what’s that?]
17. a::da (high rise and mid fall) ‘another picture; now you say what that subsequent initiation of object-oriented interaction
one is’ [what’s that?]
18. Z(de-)dZ: ‘nice to see you, shall we look at this?’ initiation of person-oriented interaction [what’s
proclitc and (high level and high fall) that?]
Personal
19. z(de--)dZ: (mid) ‘look, that’s interesting!’ expression of personal interest
20. da (midlow) ‘a dog!’ specific interest in a dog
21. ba (mid low) ‘birds!’ specific interest in a bird
22. ba (midlow) ‘a bus!’ specific interest in a bus
23. 0e”cz (mid low for both) ‘an aeroplane’ specific interest in an aeroplane
24. eYi: (mid) ‘that’s nice’ expression of pleasure
ZYi:
25. m5i (high rise-fall) ‘that’s funny (look where it’s gone!)’ expression of surprise
26. bwga(-) (low fall) ‘a lot of talk’ expression of disgust
bug“(-)
27. gwyi--- (narrow low) ‘I’msleepy’ expression of desire to withdraw
Imaginative
28. (same as no. 27) ‘let’s pretend to go to sleep’ pretend play
29. bwe--- (high sung) ‘tra la la’ song
--- indicates repeated syllable; (-) (--) indicates number of optional repetitions; [ ] indicates my own guess.
174 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
functions. The six functions of Phase I merge into two general functions,
the mathetic and the pragmatic.
Some of the features of Phase I1 are part of the period of early word
combinations, so we will leave a discussion of them until the next chapter.
We can see, however, that Phase I contains very specific claims about the
nature of single-word utterances. To summarize, they express a set of basic
communicative functions that have the child as their source. Further, the
phonetic form of these is taken from the child’s vocalization, not borrowed
from the adult language. These words are referred to as proto-words, and
the child’s language during this period as a proto-language.
Several of the investigators cited in Table 6.14 have noted some of the
same features of the child’s early intentions. Carter (1979) refers to
proto-words as sensorimotor communicative schemas, preferring to use
terms that map the child’s phonetics onto schemata, the Piagetian term for
the child’s structures at this stage. Dore et al. (1976) prefer to focus on their
unique articulatory structure. They call them phonetically consistentforms
(PCFs), i.e. child vocalizations that are not adult words in the normal sense,
but which are fairly consistently produced, with some phonetic variation,
and which appear to have intentional meaning. With some minor discrep-
ancies, these terms appear to be interchangeable. The real differences, it
seems, are in the theories that underlie each.
Greenfield & Smith (1976) The study by Greenfield & Smith presents a
slightly different description of the child’s early vocalizations, and demon-
strates how susceptible these utterances are to variable interpretations. To
understand their proposals, it is important to review the data which they
analyzed. They studied two children, Matthew and Nicky, over several
months. The data consisted of diary notes and several formal sessions with
each child during which language sampling took place. Table 6.18 gives the
formal sessions, ages, and distribution of single-word and multimorphemic
utterances for both children during those sessions.
In examining Table 6.18, we can see that the data on single-word
utterances are taken from both the period of single-word utterances and the
period of early word combinations. In fact, most of the data on the earlier
period is from Matthew, sessions I-V. Only Nicky’s first session has no
instances of multimorphemic utterances - it is important to realize this in
comparing their analyses to others like Halliday’s, who was looking only at
the period of single-word utterances in proposing his functions for Phase I.
Further, given that at least Halliday sees Phase I1 (or roughly speaking, the
period of early word combinations) as qualitatively distinct, we need to be
cautious in expecting single-word utterances after the onset of multiword
utterances to be the same as those before them. I have argued elsewhere
6.4 Pragmatic and grammatical development 175
Table 6.18 The formal sessions for Nicky and Matthew, giving their ages and
number of single-word and multimorphemic utterances at each, based on
Greenfield & Smith (1976: Tables 2, 3, 5)
~~
Matthew Nicky
No. of utterance9 No. of utterancesa
Session and age Single-word Multimorphemic Session and age Single-word Multimorphemic
I 1;0(15)(22) 13
I1 1;2(10)(18) 25
111 1;3(5)(17) 66
IV 1;4(2)
V 1;5(13) 83
I 1;6(4) 66
VI 1;6(18) 99 12
I1 1;6(27) 130 I
VI1 1;7(21) 91 17
111 1;7(29) 96 38
IV 1;8(23) 98 42
VI11 1;8(26) 108 72
V 1;9(17) 118 28
IX 1;10(1) 32 87
VI 1;10(21) 170 80
VI1 1;11(21) 119 119
VI11 2;0(23) 42 32 1
‘These are token frequencies; no information is given on types of words within these categories.
PERFORMATIVES
Performative: use of nonstandard sounds to accompany actions; e.g. Matthew
used ‘dat’ at 0;8(6) to accompany clapping and playing pat-a-cake.
Later, more recognizable words would be used in similar ways.
Indicative Objects: calling attention to objects by naming them, usually accompanied
by pointing; e.g. Nicky at 1;0(7)would use ’dada’ as he went around
the house and pointed to various objects.
Volition: appears after the above function. It occurs when the child wants
something, and focusses on the desired object; e.g. Nicky’s use of
‘mama’ at 1;1(19) for general requests; Nicky’s use of ‘no’ to
express desire not to go to the backyard at 1;6(4).
Volitional Object: expression of desire for an object by naming the object; e.g.
Matthew at 1;5(13)says ‘bottle’with a whine, looking for his bottle.
ACTION-ENTITY RELATIONS
Action or State of Agent: reference to an action or state that requires an agent; e.g. Nicky at
1;6(27) says ‘down’ as he gets down from a chair; Matthew says
‘night-night’ at 1;2(5) while getting ready for bed.
Object: reference to an object which is directly involved in an action or
change of state; e.g. Nicky at 1;4(19)says ‘fan’ wanting the fan to be
turned on; at 1;1(0) Matthew says ‘ball’ after throwing a ball.
Action or State of Object: focus on the change of the object, rather than the initial or resultant
state; e.g. Nicky at 1;6(27)says ‘down’ after pulling his train down,
where the focus is on the state of the train; Matthew at 1;4(17) says
‘dirty’ in reference to milk in a dirty baby bottle.
sequence consisting of four general groupings. The first two of these groups
are acquired by Matthew and Nicky while they are still in the period of
single-word utterances. The first group of semantic functions acquired are
performatives. The second group are functions that show relations between
Actions and Entities. Table 6.19 gives definitions and examples of the
semantic relations that fit in each of these two general groupings, subject to
the restrictions cited at the end of the previous paragraph.
The first group of performatives look similar to Halliday’s categories in
the sense that they may consist of nonstandard vocalizations, and that they
are pragmatic, i.e. they focus on the purpose of the speech act. An exact
pairing of the two systems, however, is difficult. The Action-Entity
relations move from speech acts to the content of the child’s utterances. The
four relations shown are based on the assumption that the child has an
awareness of the concepts of Agent, Action, State, and Object. Given that
these categories follow the Performatives, their appearance is occurring
around the end of the period of single-word utterances, and it continues into
the next period.
The Action-Entity relations resemble to an extent the semantic relations
6.4 Pragmatic and grammatical development 177
that appear to be understood at the end of this period, based on the
evidence presented in the previous section. The Object and Action or State
of an Object function could be related to the child’s ability to understand
Agent+Action sequences, yet Greenfield & Smith (1976) have an Action
or State of Agent. When we look at the examples used by Greenfield &
Smith, however, we find that the words the child uses are usually Action or
State words. One could relate these single-word productions to the com-
prehension of Action words, as defined in Table 6.12.
The second discrepancy concerns the Possessor-Possessed relation. Both
Huttenlocher and Miller et al. found evidence for the comprehension of this
semantic relation during the period of single-word utterances. Greenfield &
Smith, however, do not include it among their 12 semantic relations. There
are, however, two relations that look comparable. These are:
(a) Object associated with another Object or Location: this involves
naming one object in relation to another, e.g. Nicky at 1;7(29) says
‘apple’ while holding the refrigerator door; Matthew at 1;2(29) says
‘caca’ (cookie or cracker) while pointing in the direction of where
cookies are kept.
(b) Animate Being associated with Object or Location: when a child points
to an object and names its absent owner, e.g. Nicky at 1;6(19) says
‘Lauren’ while pointing at her empty bed; Matthew says ‘fishy’ at
1;3(19) while pointing at the empty fish tank.
The (b) example is like the Possessor-Possessed relation defined in the
comprehension task described in Table 6.13. The task itself does not
separate ‘association with’ from ‘possession’. The first cases of Animate
Being associated with Object or Location appear for Nicky at sessions IV
and V, but never become frequent in the subsequent sessions. For Nicky,
there are two instances at 1;6(27), but it only becomes frequent at 1;8(23).
The emergence of some form of a Possessor-Possessed relation, therefore,
is only weakly supported by the Greenfield & Smith data.
There is, however, some other support for the production use of
something like Possessor-Possessed in the data reported by Rescorla.
Recall that Rescorla defined one kind of overextension as a predicate
statement (see Table 6.8). Predicate statements look quite similar to the
function in (a) and (b) above. Rescorla notes the following (p. 330):
‘for the four children using some word combinations by the end of the
study, the peak in new predicate statement applications occurred in the
month preceding the onset of word combinations’. Such data can be
taken as indirect evidence of some parallels between the child’s recep-
tive and productive ability at the end of the period of single-word
utterances.
178 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
The data from studies like Halliday’s and Greenfield & Smith’s suggest
some general characteristics of early meaningful vocalizations. The first
ones may not look very much like adult words in the language, yet they
appear to express speech acts of wishing and noticing objects and events in
the environment. As the vocabulary expands to include more identifiable
adult words, the child’s words become more classifiable semantically. The
classification of these utterances into semantic categories appears to bear
some resemblance to the semantic categories that children comprehend
around the same time.
The theoretical implications of the specific proposals by the researchers
cited in Table 6.15 is critically discussed in Atkinson (1982). One concern of
Atkinson’s is that the taxonomies proposed are often not related to any
theory of language or, in most instances, theory of speech acts. Halliday is
an exception, in that he does have his own functional theory of adult
language. As we will see in Chapter 7, his functional categories must
undergo relatively extensive restructuring in Phases I1 and 111. The Green-
field & Smith semantic functions are not related to any theory of adult
language, and so they lack any explanation of how these lead to the
grammar of English. Another concern of Atkinson’s is at the other end of
development, that is, the relation of these taxonomies to some explanation
for their appearance. On this issue Greenfield & Smith fare better in that
they attempt to relate the semantic functions to earlier acquired concepts
and cognitive developments. It is less clear where Halliday’s functions
originate.
This discussion has concentrated on description, isolating what looks like
important observations. These observations will need to be part of any
attempt to explain the developments of this period. At the end of the
chapter I will address generally the Constructionist Assumption in regard to
the child’s ability to understand and produce language during the period of
single-word utterances. Before that, however, we need to consider the
possible effects of the child’s linguistic input during this period, as well as his
phonological development.
1. Day 1. Spend time with the child teaching a nonsense word, e.g. ‘bak’, until the child shows
evidence of knowing the word.
2. Day 2. Teach the child a second word, e.g. ‘zub’, until the child shows evidence of learning
the word.
3. Test for non-minimal opposition:” Ask the child to respond to two nonsense words that have
non-minimal oppositions, e.g. ‘bak’ vs. ‘zub’. Do this until the child shows evidence of
hearing a difference.
4. (Next day? Time unclear). Teach the child a third nonsense word that contains a minimal
opposition to one of the earlier words, e.g. ‘mak’.
5 . Testsfor new non-minimal opposition:”Ask the child to respond to the newest word taught
with the second word taught, e.g. ‘mak’ vs. ‘zub’.
6. Test for minimal opposition: Place the objects for all three nonsense words in front of the
child. Test for perception, particularly in the cases where the child must perceive a minimal
difference, e.g. ‘mak’ vs. ‘bak’.
Examples in the text suggest that occasionally minimal oppositions would be tested in
step 3.
1. Pointing to the object: The child would be asked to point out the object among a selection of
objects. The position of the object would be altered systematically.
2. Giving of the object: The child would be asked to hand the object to the experimenter,
under similar circumstances as in 1.
3. Placement of an object: The child would be asked to place several objects in different places
in the room.
4. Finding the object: The child would be asked to find one of the objects.
5. Operation of one object in relation to another object: The child would be asked to seek out
the object to put one object upon the other.
6. Substitution of objects: The child would be asked to get an object in a particular place, but
another object would be there instead. The child was observed to see if there was a reaction
of disappointment.
provide information about the number of times in a row that the child must
get a contrast correct before being assigned success on the method, a
characteristic of the clinical method.
There was apparently a long period of pilot testing until a word list was
decided upon to test the emergence of Russian contrasts. This word list
deservesa brief mention. It consisted of monosyllables that were CVCor VC.
The contrasts tested were: (i) between vowels in CVC syllables when the
consonants were the same; (ii) between initial consonants where the vowels
and final consonants were the same; (iii) CVC or VC where the vowel and
final consonants were the same. In other words, he worked with a very speci-
fic set of contexts, not looking at final consonants or multisyllabic words. This
point will be important when we look at the generality of his results.
Description. Shvachkin’s study had two phases to it. In the preliminary
phase, he worked carefully with individual children to establish what
appeared to be the earlier acquired contrasts. These results were then
checked in a more extensive study on other children, bringing the total
number of children studied to 19. All children were studied longitudinally for
approximately six months. The following is a profile of Shvachkin’s subjects:
Shvachkin’s subjects
Age at onset: range 0;10-1;6, mean: 1;3
Age at end: range 1;O-2;0, mean: 1;9
Sex: 14 girls, 5 boys
Unfortunately, Shvachkin gives us little specific information on the chil-
dren’s language abilities. If the children were normal, the mean age of 15
months at the onset suggests that they would only be producing single-word
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 183
Table 6.22 Shvachkin’s stages in the acquisition of Russian phonemic
contrasts, adapted from Shvachkin (1948173: 124, Table 2)
a These are those obstruents that can actually be produced by the child at the time of
testing. Their membership will thus vary from child to child. See discussion in text
under Explanation.
utterances at the beginning of the study. The 21-month final age in turn
suggests that they were probably beginning to produce multiword utteran-
ces by the end. The predominance of girls in the study is an interesting fact
that Shvachkin does not comment upon.
It is helpful to look at some results from the preliminary phase before
presenting the general results. The first discrimination Shvachkin found was
between vowels. The data for this were as follows:
Success Failure
Nina K. ‘kot’ vs. ‘kit’ ‘bak’ vs. ‘mak’
(1;3) ‘zuk’ vs. ‘zak’ ‘bak’ vs. ‘pak’
Zina P. ‘kot’ vs. ‘kit’ ‘bak’ vs. ‘pak’
(M) ‘zuk’ vs. ‘zak’
‘bak’ vs. ‘mak’
184 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Nina could only successfully respond to contrastive pairs that differed only
in their vowels. She failed both ‘b’ vs. ‘p’ and ‘m’ vs. ‘b’. Zina, on the other
hand, could succeed in all the cases that Nina could, plus the ‘b’ vs. ‘m’
opposition.
Next, Shvachkin wanted to see when the ability to perceive CVC was
acquired in relation to the above sequence. To do this, he gave Nina K. the
words ‘os’,‘rnos’, ‘pos’, ‘bos’. She succeeded on ‘mos’ vs. ‘os’,‘bos’ vs. ‘os’
and ‘pos’ vs. ‘os’, but failed on ‘mos’ vs. ‘bod and ‘mos’ vs. ‘pos’. He con-
cluded then that the contrast of presence vs. absence of consonants occurs
after differentiation of vowels and before the differentiation of consonants.
In this way, he proceeded to develop a series of stages for the order in which
contrasts are perceived by Russian children. These stages were developed
in their final form after the data from all 19 children were analyzed.
Table 6.22 gives Shvachkin’s results on the stages his children followed.
To understand this table, it is useful to take a brief look at the phonemes of
Russian, based on the appendix in Shvachkin. The vowels and non-palata-
lized consonants are given below:
Vowels Consonants
i, e , a , 0 ,u P t k
b d g
f s s
v z i x
m n
1
r
W 1
Each of the consonants, except j , s, z, 5, and i has a palatalized counterpart
(for a description of palatalization, see Ladefoged 1975). It is a complex
system, and there is controversy concerning its exact nature. For example,
other descriptions of Russian include a ts and E , but Shvachkin makes no
reference to these in his data. Importantly, Shvachkin claims that children
show the acquisition of all the Russian contrasts by age 2 years at least in
simple CVC or VC syllables, and in initial position for consonants. The
findings show relatively rapid phonemic perception between 1 year and 2
years that parallels the rapid phonetic perceptual development between
birth and 1year of age. They do not, however, show that perceptual acqui-
sition is complete at 2 years; rather, they indicate that the basic perception
of Russian oppositions is available to the young child to use in later develop-
ment of more phonologically complex words. As we shall see in the discuss-
ion of production, most child words during the period of single-word utter-
ances are simple CV and CVC syllables.
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 185
We can get some ideas of age in relation to these stages by reworking
some of Shvachkin’s data. In his Table 1, he gives data showing that six of
the children only achieved stage 7 by the end of the study. These six children
ranged in age from 18to 21 months at the end of the study, with a mean of 19
months. Again, if we assume the children were normal, this would be about
the time that most children begin to produce multiword utterances. The
data suggest that children begin the phonological analysis of words percep-
tually during the period of single-word utterances, and that they develop
many of the basic contrasts (presumably in Russian children at least to
stage 7 ) .
The sequence of acquisition for Russian in Table 6.22 merits two specific
comments. First, observe that the distinction of palatalized vs. non-palata-
lized consonants occurs relatively early, in stage 4.This distinction does not
occur in English, and it might appear to the English speaker learning
Russian to be a difficult one. We need to be careful, however, not to be
Anglomorphic in our ideas about what will be difficult for a young child who
has not yet acquired language. For example, tones in Chinese are con-
sidered difficult to hear by many English speakers yet Chinese children
acquire them quite early (Tse 1982). Second, the voiced-voiceless oppo-
sition is very late (stage lo), yet we know from the infant perception studies
reviewed in the previous chapter that it is phonetically perceived early. We
will want to look for an explanation for this late appearance. As we will see,
Shvachkin has his own explanation to offer.
Explanation. Before looking at Shvachkin’s explanation of his results,
consider his use of ‘stage’. We need to extract his meaning for the term from
Table 6.22 since he offers no definition. If we compare the stages in 6.22 to
the kinds of stages presented in Chapter 3, several appear to be co-
occurrence stages, defined by a new behavior (Figure 3.6). Compare, for
example, stages 1 and 2. At stage 2, the vowel distinctions from stage 1
remain, and a new behavior is added, the ability to recognize the presence
or absence of an initial consonant. The new behavior is not directly the
result of an earlier one, and there is no logical relation between them. We
need, therefore, some principle to relate the two behaviors. This would
make the stages descriptive, in the sense of section 3.3. Shvachkin, in fact,
offers some principle to relate these behaviors, but to make them explana-
tory we will also need some independent evidence for the principles.
Shvachkin also makes a preliminary attempt to do that; we will consider his
proposals below.
Other stages of Table 6.22 are implicational stages in the sense of Figure
3.8, of Chapter 3 . Compare, for example, stages 2 and 3. The new behaviors
of stage 3 are not independent from stage 2. In fact, the occurrence of a
distinction between sonorants and stops and labial fricatives implies the
186 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
awareness of the presence of consonants (a stage 2 behavior). The sequenc-
ing of implicational stages does not require principles to relate the change
and is in a sense uninteresting. An implicational relation also exists between
stages 3 and 5 . Most of the relations between the stages, however, are
non-implicational and therefore require an explanation. For example, why
should the distinction between palatalized and non-palatalized consonants
precede that of voiced and voiceless consonants?
Shvachkin begins his explanation of phonemic perception by contrasting
two general periods or stages, the prephonemic period and phonemic
period. The prephonemic period is not what it might appear to be, that is, all
the development that occurs between birth and the first words; instead, it
refers to the period when the child first assigns meanings to sounds. The
child does not analyze the parts of the vocalization but maps meaning
directly onto the word. Shvachkin states (p. 94):
The unique phonemic features of the initial period in child speech
development correspond to the unique semantic features . . . it is not
the phoneme (a phonetic unit of speech) but the intonation, the
rhythm, and later a general sound picture of words which bear a
semantic load at this stage.
From the examples, this period occurs around 6 months to 1 year and
characterizes the child’s understanding of its earliest words. There are two
features to the stage: there is a correspondence between semantic differ-
ences and phonetic differences, and there is direct mapping of meaning onto
a general phonetic characteristic of the words. His use of ‘semantic
differences’ looks similar to Piaget’s discussion of ‘symbol’.
The phonemic period is the time when the child acquires the phonemic
contrasts of the language, as shown in Table 6.21. Shvachkin directly
addresses the possible cause of this change, which he argues to be the
acquisition of the semantic system of the language. He states (p. 96):
Thus, under the influence of semantic change the child moves toward
the phonemic perception of speech, which is connected with a radical
reconstruction of both articulation and speech perception. The
elements of this transformation are seen in the beginning of the second
year of life.
Linguistic organization, according to Shvachkin, begins very early, starting
with semantics.
There are a number of crucial aspects to Shvachkin’s proposal. One is
that he is proposing a radical reorganization around age 1 year. The
transition between prephonemic and phonemic development is one of
discontinuity, and there is no attempt to relate the developments of the
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 187
phonemic period to those of the prephonemic period. Ironically, his stages
for the phonemic period are developmental and imply a Constructionist
Assumption. This is not true for the onset of phonemic perception,
however, which would need some innate principles unrelated to previous
development, This is similar to Stern, who argues for a developmental
perspective and yet proposes a series of discontinuities.
Another aspect of this claim is that the proposal of semantics as the cause
of the onset of phonemic perception is not developed. It seems to me that
the claim is that the child’s receptive vocabulary grows and the semantic
system becomes organized in some way that triggers phonemic organi-
zation. We could reinterpret Shvachkin and argue that the Principle of the
Linguistic Sign precedes and triggers another linguistic principle. Let’s call
the latter the Principle offhonemic Organization. If so, we should realize
that the relation between the two is implicational; that is, a phoneme is a
unit that speakers use to differentiate words that differ in meaning. This
raises the question, then, as to whether or not there is any way to test this
claim.
I would like to propose the following. While the Principle of Phonemic
Organization implies the Principle of the Linguistic Sign, there is nothing in
this implication that requires the former immediately to follow the latter.
The child could function for at least some time with a notion of linguistic
signs without yet phonemically organizing words. Shvachkin’s claim,
however, is that the two occur closely together, with phonemic perception
developing gradually. If this claim is true, one should expect evidence of
early phonemic perception in both perception and production. Shvachkin is
very clear on this point. He believes that the child begins acquiring a
psychological representation of words that underlies his perception and
production.
The onset of the ability to organize phonetic segments into psychological
units or phonemes (the Principle of Phonemic Organization) only accounts
for the onset of the phonemic stage. Shvachkin still needs to account for the
sequence of stages in Table 6.21. Unfortunately, his account of this is not
always clear. A major reason for this is that his stages reflect a process of
differentiation: the child differentiates the most general classes of sounds,
and gradually discriminates between lower classes. To do this, however,
requires some theorizing about what are the natural classes in language and
their defining or distinctive features. Nowhere does Shvachkin discuss this
question. He could have proceeded in one of two ways: he could have taken
a proposed theory of phonological features and tested its predictions (a
study in Language Acquisition); or he could have analyzed his results into
classes and proposed a set of natural classes based on his results (a study of
Child Language). If anything, Shvachkin appears to be doing the latter.
188 THE PERIOD OFSINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Let’s assume that Shvachkin is proposing that there is a sequence of
acquisition that follows from some theory of phonological features. The
child will discriminate down the set of features, going from the most
general to the most specific. This is a viable proposal, and one that could
be seriously pursued today, given the range of theories we now have on
phonological features. Shvachkin’s own classes are in some cases unusual.
For example, in stage 3 he distinguishes between articulated and non-
articulated consonants. The examples in his table contain stops and labial
fricatives, which are not normally considered to be a natural class. For
reference, let’s call this proposal the Principle of Phonemic Differen-
tiation.
Shvachkin argues that differentiation is directly affected by two factors:
perceptual salience and articulation. Neither of these is discussed satisfac-
torily, but his remarks are suggestive. Perceptual salience means that some
distinctions are easier because they are in some sense easier to hear; he uses
this factor to explain why vowels are discriminated first. Apparently two
aspects of vowels lead to their salience: they are the loudest or most audible
segments and they are frequent (Le. in Russian they are about five times
more frequent than consonants). We are not given any suggestions,
however, on how these two factors interact. He uses these same factors to
explain the early differentiation of /a/ from other vowels.
Importantly, Shvachkin attempts to provide independent evidence in the
form of patterns found in adult language. For example, he cites languages
that only have a vocalic difference between /a/ and other vowels, and others
that only have /i/, /a/, /u/. The point appears to be that the stages the child
goes through should correspond to possible systems in the adult language.
This is very similar to White’s condition (1982) that the child’s language at
any stage should be a possible human language. Shvachkin does not,
however, provide evidence of this kind for his stages.
The second factor that aids differentiation is articulation. The point
appears to be that sounds that are easier to articulate tend to be discrimi-
nated earlier. He uses this factor to explain why children could at stage 3
discriminate between sonorants and so-called articulated consonants.
Examples of articulated consonants are /b/, /d/, /g/;of non-articulated /z/,
/a,/x/. (He is unclear in regard to /v/, treating it sometimes as articulated,
sometimes as non-articulated.) He says (p. 114):
Jakobson (1941/68) and Jakobson & Halle (1956) It is rare to find any
discussion of phonological acquisition that does not refer to the work of the
late Russian linguist Roman Jakobson. In 1941 he published in German a
short book (Kindersprache, Aphasie und allgemeine Lautgesetze) that
outlined a theory of phonological acquisition. This theory was initially
accepted in the 1940s and 50s without question, but recently it has gone
through a period of evaluation and criticism (see Menn 1980 for a discuss-
ion). In fact, in some places it is felt that the theory has been refuted
(Atkinson 1982: 1). Here, however, I will propose that the reports of the
death of Jakobson’s theory are greatly exaggerated; its demise will require
more elaboration of the theory to render it more testable, and better
methods to test it. We will begin with an outline of his theory, then turn to
methods of analysis in the next section.
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 191
Jakobson’s theory is most extensively described in Jakobson (1941/68;
page references are to 1968, the English translation). It is altered somewhat
in Jakobson & Halle (1956), and I discuss these changes later in this section.
Unlike Shvachkin, Jakobson (1941/68) begins with a theory of phonologi-
cal features. This theory, which is widely accepted in its most general form,
is that the phonemes of languages can be divided into a universal set of
distinctive features. (Changes in Jakobson’s theory can be frequently traced
to changes in his proposals concerning the set of universal features.) These
features can be seen as part of the child’s innate linguistic capabilities. The
child’s acquisition of a phonological system consists of his acquiring these
features in a consistent and predictable sequence.
In section 5.3.1 it was noted that Jakobson proposes a discontinuity
between babbling and language; we also noted that this discontinuity does
not appear to be supported. The counterevidence to that claim, however,
does not necessarily constitute counterevidence to his claims about devel-
opment during the period of single-word utterances. We can think of his
proposals about the child’s phonological system as linguistic constructs
imposed upon the child’s articulations.
Jakobson sees phonological acquisition as the result of the interaction of
the child’s internal structure (or innate knowledge) and the linguistic
environment. The child actively imposes structure on the linguistic input,
then alters this structure in response to the input. That the interaction is
very much like the processes of assimilation and accommodation proposed
by Piaget is shown by the following remarks, which also make clear that the
similarity is not accidental. The Genevan scholar referred to is de Saussure
(1922), who was writing at the same time as Piaget was doing his research on
infancy:
Accordingly, we recognize in the child’s acquisition of language the
same two mutually opposed but simultaneous driving forces that
control every linguistic event, which the great Genevan scholar
characterizes as the ‘particularist spirit’, on the one hand, and the
‘unifying force’, on the other. The effects of the separatist spirit and
the unifying force can vary in different proportions, but the two
factors are always present. (Jakobson 1941/68: 16)
The child’s system at any point in time, then, is the result of its internal
organization of the linguistic input and its adaptation to that input.
While he emphasizes this interaction, Jakobson nonetheless concludes
that the child constructs an invariant sequence of phonological contrasts.
This is an apparent contradiction in that one would expect some effects of
the nature of the linguistic input as a result of the interaction. He’does not
discuss when the child’s phonology of Language A will begin to look
192 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Table 6.23 The first stage of phonological development, adapted from
Jakobson (1941148)
Substages
1. The acquisition of vowels and consonants develops from a basic CV syllable which
contains a forward articulated stop, and a wide vowel; it may appear singly, e.g. ‘pa’, or
reduplicated, e.g. ‘papa’.
2. The appearance of the first consonantal opposition, nasal vs. oral, e.g. ‘papa’, ‘mama’.
3. The appearance of the second consonantal opposition, labial vs. dental, e.g. ‘papa’ vs.
‘tata’, ‘mama’ vs. ‘nana’.
4. The appearance of the first vocalic opposition, narrow vs. wide vowel, e.g. ‘papa’ vs.
‘pipi’.
5 . The appearance of the second vocalic opposition, either:
(a) splitting of narrow vowel into front vs. back
e.g. ‘papa’ vs. ‘pipi’ vs. ‘pupu’
(b) splitting of narrow vowel into a more open vs. narrow opposition
e.g. ‘papa’ vs. ‘pipi’ vs. ‘pepe’
Minimal consonant system: m-n
P- t
Minimal vowel system: 1 (or) i
a e
a
CONSONANTS
1. The existence of fricatives implies the Stops are acquired before fricatives;
existence of stops (p. 51). fricatives are changed into stops, e.g.
lfl+lpl.
2. The existence of front consonants (labials Front consonants are acquired before back
and dentals) implies the existence of back consonants, back consonants are replaced
consonants (palatals and velars) (p. 53). by dentals, e.g. lkl+lt/.
3. If a language has only one fricative, it will The first fricative acquired is Is1 (a variable
be 1st. articulation between [SI and [J]); other
fricatives will be changed to 1st.
4. The existence of an affricate in opposition An affricate is acquired in opposition to a
to a stop implies a fricative within the same stop after the acquisition of the fricative in
series, e.g. Ipfl vs. /PI implies If/ vs. lpl. the same series; affricates are changed into
stops or fricatives, e.g. ltskltlorlsl.
VOWELS
5 . An opposition of two vowels with the same The opposition between vowels of similar
degree of aperture implies the existence of aperture is acquired late.
an opposition with a narrower aperture;
e.g. 191 vs. la1 implies la1 vs. le/.
6. An opposition between rounded vowels Oppositions between unrounded vowels
implies the same opposition between are acquired before those between rounded
unrounded vowels, e.g. /u/ vs. lo1 implies Iil vowels.
vs. le/.
Jakobson states that many languages will have a single liquid (usually Ill),
and that the acquisition of a second liquid is late. We are not told, however,
when the first liquid is acquired, nor its first opposition. One needs to
realize, therefore, that we are dealing with an incomplete theory, or
actually the outline of a theory. These laws will need to be elaborated,
altered and joined with other ones before a complete theory can be
proposed. Also, Jakobson is sometimes careless in the way he states his
predictions. For example, he states that front consonants precede back
consonants, as if he were dealing only with the acquisition of sounds. Given
that he is really concerned with distinctive features or oppositions, this is
quite misleading. What he actually means is that oppositions between front
consonants precede oppositions between back ones. For example, labial vs.
dental appears before palatal vs. velar, or even dental vs. velar.
Since Jakobson gives no analysis of child data, but only anecdotal
examples, we have no idea of when children acquiring different languages
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 195
will begin to sound different from each other. Since the child has to acquire
the oppositions of a specific language, however, one would expect some
differences before very long, but the processes that merge oppositions
should look similar across languages. The child’s oppositions, though, are
always acquired in relation to some adult language. This point is worth
emphasizing because it has sometimes been misunderstood in the literature.
Jakobson is not always clear on the level of representation of distinctive
features, but it appears that he recognizes a level of linguistic representation
that is distinct from the phonetic level. This level often appears to
correspond to the perceived surface structure of the adult word. There are
two kinds of examples which indicate a level of linguistic representation.
One is his discussion of the early merger of /k/+/t/. He states (p. 54):
‘Occasionally, an intermediate stage is introduced . . . in which, although
the velar series is not established, the two phonemes are already distin-
guished. In this case, a glottal stop corresponds to /k/ (or velars, in general)
of the mother tongue.’ In other words, a phonetic distinction between [t]
and [3] represents an underlying dental vs. velar contrast. The second
example concerns a French child who said ‘papa’, [dCdC] (for ‘tCter’) and
[de] (for ‘bC’) (p. 49). Jakobson proposes that the child has only one vowel
phoneme /a/with a rule that /a/+/e/ after dentals. The phonological
representation of the last two words ‘tCter’ and ‘be’ would be /dada/ and
/da/. This example differs from the first in that the child’s phonemic
representation is distinct from the perceived adult form. The second
example is similar to the first, however, in showing that there is a linguistic
representation that is distinct from, but related to, the perceived and
produced form of words.
In Part I11 of his book, Jakobson attempts to explain the laws of
irreversible solidarity by reference to the acoustic and articulatory prop-
erties of speech sounds. The style of explanation is similar to that discussed
by Shvachkin in that there is gradual differentiation. When discussing
Shvachkin I called this the Principle of Phonemic Differentiation. Jakob-
son’s term for the same general principle is the ‘principle of maximal
contrast’. In reference to his stages, he says (p. 68): ‘This sequence obeys
the principle of maximal contrast and proceeds from the simple and
undifferentiated to the stratified and differentiated.’ He discusses possible
explanations for the early oppositions acquired by the child and these are
summarized here in Table 6.25. They develop in this fashion, moving to
lesser degrees of contrast. This term is less than satisfactorily defined but
appears to refer to differences between features that are as acoustically
distinct as possible. This is similar to Shvachkin, except the latter also
discusses the role of frequency. In his later work, particularly Jakobson,
Fant & Halle (1963), Jakobson attempts to refine these acoustic differences
196 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Table 6.25 The principle of maximal contrast applied to the first
oppositions acquired by children (Jakobson 1941168)
The basic CV syllable The maximal contrast in the syllable is between closure and
opening. The maximal closure is a labial stop (which seals
the entire vocal tract); the maximal opening is the vowel /a/.
Nasal vs. oral consonants The maximal contrast within consonants is the obstructed
oral cavity in contrast to the open nasal cavity.
Labial vs. dental consonants Both of these involve pitch contrasts; dental consonants
and narrow vowels are greater in pitch than wide vowels
and labials.
Front vs. back consonants Back consonants contrast with front consonants by having
greater resonance (or loudness).
Spontaneous Imitated
Lexical type phonetic type phonetic type
1. allgone 1. ?augho
2. ?auwo
3. ?okh6
4. ?okhu
2. baby 5. apepi
6. abi
7. bibi
3. ball 8. bau
4. blanket 9. bijae bjae
5. book 10. ag
11. bA?
6. bounce 12. bA
13. be
14. bwae
7. byebye 15. phaedi 16. bae'bae
8. cereal 17. "o$uiJ
9. cheese 18. $i
10. dog 19. "dae (2 tokens)
20. da
21. darhai
11. hi 22. ha1
12. ice 23. ai$ (2 tokens)
24. ?a
13. nightnight 25. naina
14. no 26. n6n6 27. nAh
28. n6
15. paper 29. 0etJa
30. baedu
16. pat 31. phaet (3 tokens)
32. phae
17. please 33. phe (2 tokens)
18. pretty 34. prhi
19. purse 35. phe
36. phe
20. rock 37. wakuak (2 tokens)
38. uakwak (2 tokens)
39. uakuak
40. wak
21. shoe 41. rJu
42. $'u
43. $u
44. thuh
22. tea 45. fhi
46. thi
23. thank you 47. thafhi
24. up 48. ?a?
25. yeah 49. ijAh
200 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Phone classes and phone trees This method was originally proposed by
Ferguson & Farwell (1975). It has been used since by several other
researchers, in particular Shibamoto & Olmsted (1978), Leonard, Newhoff
& Mesalam (1980), and Stoel-Gammon & Cooper (1984). A reading of the
literature requires an understanding of the phone class/phone tree
methodology.
The study by Ferguson & Farwell limited itself to word-initial con-
sonants. The definition of phone class, however, can be extended to all
word positions (as is done in Shibamoto & Olmsted 1978) and this should be
kept in mind when we look at their definition of phone class. A p h o n e class
(Ferguson & Farwell 1975: 424) is determined as follows:
Then all words beginning with the same phone or set of variant phones
were put together. The set of initial-consonant variants of each of
these groups of words constitutes a ‘phone class’, and is represented
by the appropriate phonetic symbols in a box, or between vertical
-
lines. Thus a phone class [d th]consists of the initial consonants of all
those words whose initial-consonant sound varied between [d] and
[thl.
Phone classes, then, are primarily determined by the distribution of
segments across words.
In an earlier version of their paper, Ferguson and Farwell provide an
appendix giving the data which is the basis of their analysis. Table 6.26 gives
a phonological lexicon of their data for one of their subjects, T , at the sixth
sample session. The phone classes for this session were as follows (subscrip-
ted numbers refer to the number of tokens):
(6.9) Phone classes for T a t session VI
1. [b - - - - -
bw ph (I 01 for ‘baby’, ‘ball’, ‘blanket’, ‘book’,
‘bounce’, ‘bye-bye’, ‘paper’
2. IP”4 for ‘pat’, ‘please’, ‘pretty’, ‘purse’
3. [WII for ‘rock’
4. [dl for ‘dog’
5. [th12 for ‘tea’, ‘thankyou’
6. [n12 for ‘nightnight’, ‘no’
7. for ‘yeah’
8. [$ -‘q -
J th]3 for ‘cereal’, ‘cheese’, ‘show’
9. [hll for ‘hi’
-
10. [? 0 1 3 for ‘allgone’, ‘ice’, ‘up’
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 201
First of all, there is a problem concerning how words are assigned to
phone classes. Here it appears that words are grouped into phone classes if
some of the variants are the same. For example, ‘ball’ and ‘baby’ are
-
grouped together because the former’s [b] is a variant of the latter [0 b].
Shibamato & Olmsted (1978: 421-2), however, point out that for some data
this can result in some analyses that produce a very small number of phone
classes with very large membership. This happens in Ferguson & Farwell
(1975: 426), in fact, when T at VI1 has a phone class of the following:
- - - - - - - - -
[J tJ 3 j th s h q tq 91.
The next question, then, concerns the purpose of phone classes. Fer-
guson & Farwell (1975: 425) state it as follows:
The notion of ‘phone class’ here is similar to the notion of ‘phoneme’
of American structuralism, in that it refers to a class of phonetically
similar speech sounds believed to contrast with other classes, as shown
by lexical identification.
Phone classes, by this definition, are isolated in order to follow the
development of phonemic oppositions.
Ferguson & Farwell determine the phone classes of a longitudinal series
of language samples, and then connect the classes across time. These
longitudinal connections are phone trees. They state (p. 424):
If successive phone classes did not contain the same word but were
related to phone classes which did, dotted lines were drawn connect-
ing them. For example in T’s /m/ class:
/m/ (mama)
/m/ (milk)
I
/m/ (milk, mama)
Figure 6.2 gives T’s phone classes for nine longitudinal sessions, over 13
weeks, beginning at 11 months.
As stated earlier, this approach has become quite popular in recent years
for the phonological analysis of children during the period of single-word
utterances. In 6.5.4 we will present some results of these analyses. Here,
however, we would like to point out some concerns with this method. First,
there is a minor methodological point. These trees like Figure 6.2 are hard
to devise, since the procedures are not often clear, and they are difficult to
read. More elaborate phone trees look like the wiring diagram of a
television set. This would be worth the effort, of course, if they reflected the
child’s emerging phonological system. There are difficulties, however, in
arguing that they do.
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 203
The most serious problem with phone trees is that they are extremely
sensitive to the phonetic variability of a single lexical item. Suppose, for
example, that a child’s attempt at English /b-/ were as follows:
(6.10) ‘ball’ [ba] ‘button’ [bh] (6 tokens), [hth], [thth]
‘bike’ [bar]
‘book’ [bu]
- -
The phone class would be [b 0 t] suggesting extensive variability where,
in fact, only one out of four lexical types shows this variability. Further, the
variability of ‘button’ is not as great as it might appear, since six of the eight
phonetic tokens begin with [b]. The phone class analysis, however, misses
this point. This approach places tremendous emphasis on variability that
may result from performance factors, yet uses the results for conclusions
about the child’s phonological competence, i.e. his emerging phonological
oppositions. Still further, this variability is enhanced the more narrow the
phonetic transcription. The phone class given above for T at session VI1 is
an example of this. My general conclusion is that phone clasdtree analyses
are awkward to do, and they predispose the analyst to focus on the surface
variability of lexical items, variability that is subject to sampling conditions
and performance factors in general. It is useful as a method to draw
attention to such variation. As a measure of competence, however, it is a
measurement sequence in the sense of Chapter 3, that is, it can only lead to
conclusions that development is variable from lexical item to lexical item.
Table 6.27 An abbreviated phonological lexicon for T a t VI, with only the
most typical phonetic types indicated
1. allgone ?okho
2. baby bibi
3. ball bau
4. blanket bija: bja: (imitated)
5. book ag
6. bounce be
7. bye-bye phzdi
8. cereal SU’S
9. cheese FI
10. dog dz
11. hi hai
12. ice a1.r
13. nightnight naina (imitated)
14. no no
15. paper cpetsa
16. pat phzt
17. please Phe
18. pretty Pbhi
19. purse Phe
20. rock wakuak
21. shoe su
22. tea thi
23. thankyou thathi
24. up ?a?
25. yeah ijA
most typical of all the phonetic types for a lexical type. The following rules
seem to work most of the time:
(a) If a phonetic type occurs in a majority of the phonetic tokens, select it.
(b) If there are three or more phonetic types, select the one that shares the
most segments with the others.
(c) If there are two phonetic types, select the one that is not pronounced
correctly.
(d) If none of the above work, select the first phonetic type listed
We can see how these rules work by attempting to select the most typical
phonetic types in Table. 6.26. Rule (a) will apply in ‘ice’, which has the
phonetic types [arJ’] (two tokens) and [?a]. Since the former occurs in more
phonetic tokens than the latter, it is selected as the phonetic type. Rule (b)
will operate for ‘allgone’. The medial consonant that is most typical is ‘k‘
because three out of four phonetic types have a stop, and two out of three of
the stops are [k]. Three of the phonetic types end in [o], so it is the most
typical vowel. The only phonetic type with both of these is [?okho]. There
are no examples where rule (c) would apply in Table 6.25. An example
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 205
Table 6.28 The criterions of frequency for marginal, used and frequent
consonants at selected sample sizes
(‘Normally, we want to avoid including a sound that only occurs once, even as marginal. An
exception is made for samples with 37 or fewer lexical types because the database is so
small.
would be if ‘dog’ were [dag] and [da]. The latter is selected by rule (c), for
we want to be conservative in our claims about the child’s ability. Lastly,
rule (d) will operate if the other rules do not apply. For ‘paper’, for example,
it would select [etJa]. Table 6.27 gives the abbreviated phonological lexicon
for T at session VI. (Imitations are included.)
The child’s phonetic inventory is determined separately for word-initial
and final consonants. Example (6.11) gives the initial and final consonants
that occur in Table 6.27 along with the phonetic forms in which they occur:
(6.11) Initial consonants Total phonetic forms
b- bibi, bau, bija bja, be 4
p- phadi, phat, phe (2 tokens), pghi 4
d- d a 1
t- thi, t h a thi 2
3- ?okho,?a? 2
fricative- ~ u I JGi,
, Ju 3
h- ha1 1
n- nama; no 2
0- 0etSa 1
w- wakuak 1
Final consonants
g- ag
-fricative SUIJ,arJ
-t phat
-k wakuak
-3 ?a?
Sample
Session [m n b d g p t k f s 6 I tl h w] i m n h d g p t k f 0 s I t J d 3 w j r h/ size
I 4
II (?) 5
Only sounds are shown that occur in more than one session, except for IX.
Imitations are not included in the analysis.
Parentheses indicate a single occurrence of a sound
Criterion of frequency for sessions I-VI1 was 2(1); 2 for sessions VIII, IX.
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 209
A phonetic type beginning with [d] was also carried over from a previous
session, i.e. [dzdi] ‘daddy’ (V). Thus, [d] meets the criterion of frequency of
two for used sounds. We refer to such analyses as cumulative phonological
analyses, in that they carry data from previous samples over to the one
under analysis. A second feature of the analyses is that imitations were not
used. These were dropped because it was felt that claims about the child’s
emerging phonological system should only be made in reference to spon-
taneous language. The criterion of frequency for marginal and used sounds
was one and two respectively for all nine sessions, a departure from the
guidelines in Table 6.28 in that there should have been no marginal sounds
for sessions VI11 and IX, due to the sample size. This was changed in order
to present as much data as possible in Table 6.29.
Longitudinal data allow us to add one more important criterion for
defining an opposition:
A phoneme is acquired in the first session in which the criteria (i) and
(iii) are met, if they are also met in all further sessions.
We have circled those sounds in Table 6.29 that meet these criteria. As we
can see, /dl is acquired right from session I. /b/ is next at session V, followed
by /p/ at VI, and It/ at VII. It/ is not circled at session VI because it is a match
in only one lexical type. The last session shows evidence for a /k/,although it
would be nice to see data from subsequent sessions. The data on /s/ are not
as neat. It does not meet criterion (iii) in that there are no [s]s in sessions
VI1 and VIII. During these sessions, and IV for that matter, [s] and [F] are
phonetic alternants. We can circle Is/ at V, then, if we define this phoneme
as having two alternants for the child. The right side of the table shows that
these two are consistently used for adult words with Is/.
T’s data show the following developments:
(6.15) Sessions
I d dental
IV b d labial vs. dental
V b d dental stop vs. dental fricative
S
VI11 b d
p t k velar vs. non-velar stop
S
210 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
It is data like these which can be used to test and elaborate Jakobson’s
theory, as well as others.
They are inductive, letting the data from children contribute to theory,
rather than vice versa. Interestingly, they also cite (p. 438) a form of the
Competence Assumption.
214 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Given all of this, it is not surprising that they emphasize individual
variation and performance factors, both important aspects in Child Lan-
guage. In doing so, they need to explain how the child even reaches a
non-lexical ,systematic phonology. They are consistent in that they suggest
that phonological theory may need to be altered to be more lexical and
individualistic. They even hint at the possibility that all speakers may in a
sense have their own unique phonology.
Most important, however, is the need to explain what is meant by
individual strategy. This term is used throughout the Child Language
literature, but it is not often defined. Ferguson & Farwell never define the
term. They acknowledge (p. 435) that some differences between children
may be due to the linguistic environment, but propose that others are due to
individual strategies. Their definition is by example (p. 436):
Such individual strategies include preferences for certain sounds,
sound classes, or features (‘favorite sounds’); extensive use of redupli-
cation; special markers for certain classes of words, . . ; preferences
for lexical expansion or phonological differentiation at the expense of
the other; and persistent avoidance of particular ‘problem sounds’.
Some of these may possibly be instances of linguistic variation (in the sense
of section 4.5); most, however, seem to be cases of performance variation.
To summarize, Ferguson & Farwell have demonstrated through their
phone class analysis the role of the lexical parameter. At the same time,
though, they also provide evidence through phonological idioms and
salience and avoidance that there is a phonological parameter at work.
Their study, due to the limitations of their method, concentrates on
performance factors and individual variation. We are still waiting, however,
for extensive evidence for or against Jakobson’s theory as a theory of
phonological competence.
Pye, Ingram & List (1987) Quiche is a Mayan language spoken by half a
million people in the western highland region of Guatemala. Its phonologi-
cal inventory is quite different from that of English. Table 6.30 provides the
6.5 The onset of phonemic perception and production 215
Table 6.30 The word-initial consonants of adult Quiche'
Plosives p t, tS tS k q 2
Nasals m n
Liquids r, 1
Glides w j
initial consonants that occur in QuichC. Stops and affricates are grouped
into a category labeled plosives. Quich6 initial consonants differ from
English in the following ways: (i) there is a series of electives (or glottalized
stops; see Ladefoged 1975); (ii) there are uvular and glottal stops /q/ /?/;
(iii) there is no /f/, but there is/x/, the voiceless velar fricative. This system is
sufficiently different from English to lead to some interesting tests of
predictions about phonological development. In section 5.3.1 we examined
Locke's (1983) maturational theory which predicted that there would be no
effects of the child's linguistic environment until some time after the first 50
words acquired (Locke 1983: 84). On the other hand, a constructionist
position such as Oller's (1981) suggests that some modifications due to the
linguistic environment should occur. In particular, Jakobson's theory
predicts linguistic effects after his stage 1 (the very earliest words) since the
child is proposed to have a phonological level of representation.
Phonological data from QuichC children were collected by Cliff Pye as
part of a longitudinal study on acquisition (Pye 1980). He visited QuichC
children in their homes over a nine-month period, approximately every two
weeks, for a one-hour play session. All sessions were tape-recorded and
transcribed by Pye with the help of two native QuichC speakers. In Pye,
Ingram & List (1987) the initial consonants from five of the children were
analyzed using the phonetic inventories method described above. The
sample sizes ranged from 23 to 115 lexical types with a mean of 68. The
children's vocabularies were larger than those of the children studied by
Ferguson & Farwell. According to Pye's morphological analysis (Pye
1983a), however, they were still primarily using single-word utterances.
Table 6.31 presents the phonetic inventories for the five children. Pye,
Ingram & List then determined a composite inventory for the five children,
using procedures for composite transcriptions. This composite phonetic
inventory was taken as representing a basic or core set of consonants that
Table 6.31 Phonetic inventories offive Quiche children, taken from Pye, lngram & List (1987)
Q U I C H ~CONSONANTS
Table 6.32 The rank order frequencies for initial consonants common to
Quiche‘ and English
Sounds
Language /tJ w k p t I n s m r J j/
the number of oppositions or minimal pairs it occurs in. English /g/, for
example, has a smaller functional load than /m/ because /g/ does not occur
initially. Wang & Crawford (1960) have found that English I6l is the second
most frequent fricative. This is because it occurs in a small class of frequent
words, like ‘the’, ‘this’, etc. Its functional load, however, is quite small in
that these words are a small class and subsequently enter into a small
number of minimal pairs. We could change all English /6/into [d]s and still
communicate.
To get an indirect measure of functional load, Pye, Ingram & List looked
at the frequency of English and Quiche initial consonants in terms of lexical
types. For English, we used the 500 most frequently used words of 5- and
6-year-old children in Birmingham, England, based on Burroughs (1957).
Since no adult data are available on QuichC, we had to resort to looking at
the frequency of Quiche initial consonants in the adult word types
attempted by the children. Table 6.32 gives the frequency rank order for
those sounds shared by the two languages. These frequencies seem to
account for the differences quite well. For example, /tJ/ occurs in many
more words in Quiche than in English, while the opposite is true for /SI;/I/ is
also nearly twice as frequent in lexical types in the words Quiche children
use as in English.
This preliminary study provides some suggestive data on the effects of the
input language on early phonological development. Similar analyses on
children acquiring other languages will need to be done before more
definitive conclusions can be drawn. If valid, the data indicate that children
begin during the period of single-word utterances to acquire the phonologi-
cal system of their language. While there may be some articulatory effects
that restrict the child’s production, these effects may be less than previously
expected. The primary factor behind the appearance of a sound in the
child’s early system appears to be its importance in the phonological system
which underlies the words that the child hears. It would not be surprising to
6. The linguistic environment 219
find that languages also tend to assign these highest functional loads to
sounds that are easier to say. We need to be cautious, therefore, in
concluding that the sounds that are acquired later in English are in some
sense harder to say. In some cases, such as /1/ and /tJ/, they may just be not
as important phonologically.
1. (Mother is dressing K in front of the gas fire; K points to fire and speaks)
1;5(10) ‘Aha’ aha
‘Fire’ fa
(Mother points to fire)
‘What’s that?’
‘Fire’ fa
2. (Around bath time, K climbs upstairs, with his mother following him)
1 ;W) ‘Where are you going?’
‘Bath’ ba
3. (The mother is standing by the bureau in which chocolate is kept)
1 ‘I’ve got something nice for you.’
‘Chocolate’ gjga
‘Chocolate’ gjga
4. (Mother is wheeling K s carriage toward a bed of tulips)
1;6(16) ‘What can you see?’
