Joshua Ramey Gilles Deleuze and The Pow
Joshua Ramey Gilles Deleuze and The Pow
Joshua Ramey Gilles Deleuze and The Pow
Villanova University
In Partial Fulfillment
Doctor of Philosophy
in
Philosophy
by
July, 2006
John Carvalho
UMI Number: 3220390
ii
Table of Contents
Acknowledgements
Abstract
List of Abbreviations
Platonism Reversed
Creative Encounters
Challenging Immanence
Toward a Haptic Form of Thought
iii
V. Writing Power: Desire and the Signs of Life
VII. Immanence Challenged: Politics, Art, and the Fourth World War
Notes
Bibliography
iv
Acknowledgements
The elegance and sophistication of my director, John Carvalho, has been the
charm of my years in graduate school. Without his humor, his pragmatism, and our
shared passion for music, I would never have glimpsed the end of this road. I cannot
express how grateful I am for his attention, compassion, and profound dedication to
helping me find my own voice. His graduate seminars on topics ranging from Socrates to
were the beacons of my intellectual voyage at Villanova. Dr. Carvalho’s appreciation for
the arts of healing and the healing of art, his bureaucratic savvy, and his profound
understanding of both ancient and modern paradigms in philosophy drew me into a life-
long quest.
Dr. Walter Brogan’s hospitality and collegial demeanor was responsible for my
attraction to Villanova in the first place. His enthusiasm for my work and his deeply
insightful seminars on Nietzsche and ancient philosophy are resources on which I have
continuously drawn. I cannot thank him enough for the way he helped me form a bridge
between earlier and present phases of my own thought, and for how he has made me feel
My downtown meetings with Dr. Julie Klein at Café Lutece were tasty ways of
continuing the work of her inspiring Spinoza seminar. Dr. Klein’s sophisticated approach
to late medieval and early modern thought encouraged my own research in many, many
ways. This project could not have materialized without her support and her confidence in
my abilities.
v
John Milbank’s incisive appraisals of the hermetic traditions in Western thought
has been a source of constant inspiration to me, ever since I first came across his work in
print. I have been deeply challenged by the boldness of his vision, and I am very grateful
for his willingness to be part of this committee, and for his support of my research.
For years before any of these phrases began to take shape, before the paragraphs
and chapters emerged, when even the ideas themselves were barely more than flashes of
energy and surges of life, a density of friendships formed (and still form) a life which I
am happy to say will never be fully my own possession. My brother, Philip Ramey, has
always been and always will be my greatest intellectual sparring partner, and the one with
whom I have most deeply shared the pain and ecstasy of why thought matters.
My best friends, most astute colleagues, most intimidating mentors, and the most
venomously angelic minds I know are those of my collaborators Paul Haidle, Clark Roth,
and Aron Dunlap. My ambition for this thesis, from the start, was that it in some way
Kazarian, Giorgio Agamben, Rocco Gangle, Creston Davis, Jessica Elkyam, Adriel Trott,
Ray Brassier, and James Wetzel has constantly reminded me of the collective nature of
The artists and sages of the sweet city of Philadelphia, a town that has supported
me in ways too subtle and too powerful to say, have included Rick, Barbara, and Francis
Alton, Anne de Quillettes, Elizabeth Haidle, Loren Johnson, Aaron Straight, Jesse
Ketteridge, James Sugg, Victor Fiorillo, Lee Etzold, Dito van Reigersberg, David Brick,
Maggie Sift, Hilary Dick, Lorin Lyle, Bill Reil, Jeb Kreager, Jim Sutcliffe, Mike Kiley,
vi
Nicole Canuso, Matt Saunders, Christie Lee, Olase Freeman, Jillian Bird, Nora Johnson,
Leslie Delauter, Bob Ennis, Jack Norris, Emily and Ivy Ramey, Elizabeth Doering, Jeb
Lewis, Mike Hood, Lou Fuiano, and the untamed alley cats of South Camac Street.