‘Flower’ fafa
(1) Respond to wh-question (provided the answer was already known to the questioner), e.g.
‘What are you eating?’ Nigel: ‘banana’.
(2) Respond to a command, e.g. ‘Take the toothpaste to Daddy and go and get your bib.’
Nigel does so, saying: ‘daddy. . . noddy . . . train’, [i.e. ‘Daddy (give) noddy (toothpaste to
him, and go and get your bib with the) train (on it)]
(3) Respond to a statement, e.g. ‘You went on a train yesterday.’ Nigel signals attention, by
repeating, and continues the conversation: ‘train . . . byebye’ [i.e. ‘Yes, I went on a train,
and then (when I got off) the train went away.’]
(4) Respond to a response, e.g. Nigel: ‘gravel’ Response: ‘Yes, you had some gravel in your
hand.’ Nigel: ‘ooh’ [Le. ‘It hurt me.’]
( 5 ) Initiate dialogue, e.g. Nigel: ‘what’s that?’ Response: ‘That’s butter.’ Nigel repeats:
‘butter’.
The session contained 61 uses of ‘huh’ out of 199 utterances. Two other such
words were ‘tata’, which was used when handing items back and forth, and
‘oooh!’, which indicated excitement.
Another aspect of K s language was that she and her mother (M) would
practice discourse routines. The most striking example occurred in a session
when K was 1;0(26) (p. 276):
(6.19) K: ‘Uncle Ben’ (akhaba]
(I don’t understand and turn to her mother)
M: ‘Uncle Ben’ (whispered to me)
M: ‘Uh huh. Ask her where he is’ (to me)
Me:‘Where’s Uncle Ben?’
K: ‘huh?’
‘Norway’ [i:wei]
M: ‘Norway’ (to me)
K: ‘Norway’ [ni:wei]
Me:‘What’s that?’ (to M)
M: ‘Norway’ (to me)
Me: ‘Norway?’
M: ‘Yeah, that’s where he is.’
K: ‘yeah’ [ja]
In this example, K is clearly too young to have any idea of where Norway is
or even what such an answer would mean to an adult. K’s mother felt that
Uncle Ben’s departure was an important event, and had discussed this at
length with K. Such discourse dialogues allow a mother and child to have
brief conversations, albeit one-sided ones.
Mothers MI M2
Children C, C?
Condition
Measure FP IP
by Schwartz & Terrell. The first measure shows that the child named more
of the frequently presented exemplars than the infrequent ones. There was
then a significant effect of frequency regarding naming. The next two
measures are particularly interesting. They show that the infrequently
presented exemplars were still acquired around the same rate as the
frequent ones, even though they were presented only half as often. This can
be seen by a reanalysis of measure 2. Measure 2 gives the mean number of
presentations that an exemplar needed to be first named. For the
infrequently presented exemplars, they need approximately seven-and-a-
half sessions (since one exemplar was given per session). The frequently
presented exemplars needed approximately six-and-a-half sessions (a
number obtained by dividing the mean of 12.77 and 12.19 by two, the
number of presentations per session). That is, even though the frequently
presented exemplars were presented twice as often, they were only first
named approximately one session before the infrequent exemplars. In these
data, then, rate of presentation appears to be nearly as important as
frequency.
The Schwartz & Terrell study is an insightful attempt to examine the
interaction of frequency and rate. Two reservations, however, need to be
made. First, they did not look at comprehension, only at production: the
next step would be to examine these factors in relation to the child’s growth
of receptive vocabulary. Second, the difference between frequent and
infrequent presentations within exemplars was not particularly great, and
the study, therefore, cannot be taken as definitive evidence against Moerk’s
proposals concerning the short-term effects of massed presentations.
Different results might have occurred if frequent presentations were
increased, say to four presentations per exemplar per session.
While Schwartz & Terrell studied the acquisition of nonsense words,
Della Corta, Benedict & Klein (1983) looked for environmental effects on
the acquisition of English vocabulary. In Section 5.5.3, there are examples
6.6 The linguistic environment 229
from Kaye (1980a) of two mothers, one of whom was very directive while the
other was more narrative. In this chapter, section 6.2.2, we have presented
Nelson’s (1973) analysis of children in this period falling into the groupings of
referential and expressive learners (see Table 6.4). Della Corta, Benedict &
Klein report on a study undertaken to see if the expressive vs. referential
distinction can be accounted for by environmental factors.
To study this issue they conducted a Time 2 study in the sense of the pre-
vious section. They collected 50-utterance samples from 16 mothers during
caretaking situations (diapering, dressing, bathing) with their children. The
children were between 1;3(15) and 1;7 and were divided into either
expressive or referential children. The samples from the mothers of the five
most referential and five most expressive children were then separated for
further analysis. Unfortunately, the authors provide no information about
the measures applied to the children to make this separation. Presumably
the children were only using single-word utterances at the time.
The mothers’ samples were subsequently analyzed for general structural
and pragmatic characteristics; an overview of the aspects measured is given
here:
General measures
(a) MLU; yesho questions; common nouns; 3rd person pronouns;
noun/pronoun ratio; noun type/token ratio
(b) number of utterances per caretaking event
Pragmatic measures
(a) communicative intent (13 measures): labeling; requests for infor-
mation; suggestions; prescriptives; proscriptives; phonological
corrections; referential corrections; description; displaced
speech; conventional social expressions; social play; fillers; other
(b) focus of attention: child- vs. mother-oriented speech; task- vs.
context-oriented speech; indeterminant
Evaluation: approval; disapproval; neutral
For communicative intent, the two categories of prescriptives and descrip-
tion are particularly important as possible sources for the referential and
expressive difference in the children. These two were defined as follows
(p. 38):
Prescriptives: Commands made in an attempt to direct the child’s
behavior or verbalizations, e.g. ‘Put the doll over here’, ‘Say Daddy’.
Description: Statements that describe a person’s behavior, actions,
feelings, appearance, etc. or an object or an event that is present in the
immediate situation, e.g. ‘Mommy’s getting your diaper’, ‘You look
sleepy’.
230 THE PERIOD OF SINGLE-WORD UTTERANCES
Table 6.36 Selected findings from Della Corta, Benedict & Klein (1983)
on the language of mothers of expressive and referential children
Mothers
Referential Expressive
Measures children children
General measures
MLU 4.30 4.03
no. of utterances per caretaking event *20.8 *6.2
other measures no significant effects
Pragmatic measures (mean no. of each category per 50 utterances)
(a) Communicative intent
description *19.6 * 13
prescriptives *6.8 *12.6
requests for information 8.0 8.8
fillers 6.6 6.6
(b) Focus ofattention
child-oriented speech 26.0 31.4
task-oriented speech 8.4 4.98
(c) Evaluation
approval 31.2 24.4
neutral 13.2 20.6
Table 6.36 presents the major results of the study. Concerning general
measures, there were no significant differences between the speech of
mothers of referential and expressive children except for the number of
utterances per caretaking event. Even though both groups of mothers had
comparable MLUs (around 4.0) the referential mothers produced three
times as many utterances. Unfortunately, the study was not designed to see
if this difference would lead to a greater rate of acquisition for the
referential children. (We also do not know if the expressive mothers would
have spoken more to referential children.) Regarding the pragmatic
measures, there were no differences between the mothers on focus of
attention 'or evaluation. There were, however, significant differences on
two of the 13 measures of communicative intent, these being prescriptives
and description. The mothers of referential children used more description,
whereas the mothers of expressive children used more prescriptives. The
authors see the high use of description as a possible source of the high
proportion of general nominals in the speech of referential children. They
do not comment on how the high use of prescriptives would lead to the
relatively high use of personal-social words in expressive children (Table
6.4).
Further reading 231
The study by Della Corta, Benedict & Klein is an example of the
difficulties in doing a Time 2 study in order to determine causal effects. The
authors are aware of this problem, but say nonetheless: ‘Although a causal
inference cannot be made, the findings lend some support to the notion that
the mother’s speech has some influence on that of the child’ (p. 42). Of
course, we can also conclude that their mothers are simply responding to
differences in their children. A more definitive answer will require a Time 1
vs. Time 2 study. In such a case, Time 1would be at some point around the
onset of word comprehension. To date, such studies are quite small in
number; they will be looked at in Chapter 9.
Further reading
Lexical development
The early research on word acquisition (reviewed in McCarthy 1954)
concentrated on onset and rate for the purpose of determining norms of
acquisition. In recent years the research has been interested in developing a
theory of semantic acquisition, in large part inspired by Clark (1973a).
Much of the recent research has concentrated on early word over-
extensions.
McCarthy (1954: 523-34) provides a useful overview of the early studies
on word acquisition. Nelson’s (1973) study has provided the frequently
discussed distinction of referential vs. expressive children, and has inspired
a number of studies. A reading of the first three chapters (pp. 1-56) will
provide the major aspects of the study. Also read two of the studies that
follow Nelson’s study, Benedict (1979) and Rescorla (1980). Lastly, Piaget’s
observations on early lexical acquisition can be found in Piaget (1948) for
Stage V (pp. 52-4), Stage VI (pp. 62-72) and the emergence of signs
(pp. 215-24).
Phonological development
Perception. While relatively little research has been done on phonemic
perception, even less has treated this period of acquisition. Elkonin (1971)
provides a summary in English of the rich literature on research in language
acquisition by Russian psycholinguists. Abstracts of 32 Russian studies are
provided by Slobin (1966) and comprise the major English summary of
Russian research. Most of the literature, however, is unavailable in English
at this time. Most of what is translated can be found in the collection of
articles in Ferguson & Slobin (1973). Thanks to the work of Dan Slobin, the
volume contains seven articles translated from Russian. One of these is an
overview by Elkonin of the famous Russian diary of Gvozdev (1949) of his
son, Zhenya. Another is the study (discussed in this chapter) by Shvachkin
on the development of phonemic perception. Shvachkin’s original study on
Russian children remains the major contribution. Unfortunately, little is
known about Shvachkin. The bibliography done by Slobin (1972) lists four
articles by Shvachkin between 1947 and 1954. According to the index at the
end, the first two articles are on the development of phonemic perception.
Since the latter of these was translated, we can assume that it was the more
important of the two. The last two papers, both published in 1954, are
indexed as studies on syntactic and semantic comprehension. Neither is
summarized in Slobin (1966). Shvachkin’s 1948 paper is valuable for its
creative methodology, descriptive findings, and theoretical proposals. In
the 1970s, a group at Stanford attempted to adopt Svachkin’s method and
Further reading 233
applied it to English children. A brief report of this effort is found in
Garnica (1973). The method was also tried with older children in Edwards
(1974). A different method for the study of phonemic perception was
developed by Eilers & Oller (1976). A general review of the topic for this
period and later ones is Barton (1980).
Production. There is a large and diverse literature on the child’s early
production of words - the text has been restricted to works focussing on the
acquisition of the first 50 words. Much of the literature in the field con-
centrates on children with larger vocabularies than this, usually in the 50 to
150 range.
It is necessary to read Jakobson directly to gain an appreciation of his
proposals for phonological development. Jakobson (1941/68) remains the
major place to begin. The following sections give the most important
discussions of child language: pp. 12-31’46-59’66-81,8491. The revisions
to this original theory are in Jakobson & Halle (1956), section 4 ‘Phonemic
patterning’, pp. 50-5. (A good summary of Jakobson’s theory can be found
in Ferguson & Garnica 1975: 162-9.) The lexical orientation of recent years
can be seen in Ferguson & Farwell (1975), and Stoel-Gammon & Cooper
(1984). An alternative point of view can be found in Goad & Ingram (1988).
Linguistic environment
The 1970s have seen the emergence of the study of the child’s input. In this
time there has arisen an extensive body of works on how adults speak to
their children. We will look at this literature in subsequent chapters. The
Bibliography here is restricted to studies which focus on speech to children
during the period of single-word utterances, and attempts to establish
effects. This limitation results in a much smaller list. The major collection of
articles on linguistic input is that by Snow & Ferguson (1977). An overview
of the topic can be found in Chapman (1981b).
7 The period of the first word combinations
1 ;5 5 1
1 ;6 10 3
1 ;7 14 36 10 15
1;s 24 72 37 33
1 ;9 54 130 - 7 57
1;lO 89 256 108 70 131
1;11 350 - 401 81 272
2;0 1,400 - - 243 575
2;l 2,500+ - 902 458 1,029
refers to the development from MLU 1.0 to 1.5 as early Stage I. Here, we
will retain Brown’s term for this subperiod of the period of the first word
combinations, but alter its measurements. Somewhat arbitrarily, I will
specify this period as having the following boundaries. It begins when the
child has produced 25 recognizable syntactic types (i.e. multiword utteran-
ces). This measure is used because of the difficulty, to be discussed, of
identifying the child’s first multiword utterances. It ends with the syntactic
spurt, which is operationally defined as occurring when the child either has
an MLU of 1.5 or has used 100 syntactic types. At this point there is nothing
of theoretical importance in making these boundaries: their purpose is to
enable us to identify children at this stage in our review of relevant studies.
Most generally, I describe this first subperiod of the child’s first multiword
utterances as one during which the child very gradually develops the ability
to use words in novel combinations.
As with the spurt in vocabulary development, the syntactic spurt does not
necessarily indicate that the child’s linguistic system is now adult-like,
Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975) report on two patterns of syntactic-
semantic acquisition that their subjects followed after the syntactic spurt up
to approximately MLU 2.00 when their systems converged. Results like
these suggest that the syntactic spurt is followed by another formative
period in which fundamental aspects of the grammatical system are being
established. This subperiod roughly coincides with what Brown has referred
to as late Stage I when the child’s MLU is between 1.5 and 2.0. Here we will
define this second subperiod of the period of the first word combinations as
beginning at the end of early Stage 1 (as defined above), and ending when
the MLU reaches 2.0 or when there are at least 250 unique syntactic types.
236 T H E PERIOD O F T H E FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
The latter number is based on the figures in Bloom, Lightbown & Hood
(1975) when the individual patterns seemed to merge. We speculate that the
child begins this second period with possibly an idiosyncratic grammar, and
ends it with a grammar that is much more adult-like.
Eric I1 1;8 Bloom (1970) Most of the syntactic types used are presented with
Gia I 1 ;7 discussion for Eric I1 and Gia I.
Gia I1 1;8 Examples of the 226 syntactic types produced in
Kathryn I 1;9 Gia 11, and of the 226 and the 767 syntactic types in
Kathryn I1 1;10 Kathryn I and I1 respectively.
Allison IV 1;10 Bloom (1973) Entire language sample of 271 utterances is given
in the Appendix.
Kendall I 1;10 Bowerman Lists in the Appendix are given for 102 syntactic
(1973a) types for Kendall I (MLU = 1.10) and 152
syntactic types for Kendall I1 MLU = 1.48).
Andrew 1;7-1;11 Braine (1963a) List of 102 first syntactic types for Andrew, of 33 of
Gregory 1;7-1;11 the first 89 syntactic types for Gregory, and of 82
Steven 1;ll-2;o first syntactic types for Steven.
David I 1;9 Braine (1976) List of 60 first syntactic types (MLU = 1.3) for
David I1 1;lO David I, and 149 syntactic types for David 11.
Jonathan I 1,11 List of 73 first syntactic types for Jonathan I, and
Jonathan I1 2;l 187 syntactic types for Jonathan 11.
Jonathan, and also reanalyses of data from several other published works. It
is both a useful source of data and an important attempt to present a lean
interpretation of children’s early utterances. Braine’s work has included a
series of experimental studies in addition to the observation of spontaneous
speech.
The subjects of these studies represent a large part of the data used to
make observations on the child’s acquisition of grammar during this period.
Table 7.2 gives a summary of the available published data on these
children. Two points are worth making. First, few attempts have been made
to divide development of this period into subperiods, as is done above.
When this is attempted, it is usually based solely on MLU or age. One has to
be very cautious, however, in comparing a child like Gia I1 (where the I1
refers to the sample time) with an MLU of 1.34 with Eric I1 with an MLU of
1.19, when both children were twenty months old. While they appear
similar on these superficial measures, Eric I1 used 37 unique syntactic types
while Gia I1 used 226. By our definition, Eric I1 is at the onset of early
Stage I while Gia I1 is at the end of late Stage I. Such comparisons are
vulnerable to type errors, as discussed in Chapter 3.
A second point concerns the small amount of data on children in early
Stage I as defined above. Many of the samples are for children who already
have 100 syntactic types, e.g. Kendall (see Table 7.2). Bloom (1973)
238 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
exemplifies the problem in getting data on this subperiod. She presents
data for her daughter Allison at four ages, and the numbers of syntactic
types for these four samples are 11,4,19, and 94 respectively. We see that
the first three samples are before this subperiod, and the last one is at its
end. Allison’s data, therefore, tell us little about development up to the
syntactic spurt. Much of the data on this subperiod are from Braine’s sub-
jects. Unfortunately, they are presented without any information about
daily longitudinal changes. We can only conclude, therefore, that our data
on this period remain relatively meager, despite the incredible amounts of
effort expended on collection.
Stage I: Each word has the same intonational contour and a primary stress. It is only their
closeness in time which suggests any relation.
Stage 2: There is still a pause between the words, and each has a primary stress. The terminal
falling pitch of the first word, however, is not as great as that for the second one.
Stage 3: The stress on the first word is weaker than that of the second one, and the pause
between them is reduced (from examples, apparently to less than 500 msec).
Stage 4: There is no longer a pause between the two words. A succession of two words is still
indicated because of (i) the force of the two accents; (ii) frequently a glottal stop occurring
between the two words; and (iii) the terminal falling pitch of the first word.
though, only if we can demonstrate that order is also a feature of the child’s
knowledge at the time when successive single-word utterances are occur-
ring. Evidence so far is lacking in this regard. It may be that children first
understand some basic semantic relations and only later work out their
ordering for the language. Also, there is some evidence (e.g. Braine 1976)
7.2 Grammatical development: an overview 245
that not all early word combinations show such ordering. It may be that the
ordering is really the result of adults imposing adult interpretations upon
children’s utterances, as pointed out by Howe (1976). Even with this
response, it remains the case that the lack of ordering in these sequences is a
potential problem for the rich interpretation as currently presented.
Before concluding this section, there is one last point that needs to be
made about the rich interpretation. While we have used the term ‘rich’, the
view presented is by no means the richest interpretation that could be given.
We could propose, for example, that there is an underlying syntactic
structure, or even that the underlying structure is the grammatical structure
of the adult language being acquired. This is, however, far from the case.
The rich interpretation discussed above is actually quite conservative, and
conforms to the Competence Assumption of Chapter 3. That is, the
competence assigned to the child is based on behaviors such as the child’s
understanding and its use of sequences of single-word utterances. It only
claims that there is some evidence for primitive semantic structures under-
lying the child’s utterances during the weeks before the first multiword
utterances.
Pivotal constructions
Other utterances
Weir (1962) was one of the first to identify different types of sentence
paragraphs. She observed these in the presleep monologues of her son
Anthony between the ages of 26 and 28 months. The three types she found
are build-ups, breakdowns, and completions. In (7.4) these three types are
presented, with examples taken from Bloom’s (1973) corpus of Allison at 22
months of age. Allison had an MLU of 1.73 at this time, placing her in late
Stage I.
248 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST W O R D COMBINATIONS
(7.4) a. Build-ups
‘baby eat’ ‘baby doll ride’
‘baby eat’ ‘baby doll ride’
‘cookie’ ‘truck’
‘baby eat cookie’ ‘baby doll ride truck’
b . Breakdowns
‘walking around’ ‘there baby’
‘around’ ‘there’
c. Completions
‘mommy’ ‘cow’
‘comb hair’ ‘stand up’
In Allison’s data, the build-ups where the child shows the parts of an
utterance before eventually getting them all together seem to be the most
common type. Breakdowns are similar to build-ups except that they are
going in the opposite direction. Both types indicate some awareness of the
parts of the longest sentence produced. There are two extreme explanations
that can be offered as to why the child is producing these. Using the terms in
Peters (1977), we could propose that the child is learning language either
analytically or synthetically. The child is being analytic if she is using rules of
combination to produce longer sentences. The other possibility is that she is
acquiring language synthetically, by learning an entire sentence and then
breaking it down into its different parts. Unfortunately, data like these do
not alone help us to determine which of these is happening. The com-
pletions show less evidence for a single underlying structure. Such an
assumption would be supported, however, if a single utterance such as
‘mommy comb hair’ and ‘cow stand up’ were found elsewhere in the sample.
Although we write the child’s sentences in adult orthography, it is
important to realize that the child is not actually pronouncing most words
‘correctly’. Later we will look at some of the kinds of phonological patterns
children use in this stage, but first we need to examine the implications of
these imprecise speech forms for the child’s speech and for our attempts to
analyze it.
One obvious effect of the child’s incomplete phonology is that there are a
number of child utterances which will be unintelligible. Bloom (1970: 106),
for example, reports that she was only able to elicit 490 intelligible
utterances from Eric in a six-hour visit when he was 20 months, 2 weeks old.
This can be contrasted with the 1,043 intelligible utterances she collected
from him during a comparable sampling six weeks later. His MLU was 1.19
and 1.42 for these two samples respectively, suggesting a noticeable
increase in intelligibility by the end of early Stage I. Also, during the time of
7.2 Grammatical development: an overview 249
I
Ambiguous: a form having two (or more) possible interpretations that can be distinguished or
resolved - for example, ‘Mommy sock’ meaning ‘Mommy’s sock‘ or, alternatively, ‘Mommy
(verb) sock’;
Equivocd: a form having two (or more) possible interpretations that cannot be distinguished -
either one or the other interpretation being acceptable in the particular situation, for example,
‘Mommy iron’;
Indeterminare: a form for which an interpretation cannot be made, most often because of
insufficient evidence;
Anomalous: a form that appears to have no interpretation- the occurrence of an utterance in a
situation to which the linguistic expression bears no apparent relation- for example, Gia eating
peaches and saying ‘no more’.
one word in a sentence, and that they may even relate these semantically.
There was, however, no convincing evidence that they understand gram-
matical morphemes. In the period of the first word combinations, there is
some evidence which suggests that syntactic understanding is taking place.
As with the studies on the earlier period, these studies need to be
interpreted cautiously, owing to the inherent difficulties in testing com-
prehension in young children. Here we will review four studies which
indicate syntactic processing of grammatical morphemes in advance of their
appearance in spoken language. In one of these, we see another method for
determining a child’s grammatical knowledge, that of elicited imitation.
Shipley, Smith & Gleitman (1969) The major features of this study have
already been given in 6.4.1. To summarize: they asked parents of young
children to direct a series of commands to their children which varied in their
syntactic structures. There were three main commands: well-formed (VFN)
‘Throw me the ball!’; telegraphic (VN) ‘Throw ball!’; and holophrastic (N)
‘Ball!’ The children’s responses to these commands were monitored to see if
they would show a preference for one type over the others. Chapter 6 pre-
sented the results of this study with the four holophrastic subjects. We inter-
preted these results as suggestive of some preference for well-formed and
telegraphic commands over holophrastic commands, although this was only
a statistical tendency which did not prove significant.
Here we will present the more clear-cut results that were found for the
second group of subjects who were tested. This second group, referred to as
the telegraphic group, consisted of seven children between the ages of 19
and 32 months, with a mean age of 25 months. Their MLUs ranged from
1.40 to 1.85 with a mean of 1.57. This measure places these subjects in the
middle of the period being discussed in this chapter.
7.2 Grammatical development: an overview 251
Table 7.6 Percentage of times each of seven children in the telegraphic
group in Shipley, Smith & Gleitman (1969) would touch an appropriate
toy in response to each of three constructions
Subject’s Structures
Name Age MLU N(%) VN(%) VFN(%)
Carl 23 1.85 33 33 58
Dottie 19 1.75 15 27 36
Eric 25 1.65 25 28 38
Fran 29 1.48 21 54 64
Gregory 28 1.43 37 25 57
Helen 21 1.41 33 38 62
Ira 32 1.40 50 33 54
Mean 31 34 53
Katz, Baker & Macnamara (1974) We know from Benedict’s study (1979)
discussed in 6.8.2 that specific and general nominals are a prominent part of
the receptive vocabulary of the holophrastic child. The paper by Katz,
Baker & Macnamara is a brief report on research into the question of
whether or not young children know that the difference between proper and
common nouns in English is normally marked by the absence or presence of
an article. In normal usage, proper nouns such as ‘John’, ‘Mary’, and
252 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
Condition
1 30 girls 22 mos. 48 75
25 boys 24 mos. 47 51
2 10 girls 17 mos. 42 76
15 girls 22 mos. 53 72
These are what we will refer to as the active sentences. A second set was
created from these, which we will call the reversed active sentences. These
are the same as those in (7.5) except that the subjects and objects are
reversed, e.g. ‘Make the cat bite the dog’. Two further sets were created,
the passives and reversed passives, which were the 12 active sentences made
into passives, e.g. ‘Make the dog be bitten by the cat’, and ‘Make the cat be
bitten by the dog’.
Each child was tested in two experimental sessions. In each session, the
child was shown 12 toys and asked to act upon them. Each session was
restricted to the testing of either active or passive sentences - pilot testing
indicated that mixing the sentences was difficult for the children. Half of the
children received the active sentences in the first session, and half received
the passives first. Six sentences were tested in each session, with the
presentation of reversed alternates being counterbalanced across children.
Table 7.8 presents the results in terms of the mean percentages of the four
different responses given by subjects in the two groups. ‘Correct’ indicates
that the child processed the sentence as an adult would; ‘Reversed’ indicates
that they reversed the subject and object, i.e. treated actives as passives and
vice versa. ‘Child as Agent’ is a response mode which was not anticipated.
Here the child would do the act itself on either the subject or object,
treating itself as the Agent of the sentence. ‘Refusals’, as expected, is when
the child did not respond to the test sentence.
The results indicate that the early Stage I children are understanding
neither the basic word order of English, nor the passive morphology. Given
the design of the study, we should restrict this to the claim that they could
not understand the constructions embedded in a sentence command begin-
ning with ‘Make’. It is still possible that they could process word order in a
simpler structure, such as ‘The cat is biting the dog’. The high number of
Child as Agent responses suggests that this structure might be having some
effect on their processing. Another possibility, however, and a very
256 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
reasonable one, is that this response is used when the child cannot process
the grammatical structure of the sentence. The 75.5 percent correct
responses of the three late Stage I children indicate that they have acquired
the English word order rule. This leads the authors to conclude that the
‘ability to use word order information in reversible active sentences first
appears in late Stage I’ (p. 338).
De Villiers & de Villiers do not comment on the responses of the subjects
in these groups on the passive sentences, except to say that there was little
evidence that they had acquired passives. It seems to us, however, that the
data in Table 7.8 indicate clearly that they are at least aware that there is
something about passives that is different from actives. The last three
measures, in fact, show evidence to this effect. Our interpretation is as
follows. If the children were treating the passives as actives, then the
percentage of reversals for passives should have been comparable to the
percentage of correct actives. This, however, was not the case, with only 30
percent of the passives being reversed. Instead, they just as often responded
to the passives with Child as Agent responses. This response occurred twice
as often for the passives as for the actives. We saw that this response type
occurred in the data for the early Stage I children as a strategy which was
used when they didn’t yet have the construction being tested. We take this
increased use of the Child as Agent response for passives as evidence that
they recognized these as a form they didn’t know. Lastly, there were twice
as many refusals for the passives as for the actives.
In sum, the data from de Villiers & de Villiers indicate that children are
receptively aware of the role of English word order by late Stage I. Further,
the data suggest that the same children distinguish passives from actives.
The children know that passives are a form that they have not yet acquired,
and respond differentially to it. They show three separate ways to respond
to such a dilemma: (i) treat passives as a form they have acquired, i.e.
actives; (ii) use a non-linguistic strategy such as Child as Agent, Le. when in
doubt, do the action yourself; or (iii) refuse to respond, i.e. ignore the
utterance.
Rodd & Braine (1970) This study examined three main areas of the child’s
grammar during the period of the first word combinations: (i) the gram-
matical morphemes which occur between verb+noun constructions; (ii) the
word order of subjects and predicates; and (iii) subject pronouns. We have
already looked at some information on the first two of these areas of
development, with Shipley, Smith & Gleitman’s research on the first, and
de Villiers & de Villiers’ research on the second. Here, we will address each
topic separately.
As stated, the method used was that of elicited imitation. The sessions
took place in the child’s home, where the experimenter and at least one
parent were present. The parents were instructed as to the nature of the
sentences to be tested, and asked to present them to the child, interspersed
with normal conversation. Rodd & Braine state (p. 432): ‘The model
offered for imitation was most often a question with a rising intonation,
intended to encourage relevant comment or assent from the child; such
comment often took the form of imitation.’ As might be expected, this
method takes time and a certain amount of patience. They found that the
children would imitate approximately one-third of the model sentences,
with variation between children in their interest to imitate. There were two
general kinds of data that were anticipated: they expected that the children
would selectively imitate, avoiding sentences that were not part of their
competence, and that they would show different kinds of imitations to
different constructions.
The first study was with a young boy, Owain, who was 23 months old.
Unfortunately, Rodd & Braine do not tell us much about his productive
language, except that he, as well as the other subjects, ‘had been producing
multi-morphemic utterances for at least a few weeks before the study began’
(p. 432). Owain was presented during two sessions with five kinds of
verb+noun constructions, which are shown in Table 7.9. Two of these,
verb+noun and verb+‘it’+noun, are ungrammatical phrases in English,
but occur in the speech of young children. They state, for example, that the
latter construction occasionally was used by Owain. Owain’s responses
258 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST W O R D COMBINATIONS
Table 7.9 Percentages of occurrence of six kinds of intermediate elements
forfive constructions in the imitations of Owain, based upon Rodd &
Braine (1970: Table 1 )
Verbnoun 74 21 38 38 19 - - 5
Verb ‘a’ noun 53 13 38 23 23 - - 16
Verb ‘the’ noun 64 26 - 65 11 - 8 16
Verb ‘it’ noun 45 14 7 57 14 - - 21
Verb ‘-ing’ noun 12 7 14 - 14 72 - -
a 0 indicates no intermediate element.
were placed into three categories: complete imitations, when the noun and
verb were both repeated with or without additions; partial imitations, with
either the noun or verb omitted; and no imitation. Only complete imitations
were used in the analysis.
Table 7.9 presents the results of this first study, given in the form of the
percentage of times each of six kinds of imitation took place. These six types
are defined by the element whch Owain inserted between the verb and
noun. The first finding was that Owain did not show selective imitation, as
expected. He imitated all models to about the same extent, which was
approximately 33 percent of the time. He did, however, show differential
patterns of imitation. Statistical analysis revealed the three patterns sum-
marized in (7.6):
(7.6) Pattern Dominant element inserted
1. verb ‘-ing’ noun [In1
2. verb ‘the’ noun [dal
verb ‘it’ noun
3. verbnoun @,[a],[dal
verb ‘a’ noun
That is, Owain treated the five constructions as if they were three, with
neither 0 and ‘a’, nor ‘the’ and ‘it’, distinguished from each other. This
supports Shipley, Smith & Gleitman’s finding that children in this period
have some grammatical awareness of the occurrence of morphemes
between verbs and nouns, as well as bearing out their caution that such
awareness does not necessarily mean adult grammatical knowledge. It also
suggests that ‘the’ rather than ‘a’ is the important article in the results of
Katz, Baker & Macnamara.
7.2 Grammatical development: an overview 259
Table 7.10 Number of times that Owain and Carolyn maintained or
changed the word order of two kinds of constructions in their imitations,
based on Rodd & Braine (1970: Tables 3 and 4)
Owain
NP + VP 185 substitution 10 10 0
complete 25 23 2
VP + NP 175 substitution 10 0 10
complete 25 2 19
Carolyn
NP + VP 153 substitution 11 11 0
complete 41 39 2
VP + NP 24 substitution 0 0 0
complete 14 3 11
The second study turned to the issue of the word order of intransitive
verbs and their subject noun phrases. Two types of constructions were used,
as exemplified in (7.7):
(7.7) 1. NPSVP e.g. (The) bird’s flying
Is the bird flying?
(The) bird flying?
2. VP+NP e.g. (He’s) flying, the bird
Is he flying, the bird?
Flying, the bird?
There were two children used, Owain and Carolyn. Owain was 24-25
months old for this study, and was tested over three sessions. Carolyn was
25 months old and tested in two sessions. The method was similar to that of
the previous study. The responses were categorized as in the first study,
except that substitutions were included in the analysis with complete
imitations. A substitution was when the child repeated the NP and VP but
replaced one or the other with a syntactically suitable substitute. The results
are given in Table 7.10, and are very straightforward. Both children
maintained the word order of NP+VP constructions, but changed it in the
VP+NP ones. The results support the findings of de Villiers & de Villiers
that children have acquired some knowledge of word order around 24
months of age.
The third study reports on the imitation of sentences with subject
pronouns. The test sentences were similar to the type 2 constructions in
(7.7), except that the following NP was missing, e.g. ‘He’s flying’. These
260 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
were elicited from Owain and Carolyn during the same sessions that were
used for the second study. They were also given to Owain again when he
was 28 months old. This later data is referred to as Owain2, and the earlier
data Owainl. There was also a third subject used in this study, Christine,
who was tested on the sentences in (7.7) and the subject pronoun sentences
during four sessions at 21-22 months of age.
The analysis of the data for the four sets of sessions (Carolyn, Christine,
Owainl, and Owain2) revealed three patterns of acquisition of the subject
pronouns. These are summarized below, with some relevant percentages
which were used to determine them.
Pattern I : no pronouns. Both pronoun+VP and VP test sentences
elicited most often VP responses, i.e. VPs without a subject (77% and
86% for Owainl, and 61% and 72% for both for Carolyn).
Pattern 2: optional subject prefixes. Pronouns occur with equal fre-
quency for both pronoun+VP and VP sentences (e.g. around 36%
and 27% respectively for Christine), with virtually no NP subjects for
either one.
Pattern 3: obligatory subject pronouns. Pronoun+ VP sentences elicit
a subject, either an NP or pronoun (33% and 38% respectively for
Owain2), and even VP sentences elicit either an NP or pronoun in
33% of the test sentences.
These patterns are presented in a way that suggests a developmental
sequence. The sessions for Owainl show little evidence of any knowledge of
subject pronouns (pattern 1). Christine seems to place the subject pronouns
on both VP and pronoun+VP constructions, suggesting to the authors the
followinp conclusion (p. 439): ‘A plausible interpretation of her total
response pattern is that Christine’s ‘pronouns’ are optional prefixes to
isolated VPs, without referential function.’ While quite an interesting
speculation, it needs to be taken cautiously for at least two reasons. First, if
this were true, one would expect uses of the pronoun in NP+VP test
sentences also, e.g. as ‘NP+pronoun+VP’, which apparently did not occur.
Second, there is no discussion of what would ever lead the child to this
grammar; the English child does not hear optional pronouns. This point is
one that we will return to later. As they stand, however, the data on
pattern 2 provide some evidence for English as being marked for the pro
drop parameter, a point discussed briefly in section 4.5. Pattern 3 is the
pattern expected for the English-learning child. Since we have little
information on Owain’s language at time 2, we don’t know when this change
took place. It seems that he is acquiring some knowledge of the status of
English subject pronouns around the end of this period.
7.3 The grammatical analysis 261
The discussion of pattern 2 by Rodd & Braine contains a particularly
useful exploration of its explanation. The authors propose pattern 2 by
assuming something very close to the Competence Assumption of
Chapter 4.They discuss the alternative that the child may have obligatory
subject pronouns at this time, but that there are performance factors which
inhibit their use. Two possible performance factors are considered. One is
that the child may be constrained to repeat after the adult verbatim, thereby
reflecting the nature of the stimulus sentences rather than its own grammar.
They point out that all the data suggest that the three subjects altered the
model sentences in systematic ways rather than repeating them as pre-
sented. A second factor is that the subjects may have been constrained by
the length of the model sentences. Upon analysis, however, they found no
effect of length of model sentences on the use of pronouns. After excluding
these possible performance factors, they support the analysis of data for the
four sets of sessions as given above.
We can see that this is a very simple grammar, with a small number of rules
and only three classes of words. Andrew has a long way to go to get from
this grammar to that of adult English. There are also 29 of Andrew’s
utterances which are placed into the ‘other utterances’ category. Braine
does not address this problem, but it is one that needs explanation. It is
possible that these utterances are indicative of future advances, or the result
of performance factors. Any theory will need to account for the child’s
productions which are outside the predictions of the proposed grammar.
Braine’s pivot grammar is quite ‘lean’ in the sense used in the previous
section.
Braine’s analysis also gives some insights into the relative importance of
the defining characteristics of the pivot class. Two pivot words, ‘by’ and
‘come’, only occur twice, and three others, ‘I,, ‘see’ and ‘hi’, only occur three
times; frequency does not appear to be as important as positional consist-
ency. The data also show some internal inconsistencies in the analysis. One
sentence, ‘I see’, is a combination of two pivot words, which is a violation of
the theory. Also, the distribution of ‘byebye’ is peculiar. This is a frequent
word which is a likely candidate as a pivot word, yet it appears to occur in
free variation with open class words. Even ‘off’, a final pivot, can be found
in the list of ‘other utterances’ in initial position.
Assessment. At first glance, a pivot grammar has a certain appeal due to
its simplicity and apparent success at characterizing the child’s early
utterances. In the years after its first appearance, however, several investi-
gators began to challenge its validity. Substantial criticisms appeared in
Bloom (1971)’ Bowerman (1973a), and Brown (1973). By the mid 1970s
pivot grammar was generally considered to be discredited. Here we will
briefly review the arguments against it, and then provide a defence on its
behalf.
Brown (1973:97-111) presents three arguments against pivot grammar as
an adequate account of the child’s language at the onset of syntactic
acquisition. The first argument is that it doesn’t even account for Braine’s
original data. We have already commented on the internal inconsistencies
in the data for Andrew. The second argument is against its universality.
Both Bloom (1971) and Bowerman (1973a) found that it was too lean to
capture the grammars of the children they studied. Brown concludes that
the only data that show some support for it are those from children at the
very onset of acquisition. The third argument was on its grammatical 8
7.3 The grammatical analysis 267
adequacy. As we will shortly see, Bloom (1970) pointed out semantic
regularities in early speech that are missed in the pivot account. In
particular, she emphasized the existence of ambiguous sentences like
‘mommysock’ which occurred in different contexts with different meanings
-one as ‘mommy is putting on your sock’, and the other as ‘mommy’ssock’.
Investigators have generally been convinced by these arguments but
some reservations are necessary. First, it is not clear that the theory itself
could not be revised to deal with some of the problems with the internal
consistencies in the original analyses as well as with its application to other
data. This would need to take the form of better criteria for determining the
defining features and their interaction. Also, it needs to be emphasized that
the theory was only designed to apply to the earliest sentences of young
children. Much of the data shown to be inadequately described by pivot
grammars are actually from children who are relatively advanced. The
‘mommy sock‘ example, for instance, comes from Kathryn I who, by our
definition, was at the end of late Stage I with 226 unique syntactic types in
her sample. The data that seem most like pivot grammars, e.g. those of
Eric 11, tend to be at much earlier points of development.
The strength of the pivot approach is that it offers an account of certain
distributional facts about the child’s early word combinations. It also offers
some idea, albeit imprecise, on how the child might achieve such a grammar
from the adult input. The suggestion that the child looks for positional
consistency in frequent words as a basis for building word classes and
presumably rules of word combination is a possible initial learning heuristic.
To make it work, however, requires additional specification about how the
classes and rules get established. In particular, it needs to include the role of
semantic information, and how the child gets from this primitive system to
the adult grammar. Braine (1976), in fact, attempts some revisions along
these lines, and we will look at these later in this chapter.
This grammar has features in common with other grammars written for this
period of development. First, there are a number of optional elements,
since the child’s actual productions are much shorter than the longest
utterance which this grammar can generate. Adam, for example, produced
349 two-word utterances at this time, but only 49 three-word utterances.
Table 7.12 gives information on the grammatical relations which were
attested in Adam’s sample. The grammar is very powerful, therefore, in the
sense that it predicts a lot of utterances which were not attested. Second,
there are no grammatical morphemes, such as prepositions or articles,
represented; the theory implies, in fact, that these will be acquired after the
basic grammatical relations.
Assessment. McNeill’s theory is the first extensive theory on syntactic
acquisition to be proposed. It relies on the child’s innate ability to have and
determine the basic grammatical relations in language by the end of the
period of the first word combinations. It has a developmental component to
it in that it allows for the relations to emerge gradually over several months.
The theory also claims that all children will form the same universal
grammar at this point. It is less clear whether children will necessarily also
show the same order of emergence, but it implies that they will.
The theory has been attacked as assigning too much structure to the child.
If true, it would be in violation of the Competence Assumption. If we look
at the grammar proposed for the end of this period in (7.10) however, we
are hardly looking at the adult grammar of English. We would argue that
McNeill’s proposals are not nearly as rich in their assignment of structure to
the child as has been claimed by some critics. Also, this grammar is not the
one which he would write for early Stage I. He seems willing to accept the
surface patterns that Braine observed for the first multiword utterances.
The difference in Braine’s and McNeill’s grammars for the early data is not
in the number of categories and rules, but in their nature: McNeill wants to
constrain them in ways that make them closer to the adult ones which will
occur later.
We already have some evidence for syntactic processing from our review
272 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
of comprehension studies. The arguments for syntactic relations will need
to fall in large part on internal arguments of McNeill’s theory. That is, the
theory accounts for the emergence of syntax, and in part for the develop-
ment of an adult grammar in a way that pivot grammar does not. Later we
will look at a more recent theory by Pinker (1984) which is similar to
McNeill’s in many ways, but which addresses many of the issues left open.
The use of the Standard Theory as a descriptive tool was probably first
attempted by Menyuk, who wrote transformational grammars for a large
sample of children. The results of these analyses appeared in a series of
articles which are pulled together in Menyuk (1969), which provides a useful
introduction to the kinds of errors and omissions children show across
several years in acquiring the structure of English. The samples from
individual children, however, were relatively small, and no individual
grammars are presented. The first in-depth attempt to write individual
grammars was that of Bloom (1970).
Bloom (1970) The extensive data collected by Bloom have already been
discussed in a general way in Chapter 2 and again at the beginning of this
chapter. Bloom was interested in providing detailed analyses of the early
word combinations from the three children she studied. To do this, she used
the Standard Theory as a method to describe the child’s data. Her concern
was more with describing the children’s grammars, however, than testing
the predictions about language acquisition that follow from trans-
formational grammar. As a result, she changed the formal features of the
theory when necessary to enable it to account for the children’s patterns of
acquisition. The result was a set of grammars for the three subjects which
looked different from one another, and unlike that for adult English. 1
Superficially, Bloom’s grammars appear to fall somewhere between those
of Braine and McNeill. Those on data from early Stage I bear resemblances
to the pivot grammars of Braine, while those from late Stage I data look
more like McNeill’s grammar for Adam. Bloom’s early Stage I grammars,
however, assign more structure than that of a pivot grammar, while those
for late Stage I are less adult-like than McNeill’s, and require more
restructuring to reach the adult model. We will argue that Bloom’s
grammars are more similar to those of Braine and McNeill than is normally
credited.
Before looking at a sample of these grammars, however, we need to
examine Bloom’s procedure for selecting data for analysis. She was very
concerned about keeping close to the data and not assigning structures to
children on the basis of one or two examples. All sentences were assigned to
one of three categories.
7.3 The grammatical analysis 273
Generally, a structure was unique if it occurred only once in the corpus
of a speech sample, marginal if it occurred fewer than five times with
different formatives in different situations, and productive if it occur-
red five times or more. (Bloom 1970: 17)
The grammars presented usually excluded unique and marginal structures,
although these were often referred to in the discussion.
We begin by looking at Bloom’s grammar for Gia I. This sample, collected
when Gia was 19 months, 2 weeks old, yielded 1,015 utterances, with an
MLU of 1.12. Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975) give 55 syntactic types for
Gia I, probably not counting the constructions with [a] to be discussed.
Gia I appears to be in early Stage I, at a point comparable to Braine’s
subjects. One would expect, therefore, that Gia’s grammar would be a pivot
grammar.
Bloom considers two phrase structure grammars for Gia I both of which
are given in (7.11). Examples of the constructions for the first grammar are
listed in Table 7.13 (Bloom uses VB for V, so I follow that practice here).
-{;} } : {
P- ‘more’, “nother’,
Q--,‘more’, ‘another’ ‘hi’, [a]
’Used in two contexts, one when she wanted to scribble again after her book was taken away,
the other when she was scribbling after she had scribbled before.
Used while looking at a picture of a dog running alongside a boy in a toy car.
Used twice, once when fly landed on her blanket, the other when it did so again.
Used twice, once waiting for mother to come back, the other as mother came through the
door.
The advances which are made over this period can be seen by looking at
Bloom’s grammar for Kathryn I. This sample yielded 1,225 utterances over
seven-and-a-half hours. Bloom states (p. 40) that there were 397 multi-
morphemic utterances, presumably tokens, and that the MLU was 1.32.
Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975) identify 226 syntactic types in five-and-a-
half hours of the sample. While the MLU suggests that she is in early
Stage I, the high number of syntactic types places her at the end of late
Stage I, and shows how MLU can be misleading as a measure of syntactic
development. The phrase structure rules for Kathryn I are presented in
(7.12):
7.3 The grammatical analysis 275
(7.12)
1. SI-
2. s2+ Pivot+N
3. VP-
5 . Nom-
( :em
Ng -
Pivot -+ ‘hi’, ‘oh’, ‘OK, ‘thank you’
‘no’
The second formal difference is the NP in Bloom’s first rule for Kathryn I.
This is needed to generate possessive constructions, e.g. ‘mommy sock’
meaning ‘mommy’s sock’, as will be shown below, and subject demonstra-
tives such as ‘this book’ meaning ‘this is a book’. McNeill captures these by
generating two Ns inside of the NP for possessives, and using P+N for
demonstratives, where P is the category symbol for modifiers. He points
out, however, that the latter construction may not be adequate if children
use demonstratives in two meanings, one as a subject of a predicate
nominative, the other as a modifier of a noun. Again, Bloom wishes to
avoid writing a grammar that is too powerful.
Despite being generatively weaker than McNeill’s grammar for Adam,
Bloom’s grammar for Kathryn generates basically the same grammatical
relations as does McNeill’s. For example, there were several cases of the
subject-predicate relation as in ‘mommy push’. Bloom discusses at length
(pp. 62-7) the inadequacy of a simple rule such as S -+ N+N to account
for the child’s early N+N constructions. She argues that there were five
distinct kinds of N+N sentences, based on the context of their use and their
consistent word order. They are each given a distinct underlying structure,
presented here in Figure 7.1. The 0 indicates underlying constituents which
do not appear in the surface structure of the sentence. Two of these
relations, conjunction and locative, are not actually generated by the rules
in (7.12) because they did not meet the productivity criterion of occurring at
least five times.
McNeill’s arguments for the importance of grammatical relations were
based primarily on logical grounds, that is, the innate nature of grammatical
relations provides the child with a starting point for acquisition of the adult
grammar. Bloom, however, was mostly concerned with proving the
existence of these relations on the basis of the child’s data. They arrived at
the same conclusions via deductive and inductive methods respectively, as
these terms were used in Chapter 4.
Bloom (pp. 50-62) describes five tests for proving the existence of these
relations in the child’s language. Each of these tests is summarized below; as
will be indicated, some proved to be better than others.
1. Sentence patterning. If a construction occurs in the same place as its
head without a change of meaning, then there is evidence of a constituent.
For example, if both ‘sock’ and ‘mommy sock’ occur as an object of the
same verb with the same meaning, then they are the same constituent, e.g.
7.3 The grammatical analysis 277
conjunction (2) attribution (6) suhject - object (18)
A A A
N
I
umbrella
N
I
boot
I A
N
0 ADJ N
N
A NP
I I I I
party hat N
I O - I
I
Mommy sock
N NP
I
N
I I
N-
2
I N' l 0
Kathryn sock
0 v
I
PrepP
I
@v N NP
I
Wendy
N
I
e levator sweater
7
chair
Figure 7.1 The underlying structure of five kinds of noun+noun construction for
Kathryn I, along with their frequency (in parentheses), adapted from Bloom
(1970).
'give sock', 'give mommy sock'. This argument was also used by McNeill
(1970b:1079), but was not very helpful for Kathryn's data because most of
her multi-morphemic utterances were restricted to two words.
2. Linear order. If a construction shows the order of the adult construc-
tion, then it has the same grammatical relation. This proves to be a weak
test because some relations have the same order, e.g. subject-object and
genitive, and conjunctions in random order, yet these could be mis-
interpreted as another relation. Another problem with this test, not
mentioned by Bloom, is that adults tend to interpret child speech with the
meanings they would use as adults (Howe 1976).
278 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST W O R D COMBINATIONS
3. Replacement sequences. If the child produces two or more sentences
in a row in the same context, and one is an expansion of the other, then the
shorter sentence has the same relation as the longer one. An example is the
sequence ‘mommy milk’, ‘mommy’s milk’, where the expansion indicates a
genitive relation. This test was first proposed by Braine (1973). These
constructions were not, however, very frequent in the data.
4. Replacement and deletion. This is a variation of the previous test
where expansion and simultaneous deletion indicates the relation. An
example is ‘Baby milk’, ‘touch milk’ where the second sentence suggests
that the first one is subject-object. This proved to be the most valuable
linguistic test.
5 . Non-linguistic context. The use of the non-linguistic context to infer
the child’s intended meaning. This includes the child’s overt behavior and
aspects of the environment at the time of the utterance.
While Bloom’s grammar is more restricted than McNeill’s, it still gener-
ates structures where constituents are proposed which do not occur in the
surface structure of the sentence. This is evident in the cases where 0 occurs
in Table 7.14. While there was evidence that three or more categories were
underlying a sentence, most showed only two at one time. Only four actual
three-term utterances occurred in the data: ‘me show Mommy’, “chine
make noise’, ‘man ride [a] bus’, and ‘I comb pigtail’. These sentences and
the patterns in two-word sentences led Bloom to conclude that Kathryn
had an underlying subject-verb-object order.
The problem arose, then, of how to account for this discrepancy between
the surface and underlying order. McNeill accounted for this by generating
optional subjects and predicates. Bloom does not do this because she wants
to represent the missing elements in the underlying structure of the
sentence. As the grammar in (7.12) currently operates, however, it will
generate surface strings with more categories than are appearing in Kath-
ryn’s language. Bloom adds an additional rule, called the reduction trans-
formation, which deletes one of the categories when three are generated by
the grammar. The selection of the category to be deleted is random, thereby
allowing for the various two-word combinations which appeared.
As pointed out in several places (e.g. Wall 1972; Brown 1973: 234-9), this
rule has several questionable characteristics; here we will briefly mention
two of them. One problem is that it is inconsistent with the formal
properties of transformations. Deletion transformations, for example,
apply in cases where information about the constituent deleted can be
‘recovered’ through other constituents in the surface structure. For
example, subject pronouns in languages like Spanish and Italian can be
deleted because information about the person of the sentence can be found
in the agreement affixes on the verb. No such recoverability, however,
operates in the case of the reduction transformation. Another problem is
7.3 The grammatical analysis 279
that the rule violates the Constructionist Assumption. It is a rule that is
unique for this period, and which will be lost in later acquisition. Brown
(1973: 239) points out the peculiarity of having development proceed ‘from
the more complex to the less complex’. The rule’s real effect is not to map
from deep to surface structure, but rather from surface structure to speech.
That is, it is really a description of a performance factor which limits the
number of constituents that the child can say at one time. As a performance
factor, its eventual loss also becomes easier to understand.
Assessment. Bloom’s grammars are an important empirical attempt to
verify the existence of basic grammatical relations underlying children’s
early word combinations. They show that these relations are difficult to
establish in the earliest data, but that they exist at a more advanced level
such as that of Kathryn I. Importantly, this finding is based on evidence
found in the child’s language, not just of logical arguments following from
the theory of transformational grammar.
These grammars are also a serious attempt to restrict the generative
power of grammars for children in this period. While they go beyond the
restrictiveness of pivot grammars, they are less powerful than the grammars
of McNeill. As such, they are the first extensive attempt to implement the
Competence Assumption in writing formal grammars for children. Like-
wise, postulating the reduction transformation is a pioneering attempt to
provide some justification for the discrepancy between the child’$proposed
underlying grammar and its surface manifestation. The fact that the formal
properties of these grammars may be criticized should not take away from
the importance of their contribution.