Without the generosity and constant attention of my parents, John Calvin and
Michelle Joy Ramey, I would not have had the strength to finish this project.
me the space, the time, and the experience required to bring this work to fruition. May it
vii
Abstract
“Gilles Deleuze and the Powers of Art” is a preliminary investigation into how certain
key notions of French philosopher and aesthetician Gilles Deleuze (1925-1995) may be
defined more richly they have been so far. Against either overly idealist or overly
reductivist accounts of the simulacral, singularity, difference, immanence, univocity,
signification, and life in terms of which Deleuze is usually understood, the thesis attempts
to emphasize the performative, pragmatic, and transformative dimensions of these terms
against their presumably ontological referents. By reading Deleuze as a reader of art, and
by rendering his notion of art in terms of a peculiar power to generate worlds, this
dissertation argues that artistic inspiration for a “constructivism” in philosophy links
Deleuze to a Renaissance tradition of neoplatonic speculation that saw poetic and magical
acts as being co-incipient and co-terminus. This thesis is argued for through a reading of
Deleuze on the powers of certain modern art forms and on the way in which the practices
of certain artists model a form of thought that is immediately the genesis of new forms of
life. Deleuze’s philosophizing on behalf of such a life is defended in the face of recent
criticisms by Slavoj Zizek and Alain Badiou, as well as earlier critics such as Rene
Girard. The importance of connecting Deleuze’s notion of creation to earlier
Renaissance and magical notions of poiesis becomes clearer against the backdrop of
current debates about which materialism is necessary to overcome the anti-materialism of
capitalism in contemporary life. While Deleuze’s philosophy is proposed as offering new
futures for our times, it is also taken as a proposal for further work—work beyond
Deleuze’s own—in the elaboration of a complex notion of materiality that would exceed
the modern (and postmodern) opposition of the magical to the real. This project is
outlined but not comprehensively accomplished here.
viii
List of Abbreviations
(AO) Anti-Oedipus*
(ATP) A Thousand Plateaus*
(ES) Empiricism and Subjectivity
(C1) Cinema I: The Movement-Image
(C2) Cinema II: The Time-Image
(CC) Essays Critical and Clinical
(D) Dialogues
(DI) Desert Islands and Other Texts (1953-1974)
(DR) Difference and Repetition
(FB) Francis Bacon and the Logic of Sensation
(LS) The Logic of Sense
(F) The Fold
(NP) Nietzsche and Philosophy
(PI) Pure Immanence: A Life
(PS) Proust and Signs
(WIP) What is Philosophy?*
ix
Introduction: The Aesthetic Paradigm
the arts. Plato’s Socrates claims, however, that his critiques of poetry and artistic device
are not peculiar to him, but issue from an ancient war between philosophy and poetry, a
perpetual antagonism between logos and poiesis. Socrates makes several different
complaints against poetry in Plato’s dialogues, but his criticisms can be crystallized in the
complaint that poetry is essentially indifferent to truth. Truth for Socrates is always an
endeavor to present the way things most deeply and truly are, beyond all appearances.
Insofar as what makes art compelling is its appearances per se and not the presentation of
an ideal essence existing beyond all appearance, for Socrates art fails to present the
Forms (eidei) of reality: those essences only ever partially realized in the appearances of
a changing world. What captivates our attention in art, for Socrates, is precisely what
questioning himself and others about the nature of things—his famous search for
rhetor or the rhapsode, who entrusts her truth to the persuasive force of the images of
reality she is able to conjure through her art. The philosopher, on the other hand, is ready
to submit her image of reality to constant cross-examination. At stake in this battle are
the merits of two different forms of discourse: one which perpetually seeks truth beyond
appearance, image, and imagination, and another which proposes a truth of (or within)
appearances, themselves.
1
In ontological terms, because for Socrates the fundamental elements of reality are
given only in the ideal forms, the poet or rhetor can present only abstract shards of true
being. Poetry presents only the more or less incomplete ways in which the empirical flux
of time, space, and historical circumstance is more or less participating in the ideal reality
of the Forms. Poetry is thus “twice removed” from reality: as an imitation of actually
existent people, places, and things, what poetry presents is already a mere copy of an
ideal Form. The “lie” of poetry, for Socrates, is that it attempts to pass off one or several
combinations of these shards or shadows of the ideas as a true description of reality. For
Socrates, we are persuaded of art’s truth based only on the power of those shadows over
our sensibility and imagination (aspects of mind that are locked into the illusions of the
empirical flux) and not by any purchase art might have on what is most truly real.
In his early and important study of the work of Marcel Proust, French aesthetician
and philosopher Gilles Deleuze claims, contrary to Socrates, that artistic style has the
power to access the most fundamental elements of experience. In Deleuze’s view, artistic
style renders the essence of things in a way that not only has a legitimate purchase on
reality, but in fact embodies a method and a structure that can be paradigmatic for
philosophy itself. Deleuze describes the power of art to present essence in the following
way:
2
confers the common quality upon them . . . This is because style, in order
to spiritualize essence, reproduces the unstable opposition, the original
complication, the struggle and exchange of the primordial elements that
constitute essence itself. (PS 48)
least two different objects such that, in a way that would be otherwise impossible, artistic
style expresses qualities common to disparate things—a set of essences divided among,
or “complicated” in objects that only style can reveal. Deleuze’s claim is not so much
that the essence of art is metaphor, but that the essence of metaphor (this is that) is
and exchange” of qualities beneath the level of identifiable objects (quantities and
medium” of an artistic style. This new medium both confers an essence on disparate
objects and reveals that primitive struggle or “unstable opposition” in which the essence
consists. Essence for Deleuze, therefore, is not an immutable Platonic ideal form, but is
Deleuze’s thesis, in part, is that art is able to combine and change elements that
an “effect” of its operations, does this mean that the essences art invokes are “unreal” or
are somehow less real than, say, what causes a chemical reaction or a tectonic plate shift?
Is the power of art ultimately the power of illusion, or is the metamorphosis of things in
3
Style matters, or brings its own substance into being, because for Deleuze the
elements appear. And when appearing in repetition, in series, elements appear not so
much as what they are as what they may become. Deleuze’s philosophy is thus a
platonism of essences in becoming, where the idea of a thing is not given in advance of
an event which transforms that idea in a differentiating repetition. In short, for Deleuze,
becoming is both ontologically and logically prior to being, and what for Plato were
Because the truth of art is the truth of a world whose substance is found through
dynamics of things as they are in becoming. For Deleuze, the worlds presented by a work
of art are not independent from mind in the sense that, say, natural kinds might be
thought to be. But neither are the worlds of art merely subjective perspectives which
artists or audiences take up at will. Never taken up at random, yet never a mere product
of fate, the work of art embodies the paradox of a forced choice, an experiment with
destiny. This is why, for Deleuze, artistic creation offers a deep if somewhat paradoxical
thought of the real, or of what he calls a “strange complicity between mind and matter.”
In this thesis, “Gilles Deleuze and the Powers of Art,” I explicate Deleuze’s
diverse philosophical enterprise in terms of his attempt to use this artistic model or
Deleuze’s oeuvre, I trace how art illuminates the possibility of a new kind of thought, a
4
thought not of the identities proper to being but the transformations possible for a world
in becoming.1
Platonism Reversed
notion that being is inherently expressive, and that this sense of expression or creativity
not only cuts across or “deconstructs” dualisms between subject and object, essence and
accident, form and content (which it does), but also implies a creative role for mind in
construed as creative acts, and how the singular nature of things becomes available in
certain extraordinary signs and figures that clue us in not to the nature of a substance, but
to the nature of expression. Deleuze is thinking in a space where willed action and
natural causation cannot be distinguished any longer, where the Kantian antinomy
between natural causation and subjective freedom does not apply. Whether finally nature
or culture “is” expressive, whether being “is” expressive, is simply the wrong place to
start. The much more subtle and vital question, for Deleuze, is under what conditions of
real experience experimentation makes possible more joy, love, and life than would be
otherwise available.
test of whether or not they actually play a role in the experiences which give rise to them.