No of
Age utterance
Child Sex (months) MLU types” Language Investigator
LOC --
Proloc
{ PNroloc
‘tuossa’ (‘there’)
The later grammar for Seppo at 26 months showed a number of advances
over the earlier one. Some of the more noteworthy are as follows: (1) while
the previous grammar was primarily restricted to two-word strings, three-
word strings became more frequent; (ii) modifier-noun strings could now
be embedded within subject and object NP; (iii) locatives could now
co-occur with object NPs; and (iv) new constructions that appeared
included (a) the use of adverbs with the previous constructions, and
(b) copular sentences. There was still no evidence of the development of
inflectional morphology. The flexible word order of adult Finnish also
became more evident. Bowerman includes optional transformations which
allow for each of the following reorderings of constituents from their
unmarked orders: reversal of prolocative and object NP; reversal of’verb
and direct object, locative, or adverb; reversal of subject and verb; and
movement of adverb or prolocative to front of sentence. Rina’s grammar at
approximately the same MLU showed several, but not all, of the same
features. Rina did show the same degree of variable word order. Impor-
tantly, the distribution of the varying orders of constituents for both
children correlated with that of their mothers.
Bowerman uses these data to argue against the existence of two gram-
matical aspects of the child’s grammar at this time. Specifically, she wants to
argue that there is no evidence for the existence of either the constituent
7.3 The grammatical analysis 283
Table 7.15 A summary of Bowerman’s (1973~)arguments against the
existence of a VP in children’s grammars
Children should respond to questions like No evidence exists that this is the case.
‘What’s it doing?’ with VPs.
V and V + N utterances in child speech should The data indicate that V shows the same
show the same privileges of occurrence. privileges of occurrence with V + N and
N+V.
The use of ‘do’ as a pro-verb for VP,e.g. as in Such sentences are not found in the language
‘daddy like cake. mommy does too.’ samples of children during this period.
V + N utterances are more frequent in the The data from Rina, Seppo, and Kendall
speech of children at this time than N+V show the opposite (Table 16 in Bowerman
strings. 1973a).
In replacement sequences with verbs, The data from Rina, Seppo, and Kendall
children will first expand to an object NP show both kinds of replacement sequence.
before adding a subject NP.
VP, or the relation ‘subject’. The hrguments are built upon a version of the
Competence Assumption. The first set of arguments are against the
postulation of a VP. These are summarized in Table 7.15. These arguments
claim that there is no valid test available to establish the existence of a VP.
Those tests based on frequency are inadequate, because they would lead to
the conclusion that subject and verb form a constituent for Seppo, Rina,
and Kendall, since subject+verb constructions for these children were more
frequent than verb-kobject ones.
A second set of arguments are made against the existence of the
grammatical relation ‘subject of’. Bowerman considers two reasons why the
notion of subject is needed in a grammar, and argues that neither of these
yet exist for the developmental data. One reason for subject is that it is
needed for certain grammatical transformations like Passive, where the
underlying subject becomes the surface object. This is not the case for this
period, because children at this time are not producing constructions like
the passive which require this category. The second reason is for the
operation of rules like Verb Agreement, Subject Pronominalization, and
Case Marking (in Finnish). Again, there is no evidence yet in the child’s
sentences for the operation of these rules. She comments that the assign-
ment of subject to the child’s early sentences is imposing our adult
knowledge of the language upon the child. She concludes that the data only
support the postulation of sequenced semantic categories.
Brown also provided an in-depth review and critique of pivot grammar, the
Standard Theory, and case theory. Like Bowerman, he took the position
that the primary development during this period is the acquisition of a basic
set of semantic relations, which are the building blocks of later develop-
ment. His work extended that of Bowerman, however, in attempting to
determine the set of semantic relations that children have.
Brown’s study of children’s semantic relations consisted of analyzing the
data from 24 language samples collected from 18 children. While the bulk of
the data are from English, there are also samples from Finnish, Swedish,
Samoan, and Mexican Spanish (see Brown 1973: 66, Table 9 for details).
He also used a second set of data from 17 children acquiring American
English, French, German, Hebrew, Japanese, Korean, Luo, and Russian.
These data are secondary in that there is less information on these samples
than the others. The two sets of data together constitute a broad base from
which some general statements can be made.
7.3 The grammatical analysis 285
Brown’s analysis resulted in the claim that there are 11 kinds of semantic
relations that underlie the child’s early word combinations, divided into two
subtypes. First, there are the operations of reference. These are relations
where one term defines a property for a set of arguments. Brown specifies
three of these, which are defined here in Table 7.16. An example would be
Gia’s category of ‘recurrence’ discussed above for the grammar in (7.11).
The words marking recurrence, such as ‘more’, define a property of
nominals, in this case that they are repeated or occur in several instances.
Brown proposes that these are the relations that create the pivot look of
early grammars. The second subtype is a set of eight prevalent semantic
functions or relations. These relations consist of the categories that semanti-
cally underlie the grammatical relations such as those in (7.9). These are
called ‘prevalent’ because these are the ones that occurred in the samples
discussed above; Table 7.16 also gives definitions and examples of these.
In Brown’s analysis, all of the multi-morpheme types used by the first
group of subjects were categorized according to their semantic relations,
using the kind of evidence discussed above for Bloom. For purposes of
analysis, he collapsed Nomination with Demonstrative and Entity. The data
were scored according to the percentage of each child’s multi-morphemic
types which fell into each semantic relation. Brown found that the eight
‘semantic functions’ or ‘prevalent relations’ accounted for approximately 70
percent of children’s utterances (Brown 1973: 174, Table 22). Two of the
relations, Agent+ Object and Entity+Locative, were somewhat marginal,
in that neither constituted over 9 percent of any child’s sentences by this
measure.
Brown goes on to propose that this particular set of relations occurs
because they represent the knowledge acquired about the world during the
period of sensorimotor development. He states (p. 200): ‘Representation
starts with just those meanings that are most available to it, propositions
about action schemes involving agents and objects, assertions of nonex-
istence, recurrence, location, and so on.’ Since they are part of every child’s
early representation, they are also proposed as being universal. That is,
every child acquiring language will show the same relations.
Another important feature of Brown’s study is his comparison of
two-term and three-term multi-morpheme relations. He found that there
were two ways in which his subjects expanded their constructions. These are
what he calls concatenation-with-deletion and expansion-of-one-term.
Concatenation-with-deletion is the case where two appear to combine, with
the shared term being deleted in one of them. An example would be the
combination of Agent+Action with Action+Object to form a new
Agent+Action+Object construction. Expansion-of-one-term is the case
where categories that are NPs are expanded. For example, the Object in an
286 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
Action+Object construction will expand to also mark Possessor+Possess-
ion, as in ‘hit ball’ expanding to ‘hit Adam ball’. The latter type is
particularly of interest because such utterances can be taken as evidence of
an emerging NP structure. Brown’s analysis of these indicates that they are
relatively rare, only appearing toward the end of Stage I.
The above analysis led Brown to propose the law of cumulative com-
plexity :
It predicts that any child able to construct x+y will also be able to
construct either x or y alone. It does not predict . . . that a child able to
construct both x and y, severally, will be able to construct x+y. There
is evidently, and this is simply an empirical discovery, some additional
knowledge involved in putting the component items of knowledge
together to make a more complex construction. (Brown 1973: 186)
The fact that Brown does not want to make this law predict the existence of
x+y on the basis of the separate occurrences of x and y shows the
conservative stance which Brown takes about the child’s grammatical
knowledge. For example, he does not want to propose that the child has an
Agent+ Action+Object structure ( x + y ) on the basis of observing
Agent+Action ( x ) , and Action+Object 01).In this way he is more cautious
than Bloom, who does just that. A further feature of this law is that it is also
quite similar to what we have called the Constructionist Assumption. It
relates the structures at one point in acquisition to those which have
preceded them.
Braine (1976) Another study which takes issue with the semantic rela-
tional analyses of that time is Braine (1976). Like Howe, Braine feels that
the number of semantic distinctions in child speech at the onset is much
smaller than those proposed by others such as Brown (1973). Unlike Howe,
he believes that these meanings are more specific, rather than more general.
In Braine’s view, the child sentences first express a small set of very specific
meanings that will vary from child to child. This position looks very much
like a revision of pivot grammar which takes into account the intended
meanings of the child’s sentences. Due to the extent of the data analyzed
and the methodological care taken, Braine’s study has had a major impact
on the analysis of early grammars. Here we will look at the results of his
study, as well as his methodology.
Braine conducted grammatical analyses on 16 corpora from 11 children
acquiring either English, Samoan, Finnish, Hebrew, or Swedish. Several of
these corpora have been discussed already. Collectively, they are children
who tended to be in early Stage I in our definition of this stage. The fact that
these children were at a relatively early point in grammatical acquisition
becomes important when we compare the results with the other studies we
have reviewed. Table 7.17 provides some information about the children
studied.
Of particular importance are the methodological procedures Braine used
in his analysis. First and foremost, Braine was very strict in setting criteria
for the existence of rule-based behavior. H e examined two properties in
making decisions of this kind - positional consistency and productivity.
Positional consistency refers to the requirement that a proposed pattern
reflect a strict ordering of its constituent parts. This property is never fully
justified but presumably follows from the assumption that children acquir-
ing languages with strict word order will use that in their first rules. In
specifying this, Braine also was responding to the earlier criticisms of pivot
grammar that no criterion was used to determine if a morpheme was
occurring in a fixed position or not. Positional consistency is operationally
defined as follows:
While they meet the criterion of positional consistency, they do not meet
that of productivity. Braine states (p. 8):
It is unlikely, however, that the pattern is productive for the following
reason: because the set of English words that can co-occur with,‘all’is
rather small . . . it would follow that, if Andrew had some formula for
making combinations with ‘all’, one should expect that his use of the
formula would yield some . . . strange combinations he could not have
heard.
Since this is not the case, however, Braine places these into the positional
associative category. Lastly, Braine analyses the sentences with ‘all gone’
and ‘all done’ as examples of a groping pattern. They are small in number
and show variable word order. He also claims that they were uttered
‘hesitatingly’ (p. 11).
Braine did not write grammars for his data, but presented his results in
the form of lists of utterances grouped according to their semantic consist-
ency. Table 7.17 presents a summary of these semantic taxonomies. It gives
the meanings Braine proposed for each of the 11 children he studied along
with its pattern. This somewhat lengthy summary is given because his
analysis remains the most rigorous cross-linguistic grammatical study con-
ducted on this period. Also, the results of his analysis indicate the extent of
individual variation that appears to characterize early grammars once strict
criteria on productivity are applied.
When we compare the meanings used, we see that certain ones are more
frequent than others. Actor/Action, Possession, Location, and Identifica-
tion are the most frequent, followed by Recurrence and Requests. This is a
shorter list, however, than the one given by Brown. Importantly, Brown
was putting together a composite list, not trying to specify which patterns
would occur with individual children. Brown’s own data, in fact, show
variation of this kind, which Brown discusses. Each child appears to differ in
the meanings it selects for expression. Even though the labels suggest
comparable meanings, Braine also emphasizes that individual children may
restrict these in their own ways. These meanings are not universal €or
Braine in the way that they are for Brown. Braine states (p. 57): ‘Children
differ considerably in the kinds of contents expressed by their productive
patterns and in the order in which they acquire them.’ He points out, for
example, that there is virtually no overlap between Andrew’s patterns and
those in Kendall 11.
We have already discussed the issue of individual variation in regard to
phonological acquisition in 6.5.4. We pointed out then that the individual
differences claimed after analyses using the phone classes and phone trees
approach could be explained as a measurement sequence, i.e. that
7.3 The grammatical analysis 291
Table 7.17 Summary of the subjects, meanings, and patterns found in
Braine (1976)
Children and
information’ Meanings Patterns
’ These are only given for children not previously discussed in the text.
Data used to exemplify the kinds of patterns found. The meanings of individual patterns are
not usually given.
Braine actually labels these as Possessives for Kendall 11, but states in the text that he uses
‘Possessives’ and ‘Possession’ interchangeably (p. 16).
Braine speculates that ‘here’ was a positional (final) pattern at Kendall I, and that Kendall
has now learned that ‘here’ and ‘there’ can occur initially and finally.
Also called Class Membership.
There are several action phrases in the data without an agent, and with the object either
before or after the action word. Braine does not actually include these in his analysis because
the semantic basis for it is unclear.
’ Translated by Kernan as either ‘and’, ‘with’, or ‘for’. Braine is not sure if these are one or
several semantic patterns.
The basic word order in Samoan is Verb-Subject-Object although it is variable. Braine
+
combines Agent Action and Noncausative Movement Verbs (e.g. ‘pa’u:’ meaning ‘fall’) +
Object Moved in this pattern. He feels that the child makes a distinction between causative and
noncausative verbs, with the nominals having some kind of agent role.
+
This pattern includes Causative Movement Verbs Object Moved, and other transitive
Verb + Object sentences. The nominals are speculated as being Patients, i.e. objects affected.
lo These were semantically peculiar in that the color words were not used correctly.
Braine speculates that the nature of these sentences are such that they could be collapsed
+
with the Object Locative pattern on a semantic basis.
l2 Exact ages are not given, but the first samples were around 21-22 months, and the second
ones around 22-23 months.
7.3 The grammatical analysis 293
approach gives a lot of importance to infrequent and idiosyncratic data. We
can now ask if Braine’s method does the same. In fact, by setting strict
criteria for what is considered a productive pattern, Braine has developed a
method which should minimize individual variation. Given this, his finding
of individual variation needs to be taken quite seriously.
Braine takes these grammars as an indication that children begin acqui-
sition by developing a small set of meanings for expression. These meanings
may be quite narrow, and have one member restricted to a single word, as in
David 1’s Identifying form ‘here’ or his Request expression ‘want’. Since
these early patterns appear to be independent, he doesn’t even want to call
them ‘rules’, since the latter implies the features of a generative grammar.
Instead, he calls them formulae of limited scope. They only become more
general as formulae with similar meanings are acquired.
Braine also accepts Bowerman’s criticisms against assigning a trans-
formational grammar to the child at this stage, but adds a third argument.
He gives the example of Kendall who acquired ActodAction as one of his
first productive patterns. According to the syntactic approach this should
lead to the rules:
rule 1 S- NP+VP
rule2 VP- (V)+(NP)
rule 2’ VP -
When the child acquires locatives, rule 2 would be then changed as shown:
Locative
Since the order of the subject in relation to the locative is done by rule 1,
then locatives should appear with appropriate ordering. The data from
Kendall and Seppo, however, indicate that Locatives were a groping
pattern at the time when ActodAction was acquired. These data, then, are
taken as evidence against the syntactic explanation of early word combin-
ations.
Assessment. Braine’s monograph is an important methodological and
descriptive contribution to our knowledge about early word combinations.
Its methodology is a major step towards extracting the productive utteran-
ces from a spontaneous language sample. The results of his analyses are an
impressive set of observations that require explanation. It appears that
children can be quite different in their selections from the set of meanings
which they could express. These data are quite a problem for any theory of
acquisition which states that all children begin in the same way.
We see two major limitations to Braine’s account of early word combin-
ations. One concerns the restriction of the data being considered to
spontaneous speech samples. While Braine is adhering strictly to his version
294 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST W O R D COMBINATIONS
of the Competence Assumption, our formulation of it does not restrict data
in this way. Information about the child’s receptive knowledge as well as
other forms of expressive language can and should be used. We have
already seen the viability of the imitation technique in Rodd & Braine
(1970), and will explore still others in Section 7.5. The second limitation is
that it avoids accounting for how the child ever gets from this kind of
grammar to an adult one. Braine briefly discusses this fact toward the end of
his study (pp. 88-9). He correctly points out that there is no inherent
discontinuity in development in his proposals, should adult grammars be
different from the current syntactic models being considered. Only
additional research on later development will find if and when discontinuity
occurs.
Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975) The last study done during this period
of initial research into semantic relations is that of Bloom, Lightbown &
Hood (1975). Like the previous studies, it was concerned with examining
the language samples of young children for the kinds of semantic relations
which occurred. Its goals in doing this, however, extended far beyond
simply identifying a set of relations. They wanted to answer the last problem
just expressed concerning Braine’s study, i.e. how and when does the child
go from a semantic grammar to a syntactic one? They make this point very
clearly (p. 1) when discussing semantic relations:
It should not be surprising that these are the kinds of things that
children first learn to talk about. However, the linguistic means that
children learn for the representation of such notions, the sequence of
development in child grammar, and the relation of systems of child
language to the adult model remain to be determined.
In essence, this was an attempt to reconcile the apparent difference between
the proposals of McNeill (1970b) and Bloom (1970) with the results of the
studies by Bowerman (1973a), Brown (1973), and de facto Braine (1976).
That is, when does the child change from a semantic grammar to a syntactic
one? Or, stated differently, when does the child shift from semantic
categories (e.g. Agent) to syntactic ones (e.g. subject)?
The study was done by examining the spontaneous speech samples of four
children: Eric, Gia, Kathryn, and Peter. The first three children were the
ones studied in Bloom (1970), while Peter’s data were collected in a similar
fashion at a later time. Several samples were obtained from each child while
they were approximately 19-25 months of age (see Table 1 in Bloom,
Lightbown & Hood 1975: 7). Their MLUs across the samples ranged from
1.04 to 2.83. Based on the children’s MLUs, the authors felt that the
samples presented data from all four children on both early and late Stage I,
7.3 The grammatical analysis 295
Table 7.18 Number of syntactic types for each sample period of four
children studied in Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975:7, Table 1); the
number of the sample period, and its MLU, are shown in parentheses
Ranges of
syntactic
types Peter Eric Gia Kathryn
as defined by MLU values in Brown (1973), as well as Stage 11. This is so, as
can be seen by examining their MLUs, which are given in Table 7.18.
Recall, however, that we have challenged this definition at the beginning of
this chapter, and have defined the periods in Stage I by the number of
syntactic types as it interacts with MLU. Table 7.18 presents the four
subjects based on their number of syntactic types.
Table 7.18 reveals that these four children’s samples do not equally
represent both early and late Stage I, at least by our definition. There are
nine samples with 108 or fewer syntactic types, placing them in early
Stage I. Eight of these nine are from Peter and Eric. After a gap between
108 and 226 syntactic types, there are four samples between 226 and 288
which could be placed into late Stage I, assuming some flexibility in
interpreting our measure. Three of these four are from Gia and Kathryn,
and none are from Eric. The rest of the samples are beyond this range and
are in Stage I1 from our perspective. In other words, most of the early
Stage I data are from Eric and Peter, and most of the late Stage I data are
from Gia and Kathryn. This observation is important when we come to
analyze their data. We will only present their results regarding semantic
relations for those samples which fall within these two periods by our
definitions of them.
Bloom, Lightbown & Hood determined a semantic relation for each
syntactic type in the data. They did not use a predetermined list of relations,
296 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
but instead let the data reveal the meanings. Like Braine, they did not
provide a set of explicit criteria for this task, but imply as Braine does that
the meanings are in some way self-evident. They state (pp. 7-8):
These nine relations are remarkably similar to the frequent ones found by
Braine (1976). The primary differences appear to be in name. Braine’s
Requests and Identifications are classified here as State and Existence
respectively. Their terminology for locatives also differs. Braine refers to
Locative Actions as Movement-to-Locatives. Lastly, Negation occurs with
two of Bloom, Lightbown & Hood’s subjects, but it is not as frequent in
Braine’s data. Generally, though, there is a great deal of overlap.
Table 7.19 presents the acquisition of these relations by the four children
studied, divided into early and late Stage I. Like Braine’s study, the data
from Bloom, Lightbown & Hood reveal a certain degree of individual
variation. Even so, there are patterns which emerge. We can see this by
requiring that a relation exists when at least two children acquire it.
298 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
Table 7.19 The productive semantic relations for early and late stage I for
Eric, Peter, Gia, and Kathryn, adapted from Bloom, Lightbown & Hood
(1975: 15, Table 2). Relations are shown with the sample in which they
first appeared
Children
Early I: 111, IV I1 I
Action Action Existence
Recurrence Negation Recurrence
Attribution Existence
V I11
Locative Action Locative Action
State
Recurrence
Attribution
Late I: VI I1 I
Locative State Action Action
Locative Action Locative Action
Possession State
Attribution Existence
Negation
111 Recurrence
Locative State Possession
Attribution
Applying this measure to early Stage I, the following patterns appear in this
subperiod: Action, Recurrence, Existence, Locative Action, and Attri-
bution. The fact that two of the children show developmental changes even
allows us to impose an order to these. Action, Recurrence, and Existence
appear first, followed by Locative Action and Attribution. Given the
individual variation involved, however, we can only state this as a statistical
tendency. In late Stage 11, Locative State, State, Negation, and Possession
also meet our criterion. The data also indicate that there is an acquisition
order which is exceptionless in the data: Actions are acquired before
Locative Actions, which are in turn acquired before Locative States.
Bloom, Lightbown & Hood discuss these data in terms of their impli-
cations for the child’s grammar, particularly as evidence for the emergence
of the grammatical category of ‘subject’. First, several of these relations
involved initial nominal categories, i.e. Action, Locative Action, Locative
Ranges of
syntactic Peter Eric Gia Kathryn
types agent object agent object agent object agent object
0-50 - - - -
- - - 0.67
51-100 - - - -
0.86 0.74
0.75 0.89
101-150 0.88 0.78
151-200
201-250 1.00 0.64 0.00 0.05 0.17 0.08
25 1-300 0.01
301-350
351-400
401-450 0.75 0.49
451-500 0.76 0.45 0.06 0.12
over 500 0.77 0.39 0.77 0.30 0.08 0.34
0.57 0.38
Calculations are shown only for cases where Jive or more instances occurred.
children’s initial rules were solely semantic. Bloom, Lightbown & Hood
state (p. 28): ‘The kind of evidence that both Bowerman and Schlesinger
might accept in order to attribute such knowledge of grammatical relations
to the child would be the occurrence of superordinate categories whereby
words in the same syntactic position took on different semantic functions
relative to one another.’ They interpret the gradual and consistent spread of
initial nominals to different semantic roles as evidence for the syntactic
category of subject. In Kathryn I, for example, the subject of sentences
could be either an agent (in Actions), mover (in Locative Actions),
possessor (in Possessions), or object (in Locative States).
Besides examining the emergence of semantic relations, Bloom, Light-
bown & Hood looked into the acquisition of pronouns and nouns by their
subjects. They observed that the two boys, Eric and Peter, tended to mark
the semantic roles accompanying actions with pronouns. The two girls,
however, did so with nouns, and did not show pronouns until later in
development. This pattern was consistent for Possession, Action, and
Locative Actions. It was demonstrated by counting the number of times a
possessor, agent, mover, affected object, or place was indicated by either a
noun or pronoun in syntactic types. Here we will present their results
somewhat differently, using the format of Table 7.20, and a different
measure than absolute numbers. For each semantic role, I calculated the
300 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST W O R D COMBINATIONS
proportion of pronouns, which is the proportion of times that the child in
any sample used a pronoun instead of a noun. These data are presented in
Table 7.20 for the agent and affected object roles of Actions. Both Eric and
Peter used pronouns predominantly until they were beyond Stage I. The
opposite was the case for Gia and Kathryn who used predominantly nouns.
All subjects eventually acquired the other category by the latest samples
where their proportions are relatively similar.
Bloom, Lightbown & Hood interpret these results as indicating that there
are two distinct strategies that children may use in acquiring an early
grammar. One is the categorization strategy which was used by Gia and
Kathryn. The girls used the semantic relations of early sentences to abstract
grammatical relations such as ‘subject’ and ‘predicate-object’. This strategy
has come to be known in more current literature as semantic bootstrapping.
We will examine this notion more carefully later, but essentially it claims
that the child’s language acquisition device looks for semantic roles which
pattern together for the purpose of forming more abstract categories. As
pointed out by Bloom and her colleagues (p. 32), these may not initially be
adult-like. Gia and Kathryn’s initial subject included possessors as well as
agents and movers. Even so, it presumably will restrict the possibilities
available in ways which are unknown at this time.
The second strategy is the pronominal strategy which was proposed for
Peter and Eric. This strategy is one which bears similarities to the early
pivot grammars and Braine’s more current view of formulae. Here we will
refer to it as an alternative to semantic bootstrapping which accounts for
early development by distributional learning. The children’s pronouns
operated like pivots with each marking a particular meaning. Peter and
Eric, for example, used ‘I’ to indicate agents, ‘my’ for possessors, ‘it’ and
‘this one’ for affected objects, and ‘here’ and ‘there’ as locations. If the
children were acquiring pronouns semantically for the purpose of estab-
lishing grammatical relations, we would expect a very different pattern.
Some pronoun such as ‘my’, ‘me’, or ‘I’, for example, would be expected to
represent several semantic roles as the subject, much the same as ‘Mommy’
did for Kathryn. We would then expect mistakes in their use until the adult
pronominal case system was acquired. This did not happen, however, and
instead the pronoun functioned as a formal marker of the individual
semantic role of the word with which it occurred.
If these pronouns are not leading to grammatical relations, what do they
help the child to acquire? As given in our discussion of pivot grammar, they
allow the child to acquire the grammatical classes of the language. For
example, the child might begin by identifying ‘it’ as a frequent morpheme
which occurs after a number of action words which it knows. ‘It’ then comes
to define that particular class as ‘words which occur with ‘‘it”’. Eventually,
7.3 The grammatical analysis 301
as other properties are added, this becomes the class of English transitive
verbs. Another morpheme such as ‘the’ comes to identify the common
nouns. Only later will more detailed information be acquired about these
initially formal markers.
These two strategies lead to very different theories of early acquisition.
The categorization strategy (or semantic bootstrapping) leads to early
identification of grammatical relations, with subsequent distributional
learning. For example, the early identification of lexical items which
function both as agents and movers establishes an early category of subject.
Presumably Universal Grammar or subsequent distributional learning leads
to grammatical classes like noun or noun phrase. The pronominal strategy
(or more general distributional learning) predicts early specific learning of
positional word classes which develop eventually into grammatical cate-
gories, then grammatical relations. For example, words which occur with
‘it’ become verbs, and subsequently function as the predicate in the
predicate-object relation. In Section 7.5 we will look in more detail at a
recent proposal of this kind.
Assessment. The Bloom, Lightbown & Hood study was an important
first attempt to reconcile the discovery of semantic relational meanings in
children’s early word combinations with earlier proposals for the existence
of a syntactic grammar. They pointed out the need to account for the
transition to an adult grammar, and provided a major argument in support
of the existence of grammatical relations. This argument was empirically
based, i.e. it came from the analysis of children’s language. They also
noted that the development of these relations could occur in two very
different ways. One allowed for the early establishment of general semantic
categories, the other for early formal ones. The effort to decide between
these alternatives characterizes most of the subsequent theoretical research
in the field.
Its weaknesses stem from both its method and its gaps in theoretical
interpretation. The measure of productivity was too weak to establish with
confidence what the children’s grammars actually looked like. No formal
grammars were written, and claims about the child’s grammatical know-
ledge were usually in the form of taxonomies or lists of numbers. Even with
this reservation stated, the numbers in the larger studies, with our added
criterion, result in data that need to be explained by any serious candidate
for a theory of grammatical acquisition. The theoretical interpretations do
not deal with some important questions. One is how the child actually gets
from the semantic relations to grammatical ones, i.e. what is the child’s
learning mechanism? Later we will examine a proposal by Pinker (1984) for
one such mechanism. There is also little in the way of theoretical expla-
nation as to why children would use two apparently opposing ways to
302 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
acquire language. Bloom, Lightbown & Hood may be on the right track
when they suggest it may be due to alternative hypotheses on what type of
language English is. Most recent work attempts to select one or the other
procedure as the one children follow. The presentation of the data,
however, forces all present investigators who support one of these views to
account for the development of the two children who seem to have used the
other.
7.4.1 Functionalism
This is a term which can be traced back to the distinction between ‘form’ and
‘function’in language, where form refers to grammatical properties such as
verb agreement, and function refers to the role these play in communi-
cation. Functional properties cover a range of things, for example the
semantic relations that underlie sentences, the pragmatic intentions of
speakers, the influence of cognition on language, and communicative
aspects such as informativeness. In its most broad use, functionalism can be
said to be the emphasis on the functional properties of language in general,
and in our case, in early acquisition. As such it can cover a diversity of
studies. We have already discussed a number of works that come under this
general use of the term - Halliday’s (1975) analysis of the first words and
304 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST W O R D COMBINATIONS
Brown’s (1973) specification of universal semantic relations. Muma (1986)
surveys the range of research which comes under this general definition of
functionalism.
While a large number of studies can be considered functionalist, the term
itself did not become consistently used until around 1979, when it appeared
in the title of Karmiloff-Smith’s (1979) study of the acquisition of deter-
miners, and in a review of research by Bates & MacWhinney (1979). The
latter two in particular have developed the use of the term, as seen in their
I
subsequent review in Bates & MacWhinney (1982). In its broad or
descriptive use, functionalism refers to a range of research on pragmatic
aspects of language. The recent uses of it, however, are more as an
explanatory theory of language.
Maratsos & Chalkley (1980) This long paper has become the most com-
monly cited approach attempting to outline how distributional learning
can take the child from specific knowledge about individual lexical items to
broad grammatical categories. A summary of some of its points can be
found in Maratsos (1982). Its presentation here combines the views of
both of these papers on the acquisition of rules of word combination and
i __ of grammatical classes.
Like other recent studies, Maratsos & Chalkley (1980) present a theo-
retical model based on their interpretations of data collected by the earlier
studies. Much of the work deals with acquisition in older children, and
particularly the acquisition of gender in German. There is, however, a
reasonably detailed later section on early development. Maratsos &
Chalkley do not work from a current model of grammar, but they do have
definite ideas about the nature of the adult language. They see language as
consisting of classes that are defined in large part by their distributional
properties: ‘It is probable that what are called syntactic categories, such as
verb, adjective, or gender class, are so called because they rest on differ-
entiation among themselves by partly distributional distinctions among the
sets of correlated semantic-distributional patterns in which their members
appear’. For example, a verb such as ‘spill’ is not just defined as an ‘action’
word, but also as a word which takes the progressive ‘-ing’ suffix, the
present tense suffix ‘-s’, and the past tense suffix ‘-ed’. The child’s goal,
then, is the discovery of these distributional properties.
As with our discussion of functionalism, we will present what we see as
the steps in this model for the acquisition of grammatical knowledge (the
7.4 Current theoretical approaches 311
authors do not actually present numbered steps as here, although they do
talk about sequences of development).
Step 1: Identification of individual morphemes. Use phonological,
semantic, and lexical properties of sentences to identify the separate
morphemes in utterances. Little is said as to how this takes place but it is an
important step in all theories of acquisition.
Step 2: Formation of the first semantic-distributional patterns. The
initial patterns have a form:
Word A
This states that the child has noted some property for an individual word
(word A), and thus assigns this word to a preliminary category (cate-
gory X). The specification of the category as X is important because the
child’s categories are not predetermined by Universal Grammar to be
highly restricted at the onset to noun, verb, or some other universal
category. Depending on the number of properties noted, the child may
begin with several restricted patterns. The first properties of these early
categories are likely to be positional ones such as ‘occurs with “it”, or some
other word. Each category which occurs is noted as a separate pattern. The
first categories are restricted to individual words, that is, they are not general.
Step 3A: The strengthening of patterns. Patterns become strengthened
in two ways. One is through the identification in the input of known words in
their previously established semantic-distributional pattern. The other way
is through the addition of new words to a pattern when those words are seen
to have the same categorical property. This generalization can be repre-
sented as:
(7.16)
Pattern 1 (. . . Category X .. . )
Word A
:
Word B
Pattern 3 (. . . Category Y .. . )
Word D .. . etc.
Pattern 2 (. . . Category Y .. .)
Here all the words, including the new one, have been connected with
pattern 2. There are only three direct connections, however, between
patterns 2 and 1(words A , B, and C). The connection would not be accurate
enough (by measures to be determined) for the new word to overgeneralize
to pattern 1. The accuracy requirement predicts that certain overgenerali-
zations should never occur.
Step 5 : The correction of overgeneralizations. Accuracy is not suffi-
cient to prevent overgeneralizations from occurring occasionally: examples
are well-documented in the child language literature, e.g. ‘foots’, ‘knowed’,
etc . . . The child needs to correct those which occur. Maratsos & Chalkley
propose that this is done through indirect negative evidence. That is, the
child keeps track of the number of times he or she does or doesn’t hear a
word appearing with a particular grammatical property. For example, once
the child never hears ‘know’ occurring in the past with ‘-ed’, he or she
records as part of the lexical information for this morpheme that it is
restricted from doing so. They refer to these as positive inhibitory blocks.
Maratsos (1982) provides an example of how the child follows these steps
through his early word combinations. Using a slightly modified termino-
logy, Maratsos begins his example with the child acquiring the sentence
‘daddy walk’ with the meaning ‘that daddy moves himself along by
movement of the lower limbs’ (p. 256). This would be step 2, when the child
forms a restricted semantic-distributional pattern. The pattern consists of
two ‘sequential loci or slots’ (p. 256), with each slot defined by the
properties of the terms which can occur within the slot. (7.19) provides the
structure of this initial pattern:
(7.19) X + Y
I I
daddy walk
314 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
This is somewhat different from the discussion in Maratsos & Chalkley
where one of the morphemes would be the category (e.g. category X), and
the other would be its defining property. Here the defining property is also
assigned categorical status.
Step 3A occurs when the child next acquires ‘mommy walk’. The words
‘mommy’ and ‘daddy’ become members of the emerging category of things
that can walk. With the addition of other words, it can become ‘an
individual word formula’ (p. 257) with the structure of ‘walker+walk’. the
Y class can also expand in this manner, so that the eventual pattern may
have the meaning of ‘mover+movement’. Maratsos points out that the child
will be restricted in building a broader category from comparisons of ‘daddy
walk’ and ‘daddy chair’ with a possessive meaning. Maratsos states (p. 258):
‘The scheme thus builds grammatical categories on the basis of overall
sequential similarity, but also on the basis of semantic function and analysis
of parts of the sequence. It is hence not a purely distributional analysis.’ No
details are given, however, on the semantic properties that the child will use
to restrict such broader categories, and the example is not carried on
through any further developments.
Assessment. The work by Maratsos & Chalkley is a relatively detailed
attempt to follow acquisition after the early restricted formulae proposed by
Braine (1976) and to see how the child could develop adult categories.
Interestingly, it led them to a position that the adult grammar may consist of
complex networks of semantic-distributional patterns, with general terms
such as noun, verb, and subject being unnecessary: it is an ultimate example
of using child language data and something like the Constructionist
Assumption to develop a theory about the adult language.
Much of the demonstration of how such learning proceeds was done with
examples of the acquisition of grammatical morphemes to define grammati-
cal classes. For example, we discussed the proposed steps with examples of
the acquisition of categories such as words which take ‘-ed’, ‘-ing’, etc. (Le.
potential verbs). There is relatively little discussion on how general senten-
tial relations such as ‘subject-predicate’ (or the equivalent in their theory)
are acquired in relation to the acquisition of grammatical classes. For
example, do relations like agent-action precede, follow, or occur simul-
taneously and independently with emerging patterns like ‘words which take
“-ed”’? This is an important issue, as we will see in our discussion of
semantic bootstrapping, where semantic relations are claimed to precede
distributional learning. Maratsos (1982: 263) points out this problem,
among others, for his theory at this point in its development. He states
(p. 265): ‘These problems indicate that considerable empirical and theoreti-
cal analysis is required before we can be said to have any good idea of
plausible complete accounts of formal category formation.’
7.4 Current theoretical approaches 315
Pinker (1984) presents two arguments against the semantic-distributional
model of Maratsos & Chalkley. The first is what he refers to as the
learnability argument. This is the claim that the child in this model will
require some form of negative evidence in order to acquire the adult
language. We have already discussed the problems with negative evidence
in Chapter 2, and how Maratsos & Chalkley propose it in Step 5. The
problem of how children acquire language without negative evidence is a
serious one for a number of approaches in both grammatical theory and
acquisition (see Lightfoot 1982: Chapter 2). Pinker’s second argument is
the eficiency argument. Without better-defined measures of how patterns
correlate with each other, the number of potential patterns is enormous.
The theory as it now stands requires a tremendous amount of computation
and thus memory for it to take place. Pinker’s own solution to these
problems, as well as many others, is to restrict the range of possible
solutions in language acquisition to a limited number which are innately
endowed. The next section examines the views of Pinker, as well as of
others who assign a richer syntactic structure to the young child.
Categories
noun Name of person or thing
verb Action or change of state
adjective Attribute
preposition Spatial relation, path, or direction
sentence Main proposition
Functions
subject Agent of action; cause of causal event; subject of an attribution of
location, state, or circumstance
object Patient or Theme
oblique Source, Goal, Location, Instrument
Cases
nominative Agent of transitive action
accusative Patient of transitive action
dative Goal or Beneficiary
Features
tense Relative times of event, speech act, and reference point
aspect Durativity
Configurations
sister of X Argument of X
relates two semantic notions such that one is an argument of the other, the
child places them into a phrase structure configuration. For example,
Agents are arguments of Actions. The corresponding syntactic categories,
noun and verb, will therefore be sisters, i.e. attached to the node, in this
case S. If this looks familiar it should be; we saw a similar claim in McNeill
(1970b), exemplified in more detail in (7.9).
Up to this point, the approach looks very much like a combination of
the insights on semantic bootstrapping of Macnamara (1972) and the
claims about syntactic structure of McNeill (1970b), with supporting
evidence in the data in Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975). Pinker goes
on, however, to address the crucial issue of how the child acquires the
particular grammatical properties in languages. Different types of lan-
guages are discussed, but we will limit the examples to two problems in
acquiring English.
Two potential problems for the English-learning child are predicate
adjectives and oblique preposition phrases. (7.20) gives examples of each
with a simple phrase structure configuration of the adult structure for the
italicized part of each sentence:
320 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
(7.20) a. Predicate adjective b. Oblique prepositional phrase
‘The dog is big’ ‘I went to the store’
Thedog V AP went P NP
I I i n
is A to the store
I
big
The problem pointed out by Pinker is how to describe the grammar of the
child who says ‘dog big’ and ‘go store’ with the same intended meaning as
the adult sentences. Since the child does not have either the copula ‘is’ or
the preposition ‘to’, there is no evidence for the adult structures in (7.20).
Based on the child’s sentences, the child could just as well have the
structures in (7.21):
(7.21)
NP AP
b.
A
I I
The sentence ‘go store’, for example, would be similar to the adult phrase
‘go home’ which would have the structure of (7.21b). We also need to
account for how the child gets from categories like noun to phrases like
noun phrase (NP).
Pinker proposes a series of procedures that take the child from the initial
acquisition of semantics to syntactic structures. We will demonstrate these
in the same way as earlier, by defining a series of steps. (Pinker does not
provide labeled steps, but labels them as a series of procedures - P1 through
P6. We will give his procedures in the appropriate steps.) These will be
demonstrated by following through the acquisition of the structures in
(7.20) by a child who has only ‘dog big’ and ‘go store’ at the onset.
Step 1: Acquisition of basic semantic notions. This will be a subset of
those shown in Table 7.21. We assume in our example that the child has
acquired Proposition, Name of person or thing, Action, Attribute, Agent,
Theme (the future subject of the sentence ‘dog big’), Goal, and Argument
of x.
7.4 Current theoretical approaches 321
Step 2: Semantic bootstrapping. The child assigns syntactic properties
as shown in Table 7.21. The child has thus also acquired the syntactic
properties of sentence, noun, verb, adjective, subject, object, oblique, and
sister of X. These properties will allow the child to process a number of
simple sentences as determined by the following procedures.
Step 3: Application of existing phrase structure rules ( P I ) . Trees for
sentences are understood and produced by the syntactic properties avail-
able from step 2. Presumably these may include rules for word order. The
sentence ‘dog go’, for example, will have the structure in (7.22a):
(7.22) a. N V b. S C. S
I I I I
dog go NP VP VP
I I I
N V N V
dog go I I
dog go
Step 4: Apply X-bar theory (P2). X-bar theory refers to work since
Jackendoff (1977) to impose general conditions on grammatical categories.
Simply stated, it proposes that all categories share the same phrase structure
properties. For example, all Xs (where X=category) belong to a higher
category X-bar (usually shown as x). The X-bar for lexical categories like N
and V are phrases such as NP and VP. Within this theory, the higher
category of a VP is S. This step imposes this theory onto the child’s grammar
so that phrases are generated over the child’s lexical categories in the tree.
The results of this step for our example are shown in (7.22b). (See Radford
1981 for an introduction to X-bar theory.) While Pinker proposes this step,
he does allow for the possibility of restricting it to apply only if there is
evidence for the proposed phrases in the data (p. 108). If we apply this
adjusted P2, then our child would still only have the structure in (7.22a) for
NP since there is no evidence for the phrase, i.e. there are no adjective-
noun or determiner-noun constructions. There is evidence, however, for
the VP in that the child has the relation Object. Let’s assume that such is the
case and that she can produce sentences such as ‘eat apple’. Also, we have
evidence for S since the child has the notion of Proposition. This would then
give us the structure in (7.22~).
Step 5: The assignment of grammatical functions (P3). Functions like
subject and object are added to the syntactic categories in the tree, again
based on the correlations from Table 7.21. These functions are used in the
next step to connect categories to their appropriate nodes, for example
subjects to the S node, and objects to the VP node. The application of this
step to our example results in (7.23a):
322 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
(7.23) a. b.
S
- S
I /1'P
VP / \
I / I
Nwhl V N,",, V
I I I I
dog go dog go
Step 6: Connection of unattached branches (P4). Connect all unat-
tached branches to their appropriate categories based on their configura-
tions. Subjects, for example, will attach to S. This gives us (7.23b).
It is at this point that our child runs into a problem with its sentences 'dog
big' and 'go store'. After step 5 , they will have the structures in (7.24a) and
(7.24b) respectively (ignoring the broken lines for now). (Pinker represents
the critical nodes as AP and NP but the restricted form of P2 should leave
these as A and N in our example. We will use A and N, but the arguments
equally hold for AP and NP.) The problem is that the child does have more
than one option available for the attachment of the A and Nobliquesince
neither the copula nor the preposition are yet acquired to guide their
attachment. The A could attach to either S or VP, and the Nobliqueto either
VP or a newly created PP. Pinker refers to categories in this situation as
orphans. He does not wish to create lexically unfilled categories, for two
reasons: such categories would not be substantiated by the child's data (a
violation of the Competence Assumption), and, more seriously, they might
lead to the creation of categories which do not exist in the language.
Pinker's solution to this problem is to give orphans special marking (in our
example ?A? and ?N?obliquerespectively), and assign them temporarily to
an ancestor node. These connections are shown with the broken lines in
(7.24). We will return to the question of how orphans are assigned
eventually to the correct English nodes.
(7.24) a. b.1
S S
I
Nwhj
?A? VP
I I 1.
dog big
go store
These rules will account for the four sentences that we have used so far: ‘dog
go’, ‘eat apple’, ‘dog big’ and ‘go store’. As can be seen, the orphans are
marked differently from the other categories.
Step 8: Lexical storage and strengthening ( L l ) . Add new words to the
lexicon with information about their grammatical properties. Verbs, for
example, will be entered with information about the complements which
they may take. Entries which already exist are strengthened.
Step 9:The collapsing of rules (P6). This procedure operates when a
new rule is added to the phrase structure which already has a rule which
expands the same category. For example, if the new rule is as in (7.25a) and
the old rule is (7.25b), then this procedure will collapse them to (7.26~).
Pinker provides a number of proposals on how collapsing takes place.
(7.26) a. VP- PP
b. VP- NP
We can now return to a discussion of how the child will adjust the status of
the orphans and reassign the orphans to their appropriate place in the tree.
Using the acquisition of prepositions as our example, it will happen as
follows. First, let’s assume that our young language learner acquires the
sentence ‘go to store’. In step 2, he or she identifies ‘to’ as a preposition
according to its semantic properties listed in Table 7.21. Step 3 (or P1)
allows the child to make the tree in (7.27a), since it now has the rules in
(7.25). Step 4 (or P2) then creates a PP (prepositional phrase node) above
the P, as in (7.27b). Such an expansion is allowed on the grounds that there
is a constituent present, i.e. ‘store’, which can function as the object of the
preposition. This structure creates a problem, however, when we come to
step 6 (or P4) and have to attach the PP to the VP. Since the ?N? is already
attached to VP, it needs to be detached and placed within the PP. Pinker
adds a condition to P4 (p. 104) that orphan nodes are replaced by a new
node (in our case PP) when the new node has the same structural relation to
the ancestor node (in our case VP) as the orphan. This then results in
(7.27~).
324 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
(7.27) a. b. C.
S S S
I I I
I '. \
VP
p. 1
VP
r\
v
I I
p
go to store
?~?,>l,Ilq,,<
I
go
v
I
pp
l
P
?N?,,,,,,,,,,,
l
store
YK
go p N<,l,,,<,,,,
I
to
I store
to
I
In my introduction to Pinker's assumption about acquisition, I reviewed
his continuity condition which assumes that child and adult grammars are
the same unless evidence shows otherwise. The orphans are such a
situation, since the child needs to restructure its grammar once the
prepositions are acquired. Such a restructuring would not be allowed under
our Constructionist Assumption, which requires that rules be retained once
they are formed. In this case we could claim that the rule in (7.25b) is
retained for oblique NPs, and used for phrases such as 'go home'. Pinker
considers, and rejects, the possibility that the child adds a new rule and
maintains the old one. Instead, he argues that the child is constrained by a
uniqueness principle from maintaining two rules to produce the same
function. This, admittedly vague, principle claims that the child, when
presented with alternative rules to represent the same function, will only
use the one for which positive evidence exists. In his account, rule (7.25b) is
deleted from the grammar, replaced with the one created from the structure
in (7.27~)by P5. The uniqueness principle, an innate property of the
language acquisition device, forces the child to do this. The new rules are
shown in (7.28). P6 will collapse the new rule with the old rule which
generates object NPs as in (7.28a).
b. PP- P NP
The initial semantic bootstrapping is followed by what Pinker calls
structure-dependent distributional learning. This is needed for acquisition of
the aspects of the language which are not semantically transparent. For
example, not all nouns are objects ('flight'), and not all subjects are agents
('John received a parcel'). Grammatical morphemes, like the articles and
verb inflections, can in turn be used by the child to identify abstract nouns
and verbs. This occurs through a procedure referred to as D1. Here we will
label this step 10:
7.4 Current theoretical approaches 325
Table 7.22 Pinker’s LFG grammar for late Stage I, from Pinker (1984:
11), with examples of possible utterances
Grammar Examples
‘mommy fix’
‘tree there’
-S NPsubj
‘pillow dirty’
?NP? ‘that man’
‘mommy soup’
‘pretty boat’
‘more tree’
‘put book here’
‘give food doggie’
‘put truck window’
‘take baby downstairs’
Step 10: Distributional learning. If a new word or phrase has the same
distributional properties as an acquired word or phrase, assign the new
word or phrase to the category of the acquired one. Pinker is purposely
vague on when this operation begins. He says at one point that it could
begin as soon as the second sentence heard (p. 53). More likely, however,
‘one expects the accretion of rules (and possibly the strengthening of rules)
to be slow enough that large amounts of structure-dependent distributional
learning do not follow the very first acquisitions’ (p. 56). It depends, in large
part, on the acquisition of grammatical morphemes, yet, as we will see,
Pinker does not see these as being part of the Stage I grammar. For this
reason we have placed this learning as the last step in Pinker’s sequence of
mechanisms.
These procedures, Pinker argues, will lead the child to the basic phrase
structure rules of the language. However, there are questions which arise
concerning how they operate. For example, it is not clear from the
presentation how the S is created for the sentence ‘dog big’ in (7.24), since
the S results from the operation of X-bar theory on V, not A. Also, it is not
clear how the child is going to distinguish sentences with verb particles from
those with prepositions such as ‘pick up ball’ vs. ‘sit on chair’. Other
questions arise as other examples are tried out (see Pye 1985). The
important point, however, is that Pinker has presented the most detailed
attempt yet to account for such facts, and some adjustments and clarifi-
cations may reasonably be expected.
Pinker uses this approach to write an LFG grammar for late Stage I or
early Stage 11, using the data cited by Brown (1973) in his discussion of
Stage I speech for Adam, Eve, and Sarah. Table 7.22 presents this
grammar along with some examples of the constructions it generates. The
326 THE PERIOD OF THE FIRST WORD COMBINATIONS
language. Hyams argues that this accounts for several features in the
acquisition of English, including the early optional use of subject pronouns.
While Pinker treats this as a performance factor, Hyams proposes that it is
due to the child’s original analysis of a language which has optional subject
pronouns.
Since this theory is relatively recent, it is only now just being developed as
a possible theory of language acquisition: for example, it is still not clear
what the range of parameters is, nor how the parameters get set. The theory
is also undergoing change at a very rapid pace, which makes its adaptation
for child language somewhat difficult. I expect, however, that its use as an
explanatory theory of language acquisition will become more frequent.
Further reading
The major studies
Despite their age, the early studies by Bloom (1970, 1973), McNeill
(1970a), Braine (1963a, 1976), Brown (1973), and Bowerman (1973a) are
still necessary reading in the area of child language. Descriptions of Bloom’s
subjects and goals can be found in Bloom (1970: 1-23, 1973: 11-15), and
Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975: 1-8). Brown’s subjects are described in
Brown (1973: 51-8, 63-74), and I recommend the entire ‘Unbuttoned
introduction’. A brief introduction to Bowerman (1973a) can be gotten
from the first two chapters.
Syntactic comprehension
The three new studies reviewed in the text are all relatively short and should
be read: Katz, Baker & Macnamara (1974), de Villiers & de Villiers
(1973a), and Rodd & Braine (1970).
Current approaches
Two recent collections of articles, Kuczaj (1982b) and Wanner & Gleitman
(1982) are major sources of information about several of the recent
approaches. The first work contains papers by R. Clark, Kuczaj, and
MacWhinney which all tend toward a distributional learning view of
acquisition. The paper by MacWhinney (1982) is long, but provides a great
deal of information on the linguistic behavior of children around this period
of acquisition and beyond. Wanner & Gleitman (1982) contains the paper
on functionalism by Bates & MacWhinney and the summary by Maratsos of
his view of distributional learning. It also contains a summary by Wexler of
the 3asic features of learnability research. Since 1980, Keith Nelson has
edited six volumes of collected papers entitled Children’s language. The
most extensive book-length work by a single author is that of Pinker (1984).
Further reading 339
A feel for Pinker’s work can be gotten from the following sections:
(pp. 1-12) ‘Introduction’, (pp. 34-47) ‘The bootstrapping problem’,
(pp. 67-8) ‘Acquisitionmechanisms’,(pp. 101-28) ‘Threelearnability prob-
lems for the Stage I grammar’.
8 The period of simple sentences: phonological and
semantic acquisition
8.1 Introduction
Chapter 7 dealt exclusively with one topic, that of grammatical develop-
ment. The reasons for this were twofold. First, the literature in this area is
quite extensive and requires an unusually long discussion for comprehen-
sive coverage. Second, that aspect of acquisition is usually broken down
into a separate period coinciding with the period of the first word combin-
ations (i.e. approximately from ages 1;6 to 2;O). It is, however, possible to
combine our treatment of acquisition of phonology and semantics over the
previous period and the current one.
There have been few attempts to provide general stages of acquisition for
phonology. In one of the first attempts to do so (Ingram 1976a:ll) the
following are discussed:
1. Prelinguistic vocalization and perception (birth to 1;O)
2. Phonology ofthefirst 50 words (1;0-1;6)
3. Phonology of single morphemes (1;6-4;0)
‘Child begins to expand inventory of speech sounds. Phonological
processes that result in incorrect productions predominate until
around age 4 when most words of simple morphological structure are
correctly spoken. ’
These are very much descriptive stages in the sense of Chapter 3, i.e. they
do little more than document changes over time. Nonetheless, they provide
an overview of the major behavioral changes which occur.
I have already examined the first stage in Chapter 5, and the second one
in Chapter 6. In the present chapter I will look at the period of the
phonology of single morphemes, which is proposed to last usually from age
18 months to around 4 years. It is claimed to be a period during which the
child goes from a small set of spoken words (approximately 50) to a large
vocabulary of words that are relatively correctly spoken. These words are
claimed to be simple in that they mostly consist of a single morpheme,
except for inflectional endings which are also acquired during this time.
340
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 341
Later development, which I will only briefly discuss, includes the acquisition
of (i) a small set of difficult sounds (e.g. English dental fricatives), (ii) the
morphophonemic rules of the language, and (iii) the spelling system.
There have been even fewer attempts to divide semantic development
into stages. Often it is simply divided into two periods, i.e. before and after
the word spurt around 18 months. The interest in viewing semantic
development in relation to cognitive development led us to follow it (in
Chapters 5 and 6) in relation to Piagetian stages of cognitive development,
up to the end of the sensorimotor period of development. Chapter 6 also
included discussion of studies on word acquisition which covered data on
children up to age 2 years.
In this chapter I review semantic acquisition between the ages of 18
months and 4 years, as with phonological acquisition. This time period is the
first part of what Piaget has referred to as the period of concrete operations,
which in his earlier work he divides into three subperiods. The first two
subperiods are summarized below, based on Ingram (1976:11) where they
are compared to phonological stages of acquisition:
1. Preconcept subperiod (1;6-4;0)
‘The onset of symbolic representation. Child can now refer to past and
future, although most activity is in the here and now. Predominance of
symbolic play.’
2. Intuitional subperiod (4;O-7;O)
‘Child relies on immediate perception to solve various tasks. Begins to
develop the concept of reversibility. Child begins to be involved in
social games.’
An important feature of this period is that the child is primarily involved
with her immediate environment. This will be seen in the way she comes to
understand temporal and spatial terms. The early attempts to do this will
demonstrate the use of ‘immediate perception’, for example, in interpreting
two clauses as reflecting the natural order of the events. Besides examining
some of the semantic errors children make, we will also look at some of the
theories that have been proposed to account for them.
The topic of grammatical acquisition will be returned to in Chapter 9,
concentrating on the child’s acquisition of grammatical morphemes, but
also considering the child’s developing ability to comprehend and produce
more complex sentences.
IThe capital letter of the syllable shape indicates the syllable position in which the contrasts
were tested.
are: (i) lexical status, Le. whether a word is a real word or a nonsense word,
(ii) frequency of usage, i.e. how well the child knows a word, and
(iii) grammatical variables.
Task variables are those which have to do with 'the configuration in which
the stimuli are presented and the method by which subjects respond to
them' (p. 124). One common procedure is to use a discrimination tusk in
which two items are presented and the child must decide whether they are
the same or different. Barton (1980), in particular, is critical of this task on
the grounds that the child could process the stimuli acoustically without
using his linguistic (or phonemic) system, much in the way the prelinguistic
infant does. The alternative is to use an identijication task in which the child
needs to match the stimulus to an internal model to identify something that
represents the meaning of the word, such as an object or picture. Other task
variables pointed out by Strange & Broen are the number of trials used, and
if the subjects are given feedback on their responses. Barton also mentions
the potential problems of experimenter effects when the stimuli are
presented live instead of being recorded.
With so many variables involved, it is not surprising that the results from
the literature in this field do not constitute a homogeneous body of findings.
It is also possible to find fault with most studies on phonemic perception, for
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 345
one reason or another, as has been done in Barton (1980). Table 8.1
presents a summary of the methodological features of a selection of these
studies. The list is restricted to those studies which used an identification
task, since these are felt to reflect linguistic processing more directly. Here I
highlight some of these findings, claiming that they are actually more in
agreement than has been thought by some - the controversy which exists
seems rather to be tied to their interpretation.
Most of these studies were done in the early 1970s when there was a flurry
of interest in this topic. The first were done at Stanford University by
Garnica, who adapted the technique used by Shvachkin. This adaptation,
which has been referred to by some as the Shvachkin-Garnica method,
changes the testing procedure into a more strict experimental format. In
particular, a criterion of acquisition was added that the child would need to
respond correctly in seven out of ten trials before it was concluded that the
contrast was acquired. This method was used in Garnica (1971, 1973), and
Edwards (1974). It was first criticized in Barton (1975) on the grounds that
the criterion of seven out of ten is not an adequate statistic. Barton also
comments: ‘approximately one in six of the results thought to be significant
will in fact not be SO’ (Barton 1980: 100). The technique was subsequently
adjusted by Clumeck (1982), who used the following criteria to judge a
child’s perceptual ability on a contrast:
Clumeck’s criteria for phonemic perception
1. If the first five responses are correct, then conclude correctness and go
on to next pair.
2. If not, give five more trials and conclude correctness if nine out of ten
are correct; if five or fewer are correct, conclude that the child cannot
discriminate the contrast.
3. If six to eight are correct, give ten more trials and conclude correctness
if 15 out of 20 are correct.
This was an adaptation of Barton (1976a, 1978) who used criterion 1 and
then if the first five were not all correct went on to 20 trials. In the latter
case, 15 out of 20 needed to be correct. Other criteria used are nine out of
ten in Strange & Broen (1980) and ten out of 12 in Johnson, Hardee & Long
(1981).
Barton has also criticized the Shvachkin-Garnica method on the grounds
that the use of nonsense words rather than real words makes the task more
difficult. Barton (1976a) found, for example, that his subjects did poorer on
words that they had to be taught than on ones they already knew before the
experiment. The effects of familiarity were also found by Clumeck (1982).
Such concerns have led some investigators to restrict their stimuli to real
and familiar words. Since this choice restricts one’s choice of possible test
346 SIMPLE SENTENCES
items, others by necessity have still used nonsense forms (e.g. Johnson,
Hardee & Long 1981).
Before looking at some results of these studies, I would like to comment
on the two above criticisms of the earlier studies. Regarding the statistical
error of the early Shvachkin-Garnica studies, it should be pointed out that
this error is in the direction of overestimating the child’s perceptual abilities.
The results of these studies can be examined with this direction of error in
mind. They can be interpreted with more confidence, however, if their
results turn out to be comparable to those in studies with stricter measures
of acquisition. (It is somewhat ironic that Barton was the one to point out
this error, given that his own theoretical view is that children have complete
phonemic perception at the onset of acquisition.)
The second criticism about the use of nonsense forms raises a general
issue about our definition of rule acquisition. Recall that Chapter 6 began
with six definitions of what it means to say that a child has acquired a
word. Defining acquisition continually returns to the question of the
extent of a rule’s productivity. In various domains of language acqui-
sition, such as morphological development, productivity is typically
defined as the ability to apply a known rule to a new or novel form. The
same issue is at stake here. If a child has a general phonological oppo-
sition, then it should be applicable to new words being acquired. Indeed,
when we consider it, the thousands of words that the child acquires after
18 months of age are nonsense forms to the child when first heard. Little
in the phonemic perception literature has been concerned with the ques-
tion of the productivity of the system. Most work with real words tests
ones that are familiar to the child, often with oppositions tested in just
one pair of words. The nonsense word studies are actually the only data
we have that begin to address this issue. We suggest, therefore, that the
nonsense word data are actually the most robust data we have on phone-
mic perception.
It is necessary to raise a further methodological problem before exam-
ining the results to date on phonemic perception, a problem concerning
the selection of the contrasts used in the various studies. Even if we
restrict ourselves to simple CVC syllables, we still have an enormous
range of possible oppositions to test. Every English consonant and con-
sonant cluster can be paired with every other, both in initial and final
position (as well as medial position in longer words). Much of this
selection is arbitrary, by necessity, even when the domain is restricted, as
in Johnson, Hardee & Long (1981). As a result of the wide range of
possible choices, few studies have examined the exact same contrasts.
Here this problem will be attacked first by looking at one general study,
then by examining the acquisition of contrasts within general classes such
as fricatives and glides.
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 347
Table 8.2 The contrasts tested, stimulus words used, proportions of
response on all words and known words for 20 children between 2;3 and
2;11 tested in Barton (1976a), based on Figures 3.4 and 3.5
STOPS
lp-,t-1 pie, tie 1.00 (15) 1.00 (13)
1-p,-tl cap, cat 0.90 (19) (1.00) (3)
lk-,g-l coat, goat 0.81 (16) 0.85 (13)
curl, girl 0.75 (16) 0.92 (12)
card, guard 0.93 (15) 1.00 (10)
l-k,-gl lock, log 0.92 (13) (1.00) (3)
back, bag 0.94 (16) 1.00 (15)
frock, frog 0.47 (15) - -
/b-,g-/ boat, goat 1.00 (17) 1.00 (15)
/b-,p-/ bear, pear 0.95 (19) 0.94 (17)
STOP-NASALS
/b-,m-I bat, mat 0.94 (16) 1.00 (11)
1-d,-nl head, hen 1.00 (15) 1.00 (17)
cloud. clown 0.50 (14) 0.83 (6)
FRICATIVES
Is-,f-1 seat, feet 1.00 (20) 1.00 (8)
I-s ,-e1 mouse, mouth 1.00 (19) 1.00 (17)
APPROXIMANTS
n-,r-/ lock, rock 0.79 (14) 1.00 (8)
/w-,r-l wing, ring 0.89 (19) 0.94 (16)
CLUSTERS
lgr-,gl-l grass, glass 0.83 (18) 0.83 (18)
lkr-,kl-l crown, clown 0.77 (17) 1.00 (7)
Itr-,tJr-/ train, chain 0.77 (17) (1.00) (4)
Parentheses are placed around those proportions where there were four or fewer subjects
who knew the pairs.
m n
clusters:
gr, gl, kr, kl, tr, tf r
We can see that eleven of the phonemes tested by Barton are typically
acquired by English children by age 2 years (the shared sounds are indicated
within boxes). Interestingly, those few sounds tested that aren’t are the ones
which received the lowest scores in the experiment. For example, all of the
words with clusters appeared to create some difficulties. All of this suggests
that the only conclusion we can draw from Barton’s experiment is that
children between 2;3 and 2 3 1 can perceive differences between sounds that
they already have been able to produce since age 2. This limited conclusion
is not surprising in that the study is actually a measurement sequence in the
sense of Chapter 3. By selecting sounds to test that are among the first
acquired by children, and restricting the stimuli to known words that can be
named by the children already, the method predetermined its outcome.
The lesson to be learned from Barton’s study is that perception research
cannot be done without considering the child’s articulatory abilities, for
example, by using norms of acquisition as the basis for selecting stimuli.
As we shall see in the next section, several large sample studies exist
350 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.3 Contrasts used and proportion of subjects to meet the criterion
of acquisition in perception and production for 28 children between 1;8
and 3;ll to test four hypotheses in Edwards (1974)
H1:
/s/-l~ 0.50 (316) 0.00 (016)
Itl-Id1 0.67 (416) 0.50 (316)
If/-/VI 0.57 (417) 0.71 (517)
lpl-lbl 1.00 (717) 0.86 (617)
/J/-lzl 0.80 (415) 0.20 (115)
/t$l-d3/ 0.80 (415) 0.80 (415)
101-161 0.56 (519) 0.11 (119)
It/-Id/ 0.89 (819) 0.78 (719)
Totals 0.72 (39154) 0.50 (27154)
H2:
/s/-ld 0.50 (418) 0.00 (018)
/s/-lJl 0.75 (618) 0.38 (318)
Id/-I61 1.00 (818) 0.25 (218)
If/-I01 0.75 (618) 0.38 (318)
Totals 0.75 (24132) 0.25 (8132)
H3:
/kl-/g/ 1.00 (818) 0.88 (718)
lfl-lvl 0.75 (618) 0.75 (618)
101-161 0.75 (618) 0.38 (3/8)
1x1-lyl 0.75 (618) 0.25 (218)
Totals 0.81 (26132) 0.56 (18132)
H4:
/I/-Id 0.90 (17119) 0.32 (6119)
Ill-IWI 0.90 (17119) 0.47 (9119)
l~l-lwl 0.79 (151191 0.21 (4119)
/Il-/j/ 0.74 (14119) 0.32 (6119)
lrl-ljl 0.68 (13119) 0.32 (6119)
lwl-ljl 0.84 (16119) 0.79 (15119)
Totals 0.81 (921114) 0.40 (461114)
which provide such norms. Sander (1961), for example, has found that the
last sounds acquired by English children between 4 and 6 years of age are
/e/, IS/, /i/,/j/,/v/, /e/, /a/, and /z/. Note that Barton only tested one of
these sounds, /e/, and only in opposition to an early one, /s/. Another
option is to study the child’s productive ability at the same time as
perception. We will now turn to a few studies which have, in fact,
attempted these options.
-- [PI /t/--
Subject 114
[t]
Subject 111
--
/PI- [PI
-
/b/- [PI Id/ [al,[d3l,[zl /b/ [bl
If/ [f] /SI ------3 [SI If/ [f]
/VI [f] /z/ [SI /VI +- [w]
It seems to us, however, that these data do not contradict the predictions of
H1. Subject 199 has not acquired voicing in either pair, so it is irrelevant for
H1. Subject 114 supports H1 in that voicing is acquired for the stops, but not
the fricatives. Subject 111 is irrelevant because voicing has already been
acquired for both pairs.
The first part of H2 predicts perception before production and is
supported by the data in Table 8.3. The second part of H2 is a very strong
claim about the interaction of perception, production, and the child’s
substitutions. Edwards proposes a four-stage model of acquisition of a
contrast which she feels is predicted by H2(ii). This model is given here in
(8.4) with hypothetical examples for the acquisition of Is/ and Id. (The
unmarked members of each pair tested are shown on the left in Table 8.2.)
(8.4)
I.
Stage
Perception and production of
marked member as being
Is/
/z/+
-
Perception
[SI
[SI
Production
Is/ .--) [SI
/z/- [SI
-
unmarked
11. Substitution of unmarked /SI- [SI /SI* [SI
member for marked member in /z/ [z] /z/ [s]
production
111. Variable production of the Is/- -
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 353
[SI Is/ [SI
marked member
IV. Acquisition of both members in Is/
perception and production
[SI
/z/ -+ [z]
- -
/z/- [z] /z/-
Is/
[s],[z]
[SI
/z/ -+-[z]
Edwards claims that the data support the prediction strongly for the pairs
Is/-IS/ and /d/-l6/, and weakly for /f/-/O/ (since one subject replaced /O/ with
[SI instead of [f]). They did not support H2 for /s/-/z/ where four subjects
replaced Is/ with [z] instead of replacing /z/ with [SI. This kind of variability
in fricative substitutions has been more recently substantiated in Ingram,
Christensen, Veach & Webster (1980). Edwards also found that the
children were variable concerning which stages were occurring for which
pairs. Subject 110, for example, was in stage I1 for /s/-/J/, but stage I11 for
/d/-/O/.
Of particular interest in this model is the prediction of stage I, i.e. a stage
of incomplete perception. Unfortunately, few data are given to support its
existence: the only case cited is Subject 113 who was found to be in stage I
for the pair /f/-/O/. It is such data which will constitute true counterevidence
to Barton’s claim that children have correct perception of words before they
produce them. We will later report stronger evidence for stage I in the study
by Eilers & Oller (1976).
H3 is of interest because it tests for the perception of a distinction that
does not occur in English, that is /x/-/y/. The prediction is that the
acquisition of a voicing distinction in English fricatives should generalize to
this non-English pair. The data in Table 8.3 support H3, although they did
not fully support some other predictions about this set of contrasts, which
Edwards discusses. Lastly, H4 on the acquisition of glides was strongly
supported by the data, Le. the subjects showed better perception than
production of each of the pairs. Edwards also points out that the order of
the scores differed for perception and production, leading her to conclude
that the order of acquisition of contrasts may differ between perception and
production. Since the numbers are so small, however, this can only be taken
very tentatively.
Edwards draws seven conclusions from the results of her study
(pp. 218-19; her own words are used here).
Eilers & Oller (1976) Eilers & Oller were interested in studying the
relationship between perception and production. In particular, they wanted
to see if the common errors in children’s productions were the result of
articulatory or perceptual factors. As such, the study investigates the
existence of stage I as proposed by Edwards. I have already pointed out
that Edwards’s data were not sufficient to conclude the existence of such a
stage. If it exists, then at least some of the child’s errors could be accounted
for as perceptual errors. If there is no such stage, which is Barton’s
conclusion, then substitution errors could only be the result of articulatory
or linguistic factors.
Eilers & Oller used three types of stimuli to study this question. Type 1
stimuli were pairs of words which differ in sounds which are often collapsed
in the speech of young children. One such pair, for example, is /r/-/w/ which
are often collapsed to [w] by children. Type 2 stimuli were pairs of words
which differ in sounds that children do not usually collapse, e.g. /p/-/t/.
Type 3 consisted of just one pair which differed in /lc-/p/. This was a control
item to ensure that the children understood the task. If the errors on type 1
pairs are due to perceptual factors, then the children should find these more
difficult than types 2 and 3. If there are no perceptual factors, then the
type 1 pairs should be perceived correctly. For purposes of the later
discussion, we shall refer to these predictions as the perceptual hypothesis
and articulutoryllinguistic hypothesis respectively.
The study is particularly interesting because of the stimuli it used. Instead
of using either pairs of nonsense words or real words, they used real words
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 355
Table 8.4 Information about stimulus items and the proportion of subjects
to meet the criterion of acquisition in perception and production for 14
children between 1 ; l O and 2;2 tested in Eilers & Oller (1976), adapted
from Tables 1 and 4
TYPE 1
car-gar [khar] [kar] 0.86 (12114) 0.21 (3114)
block-bock [ P W [PW 0.58 (7/12) 0.17 (2/12)
monkey-mucky [mKgki] [ m ~ k i ] 0.20 (2110) 0.00 (0110)
fish-thish [fJI[WI 0.00 (O/lO) 0.10 (UlO)’
rabbit-wabbit [raebrt] [waebtt] 0.60 (6110) 0.10 (1110)
TYPE 2
pig-tig [phigl [thigl 0.50 (7114) 0.86 (12114)
block-lock [ P W [19kl 0.83 (10112) 1.00 (12112)
TYPE 3
cow-bow [kawl [pawl 1.00 (14114) 1.00 (14114)
paired with nonsense words. For example, the child would be shown a
familiar toy object, e.g. ‘car’, and one unfamiliar nonsense toy, e.g. ‘gar’.
They decided on this method because it avoids the problem with real words
of having a restricted number of possible minimal pairs, and the problem of
nonsense words of having to teach them. Table 8.4 presents the stimulus
pairs used in the experiment.
The subjects were 14 children between 1;lO and 2;2. The procedure was
to show the child two objects which were each placed on top of a container,
one with candy inside. The child was told that the candy was ‘under
the (name of one of the objects)’. Each subject was first tested on
nonminimal pairs such as ‘horse’ and ‘dog’ until four correct answers in a
row were obtained. Then the experimental sessions began. The testing of
each pair began with a warm-up session during which the child was
encouraged to play with the objects. Each pair of words was tested eight
times, with the real word correct four times and the nonsense word correct
four times. The orders of presentation and location were randomized to
avoid biases due to hand or object preferences. The children’s responses on
the pairs were scored as correct if they got seven out of eight. The children’s
production of the test words was also recorded. A child was scored as
correct in production if he imitated ‘both the nonsense word and real
object word in such a way as to maintain some clear phonetic contrast’
(p. 325).
356 SIMPLE SENTENCES
The results are presented in Table 8.4. They do not support fully either
the perception hypothesis or the articulatory/linguistic hypothesis. The
type 1 pairs were neither all correctly perceived nor all the most difficult to
perceive. The statistical analysis of the perception data revealed three levels
of difficulty. For purposes of reference, we will refer to these as ‘difficult’,
‘moderate’, and ‘easy’. Example (8.5) shows how the pairs fell into these
three levels.
(8.5) Level Pair TYP
Difficult fish-thish 1
monke y-muck y 1
Moderate rabbit-wabbit 1
block-bock 1
block-lock 2
pig-tig 2
Easy pig-tig 2
car-gar 1
cow-bow 3
We can see that the type 1 pairs fall into all three levels of difficulty. They
constitute two of the most difficult pairs, as well as one of the easiest. The
score for ‘pig-tig’ fell between ‘moderate’ and ‘easy’, so could not be
assigned to a unique level.
Eilers & Oller also present results on how individual subjects performed
on each of the pairs. For the difficult pairs, most of the subjects showed
neither correct perception nor production (nine out of ten for ‘fish-thish’,
and eight out of ten for ‘monkey-muckey’). For the easy pair ‘car-gar’, on
the other hand, nine out of 14 subjects showed correct perception without
correct production. Subjects were more evenly divided between these two
patterns of response for the moderate pairs. These data thus constitute
much stronger evidence for Edwards’s proposed stage I than that presented
in Edwards (1974).
In the above analysis, one seemingly peculiar result emerged. On the two
type 2 distinctions, several children showed incorrect perception but
correct production (five subjects for ‘pig-tig’, and two for ‘block-lock’).
This result leads initially to the peculiar conclusion that production precedes
perception. I would like, however, to offer an alternative explanation.
Observe first that the criteria for correctness were more strict for perception
than production (see above). Pairs of words which are articulatorily easy for
children when compared to their perception will be likely to show the above
pattern when an imbalanced scoring system is applied which favors pro-
duction. We take these results to indicate that these two pairs are difficult to
perceive relative to their likelihood of being imitated successfully. This is
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 357
just one example of the general finding of this study that the relation of
perceptual and articulatory difficulty is a complex one.
The results support the first conclusion drawn by Edwards about phone-
mic perception: its acquisition is gradual, with certain distinctions appearing
earlier than others. They also support the speculation that the child may
have a perceptual representation of a word which is not a correct perception
of its adult surface form. They do not, however, support a view that all of
the child’s substitutions are the result of perceptual problems. At least one
pair tested was perceptually easy but articulatorily difficult for the children.
Since both Edwards and Eilers & Oller are cross-sectional studies,
neither can be taken as definitive evidence for the stages suggested by
Edwards. They are suggestive, however, of distinctions first appearing
perceptually, and then later in production. Nor do they provide an idea of
the extent to which we can say that a child’s perceptual development at any
time is incomplete. Studies on phonemic perception, apart from Barton
(1978) and Clumeck (1982) at least, tend to select stimuli that are likely to
pose problems for the child. We still have little in the way of direct evidence
on the extent to which incomplete perception characterizes the young
child’s total vocabulary.
So far, we have examined phonemic perception through reviewing experi-
mental studies which directly pair words for the child to process. We would
like to conclude our discussion of the topic by looking into a very different
approach. This is the possibility of making claims about the child’s percep-
tual ability on the basis of her productive language.
The general method is something like this. First we do phonological
analyses of the child’s matches and substitutions, presumably by methods
such as those discussed in 6.5.3. Different theories about the relation
between the child’s perception and production lead to different predictions
about the resulting analysis. I list here three possible theories (one with two
subtheories) and the kinds of analyses that each predicts. The subsequent
discussion will attempt to clarify their claims.
1. Globalperception theory. The child only identifies general features of
words without assigning them necessarily to individual segments,
Prediction: analyses should show poor correspondences between
adult and child sounds with variable pronunciations.
2. Partial perception theory. Segmental perception is good but incom-
plete for some more difficult sounds. Prediction: pairs of adult sounds
that are not distinguished will surface with similar substitutions.
3. Complete perception theory I , The child perceives all adult sounds.
Prediction: the child’s substitutions are use of an unmarked for a
marked sound, with variable articulation for the marked sound.
358 SIMPLE SENTENCES
4.
Complete perception theory ZZ.The child perceives all adult sounds and
keeps them distinct in his own speech. Prediction: the child sounds
never correspond to more than one adult sound.
Waterson (1970, 1971) was one of the first to discuss the possibility of
drawing conclusions based on the child’s productive language. She dis-
cussed this in relation to the analysis she made of her son P around the ages
of 1;6 to 1;8. At this time P had about 155 words, with approximately 100 of
them monosyllables (Waterson 1970: 9). She found that several of his words
couldn’t be analyzed as simple correspondences between his sounds and
those of the adult language. She concluded that he was extracting only
certain features from the adult words which he used in his own. Since this
research is the strongest data in the literature in support of the global
perception theory, it will be examined more closely.
Example (8.6) gives a phonological lexicon of a subset of P’s vocabulary
upon which Waterson based her arguments.
In Table 8.5 we give two analyses of these data. The first is a substitution
analysis of P’s initial consonants of the kind presented in Chapter 6. The
second is a summary of Waterson’s analysis.
The segmental analysis in Analysis 1 supports the predictions for the
global perception theory. The correspondences look questionable in that
they are not what we would expect if the child were simply attempting an
adult sound. [JI] seems to occur for several sounds which it does not
particularly resemble. Also If/ shows extensive variable pronunciations.
The fact that [t] occurs for both /t/ and /k/suggests another possible
perceptual confusion. Waterson wants to suggest that such patterns are
indicative of the child’s incomplete perception. Instead of matching indi-
vidual segments, ‘the child perceives only certain of the features of the adult
utterance and reproduces only those that he is able to cope with’ (Waterson
1971: 181).
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 359
Table 8.5 Two analyses of the data for P in (8.6). Analysis 1: a segmental
analysis of P s initial consonants; Analysis 2: a summary of Waterson’s
(197I) analysis
Analysis 1
As stated earlier, Waterson’s data make a strong case for the global
perception theory. There are, however, two reservations that stop us from
accepting this position. First, the data in (8.6) constitute only 21 of P’s 155
words. We are given little information about the nature of these other
words. It may be that the other words demonstrated correspondences more
consistent with segmental analyses. If so, then the data may be more
consistent with the partial perception theory in that they point out a small
number of the more difficult discriminations which P is still working out,
such as initial /f/-/fl/ and medial nasals. A second concern is that extensive
data of this kind are not widespread in other phonological diaries which
have been reported. This will be apparent when we review some of them in
the next section.
The opposite position to the global perception theory is the complete
perception theory II. This would be the strongest claim for early perception,
in that the child would never in its speech show mergers of adult categories.
Such a situation is logically possible on the grounds that the child’s language
acquisition device would dispose the child to attempt to maintain distinc-
360 SIMPLE SENTENCES
tions of the adult language in his own language. We will, in fact, in our later
discussion of homonymy provide some evidence that such constraints are at
work. Current evidence indicates, however, that perceptual and/or articula-
tory factors still prevent this tendency from being totally successful.
This leaves us then with the partial perception and complete perception I
theories. It is our impression that the above data from perception studies
and data such as Waterson’s favor at this time the partial perception theory.
It is not possible to take a definitive position between these two, however,
because the crucial research to decide the issue has not been done. This
would be work which does phonological analyses on the child’s spontaneous
language, and then tests for perceptual awareness of those adult distinctions
which are merged by the child. In taking this position, I wish to clarify that I
do so with the feeling that the child’s incomplete perception will be more
noticeable in the child’s earliest words, and that it may never be apparent
for more than a few distinctions at any time.
The difficulty in determining which of these theories is at work can be
exemplified by looking at our analysis of T in Table 6.29. There are no cases
of two adult sounds being merged into one sound in T’s speech where both
cases involve non-lexical matches or substitutions. For example, /t/ is [t] and
/8/ is [t], but the latter only occurs in one word. Also, the cases of mergers
which occur tend to fit the predictions of the complete perception theory I.
For example, /t/ is [t] while /k/ appears both as [t] and [k], and /J/ appears as
[t] and [SI. These are the variable pronunciations of Edwards’s stage Ill
when perception is good.
Summary. We have explored the extent to which we can say that children
during the current period of acquisitions have acquired phonemic per-
ception. We have looked at both experimental studies and production data
in attempting to find an answer to this question. The evidence to date
suggests that children at this time have reasonably good perception of the
words they know, but not necessarily complete knowledge. There may be
particular distinctions which are inherently more difficult and which thus
take longer to acquire. We have also seen from Schwartz & Leonard (1982),
as discussed in Chapter 6, that children are selective in the words that they
use. We need to establish the extent to which such selectivity contributes to
this impression.
Templin (1957) We can get an idea of the general nature of these studies
by examining the most frequently cited in Templin (1957). That this study is
still perceived by many as the single most important normative study on
English is supported by the fact that it is heavily cited for this purpose in the
most recent text on phonological acquisition by Stoel-Gammon & Dunn
(1985: 30-3). The general aspects of Templin’s study have already been
summarized in Table 2.3. To reiterate briefly, Templin tested 60 children at
each of eight age intervals between 3;O and 8;O on 176 sounds in English.
The younger children (3;0-5;0) were asked to identify a picture or asked to
imitate the experimenter. The older children either read the words or
repeated them.
Here we are particularly interested in how Templin constructed the test
words, recorded the responses, and scored for acquisition. Table 8.6 lists
the words used by Templin, distributed according to the consonants in
them. Importantly, each of the 176 test sounds was tested in only one word.
These test sounds are shown in Table 8.6 in capitals. For example, while
there were six words which began with a lpl, only the child’s response to
‘pie’ was scored for this sound. All responses were scored by Templin on
site without the use of a tape-recorder. Only the test sounds in a word were
362 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.6 Test words used in Templin (1957)for children aged
3;O-5;0, arranged by the word position of their consonants. I =
word-initial, M = word-medial, and F = word-final, based on
Templin’s analysis of these words. Test sounds in each word are
capitalized
~ ~~~
STOPS
IPl I: paGE, peaCH, peas, Pie, piG, pIn, PROMPT, playTHing, PLeaSure M:
open, o’poSSUM, Upon F: CHip, SHip, soap, SOUP, SLeep, Sweep, graSP,
heLP, laMP, shaRP
It/ I: tIE, Toes, tuB, TRain, tweLFTH, TWiNKLE M: SKaTing F: baT, Feet,
Goat, Seat, WHite, biGGest, buRST, giFT, JumPED, neXT, PROMPT,
QUILT, SQUIRT, condUCT, elePHaNT
/k/ I:caGED, caR, caRD, Cards, cone, conduCT, clocks, cloud, CLown,
QUILT, CRaCKER, chaSM M: Vacuum-cleaner (X2), black-and-
WHite F: bAck, raKE, music, aSK, miLK, SHRiNK, WORK
/b/ I: bAck, bAll, baT, baTH, Beans, bEEts, beLL, bOILS, bOOKS, buLB,
buRST, baTHing, biGGer, biGGest, bo’lTLE, buBBLE, buCKLE, BLocks,
bloTTer, BRead, black-and-WHite M: rhuBaRB F: tuB, buLB, rhuBaRB
Id/ I: Dish, daNGLE, DRum, driving M: WaDing, black-and-WHite F:
BReaD, cloud, rEd, SPRead, caRD, saND
I: g i n , Goat, guM, gun, garaGE, giGGLE, GLass, gliMPSE, graSP,
GRass M: biGGest F: piG, icebeRG
FRICATIVES & AFFRICATES
I: Feet, fiSH, FLoWing, FRoZen M: elePHaNT F: kniFE, mySeLF, whaRF
I: THiNNer, THRee M: playTHing F: baTH, Mouth, eaRTH, heaLTH,
moNTH, tweLFTH
I: sAI1, saND, Seat, Soap, SOUP, SCRatch, SLeep, SMooTH, SNOW,Spoon,
SPRead, SQUirt, STairs, stoNE, stOVE, STRing, Sweep, swiNG, swiNGing,
SKaTing, SPLaSHing M: mySeLF, icebeRG F: GLass, GRass, HORse,
mouSE, bEEts, BLocks, bOOKS, clocks, gliMPSE
I: shaRP, SHip, ship-aHoy, SHRink M: SPLaSHing F:Dish, fiSH
I: Vacuum-cleaner M: driving F: stoVE
I: THose M: baTHing F: SMooTH
I: ZiPPER M: FRoZen, music F: peas, Toes, THose, Beans, bOILS,
Cards, STairs
M: PLeaSure F: rouGE*, garaGE
I: CHip, chuRCH, cheRRy M: reaCHing F:peaCH, SCRatch, chuRCH
I: JumPED M: aGing F: paGE, caGED, laRGE
scored, and these were either (a) correct, (b) omitted, (c) substitutions
with other English sounds, or (d) substitutions with other sounds. A sound
was considered acquired when at least 75% of the subjects in an age group
produced it correctly. Templin provided a number of tables which allow
manipulation of her results, although she unfortunately did not present
information about the actual substitutions used by the subjects. Her results
will be discussed first for single consonants and then for clusters. The
discussion will concentrate on consonants because all twelve vowels which
were tested reached the criterion by 3;O.
By 3;0, all the nasals were acquired, and all the stops except /-k/, /-t-,/ and
final voiced ones /b,d,g/. All of these were subsequently acquired by 4;O
except /-t-/. If we look at the data more carefully, we can account for the
superficially individual behavior of /-kl and /-t-/. For /-k/, 73 percent of the
3-year-oldsproduced it correctly so that it just missed criterion. Also, at 4;0,it
scored 87 percent compared to only 75 percent for /-t/ which did meet the
criterion at 3;O. Further, l-W was tested in ‘rake’, which contains a front vowel
which fronts the tongue position of the /W and often influences children to
produce a more frontedsubstitute. Becauseof these factors, we will group/-k/
with the other voiceless stops and conclude that it is acquired by 3;0, lowering
the criterion for acquisition in the process to 70 percent. Medial position At-/
was tested in the word ‘skating’.It is a well-knownfact of English that both/-t-/
and I-d-/ undergo a rule of flapping where each is produced as [r]. Unfortu-
nately, the acquisition of this rule has yet to be studied. In particular, we
would want to know when children determine that the surface form [r] is the
surface neutralization of two phonemes. Such a study would include an exam-
ination of the use of flapping in the speech of parents to children. Templin’s
data indicate that the /-t-/vs./-d-/ contrast may be acquired late, but her scoring
system is not adequate to conclude this. A child’s flapping a I-&/ would be
scored as incorrect even though it is an appropriate English pronunciation.
364 SIMPLE SENTENCES
The glides lwl, lhl, and Ijl are all acquired by 3;O. The first two are to be
expected from our study of the previous period of acquisition. The sound
Ijl is not particularly frequent in English and may be subject to the influ-
ences of functional load discussed in Chapter 6. The liquids I11 and Irl reach
criterion for acquisition by 4;0, with two exceptions: I-rl in ‘car’ is correct
80 percent of the time by 3;5, while 1-11 in ‘bell’ does not reach criterion
until 6;O. Both these sounds, however, need more careful testing than in
one word. As pointed out by Olmsted, /-rl is one phoneme, but is phoneti-
cally quite variable depending on the preceding vowel. He, in fact, uses
several phonetic symbols to transcribe this sound. Syllable-final 1-11 is also
quite different phonetically from syllable-initial /1/ by showing a high
degree of velarization (see Ladefoged 1975). The velarization of 1-11may be
so great as to reduce the sound to a vowel. Given these difficulties with 1 4
and /-11, we will separate them from the syllable-initial liquids and conclude
that the latter are acquired according to Templin’s data between 3;O and
4;O.
This leaves the fricative class. For a first look at this class, the percent-
ages of correct responses for the three word positions in (8.7) are collapsed
and are given here for each of five age groups. (The acquired sounds are in
bold type.)
(8.7) Percentages of correct responses in Templin (1957)
Age If1 I81 Is1 IS1 lv1 I61 lzl 131 Its1 la1
3;O 84 26 64 44 31 20 34 15 47 35
3;5 88 32 78 63 39 23 55 23 61 41
4;O 92 49 76 71 51 42 58 33 72 69
4;5 97 59 77 84 54 47 66 38 83 72
5;O 91 63 78 82 62 56 64 43 84 81
As we did with the acquisition of I-kl, we will modify the criterion of acqui-
sition from 75 percent to 70 percent. Also, for the years where half-year
data are available, we will average the two. For example, the percentage of
acquisition for 3;O will be the average of the figures €or 3;O and 3;5. This
loosening of the criterion is done on the grounds that 75 percent is a rela-
tively strict criterion. Recall that the measure for matches in Chapter 6 was
over 50 percent, a lower measure also used in Olmsted (1971). The revised
measure shows the following acquisition. First, If1 and Is1 are both acquired
at 3;O. This is consistent with the findings of English fricatives reported for
the period of the first 50 words. Next, the palatals IJI, Itll, and /@Iare
acquired at 4;O. None of the other sounds reach either Templin’s or our
adjusted criterion, indicating that these are the latest consonants acquired
in English.
While the positions for these sounds were merged, it can be seen that at
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 365
least some of the non-acquired fricatives were acquired differently in
different word positions. These differences are given in (8.8):
(8.8)
Age /v/ /z/ 131 ti/
I M F I M F M F I M F
3;O 12 60 22 30 47 25 18 12 23 17 20
3;5 30 65 23 55 75 35 25 20 32 27 12
4;O 40 75 38 62 72 42 45 22 57 45 23
4;5 47 78 38 72 75 50 48 28 60 52 30
5;O 55 80 50 65 75 53 57 28 62 67 40
The voiced fricatives /v/, /z/, and /3/ all show more of a tendency to occur
correctly in medial position than in either initial or final. The pattern is most
obvious for /v/, but is found for the other two also. The voiced dental /a/
shows a different pattern, in which the initial and medial positions are
noticeably better than final position. There is a slight tendency for /e/ to do
this also, but not enough to suggest grouping them into a class in this regard.
(8.9) presents a summary of our interpretation of Templin’s results on the
acquisition of English consonants.
This summary indicates that the majority of English phonemes are acquired
by 4;O. The sounds still to be acquired are the flapped intervocalic alveolar
stop and several fricatives, particularly the dentals /€),a/ and the voiced
palatal 131.
As can be seen from Table 8.6, Templin also examined a larger number of
consonant clusters, 71 with two consonants and 19 with three consonants by
her count. (We say ‘by her count’ because not everyone would classify
clusters in the way Templin does. This point will be returned to below.) A
brief summary of these data is as follows. (i) Active acquisition of fricatives
begins between 3;O and 4;O. At 3;0, only one cluster, /gk/, reached
Templin’s criterion; this increased to 15 clusters at 3;5 and to 35 or nearly
one-half of those tested by 4;O. (ii) The clusters acquired during this time
belong primarily to the following categories: (a) initial clusters with /s/ and a
following stop /p,t,k/ or nasal /m,n/; (b) initial clusters with stops
/p,t,k,b,d,g/ followed by a liquid A,r/ or glide /w/; and (c) final clusters with
a nasal /m,g/ followed by a voiceless stop /p,M. (iii) Those clusters which are
366 SIMPLE SENTENCES
acquired later tend to fall into the following categories: (a) clusters with
three consonants - only three of the 19 tested reached criterion at 5;0,while
12 did at 6;O; (b) initial clusters which combine fricatives and liquids, e.g.
/sl-/, /fr-/; (c) final clusters which combine liquids /l,r/ with obstruents, e.g.
/-rb/, /If/; and (d) final clusters which combine /s/ with stops /p,t,k/.
Templin’s study provides a useful descriptive overview of English phono-
logical acquisition. It can be used for comparison with similar studies on
other languages, and as normative data for English acquisition. Here,
however, we will conclude with a caution about using large sample data such I
as these for anything more than the most general of purposes, setting out a
series of problems with Templin’s study in particular and large sample
studies in general. The limitations of such studies need to be emphasized
since their results may be inappropriately used both for theoretical and #
could have pursued questionable aspects of the results, much in the way
suggested for syntactic studies at the end of Chapter 7. This approach would
have yielded tremendous information about the phonological acquisition of
English.
Velten (1943) Velten (1943) was the first major phonological diary to
appear in support of Jakobson’s (1941) theory of phonological acquisition,
newly published at that time in German. Velten reports on the acquisition
of his daughter Joan from her 11th to 36th month. Her words are presented
in a broad phonetic transcription, and are usually dated by the month in
which they appeared. No variable pronunciations are presented for indi-
vidual words and it appears that Velten has presented the most typical form
used by Joan for the period being discussed. Not all words are presented for
the entire period studied so that it is sometimes difficult to determine how
each word used was pronounced during each month of the study.
Before looking at Joan’s data, it is important to discuss her linguistic
background. The mother spoke American English, but other languages
were also used. Velten states (p. 285):
Since French and Norwegian are frequently spoken in the household
and used to address the child (though less often than English), she
acquires at an early age a large passive vocabulary, and is able to i
descriptive labels; when necessary, some of the examples are from the data
in later samples.)
1. Prevocalic voicing; the voicing of obstruents before vowels, /p/ to [b],
e.g. ‘pocket’ [bat]; /t/ to [d], e.g. ‘toe’ [du:]; /k/ to [d], e.g. ‘cup’ [dap]
2. Final devoicing: the devoicing of final voiced obstruents, I-b/ to [p],
e.g. ‘knob’ [nap]; /d/ to [t], e.g. ‘bad’ [bat]; /-g/ to [t], e.g. ‘egg’ [ut]; /-v/
to [f], e.g. ‘stove’ [duf]
3. Stopping: the change of fricatives and affricates into stops, e.g. /v-/ to
[b], e.g. ‘vinegar’[bidu]; /iYto [d], e.g. ‘cherry’ [dawa]; [j] to [d], ‘jam’
[dab1
4. Fronting: the production of velar and palato-alveolar sounds as
alveolars, /k/to [t], e.g. ‘duck’ [dat]; /g/ to [d], e.g. ‘goat’ [dut]; /S/ to
[z], e.g. ‘shoes’ [zus]; /il to [z], e.g. ‘rouge’ [wu:~];/C/ to [ts], e.g.
‘match’ [mats]; /j/to [daz], e.g. ‘cabbage’ [ta:budz]
5. Gliding: the changing of a liquid into a glide, /r/ to [w], e.g. ‘rock‘
[wat].
Of the five patterns just named, the first two and stopping are the most
prevalent in the data. Stopping appears to be marginal and primarily affects
the initial affricates. This process is more widespread with other children,
but Joan clearly had an ability to produce fricatives from the onset of
acquisition. Gliding is restricted to initial /r/ and not /1/ according to
Table 8.8. Subsequent discussion in the text, however, shows that the
pattern is more widespread than this, as follows:
5. Gliding (revised): also affects intervocalic /-r-/ after the vowels /a/,
/ire/, and / c / ,e.g. ‘sorry’ [sawa], ‘Mary’ [mawa], ‘carry’ [dawa]
372 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Some other common patterns occur in the data which are not included in
Velten’s summary on p. 286, but which are mentioned later in the text. One
such pattern affects certain liquids which surface as vowels, which we will
refer to as vocalization:
6. Vocalization: the production of syllabic or nonsyllabic liquids as
vocalic elements: syllabic /r/ and /1/ as [a] or [u] (these would usually
assimilate to the vowel of the preceding syllable), e.g. ‘hammer’
[hama], ‘table’ [dubu]; postvocalic /1/ after the vowels /A/, /ad,/ E / to
[w], e.g. ‘well’ [waw], ‘shall’ [saw], ‘belt’ [bawt]
There are also cases which involve deletion of either segments or
syllables, labeled as follows:
7. Final consonant deletion: the deletion of consonants at the end of
words to preserve open syllables, /-I/ after the vowels /d, /ai/, and /awl,
(which all surface as [a]) e.g. ‘doll’ [da], ‘while’ [fa], ‘owl’ [awl, and
after all the English vowels which surface as [u], e.g. ‘peel’ [pu]; /-r/,
e.g. ‘far’ [fa]
8. Cluster reduction: the simplification of consonant clusters into single
segments. The direction of the reduction is often predictable:
(a) stop and liquid /I/ or /r/ combinations are reduced to stops, e.g.
‘bread’ [but]; ‘glass’ [das];
(b) /s/ and stop or nasal initial clusters are reduced to stops, e.g. ‘star’
[da:], ‘snap’ [nap];
(c) final nasal and voiceless stop clusters are reduced to stops, e.g.
‘bent’ [bat];
(d) final nasal and voiced stop clusters are reduced to nasals, e.g.
‘hand’ [han].
9. Unstressed syllable deletion: delete unstressed syllables, particularly
if before a stressed syllable, e.g. ‘pocket’ [bat], ‘banana’ [na:’na].
Since Joan was reasonably good at producing syllables and final consonants,
neither final consonant deletion nor unstressed syllable deletion were
prominent in the data.
Besides the above patterns, Joan also showed some correspondences
which, based on Ingram (1981a), are less common in other children
acquiring English. One of these involved the deletion of liquids. This
process, intervocalic consonant deletion ,in Joan’s speech deleted intervoca-
lic /-r-/ and 1-14when they followed any English vowel which surfaced as [u],
e.g. ‘worry’ [wua], ‘pillow’ [pua]. Two others stand out in particular and
have been the basis for later analyses, particularly in Stampe (1973). They
are: (a) the change orfricution of /j-/, /l-/, /-I-/, /-r-/ and I-t-/ (presumably a
flapped consonant) into [z], (for the intervocalic liquids, this only applies to
cases where intervocalic consonant deletion does not apply); (b) the
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 373
denasalization of final nasals as in ‘lamb’ [bap]. Denasalization occurred in
words beginning with consonants or [hu], but not elsewhere.
(8.10) presents some examples of these particularly interesting changes.
(8.10) Frication Denasalization
Ij-1 ‘yellow’ [za:‘wa] ‘broom’ [bub]
‘yard’ [za:d] ‘spoon’ [bud]
11-1 ‘leaf’ [zuf] ‘jam’ [dab]
‘lady’ [zudu] ‘train’ [dud]
1-1-1 ‘color’ [daz] ‘swim’ [fub]
‘Napoleon’ [buz] ‘room’ [wub]
1-r-I ‘tomorrow’ [maz] ‘rain’ [wud]
(later [maza]) ‘home’ [hub]
‘Harry’ [haz] but:
(later [haza]) ‘arm’ [am]
1-t-I ‘bottle’ [baz] ‘moon’ [mun]
‘water’ [waz] ‘ham’ [ham]
A last unusual pattern is the reduction of all English vowels into just two
phonetic variants of [u] and [a]. We will present the English model vowels
for these two surface vowels through the vocalic chart given in (8.11), using
the phonetic symbols from Ladefoged.
(8.11) /i/ /ul
/I/ lul
lei/ /ow/
/E/ (before stops 131 before Ill
and spirants)
/a/ /31/
__________-_____________________________----------------
/E/ (before nasals /A/ Id
and liquids)
/E/ /ai/ /a/
Generally speaking, mid and high vowels surface as [u] and low vowels as
[a]. We will refer to these two patterns as vowel raising and vowel lowering
respectively. These can be exemplified while pointing out another aspect of
Joan’s phonology. She had a small set of phonetic forms which she used for
several adult words, resulting in a large degree of homonymy for them. The
three most used forms in this way were [bat], [but], and [bu]. (8.12) gives
adult words for these four (Velten 1943: 287-8) which can also be used as
examples for the vowel correspondences in (8.11).
(8.12) [bat] ‘black, bark, spot, pocket, bought, button, bent, bite’
[but] ‘brick, pig, bead, bed, break, board, boat, bird, put, boot’
[bu] ‘boy, pea, beer, bare, pear, ball, blow, bowl, blue’
374 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.9 Summary of patterns affecting liquids (0 = deletion)
Frication
Gliding
after la, E , E/
Vocalization
after /A, e, cl
Final consonant deletion
except after /A, ae, cl
Cluster reduction
Intervocalic consonant deletion
Frication
(if not deleted by above)
0 22nd Only long vowels are in words with ‘down’ [da] vs. ‘pie’ [pa:]
open syllables, with four exceptions. ‘shut’ [ba] vs. ‘toe’ [du:]
1. 23rd [a:] occurs for la1 in stressed closed ‘top’ [da:p] vs. ‘cup’ [dap]
syllables
2. 24th [a:] and [u:] occur for all vowels in ‘bad‘ [ba:t] vs. ‘back’ [bat]
stressed closed syllables before voiced ‘red’ [wu:t] vs. ‘wet’ [wut]
stops and spirants ‘bead’ [bu:t] vs. ‘beat’ [but]
‘nose’ [nu:s]
3c. 24th’ [u] for Ii, ei, a., ow, ul becomes [u:] in ‘goose’ [du:~],‘lake’ [du:t]
all stressed syllables ‘coat’ [du:t], ‘hurt’ [hu:t]
3b. 24th [a:] for lhl and /u:/ for I d become ‘red’ [wud]* (from [wu:t])
shortened ‘mud’ [madI2 (from [ma:t])
3a. 24th Final I-bl and l-dl are acquired ‘meat’ [mu:t]’ vs. ‘maid‘ [mu:d] vs.
‘moon’ [mu:nl
‘hat’ [hat] vs. ‘hug’ [hadI4 vs. ‘hen’
Ihan14
but ‘iib’ [wub] vs. ‘rim’ [wub]’
final [z] is acquired for I-z, -31 ‘nose’ [nu:z], ‘rouge’ [wu:~]
‘hose’ [hu:z]
25th6 [ I ] becomes an allophone of lul before ‘foot’ [frt] vs. ‘fit’ [fUt]7
dentals ‘whip’ [fup], ‘swim’ [fub]
4. 25th the oppositions lpl-lbl, It/-Id, and ‘cold’ [tu:d] vs. ‘Joan’ [du:d]
Is/-lzl appear in initial position ‘sign’ [sa:d] vs. ‘yard’ [za:d]
5. 27thR oppositions of stage 4 also occur for ‘needle’ [nu:du] vs. ‘naked’ [nu:tu],
medial position, except for I-t-1 ‘grocer’ [du:sa] vs. ‘daisy’ [du:zu] vs.
‘letter’ [zu:zu]
These, then, are the major patterns discussed by Velten for the acqui-
sition of his daughter’s phonology. The only other changes briefly discussed
are the loss of denasalization during the end of the third year, and the
eventual development of other vowels. Velten’s data show both the general
aspects of early phonological acquisition during this period and the pecu-
liarities that can be found in data from individual children. We have
identified nine common patterns in the data - common in the sense that they
can be found to some extent in the language of most other children
acquiring English. We have also pointed out several of Joan’s very unusual
patterns. Four of these affect vowels (vowel raising, lowering, shortening,
and lengthening), and two affect consonants (frication and denasalization) .
All of the patterns are striking in the detail in which they are found.
While Velten states that his data are in support of Jakobson’s theory, he
actually spends little time trying to justify this claim. Certainly Joan’s early
system does not match up particularly well with Jakobson’s first stage of
acquisition given in Table 6.23 on page 192. Nor does Velten attempt to
show how Joan’s complex patterns support Jakobson’s claims about an
invariant sequence of contrasts. What we have here, then, is a detailed set
of descriptive data which need to be explained: later I will examine a major
explanation for these data, proposed by Stampe (1969, 1973).
Leopold (1947) I have focussed on Velten’s data because of its detail and
uniqueness. Before turning to the issue of explanation, two further impor-
tant diary studies will be briefly considered; along with Velten, these
constitute the three most frequently cited sets of data.
The next significant diary study on an English-learning child was that of
Leopold on his daughter Hildegard. The report on Hildegard’s phonologi-
cal development appeared in 1947 in the second volume of Leopold’s four
volume work, subtitled ‘Sound learning in the first two years’. Like Joan,
Hildegard was not exposed just to English; she was acquiring both German
and English simultaneously, and Leopold reports data for both languages.
Her English data have been widely discussed, and her acquisition of her first
50 words has been analyzed in the study by Ferguson & Farwell (1975)
already discussed in Chapter 6.
Leopold reports on Hildegard’s development from the first words around
0;8 to the end of 1;11, with some selected remarks on later development. As
reported in Ferguson & Farwell (1975), the period of the phonology of the
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 377
first 50 words lasted up to 1;5 when a word spurt occurred. By the end of
1;11, Hildegard had acquired 400 words in her spoken language. Her
development of phonology was similar to Joan’s in the sense that she first
acquired a small inventory of sounds, then expanded the combinatory
potential of these during the word spurt. In other words, her development
from 1;6 to 1;11 was not marked by the addition of new sounds as much as
by increased use of the ones she had already acquired.
In Ingram (1985d), there was a brief report on Hildegard’s phonetic
inventory at 1;11, using the method presented in Chapter 6. This inventory
was as follows:
(8.13) Word-initial consonants Word-jinal consonants
m- n-
b- d- -t -k
W- h- -S
This is a strikingly small consonantal inventory for the size of her vocabu-
lary at this age. It is even small when compared with the English phonetic
inventory presented in Chapter 6 for the end of the phonology of the first
50 words. An important general aspect of Hildegard’s acquisition, then, is
a marked delay in phonetic acquisition compared with her lexical acqui-
sition.
One consequence of Hildegard’s slow phonetic development was the
extensive existence of homonymy, i.e. the use of a phonetic form for two
or more adult words. We pointed out that Joan also had extensive homo-
nymy, but it appeared to be tied to the use of a small number of phonetic
forms. Leopold’s list of Hildegard’s homonymous words (pp. 231-4) indi-
cates that it extended throughout her lexicon. In Ingram (1985d), Hilde-
gard’s use of homonymy was measured and compared with that of two
other children. The measure used was the proportion of homonymous
types in each child’s lexicon. A homonymous type is a word (or lexical
type) which has at least one phonetic type which is homonymous with some
other word in the lexicon. Some examples from Hildegard’s diary are [ba]
for ‘ball’, ‘box’, ‘block’, and ‘Paul’, [hat] for ‘hot’ and ‘hat’, and [titi] for
‘cookie’ and ‘sticky’. While homonymy decreased over time for the other
two children, it actually increased for Hildegard. For example, her propor-
tion of homonymous types was approximately 0.15 at 1;7 compared to over
0.40 at 1;ll. In other words, by 1;11 nearly every other word of hers was
homonymous with at least one other word.