5
The evaluation of knowledge in Deleuze is at one with its enacted performance. Despite
the revival, at least since the German Romantics, of interest in occult or hermetic forms
structuralist interest in gifts and potlatch, all the way up to Barthes and Baudrillard’s
far as Deleuze toward articulating the conditions under which truly transformative
Therefore the critiques of Deleuze recently levied by Alain Badiou and Slavoj
Zizek are most pressing, since they claim that Deleuze’s philosophy fails a practical test:
it does not recommend or inspire, these critics argue, the kind of changes that are most
necessary for life as we know it under the pressures of late capitalist ideology. It is by
connecting Deleuze’s vision with that of certain Renaissance thinkers, philosophers who
were investigating the possibility of a magical rapport between mind and its concerns,
that I propose his thought has its most genuinely creative connections with the problems
activity to give an account of the real conditions necessary for the ritual generation of
to explain Deleuze’s idea that the experience of certain forms of art transforms the world.
Deleuze insists that certain forms of art (which are allied with certain forms of
philosophy and science) render the true (if hidden) dynamics of the world. In a way,
Deleuze’s philosophy could be called occult, but only in the true sense of this word,
which means not obscure but hidden.2 It is not a matter of intuiting the invisible (as it
6
might have been for, say a thinker like Merleau-Ponty), but of seeing the visibility of the
have denied the kind of “intuition” of the “nature” of things that Deleuze seems to be
about his “vitalism,” his claim to speak in the name of life (even if that life is understood
observable mechanisms and behaviors). The bold claim of Deleuze’s philosophy is that
life is artful, and that only when we begin to understand the structure of art do we
available only under the conditions of experimentation. The vital truth of life is found
only when certain regimes of signs are invented. As Vico might have put it, the true is
the made. Or as Deleuze himself puts it, there is an intellectual path beyond the contrast
of reflective insight and active enactment. As he puts it early on in his career, “it’s
possible that the actual idea of interpretation goes beyond the dialectical opposition
between ‘knowing’ and ‘transforming’ the world” (DI 129). In what follows I show how
it is to art that Deleuze looks for the model of a form of interpretation which would be at
Creative Encounters
multiplicities (and not as a set of static objectivities), Deleuze sees in the generative and
7
transformative power of certain art forms not only the origin of artistic experience, but of
painting, and music especially) give us a true sense of how worlds are constituted, but
again, this is not a truth available to “common sense,” which is always interested in
clarifying that which is productive as indiscernible, that which is at the porous borders of
a multiplicity, a becoming. To see these borders and limits, to see lines which are neither
contours nor outlines, but vectors, forces, and machines requires the intuition of an
anorganic and “intensive” process of creation that is tertiary to both “nature” and
“culture.”
Deleuze’s project is realist in the sense that he affirms that through certain
practices mind has actual contact with the genetic and constitutive processes of being.
Such a realism, however, is not one that comes by way of a reflection upon what is
being forced to think, the most authentic result of which is a great work of art (although
experimental science also has its own version of this Acteon’s quest where, like Acteon
What Deleuze thinks we invent in genuine concepts are uncanny, paradoxical, and
complicated parameters of the real. But again, rather than simply asserting a new dogma
of complicatio, asserting that the world of co-existent contraries is the new foundation of
judgment, what Deleuze’s concepts embody is not the identity but the difference
complication makes, and the creative process under which complication is encountered.
What are the intense conditions under which we contact the genetic features of life?
What can force us to think, beyond our habits, our memories, and our stupidities, which
8
have been so often enshrined in philosophical concepts? For Deleuze, these two
questions, one addressing the real conditions of genesis and one addressing the genesis of
For Deleuze, the philosopher, like the artist or the scientist, must first be moved
into an extraordinary perspective in order to begin to think. But this perspective is not
something one can take up and put down at will. Perspective for Deleuze is a
monadological vector into which we become absorbed. This vector is measured not
present moments, but instants shorter than countable time and longer than thinkable time.
In the same way that art enables us to see things we would not otherwise see,
Deleuze thinks that artists are constrained to create, they are forced to create because of a
traumatic encounter they have with the world. Again, paradoxically, the encounter that
provokes art is not the encounter with the world of medium-sized physical objects, the
world of habits, memories, and egos. The world of thought is replete with the primordial
elements from which the common or public world is made. Genuine thought always
involves an encounter with a reality that remains problematic with respect to all the ways
in which we have “solved” the problems life poses, through the establishment of routine,
the force of habit, the consolidation of memory, through the repression of guilt, and the
For Deleuze, creating a world and knowing a world occur in the same fell swoop.
There is always this double implication of epistemology and ontology, a discursive action
that bespeaks both what there is and how we know what there is at the same time. This is
9
the paradox of expressivism in philosophy, that the concepts generated in philosophy do
not reflect on objects or problems that pre-exist those concepts. The primary goal is not
to solve problems but to discover them; to discover new and more interesting and more
engaging problems than we thought before existed. That Deleuze sees this as an
“immanent” process while Vico and others before (and since) him relate creativity to a
certain transcendence may not be the crucial difference. The crucial difference may be
between those who would have us bound to a paradigm of knowing that proceeds via
cannons of recognizability which confirm the intuitions of common sense, and those who
are prepared, and indeed are seeking, the transformation of that very sense deemed
Challenging Immanence
and epistemological treatise is entitled Ethics. That is because on this view politics, as
great societies would have to be measured in the way we measure art. Does this society
enlarge our perspective? Does it give us an entrée to a health and a humor we have not
yet experienced beyond our melancholy decadence and tragic negativity? Or does it
This is what I take to be the situation in which most readers are right now
of Slavoj Zizek and Alain Badiou. Deleuze’s thought is being questioned in the name of
10
theology, and ethics. The gambit of the new universalists is to re-invent and re-marshal
community in a continuing and total, globalized war of all against all (what Baudrillard
has recently called “the fourth world war”). In other words, the new universalists are
suspicious that the immanent consolidation of difference in any given group or locality
constitutes a gain (or is realized) only for the hidden but dominating project of an abstract
totality that remains unperturbed. Usually this totality is labeled “global capitalism” but
reject any ontological scheme which figures life as an unregulated flow of immanent
differences (in powers, potentials, affectivity, etc.) and figures human groups as more or
favor of thinking difference as either a kind of undead substratum of the real (Zizek’s
affects, achronological temporality, and intensive spaces the true objects of thought plays
directly into the hands of today’s microfascisms of global domination by the powers of
international technocracy, since those powers more and more manipulate us on this level.
What we need to do, the universalists insist, is reclaim the “indivisible remainder” of the
11
mathematically singular, undead, or resurrected life, a life that persists by cutting into or
subtracting from or transcending the flow of affective life in the name of a greater if more
pragmatic approach to problems is the way to go, since the technocratic capitalists
investing the lives of our desire are nothing if not great pragmatists. What I will argue
here, however, is that Deleuze’s ability to identify the nature of microfascism (the
mechanisms by which we come to desire our own enslavement to the Other) is at one
with a powerful way of articulating how to combat fascism: we can combat it on its own
terms. This is what artists do: the proximity of artistry to fascism that the universalists
seem to think calls for a retreat is for Deleuze the only means of advance.4
Deleuze (and his co-author Felix Guattari) were sometimes suspected of asking us
to simply embrace chaos or social disorder—a world of “no more limits”—as if somehow
the “nomadic” formations of biker gangs, hippie communes, neo-pagan religions, and
other “minor” formations that were taking shape in the 1960’s and 70’s were somehow
the telos or goal of this kind of thinking. Even though Deleuze and Guattari wanted to
encourage experimental forms of social life, what their thinking means to achieve is not
beginning that thought can assist in generating. It will have different effects in different
times and places relative to the different ossifications with which life is faced.
artistic, perhaps even magical5) other than those that are conceived by the “givens” of a
transcendental schema of space, time, and the categories or the “givens” of a primordial
12
life-world/urdoxa that would give a natural semiosis or pre-abstractive grammar of
meaning. This is partly why those familiar with the thinkers from which Deleuze should
and Badiou—continually fall against the rock of Deleuze’s “vitalism.” The general
The reason this critique ultimately fails, I argue, is because philosophy is not a
purely descriptive science, for Deleuze. It is not an act of reflection, but of institution.
Deleuze’s concepts do not describe things as they are, or as they should be, but as they
can be under certain conditions. His concepts therefore attempt to be real definitions of
things and activities that are actually there for us only under certain (virtual) conditions:
the conditions of intensity and singularity that only multiplicities (and not
intensive set of forces and not on an organized, extensive set of properties and attributes.