Despite some peculiarities in individual lexical items, Hildegard’s substi-
tution patterns are by and large restricted to the set of common ones men-
tioned in the discussion on Joan’s language. (8.14) is a summary of these
with some examples for each pattern.
378 SIMPLE SENTENCES
(8.14) Some phonological patterns of Hildegard Leopold
1. Prevocalic voicing: e.g. ‘Paul’ [ba], ‘toast’ [dok]
2. Final devoicing: e.g. ‘bug’ [bok]
3. Stopping: e.g. ‘Joey’ [do.i], ‘June’ [du]
4. Fronting: e.g. ‘Jack‘ [da]
5. Gliding: e.g. ‘lie7[jail, ‘rock’ [w3k]
6. Vocalization: ‘bottle’ [balu], ‘ball’ [bawl
7. Final consonant deletion: ‘poor’ [pu], ‘big’ [br], ‘comb’ [do],
‘June’ [du]
8. Cluster reduction: ‘stick’ [dik], ‘brush’ [baJ]
9. Unstressed syllable deletion: ‘pocketbook’ [babul
The peculiarities which occur in Hildegard’s data are restricted primarily
to the acquisition of voicing and the fricatives. The early data show the use
of both [p] and [b] word initially, with a later shift to only [b] with prevocalic
voicing of [p]. As Leopold points out, however, this was the consequence of
what he calls the ‘whispering stage’ (p. 208) which characterized Hilde-
gard’s first months of producing certain of her words. We have already
mentioned one example of this in 6.5.4, the word ‘pretty’. The [p] in these
words became [b] once the vowels also were pronounced. What initially
appears as a regression in development, then can actually be traced to
Hildegard’s tendency to whisper selected words.
Hildegard is noticeably different from Joan in her acquisition of frica-
tives. First, the only one in her phonetic repertoire is [J]which occurs finally
for /-f,/-s,/-z,/-~,/-~/.
This sound not only occurs as a final substitution, but
also as part of a preferred pattern for some words with a fricative elsewhere,
e.g. ‘stone’ [dorJ], ‘story’ [131J]. When we examine her substitution patterns
for initial fricatives, we find that there are very few words even attempted
with them. That is, as pointed out by Ferguson & Farwell (1975), Hildegard
appears actively to avoid attempting fricatives. The one exception is /f-/,
which becomes [w]. Interestingly, this is a substitution that was not found in
any of the 73 subjects studied in Ingram et al. (1980). It is a substitution
which suggests some influence from her simultaneous acquisition of
German.
Smith (1973) The last diary study to be reviewed here is Smith (1973) on
his son Amah1 (or A as he is referred to in the book). Like Joan and
Hildegard, A was raised in a multilingual environment. His father is British,
and his mother Indian. The mother spoke Hindi, Bengali, Marathi, and a
dialect of English referred to as Standard Indian English. Smith states that
A was exposed to Hindi and Marathi, but was still raised primarily as a
monolingual English speaker.
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 379
A started speaking late, around 20 months of age. Smith began his diary
observations somewhat later, when A was 2;2, and continued them until
3;11. The data are divided into 20 stages for purposes of analysis. At the
onset of the study, A had already acquired over 200 words. The study,
therefore, provides more data on later acquisition than do either Velten or
Leopold. All the data collected by Smith are conveniently given in
alphabetical order in an appendix at the end of the book. Given this, it is
somewhat surprising that more analyses of these data have not been done
since their first appearance.
Smith’s goal is to compare two kinds of analyses of A’s data. One analysis
assumes that the child is operating with the adult surface phonology of the
language, and that the child’s phonology is a set of realization rules which
map from the adult surface form to the child’s output. This position, then,
assumes the complete perception theory discussed on page 357, and that
the child’s competence is greater than what is seen in his performance. The
other analysis is one which treats the child’s system as independent from
that of the adult one, where the child moves ‘from a more idiosyncratic and
simple system to one which was more complex and more closely isomorphic
with the system of the adult language’ (p. 1). This alternative assumes
something like the global perception theory, and a universal sequence of
development which will determine the child’s acquisition order indepen-
dent of the adult language. The child’s performance is seen as virtually
isomorphic with his competence.
Smith considers these alternative theories by analysing the stage 1sample
separately for each one and following the changes that occur over time. The
rules for each analysis are presented in formal notation following the
general conventions of Chomsky & Halle (1968). Smith concludes that the
first analysis, which proposes realization rules, accounts for the data better
than the second. Here we will not go into detail over the arguments for or
against each analysis. It seems to us that the second analysis (or theory) in
its most general form is somewhat of a straw man. The only theories which
predict idiosyncratic and autonomous development (possibly such as that in
Ferguson & Farwell) are typically only for the phonology of the first 50
words, not for children as advanced as A. While Smith suggests Jakobson as
one such theory, we have already discussed in Chapter 6 how Jakobson sees
the influence of the adult language as always present and asserting a role
very early in acquisition. Smith’s observations are in fact consistent with
many proposals on phonological acquisition, including the one by Stampe
which we will examine in the next section.
We can get a feel for A’s data and Smith’s proposed realization rules by
looking at Smith’s analysis for the first sample (or stage 1). Table 8.11
presents a summary of this analysis along with some examples. We
380 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.11 A’s realization rules at 2;2, taken from Smith (1973: 13-22)
1. A nasal consonant is deleted before any voiceless consonant, e.g. ‘stamp’ [dcp], ‘bump’
[bnp], ‘uncle’ [ngu].
2. A voiced consonant is deleted after a nasal consonant, e.g. ‘window’ [winu:], ‘mend‘
[men], ‘angry’ [cgi:], ‘finger’ [wina].
3. The alveolar consonants In/ and It,dI (but not continuants /s,z/) become velars, [rj] and [g],
before a syllabic [I], e.g. ‘handle’ [cr~u],‘pedal’ [bcgu], bur ‘whistle’ [wibu].
4. Syllabic [I] vocalizes to [u], e.g. ‘apple’ [cbu], ‘nipple’ [mibu].
5. A continuant consonant preceded by a nasal and a vowel, itself becomes a nasal
(optional), e.g. ‘noisy’ [ns:ni:], ‘smell’ [men], but ‘nice’ [nait], ‘mice’ [mait].
6. /I/ is deleted finally and preconsonantally, e.g. ‘ball’ [bs:], ‘bell’ [bc], ‘bolt’ [bs:t], ‘milk’
[mik].
7. /s/ is deleted preconsonantally, e.g. ‘spoon’ [bu:n], ‘swing’ [wig].
8. In ClwVC2 syllables, C2 assimilates to [p], [m], or [f], e.g. ‘squat’ [gsp], ‘queen’ [gi:m],
‘twice’ [daifl.
9. In sVC words, the /s/ is optionally deleted if the C is labial or alveolar, e.g. ‘soup’ [u:p],
‘seat’ [i:t], ‘sun’ [nn] or [dnn], but ‘sing’ [gig].
10. In J VC words, /$/ is optionally deleted if the C is labial or velar, e.g. ‘sharp’ [a:p], ‘sugar’
[ u p ] , but ‘shopping’ [wsbin], ‘shine’ [dain], ‘shirt’ [da:t].
11. IzI but not lslis deleted finally, e.g. ‘eyes’ [ai], ‘nose’ [nu:], ‘glasses’ [ga:gi:], but ‘kiss’ [gik],
‘mice’ [mait].
12. A nasal consonant following an unstressed vowel becomes alveolar, unless there is a
preceding velar consonant, e.g. ‘bottom’ [bsdin], ‘driving’ [waibin]; but ‘singing’ [gigin].
13. /h/ is deleted everywhere, e.g. ‘hair’ [E], ‘head’ [ct].
14. An initial or post-consonantal unstressed vowel is deleted, e.g. ‘away’ [we:], ‘banana’
[ba:na], ‘belong’ [bsn].
15. It/ and /d/ are optionally deleted before /r/, e.g. ‘driving’ [waibin], ‘troddler’ [Isla], ‘trolly’
[Ish:] (only cases found).
16. Post-consonantal sonorants /l,r,w,j/ are deleted, e.g. ‘play’ [be:], ‘brush’ [bnt], ‘new’
(/nju/) [nu:].
17. Non-nasal alveolar and palato-alveolar consonants harmonize to the point of articulation
of a preceding velar, e.g. ‘kiss’ [gik], ‘coach’ [go:k], but ‘skin’ [in].
18. /l,r,i/ (a) are neutralized as [I] _ - when they are the only consonants in the word, e.g. - ‘lorry’
[~s~i: I,. ‘yellow’ [MU: I;
(b) become [w] or are deleted when intervocalic, e.g. ‘telephone’ [dewi:bu:n], ‘follow’
[wswo:];
(c) elsewhere are neutralized as [d], e.g. ‘light’ [dait], ‘write’ [dait], ‘yes’ [dct].
19. Alveolar and palato-alveolar consonants harmonize to the point of articulation of a
following consonant, obligatorily if that consonant is velar, optionally if it is labial, e.g.
‘dark’ [ga:k], ‘snake’ [rje:k], ‘knife’ [maip], ‘nipple’ [mibu], but ‘stop’ [dsp], ‘drum’ [dnm].
20. /f, v/ become [w] prevocalically, e.g. ‘feet’ [wi:t], ‘fire’ [wae:].
21. Post-consonantal alveolar consonants are deleted, e.g. ‘empty’ [bi:].
22. Alveolar consonants are optionally deleted in final position, e.g. ‘moon’ [mu:], ‘open’
[ubu:] .
23. & 24. Alveolar and palato-alveolar fricatives, and affricates become alveolar [t] or [d], e.g.
‘bus’ [bnt], ‘zoo’ [du:], ‘brush’ [bnt], ‘church’ [da:t], ‘John’ [dm].
25. Prevocalic consonants are voiced and final ones are voiceless, e.g. ‘teddy’ [dcdi:], ‘kiss’
[iikl.
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 381
recognize many of the general patterns seen earlier in the data from Joan
and Hildegard. For example, rules 1,2,6,7,15,16,21, and 22 are all rules
of consonant cluster reduction. Smith’s analysis, however, makes strong
claims about the nature of such patterns. First, Smith argues that these rules
are formally separate from one another and strictly ordered. For example,
rule 11 which deletes final /-z/ must occur before rule 17 or else words like
‘keys’ would be [gi:k] instead of [gi:]. A complex set of such orderings is
proposed. The general patterns, therefore, are not psychologically real
rules themselves, but rather functional similarities that realization rules
share. The child’s actual rules will be a rather long and complex list of
realization rules which carry out a small number of functions. Smith
proposes that realization rules operate to perform one of the following four
functions (p. 162): (i) a tendency toward vowel and consonant harmony
(rules 3, 5 , 8, 12, 17, Ma, 19); (ii) cluster reduction (rules 1, 2, 6, 7, 15,
16, 21, 22); (iii) systematic simplification (replacing marked sounds with
unmarked ones such as replacing fricatives with stops - rules 13,14,18b,c,
20, 23, 24, 25); and (iv) grammatical simplification. The last function does
not operate in the first sample but is found later when rule 11 becomes
restricted to ungrammatical morphemes, e.g. ‘nose’ [nu:], ‘cheese’ [di:] vs.
‘pages’ [be:did], ‘peas’ [pi:d] (see Smith 1973: 67-70).
In attempting to describe A’s phonological development, Smith states at
the onset that he expected his task to be to account for an identifiable set of
regularities in the child’s spoken language. He says (p. 1): ‘It soon became
apparent that there were a wider range of phenomena . . . to be explained
. . . In addition to the mere fact of regularity, any theory of acquisition must
be able to account for at least the following classes of data observed in the
acquisitional process.’ He goes on to identify seven such phenomena, each
of which will be briefly examined here.
The first of these phenomena is the occurrence of systematic exceptions to
the general regularities. Exceptions can occur with individual lexical items,
but they can also apply to a group of words. We have already seen cases of
this, e.g. Joan’s lack of final vowel lengthening in the open syllables of
‘down’ and ‘shut’. The realization rules above show several kinds of
exceptions also. For example, rule 9 deletes initial /s/ in CVC words, yet it is
optional and does not apply if the .final consonant is a velar. Both the
optional forms like ‘sun’ [ d ~ nand
] velar cases like ‘sing’ [gig] are exceptions
to the generality of the rule.
There are probably several different reasons why exceptions arise. Smith
in his discussion of this point suggests one cause in particular, which he calls
restructuring (or relexicalization). He gives an example which arose when
the assimilation rule 19 dropped out of A’s system (p. 144). While words
like ‘duck’ changed from [gnk] to [ d ~ k ] the , word ‘take’ remained as
382 SIMPLE SENTENCES
[kherk]. This also occurred in derived forms like ‘taking’ and ‘taken’ which
were [kerkin] and [kukan] respectively. Smith proposes that this is the result
of the child changing or ‘restructuring’ the internal lexical representation of
his word from that of its adult surface form to that of the child’s produced
form. We have seen a related set of facts earlier from Joan Velten, where
earlier acquired words resisted new sound changes. Whether we accept
Smith’s restructuring proposal or some other account, such exceptions need
to be accounted for in some way.
The second phenomenon raised by Smith is one which was also empha-
sized by Velten (1943: 288):
The child’s phoneme system and the phonetic structure of English are
obviously non-congruent. That is to say, not only does almost every
unit of the child’s system render several English phonemes, as might
be expected, but, conversely, the phonetic variants of a given English
unit may appear as different phonemes in the child’s language.
I will refer to this phenomenon as non-congruence, using Velten’s
terminology. Smith gives the examples of A’s [d] representing 13 different
English phonemes, e.g. ‘teeth’ [di:t], ‘zoo’ [du:], ‘chair’ [dr:],yet English Is/
surfacing in four different forms, e.g. ‘sun’ [m], ‘sock‘ [g3k], ‘mice’ [mait],
and ‘whistle’ [wibu].
The third phenomenon concerns the observation that changes in the
child’s phonological system usually occur across-the-board. That is, when
the child begins to change a particular correspondence between his sounds
and those of the adult language, the change usually maintains a systematic
correspondence that is narrower than the earlier one. For example, A at
one point produced /w/ and If/ as [w]. When A began to acquire the sound
[f], it was consistently used for If/ only, not for both /w/ and If/. Such facts
suggest that the child had perceived the adult distinctions, but had merged
them in his own speech. This kind of observation has been used to argue
against the global perception theory cited earlier. It is important to point
out that across-the-board change does not imply that the change is
instantaneous. It only refers to the correspondences that occur as a sound
emerges in the child’s system.
The next three phenomena are the occurrence of non-native sounds,
puzzles, and recidivism. Smith observed cases where A used sounds which
are not part of the phonetic inventory of English. Some examples are ‘slug’
[ h g ] with a lateral fricative, and ‘Smith’ [mis] with a voiceless nasal. The
term ‘puzzle’ is taken from the example Smith provides in which A
produced ‘puzzle’ as [ p ~ d a l ]but ‘puddle’ as [p~gal].That is, A could
articulate a medial [d] but not in ‘puddle’ where it is required. This is a
general observation pointed out long ago by Jakobson as evidence against
8.2 The phonological acquisition of single morphemes 383
a strictly articulatory account of phonological acquisition. Recidivism is
Smith’s term to refer to ‘the loss of a contrast which has already been
established’ (p. 4). He gives the example of the words ‘side’ and ‘light’
changing over three time periods, reproduced here in (8.15).
(8.15) Time 1 Time 2 Time 3
‘side’ [dait] [dait] [lait]
‘light’ [dait] [lait] [lait]
Superficially at least, the child appears to have taken a step backward at
time 3 in the sense that a contrast between two words has actually been
lost.
The last phenomenon which Smith discusses is one he observed through
a clever experiment with his son. Smith tape-recorded A speaking and
played it back to him. When he heard himself, A was able to recognize his
reduced English words. For example, when A heard himself say ‘squeeze’
[gip], he responded by squeezing a piece of cloth. This ability was also
shown when Smith would say the words to A, e.g. Smith: ‘What’s a [sa:t]?’,
A points to his shirt, and Smith: ‘What’s a [su:]?’, A points to his shoe
(p. 136). Importantly, A not only recognized his reduced forms but was
aware that these were different from those of the adult language. For
example, when Smith pressured A to say ‘ship’, A responded ‘No. I can
only say [sip]’ (p. 137). Smith refers to this situation as the ‘child’s ability to
understand his own speech’ (p. 5). There were two limitations on this
ability. First, it only occurred when A was currently producing the word in
the reduced form he heard. Once his pronunciation improved, he would
not recognize his earlier form. Second, it would only occur if there wasn’t
an adult form that was homophonous with A’s reduced form. For example,
A pronounced ‘mouth’ as [maus] yet processed this as if it meant ‘mouse’
when Smith tested it in the above way.
‘room’
‘salmon’
‘home’
‘ham’
‘lion’
‘non’”
‘M’
‘bed’
Processes
A Child’s form after several phonological processes not related to the ones under analysis
1. Final obstruent devoicing (now ordered before 4).
2. Iterative regressive (vowel) nasalization: vowels, non-high nonsyllabics [ha], and
non-high sonorants [I] nasalize before nasal consonants. (The nasality of vocalics is
inversely related to their height, see Chen 1975.)
3. Nasalized [I] becomes [n].
4. Iterative progressive denasalization: of all nasal segments preceded by a non-nasal
segment .
5 . Denasalization of vocalics (context-free vowel denasalization).
~~~ ~ ~ ~ ~
a Joan produced a small set of French words which followed this pattern.
If all of the sound productions of the child are tossed into the same
heap, it is understandable that the laws of development cannot be
disclosed. By careful elimination, however, the regular succession of
acquired phonemic oppositions emerges.
Stampe (1973: 11) also recognizes the extent of this diversity:
Despite the opinion of early investigators, it is now generally recog-
nized that different children acquire sounds and sound-patterns in
394 SIMPLE SENTENCES
quite different relative orders . . . children choose bewilderingly
diverse substitutions for the sounds and sound-patterns they have not
yet acquired. 1
1. ‘Identification of an individual whole’. The child recognizes the things it acts upon as
objects, not pictures or collections of features.
A ball is recognized as an object in space and time.
2. ‘Identification of important relationships of objects and assigning individuals on the basis of
their functional relations to a synthesized cognitive “chunk” or “concept”’. This process
can take place after experience with a single member of the class of objects.
A ball is known as an object which enters into several relations, such as the thing that can be
thrown, rolled, bounced, picked up, etc. For example, ‘mother throws ball in the living
room’. It is known both for its own actions and the uses it has. It does exist independent of
these relations.
3. ‘Identification of new concept instances by noting the salient stable (‘invariant’) character-
istics of members included in the concept on functional grounds and forming a hierarchy of
identification attributes therefore.’ From experience with other members of the class, the
child recognizes that certain attributes define the concept and others do not. ‘For some
concepts the child may retain relations that the adult regards as superfluous.’
The child sees a boy throw a ball in the park and identifies the relation of ‘throwing’ as a
defining feature, and location such as ‘in the living room’ vs. ‘in the park’ as not. A
superfluous feature such as ‘is thrown to child’ may be retained as a defining feature for a
while. The functional core concept of ‘ball’ is as follows:
BALL: Core functions = rolls, bounces
Location = Li i.e. any place for playing
Actor = Xj Le. any person
Action = Ak Le. other actions can be performed that can
be done to small objects
Direction = to child”
4. ‘Attach a name to the concept so formed.’
The child attaches the phonetic sequence [bd] to the functional core concept of ‘ball’.
” This feature will need to be eliminated from the concept before this process is complete, since
it is not a defining feature of ‘ball’.
and then attaches meaning to it. Second, Nelson argues that there is a level
of cognitive organization which exists intermediately between perception
and language. She interprets Clark as mapping directly from perception to
language.
Nelson outlines four processes, or steps, that the child follows in
acquiring a concept. These are summarized in Table 8.13, with the acqui-
sition of ‘ball’ as an example. The first process is the simple identification of
the ball as a real object. The second process involves the recognition of
functional features for the ball. At this point they are context-bound, and
the ball is not known outside of these relations. The third process separates
the core functions from the other relations which can be represented by
abstract markers such as Li ‘any place for playing’. The last process involves
the acquisition of a word for the concept.
8.3 The further development of word meaning 401
We see then that the child acquires quite a bit of knowledge about a
concept before attaching a word to it. Also, as pointed out by Anglin
(1977), this suggests that the child has the meaning of words basically
correct when they are acquired. Should the child acquire a word earlier,
say during processes 2 or 3, then the error would be one of using a more
narrow meaning for the word than the adult does: that is, the direction
of error is in the direction of underextension. This prediction of the
functional core concept theory is markedly different from that of the
semantic feature hypothesis which predicts overextension of early word
meanings.
It is important to point out that the functional core concept theory and the
semantic feature hypothesis differ primarily in their claims about the onset
of acquisition. The former, for example, recognizes that perceptual features
will eventually be added to the child’s concept, just as the latter recognizes
the addition of functional features. They are both theories that approach
meaning from the definitional view of word meaning and see the acquisition
of word meaning as one which requires the establishment of an invariant set
of features. Macnamara (1982: 10) points out the overall similarities when
he states that the difference between the two theories is mainly one of
emphasis.
A last point about Nelson’s theory is that it is proposed for the acquisition
of referring expressions such as ‘ball’. It is not clear how Nelson would
account for the acquisition of relational terms such as ‘big’ and ‘little’. One
of the early appeals of Clark’s theory was its wider range of predictions.
Child
Adult Percent correct Most common response
animals 50 animals
dogs 100 dogs
co11i es 0 dogs
plants 15 flowers
flowers 70 flowers
roses 10 flowers
foods 40 foods
fruits 20 foods
apples 95 apples
that are first acquired. One of these is relevance, i.e. the extent to which the
object labeled is important to the child in its daily activities. This factor may
override the tendency towards intermediate terms, since specific individuals
like the mother and father are important to the child and will receive names.
‘Dog’ may be the usual intermediate term but the child will also learn the
name of the family dog. The second factor is function, which is used to
capture the fact that adults name objects at an intermediate level for a
particular purpose. They group objects together when they constitute a
group that the child should behave similarly toward. For example, the child
might not need to be careful with all animals, but dogs might constitute such
a group. Lastly, Anglin found that there was a correlation between order of
acquisition and frequency of occurrence of the words in the speech of
children. Anglin suggests that this correlation can be used as a general
heuristic for determining the categories used in children’s vocabularies. His
subsequent analysis provides a taxonomy very similar to the one in Nelson
(1973) which was reported in Chapter 6.
To answer his second research question, Anglin next examined the
occurrence of extension by studying children’s labeling in both comprehen-
sion and production. Chapter 6 already presented some studies on chil-
dren’s overextensions in comprehension and production. Those studies are
similar to Anglin’s, to the extent that they begin with spontaneous over-
extensions in the child’s spoken language, and use these as the basis of
further examination (e.g. Thomson & Chapman 1977). Anglin’s studies
differ in that they present a range of pictures to children and see how they
label them. The pictures, however, are not selected on the basis of the
child’s previous naming behavior. Anglin offers a general criticism of the
previous studies that they bias the study of word meaning in the direction of
overextensions.
408 SIMPLE SENTENCES
To get around the above experimental bias, Anglin used a method which
would be sensitive to both over- and underextensions. His use of this
method in his experiment 4.1 is examined here. Three sets of test words
were used which differed in three degrees of generality: see (8.21) and
compare with (8.20):
(8.21) I I1 111
animal food plant
dog fruit flower
collie apple tulip
The subjects were two groups of 18 children each, with the ages 2;6 to 4;O
(younger group), and 4;6 to 6;O (older group). There were also 18 adults
tested. Each group was divided into three subgroups of six subjects each.
Within each subgroup, each subject would be shown 120 pictures distribu-
ted across three test words in the following way: 10 instances and 10
non-instances of a subordinate term, e.g. ‘collie’; 20 instances and 20
non-instances of an intermediate term from a different set, e.g. ‘fruit’; and
30 instances and 30 non-instances of the subordinate term from the
remaining set, e.g. ‘animal’. For each test picture, the child was asked ‘Is
this a (test word)?’
Detailed results were presented for each subject and selected pictures.
The general results can be summarized as follows. The children showed
both overextensions and underextensions, the latter being the more fre-
quent. For example, the younger children underextended 29% of the
possible underextensions, and overextended only 8 percent of the possible
overextensions. These figures were 16 percent and 6 percent respectively
for the older children. The most frequent underextension was the denial
that a picture of a woman was an ‘animal’. Other examples were rejecting
the pictures of a praying mantis and a caterpillar as ‘animals’.
There were three factors which influenced the data: (i) individual vari-
ation between children, (ii) the concept studied, and (iii) the nature of the
instances and non-instances being tested. Individual variation was evident
in that some terms were overextended by some children, underextended by
others, and correctly used by still others. Such data support the contention
of Chapter 6 that multiple factors may underlie a child’s errors in extension.
Despite the individual variation, there were some patterns for specific
concepts. ‘Flower’, for example, tended to be overextended to items such as
an elephant ear, a coconut, and a philodendron. ‘Plant’, on the other hand,
was usually underextended. In particular, trees were rejected as examples
of plants. Lastly, atypical or peripheral instances of a test word were more
likely to be incorrectly identified than others. This point was verified by
Anglin in subsequent studies.
This experiment was followed by a series of others to explore whether the
8.3 The further development of word meaning 409
child’s extensional errors resulted more from perceptual or functional
factors. The findings supported Clark’s early findings that overextensions
tend to be primarily based on perceptual similarities.
Lastly, Anglin examined the intension of children’s early words. He
studied 14 children between 2;s and 6;7. Each child was interviewed and
asked to discuss the meanings of 12 words: ‘dog’, ‘food’, ‘flower’, ‘vehicle’,
‘animal’, ‘apple’, ‘rose’, ‘car’, ‘collie’, ‘fruit’, ‘plant’, and ‘Volkswagen’.
Anglin comments as follows (p. 189) on the methodology:
In general, we tried to ask five questions about each word in roughly
the following order: (1) ‘What is a -?’ (2) ‘Tell me everything
you can about (a) -.’ (3) ‘What kinds of -s are
there?’ (4) ‘What kind of thing is a -?’ ( 5 ) ‘Tell me a story
about a -?’ However, apart from the first one, these questions
were not always asked of each child for each word and quite often a
variety of other questions were asked.
The method, then, was very much in the spirit of Piaget’s clinical method.
This particular experiment, in fact, is similar to the one in Piaget (1929).
Anglin presented his results as a series of conversational samples with
individual children. Most generally, the children did not show knowledge of
the ability to give a set of defining properties for a word’s meaning. One
interview with a child Peter, age 2;8, particularly shows the limited kinds of
definitions available from young children. When discussing ‘dog’, Peter
states that ‘it goes woof, barks’. H e also recalls two dogs that he has seen
and what they looked like. That is, ‘the very young child’s expressible know-
ledge of a concept, as in this case, often appears to be “instance-oriented”
and quite possibly is based to a considerable degree on visual imagery’
(p. 191). Anglin emphasizes, however, in his analysis, that the definitions
are more often based upon the functional properties of objects rather than
strictly perceptual features.
Anglin cites the above findings on lexical acquisition as support for his
version of a prototype theory which we have already seen. The data on the
early acquisition of intermediate terms and the use of overextensions and
underextensions are cited as evidence for the child establishing early
prototypes which are perceptually based. The data from word definitions is
given in support of the claim that the child’s intensional knowledge is
functionally based. The fact that both kinds of knowledge appear to be
available to children leads to the proposal that a concept contains both
intensional and extensional knowledge.
about her data (p. 264): ‘Fairlycomplete records are available on the way in
which almost every word was used from its first appearance in the child’s
speech to about 24 months. Data on word use continue beyond that point
but are more selective.’ Bowerman presents her data in four tables in the
form of selected examples, summarized here in Table 8.15. These examples
from Eva and Christy are frequently cited in discussions on the acquisition
of early word meaning.
The first table deals with the issue of whether the child’s early extensions
are on the basis of perceptual or functional similarity. First, Bowerman
observes that most of the girls’ overextensions appeared on the basis of
shared perceptual features, a finding consistent with Clark’s (1973a) diary
analyses and the findings from Anglin (1977) presented above. She points
out, however, that this finding would not be incompatible with Nelson’s
functional theory if the perceptual features were ‘used primarily to predict
the function of an object so that the object can be identified as a member of
a known function-based category’ (p. 265). The examples in her Table 1,
however, are given to show that such was not the case in most instances. For
example, Eva used ‘moon’ for the following situations, among others: ‘for a
ball of spinach she was about to eat, for hangnails she was pulling off, for a
magnetic capital letter D she was about to put on the refrigerator’ (pp. 265,
267). In each case, the perceptual feature of shape was similar while the
actions were quite distinct.
We have already pointed out that the functional core concept theory is
limited to predictions about the acquisition of nominals. Bowerman men-
tions this point, and turns to a discussion of the fact that Eva’s and Christy’s
8.3 The further development of word meaning 411
non-nominal terms could not be explained by either functional or percep-
tual features. She argues that the overextension of several of these words
appeared to be based on the subjective experiences of the child. She offers
the following interpretations (8.22) of the words given in her Table 2:
(8.22) ‘there!’ the experience of completing a project;
‘aha!’ the experience of discovery and surprise;
‘too tight’ protest in situations involving physical restriction or
interference;
‘heavy’ physical exertion, often unsuccessful, with an object,
whether or not it is heavy;
Bowerman concludes from data such as that in her Tables 1 and 2 that
theories of word meaning need to expand to include the possibility that
overextensions can occur on the basis of several kinds of similarities, not
just one. In this way, her approach is similar to Anglin’s in trying to
incorporate at least both perceptual and functional features.
Bowerman’s next two tables turn to the issue of whether children’s first
overextensions are complexive or noncomplexive. We discussed this issue
in Chapter 6 in relation to Rescorla (1980), where complexive uses (or
associative complexes) refer to cases where the child links the use of a word
from one situation to another but does not relate all the uses to one shared
feature or set of features. Bowerman draws the following conclusions about
this issue: (i) both complexive and noncomplexive overextensions occur
from the onset of acquisition (a claim later supported by Rescorla’s study);
and (ii) complexive use was somewhat more common for action words than
for object words, suggesting that its use cannot be directly tied to the
attainment of object permanence (an issue discussed already in Chapter 6).
In presenting the examples in her Table 3 to show early noncomplexive
words, Bowerman emphasizes a striking feature of her daughters’ word
meanings, i.e. the way in which the girls could assign very different
meanings to the same words. This was particularly noteworthy since we can
assume that the environment was relatively similar for the two children. The
best example of this was Christy’s ‘on-off’ and Eva’s ‘off’ which are
summarized in (8.23):
(8.23) Christy ‘on-off’: ‘any act involving the separation or coming together
of two objects or parts of an object’ (p. 271), e.g. getting socks on or
off; getting off a spring-horse; taking pop-beads on and off; separat-
ing stacked cups; putting phone on hook; etc.
Eva ‘off’: ‘removal of clothes and other objects from the body’
(p. 271), e.g. for shoes, car safety harness, glasses, pacifier, bib,
diaper, etc.
412 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.16 Prototypes proposed by Bowerman (1978a) for Eva and
Christy
Such observations support the view of the child as an active organizer of her
linguistic experiences.
The last of Bowerman’s tables turns to examples of complexive use of
words, that is, cases where the features change from instance to instance.
Bowerman emphasizes that most of these cases indicated prototypical
structure, that is, the instances of overextension would share at least one
feature with some central or prototypical example. Such a situation is
distinct from the possible one in which the child links or ‘chains’ words from
situation to situation without any shared features across the instances.
Bowerman offers the analyses in Table 8.16 of the examples in her Table 4
(see Bowerman 1978a: 274-7 for details).
We can see how diverse these activities can be by looking at some of the
uses by Eva of the word ‘kick’. It was used in the following situations,
among others: seeing a picture of a kitten with a ball near its paw; watching
cartoon turtles on TV doing the can-can; pushing her stomach against a
mirror.
Bowerman’s analysis leads her to conclude that her daughters were
showing adult-like categories at a very early age of development. She states
(p. 278): ‘These findings suggest that there is less discontinuity between
8.3 The further development of word meaning 413
child and adult methods of classification than has often been supposed.’ She
takes the examples of early complexive words as indicative that the children
were able to apply a featural analysis to the data, and that these features
were similar to those used by adults. She does not discuss, however, how the
child gets from its early prototypes to those of the adult language.
‘When’ is the simplest of the three terms since it is not marked for the
feature [prior]. ‘Before’ is the next in complexity because it is positively
marked for [prior]. There is minimal justification for this decision, with
references to Leech (1970) and H. Clark (1970) for further argumentation.
The major claim is that ‘before’ is more basic because ‘it is used to describe
the visual perceptual field, whereas its counterpart “behind” . . . is negative
since it describes the area that is out of sight’ (Eve Clark 1973b: 267). The
predicted order of acquisition based on complexity then is ‘when’ > ‘before’
> ‘after’.
‘Before’ and ‘after’ were tested in four kinds of constructions, referred to
as ‘before]’, ‘before2’, ‘afterl’ and ‘afte1-2’. Each of the constructions
contained two clauses, so that the subscripts 1and 2 refer to the position in
the sentence of the clause that began with the test word. Examples of the
four types of construction are given in (8.25).
(8.25) Before2 ‘He jumped the gate before he patted the dog’ EIEz
Before1 ‘Before he patted the dog, he jumped the gate’ E2E1
After2 ‘He patted the dog after he jumped the gate’ E2E 1
After1 ‘After he jumped the gate, he patted the dog’ E1E2
416 SIMPLE SENTENCES
indicating that something else was going on in the data. Clark attempted to
capture this further factor by dividing the subjects into four stages of
acquisition. These stages are as follows:
Stage
A Use the order of mention strategy to interpret sentence
B1 Correct understanding of ‘before’; use order of mention strategy
on sentences with ‘after’
B2 Correct understanding of ‘before’; interpret ‘after’ as if it meant
‘before’
C Correct understanding of ‘before’ and ‘after’
The data on which these stages are based are presented in Table 8.17. The
stages above also lead to strong claims about the order of acquisition of
words like ‘after’ and ‘before’ which only differ in a single feature. Here we
restate the four stages above in more general terms:
Proposed stages in the acquisition of antonyms
Stage Interpretation and predictions
A Acquisition of superordinate feature: use a non-linguistic
strategy for both terms
B1 Acquisition of unmarked word: restrict use of non-linguistic
strategy to marked word
B2 Acquisition of unmarked word: treat marked word as if it has
the unmarked meaning
C Acquisition of marked word: correct understanding of both
words
Clark interprets the results as supporting the semantic feature hypothesis.
She states (p. 275): ‘children learn the meanings of words component by
component, and furthermore, where these components are hierarchically
related to each other, the feature hierarchy is learned in order beginning
418 SIMPLE SENTENCES
with the superordinate component, e.g. +Time, followed by +/- Simul-
taneous, followed by +/- Prior’.
This study inspired a great deal of discussion and further study, both on
‘before’ and ‘after’ and on other works. In Ingram (1981b) some general
questions were raised about the interpretation of the data. As already men-
tioned, the difference between ‘beforel’ and ‘before2’ is not explained. It
appears to result from the drop in performance on ‘beforel’at stage B2. If we
look at B2, we see that this is the result of the use of an order of mention
strategy that affects both ‘after’ and ‘before’. Note that both pairs of these
words have 17percent more errorson the words with E2E1order, This creates
alogical problem for B1 and B2 since the child is supposed to have abandoned
the order of mention strategy for ‘before’ at B1 and for ‘after’ at B2. A further
problem is that there is no mechanism proposed which gets the child from B1
to B2. At B1, the child knows that ‘after’ is different from ‘before’ since it is
treated differently. What causes the child to abandon this knowledge and
treat them the same at the next stage? Lastly, there was no age effect between
B1 andB2, and thus no independent measure for them. They thus constitute a
‘stage error’ in the sense of Chapter 3. It is concluded in Ingram (1981b) that
there is little evidence to consider these as separate stages; they should only
possibly be considered as two different ways to acquire word meaning.
Further research on these words has led to other problems with Clark‘s
original study and further insights into the acquisition of word meaning.
These studies have been excellently reviewed in Blewitt (1982), on which
I will base my review here. The general findings have been as follows.
First, no study has replicated the finding that for some children ‘after’ is
interpreted as ‘before’. This is a striking result which has devastating effects
for the proposed stage B2. If true, it also is one that requires some
explanation, in that evidence exists that such a general stage may exist for
some other pairs, e.g. ‘more’ and ‘less’ (Donaldson & Wales 1970), ‘tell’
and ‘ask’ (C. Chomsky 1969), where children have been found to interpret
the second word in each pair as if it had the meaning of the first one. Second,
the order of acquisition of ‘before’ and ‘after’ has been controversial. Some
studies have replicated Clark’s result, while some others have found ‘after’
acquired first (Barrie-Blackley 1973; Amidon 1976; Feagans 1980), and
others have found no difference in their order of acquisition (Amidon &
Carey 1972; Friedman & Seeley 1976; French & Brown 1977).
Blewitt’s review of these studies leads her to propose several factors
which have affected children’s performance on a language comprehension
task. Three of these are summarized below:
(i) The structure ofthe sentence: Amidon & Carey (1972) used sentences
such as ‘Before you move the green car, move the red car’ where the
8.3 The further development of word meaning 419
agent is 2nd instead of 3rd person and there is one action instead of
two. Children performed worse than in the Clark study.
(ii) The syntactic role of the test word: Coker (1978) tested with three
different tasks where ‘before’ and ‘after’ were prepositions in two
tasks and adverbs in the third, as in Clark’s study. ‘Before’ was harder
than ‘after’ on task 1, the same on task 2, and easier on task 3.
(iii) Semantic content of the sentence: French & Brown (1977) compared
sentences with logically constrained events, e.g. ‘After Raggedy Ann
fills the bottle, she feeds the baby’, with sentences that are not
logically constrained, i.e. as in the Clark study. Children performed
better on logically constrained sentences.
The first one, the structure ofthe sentence, is a factor which was also found in
Carol Chomsky’s study of ‘ask’ and ‘tell’. She found that children would
interpret ‘ask’ as if it meant ‘tell’, but that it would be restricted to only
certain sentence patterns, at least for older children. This factor suggests
that the child may have the correct meanings of the words, but that
processing more complex sentence structures affects the retrieval of more
recently acquired meanings. The second factor points out the crucial way in
which the syntactic role of the test word may influence the results of a study.
Coker replicated Clark’s results when testing ‘before’ and ‘after’ as subord-
inate adverbs, but found that children did better with ‘after’ when they were
tested as prepositions. This initially suggests the peculiar situation that the
relation of markedness between two words may vary according to their
grammatical role. Since the effect was influenced by the questions
addressed to the child, however, it appears more likely that it was an
experimentally induced bias. The third factor, the influence of the semantic
content ofthe sentence, is a performance factor like the first one. That is, it
indicates how earlier acquisition can be demonstrated if facilitative test
sentences are used.
Bidtall Possibly the most important claim of the semantic feature hypo-
thesis is that the order of acquisition of relational words is based on their
semantic complexity. While this claim did not hold up very well for ‘before’
and ‘after’, they are a single pair which are antonyms. It is still possible that
the claim may hold between related pairs of antonyms such as ‘big’l’little’
vs. ‘tall’l’short’. According to Bierwisch (1967), ‘big’/‘little’ are the least
complex size words because they are global and are not limited to a specific
dimension. ‘Tall’l’short’, however, are limited to the dimension of height.
Other such pairs in increasing complexity are ‘high’/’low’, ‘long’l’short’, and
‘wide’l’narrow’. Because dimensional terms can be graded in this fashion,
they have proved to be a rich area for the study of semantic acquisition in
general and of the semantic feature hypothesis in particular.
420 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Several studies have supported the findings that such pairs have a
predictable order of acquisition based on their proposed semantic complex-
ity. Testing children between 2;6 and 3;6 on pairs of objects, Eilers, Oller &
Ellington (1974) found the acquisition order of ‘big’rlittle’ > ‘long’/
‘short’ > ‘wide’/(narrow’. Using the additional pair of ‘tall’/‘short’, Bartlett
(1976) replicated the results of Eilers, Oller & Ellington, with the additional
finding that the pair ‘tall’hhort’ was acquired simultaneously with ‘long’/
‘short’. Other studies with similar results include those by Clark (1972),
Klatzky, Clark & Macken (1973), Brewer & Stone (1975).
In the midst of studying this issue, one peculiar finding emerged. In a
series of studies on the meaning of ‘big’, Maratsos (1973,1974b) found that
3-year olds correctly used ‘big’ as predicted by the semantic feature
hypothesis, but that 4-and 5-year olds incorrectly processed ‘big’ as if it
meant ‘tall’. Further, ‘tall’ appeared to be correctly understood by all ages
tested. This finding is interesting for a number of reasons. First, it is a
problem for the semantic feature hypothesis since ‘tall’ seems to be easier to
acquire than ‘big’. Second, it poses a peculiar situation of children correctly
using a word, then changing to an incorrect meaning. Third, it has been
widely cited and has led to a number of subsequent studies. We will take a
closer look at one of the studies on which this finding is based, then turn to a
more recent study which appears to account for it.
In Experiment 1(of four) in Maratsos (1973), 30 children between 3 and 5
years of age were tested on their understanding of ‘big’. The children were
presented with pairs of cardboard rectangles and toy animals, and for each
pair, the child was asked ‘Which one is the big one?’ Maratsos states
(p. 748): ‘The comparative ‘bigger’ was not used because pilot work
observations indicated that preschool children do not have a clear under-
standing of the comparative.’ Since the stimuli for such experiments have
proved to be crucial for the results, we will present them in detail. Maratsos
used three test pairs and one pretest pair for each of the three types of
rectangles, and three pairs of toy animals. The stimuli used are summarized
below:
Pretest pairs: larger rectangle is higher and wider;
Unequal height and width pairs: one rectangle is higher and narrower
than the other (G & H in Figure 8.1);
Equal heightpairs: one rectangle is wider than the other but both are
equal height (C & D in Figure 8.1);
‘Animal‘pairs: giraffe vs. hippopotamus; donkey vs. bear; policeman
vs. leopard.
Facsimiles of the test pairs are shown in Figure 8.1 as pairs C, D, G, and H
in the inventory of stimuli later presented by R a m & Gelman (1984).
421
U N E Q U A L HEIGHT
and WIDTH
(1)
EXTREME (L)-
DIMENSION
nn n
(P) uu ((ir) Uo
Figure 8.1 Sets of rectangles constructed by Ravn & Gelman (1984) for testing
‘bigness’.
422 SIMPLE SENTENCES
The results were scored in terms of percentages of correct responses. A
correct response was to pick the member of the pair with greater overall
size, e.g. the second rectangle in the pairs C, D, G , and Hof Figure 8.1. The
3-year-olds show the results of the studies mentioned above where young
children respond correctly to ‘big’. In this case 73 percent chose the correct
item. This correct response pattern, however, drops dramatically for the 4-
and 5-year olds to only 37 percent and 23 percent respectively. Maratsos
interprets this as indicating that the older children understood ‘big’ as if it
meant ‘tall’, citing the following anecdote (p. 749) as an example:
At one point, one boy, who consistently answered incorrectly, took
the shorter animal (the leopard) and set it on its rear legs, which made
it taller than the other figure. H e then exclaimed, ‘Look! Now it’s the
big one!‘
This general finding was substantiated in other experiments reported in
Maratsos (1973) and (1974).
This is a peculiar finding for several reasons. Besides those mentioned,
there is the further question of whether this result is unique to the
acquisition of ‘big’, or is a characteristic of semantic acquisition. We could
propose that it is a general feature of acquisition when the child is acquiring
words where one has a more specific meaning than another. This could be
done by adapting the stages on page 417 for the acquisition of pairs like ‘big’
and ‘tall’. If so, we would need a revised stage B, which is given below:
Stage B:
Loss of acquisition of unmarked word: upon acquisition of marked
term, reinterpret the unmarked word as having the meaning of the
marked one
As such, this proposal is very strong since it implies that the shift should
occur for a wide range of words which bear this relation. Since such shifts
are not widely attested in the literature, we will assume for the current
discussion that it is a specific aspect of the acquisition of size words.
A recent study by Ravn & Gelman (1984) has provided an explanation for
the results found by Maratsos. Ravn & Gelman picked up on an earlier
suggestion by Bausano & Jeffrey (1975) that older children may not be
treating ‘big’ as if it meant ‘tall’, but that another meaning might be used.
Bausano & Jeffrey point out that the same results would occur for the older
children if they were using a ‘salient-dimensional difference rule’, i.e.
picking out the dimension as ‘big’ which was most different between the
rectangles. Ravn & Gelman build upon this by proposing five possible rules
which children might use in judging ‘bigness’. These rules are summarized
below:
8.3 The further development of word meaning 423
Table 8.18 Predicted patterns of response forfive rules on four types of
rectangle pairs from Figure 8.1, adapted from Ravn & Gelman
(1984:2145, Table 2). (1st = first rectangle selected; 2nd = second
rectangle selected)
Stimuli pairs
Rule K L M N
Definition
Correct rule: Biggest area in two dimensions
Height rule: ‘tall’
Width rule: ‘wide’
Salient-dimensional difference rule: Biggest in whichever dimension
shows the greatest (most salient) difference
Salient-dimension rule: Biggest in the dimension of greatest extent
To test these rules, Ravn & Gelman constructed several sets of rectangles
which have been reproduced here as figure 8.1. They were constructed in a
way such that each of the five rules should lead to a different set of choices
from the different sets of rectangles. Table 8.18 gives the predicted patterns
of responses for each of the five rules for four of the pairs tested. These pairs
proved to be the most useful ones in distinguishing between the five rules
since the dimensional differences were most clear-cut.
As in the study by Maratsos, the subjects were 30 children between 3 and
5 years of age, ten at each age level. The method was also similar in that the
children were asked to point out which of the rectangles was the big one.
Each child’s responses were coded into five scores, one for each of the rules
tested. Here we will give just the results on the four pairs listed in
Table 8.18. The child was assumed to be using one of the five rules if all four
pairs were scored as correct for that rule. Table 8.19 gives the results for the
three age groups.
The results show clearly that the children at all ages have a preference for
the ‘height’ rule, the preference increasing with age. While the increased
use of the height rule is consistent with Maratsos’s results, the development
of the ‘correct’ rule is not. Recall that Maratsos found that 3-year olds
processed ‘big’ correctly, while here none of the 3-year olds have correct
424 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.19 Percentage of children who used one ofjive rules adapted from
Ravn & Gelman (1984: 2147, Table 4)
Age in years
All
age
Rule 3 4 5 groups
Correct rule 0 10 20 10
Height rule 40 60 70 57
Width rule 0 0 0 0
Salient-dimensional difference rule 0 0 0 0
Salient-dimension rule 30 20 0 17
N o rule 30 10 10 17
Spatial words Still another factor which could affect the order of acqui-
sition of a set of words is the child’s cognitive development. For example, we
could propose that a child has not acquired the meaning of a particular word
because he does not have the concept which underlies it. This possibility has
been demonstrated in particular with the acquisition of spatial terms. There
are two complementary kinds of evidence which can be brought forward to
8.3 The further development of word meaning 427
prove this possibility: one would be the demonstration of similar develop-
ment in children across linguistic communities; the other would be the
demonstration that children acquire certain words only after they have
shown competence for their underlying concepts on a non-linguistic cogni-
tive task. Both kinds of evidence, in fact, have been presented in a series of
works by Johnston and Slobin (e.g. Johnston & Slobin 1979; Johnston
1979). An excellent summary of them can be found in Johnston (1986).
Johnston & Slobin (1979) examined the acquisition of the locative
expressions ‘in’, ‘on’, ‘under’, ‘beside’, ‘between’, ‘back’, and ‘front’ in four
languages: English, Italian, Serbo-Croatian, and Turkish. Based on
Piagetian research (Piaget & Inhelder 1967), they predicted that the order
of acquisition (below) should occur regardless of linguistic community if
cognitive development were the sole determinant of acquisition.
Predicted order of acquisition and justiJication (Johnston & Slobin
1979)
1. ‘in’, ‘on’, ‘under’: the first spatial concepts are of containment,
support, and occlusion.
2. ‘beside’: a purely spatial proximity relation, not dependent on the
speaker’s viewpoint.
3. ‘front;, ‘backi (Le. of objects which have inherent fronts and backs,
e.g. houses): proximity to an inherent feature.
4. ‘between’: coordination of two proximity relations.
5. ‘front’, ‘back’ (in relation to objects without inherent fronts and
backs, e.g. balls): coordination of the relative proximities of the
speaker, reference object, and located object.
Forty-eight children between the ages of 2 and 4 years of age were tested
in each of the four linguistic communities. Most generally, each child was
tested by an experimenter who placed a ‘reference object’ in front of the
child, and then a ‘located object’ in relation to it. For example, the child
might be shown a plate (reference object) with a stone (located object) next
to it, and then be asked ‘Where is the stone standing?’ Children were
credited with having acquired a particular locative word if they used it more
often in appropriate contexts than in inappropriate ones. The data from the
study were subjected to a variety of statistical analyses. The results from one
such analysis, involving Guttmann scaling procedures, are presented in
Table 8.20.
The analysis results in three groups of locative terms being acquired for
each language. Four of the words, ‘in’, ‘on’, ‘under’, and ‘beside’, were
always acquired before the others. This was followed by a second group of
‘between’, ‘back; and ‘front;. The last two words acquired were ‘back’ and
‘front’. This pattern is in general agreement with the cognitive predictions,
428 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.20 Order of acquisition of locative expressions in four languages
and the percentage of subjects producing each, taken from Johnston &
Slobin (1979: Table 5) ~
in 90 in 91 on 88 in 90
on 83 on 88 in 84 on 80
under 81 under 84 beside 82 under 79
beside 74 beside 77 under 72 beside 79
between 49 between 57 back1 31 backt 71
frontr 30 backt 42 between 26 frontr 53
back1 21 frontt 41 frontt 19 between 50
back 14 back 23 back 16 back 7
front 3 front 18 front 12 front 4
with less specificity for ‘beside’ and ‘between’, which were each expected to
constitute a separate grouping. Also, there is variability within the group-
ings. For example, the English children acquired ‘between’ before ‘back;,
while the Turkish children showed the opposite order.
To account for the instances where cognitive complexity did not
account for the order of acquisition, Johnston & Slobin propose a second
factor, that of linguistic complexity. They discuss five ways in which
linguistic complexity might affect acquisition: (i) position of word - some
evidence suggests that postpositions (e.g. Turkish) are easier to acquire
than prepositions (English); (ii) lexical diversity - the number of terms
available in the language for a particular proximity (for example, Turkish
‘yannida’ captures the meanings of English ‘beside’, ‘by’, ‘next to’, ‘near’,
and ‘close to’); (iii) clear etymology - the extent to which a word’s
meaning is semantically transparent (for example, English ‘back’ names
an identifiable body part, while ‘between’ doe$ not); (iv) morphological
complexity - e.g. ‘in’ vs. ‘on top of’; and (v) homonymity - the extent to
which one term covers several meanings, e.g. ‘back‘ in English for both
featured and nonfeatured objects. Using an elaborate coding system,
Johnston & Slobin score the results for the influence of these five factors
and conclude (p. 541): ‘Wherever conceptual complexity fails to predict
actual order of acquisition, we find some pocket of relative linguistic
difficulty.’
The second kind of evidence in support of the effects of cognitive
complexity can be found in Johnston (1979). Johnston focussed on the
acquisition of the English terms ‘in front of’ and ‘in back of’. To acquire the
full range of meanings of these terms, the child needs to acquire several
concepts which are listed here in order of increasing complexity.
8.3 The further development of word meaning 429
Concept Description
PROXIMITY The concept that two objects are in a
spatial relation to each other
OBJECT FEATURE The identification of an inherent spatial
orientation for an object such as having a
‘front’ and ‘back’
ORDER The concept that objects can be in a
particular linear arrangement with one
another
PROJECTIVE RELATIONS The conceptualization that the spatial
relation between objects is relative, such
as in relation to a viewer’s line of sight
Johnston hypothesized that children’s use of the terms ‘in front of’ and ‘in
back of’ would parallel the order of complexity given above. For example,
early uses of ‘in front of’ would be in the sense of ‘next to the front of some
object with an identifiable front’. This use (which we will call the featured
use) would only require the concepts PROXIMITY and OBJECT FEATURE. Later
uses with nonfeatured objects would have the meaning ‘first in line of sight’,
which requires the concepts ORDER and PROJECTIVE RELATIONS. (Following
Johnston, we will refer to this as the deictic use of the term.)
Johnston discusses three kinds of evidence that are necessary to demon-
strate that semantic development is determined by cognitive development.
First, there needs to be a correlation between performance on linguistic
tasks and the nonverbal cognitive tasks of the presumed cognitive precur-
sor. Second, the cognitive ability must precede the linguistic ability. Third,
there need to be similar orders of acquisition of concepts and their linguistic
forms. For example, children who use ‘in front of’ only to mean ‘in front of
some object with an identifiable front’ should (i) be able to pass nonverbal
tests of the concepts PROXIMITY and OBJECT FEATURE; (ii) show acquisition of
PROXIMITY and OBJECT FEATURE before the use of ‘in front of’; and (iii) show
an order of acquisition of the meanings of ‘in front of’ which is similar to the
order of acquisition of the related concepts.
Johnston tested the meanings of ‘in front of’ and ‘in back of’ in 33
children between 31 and 54 months of age on a variety of spatial tasks
designed to explore the range of their possible meanings. She also tested the
children on nonverbal tasks for the concepts listed above. She scored the
results in terms of the number of children to pass or fail the task on a
particular concept in relation to the number who passed or failed on the
related linguistic task. These results are summarized in Table 8.21.
The first two columns of results in Table 8.21 do not provide insight into
the relation between cognitive development and language use, since the
430 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Table 8.21 Number of subjects tested on nonverbal (concept) tasks and
linguistic (‘in back of’and ‘infront of’) tasks who either (i) passed both
tasks, (ii) failed both tasks, (iii) passed only the linguistic task, or (iv)
passed only the nonverbal task, on three kinds of comparisons between
concept and use. Adapted from Johnston (1986: Table 1 )
PROXIMITY, FEATURE
and featured use ‘back’ 9 3 1 20
‘front’ 6 3 1 23
ORDER and deictic use ‘back’ 6 20 1 6
‘front’ 0 21 0 12
PROJECTIVE RELATIONS
and deictic use ‘back’ 5 9 2 17
‘front’ 0 11 0 22
Totals 26 61 5 89
subjects here either passed or failed both tasks. The crucial data, however,
are in the third and fourth columns under ‘pass only one task‘. Here 89
responses were cases where the subjects passed the nonverbal cognitive
task, but failed the parallel linguistic one. The opposite result, however,
only occurred five times. These results show that children consistently
acquire the concepts which are related to these terms before the terms are
used in related ways.
These data provide strong evidence in support of the influence of
cognitive development on semantic development. In her recent review of
this relation, however, Johnston (1986: 983) stops short of concluding that
linguistic order of acquisition can always be determined by cognitive
development. Basing her review on some of the studies discussed above as
well as on Johnston & Slobin (1979), she states:
Taken together they [the studies reviewed] provide a solid platform
from which to argue that nonverbal conceptual development is an
important determinant of language growth . . . Further evidence from
child language studies, linguistic analysis, investigations of nonverbal
cognitive growth, and experimental tests of linguistic dependency did
not always confirm this initial estimate. Children’s learning of locative
prepositions, ‘more’/‘less’, and ‘big’/’little’ does seem to be affected by
the evolution of spatial and quantificational knowledge. But the
acquisition of dimensional adjectives other than ‘big’/‘little’ is not yet
so clearly related to parameters of conceptual growth. In that domain
8.3 The further development of word meaning 431
factors such as frequency of input or semantic complexity may play a
more dominant role.
Cognitive factors, therefore, are an important influence, but not the only
one in explaining the child’s acquisition of word meaning.
8.3.5 Assessment
In this section we have reviewed a range of topics on the child’s acquisition
of word meaning, by outlining the most cited theories which have been
proposed to date, and then examining research into the areas of nominal
words and relational words. In doing so we have seen that a number of
predictions by the various theories have not been borne out. The semantic
feature hypothesis, for example, generated a great deal of research, and yet
support for it has been restricted at best. Carey (1982), for example, gives a
nice review of its rise and demise.
The one theory which has managed to survive so far, in several variants, is
prototype theory. This is true at least to the extent that it continues to be
mentioned in recent reviews as the theory most able to account for current
findings. Even prototype theory, however, is not without its critics. One
problem is that it does not lend itself to an account of relational words as
easily as it does to referring expressions. Another problem concerns even
the results on nominals. This form of criticism of prototype theory can be
found in Armstrong, Gleitman & Gleitman (1983). These authors attack
prototype theory on methodological grounds. They argue that the results of
numerous studies showing subjects judging exemplars as being more or less
typical of some prototype is the artifact of the way in which the studies are
conducted. Armstrong, Gleitman & Gleitman propose that human beings
are very able to provide relative judgements when asked to do so. This does
not, however, reflect their linguistic organization of the world.
Armstrong, Gleitman & Gleitman provide evidence for their claim with
results from a series of studies in which subjects were asked to judge which
exemplars were most typical of certain words. Some of the words tested
were similar to those used in other studies in support of prototype theory,
such as ‘fruit’ and ‘sport’. Other words tested, however, were what the
authors referred to as definitional concepts. These are terms which normally
cannot be broken down into features. One such term is the phrase ‘odd
number’, which is defined as ‘an integer not divisible by two without
remainder’. They found that subjects were just as able to give graded
responses to definitional terms such as ‘odd number’ as they were to other
terms such as ‘sport’. The number ‘3,, for example, was found to be the most
typical odd number. They conclude that graded responses in such experi-
432 SIMPLE SENTENCES
ments do not reflect semantic structure, but rather an aspect of performance
which operates as a heuristic to assist people in identifying instances of
concepts in the real world. They go on to give a critique of featural theories
in general, and argue for a holistic theory of the kind mentioned briefly at
the beginning of 8.3.1.
All of this leaves the area of semantic acquisition somewhat in a
theoretical hiatus. The research that continues has turned to some of the
factors which have been discussed above, such as frequency of input and
cognitive determinants. Some recent studies, for example, have tried to see
how the linguistic presentation of words affects the child’s acquisition.
Carey & Bartlett (1978), for example, attempted to teach a child a new
meaning by contrasting it with one the child already knew. The new word
was ‘chromium’, which was given the meaning of the color olive-green.
Subjects were shown two trays which were exactly the same except that one
was red and the other was olive-green. They were then asked ‘Bring me the
chromium tray, not the red one, the chromium one.’ Other research of this
kind is reported in Dockrell(l981). The results so far have been mixed as to
the extent to which such linguistic framing aids in acquisition. Such studies
also often avoid discussion of broader theoretical issue.
It is difficult to predict at this time where research into semantic
acquisition will direct itself in the years immediately ahead. A comment
made by Armstrong, Gleitman & Gleitman about research in cognitive
psychology seems equally relevant to the current state of affairs in semantic
acquisition: ‘we ourselves are not optimistic that a general theory of
categorization, one that will answer to the serious problems (explication of
functions from words to the world, and of the units that figure in phrasal
meanings and in lexical entailments) is just around the corner.’ The lesson
so far has been caution about finding simple explanations, as well as
heightened awareness of the methodological problems involved in studying
this area.
Further reading
Phonemic perception
Much of the work in this area seems to have been done in a relatively short
period of time around the early 1970s. It is also our impression that some
have felt that Barton (1976a) was the definitive study on the topic (Clumeck
1982, for example, appears very much an extension of Barton’s work). It
should be clear from our discussion that we feel that this is far from true. An
insightful recent study that bears this out is Johnson, Hardee & Long
(1981). Edwards (1974) and Eilers & Oller (1976) remain classic studies in
Further reading 433
this difficult area. An insightful methodological review can be found in
Strange & Broen (1980). A more critical overview is that of Barton (1980).
Phonological production
There are currently no textbooks devoted exclusively to phonological
acquisition, although most of the general texts mentioned in Chapter 1
contain chapters on the topic. There are, however, several books on
phonological disorders in children which discuss normal acquisition in some
detail. The primary ones are Ingram (1976a), Edwards & Shriberg (1983)
and Stoel-Gammon & Dunn (1985).
The research on phonological production has gone through several
phases, based on the theoretical view popular at the time. Up until the late
1960s,most research was geared toward testing Jakobson’s theory. The early
1970s were marked by an interest in determining the set of phonological
processes (Stampe 1969) or realization rules (Smith 1973) that map from the
adult surface form to the child’s form. Much of the most recent work in this
area has been from the perspective of the Stanford theory, with its
corresponding emphasis on individual differences.
Overviews of phonological acquisition include Edwards & Shriberg
(1983) which provides a comprehensive discussion of phonological pro-
cesses, Chapter 2 in Ingram (1976a), Menn (1983) which presents the
Stanford theory, and Chapters 2 and 3 of Stoel-Gammon & Dunn (1985).
Their Chapter 3 provides a useful overview of current theories, updating
the discussion in Ferguson & Garnica (1975) which was mentioned in our
Chapter 6.
A feel for the large sample studies can be obtained from selected readings
from Templin (1957). Earlier in this volume Chapters I and I1 were
recommended; Chapter I11 on articulation of speech sounds should now be
added. Turning to the diary studies, Velten (1943) is standard reading.
Leopold (1947) is long and somewhat tedious to read, and can be scanned to
get an idea of its contents. The section entitled ‘General phonetic problems’
(pp. 207-56) contains a number of rich observations. A brief but effective
overview of Smith (1973) is found in his first chapter. Chapter 4 is the
central chapter in which he discusses the results and presents a defense .of
his theory. Stampe’s theory can be found in the short original form in
Stampe (1969), or in the longer, more recent, review in Donegan & Stampe
(1979). The Stanford theory is presented in a general form in Macken &
Ferguson (1983). Its use in analyzing data can be seen in Macken (1979).
434 SIMPLE SENTENCES
Word meaning
As with phonological acquisition, there is little in the way of textbooks on
the topic. There are, however, some lengthy review articles, and some
edited books of articles. Most introductory textbooks such as those men-
tioned in Chapter 1 also have chapters on this topic. One of the first edited
texts is Moore (1973), which contains the first review articles presenting the
semantic feature hypothesis (Clark 1973a), and prototype theory (Rosch
1973). More recent collections are Kuczaj (1982b) and Kuczaj & Barrett
(1986), both of which reflect the more recent prominence of prototype
theory. Nelson’s own recent booklength treatment of her views in this area
is Nelson (1986). A good review of the topic is that of Blewitt (1982). Carey
(1982) reviews the impact of the semantic feature hypothesis, its failings,
and the current lack of an accepted theory. Rice & Kemper (1984) is a
highly readable discussion of the relation between cognition and word
acquisition.
If time allows, reading of the first statements of the three most influential
recent theories by Clark (1973a), Rosch (1973), and Nelson (1974) will
provide an insight into each. The latter attempt to develop these into a more
eclectic theory in Bowerman (1978a) is a widely cited article that is also
basic reading. The most extensive data-based treatment of the topic
remains Anglin (1977); the first chapter is an excellent review of the theories
up to that time and of Anglin’s viewpoint, and the last chapter is a good
overview of his results and the interpretations he gives them. Of the recent
reviews, I lean toward Blewitt (1982). Important recent criticisms of
attempts to explain word acquisition are Carey (1982) and Armstrong,
Gleitman & Gleitman (1983). A nice summary of the possible influences
between cognition and language is contained in the first three chapters of
Rice & Kemper (1984).
9 The period of simple sentences: the acquisition of
grammatical morphemes
9.1 Introduction
We have seen in Chapter 7 that the first sentences of children consist
primarily of words which belong in the adult language to lexical categories
such as noun, verb, and adjective. Because of this, most studies of the
period of the first word combinations have concentrated on explaining the
emergence of these early lexical forms. In particular, their semantic
characteristics have been emphasized. Brown (1973), for example, des-
cribes the period as one in which the first semantic relations appear. Even
while arguing for early syntactic structure, Pinker (1984) has nonetheless
also relied on the child’s first use of semantic information to enable him to
‘bootstrap’ into the syntax.
In this chapter, we turn to how the child acquires the range of morphemes
in language that do not have the transparent semantic meanings of the
major lexical words. These morphemes are often called grammatical
morphemes (or function words) in the sense that their meanings are either
partially or totally defined by the set of rules (or grammar) of a particular
language. Brown (1973: 253) refers to them as modulations of meaning in
that they:
. . . seem to ‘tune’ or ‘modulate’ the meanings associated with the
contentives in the sense that the modulation is inconceivable without
the more basic meanings. Thus ‘a’ and ‘the’ make the thing referred to
by a noun specific or nonspecific.
Gleitman in numerous places (e.g. Wanner & Gleitman 1982) refers to
them as a closed class (as opposed to the ‘open class’ of content words)
which can be defined by both syntactic (e.g. restricted membership and
positions) and phonological (e.g. unstressed, often nonsyllabic) properties.
These morphemes tend to be acquired later than lexical morphemes and
are usually associated with development beyond the period of the first word
combinations. Brown assigns their onset to Stage 11, although their devel-
opment takes several years. Their study has been mostly descriptive, i.e.
435
436 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
Table 9.1 A sampling of some grammatical properties not found in
English, based on Comrie ( I 981, 1983)
tracking when they occur and the kinds of error patterns in which they
appear, but more recently, some attempts have been made to explain how
they are acquired, both in terms of their syntactic properties and the
performance factors that affect them. This introduction begins with a
general discussion of the issues at stake in studying the acquisition of
grammatical morphemes.
A major issue is defining the class of grammatical morphemes. As noted,
several people have discussed them as a psychologically real category of
grammar, distinct from the lexical morphemes. No consensus has been
reached, however, on the extent to which this is true. We could, for
example, deny a unified class and propose a taxonomy of classes of grammar
that fall along some continuum in regard to one or more properties. The
problems involved can be exemplified by looking at the status of preposi-
tions. These are typically included in the class of grammatical morphemes,
yet Chomsky (1981) has included them within a feature system that includes
nouns, verbs, and adverbs. For example, they can function as heads of
constructions (prepositional phrases) and, like verbs, assign grammatical
case. The Government and Binding Theory of Chomsky, in fact, has yet to
9.1 Introduction 437
come up with an adequate theory of the range of possible grammatical
categories. This is true, to some extent, of other theories as well; as a result,
the study of the acquisition of grammatical morphemes is often theory-
independent and based upon traditional category labels.
Much of the work in this area has focussed on English, but it is important
to recognize at the onset the range and variability of grammatical mor-
phemes cross-linguistically. Any account of their acquisition will need to
deal with the cross-linguistic cases also. Table 9.1 presents a very brief
sampling of the diversity which is involved. After reviewing the research in
English, we will discuss some of the cross-linguistic data studied.
Another important step in studying the acquisition of grammatical mor-
phemes is to establish the ways in which they differ from one another, and
how these differences interact. Brown (1973) was one of the first to do this.
One set of differences concern the effects of perceptual salience. This
includes the position of a morpheme in a sentence, and whether it is free or
affixed, syllabic or nonsyllabic, and stressed or unstressed. Another pos-
sible influence is frequency of occurrence in the parental language. As we
will see later, Newport, Gleitman & Gleitman (1977) present data which
suggest that children who acquire auxiliary inversion early have parents
who direct more questions to them with inverted auxiliaries than do other
parents. A third feature of morphemes is that they differ in semantic
complexity. We have already seen in the previous chapter, for example, that
certain spatial terms can be argued to be semantically simpler than others.
Lastly, there are a number of differences between morphemes which can be
placed under the category of grammatical complexity. These include
(i) redundancy, i.e. the extent to which a morpheme is predictable, e.g.
person on verbs is redundant when pronoun subjects are used; (ii) allomor-
phy, i.e. the number of allomorphs that occur, e.g. ‘-ing’ has one allomorph
in English but plural ‘-s’has three; (iii) paradigm regularity, e.g. regular
verb forms vs. irregular ones such as ‘to be’.
Still another issue in studying morphological acquisition is a methodolo-
gical one. That is, how do we study the child’s knowledge of these
grammatical forms? We have an immediate problem when we try to do this
exclusively from spontaneous language samples. As has been documented
in several places, some of the grammatical morphemes are not very
frequent even in adult language, e.g. the passive morphology on verbs.
Brown (1973) has gotten around this problem to some extent by his measure
of the percentage of obligatory occurrence which adjusts for frequency.
Even this measure, however, requires some minimum frequency which is
not always evident. Another problem with spontaneous samples is that it is
not always possible to determine from the context what morpheme a child
should have used. For example, if the child says ‘I eat apple?’, we can
438 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF GRAMMATICAL MORPHEMES
Table 9.2 A summary of the main grammatical morphemes found in
English
Inflectional morphemes
Nominal inflections:
plural {-s} ‘two boys’
possessive { -s) ‘the girl’s socks’
verbal inflections:
progressive {-ins) ‘the cat is running’
present tense {-s) ‘the dog sits on the rug’
past tense {-ed) ‘the teacher walked to school’
passive {-en} ‘the cake was eaten by the class’
perfect {-en} ‘I have eaten the apple’
adjectival inflections:
comparative {-er) ‘the cat is bigger than the dog’
superlative {-est} ‘this is the smallest class in the school’
Derivational morphemes’
adverbial {-ly} ‘Joe ran quickly to the store’
adjectival {-ful) ‘May is hopeful of getting the job’
agentive {-er} ‘she was the bearer of good news’
etc.
Free morphemes
verb negation {not} ‘do not go in there’
modal auxiliaries e.g. {will, can, may} ‘we will arrive by midnight’
infinitive {to} ‘Mary decided to leave’
personal pronouns e.g. {I, you, it) ‘they saw her near him’
possessive pronouns e.g. {his, her} ‘our books’
reflexive pronouns e.g. {himself] ‘they did it themselves’
demonstrative pronouns e.g. {this, that} ‘I bought this book in town’
locative pronouns e.g. {here, there} ‘put it down right there’
relative pronouns e.g. {which, that} ‘we saw the book which was on the table’
determiners {the, a} ‘the apple’
quantifiers e.g. {few, some, many) ‘we only saw a few people at the dance’
complementizers {that, for..to, -ing} ‘we knew that John was leaving’
gerund {-ing} ‘the running of the bulls was yesterday’
participle {-ing} ‘the falling leaves were lovely’
assume that an auxiliary is missing, but we can’t determine which one it is,
e.g. ‘can’, ‘may’, ‘should’, e t c . . .
This area requires as much methodological caution as any other. As I
will show, several innovative techniques have been developed to assist in
this study, including comprehension tasks, imitation tasks, and the use of
metalinguistic judgements. Since children are older at the time of morpho-
logical acquisition, it is possible to use more diverse tasks. Even so, we will
see that much of what is known is still based on spontaneous language
samples.
9.2 Morphological acquisition in English: a descriptive overview 439
Berko (1958) This study probably more than any other marked the onset
of the modern era of child language studies. It is not only one of the most
famous studies ever done, it is also the most replicated. Even with so many
replications, its general findings remain sound.
Berko selected a variety of grammatical morphemes for experimental
study. These are listed in (9.1).
e. progressive {-ins}
f. agentive { -er}
g. comparatives { -er} , {-est}
h. compounds
Here the discussion will be limited to study of the inflections selected, that is
items (9a)-(9e). The five inflectional morphemes chosen give an idea of the
order of acquisition of inflections. Also, the fact that the first three listed all
have the same allomorphs provides an important test case of the interaction
of phonological and semantic factors. For example, if inflectional order of
acquisition were determined solely by phonological factors, then these
three should be acquired at the same time. Lastly, the study provides the
first information on the order of acquisition of specific allomorphs.
Berko developed a technique to study these forms which has come to be
known as the ‘wug’ procedure - as famous as the results of the study. First,
Berko created a series of nonsense words which ended in sounds that would
elicit one of the possible allomorphs. For example, one of her nonsense
words was ‘wug’ which would require a [z] in the plural by the rules of
English. She then created nonsense drawings which were to represent
meanings for the nonsense words. A ‘wug’, for example, was a bird-like
animal. In the case of ‘wug’, there were two pictures, one with one wug and
one with two. The child was then tested on the following item:
(9.2) This is a wug. Now there’s another one.
There are two of them, there are two -
The child was expected to fill in the last word. Table 9.3 gives the words
tested for the five inflectional morphemes. As can be seen, there were
different words for different morphemes, and some real English words used
-these were added to see if the child would treat them differently from the
nonsense words.
There were two groups of children tested, a preschool group of children
who were 4 and 5 years old, and a first grade group of 5i to 7-year-olds.
There were 19 children in the preschool group and 61 in the first grade
group.
Table 9.3 gives the results in the form of the percentage of correct
responses for each of the test items. Since the number of test items is small,
Berko’s results must be treated with some caution but one striking result is
that the children showed acquisition of the single consonant allomorphs [SI,
[z], [t], and [d], but not the ones with schwa, Le. [az] and [ad]. That is, even
though children may appear to have acquired an inflection, accurate use of
all of its allomorphs can be quite late. A related finding concerns the
differences in the scores with nonsense words requiring [ad] and [az], and
9.2 Morphological acquisition in English: a descriptive overview 441
Table 9.3 Percentage of correct productions of children studied in Berko
(1958) o n words requiring one of five English inflections
Nouns Verbs
Plural Past
glasses [az] 91 binged [dl 78
wugs [.I 91 glinged [dl 77
luns [zl 86 ricked [tl 73
tors [zl 85 melted [ad] 73
heafs’ [SI?[zl 82 spowed [dl 52
cras [zl 79 motted [ad] 33
tasses [az] 36 bodded [ad] 31
gutches [az] 36 rang 16
kazhes [az] 31
3rd singular
Possessive loodges [az] 56
nizzes [az] 28 nazzes [az] 48
bik’s [SI 87
wug’s [zl 84 Progressive
niz’s [az] 49 zibbing 90
~~ ~
the English words with the same requirements, that is, ‘glasses’ and
‘melted’. The scores on the latter were markedly better than the former.
This indicates that children may initially use words like these correctly, but
may not yet have productive use of the allomorph being used. It is an
important warning that spontaneous use is not sufficient evidence to
conclude rule-based behavior. At the same time, the strength of the rule
which was acquired for [d] was evident in the results for ‘rang’ where most of
the children regularized it.
Another finding concerned the order of acquisition of the morphemes.
The progressive with its single allomorph was the easiest one for the
children. When we compare the scores on the three morphemes which have
[az], we see that they are not the same. The children had more difficulties
using [az] with the plural than for the possessive and 3rd singular. That is,
the results suggest that there may be other factors involved than just
articulatory ones.
Brown & Fraser (1963) As with Berko (1958), this study was as important
methodologically as it was for its results. The study itself was very much a
preliminary one, with a small set of subjects and stimuli. It presented six
children between 2 and 3 years of age with a set of 13 sentences to imitate.
The goal was to see if the children would process the sentences through their
own grammatical system, or simply rote-imitate. The test sentences were as
shown in (9.3):
442 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L MORPHEMES
Table 9.4 Imitations of 13 sentences by the four youngest of six children
tested in Brown & Fraser (1963), as reported in Brown (1973:76)
Sentence
no. Eve Adam Helen Ian
(253 months) (284 months) (30 months) (314 months)
the modals may be easier than the copular and auxiliary forms of ‘to be’.
Lastly, there is an interesting pattern within the latter suggesting that the
uninverted forms may be more difficult than the inverted ones. These
preliminary results were to some degree substantiated in the in-depth
research which followed.
Fraser, Bellugi & Brown (1963) This frequently cited study set as its goal
the relation between imitation, comprehension, and production. Ten
grammatical contrasts were selected, and children were tested on their
ability to imitate, comprehend, and produce each one. Importantly, the
contrasts were selected in a way that the children would need to know
specific grammatical morphemes in order to process the sentences correctly.
For example, one contrast was between the sentences ‘The sheep is
jumping’ and ‘The sheep are jumping’. The authors state (p. 468): ‘No one
seems to have compared this kind of evidence for the passive control of
grammar in normal children with evidence of active or productive control in
the same children, and we have done an experiment to fill the gap.’ There is
no discussion of the rationale behind the selection of the ten contrasts used,
and also there are no predictions made about how the children would
perform with them. The ten contrasts tested with one of the sets of 40 test
sentences are presented in Table 9.6.
The subjects were twelve children between 37 and 43 months of age. Each
child underwent three tasks of imitation (I), comprehension (C), and
production (P). The test sentences consisted of three sets of 40 sentences
each. The three sets of test sentences were varied across the three tasks, and
444 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
Table 9.6 Ten grammatical contrasts with the 40 test sentences of Set A
taken from Fraser, Bellugi & Brown (1963: Table 2)
~ ~ ~~
the order of presentation of the three tasks was varied across subjects. A
pair of pictures was designed for each pair of sentences tested. For example,
for ‘The sheep is jumping’ the picture showed a picture of a sheep jumping,
while for ‘The sheep are jumping’ the picture showed two sheep jumping.
On the imitation task, the child was asked to repeat the test sentences after
the experimenter. The pictures were only used in the comprehension and
production tasks. In comprehension, the child was shown the two pictures
and then heard one of the test pair of sentences. H e then had to point to the
picture named. Next he was given the second test sentence and again asked
to select the appropriate picture. The pictures were used again for pro-
duction, although they were a different set than those for either imitation or
comprehension. ‘The S is twice told the names of the two pictures but not
which name goes with which picture . . . After repeating the names of the
pictures E points to one picture at a time and asks S to name it’ (Fraser,
Bellugi & Brown 1963: 469-70). Correctness was determined only in
relation to the relevant morphemes in the test sentences. A correct response
on any pair required that both sentences be imitated, comprehended, or
produced correctly.
9.2 Morphological acquisition in English: a descriptive overview 445
Table 9.7 Percentage of correct responses on the grammatical contrasts
across three tasks tested in Fraser, Bellugi & Brown (1963)
6. Affirmative / negative 75 71 50 65
7. Singular / plural, of 3rd person possessive
pronouns 96 63 33 64
8. Subject / object, in the active voice 79 67 46 64
4. Present progressive / future tense 83 67 24 58
3. Singular / plural, marked by ‘is’ and ‘are’ 83 50 29 54
5 . Present progressive / past tense 71 54 25 50
1 . Mass noun / count noun 50 54 4 36
2. Singular / plural, marked by inflection 58 29 4 31
9. Subject / object, in the passive voice 50 29 8 29
10. Indirect object / direct object 46 21 13 26
Cazden (1968) This was the first detailed analysis of the development of
inflections by Adam, Eve, and Sarah, and it laid the groundwork for
Brown’s later report (1973). Cazden studied the five noun and verb inflec-
tions which occur in English, Le. the first five morphemes listed in (9.1).
To do this, Cazden made several important methodological decisions
which are needed in any in-depth study of grammatical development. We
will look at each in turn.
The first decision concerns how to measure whether the child has a
particular morpheme or not. We have already discussed the problem
with counting absolute frequencies as a measure of acquisition. The
problem is that we need both to see when a morpheme is used, and the
number of times that it is used appropriately. Cazden reasoned (p. 227)
that there are four possible ways in which an inflection could be scored
for a child:
S,: ‘supplied correctly’, Le. the child used an inflection in a context
for which it was appropriate, e.g. ‘two dogs’ in reference to two
dogs;
S,: ‘supplied in inappropriate contexts’, i.e. the child used an inflec-
tion in a place where it was inappropriate, e.g. ‘one dogs’ in refer-
ence to a single dog;
0: ‘required but omitted’, Le. the child did not use an inflection in a
context where it was required, based on the rules of English
grammar, e.g. ‘two dog’ to refer to two dogs;
OG: ‘overgeneralizations’, Le. use of the inflection in a context
where an alternative form was correct, e.g. ‘two foots’ used to
mean ‘two feet’.
Distinctions like this enabled Cazden to see more clearly the ways in which
inflections were used in the data.
A second decision concerns how one can determine when a context for
appropriate use has occurred in the data. In determining transliterations
for chi!dren’s utterances’, claims about missing morphemes have to be
made. Cazden set specific criteria for determining contexts when a mor-
pheme should be required; a feel for these can be seen by looking at her
criteria for determining when a plural morpheme would be required in a
sentence (p. 227):
448 S I M P L E SENTENCES: A C Q U I S I T I O N OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
Number - required after numbers except 1: ‘two minute’;
Linguistic - required on count nouns after such modifiers as ‘more’ or
‘some’: ‘more page’;
Interaction - required for discourse agreement: ‘shoe’ in response to
parent’s question, ‘what are those?’;
Normally plural - ‘stair’ (‘upstairs’);
Routines - either public, like nursery rhymes and the names of
cartoon characters - ‘Mr Ear’ (‘Mr Ears’) - or private, like Eve’s
telegraphic version of her mother’s oft-repeated explanation of
father’s work - ‘Make penny Ema’ Hall’ (‘He’s making pennies in
Emerson Hall’).
One point about these measures is that all three need to be examined
(Cazden does this) before claims about adult-like acquisition can be made.
The child may have a high proportion of correct use, but still will not have
an adult system if the other two proportions are high. A second point
concerns the measure for the proportion of overgeneralization. This does
not appear to me to be a very useful measure since the S, contexts are not
ones where overgeneralizations can occur in the first place. I would
recommend an alternative, such as the following:
In this formula, we could also distinguish between two types of OG, those
which occur on an unmarked irregular form, e.g. ‘two foots’, versus those
which occur on the marked form, e.g. ‘two feets’. Since Cazden does not
provide the needed information, I cannot replace her measure of over-
9.2 Morphological acquisition in English: a descriptive overview 449
Table 9.8 Four periods in the acquisition of the English plural morpheme
for Adam, Eve, and Sarah, adapted from Cazden (1968: 228, table 1)
A - 0.00 - - 0 - - 0 -
B 0.36 0.15 0.13 0 0 0 0 0 0
C 0.68 0.86 0.86 25 10 4 2 8 0
D 0.94 0.98 0.98 54 1 28 40 I 23
Mean
rank Grammatical morphemes and general order of acquisition
* The contractible allomorphs discussed by Brown are {-s, -z, -m, -r}; the uncontractible ones
are {is, am, are}.
ticular (given here in Table 9.9), which begin development in Stage 11. The
methodology is very similar to that used by Cazden. Linguistic and
non-linguisticcontextual information was used to determine contexts where
the morphemes could be obligatory. Adam’s, Eve’s, and Sarah’s use of the
14 grammatical morphemes was then measured by the percentage of
obligatory morphemes supplied, which is more or less the same measure
used by Cazden which we called the proportion of correct use. A grammati-
cal morpheme was claimed to be acquired when this measure reached 90
percent. These 14 grammatical morphemes include the five studied by
Cazden .
Brown first presents his results in terms of the order of acquisition of the
14 morphemes for each of the three children. These famous results are
reproduced here in Table 9.10. Note about this table that nearly one-third
of the morphemes did not reach criterion at the last samples taken at
Stage V. The second point concerns the relative similarity across the
children of the first morphemes acquired.
Brown pursued the latter point by looking at the rank order of acquisition
of the 14 grammatical morphemes across the three children. For example,
the plural morpheme was acquired first by Sarah, and fourth by both Adam
and Eve for a mean rank of 3.00 (Le. 1+4+4 = 9 divided by 3 = 3.00).
Statistical analysis revealed a significant correlation between these rank
orders and MLU.
9.2 Morphological acquisition in English: a descriptive overview 453
Table 9.10 The order of acquisition of Mgrammatical morphemes for
Adam, Eve, and Sarah, taken from Brown (1973: 271, Figure 14)
PERIOD I
Declaratives
Grammatical
‘The nice monkey can kiss his little sister’ 38/48
Ungrammatical
Tensed verb: ‘The boy can pushed the elephant’ 0/31 13/31 14/31
Word order: ‘The boy push will the elephant’ O/26 1 1126 14/26
Wh questions
Grammatical
‘What will the boy eat?’ 117 517 1/7
Ungrammatical
Misplacement: ‘What the boy will eat?’ 3/11 8111
Yes/no questions
Grammatical
‘Can the boy push the elephant?’ 2/16 10116
Ungrammatical
Tensed verb: ‘Can the boy pushed the elephant?’0/21 19/21 2/21
PERIOD I1
Wh-questions
Grammatical
‘What will the boy eat?’ Oil0
Ungrammatical
Misplacement ‘What the boy will eat?’ 8/10
Yes/no questions
Grammatical
‘Can the boy push the elephant?’ 10110
Ungrammatical
Tensed verb: ‘Can the boy pushed the elephant?’l/lO 9/10
I This category records when Abe changes the tense of the verb, e.g. imitating ‘The boy can
pushed the elephant’ as ‘The boy can push the elephant.’
Kuczaj & Maratsos (1975) This preliminary study on one child led to
several consequent studies (e.g. Kuczaj 1978; Maratsos & Kuczaj 1978;
Kuczaj & Brannick 1979). The study is useful in providing some more
detailed facts on acquisition by a single child, as well as demonstrating a
valuable technique. The subject was the first author’s son Abe. Example
9.3 The acquisition of Aux in English questions 457
(9.7) gives a summary of Abe’s use of Aux in his speech during the time he
was studied:
(9.7) period I 2,5(21)-2,7(15) with MLU 3.01 to 3.25:
The 3,058 sentences collected revealed only 4 with either
‘will’ or ‘can’.
period I1 2,9(16)-(19):
Aux was used in declaratives but not in questions.
As can be seen, Abe was not using Aux in his spontaneous speech during
period 1. The authors anticipated, however, that Abe might have already
begun the acquisition of Aux in his receptive language. To get at this, they
gave him several sentences to imitate which contained instances of ‘can’ and
‘will’. This is the technique we saw earlier in this chapter in the study by
Brown & Fraser (1963). It was hoped that Abe would show the ‘filter
effect’, i.e. that he would change the sentences to reflect his grammatical
knowledge. These sentences consisted of declarative sentences as well as
wh-questions and yesho questions. Each type of sentence also had sen-
tences which were either grammatical or ungrammatical based on the rules
of adult English speakers. The types of sentences used, with examples of
each, are given in Table 9.11.
Abe’s imitation showed a pattern indicating an underlying grammatical
system. An examination of his imitations of declaratives reveals an
awareness of the distribution of the English Aux. He correctly imitated it in
grammatical sentences, and changed ungrammatical ones to be grammati-
cal, either by deletion (of the Aux or tense on the verb) or by reordering. He
did not, however, show an awareness of how Aux occurs in questions. In
both grammatical and ungrammatical questions, he would delete the Aux.
These results lead to a first conclusion that Abe acquired Aux in declara-
tives before questions.
Table 9.11 also presents Abe’s pattern of response during period 11. At
this time, Abe repeats grammatical yesho questions correctly, and also
changes ungrammatical ones to be correct. This indicates that he had
acquired the rule of Subject-Aux Inversion, at least for questions. The
latter restriction is made because of his responses on wh-questions. On
these, he would correctly imitate the ungrammatical ones, and change the
grammatical ones into ungrammatical ones, i.e. he would change a question
such as ‘What will the boy eat?’ into ‘What the boy will eat?’ It should be
noted here that the study only examined the modals ‘will’ and ‘can’.
bility for the collection of data from Adam. In her 1967 dissertation, she
analyzed the data from all three children and reported stages in the
acquisition of questions. Brief reports can be found in Klima & Bellugi-
Klima (1966) and Bellugi (1971). Ironically, the most complete published
summary of these stages is in Cazden (1970). A summary of these stages,
based on the latter report, is given in (9.8), which also gives Adam’s age
and stage at each period considered.
(9.8) period A: (I, 28 months) Children do not have Aux.
Yeslno questions marked by intonation, e.g. ‘sit chair?’,
‘ball go?’
Wh-questions restricted to ‘what’ and ‘where’in limited
forms, e.g. ‘what’s that?’, ‘where cookie go?’
period B: (11,111, 35 months)
period C: (IV, 38 months) Aux appears throughont system. Inver-
sion occurs in yeslno questions but not wh-questions.
Yes/no question, e.g. ‘does lions walk?’, ‘oh, did I
caught it?’, ‘will you help me?’
Wh-questions, e.g. ‘what he can ride in?’, ‘why kitty
can’t stand up?’, ‘what he can ride in?’
periods
D to F: (V and later) Gradual emergence of tag questions
These stages were widely accepted by investigators, as indicated by their
citation in texts at the time (e.g. Dale 1976). The most important stage
proposed is period C when children show inversion in yes/no questions but
not in wh-questions. This is also the pattern we just saw in Abe’s data.
Besides the uninverted wh-questions, there are two other kinds of errors
that need to be pointed out. One is the occurrence of what we will call
double tense marking, which refers to those sentences where tense is
marked twice, once in the Aux and once on the verb. An example from
(9.8) is ‘oh, did I caught it?’ Examples such as these pose an instant problem
for explanation, for they require one to account for tense being copied onto
the verb rather than being moved, which is the normal proposal for adult
English. A related error is what we will call double Aux marking. Hurford
(1975) cites examples of these from his daughter: ‘whose is that is?’ and
‘what did you did?’. These differ from double tense marking in that the
entire Aux is copied, not just the tense constituent. Examples of these other
two kinds of errors have been noted and discussed in works by Hurford
(1975), Prideaux (1976), Kuczaj (1976), Fay (1978), Maratsos & Kuczaj
9.3 The acquisition of Aux in English questions 459
Table 9.12 The proportion of auxiliaries and proportion of inversion
found in Ingram & Tyack (1979) for 21 subjects
~~~ ~ ~
Yestno Wh Yeslno Wh
~~
(1978), Erreich, Valian & Winzemer (1980), and Klein (1982), among
others.
Subsequent research into these patterns of acquisition has qualified the facts
as they have been described. One qualification concerns the accuracy of the
periods as described by Bellugi. Most of the published accounts of these
periods are anecdotal in the sense that they are presented with examples
rather than precise measures. One exception is Bellugi (1971) where some
figures are given for Adam’s use of inverted and uninverted auxiliaries. At
3;6, Adam produced only eight inverted wh-questions out of 30, for a
proportion of 0.27. This changed to 0.87 at 3;11 (33 out of 38). Brown
(1968) also gives some absolute numbers for the occurrence of these for
Adam, Eve, and Sarah. He states that Adam produced 145 such questions
between Stages I11 through V, while Eve produced seven and Sarah 18.
Such data suggest that the pattern was clearly more characteristic of the
speech of Adam than of the other two children.
Ingram & Tyack (1979) attempted to test these periods further by using a
larger sample and more precise measures of inversion. The subjects were 21
children between 2;O and 3;11 who were placed into periods A through F
based on the MLUs given for these periods. Approximately 225 questions
were collected from each child. These were then examined for (i) the use of
Aux, and (ii) the occurrence of inversion. For the first point, the measure
used was the proportion of auxiliaries, that is, how often did the questions
have an Aux in them. The second point was measured by the proportion of
inversion. This measure was applied to just those questions which had an
Aux, and determined the proportion of those which showed the Aux
appearing before the subject NP. Table 9.12 gives the general results.
We see the gradual emergence of auxiliaries as characteristic of grammati-
460 S I M P L E SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
cal morphemes, as indicated at the onset of this chapter. Of some import-
ance is the observation that they occur even in periods A and B, at least as
these can be assigned on the basis of MLU. Of more importance is the lack
of a clearly marked period C, that is, at all times the children’s use of
inversions for wh-questions was as great as that for yesho questions.
The question arises, then, of how to account for the discrepancy between
these figures and the patterns reported for Abe and Adam. Ingram & Tyack
discuss this point, and mention that two of their subjects did indeed show
uninverted wh-questions of the sort reported in the literature. Their
appearance, however, did not occur to such a degree as to differ sub-
stantially from the yes/no questions. Also, they tended to occur more for
uncontracted auxiliaries than for contracted ones. These results, therefore,
suggested that the use of uninverted Aux is not as extensive as implied in
Bellugi’s stages and that they may be restricted to certain contexts.
Such restrictions have been confirmed by subsequent research by Labov
& Labov (1978), Kuczaj & Brannick (1979), and Erreich (1984). These first
two studies are methodologically complementary in that Labov & Labov
is an intensive single-subject study, while Kuczaj & Brannick is a cross-
sectional study of several children. Their general results show that the
inversion of Aux in wh-questions occurs gradually for specific wh-words.
For example, children will show inversion for ‘what’ questions while having
uninverted ‘why’ questions. Kuczaj & Brannick (1979: 43) state:
The results suggest that children learn to apply this rule [Subject-Aux
Inversion, DI] to questions beginning with one or two wh words, then
to questions beginning with another wh word, and so on, rather than
to all relevant question types simultaneously, indicating that the
acquisition of this syntactic rule is initially relatively specific.
Another qualification concerns the generality of double tense marking
and double Aux marking. As mentioned, examples of these are mostly
presented anecdotally with little measurement of their pervasiveness. An
exception is the report by Maratsos & Kuczaj (1978) where figures are given
on the occurrence of these errors in the speech of four subjects. For two
subjects, there were virtually no examples of such errors. For two others,
these were restricted to forms with ‘do’. These data are presented in
Table 9.13. They also cite data from 15 children discussed in Kuczaj (1976)
that show the same pattern. Further data in support of the restriction of
such errors in questions to ‘do’ appear in Davis (1987).
Both Hurford (1975) and Maratsos & Kuczaj (1978) report two further
aspects to these errors. One is that double tense marking is normally
restricted to irregular past forms (e.g. ‘broke’) instead of regular pasts (e.g.
‘missed’) or overgeneralized past forms (e.g. ‘breaked’). Also, Maratsos &
9.3 The acquisition of Aux in English questions 461
Table 9.13 Proportion of double tense marking for Jive possible Aux’s
reported for two subjects in Maratsos & Kuczaj (1978)
Kuczaj claim that double Aux marking is extremely rare, and that it
constitutes a different kind of error from double tense marking. They state
(p. 344): ‘Occasional errors such as ‘is this is the powder’ may not require
any explanation at all, given their extremely low frequency. . .’
In summary, several kinds of errors in the acquisition of Aux in English
have been reported. At first, these were proposed as general patterns in
acquisition, but have since been seen to occur (i) in some children more
often than in others, (ii) in more restricted contexts than first proposed, and
(iii) with differing degrees of frequency.
Performance factors The first attempts to account for Bellugi’s periods are
found in Bellugi (1967), Brown, Cazden & Bellugi (1969), and Brown
(1968). Brown divides the child’s acquisition of wh-questions into two
general stages. Before MLU Stage 111, the child’s questions are seen as
being either memorized routines or constructions which are nontransfor-
mational in nature. This is the time when Aux is rare, and when wh-
questions are restricted to forms such as ‘what that?’. By Stage 111,
however, evidence emerges for more productive rules. The general expla-
nation of these studies is that evidence exists that the child has both
462 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF GRAMMATICAL MORPHEMES
A second argument they give is that the children did not invert auxiliary
elements in questions for declarative sentences, as in ‘you better go’, or
similar sentences with ‘gonna’ and ‘wanna’. These should be predicted, they
claim, if the child has a general Aux category. Their account of the
acquisition of Subject-Aux Inversion, then, is that the child has not yet
formulated a general rule and is instead acquiring it in a very restricted way.
The explanation of double tense marking and double Aux marking is
taken up in Maratsos & Kuczaj (1978). They begin by acknowledging that
double tense marking is usually restricted to questions with forms of ‘do’
and an irregular verb. They then go on to assume that these are the result of
performance factors. They state (p. 343): ‘. . . w e assume that these are
errors of production, rather than representing underlying rule structure,
and that the child has by and large analysed the relevant sequences
accurately’. The performance factor which is at stake is one of lexical
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 465
retrieval, that is, in selecting the appropriate verb, the child picks the wrong
one. The reason this occurs with just ‘do’ is presumably because the only
function of ‘do’ is to indicate tense.
Maratsos & Kuczaj correctly point out the retrieval error solution will not
work for double Aux marking since this involves inserting an Aux where
one does not belong. These errors, however, are seen to be much less
frequent than those of double tense marking. The implication is that errors
of such minimal frequency are probably due to some other performance
factor, and that their rarity is sufficient to give them secondary importance.
Maratsos & Kuczaj account for uninverted wh-questions through com-
petence factors (specific learning) and double marking constructions
through performance factors. More than other proposals, they also take
into consideration the restrictions on the data on such errors. Despite their
concern with the data, their account is still not a completely satisfactory
explanation. A criticism is the same as the one directed to the discussion of
distributional learning in Chapter 7: such accounts do not work from a
theory of grammar and do not deal with how the child goes from specific
learning to general rules. In this particular case, there are also at least two
gaps in the explanation given. One concerns the claim that the child has
made retrieval errors; and it seems that some theory of when such errors do
and don’t occur is needed. For example, they do not explain why the child
wouldn’t show similar retrieval problems with other Aux elements besides
‘do’. Another problem is the claim that ‘wanna’ and ‘gonna’ are auxiliaries.
One could also claim that they are main verbs, and that the child has their
appropriate structure acquired (cf. Ingram 1985a).
9.4.1 Passives
In Chapter 7, section 7.2.4 we discussed comprehension of the passive, as
tested by de Villiers & de Villiers (1973a). I interpreted their results as
466 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
indicating that children at age 27 months have some awareness that passives
are different from actives, but that they don’t yet understand the semantics
of the structure. Here I will examine the development of this construction
over a longer period of time, first by looking at some production data and
then by turning to comprehension - a reversal of the approach in earlier
chapters. Unlike the literature for earlier periods of acquisition, that on
later grammatical development is more balanced in terms of the number of
studies in each area. Also, the constructions under discussion are infrequent
in spoken language and require careful comprehension studies.
Horgan (1978) This is the most comprehensive study of the use of passives
in spontaneous speech. Some basic information on the subjects who were
observed and the methods of data collection are given below:
group I: 54 children between 2;O and 4;2. Subjects described 44
pictures in each of two sessions, three months apart.
group 11: 180 children, 30 in each age group of 5, 6, 7, 9, 11, 13
years. Subjects told stories about pictures.
group 111: 262 university students. Subjects were asked to describe
pictures with passives within a structured task.
We see that Horgan not only studied children in the period which we are
reviewing, but also older children and adults. The adult data were obtained
so that normative comparisons could be established.
The first major point that Horgan makes concerns the difference between
full passives and truncated passives. These distinctions as well as others
which Horgan makes are given in (9.11):
(9.11) Types of passives
a. Truncated passives:
inanimate logical objects, e.g. ‘The lamp was broken’
animate logical objects, e.g. ‘The boy was chased’
statives with ‘get’, e.g. ‘It got broken’
b. Full passives:
reversible, e.g. ‘The boy was chased by the girl’
non-reversible, with agent as logical subject, e.g. ‘The lamp was
broken by the girl’
non-reversible, with instrument as logical subject, e.g. ‘The lamp
was broken by (or ‘with’) the ball’
Horgan excludes truncated passives from the study on the grounds that
they are a distinct structure from the full passive. That is, she proposes that
the two kinds of passives are not transformationally related, but instead are
generated independently of each other. She presents two arguments from
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 467
Table 9.14 The frequency of occurrence of three kinds of full passives for
three age groups of children, taken from Horgan (1978: Table 3)
2-4 15 0 17 32
5-7 10 0 9 19
9-13 21 15 14 50
Total* 46 15 40 101
* Two passives were not classified because the subject was inaudible.
her data for this position. First, there is a noticeable difference in the
frequency of the two passives. Truncated passives are much more frequent
than full passives in the spontaneous speech of children. This observation is
not consistent with the predictions of the transformational analysis, since
the full passives are supposed to be more basic. The second argument is that
they have different characteristics. Most truncated passives in the child data
occurred with inanimate logical objects, while most full passives occurred
with animate logical objects. Further, truncated passives mostly had
familiar verbs like ‘break’ and were often used in a stative sense with ‘get’,
e.g. ‘it got broke’. Full passives, on the other hand, were used with a wider
variety of action verbs.
Despite the large samples, there were relatively few full passives pro-
duced by the children. Group I produced 32 full passives and group I1
produced 81. If we consider that the group I children were asked to produce
88 sentences across the two sessions, then the 32 passives occurred in a
sample of approximately 4,700 sentences. Table 9.14 gives a breakdown of
the use of the different kinds of full passives by the children. Not only are
passives infrequent, but no non-reversible agentive ones occurred until
age 9.
Horgan makes the following additional observations about these data.
First, ‘until age 11, no child produced both reversible and non-reversible
passives’ (p. 72). That is, individual children appeared to select one way or
the other to express passives. This created problems for children when they
needed to express something that required the other form. For example,
Horgan gives the following examples of sentences by children with only the
non-reversible construction, who wanted to express a reversible meaning:
(9.12) a. ‘the man was killed by the hand’
b. ‘the boy was kicked by the foot’
The second observation concerned the use of passives by the 2- and 4-year
olds. Most of their reversible passives had the wrong word order, so that
468 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
Table 9.15 Mean percentages of four kinds of responses for Stage II-V
groups on the understanding of active and passive sentences, taken from de
Villiers & de Villiers (1973a: Table I )
‘the cat was chased by the girl’ was used to describe a picture of a cat chasing
a girl. This is consistent with our impression from de Villiers & de Villiers
that children have some awareness of the form of the passive, but not its
meaning.
Given production data of the kind cited above from Horgan, it is not
surprising that most studies on passives use more specific elicitation
procedures (e.g. Smith 1970; Whitehurst, Ironsmith & Goldfein 1974) or
comprehension tasks. The comprehension research will be reviewed by
returning to de Villiers & de Villiers (1973a) and then by looking at the
studies reported in Maratsos, Kuczaj, Fox & Chalkley (1979).
In section 7.2.3, we reviewed the study by de Villiers & de Villiers
(1973a) on the acquisition of English word order in the context of chil-
dren’s ability to process active and passive sentences. To review, they
tested 33 children across several ages on reversible active and passive
sentences. They placed the children’s responses into four categories:
correct, reversed, child as agent, and refusals. On the basis of their results
presented in Table 7.8, I concluded that the data indicated that late
Stage I children show awareness of the formal characteristics of passives
since they responded to them differently than they do actives (see 7.2.4
for details).
Table 9.15 presents their data for the children who were beyond Stage I.
As with the late Stage I children, the older children show an understanding
of the actives but not the passives. Do the data, however, provide evidence
that the children are responding differently to passives than actives, as it did
for late Stage I? Recall that a crucial indicator would be if the children’s
percentages of reversals for passives were the same as those for correct
responses to actives. We see in Table 9.15 that this is not true for Stages 11,
111, and late IV, V. We also get marked differences in the ‘child as agent’
responses for Stage 111. I interpret these differences as indicating that
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 469
several children must be aware of the fact that passives are formally
different from actives, and that other children can even interpret them
correctly.
There is in Table 9.15 a striking pattern of response for the early Stage IV
children: it appears that they are treating passives exactly like actives. This
is a pattern which has been observed by others, e.g. Bever (1970). There are
two ways in which we could interpret this. One is that this effect is due to the
small sample size and to a sampling error in which children had been
selected who had not yet acquired even an awareness of passives. The
alternative is that children around this point in acquisition adopt a strategy
for dealing with passives of treating them as corresponding actives. Note
that the existence of such a performance factor does not necessarily mean
that the children are unaware of the formal characteristics of passives, but
rather that they have reached a cognitive level where they have better
problem-solving abilities than earlier. Versions of this strategy have been
around since its first proposal in Bever (1970).
In viewing results such as those in Table 9.15, there is an alternative to
the claim that children either do or do not have the passive. This is that
the children may have some knowledge of the grammar of passives, but
incomplete knowledge. Such a possibility is suggested by the data from
Horgan’s study, in that truncated passives were acquired differently from
full ones, and even full ones came in differently from each other. This
alternative would also account for the data in Table 9.15 if we assume that
children are getting some forms of passive correct but not others. The
observation that children may acquire passives differently for different
verbs was first made in Sinclair & Ferreiro (1970). More recently it has
been argued for in Maratsos et al. (1979) and in Sudhalter & Braine
(1985).
This will eventually lead to a new phrase structure rule which generates
passives as well as oblique prepositional phrases. The difference between
the two rules will be in the grammatical roles of the NPs. A last step will be
the child’s acquiring a second lexical entry for the passive form of the verb.
For example, the child’s lexicon will have ‘bite’ for active sentences and
‘bitten’ for passive ones.
These steps indicate a continuous development in which the child
establishes the Passive rule as explained by the lexical functional approach,
without any extensive discontinuity. In Pinker’s discussion, in fact, there is
no reference to a need for orphan categories in acquiring the passive, as
there was with the oblique prepositional phrase. That is, once the structure
for the oblique PPs is acquired, the acquisition of passives should follow
smoothly, given appropriate input.
Given Pinker’s explanation, there is then the question of whether this
account fits the acquisition facts as described above. There are at least two
general findings that need to be explained: (i) the treatment of passive
sentences as if they were actives, and (ii) the incomplete acquisition of
passives, where the rule is applied to active verbs but not to nonactive ones.