Without Organs,” a region or regime of affects and flows of information that would be
open or “deterritorialize,” opening their flows of energy and elements onto a “line of
connects the parts of one assemblage with the parts of other assemblages in ways that
13
“deterritorialization.” There are different techniques or “plan(e)s” for adjusting or re-
of these techniques are more dangerous than others, some are more healthy than others.
But for Deleuze the techniques themselves cannot be judged other than in terms of
This is why Deleuze’s ambition for philosophy was that it become “haptic”—that
it pass beyond the distinction between reflective concepts and reflected objects in the way
that Francis Bacon’s paintings contain diagrams that take painting beyond the distinction
between the optic and the manual, the hand and the eye. Bacon began all of his paintings
with an aleatory or chaotic splash or trait around which he then forced or constrained
himself to paint. This mark, chaotic and yet not random, when incorporated (if not
“incarnated”) in the painting as a whole then becomes a diagram for what can appear in a
nothing to do with the “factual accuracy” or verisimilitude of a painting nor with the
“formal fact” of an abstraction. It is rather a new kind of empirical regime not of given
but of “brute” fact—the fact of what this color and these lines were compelled to do
given the imposition of a starting point that comes to the painting from beyond or before
the conscious will. Here not a given representation of the world but an assembled Figure
emerges. This figure is neither illustrative nor abstract, but an autonomous living form
14
that would not have been there in any other way, under any other conditions. Deleuze
For the diagram was only a possibility of fact, whereas the painting exists
by making present a very particular fact, which we will call the pictorial
fact . . .what we will call a “fact” is first of all the fact that several forms
may be included in one and the same Figure, indissolubly, caught up in a
kind of serpentine, like so many necessary accidents continually mounting
on top of one another . . . But the fact itself, this pictorial fact that has
come from the hand, is the formation of a third eye, a haptic eye, a haptic
vision of the eye, this new clarity. It is as if the duality of the tactile and
the optical were surpassed visually in this haptic function born of the
diagram. (FB 128-129)
Just as the diagram (the trait) is not the “fact” Bacon paints, but what allows him
to paint a pictorial fact, the “creation” of a philosophical concept is not an end in itself.
Its creativity is the end, or rather the beginning, of its adventure. This “third eye” or
diagram, hovering between the object of thought and the clichés of our categories,
emerges between the chaos we entertain and the constraints selecting that chaos itself.
Certain film makers make us experience this world other than as we normally do and yet
as Deleuze puts it, their aim is not to help us escape but to once again believe in this
world.
In some cases film makers can even restore our faith in this world, or rather in the
elements, however fragmented, from which new worlds can be made of this one. That is
the peculiar “magic” of cinema, a magic to which Deleuze’s concepts also aspire: not the
ability to present what is not there (the power is not that of illusion), but the power to
present the elements that make appearances singular. This is what the early Deleuze
meant by a “dramatization” of ideas: every idea as a little play, a little drama, a little
mask, a little proportion or degree whose dimensions and sufficient reasons can be found
only in the experiment which they provoke. To have done with judgment, and to begin
15
again with life, is the power of art that so seduced Deleuze. For Deleuze, these powers
It is these three powers that we will investigate in this thesis, “Gilles Deleuze and the
Powers of Art.”
16
I. Critique as Creation: The Contours of Transcendental Empiricism
original, forces a new kind of modern thought. Insofar as modernity has attempted to
rigorously distinguish reality from illusion, it has constantly searched for either empirical
This quest for secure foundations is interrupted, for Deleuze, by the presence of
simulacra which defy all subordination to notions of original and derivative, figure and
Because certain modern art forms deal extensively in simulacra, and compose
new worlds from them, these experimental forms and the knowledge they embody model
for philosophy a new method: not the deduction of the real from the possible, but the
encounter with the singular in its extraordinary genesis. In response to such encounters,
philosophy for Deleuze should seek to construct a multiplicity of concepts that attest to
the inherently multiple dynamics of experience. These dynamics are not in any sense
pre-given in a priori categories, but emerge at the limits of sensation, memory, and
Constructivism’s concepts however, are no mere products of taste or effects of will, but
are rather creations in some sense forced by the extraordinary events that befall us.