A further, less well-documented observation is Horgan’s, that children may
express active meanings with passive morphology.
Pinker is aware of the phenomenon (i) and discusses it in his book. He
does not, however, directly offer an account for it. We will therefore
speculate about how he would deal with it. One possibility is to say that
the child has no contextual information in this situation. That is, the child
has no information which tells him that the subject is not an agent. If this
occurs, however, it seems that the procedures could lead the child t o a
grammar where actives can have either active or passive morphology.
This would account for Horgan’s observations that actives may be
expressed with passive formalism. Such a grammar could be restructured
if it contained some orphans and the child subsequently heard passives
with contextual information. Another possibility would be to consider
such examples as the result of a performance factor which has intervened
in the acquisition procedures. This performance mechanism would be one
that operates when the child can’t process all of a sentence, and yet needs
to determine some meaning. In this case, it would tell the child to ignore
the passive morphology and preposition, and impose some canonical
expected meaning. The consequences of such a mechanism is to say that
some sentences are processed for learning and others are not. This
appears to be Pinker’s proposal; in a general discussion of input, he states
(p. 28):
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 473
I also assume that not all sentences heard by the child, nor all parts of a
sentence, will be used as input to his or her acquisition mechanisms.
Presumably children encode most reliably the parts of sentences
whose words they understand individually, and the whole sentences
most of whose words they understand.
Age groups
do so in any order. While responses with only one action were scored as
incorrect, Sheldon comments that these never were more than 4-5 percent
of the total responses for any sentence type.
Table 9.18 gives the results on the eight sentence types tested. Statistical
tests revealed the following results:
(a) The coordinate sentences were easier than the relative ones, and
showed no differences across the age groups. Conclusion: the children
were aware that relative sentences are different from coordinate ones.
This finding reminds us of the one by de Villiers & de Villiers (1973a)
on actives and passives, where the children showed an awareness that
passives were different even though they hadn’t determined their
actual features.
(b) The SS and 00 relative sentences were significantly easier than
SO and OS relatives. Conclusion: sentences are easier to understand
when the NP which has a relative and the NP which is relativized have
the same grammatical function. Sheldon refers to this as the parallel
function hypothesis.
(c) SS relatives show significant improvement across age groups, but
the 00 relatives do not. Conclusion: there must be some additional
factor which causes this effect.
The first finding has been verified by other research and has not been
particularly controversial. The opposite has been the case, however,
concerning the second finding. A useful review of this issue can be found in
Bowerman (1979). This literature, in fact, has been so contradictory that
Bowerman has commented (p. 292) that it ‘presents a tangled web of
conflicting findings and alternative interpretations’. The criticisms can be
480 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
grouped into two categories. First, there are those who question whether
the data support the conclusion. Some studies have found results which
show different patterns of difficulty, e.g. de Villiers et ul. (1979). Others
(e.g. Hamburger & Crain 1982) have noted that the parallel function
hypothesis does not account for the fact that SS relatives are easier than 00
ones (although Sheldon has a proposal for this which will be discussed
shortly). Second, others have questioned the parallel function hypothesis
on theoretical grounds. It is not clear what role this function plays in the
acquisition of relatives. While it appears to be a performance factor, it could
operate under two possible conditions: (a) the child has acquired the
grammar of English relatives, but uses this as a processing constraint when
short-term memory fails, or (b) the child has not acquired the grammar of
English relatives, and uses this as a heuristic for responding while acquiring
them. As pointed out by Hamburger & Crain (1982), this is a claim about
the performance factors affecting relatives rather than one about how the
child’s competence emerges. Tavakolian (1981b) has rejected the parallel
function hypothesis in that it assigns too much competence to the child and
claims instead that the children are treating these sentences as if they were
simply two conjoined clauses.
Sheldon does offer a proposal to account for the third finding which
addresses the child’s linguistic competence. She argues that the pattern in
the third finding given above results from the child’s overuse of the English
rule of Extraposition. This is a rule in the adult language which moves a
relative clause from a subject NP to the end of the sentence. This rule, for
example, would operate on (9.21a) to produce (9.21b):
(9.21) a. The boy who left was sick
b. The boy was sick who left
c. The dog bumps into the horse that the giraffe jumps over
d. The dog that the giruffe jumps over bumps into the horse
Sheldon proposes that children have this rule, and thus treat 00 sentences
like (9.21~)as if they were an SO sentence as in (9.21d). The distribution of
the children’s responses, then, was as follows (figures are percentages):
ss so os 00
Correct 52 17 29 50
Parallel function 14 69 14 12
Extraposition 44 32
Other 33 13 12 5
An important set of evidence in support of the Extraposition argument is
that approximately one-third of the children only made this error on the
object relatives. Even more importantly, the same subjects virtually never
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 481
got any of the object relatives correct. The main criticisms of the proposal
are (i) that there is little other evidence to date that children have such a
rule at this point in acquisition, and (ii) doubt as to why the child would ever
form it this way since it is not a pattern found in the adult language. If it were
the result of overgeneralization of the rule, as Sheldon suggests, then the
children would require indirect negative evidence to overcome their
mistakes.
Sheldon’s study was important in drawing attention to children’s emerg-
ing ability to understand relatives, and it suggested some possible ways to
account for it. It also influenced the study on relatives reported in
Hamburger & Crain (1982).
Hamburger & Crain (1982) Hamburger & Crain approach the topic from
the perspective of Language Acquisition as discussed in Part I of this
volume. They are quick to point out that Sheldon’s study is more a study of
performance factors than competence factors. Their own orientation is
along the lines of what we have called a strong inclusion hypothesis. They
set out to show that children may have a better knowledge of relative
clauses than is indicated by research to date. Since they are in agreement
with Sheldon’s implicit claim that children have rules for relatives, they are
more concerned about the extent of errors found in the data. In particular,
they want to construct the experiments on the acquisition of relative clauses
in such a way as to minimize the conditions that encourage the use of
performance factors.
Hamburger & Crain studied the comprehension of relative clauses by
having children act out sentences, as Sheldon did. They adjusted other
aspects of Sheldon’s methodology in the following ways:
Patterns of response
Age groups 12,23 23,12 12 Other Sheldon’s scoring
(perfect score = 3)
3 years 42 27 0 31 2.07
4 years 18 43 13 26 1.83
5 years 5 35 55 5 1.2
Average 22 35 23 21 1.7
Table 9.19 presents the major results of the study. Hamburger & Crain
treat the three patterns given in Table 9.19 (excluding ‘other’) as all
correct, i.e. indicating correct processing of the sentence. They see the
patterns 12,23 and 23,12 as differing in that the latter reflects more
accurately the natural order of the events. They also score 12 as correct
because it indicates that the child is aware that the relative clause is
functioning to help delimit which toy to select, and that the main action is
having the main clause subject act upon the main clause object. By these
measures, then, the children can be interpreted as showing good ability at
OS structures, since the percentages of correct response are 60,74, and 95
for the three groups.
In Table 9.19, I have also entered the score which the children would
have received if Sheldon’s scoring methods had been used. By her measure,
both 12,23 and 23’12 would have been correct, but 12 would not. We then
multiplied by 3 the percentages obtained, to get an equivalent score. By
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 483
comparing these scores with those in Table 9.18, it is seen that the
Hamburger & Crain’s children did do better than those tested by Sheldon.
There appear to be two major differences in the two studies which led to
the better performance of the children: several exemplars of the head of the
relative clause were used, and only one sentence type with relatives was
tested. One can propose that these two changes made it much easier to do
the task, which indeed was the goal of the study. The general conclusion is
that at least some younger children can be shown to have more knowledge
of relative clauses than has been proposed (at least by some) when optimal
test conditions are involved.
While the above conclusion appears to be a reasonable one, I would like
to point out an alternative interpretation. If all three response types above
are correct ones, then one would expect a gradual improvement in all three
across time. This, in fact, is not the case. The 12,23 and 12 patterns are
actually going in opposite directions. A different interpretation results if we
assume that 12,23 results from incorrect processing and 12 results from
correct processing. This is also reasonable, in that 12,23 could also result
from treating the sentence as a form of coordination whereby the child
treats the last NP mentioned before the second verb as its subject. Under
this alternative, relative clause comprehension does not look as well
developed in children younger than 5 years.
A second study conducted by Hamburger & Crain involved the pro-
duction of relative clauses, which, as we observed earlier, are not common
in the speech of children at these ages. As in the above study, Hamburger &
Crain wanted to create an optimal situation for the elicitation of relatives.
To do this, they placed children in a situation where they had to describe
something to someone who was blindfolded. The child had to tell this
person to pick up one of a set of objects which was doing something. For
example, there could be a set of walruses where one was seen tickling a
zebra. An appropriate response would be ‘Pick up the walrus that is tickling
the zebra’. Ten of the 12 children responded and 72 percent of their
responses used some form of an OS sentence.
Carol Chomsky (1969) This study is a classic in the field for several
reasons. At the time of its appearance, there was a general impression
that language acquisition was complete by age 4 or 5 years. Chomsky
demonstrated that several of the more complex aspects of English syntax
may not be acquired completely until the primary school years. The
study was also important for isolating the areas which may be acquired
later. She conducted studies on children’s ability to process complex
sentences with the verbs ‘easy to see’, ‘promise’, ‘ask’, and ‘tell’. She also
proposed stages that children appear to go through in acquiring such
constructions.
The last study reported by Chomsky was one on pronominalization. It
looked at the ability of 40 children between 5 and 10 years of age to process
three specific constructions, exemplified here in (9.26). Chomsky simply
refers to these as ‘types’, and we have provided the labels for them, based
on terminology used in Ingram & Shaw (1981).
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 489
(9.26) type 1 Blocked backwards pronominalization
He found out that Mickey won the race
type 2: Backwards pronominalization
Before he went out, Pluto took a nap
type 3: Forwards pronominalization
Pluto thinks he knows everything
Each child took a 15-item comprehension test, with five sentences for each
of the three types. First the child was presented with two dolls, Mickey and
Pluto. Then the child was read the test sentence followed with a question
about its interpretation, e.g. ‘Pluto thinks that he knows everything. Pluto
thinks that who knows everything?’ The child then would answer with the
name of one of the dolls. Each response was then recorded as either
coreferential or non-coreferential.
Since the responses on types 2 and 3 could be either coreferential or non-
coreferential, Chomsky only considered the scores on type 1, i.e. blocked
backwards pronominalization. She considered this construction to be
acquired when all five test sentences were answered correctly, i.e. as being
non-coreferential. Of the 40 subjects, 31 (or 78 percent) showed acquisition
of type 1. Further, with just three exceptions, it was at age 5-6 years that
children began to meet her criterion for acquisition. She noted that 36 sub-
jects also showed at least some coreferential responses on type 2. From these
results she concluded (p. 109): ‘the principles of pronominalization appear
to be acquired by the majority of children at about the same age’. Impor-
tantly, her interpretation of the results is a maturational one. She proposes
that the principle (or principles) which children use for pronominal reference
matures around age 5 or 6 , and its emergence is independent of ‘linguistic
elaboration in the environment, intelligence, and rate of general cognitive
development’ (p. 110). This principle, using N. Chomsky’s more recent pro-
posals, would be condition C of the binding conditions.
Chomsky has little to say about the children’s performance before the
maturation of the appropriate grammatical principle. She does, however,
mention four subjects who got type 1 correct and never responded with
coreferential responses on Type 2 - backwards pronominalization. The
pattern of these subjects could result from a simple rule of linear order
rather than one of c-command. Chomsky, in fact, leans in this direction by
saying that these subjects ‘seem to be operating with the simple principle
that the basic function of a pronoun is to refer to what precedes, without
further refinements’ (p. 109). This opens the possibility that the structural
principle needed for backwards pronominalization is preceded in acqui-
sition by a simpler rule based on the order of appearance of the pronoun and
its antecedent.
490 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
Chomsky’s study was one which was clearly ahead of its time. The
development since then of linguistic theory on pronominal reference makes
it possible to restate her findings in more current terminology. Her
maturational explanation implies that c-command is a principle which
matures at a point around age 5 or 6. Before then, without that principle,
children rely on a rule which uses only the linear relation of the pronoun and
the antecedent. The result of this situation is a marked discontinuity in the
acquisition of pronominal reference.
More recent research has attempted to expand the range of constructions
studied (Ingram & Shaw 1981; Solan 1983,1987; Crain & McKee 1985), as
well as to examine other languages (O’Grady, Suzuki-Wei & Cho 1986).
This research has also included an extension of the topic to reflexive con-
structions (Wexler & Chen 1985).
One line of this research has been from a nativist perspective. The
primary support for the maturational explanation of C. Chomsky has come
from the research by Wexler & Chen (1985). They have found that the
proposed condition B, i.e. the pronominal condition in (9.24b), does not
appear to be consistently acquired until around age 6. They imply that the
principle matures around that time. Much of the other work, however, has
been in a direction away from a maturational explanation. Crain & McKee
(1985), for example, have adjusted the task conditions used and have been
able to get correct responses from children as young as 3 years of age. Their
research is in the same spirit as that reported earlier on relative clauses by
Hamburger & Crain (1982). They hope to prove, by showing correct
performance by young children, that the child’s grammar is essentially
adult-like.
A somewhat paradoxical study from the same perspective is that of Solan
(1983). Solan studied a range of constructions with pronominal reference in
four experiments on 36 children between 5;2 and 8;5. He found that the
children did well on cases of backwards pronominalization and concludes a
version of the strong inclusion hypothesis which is reproduced here:
The restrictive model
Children will have little difficulty using notions such as c-command,
d-command, precedence and clausematedness. Once they have
learned that backward anaphora is possible at all, they will quickly
hypothesize restrictions based on the correct definitions.
(Solan 1983: 92)
Solan contrasts this model with one which he calls the ‘developmental
model’. We find this paradoxical in that Solan’s results seem very much
interpretable within the constructionist perspective discussed in this text.
First, he acknowledges an early stage in the acquisition of pronominal
9.4 Other aspects of English grammatical acquisition 491
reference when children rely solely on linear order. Second, the use of
linear order (or precedence) does not drop out when structural properties
such as c-command appear, but remains as part of the rule. He thus adapts
the binding conditions of the adult grammar to include earlier properties
used by the child. This is very much in keeping with the Constructionist
Assumption of Chapter 4. Lastly, the subjects are relatively old, and at an
age when results in Carol Chomsky (1969) and Ingram & Shaw (1981) show
backwards pronominalization is acquired. Their use of a structural rule at
that point of acquisition is accepted in research from a developmental
perspective.
More explicit claims for a developmental or constructionist model of the
acquisition of pronominal reference can be found in Ingram & Shaw (1981)
and in work by O’Grady and his students (Taylor-Browne 1983; O’Grady
1986; O’Grady, Suzuki-Wei & Cho 1986). Ingram & Shaw (1981) examined
both backwards pronominalization and blocked forwards pronominali-
zation in 100 children between 3;O and 8;O. O’Grady, Suzuki-Wei & Cho
(1986) looked at pronominal reference in separate studies on Korean and
Japanese. These studies, as well as the review in Carden (1986), generally
propose four descriptive stages in the acquisition of pronominal reference.
They are summarized below, adapted from Ingram & Shaw (1981; see also
O’Grady 1986: 146-7):
Four stages in the acquisition of pronominal reference
stage 1: Use of coreference: a pronoun may refer to an NP in a clause
which may either precede or follow it;
stage2: Useoflinearorder:apronoun mayonlyreferto aprecedingNP;
stage 3: Use of dominance: a pronoun may refer to a following NP if
the appropriate structural conditions exist, i.e. children acquire
backwards pronominalization;
stage 4: Use of dominance: a pronoun cannot refer to a preceding NP
under certain structural conditions, Le. blocked forwards pronomi-
nalization is acquired.
As in Solan’s work, these studies show children moving from the exclusive
use of linear order to a system which takes into account the structural
properties of the sentence. Ingram & Shaw do not express a position on the
nature of the latter properties while Solan and O’Grady both do. The fact
that backwards pronominalization and blocked forwards pronominalization
are acquired at separate times has to be taken as evidence against the
generality and nature of condition C of Chomsky’s binding conditions.
We can see how this principle operates by looking at the English and
Japanese differences on reflexives. Since the subject condition of Japanese
is more restricted than the one for English, it will be the unmarked case.
Conversely, the English clausemate restriction is more limited than the long
distance reflexives in Japanese and is thus the unmarked case. The child is
therefore born with the following two expectations about reflexives: (i) the
antecedent is restricted to subjects, and (ii) the antecedent must be in the
same clause as the reflexive (the clausemate condition). The sentences in
any language which have a wider range of application will constitute
positive evidence. For example, the English child will know that English
does not have a subject condition when it hears antecedents for reflexives
which are not subjects. So too, a Japanese child will realize that Japanese
does not have a clausemate restriction when it hears sentences with long
distance reflexives.
The subset principle is obviously a very powerful claim about how the
diverse patterns of language are acquired. An important point is that it is
also potentially testable as long as one does not take the maturational view
of acquisition, that is, we can test children in the relevant linguistic contexts
to see if the subset principle is at work.
little older than comparable English children, they were at the onset of
multi-morphemic utterances at the beginning of the study. Recall from
our earlier discussion that QuichC mothers are not as verbal with their
infants as English ones, leading to a later onset of language (see Pye
1986).
Like Greenlandic Eskimo, QuichC is polysynthetic in that the verb takes
several prefixes and suffixes. The prefixes indicate person and aspect, while
the suffixes mark transitivity and termination. The termination affixes
constitute a complex set of facts that require some explanation. The choice 3
Acquisition Correction
(mismatches)
These three aspects will operate in the child’s perception of language as well
as his production.
Application refers to the child’s initial step in the process of using and/or
acquiring grammatical morphemes. In reception, the goal is to understand
the semantic/syntactic meaning of morphemes, while in production it is to
retrieve and use them. In either modality, the child uses the three strategies
of rote, analogy, and combination in that order. For example, a word like
‘cats’ may initially be stored as a holistic unit. Next, it will be separated into
two parts, ‘cat’ and ‘s’,but the use of ‘s’will be restricted by analogy to a few
similar words, e.g. ‘bat’ and ‘mat’. Later still, combination will result
through the use of a general rule.
A crucial feature of following a child’s application is how he proceeds
from one strategy to another. These changes are apparently the result of the
500 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
child being able to segment morphemes and place them into one of three
categories: (1) words, (2) affixes, and (3) roots. At an early stage, for
example, a word like ‘cats’ may be placed in the word category with no
further segmentation. Later, ‘cat’ will be put in the root category and ‘s’ in
the affix category. During acquisition, specific kinds of potential errors
may be made, for example, having words in different categories: the child
could have ‘cats’ as a whole item as a word (category l), and also as a root
‘cat’ (category 2). This could result in the error of taking ‘cats’ from 1 and
+
adding the plural from 2, creating ‘cats s’. To avoid this, MacWhinney
proposes that the child has a process of affiw checking which restricts the
child from creating a meaning for a new category when that meaning
already exists in another category. Notice that this will restrict the child
from producing ‘feets’ if ‘feet’ already exists as a word.
As the child identifies roots and affixes, he will also need to deal with
the existence of words with different roots, e.g. ‘wife’, ‘wives’, and also the
allomorphs of grammatical morphemes, e.g. ‘cats’ [SI vs. ‘dogs’ [z]. The
major problem here is one which arises in linguistic theory in general -
what is the nature of the child’s morphological system? There are some
rules of combination which are phonetically motivated, such as the English
plural, and others which are not. An example of the latter would be
gender in languages such as French and German where the child needs to
select the correct form of some grammatical class to go with the gender of
the noun being used. MacWhinney does not provide a linguistic theory as
a framework, but falls back on the three strategies mentioned above - that
is, the child progressively works toward the general rules of the language
being acquired, whatever those rules may be.
The application phase of MacWhinney’s model only provides the child
with the ability to segment words into classes. This is not sufficient,
however, to acquire rules or avoid potential errors. For example, the child
still can select words like ‘foot’ and add ‘s’ to get ‘foots’, a well-documen-
ted kind of error. Application does not have the necessary mechanisms for
complete acquisition and correction. For that to occur, the next two
phases must operate.
The first step is referred to as correction. This step occurs when some
mismatch takes place in the perception or production of a morphological
combination. This state is somewhat like Piaget’s idea of disequilibrium, in
the sense that the child’s system may not conform to that of the input.
MacWhinney’s notion of mismatch, however, is broader because it also
refers to mismatches within the child’s system itself. Such mismatches
draw the child’s attention to the fact that there is a potential error in his
system. This can be seen by looking at the kinds of mismatches which can
occur.
9.6 The explanation of morphological acquisition 501
MacWhinney discusses four types of mismatches (or what he calls dise-
quilibrated pairs), listed below:
Type I : Self corrections. The child overgeneralizes a rule when the
correct rule is available within the system, e.g. child says ‘wifes’, and
then ‘wives’;
Type 2: Semantic mismatches in production. The child expresses an
incomplete meaning, e.g. saying ‘dog’ to mean ‘dogs’;
Type 3: Semantic mismatches in reception. The child hears something
said which does not communicate the complete meaning intended,
e.g. hearing ‘dogs’ and only recognizing ‘dog’, yet seeing two dogs in
the context;
Type 4: Auto-instruction. A productive combination becomes a role
item, and elicits adults’ corrections, e.g. saying ‘foots’ and being cor-
rected to say ‘feet’.
MacWhinney is not completely clear how these kinds of mismatches
lead to correct acquisition, nor what mechanisms underlie each. Type 1
assumes some kind of self-monitoring of production in relation to the
current competence. This mechanism, however, could have negative
effects if the child’s competence is incorrect for it would wrongly mark an
incorrect production as correct. Type 4 brings direct positive evidence into
the process, although MacWhinney acknowledges that the child will resist
such corrections.
The real key to the child’s ability to correct itself lies in types 2 and 3.
These direct the child to seek out meanings for the speech it hears and
uses. Unfortunately, it is not clear how this takes place. The problem with
type 2 is delimiting how the child knows that what it wants to express exists
within the language being acquired. Type 3 is clearer to follow. It implies a
mechanism which leads the child to identify repeated stretches of speech
and to seek a meaning for them. No information is given, however, on
how this segmentation and identification takes place.
If the child uses a form and no mismatch results, then the form can
undergo acquisition. Acquisition here is used in a way roughly similar to
the notion of ‘strengthening’ that was discussed in Chapter 7 for syntax. As
acquisition of any form proceeds, the three strategies of rote, analogy, and
combination will compete for the way the form will be stored. In par-
ticular, rote will constantly attempt to override analogy and combination.
MacWhinney lays out five potential cycles that forms can follow in being
applied, corrected and acquired, summarized below:
sufficient. They also directed research toward more detailed work on what
might be facilitative and what might not.
The results in NGG were challenged by Furrow, Nelson & Benedict
(1979; henceforth FNB). FNB criticized a number of methodological
aspects of NGG, and reported their own results which indicated more adult
influences than found by NGG. As discussed in Chapter 6, they looked at
correlations of the mother’s speech at Time 1 (when the children were
around 1;6) and Time 2 (when the children were around 2,3), with the
children’s speech at Time 2 (around 2;3). Importantly, they found that
the correlations at Time 2 could not predict the correlations found at Time
1. They conclude from this that the possible correlations will be affected by
the child’s stage of development. They looked at correlations between
several measures of adult language and four measures of child behavior:
MLU, number of verbs per utterance, number of noun phrases per
utterance, and number of auxiliaries per verb phrase. Some of the sig-
nificant correlations they found between adult speech at Time 1 and the
children’s speech at Time 2 are summarized here:
Facilitative aspects
(a) Greater adult use of yeslno questions leads to:
i. more child use of auxiliaries,
ii. greater child MLU.
(b) Greater adult use of nouns leads to:
i. more child use of verbs,
ii. greater child MLU.
(c) Greater adult use of interjections leads to:
i. more child verbs per utterance.
Prohibitive aspects
(d) Greater adult use of pronouns leads to:
i. less child use of verbs,
ii. shorter child MLU.
(e) Greater adult use of different words leads to:
i. shorter child MLU,
ii. fewer verbs and noun phrases per utterance.
(f) Greater adult use of verbs and copulas leads to:
i. less child use of verbs,
ii. shorter child MLU.
FNB interpret their results as supporting the position that simpler adult
speech aids children in their acquisition. They manage this by offering the
following scenario. Simple speech will be characterized by salient aspects of
the grammar (such as fronted Auxs as in yesho questions), simple semantic
9.7 Linguistic input and grammatical acquisition 509
messages (such as having more nouns than verbs), and pauses which shorten
the sentence (interjections). These aspects all proved to lead to more
advanced child measures. Complex speech, on the other hand, will have
more pronouns, complex vocabulary, verbs, and copulas. Greater use of
these led to poorer child performance on the measures used.
The FNB results were a strong challenge to the earlier results in NGG.
The latter responded in great detail in Gleitman, Newport & Gleitman
(1984). First, they accepted the methodological criticisms of FNB and
provided an in-depth discussion of methodology. This was followed by a
reanalysis of their original data, as well as the data in FNB. Further, they
imposed a much stricter statistical measure of correlation to eliminate what
they refer to as ‘spurious correlations’, i.e. correlations which are found but
which seem to make little sense. Their results after this elaborate procedure
ended up being quite similar to those in NGG. All of the significant
correlations which they found are given below:
For younger children (18 to 21 months)
(a) Greater adult use of declaratives leads to more verbs per
utterance.
(b) Greater adult repetition leads to fewer child auxiliaries.
(c) Greater adult use of complex sentences leads to more child aux-
iliaries.
(d) Adult unintelligible speech leads to more child verbs (interpreted
as a spurious correlation).
For older children (24 to 27 months)
(a) Greater adult use of yes/no questions leads to more child verbs
and greater MLU.
Gleitman, Newport & Gleitman conclude from their study that there are
fewer effects than indicated in FNB once better statistical procedures are
used. Also, if such effects exist, they tend to be restricted to the younger
group of children - this partially supports the claim of FNB that such effects
may differ depending on the language level of the child. They emphasize,
however, that their reanalysis provides little support for most of the
correlations found in FNB, and thus for the FNB theory concerning the role
of the linguistic input. Lastly, they emphasize that the earlier finding about
the use of yes/no questions was replicated even with the revised statistical
procedure.
The finding about yes/no questions is important because it is at the core of
the Gleitman, Newport & Gleitman view of language acquisition. They
propose that the child acquires language most easily when the linguistic
input provides a range of grammatical constructions. They argue on logical
grounds against the FNB view about simple speech. They state (p. 69):
510 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQlJISITION OF GRAMMATICAL MORPHEMES
. . . it is relatively easy to show that the language is learnable if the
input includes complex sentences; it is awesomely harder to show
learnability if the input is restricted to the simplest sentences. This
position should not really come as a surprise.
-. .-
This point is supported by their findings that they did not get the corre-
lations in their data which are predicted by FNB. The fact that the yesho
questions in adult speech lead to more child auxiliaries is because yesho
questions place auxiliaries in a very prominent place in the sentence. It is
because of the prominence of the Aux that the effect occurs.
Gleitman, Newport & Gleitman (as well as NGG) go on from auxiliaries
to language in general. Auxiliaries are one member of a general class they
refer to as the closed class. They do not give a formal definition of these, but
say (p. 71) ‘Closed-class items, roughly, are the inflections and functors,
those items that can occur unstressed in the languages of the world.’ It is
because of their language-specific, and unstressed nature that these items
tend to be acquired later. They propose that adult speech can contribute to
the acquisition of these items if it places them in some more prominent
position for acquisition. This is the case for English yesho questions.
The studies by Gleitman er al. and by FNB serve to highlight two distinct
views on the role of adult speech in the child’s acquisition. While FNB want
to assign importance to simplified speech, Gleitman et al. want to play down
its importance, and emphasize instead the importance of hearing a range of
constructions. In the latter view, the adult speech can contribute if the
constructions used contain closed class items in prominent positions.
Nelson & Baker (1984) The studies just reviewed, as well as many of the
others on this topic, are based on the analysis of spontaneous language.
Such data are always difficult to assess, due to problems with sampling and
sample sizes. (Gleitman, Newport & Gleitman 1984, for example, criticize
FNB for using only 100 utterances per mother and child, while they used an
average of 513 per mother and up to 300 per child.) It is possible, however,
to examine this question from a more experimental perspective. Such a line
of research, in fact, has been pursued in research years in a series of studies
by K. E. Nelson and his colleagues.
The theoretical perspective which underlies Nelson’s experimental work
can best be seen in two review papers, K. E. Nelson (1981) and K. E.
Nelson, Denninger, Bonvillian, Kaplan & Baker (1984). (We refer to
Nelson here but assume his perspective has been developed with and is
shared by his several co-authors.) Nelson refers to this theory as a rare-event
comparison theory of acquisition (K. E. Nelson 1981). The theory accepts
the cross-linguistic research of recent years which indicates that many
9.7 Linguistic input and grammatical acquisition 511
features of parental speech adjustment are not necessary for children’s
grammatical development. He emphasizes, however, that such findings, as
well as those in NGG, only indicate that ‘high quantities’ of linguistic input
may not be needed. Nelson’s view on frequency is that there is not a directly
linear relation between adult frequency and acquisition rate (as is claimed in
FNB, for example). Rather, Nelson et al. state (1984:49): ‘in our view,
whether more frequently presented examples in input are more rapidly
acquired by the child than less frequent examples in input depends entirely
upon how those examples are embedded in the fabric of conversation’.
In Nelson’s approach, there are two additional factors besides frequency
which need to be considered. One is that the child has to be ready to acquire
the form under consideration. If the child is linguistically at a point where a
particular form can be acquired, the frequency of exposure to it can be quite
minimal. The other factor is the way in which the parent presents the form
to the child. Nelson has argued that there are two facilitative responses that
parents can make. One is what he calls a simple recast, a reply by the adult
which continues ‘reference to the central meanings in the child’s preceding
utterances’ but which departs ‘structurally by slight or moderate changes’
(p. 37). Such changes are limited to one major component of a child’s
utterance, e.g. the subject, verb, or object. For example, the child
utterance ‘broke’ can be recast as ‘the truck broke’. The other facilitative
feature is that the recast be a continuation of the discourse. A continuation
is an adult response which does not meet the definition of a recast but which
continues the topic under discussion. The claim is that constructions are
acquired more rapidly when the child hears them in the form of recasts and
continuations.
Nelson’s theory has been experimentally tested in a series of studies, e.g.
K. E. Nelson (1977), K. E. Nelson & Baker (1984), K. E. Nelson et al.
(1984). The general procedure is to pretest children on a construction (or
constructions) to be sure that it is not yet acquired. Next, there is an
experimental period from four to eight weeks when an experimenter meets
with the child on a regular basis and recasts the child’s speech, using the
construction(s) under study. At the same time, there is a control group
which receives no such intentional recasting. Finally there is a post-test to
see if the construction has been acquired. The results reported have in
general supported the theory.
We will present this experimental approach in more detail by focussing on
Study 2 in K. E. Nelson & Baker (1984) on the acquisition of passives,
relative clauses, and auxiliaries. The subjects were six children (four girls
and two boys) between 2;6 and 3;2 with MLUs from 3.07 to 4.17. In the
month before the study began, spontaneous language samples were col-
lected from conversations between the children and their mothers. The
512 SIMPLE SENTENCES: ACQUISITION OF G R A M M A T I C A L M O R P H E M E S
Table 9.20 Number of spontaneous productions for six normal children of
passives, relative clauses, and ‘may’ and ‘could’, taken from Nelson &
Baker (1984: Tables 5 and 6)
1 0 0 1
2 0 0 2
3 1 0 -
4 2 2 2
I 3 0 1
9 1 4 1
11 2 1 7
12 7 3 5
Total 16 10 19
children were then placed into three pairs based on similarities on three
measures: MLU, noun and verb complexity, and use of complex forms.
Each was randomly assigned to two treatment groups with each member of
a pair assigned to a different group. One group (C/E) heard their sentences
recast while the other did not (E/E). The E/E group, however, did hear the
experimenter recast her own utterances.
The syntactic forms tested were passives, relative clauses, and two
auxiliaries, ‘may’ and ‘could’. Although data are not given regarding the
pretest samples, it is implied that none of these forms was used at that point.
The experimental phase of the study consisted of four weekly sessions for
three weeks, or 12 sessions. The first sessions consisted of 15 minutes of
recasting and five minutes of observations. The last session was for
post-testing. An additional language sample was subsequently collected in
each child’s home. Proportions of the use of each syntactic form were
calculated after each session to ensure that the number of recasts was
comparable for both groups.
Table 9.20 presents a summary of the spontaneous use of the syntactic
forms tested across a selection of tape-recorded sessions. The results for
both groups have been collapsed although there was a tendency for the C/E
group to produce more forms than the E/E group. The main effect is that
the spontaneous use of these forms increased over the test sessions. For
example, none of the children produced a passive sentence until the third
session, but 16 were produced by the end. Also, full passives (eight) were
nearly as frequent as truncated passives (nine). The results indicate that the
use of these recasts by the experimenter can lead to increased spontaneous
use in the child.
To support their conclusions, Nelson & Baker also compared their results
Further reading 513
to the data collected in Horgan (1978), whose study was summarized in
section 9.4.1. They calculated the proportion of different types of passives
used and compared figures with those in Horgan for the children aged
between 2 and 4 years. These results are summarized in (9.32):
Horgan found that agentive non-reversible passives were not used until age
9. Also, none of the children she studied produced both reversible and
non-reversible passives until age 11. The Nelson & Baker subjects had
higher percentages of both of these types, and one-half of their subjects
produced both reversible and non-reversible passives.
Further reading
English morphological acquisition
This area has generated a massive literature. In particular, the classic study
by Berko (1958) has been replicated, with various modifications, literally
hundreds of times. It remains a valuable article which is probably required
reading in just about everyone’s course on child language. Much of the cited
literature is the work of Brown and his colleagues. The study by Cazden
(1968) presents an important early analysis of the Brown data which was the
basis for the subsequent report in Brown (1973). Brown (1973) is an
important but very long discussion of the acquisition of 14 English mor-
phemes. A feel for the data and the results may be obtained from reading
pp. 249-73.
Linguistic input
There have been a series of debates in the various attempts to demonstrate
causal effects between parental and child speech. The text discussed the one
between Furrow, Nelson & Benedict (1979) and Gleitman, Newport &
Gleitman (1984). Other reports have appeared which differ from these two
in various ways. Barnes et al. reports several correlations between adult and
child measures, but interpret the effects as reciprocal rather than unidirec-
tional. Scarborough & Wyckoff (1986) reanalyze their data and find
virtually no effects, that is, even fewer than Gleitman, Newport &
Gleitman.
A less prominent debate occurred after Moerk (1980). Moerk suggested
that the effects of parental speech may be more subtle than had been
suggested. In particular, he suggested that parents may increase their use of
specific forms for just a short period around the time that the child shows
evidence of acquiring them. This elicited a critique from Pinker (1981), as
well as a response from Moerk (1981).
A helpful review of this literature is that of Hoff-Ginsburg & Shatz
(1982). The article by Gleitman, Newport & Gleitman (1984) is not easy
reading, but it provides an in depth discussion of the relevant issues. Keith
Nelson’s views are probably most accessible in Nelson (1981).
10 Concluding remarks
I began this text with the goal of presenting an in-depth introduction to the
field of child language acquisition. This was to be done by providing a
balance between method, description, and explanation. We would like to
conclude by giving a brief assessment of where we now stand in regard to
these three aspects.
As should be apparent, the field has evolved tremendously in the area of
method, and should continue to do so in the years ahead. It has gone
beyond the simplistic view that a child’s linguistic knowledge can be
adequately assessed by collecting a spontaneous language sample. An
obvious way in which the approach has changed is the development of
diverse experimental methods to get at the many aspects of language that
are not immediately apparent from spontaneous speech. These have
included the use of imitation as in Kuczaj & Maratsos (1975), comprehen-
sion tests as in Thomson & Chapman (1977), and elicitation procedures as
in Berko (1958). Indeed, studies such as these across a range of linguistic
behaviors suggest that seemingly impossible aspects of language can be
studied as long as one brings a creative mind to the task.
While such experimental approaches have held great promise, their
details are still being developed. We have discussed cases where studies
have not been replicated, or where different methods of analysis have been
proposed. The area of environmental effects, for example, is still in the
midst of determining the appropriate methodological procedures needed to
determine causality. Another example is in the area of infant speech
perception where I presented the methodological debate between the
nativists and the developmentalists. So too, we are still attempting to
resolve the kinds of discrepancies that occur when an area is tested in both
comprehension and production: that is, which kinds of data are to be
considered most reliably an indication of a child’s linguistic ability? With
regard to the use of experimental techniques, therefore, particularly in
combination with each other, there are still a number of issues to resolve.
Methodological research has also sought to develop better ways to use
spontaneous speech. One effective means has been the improvements made
516
Concluding remarks 517
in the use of parental diaries to study the general aspects of early vocabulary
acquisition. Another concerns refinements in the linguistic methods used to
analyze language samples. We have addressed two areas in particular. In
the area of phonological acquisition, we discussed the need to set some
criteria for productivity as well as ways to separate individual from general
patterns. These same general issues returned when we discussed the
analysis of children’s early word combinations. Again the question of
productivity arose. In both domains we want to eliminate random and
memorized speech forms from the set of data being used to make claims
about a child’s rule system. I am somewhat concerned that the limitations of
spontaneous samples have led some to consider them to be of no value.
Instead, while recognizing such limitations, I believe that a better methodo-
logy can still lead to new insights into the developmental patterns of both
areas.
The descriptive aspect of the text deals with a review of the relevant
literature in the field. As stated in the Introduction, I have tried to limit this
aspect in the sense of restricting the range of studies discussed. Instead, I
have gone for a more intensive survey of a small set of relevant studies. The
tone of the review, therefore, is highly different from other attempts such as
McCarthy (1954).
A goal of the literature survey has been to present the reader with a feel
for the richness of the research which has already been done in the field. I
have presented a historical overview, and have opted to focus on what I
perceive to be classic studies, though, of course, including current work
which is perceived to be of importance. There is a concern among at least
some from the Child Language perspective that this literature is being lost.
This is true not only for older studies but even for more recent ones. I
pointed out, for example, the lack of any discussion of McNeill’s work in the
1970s in Pinker (1984), despite some very general similarities in the two
approaches.
The lack of interest in previous research among at least some current
researchers can be traced to two causes. One concerns the fact that current
linguistic theory has discovered new and interesting patterns of language
which have not been known before and there was no previous research,
therefore, which directly examined them. A related cause is the feeling that
the previous research was by and large descriptive. I acknowledge that there
may well be a range of linguistic phenomena which will require entirely new
research studies, particularly those phenomena which tend to be acquired
later in childhood. At the same time, however, I believe that a number of
previous studies can be reinterpreted in the light of more recent research. I
discussed, for example, the relevance of the data in Rodd & Braine (1970)
to current discussions about the acquisition of subject pronouns. While it is
518 CONCLUDING REMARKS
true that some of the earlier research was descriptive, much still contains
insightful and speculative theoretical suggestions. It just may not be
characterized by the current linguistic jargon.
Certainly the attention to explanation has expanded and now is central to
most research currently underway. I have tried to capture the directions of
this work by comparing these different general approaches to the question.
The more traditional developmental view that children go through pro-
gressive stages of acquisition has been contrasted with two nativist views.
One of these, which I have called ‘maturational’, allows maturational
milestones and is quite comfortable with discontinuities in acquisition. The
other, which I labeled a ‘strong inclusion’ view, sees the child as essentially
adult-like from the onset of acquisition.
These differences of opinion are currently being assessed by all sides as to
their predictions about language acquisition. I have some concern about the
polarization which may result from these differences, and have contrasted
Child Language and Language Acquisition as a way to characterize the
respective camps. I have some worries about the future in this regard, but
see no inherent differences in the general goal of all sides to better
understand the child’s language acquisition process. Indeed, I believe that
the disagreements may come down to whether one assigns a child’s
linguistic behavior as the result of its performance or competence. If such is
the case, we may all be satisfied at some point with the data, and only debate
its interpretation.
The more serious point perhaps, at least as concerns the future of our
field, is the interest in data at all. If language acquisition shows little about
the child’s emerging linguistic competence, then linguists will presumably
lose interest in child language data altogether. This does not mean, of
course, that there will be no more issues of interest to study. Certainly an
account of the performance mechanisms at work will be a primary issue. So
too, the logical problem of how specific constructions can be acquired from
positive evidence will keep us busy for many years to come. Even so, much
of the research in the field has been driven by the assumption that children’s
patterns of speech reveal something of interest about their linguistic rules. It
is certainly this interest which has led me to highlight the constructionist
perspective in this text. The resolution of this point, to my mind, will
constitute the single most important event in the history of the field.
Bibliography
Baldie, B. 1976. The acquisition of the passive voice. Journal of Child Language 3:
33148.
Bar-Adon, A. & Leopold, W. (eds.) 1971. Child language. A book of readings.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Barnes, S., Gutfreund, M., Satterly, D. & Wells, G. 1983. Characteristics of adult
speech which predict children’s language development. Journal of Child Lan-
guage IO: 65-84.
Barrett, M. 1978. Lexical development and overextension in child language. Journal
of Child Language 5: 205-19.
1982. The holophrastic hypothesis: conceptual and empirical issues. Cognition 11:
47-76.
Barrie-Blackley, S. 1973. Six-year-old children’s understanding of sentences
adjoined with time adverbs. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 2: 153-65.
Bartlett, E. 1976. Sizing things up: the acquisition of the meaning of dimensional
adjectives. Journal of Child Language 3: 205-20.
Barton, D. 1975. Statistical significance in phonemic perception experiments.
Journal of Child Language 2: 297-8.
1976a. The role of perception in the acquisition of phonology. Doctoral disser-
tation, University of London.
1976b. Phonemic discrimination and the knowledge of words in children under
three years of age. Papers and Reports on Child Language Development 11: 61-8.
1978. The discrimination of minimally-different pairs of real words by children
aged 2;3 to 2;11. In Waterson & Snow (1978: 255-61).
1980. Phonemic perception in children. In Yeni-Komshian, Kavanaugh & Fer-
guson (1980b: 97-116).
Bateman, W. 1916. The language status of three children at the same ages.
Pedagogical Seminary 23 ; 2 11-40.
Bates, E. 1976. Language and context: the acquisition of pragmatics. New York:
Academic Press.
1979. The emergence of symbols: cognition and communication in infancy. New
York: Academic Press.
Bates, E., Camaioni, L. & Volterra, V. 1975. The acquisition of performatives prior
to speech. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly 21: 205-36.
Bates, E. & MacWhinney, B. 1979. The functionalist approach to the acquisition of
grammar. In Ochs & Schiefflin (1979: 167-211).
1982. The development of grammar. In Wanner and Gleitman (1982: 173-218).
Bates, E. & Rankin, J. 1979. Morphological development in Italian: connotation
and denotation. Journal of Child Language 6: 29-52.
Bateson, M. C. 1975. Mother-infant exchanges: the epigenesis of conversational
interaction. In D. Aaronson & R. Rieber (eds.) Developmental psycholinguis-
tics and communication disorders. Annals of the New York Academy of Science
263: 21-9.
Bausano, M. K. & Jeffrey, W. E. 1975. Dimensional salience and judgements of
bigness by three-year-old children. Child Development 46: 988-91.
Bavin, E. & Shopin, T. 1985. Children’s acquisition of Walpiri: comprehension of
transitive sentences. Journal of Child Language 12: 597-610.
Bellugi, U. 1967. The acquisition of the system of negation in children’s speech.
Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University.
Bibliography 521
1971. Simplification in children’s language. In Huxley & Ingram (1971: 95-119).
Bellugi, U. & Brown, R. (eds.) 1964. The acquisition of language. Monographs of
the Society for Research in Child Development 29.
Benedict, H. 1979. Early lexical development: comprehension and production.
Journal of Child Language 6: 183-200.
Berko, J. 1958. The child’s learning of English morphology. Word 14: 150-77.
Berko-Gleason, J. 1975. Fathers and other strangers. In Dato (1975: 289-97).
Berman, R. 1981a. Regularity vs. anomaly: the acquisition of Hebrew inflectional
morphophonology. Journal of Child Language 8: 265-82.
1981b. Language development and language knowledge: evidence from the
acquisition of Hebrew morphophonology. Journal of Child Language 8: 609-26.
1982. Verb-pattern alternation: the interface of morphology, syntax, and seman-
tics in Hebrew child language. Journal of Child Language 9: 169-91.
Berwick, R. & Weinberg, A. 1984. The grammatical basis of linguistic performance.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Bever, T. 1970. The cognitive basis for linguistic structures. In Hayes (1970:
274-353).
Bierwisch, M. 1967. Some semantic universals of German adjectivals. Foundations
of Language 3: 1-36.
1970. Semantics. In J. Lyons (ed.) New horizons in linguistics. London: Penguin,
pp. 16684.
Blewitt, P. 1982. Word meaning acquisition in young children: a review of theory
and research. In H. Reese & L. Lipsitt (eds.) Advances in child development and
behavior, vol. 17. New York: Academic Press, pp. 140-95.
Bloom, L. 1970. Language development: form and function in emerging grammars.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
1971. Why not pivot grammar? Journal of Speech and Hearing Disorders 36: 4@50.
1973. One word at a time. The Hague: Mouton.
(ed.) 1978. Readings in language development. New York: John Wiley.
Bloom, L. & Lahey, M. (eds.) 1978. Language development and language disorders.
New York: John Wiley.
Bloom, L., Hood, L. & Lightbown, P. 1974. Imitation in language acquisition: if,
when, and why? Cognitive Psychology 6: 38W20. Reprinted in L. Bloom (1978:
452-88).
Bloom, L., Lifter, K. & Hafitz, J. 1980. Semantics of verbs and the development of
verb inflections in child language. Language 56: 38W12.
Bloom, L., Lightbown, P. & Hood, L. 1975. Structure and variation in child
language. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 40 (2,
serial no. 160).
Bloom, L., Miller, P. & Hood, L. 1975. Variation and reduction as aspects of
competence in language development. In A. Pick (ed.) Minnesota Symposia on
Child Psychology 9: 3-55. Reprinted in Bloom (1978: 169-216).
Bloom, L., Rocissano, L. & Hood, L. 1976. Adult-child discourse: developmental
interaction between information processing and linguistic knowledge. Cognitive
Psychology 8: 521-52.
Bloom, L., Lahey, M., Hood, L. Lifter, K. & Fiess, K. 1980. Complex sentences:
acquisition of syntactic connectives and the semantic relations they encode.
Journal of Child Language 7: 235-61.
522 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Bloomfield, L. 1933. Language. New York: Henry Holt.
Blount, B. 1969. Acquisition of language by Luo children. Doctoral dissertation,
University of California, Berkeley.
1972. The prelinguistic system of Luo children. Anthropological Linguistics 12:
326-42.
Bohn, W. 1914. First steps in verbal expression. Pedagogical Seminary 21: 578-95.
Borer, H. & Wexler, K . 1987. The maturation of syntax. In Roeper & Williams
(1987: 123-72).
Bowerman, M. 1973a. Early syntactic development: a cross-linguistic study with
special reference to Finnish. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1973b. Structural relationships in children’s utterances: syntactic or semantic? In
Moore (1973: 197-213).
1974. Learning the structure of causative verbs: a study in the relationship of
cognitive, semantic and syntactic development. Papers and Reports on Child
Language Development 8: 142-78.
1975. Commentary, In Bloom, Lightbown & Hood (1975: 80-90).
1976a. Commentary. In Braine (1976: 98-104).
1976b. Semantic factors in the acquisition of rules for word use and sentence
construction. In Morehead & Morehead (1976: 99-179).
1977, The acquisition of rules governing ‘possible lexical items’: evidence from
spontaneous speech errors. Papers and Reports on Child Language Development
13: 148-56.
1978a. The acquisition of word meaning: an investigation into some current
conflicts. In Waterson & Snow (1978: 263-87).
1978b. Semantic and syntactic development: a review of what, when, and how in
language acquisition. In Schiefelbusch (1978: 97-189).
1978c. Systematizing semantic knowledge: changes over time in the child’s
organization of meaning. Child Development 49: 977-87.
1979. The acquisition of complex sentences. In Fletcher & Garman (1979:
285-305).
1981. Beyond communicative competency: from piecemeal knowledge to an
integrated system in the child’s acquisition of language. Papers and Reports on
Child Language Development 20: 1-24.
1986. What shapes children’s grammars? In Slobin (1986: 1257-319).
Boyd, W. 1913. The beginnings of syntactical speech: a study in child linguistics.
Child Study 6: 21-4 and 47-51.
Braine, M. D. S. 1963a. The ontogeny of English phrase structure: the first phase.
Language 39: 1-13.
1963b. On learning the grammatical order of words. Psychological Review 70:
323-48.
1971a. On two types of models of the internalization of grammars. In Slobin
(1971: 153-86).
1971b. The acquisition of language in infant and child. In C. E. Reed (ed.) The
learning of language. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, pp. 7-95.
1973. Three suggestions regarding grammatical analyses of children’s language.
In Ferguson & Slobin 1973: 421-9.
1974a. On what might constitute a learnable phonology. Language 50: 270-99.
1974b. Length constraints, reduction rules, and holophrastic processes in chil-
Bibliography 523
dren’s word combinations. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 13:
448-56.
1976. Children’s first word combinations. Monographs of the Society for Research
in Child Development 41 (1, serial no. 164).
Braine, M. D. S. & Hardy, J. 1981. Case categories. In Deutsch (1981: 201-22).
1982. On what case categories there are, why they are, and how they develop: an
amalgam of a priori considerations, speculation, and evidence from children. In
Wanner & Gleitman (1982: 219-39).
Braine, M. D. S. & Wells, R. 1978. Case-like categories in children: the Actor and
more related categories. Cognitive Psychology 10: 100-22.
Brainerd, C. 1978. The stage question in cognitive-developmental theory. The
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2: 173-213.
Brandenburg, G. 1915. The language of a three-year-old child. Pedagogical
Seminary 22: 89-120.
Branigan, G. 1979. Some reasons why successive single word utterances are not.
Journal of Child Language 6: 411-21.
Braunwald, S. 1978. Context, word and meaning: towards a communicational
analysis of lexical acquisition. In Lock (1978: 485-527).
Bresnan, J. 1978. A realistic transformational grammar. In Halle, Bresnan & Miller
(1978: 1-59).
(ed.) 1982. The mental representation of grammatical relations. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Bretherton, I., McNew, S., Snyder, L. & Bates, E. 1983. Individual differences at
20 months: analytic and holistic strategies in language acquisition. Journal of
Child Language 10: 293-320.
Brewer, W. & Stone, J. 1975. Acquisition of spatial antonym pairs. Journal of
Experimental Child Psychology 19: 299-307.
Brown, H. D. 1971. Children’s comprehension of relativized English sentences.
Child Development 42: 1923-6.
Brown, R. 1958a. Words and things. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
1958b. How shall a thing be called? Psychological Review 65: 14-21.
1968. The development of wh questions in child speech. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior 7: 277-90.
1970a. Psycholinguistics: selected papers of Roger Brown. New York: Free
Press.
1970b. The first sentences of child and chimpanzee. In Brown (1970a: 208-31).
1973. A first language: the early stages. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
1977. Introduction. In Snow & Ferguson (1977: 1-27).
Brown, R. & Bellugi, U. 1964. Three processes in the child’s acquisition of syntax.
Harvard Educational Review 34: 133-5. Also in Lenneberg (1964).
Brown, R. & Fraser, C . 1963. The acquisition of syntax. In C. Cofer & B. Musgrave
(eds.) Verbal behavior and learning: problems and processes. New York:
McGraw-Hill. pp. 158-201.
1964. The acquisition of syntax. In Bellugi & Brown (1964: 43-79).
Brown, R., Cazden, C. & Bellugi, U. 1969. The child‘s grammar from I to 111. In
J. P. Hill (ed.). Minnesota Symposium on Child Psychology, vol. 2. Minneapo-
lis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 28-73.
524 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Brown, R. & Hanlon, C. 1970. Derivational complexity and order of acquisition. In
Hayes (1970: 11-53).
Brown, R., Fraser, C. & Bellugi, U. 1964. Explorations in grammar evaluation, In I
Bellugi & Brown (1964: 79-92).
Bruner, J. 1975. The ontogenesis of speech acts. Journal of Child Language 2: 1-21.
Bruner, J. & Sherwood, V. 1976. Peekaboo and the learning of rule structures. In
J. S. Bruner, A. Jolly & K. Sylva (eds.) Play - its role in development and
evolution. Harmondsworth, Middx: Penguin, pp. 277-85.
Buhler, C. 1931. Kindheit und Jugend. Leipzig: Hirzel.
Burroughs, G. 1957. A study of the vocabulary ofyoung children. Edinburgh: Oliver
and Boyd.
Butterfield, E. & Cairns, G. 1974. Discussion summary - infant reception research.
In Schiefelbusch and Lloyd (1974: 75-102).
Bybee, J. 1979. Child morphology and morphophonemic change. Linguistics 17:
21-50.
Campbell, D. & Stanley, J. 1963. Experimental and quasi-experimental design for
research in teaching. In N. Gage (ed.) Handbook of research on teaching.
Chicago, Ill.: Rand McNally.
Caramazza, A. & Zuriff, E. (eds.) 1978. Language acquisition and language
breakdown. Baltimore, Md.: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Carden, G. 1986. Blocked forwards anaphora: theoretical implications of the
acquisition data. In Lust (1986: 31S57).
Carey, S. 1978. The child as word learner. In Halle, Bresnan & Miller (1978: 26493).
1982. Semantic development: the state of the art. In Wanner & Gleitman (1982:
347-89).
Carey, S. & Bartlett, E. 1978. Acquiring a single word. Papers and Reports on Child
Language Development 15: 17-29.
Carter, A. L. 1975a. The transformation of sensorimotor morphemes into words: a
case study of the development of ‘here’ and ‘there’. Papers and Reports on Child
Language Development 10: 31-47.
1975b. The transformation of sensorimotor morphemes into words: a case study
of the development of ‘more’ and ‘mine’. Journal of Child Language 2: 233-50.
1978a. The development of systematic vocalizations prior to words: a case study.
In Waterson & Snow (1978: 127-38).
1978b. From sensorimotor vocalizations to words: a case study of the evolution of
attention-directing communication in the second year. In Lock (1978: 309-49).
1979. Prespeech meaning relations: an outline of one infant’s sensorimotor
morpheme development. In Fletcher & Garman (1979: 71-92).
Caudill, W. & Weinstein, H. 1969. Maternal care and infant behavior in Japan and
America. Psychiatry 32: 12-43.
Cazden, C. 1968. The acquisition of noun and verb inflections. Child Development
39: 433-48.
1970. Children’s questions: their form, functions, and roles in education. Young
Children, March, pp. 202-20.
1972. Child language and education. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Chamberlain, A. & Chamberlain, I. 1904. Studies of a child. Pedagogical Seminary
11: 26691,452-83.
,
Bibliography 525
1905. Studies of a child. Pedagogical Seminary 12: 427-53.
1909. ‘Meanings’ and ‘definitions’ in the 47th and 48th months. Pedagogical
Seminary 16: 64-103.
Chao, Y.-R. 1951. The Cantian idiolect. University of California Publications in
Semitic Philology 2: 27-44. Reprinted in Bar-Adon & Leopold (1971: 116-30).
Chapman, R. 1981a. Cognitive development and language comprehension in
10-21-month-olds.In Stark (1981: 359-91).
1981b. Mother-child interaction in the second year of life: its role in language
development. In Schiefelbusch & Bricker (1981: 201-50).
Chapman, R. & Thomson, J. 1980. What is the source of overextension errors in
comprehension testing of two-year-olds? A response to Fremgen & Fay. Journal
of Child Language 7: 575-8.
Chen, M. 1975. An areal study of nasalization in Chinese. In C. Ferguson, L.
Hyman & J. Ohala (eds.) Nasalfest: Papers from a symposium on nasals and
nasalization. Palo Alto, Calif. : Stanford University Press.
Chomsky, C. 1969. The acquisition of syntax in children from 5 to 10. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. 1957. Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.
1959. Review of Verbal behavior, by B. F. Skinner. Language 35: 26-58.
1964. Formal discussion. In Bellugi & Brown (1964: 35-9).
1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
1968. Language and mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
1972. Studies on semantics in generative grammar. The Hague: Mouton.
1975. Reflections on language. New York: Pantheon.
1981. Lectures on government and binding: the Pisa lectures. Dordrecht: Foris.
1982. Some concepts and consequences of the theory of government and binding.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
1986. Barriers. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. & Halle, M. 1968. Thesoundpattern of English. New York: Harper &
Row.
Clark, E. 1971. On the acquisition of the meaning of ‘before’ and ‘after’. Journal of
Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 10: 266-75.
1972. On the child’s acquisition of antonyms in two semantic fields. Journal of
Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 11: 75@8.
1973a. What’s in a word? On the child’s acquisition of semantics in his first
language. In Moore (1973: 65-110).
1973b. Nonlinguistic strategies and the acquisition of word meanings. Cognition
2: 161-82.
Clark, H. 1970. How young children describe events in time. In G. Flores d’Arcais
& W. Levelt (eds.) Advances in psycholinguistics. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
1973. Space, time, semantics, and the child. In Moore (1973: 27-63).
Clark, H. & Clark, E. 1977. Psychology and language: an introduction. New York:
Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Clark, R. 1974. Performing without competence. Journal of Child Language 1: 1-10.
1977. What’s the use of imitation? Journal of Child Language 4: 341-58.
1982. Theory and method in child-language research: are we assuming too much?
In Kuczaj (1982b: 1-36).
Clumeck, H. 1982. The effect of word familiarity on phonemic recognition in
526 BIBLIOGRAPHY
preschool children aged 3 to 5 years. In C. E. Johnson & C. L. Thew (eds.)
Proceedings of the Second International Congress for the Study of Child
Language. Vol. 1. Washington, DC: University Press of America, pp. 58-77.
Coker, P. 1978. Syntactic and semantic factors in the acquisition of before and after.
Papers and Reports on Child Language Development 12: 81-8.
Comrie, B. 1981. Language universals and linguistic typology. Chicago, Ill.:
University of Chicago Press.
1983. Switch-reference in Huichol: a typological study. In J. Haiman & P. Munro
(eds.) Switch-reference and universal grammar. Amsterdam: John Benjamins,
pp. 17-37.
Crain, S. & McKee, C. 1985. Acquisition of structural relations on anaphora. NELS
16: 94-110.
Cruttenden, A. 1970. A phonetic study of late babbling. British Journal of Disorders
of Communication 5: 110-18.
Crystal, D., Fletcher, P. & Garman, M. 1976. The grammatical analysis of language
disability. London: Edward Arnold, pp. 200-7.
Culicover, P. & Wilkins, W. 1984. Locality in linguistic theory. Orlando, Fla.:
Academic Press.
Dale, P. 1976. Language development: structure and function. New York: Holt,
Rinehart & Winston.
1985, Productivity analysis of early child language (PANEL): user’s guide. IBM
versions. Unpublished paper.
Dale, P. & Ingram, D., (eds.) 1980. Child language: an international perspective.
Baltimore, Md.: University Park Press.
Darwin, C. 1877. A bibliographical sketch of an infant. Mind 2: 285-94.
Dato, D. (ed.) 1975. Developmental psycholinguistics: theory and application.
Georgetown University Round Table on Languages and Linguistics 1975. Wash-
ington: Georgetown University.
Davis, E. 1937. The development of linguisticskills in twins, singletons with siblings,
and only children from age five to ten years. University of Minnesota Institute of
Child Welfare, Monograph Series 14.
Davis, H. 1983. Restructuring in child language. Paper presented to the Canadian
Linguistic Association annual meeting, Vancouver, BC.
1987. The acquisition of the English auxiliary system and its relation to linguistic
theory. Doctoral dissertation, University of British Columbia.
Day, E. 1932. The development of language in twins: 1. A comparison of twins and
single children. 2. The development of twins: their resemblances and differ-
ences. Child Development 3: 179-99.
de Boysson-Bardies, B., Sagart, L. & Durand, C. 1984. Discernible differences in
the babbling of infants according to target language. Journal of Child Language
11: 1-15.
de Laguna, G. 1927. Speech: its function and development. New Haven, Conn.: Yale
University Press.
Della Corta, M., Benedict, R. & Klein, D. 1983. The relationship of pragmatic I
Eimas, P., Siqueland, E., Jusczyk, P. & Vigorito, J. 1971. Speech perception in
infants. Science 171: 303-18. Reprinted in Bloom (1978: 87-93).
Elbers, L. 1982. Operating principles in repetitive babbling: a cognitive continuity
approach. Cognition 12: 45-63.
Elkonin, D. B. 1971. Development of speech. In A. Va. Zaporozhets & D. B.
Elkonin (eds.) The psychology of preschool children. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT
Press, pp. 111-85.
Emonds, J. 1976. A transformational approach to English syntax: root, structure-
preserving and local transformations. New York: Academic Press.
Erreich, A. 1984. Learning how to ask: patterns of inversion in yes-no and wh
questions. Journal of Child Language 11: 579-92.
Erreich, A., Valian, V. & Winzemer, J. 1980. Aspects of a theory of language
acquisition. Journal of Child Language 2: 157-79.
Fay, D. 1978. Reply to Kuczaj (1976). Journal of Child Language 5: 143-9.
Feagans, L. 1980. How to make sense of temporalkpatial ‘before’ and ‘after’.
Journal of Child Language 7: 529-37.
Ferguson, C. A. 1964.Babytalkinsix languages. AmericanAnthropologist66: 103-14.
1978. Learning to pronounce: the earliest stages of phonological development in
the child. In Minifie & Lloyd (1978: 237-97).
Ferguson, C. A. & Farwell, C. B. 1975. Words and sounds in early language
acquisition. Language 51: 49-39. An earlier version appeared in 1973 in Papers
and Reports on Child Language Development 6: 1-60.
Ferguson, C . A. & Garnica, 0. K. 1975. Theories of phonological development. In
Lenneberg & Lenneberg (1975: 153-80).
Ferguson, C . A. & Slobin, D. (eds.) 1973. Studies of child language development.
New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Fernald, C. 1972. Control of grammar in imitation, comprehension, and pro-
duction: problems of replication. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal f
Goad, H. & Ingram, D. 1988. Individual variation and its relevance to a theory of
phonological acquisition. Journal of Child Language 14: 419-32.
Goertz, C. 1973. The impact of the concept of culture on the concept of man. In C.
Goertz, Interpretation of cultures. New York: Basic Books, pp. 33-54.
Goldstein, U. 1979. Modeling children’s vocal tracts. Paper presented at the 97th
Meeting of the Acoustical Society of America, Cambridge, Mass., June 12-16.
Gottlieb, G. 1976. Conceptions of prenatal development: behavioral embryology.
Psychological Review 83: 215-34.
Graham, L. W. & House, A. S. 1971. Phonological oppositions in children: a
perceptual study. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 49: 559-66.
Greenberg, J. & Kuczaj, S. Towards a theory of substantive word meaning
acquisition. In Kuczaj (1982: 275-311).
Greenfield, P. & Smith, J. 1976. The structure of communication in early language
development. New York: Academic Press.
Greenfield, P. & Zukow, P. 1978. Why do children say what they say when they say
I
it? An experimental approach to the psychogenesis of presupposition. In K. E.
Nelson (1978).
GrCgoire, A. 1937, 1947. L’apprentissage du langage. Vol. 1 (1937); Vol. 2 (1947).
Libge, Paris: Droz.
Grimshaw, J. 1981. Form, function, and the language acquisition device. In Baker &
McCarthy (1981: 165-82).
Gruber, J. S. 1967. Topicalization in child language. Foundations of Language 3:
37-65. Reprinted in Bar-Adon & Leopold (1971: 364-81).
1975a. ‘Topicalization’ revisited. Foundations of Language 13: 57-72.
1975b. Performative-constative transition in child language. Foundations of
Language 12: 513-27.
Grunwell, P. 1985. Phonological assessment of child speech (PACS). San Diego,
Calif.: College-Hill Press.
Guillaume, P. 1927/28. First stages of sentence formation in children’s speech. In
Bloom (1978: 13148).
Gvozdev, A. 1949. Formirovanie u rebenka grammaticheskogo stroya russkogo
yazyka (Formation in the child grammatical structure of the Russian language),
parts 1 & 2. Moscow: Akad. Pedag. Nauk RSFSR.
Halle, M., Bresnan, J. &Miller, G. (eds.) 1978. Linguistic theory and psychological
reality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Halliday, M. A. K. 1975. Learning how to mean: explorations in the development of
language development. London: Edward Arnold.
Hamburger, H. & Crain, S . 1982. Relative acquisition. In Kuczaj (1982b: 245-74).
Harding, C. & Golinkoff, R. 1979. The origins of intentional vocalizations in
prelinguistic infants. Child Development 50: 33-40.
Hayes, J. R. (ed.) 1970. Cognition and the development of language. New York:
John Wiley.
Hayhurst, H. 1967. Some errors of young children in producing passive sentences.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 6: 634-9.
Hill, J. 1984. Combining two-term relations: evidence in support of flat structure.
Journal of Child Language 11: 673-8.
Hills, E. 1914. The speech of a child two years of age. Dialect Notes 4: 84-100.
Hodson, B. & Paden, E. 1983. Targeting intelligible speech: a phonological
approach to remediation. San Diego, Calif.: College-Hill Press.
Bibliography 531
Hoek, D., Ingram, D. & Gibson, D. 1986. An examination of the possible causes of
children's early word extensions. Journal of Child Language 13: 477-94.
Hoff-Ginsburg, E. & Shatz, M. 1982. Linguistic input and the child's acquisition of
language. Psychological Bulletin 92: 2-26.
Hogan, L. 1898. A study of a child, illustrated with over 500 original drawings by the
child. New York: Harper.
Holmes, U. 1927. The phonology of an English-speaking child. American Speech 2:
219-25.
Hood, L. & Bloom, L. 1979. What, when and how about why: a longitudinal study
of expressions of causality in the language development of two-year-old
children. Society for Research in Child Development, serial no. 181, vol. 44,
no. 6.
Horgan, D. 1978. The development of the full passive. Journal of Child Language 5 :
56-80.
Howard, R. 1946. Language development in a group of triplets. Journalof Genetic
Psychology 69: 181-9.
Howe, C. 1976. The meanings of two-word utterances in the speech of young
children. Journal of Child Language 3: 29-47.
Hoyer, A. & Hoyer, G. 1924. Uber die Lallsprache eines Kindes. Zeitschrift fur
angewandte Psychologie 24: 363-84.
Humphreys, M. 1880. A contribution to infantile linguistics. Transactions of the
American Philological Association 11: 5-17.
Hurford, J. 1975. A child and the English question formation rule. Journal of Child
Language 2: 299-301.
Huttenlocher, J. 1974. The origins of language comprehension. In R. Solso (ed.)
Theories in cognitive psychology. New York: Erlbaum, pp. 331-68.
Huttenlocher, J., Eisenberg, K. & Strauss, S. 1968. Comprehension: relation
between perceived actor and logical subject. Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behaviour 7: 527-30.
Huxley, R. & Ingram, E. (eds.) 1971. Language acquisition: models and methods.
New York: Academic Press.
Hyams, N. 1983. The acquisition of parameterized grammars. Doctoral disser-
tation, City University of New York.
1984. Semantically based child grammars: some empirical inadequacies. Papers
and Reports on Child Language Development 23: 58-65.
1986. Language acquisition and the theory of parameters. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Ingram, D. 1971. Transitivity in child language. Language 47: 889-910.
1972. The development of phrase structure rules. Language Learning 22: 65-77.
1974a. Phonological rules in young children. Journal of Child Languagel: 49-64.
1974b. Fronting in child phonology. Journal of Child Language 1: 233-41.
1975. If and when transformations are acquired by children. Monograph Series on
Language and Linguistics. Georgetown University 27: 99-127.
1976a. Phonological disability in children. London: Edward Arnold.
1976b. Phonological analysis of a child. Glossa 10: 3-27.
1978. Sensorimotor intelligence and language development. In Lock (1978:
261-90).
1979a. Phonological patterns in the speech of young children. In Fletcher &
Garman (1979: 133-49).
532 BIBLIOGRAPHY
1979b. Stages in the acquisition of one-word utterances. In P. French (ed.) The
development of meaning. Hiroshima: Bunka Hyoron, pp. 256-81.
1981a. Procedures for the phonological analysis of children’s language. Baltimore,
Md.: University Park Press.
1981b. The notion of ‘stage’ in language acquisition studies. Proceedings from the
Second Wisconsin Symposium on Research in Child Language Disorders 2: 1-16.
Revised version to appear in H. Wittje (ed.) Festschrift Els Oksaar. Tubingen:
Gunter Narr.
1981c. The transition from early symbols to syntax. In Schiefelbusch & Bricker
(1981: 259-86).
1981d. Early patterns of grammatical development. In Stark (1981: 327-52).
1981e. On variant patterns of language acquisition. Paper presented to the
Biennial Meeting of the Society for Research in Child Development, Boston,
Mass.
1981/2. The emerging phonological system of an Italian-English bilingual child.
Journal of Italian Linguistics 2: 95-113.
1985a. The psychological reality of children’s grammars and its relation to
grammatical theory. Lingua 66: 79-103.
1985b. [VI: the acquisition. Paper presented to the Western Conference of
Linguistics, University of Victoria, October. Revised version to appear in
Language and Speech.
1985c. The acquisition of Dative Movement from positive evidence. Unpublished
paper.
1985d. On children’s homonyms. Journal of Child Language 12: 671-80.
1986. In defense of the segment in phonological acquisition. Paper presented to
the Linguistic Society of America, New York.
1988. Jakobson revisited: some evidence from the acquisition of Polish phono-
logy. Lingua 75: 55-82.
Ingram, D. & Mitchell, G. to appear. A longitudinal comparison of French and
English phonological development.
Ingram, D. & Shaw, C. 1981. The comprehension of pronominal reference in
children. Unpublished paper, University of British Columbia. Revised version
to appear in The Canadian Journal of Linguistics.
Ingram, D. & Tyack, D. 1979. The inversion of subject NP and Aux in children’s
questions. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 4: 333-41.
Ingram, D., Christensen, L., Veach, S. & Webster, B. 1980. The acquisition of
word-initial fricatives and affricates in English by children between 2 and 6 years.
In Yeni-Komshian, Kavanaugh & Ferguson (1980a: 169-92).
Inhelder, B. 1963. Some aspects of Piaget’s genetic approach to cognition. In Kissan
& Kohlman (eds.) Thought and the young child, pp. 17-32.
Inhelder, B. & Piaget, J. 1964. The growth of logic in the child: classifcation and
seriation. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Irwin, 0. C . 1941-49. See references in McCarthy (1954).
Jackendoff, R. 1977. Xsyntax: a study of phrase structure. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
1983. Semantics and cognition. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Jakobson, R. 1939. The sound laws of child language and their place in general
phonology. Communication prepared at Charlottenlund, Denmark, in the
Bibliography 533
summer of 1939 for the 5th International Congress of Linguists at Brussels,
September, 1939. Reprinted in Bar-Adon & Leopold (1971).
1941168. Child language, aphasia, and phonological universals. The Hague:
Mouton. Translation by R. Keiler of original German version of 1941.
Jakobson, R., Fant, G. & Halle, H. 1963. Preliminaries to speech analysis: the
distinctive features and their correlates. Technical Report 13, MIT Acoustics
Laboratory, 1952. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Jakobson, R. & Halle, M. 1956. Fundamentals of language. The Hague: Mouton.
Jegi, J. 1901.The vocabulary of a two-year-old child. Child Study Monthly 6: 241-61.
Jenkins, J. & Palermo, D. 1964. Mediation processes and the acquisition of
linguistic structure. In Bellugi & Brown (1964: 141-69).
Jespersen, 0. 1922. Language: its nature, development, and origin. London: Allen
& Unwin.
Johnson, C. 1983. The development of children’s interrogatives: from formulas to
rules. Papers and Reports on Child Language Development 22: 108-15.
Johnson, C. J., Hardee, W. P. & Long, S. H. 1981. Perceptual basis for phonologi-
cal simplification. Paper presented to the American Speech, Language, and
Hearing Association, Los Angeles, California.
Johnston, J. 1979. A study of spatial thought and expression: ‘in back’ and ‘in front’.
Doctoral dissertation, University of California, Berkeley.
1986. Cognitive prerequisites: the evidence from children learning English. In
Slobin (1986: 961-1004).
Johnston, J. & Slobin, D. 1979. The development of locative expressions in English,
Italian, Serbo-Croatian, and Turkish. Journal of Child Language 6: 529-45.
Jusczyk, P. 1981. Infant speech perception: a critical appraisal. In P. Eimas & J.
Miller (eds.) Perspectives on the study of speech. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Jusczyk, P., Shea, S. & A s h , R. 1984. Linguistic experience and infant speech
perception: a re-examination of Eilers, Gavin and Oller (1982). Journal of Child
Language 11: 453-66.
Kaczmarek, L. 195311. A general view of the formation of child language. In
Bar-Adon & Leopold (1971: 13M).Translation of original Polish.
Kahn, L. 1986. Basics of phonological analysis: a programmed learning text. San
Diego, Calif.: College-Hill Press.
Kamil, M. L. & Rudegeair, R. E. 1972. Methodological improvements in the
assessment of phonological discrimination in children. Child Development 43:
1087-91.
Kaplan, E. & Kaplan, G. 1971. The prelinguistic child. In J. Eliot (ed.) Human
development and cognitive processes. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston,
pp. 358-81.
Karmiloff-Smith, A. 1979. A functional approach to child language: a study of
determiners and reference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Katz, N., Baker, E. & Macnamara, J. 1974. What’s in a name? A study of how
children learn common and proper names. Child Development 45: 469-73.
Kaye, K. 1980a. Why don’t we talk ‘baby talk‘ to babies. Journal of Child Language
7: 489-507.
1980b. The infant as a projective stimulus. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry.
Kaye, K. & Charney, R. 1981. Conversational asymmetry between mothers and
children. Journal of Child Language 8: 35-49.
534 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Keil, F. C. 1979. Semantic and conceptual development: an ontological perspective.
Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press.
Keil, F. C. & Carroll, J. J. 1980. The child’s acquisition of ‘tall’: implications for an
alternative view of semantic development. Papers and Reports on Child Lan-
guage Development 19: 21-8.
Kent, R. 1981. Articulatory-acoustic perspectives on speech development. In Stark
(1981: 105-26).
Kernan, K. 1969. The acquisition of language by Samoan children. Doctoral
dissertation, University of California, Berkeley.
Kiparsky, P. & Menn, L. 1977. On the acquisition of phonology. In Macnamara
(1977: 47-78).
Klatzky, R., Clark, E. & Macken, M. A. 1973. Asymmetries in the acquisition of
polar adjectives: linguistic or conceptual? Journal of Experimental Child
Psychology 16: 32-46.
Klee, T. & Fitzgerald, M. D. 1985. The relation between grammatical development
and mean length of utterance in morphemes. Journal of Child Language 12:
251-69.
Klein, S. 1982. Syntactic theory and the developing grammar: reestablishing the
relationship between linguistic theory and data from language acquisition.
Doctoral dissertation, UCLA.
Klima, E. & Bellugi-Klima, U. 1966. Syntactic regularities in the speech of children.
In Lyons & Wales (1966: 183-208). Reprinted in Bar-Adon & Leopold (1971:
412-24).
KuEera, H. 1983. Roman Jakobson. Language 59: 871-83.
KuEera, H. & Francis, W. 1967. Computational analysis of present-day American
English. Providence, Rhode Island. Brown University Press.
Kuczaj, S. A. 1976. Arguments against Hurford’s ‘Aux copying rule’. Journal of
Child Language 3: 423-7.
1978. Why do children fail to overgeneralize the progressive inflection? Journal of
Child Language 5: 167-71.
1982a. On the nature of syntactic development. In Kuczaj (1982b: 37-71).
(ed.) 1982b. Language development. Vol. 1. Syntax and semantics. Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Kuczaj, S. A. & Barrett, M. (eds.) 1986. The development of word meaning:
progress in cognitive development research. New York and Berlin: Springer-
Verlag.
Kuczaj, S. A. & Brannick, N. 1979. Children’s use of the wh question modal
auxiliary placement rule. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 28: 43-67.
Kuczaj, S. A. & Maratsos, M. 1975. What children ‘can’ say before they ‘will’.
Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development 21: 89-111.
1983. Initial verbs of yes-no questions: a different kind of general grammatical
category. Developmental Psychology 19: 440-4.
Kuhl, P. 1980. Perceptual constancy for speech-sound categories in early infancy. In
Yeni-Komshian, Kavanaugh & Ferguson (1980b: 41-66).
1981. Auditory category formation and development of speech perception. In
Stark (1981: 165-83).
Kuhl, P. & Miller, J. D. 1975. Speech perception by the chinchilla: voiced-voiceless
distinction in alveolar-plosive consonants. Science 1%:69-72.
Bibliography 535
Labov, W. & Labov, T. 1978. Learning the syntaxof questions. In R. Campbell & P.
Smith (eds.) Recent advances in the psychology of language: language develop-
ment and mother-child interaction, vol. 4b. New York & London: Plenum,
pp. 1-44.
Ladefoged, P. 1975. A course in phonetics. New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich.
Lange, S. & Larsson, K. 1973. Syntactic development of a Swedish girl, Embla,
between 20 and 42 months of age, I: age 20-25 months. Report No. I, Project
Child Language Syntax. Stockholm: Institutionem for nordiska sprak,
Stockholms Universitet.
Lasky, R. E., Syrdal-Lasky, A. & Klein, R. E. 1975. VOT discrimination by four to
six-and-a-half month old infants from Spanish environments. Journal of Experi-
mental Child Psychology 20: 215-25.
Leech, G. 1970. Towards a semantic description of English. Bloomington, Ind.:
Indiana University Press.
1974. Semantics. Harmondsworth, Middx: Penguin.
Lenneberg, E. H. (ed.) 1964. New directions in the study of language. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
1967. Biological foundations of language. New York: Wiley.
Lenneberg, E. H. & Lenneberg, E. (eds.) 1975. Foundations of language develop-
ment, New York: Academic Press.
Lenneberg, E., Rebelsky, G. & Nichols, I. 1965. The vocalizations of infants born
to deaf and to hearing parents. Human Development 8: 23-37.
Leonard, L. 1976. Meaning in child language: issues in the study of early semantic
development. New York: Grune & Stratton.
Leonard, L., Newhoff, M. & Mesalam, L. 1980. Individual differences in early
phonology. Journal of Applied Psycholinguistics 1: 7-30.
Leonard, L., Rowan, L., Morris, L. & Fey, M. 1982. Intra-word phonological
variability in young children. Journal of Child Language 9: 55-69.
Leopold, W. 1939-49. Speech development of a bilingual child: a linguist’s record.
Vol. 1: Vocabulary growth in the first two years (1939). Vol. 2: Sound learning in
the first two years (1947). Vol. 3: Grammar and general problems in the first two
years (1949). Vol. 4: Diary from age two. (1949). Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern
University Press.
1952. Bibliography of child language. Evanston, Ill. : Northwestern University
Press.
Lewis, M. M. 1936151. Infant speech: a study of the beginnings of language. 2nd edn.
New York: Harcourt Brace. (First edition published in 1936.)
1937. The beginning of reference to past and future in a child’s speech. British
Journal of Educational Psychology 7: 39-56.
Lieberman, P. 1975. On the origins of language. New York: MacMillan.
1980. On the development of vowel production in young children. In Yeni-
Komshian, Kavanaugh & Ferguson (1980a: 11342).
Lightfoot, D. 1979. Principles of diachronic syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
1982. The language lottery. Towards a biology of grammars. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
Limber, J. 1973. The genesis of complex sentences. In Moore (1973: 169-85).
536 BIBLIOGRAPHY
1976. Unravelling competence, performance and pragmatics in the speech of
young children. Journal of Child Language 3: 309-18.
Lipp, E. 1977. The acquisition of Estonian inflections. Journal of Child Language 4:
313-19.
Lisker, L. & Abramson, A. S. 1967. The voicing dimension: some experiments in
comparative phonetics. Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of
Phonetic Sciences, Prague.
Loban, W. 1976. Language development: kindergarten through twelve. Urbana, Ill.:
National Council of Teachers of English.
Lock, A. (ed.) 1978. Action, gesture and symbol: the emergence of language.
London: Academic Press.
Locke, J. L. 1971. Phonemic perception in 2- and 3-year-old children. Perceptual
and Motor Skills 32: 215-17.
1983. Phonological acquisition and change. New York: Academic Press.
Lovell, K. & Dixon, E. 1967. The growth of the control of grammar in imitation,
comprehension and production. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 8:
31-9.
Lukens, H . 1894. Preliminary report on the learning of language. Pedagogical
Seminary 3: 424-60.
Lust, B. 1986. Studies in first language acquisition of anaphora: defining the
constraints. Boston, Mass.: D. Reidel.
Lynip, A. 1951. The use of magnetic devices in the collection and analysis of the
preverbal utterances of an infant. Genetic Psychology Monographs 44: 221-62.
Lyons, J. 1968. Theoretical linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lyons, J. & Wales, R. (eds.) 1966. Psycholinguisticpapers. Edinburgh: University
of Edinburgh Press.
MacKain, K. S. & Stern, D. N. 1985. The concept of experience in speech
development. In K. E. Nelson (1985: 1-33).
Macken, M. A. 1978. Permitted complexity in phonological development: one
child‘s acquisition of Spanish consonants. Lingua 44: 219-53.
1979. Developmental reorganization of phonology: a hierarchy of basic units of
acquisition. Lingua 49: 11-49.
1980. The child’s lexical representation: the ‘puzzle-puddle-pickle’ evidence.
Journal of Linguistics 16: 1-17.
1986. Representation, rules and overgeneralization in phonology. Unpublished
paper, Stanford University.
Macken, M. A. & Ferguson, C. A. 1983. Cognitive aspects of phonological
development: model, evidence, and issues. In K. E. Nelson (1983: 256-82).
Macnamara, J. 1972. Cognitive basis of language learning in infants. Psychological
Review 79: 1-13. Reprinted in Bloom (1978: 390-406).
(ed.) 1977. Language learning and thought. New York: Academic Press.
1982. Names for things: a study of human learning. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
MacWhinney, B. 1975. Rules, rote, and analogy in morphological formations by
Hungarian children. Journal of Child Language 2: 65-77.
1976. Hungarian research on the acquisition of morphology and syntax. Journal of
Child Language 3: 397-410.
1978. Processing a first language: the acquisition of morphophonology. Mono-
graphs of the Society for Research in Child Development 43, no. 174.
Bibliography 537
1982. Basic syntactic processes. In Kuczaj (1982b: 73-136).
MacWhinney, B. & Bates, E. 1978. Sentential devices for conveying givenness and
newness: a cross-cultural developmental study. Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior 17: 539-58.
Malrieu, P. 1973. Aspects psychologiques de la construction de la phrase chez
I’enfant. Journal de Psychologie 70: 157-74.
Marantz, A. 1982. On the acquisition of grammatical relations. Linguistische
Berichte 8 W 2 : 32-69.
1983. The connection between grammatical relations and lexical categories in
language acquisition and linguistic theory. In Otsu et al. (1973: 165-7).
1984. On the nature of grammatical relations. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Maratsos, M. 1973. Decrease in the understanding of the word ‘big’ in preschool
children. Child Development 44: 747-52.
1974a. Children who get worse at understanding the passive: a replication of
%ever. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 3: 65-74.
1974b. When is a high thing a big one? Developmental Psychology 10: 367-75.
1978, New models in linguistics and language acquisition. In M. Halle, J. Bresnan
& G. Miller (eds.) Linguistic theory and psychological reality. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, pp. 247-63.
1982. The child’s construction of grammatical categories. In Wanner & Gleitman
(1982: 240-66).
1984. The acquisition of syntax. In J. Flavell & E. Markman (eds.) Carmichael’s
handbook of child psychology, vol. 3,4th edn. New York: Wiley.
Maratsos, M. & Abramovitch, R. 1975. How children understand full, truncated,
and anomalous passives. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 14:
145-57.
Maratsos, M. & Chalkley, M. A. 1980. The internal language of children’s syntax:
the ontogenesis and representation of syntactic categories. In K. E. Nelson
(1980: 127-214).
Maratsos, M. & Kuczaj, S. A. 1978. Against the transformational account: a simpler
analysis of auxiliary overmarkings. Journal of Child Language 5 : 337-45.
Maratsos, M., Kuczaj, S . A., Fox, D. & Chalkley, M. A. 1979. Some empirical
studies in the acquisition of transformational relations: passives, negatives, and
the past tense. In W. Collins (ed.) Children’s language and communication.
Minnesota Symposia on Child Psychology. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 1-45.
Mazurkewich, I. 1982. Second language acquisition of the dative alternation and
markedness: the best theory. Doctoral dissertation, Universitt de Montreal.
1984. The acquisition of the dative alternation by second language learners and
linguistic theory. Language Learning 34: 91-109.
Mazurkewich, I. & White, L. 1984. The acquisition of the dative alternation:
unlearning overgeneralizations. Cognition 16: 261-83.
McCarthy, D. 1930. The language development of the preschool child. Institute of
Child Welfare Monograph Series 4. Mineapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
1954. Language development in children. In Carmichael (ed.) Manual of child
psychology. New York: John Wiley, pp. 492-630.
McNeill, D. 1966a. Developmental psycholinguistics. In Smith & Miller (1966:
15-84).
1966b. The creation of language by children. In Lyons & Wales (1966: 99-115).
538 BIBLIOGRAPHY
1970a. The acquisition of language. New York: Harper & Row.
1970b. The development of language. In P. Mussen (ed.) Carmichael’s manual of
childpsychology, vol. 1, pp. 1061-1161.
1971. The capacity for grammatical development in children. In Slobin (1971:
17-40).
Mead, M. 1963. Sex and temperament in three primitive societies. New York:
Morrow.
Menn, L. 1971. Phonotactic rules in beginning speech. Lingua 26: 225-51.
1978. Pattern, control and contrast in beginning speech, a case study in the
development of word form and word function. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana
University Linguistics Club.
1980. Phonological theory and child phonology. In Yeni-Komshian, Kavanaugh
& Ferguson (1980: 2341).
1983. Development of articulatory, phonetic, and phonological capabilities. In B.
Butterworth (ed.) Language production: development, writing and other lan-
guageprocesses. Vol. 2. New York: Academic Press, pp. 3-50.
Menyuk, P. 1969. Sentences children use. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
1971. The acquisition and development of language. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Menyuk, P. & Anderson, S. 1969. Children’s identification and reproduction of lwl,
Id, and Ill, Journal of Speech and Hearing Research 12: 39-52.
Menyuk, P. & Menn, L. 1979. Early strategies for the perception and production of
words and sounds. In Fletcher & Garman (1979: 49-70).
Mervis, C. & Canada, K. 1983. On the existence of competence errors in early
comprehension: a reply to Fremgen & Fay and Chapman & Thomson. Journal of
Child Language 10: 431-40.
Miller, G. & McNeill, D. 1969. Psycholinguistics. In G. Lindzey & E. Aaronson
(eds.) Handbook of social psychology. Reading, Mass: Addison-Wesley,
pp. 666-794.
Miller, J. 1981. Assessing languageproduction in children. Baltimore, Md.: Univer-
sity Park Press.
Miller, J., Chapman, R., Bronston, M. & Reichle, J. 1980. Language comprehen-
sion in sensorimotor stages V and VI. Journal of Speech and Hearing Research
23: 284-311.
Miller, J. & Yoder, D. 1974. An ontogeneticteaching strategy for retarded children.
In Schiefelbusch & Lloyd (1974: 505-28).
1984. Language comprehension text (clinical edition). Baltimore, Md. : University
Park Press.
Miller, P. D. 1972. Vowel neutralization and vowel reduction. Papers from the
Eighth Regional Meeting, Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 482-9.
Miller, W. & Ervin, S. 1964. The development of grammar in child language. In
Bellugi & Brown (1964: 9-34).
Minifie, F. & Lloyd, L. (eds.) 1978. Communicative and cognitive abilities in early
language assessment. Baltimore, Md. : University Park Press.
Moerk, E. 1980. Relationships between input frequencies and children’s language
acquisition: a reanalysis of Brown’s data. Journal of Child Language 7: 105-18.
1981. To attend or not to attend to unwelcome reanalyses? A reply to Pinker.
Journal of Child Language 8: 627-31.
Bibliography 539
Moffitt, A. 1971. Consonant cue perception by 22 twenty-four-week-old infants.
Child Development 42: 717-32.
Moore, T. (ed.) 1973. Cognitive development and the acquisition of meaning. New
York: Academic Press.
Morehead, D. M. & Ingram, D. 1973. The development of base syntax in normal and
linguisticallydeviant children. Journalof Speech and Hearing Research 16:330-52.
Morehead, D. M. & Morehead, A. E. (eds.) 1976. Normal and dejicient child
language. Baltimore, Md.: University Park Press.
Morse, P. 1974. Infant speech perception: a preliminary model and review of the
literature. In Schiefelbusch & Lloyd (1974: 19-53).
Moskowitz, A. 1970. The two-year-old stage in the acquisition of English phono-
logy. Language 46: 426-41.
1971. Acquisition of phonology. Doctoral dissertation, University of California,
Berkeley.
Mowrer, 0. 1960. Learning theory and symbolicprocesses. New York: John Wiley.
Muma, J. 1986. Language acquisition: a functional perspective. Austin, Texas:
Pro-Ed.
Munson, J. & Ingram, D. 1985. Morphology before syntax: a case study from
language acquisition. Journal of Child Language 12: 681-4.
Nelson, K. 1973. Structure and strategy in learning to talk. Monographs of the
Society of Research in Child Development 38, no. 149.
1974. Concept, word and sentence: interrelations in acquisition and development.
Psychological Review 81: 267-85.
1975. The nominal shift in semantic-syntactic development. Cognitive Psychology
7: 461-79.
1986. Event knowledge: structure and function in development. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Nelson, K. E. 1977. Facilitating children’s syntax acquisition. Developmental
Psychology 13: 101-7.
(ed.) 1978. Children’s language. Vol. 1 . New York: Gardner Press.
(ed.) 1980a. Children’s language. Vol. 2 . New York: Gardner Press.
1981. Toward a rare event cognitive comparison theory of syntax acquisition:
insights from work with recasts. In Dale & Ingram (1981: 22940).
(ed.) 1984. Children’s language. Vol. 4 . Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
(ed.) 1985. Children’s language. Vol. 5 . Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
1981. Toward a rare-event comparison theory of syntax acquisition. In Dale &
Ingram (1981).
Nelson, K. E. & Baker, N. 1984. Recasting. First Language 5: 3-21.
Nelson, K. E. & Bonvillian, J. (1973). Concepts and words in the 18-month-old:
acquiring concept names under controlled conditions. Cognition 2: 435-50.
Nelson, K. E., Carskaddoq, G., & Bonvillian, J. 1973. Syntax acquisition: impact of
experimental variation in adult verbal interaction with the child. Child Develop-
ment 44: 497-504.
Nelson, K. E., Denninger, M., Bonvillian, J., Kaplan, B., & Baker, N. 1984.
Maternal input adjustments and non-adjustments as related to children’s linguis-
tic advances and to language acquisition theories. In A. D. Pelligrini & T. D.
Yawkey (eds.) The development of oral and written languages: readings in
developmental applied linguistics. New York: Ablex, pp. 31-56.
540 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Newmeyer, F. 1983. Grammatical theory: its limits and its possibilities. Chicago, Ill. :
University of Chicago Press.
Newport, E., Gleitman, H. & Gleitman, L. 1977. Mother, I’d rather do it myself
some effects and non-effects of maternal speech style. In Snow & Ferguson
(1977: 101-49).
Nice, M. 1917. The speech development of a child from eighteen months to six
years. Pedagogical Seminary 24: 204-43.
1920. Concerning all-day conversations. Pedagogical Seminary 27: 166-77.
1925. Length of sentences as a criterion of child’s progress in speech. Journal of
Educational Psychology 16: 370-9.
Ninio, A. & Bruner, J. 1978. The achievement and antecedents of labelling. Journal
of Child Language 5: 1-15.
Nokony, A. 1978. Word and gesture by an Indian child. In Lock (1978: 291-307).
Ochs, E. 1979. Transcription as theory. In Ochs & Schiefflin (1979: 43-72).
1982a.Ergativity and word order in Samoan child language. Language 58: 646-71.
1982b. Talking to children in Western Samoa. Language in Society 11: 77-104.
Ochs, E. & Schiefflin, B. (eds.) 1979. Developmental pragmatics. New York:
Academic Press.
O’Donnell, R. C., Griffin, W. J. & Norris, R. C. 1967. Syntax of kindergarten and
elementary school children. Champaign, Ill.: National Council of Teachers.
O’Grady, W. 1986. Principles of grammar and learning. Chicago, Ill.: University of
Chicago Press.
O’Grady, W., Suzuki-Wei, Y. & Cho, S. W. 1986. Directionality preferences in the
interpretation of anaphora: data from Korean and Japanese. Journal of Child
Language 13: 409-20.
Oksaar, 0. 1983. Language acquisition in the early years. New York: Saint Martin’s
Press. Translated from the German original of 1977.
Oller, D. K. 1980. The emergence of the sounds of speech in infancy. In
Yeni-Komshian, Kavanaugh & Ferguson (1980: 93-112).
1981. Infant vocalizations: exploration and reflexivity. In Stark (1981: 85-103).
Oller, D. K. & Eilers, R. 1982. Similarity of babbling in Spanish- and English-
learning babies. Journal of Child Language 9: 565-77.
Oller, D. K., Eilers, R., Bull, D. & Carney, A. 1985. Prespeech vocalizations of a
deaf infant: a comparison with normal metaphonological development. Journal
of Speech and Hearing Research 28: 47-63.
Oller, D. K., Wieman, L., Doyle, W. & Ross, C. 1976. Infant babbling and speech.
Journal of Child Language 3: 1-11.
Olmsted, D. 1971. Out of the mouth of babes. The Hague: Mouton.
Olsen-Fulero, L. 1982. Style and stability in mother conversational behaviour: a
study of individual differences. Journal of Child Language 9: 543-64.
O’Shea, M. 1907. Linguistic development and education. London: Macmillan.
Otsu, Y., van Riemsdijk, H., Inoue, K., Kamio, A. & Kawasaki, N. (eds.) 1983.
Studies in generative grammar and language acquisition. Tokyo: Editorial
Committee. (Inside jacket states that copies can be ordered from N. Kawasaki,
c/o Division of Languages, International Christian University, Tokyo.)
Park, T.-Z. 1978. Plurals in child speech. Journal of Child Language 5: 237-50.
Pelsrna, J. 1910. A child vocabulary and its development. Pedagogical Seminary 17:
328-69.
Bibliography 541
Penman, R., Cross, T., Milgrom-Friedman, J. & Meares, R. (1983). Mothers’
speech to prelinguistic infants: a pragmatic analysis. Journal of Child Language
10: 17-34.
Perlmutter, D. 1983. Studies in relational grammar 1. Chicago, Ill.: University of
Chicago Press.
Perroni Semoes, M. & Stoel-Gammon, C. 1979. The acquisition of inflections in
Portuguese: a study of the development of person markers on verbs. Journal of
Child Language 6: 53-67.
Peshkovskiy, A. M. 1925. Desyat’ tysyach Zvukov. Sb statey.
Peters, A. 1977. Language learning strategies. Language 53: 56-73.
1983. The units of language acquisition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Petretic, P. & Tweney, R. 1977. Does comprehension precede production? The
development of children’s responses to telegraphic sentences of varying gram-
matical adequacy. Journal of Child Language 4: 201-9.
Piaget, J. 1929. The child’s conception of the world. New York: Harcourt Brace.
1948. Play, dreams and imitation in childhood. New York: Norton.
1952. The origins of intelligence in children. New York: International Universities
Press.
1954. The construction of reality in the child. New York: Basic Books.
1955. The language and thought of the child. Cleveland, 111.: World Publishing Co.
1971. Biology and knowledge. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press.
Piaget, J. & Inhelder, B. 1967. The child’s conception of space. New York: Norton.
1969. The psychology of the child. New York: Basic Books.
Piattelli-Palmarini, M. (ed.) 1980. Language and learning: the debate between Jean
Piaget and Noam Chomsky. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Pinker, S. 1981. On the acquisition of grammatical morphemes. Journal of Child
Language 8: 477-84.
1982. A theory of the acquisition of lexical interpretive grammars. In J. Bresnan
(ed.) The mental representation of grammatical relations. Cambridge, Mass. :
MIT Press.
1984. Language learnability and language development. Cambridge, Mass. :
Harvard University Press.
Pitcher, E. G. & Prelinger, E. 1963. Children tellstories. New York: International
Universities Press.
Pollock, F. 1878. An infant’s progress in language. Mind 3: 392-401.
Prather, E. M., Hedrick, D. L. & Kern, C. A. 1975. Articulation development in
children aged two to four years. Journal of Speech and Hearing Disorders 40:
179-91.
Preyer, W. 1889. The mind of the child. New York: Appleton. Translation of
original German edn of 1882.
Prideaux, G. 1976. A functional analysis of English question acquisition: a response
to Hurford. Journal of Child Language 3: 417-22.
Pye, C. 1980. The acquisition of grammatical morphemes in Quicht Mayan.
Doctoral dissertation, University of Pittsburgh.
1983a. Mayan telegraphese: intonational determinants of inflectional develop-
ment in Quicht Mayan. Language 59: 583-604.
1983b. Mayan motherese: an ethnography of Quicht Mayan speech to young
children. Unpublished paper.
542 BIBLIOGRAPHY
1985. Review of Language learnability and language development by Pinker.
Language 61: 903-7.
1986. QuichC Mayan speech to children. Journal of Child Language 13: 85-100.
1987. Language loss in the Chilcotin. Unpublished paper, University of Kansas.
Pye, C., Ingram, D. & List, H. 1987. A comparison of initial consonant acquisition
in English and QuichC. In K. E. Nelson & A. Van Kleeck (eds.) Children’s
language, vol. 6: 175-90 Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Radford, A. 1981. Transformational syntax: a student’s guide to Chomsky’s
Extended Standard Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ramer, A. 1976. Syntactic styles in emerging speech. Journal of Child Language 3:
49-62.
Ratner, N. & Bruner, J. 1978. Games, social exchange, and the acquisition of
language. Journal of Child Language 5: 391-401.
Ravn, K. E. & Gelman, S . A. 1984. Rule usage in children’s understanding of ‘big’
and ‘little’. Child Development 55: 2141-50.
Reinhart, T. 1976. The syntactic domain of anaphora. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
1981. Definite NP anaphora and c-command domains. Linguistic Inquiry 12:
605-35.
1983. Anaphora and semantic interpretation. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago
Press.
Rescorla, L. 1980. Overextensions in early language development. Journal of Child
Language 7: 321-35.
Rice, M. L. & Kemper, S . 1984. Child language and cognition. Baltimore:
University Park Press.
Rodd, L. & Braine, M. D. S. 1970. Children’s imitations of syntactic constructions
as a measure of linguistic competence. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior 10: 430-43.
Rodgon, M. 1976. Single-word usage, cognitive development and the beginnings of
combinatorial speech. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rodgon, M., Jankowski, W. & Alenskas, L. 1977. A multi-functional approach to
single-word usage. Journal of Child Language 4: 23-44.
Roeper, T. 1981. In pursuit of a deductive model of language acquisition. In Baker
& McCarthy (1981: 121-50).
Roeper, T. & Williams, E. (eds.) 1982. Parameter setting. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Rosch, E. 1973. On the internal structure of perceptual and semantic categories. In
Moore (1973: 111-44).
1975. Cognitive representation of semantic categories. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: General 104: 192-233.
1978. Principles of categorization. In E. Rosch & B. Lloyd (eds.) Cognition and
categorization. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Rosch, E. & Mervis, C. 1975. Family resemblances: studies in the internal structure
of categories. Cognitive Psychology 7: 573-605.
Rosch, E., Mervis, C., Gray, W., Johnson, D. & Boyes-Braem, P. 1976. Basic
objects in natural categories. Cognitive Psychology 8: 382-439.
Roussey, C. 1899-1900. Notes sur I’apprentissage de la parole chez un enfant. La
Parole 1: 790-880,2: 23-40, 86-97.
RCke-Dravipa, V. 1973. On the emergence of inflection in child language: a
contribution based on Latvian data. In Ferguson & Slobin (1973: 252-67).
Bibliography 543
Rumelhart, D. & McClelland, J. 1986. On learning the past tenses of English verbs.
In J. McClelland & D. Rumelhart (eds.) Parallel distributed processing: explor-
ations in the microstructure of cognition. Vol. 2. Psychological and biological
models. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, pp. 216-71.
Ryan, J. (1973). Interpretation and imitation in early language acquisition. In R.
Hinde & J. Hinde (eds.) Constraints on learning: limitations and predispositions.
London: Academic Press, pp. 427-44.
Sachs, J. 1977. The adaptive significance of linguistic input to prelinguistic infants.
In Snow & Ferguson (1977: 51-61).
Sachs, J. & Truswell, L. 1978. Comprehension of two-word instructions by children
in the one-word stage. Journal of Child Language 5: 17-24.
Samarin, W. 1967. Field linguistics: a guide to linguisticfield work. New York: Holt,
Rinehart & Winston.
Sander, E. K. 1961. When are speech sounds learned? Journal of Speech and
Hearing Disorders 37: 55-63.
Scarborough, H. & Wyckoff, J. 1986. Mother, I’d still rather do it myself: some
further non-effects of ‘motherese’. Journal of Child Language 13: 431-7.
Schaerlaekens, A. 1973. The two-word sentence in child language development. The
Hague: Mouton.
Schiefelbusch, R. (ed.) 1978. Bases of language intervention. Baltimore, Md. :
University Park Press.
Schiefelbusch, ,R. & Bricker, D. (eds.) 1981. Early language: acquisition and
intervention. Baltimore, Md. : University Park Press.
Schiefelbusch, R. & Lloyd, L. (eds.) 1974. Language perspectives: acquisition,
retardation, and intervention. Baltimore, Md.: University Park Press.
Schiefflin, B. 1979. Getting it together: an ethnographic approach to the study of the
development of communicativecompetence. In Ochs & Schiefflin (1979: 73-108).
Schlesinger, I. M. 1971. The production of utterances and language acquisition. In
Slobin (1971: 63-101).
1974. Relational concepts underlying language. In Schiefelbusch & Lloyd (1974:
129-51).
1977. Production and comprehension of utterances. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
1982. Steps toward language: toward a theory of native language acquisition.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Schwartz, R. & Camarata, S. 1985. Examining relationships between input and
language development: some statistical issues. Journal of Child Language 12:
199-207.
Schwartz, R. & Leonard, L. 1982. Do children pick and choose? An examination of
phonological selection and avoidance in early acquisition. Journal of Child
Language 9: 319-36.
Schwartz, R. & Terrell, B. 1983. The role of input frequency in lexical acquisition.
Journal of Child Language 10: 57-64.
Scollon, R. 1976. Conversations with a one year old. Honolulu: University Press of
Hawaii.
Sheldon, A. 1974. The parallel function in the acquisition of relative clauses in
English. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 13: 272-81.
Sherrod, K., Friedman, S., Crawley, S., Drake, D. & Devieux, J. 1977. Maternal
languageto prelinguisticinfants: syntactic aspects. Child Development48: 1662-5.
544 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Shibamoto, J. S. & Olmsted, D. 1978. Lexical and syllabic patterns in phonological
acquisition. Journal of Child Language 5 : 417-57.
Shipley, E., Smith, C. & Gleitman, L. 1969. A study in the acquisition of language:
free responses to commands. Language 45: 32242.
Shirley, M. M. 1933. The first two years: a study of twenty-five babies. Vol. 2.
Institute of Child Welfare Monograph Series. Minneapolis, Minn. : University of
Minnesota Press.
Shriberg, L. & Kwiatkowski, J. 1980. Natural process analysis (NPA). New York:
John Wiley.
Shvachkin, N. 1948/73. The development of phonemic speech perception in
children. In Ferguson & Slobin (1973: 91-127).
Sinclair, H. 1971. Sensorimotor action patterns as a condition for the acquisition of
syntax. In Huxley & Ingram (1971: 121-30).
Sinclair, H. & Ferreiro, E. 1970. Etude gCnCtique de la comprehension, production
et rePCtition des phrases a mode passif. Archives de Psychologie 40: 1 4 2 .
Skinner, 0. F. 1957. Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Slobin, D. 1966. Abstracts of Soviet studies of child language. In Smith & Miller
(1966: 361-86).
(ed.) 1967. Afield manual for cross-cultural study of the acquisition of communica-
tive competence. Berkeley, Calif. : University of California.
1968. Recall of full and truncated passive sentences in connected
discourse. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 7: 876-81. ,