17
In the Clinic of Simulacra
intervention in a particular context. Its hallmark is the interruption of the same, the
common, and the ordinary in the name of the different, the novel, and the vital. Yet true
critique, for Deleuze, results not merely in a set of qualifications or negations, but in a
By “cult” Deleuze means something like a passion or a mandate for joy, for life. A will
not so much “to power” but for the power of life in the face of mortifications, in the face
And what life does Deleuze have in mind here—is it natural life, psychological life, or
spiritual life? And what could it possibly mean to criticize, or even to destroy, by
making an affirmation?
the world that is not what the world has made it seem to be.9 What is affirmed in life is
always something in the times that resists the times, what Nietzsche called the untimely.10
The subject of affirmation is not, for all that, something which “transcends” the times. It
is something that cannot exist without the times but that does not properly belong to it.
18
Critical affirmation is the process of discovering this untimely or uncanny dimension.
What critical affirmation finds in life is not another world, but a singular difference in and
of this world. To philosophize, for Deleuze, is to find the strange in the familiar, the
medicinal paradigms. We are all too familiar with our symptoms—our pettiness, our
greed, our shortsighted ambitions, our weak lusts, our cancers, our rotting joints, our
depend on them for cures. The cure consists in knowing how to interact with whatever is
causing the symptom, how to affect the pathology, the disorder, the disease. In any
etiology that matters, what a disease is, is defined by how it can be cured. In this way, as
Deleuze puts it, the doctor is a “legislator”: in giving the rules for healing a disease, she
determines the nature of the disease and the nature of that which it affects. Doctors search
For Deleuze, as for Nietzsche and Spinoza before him, knowing the essence of the
world is knowing, event by event, mode by mode, case by case, the symptoms of how the
world is doing.12 The twist for Deleuze, however, is that in his view what we know, as
we interpret the signs and symptoms of life, is always immediately transformed by that
act of knowing. Insofar as philosophy takes this route, it cannot be systematic or even
axiomatic, but must be aphoristic, poetic, and creative. As he puts it in one of his last
19
of interpreting and what must be interpreted; poetry, both the art of
evaluating and what must be evaluated. The interpreter is the physiologist
or doctor, the one who sees phenomena as symptoms and speaks through
aphorisms. The evaluator is the artist who considers and creates
“perspectives” and speaks through poetry. The philosopher of the future is
both artist and doctor—in one word, legislator. (PI 66)
This brings us to the other aspect of critique, and in fact the more important one
for distinguishing Deleuze from his precursors and contemporaries: the role of art.
Deleuze sees the ability to select and affirm as something great artists do best. Deleuze
reiterates throughout his oeuvre that philosophy must be connected to art, and must even
take art’s affirmation-structure as thought’s primary model and mode. Art’s key
structural feature, for Deleuze, is that it relates to the world not as if it were something
unified, pre-given, stable, and coherent in and of itself, but as if its essence inhered in a
series of signs that beyond clichéd or formulaic coherence, can extract sthe singular from
the clichéd, the different from the same, the extraordinary from our fixations on
This power of art is exemplified, for Deleuze, in the literature of Joyce, Proust,
Melville, and Kafka, in the painting of Warhol, Bacon, and Klee, in the theatre of Artaud,
the music of Stockhausen, and in the cinema of the Italian Neo-Realists and French New
Wave.14 In the work of these creators and in many other artists, as well, Deleuze finds
combining, and resonating despite the fact that these affective events are seemingly
unrelated or even opposed to one another, from the point of view of common sense. In
art, for Deleuze, the disparate becomes strangely unified or uncannily resonant, despite,
through “forcing” resonances between times and places and affective states, the artist
20
gives us a sense of the world that defies the categories in terms of which we generally
The artist transcends the givens of experience, but not through knowledge of the
experience not as the final but as only the initial conditions of an experiment, an
invention, a re-creation of those conditions. Deleuze contrasts this sense of the world
deriving from art with that sense which derives from politics. He writes,
In very general terms, we claim that there are two ways to appeal to
“necessary destructions:” that of the poet, who speaks in the name of a
creative power, capable of overturning all orders and representations in
order to affirm Difference in the state of permanent revolution which
characterizes eternal return; and that of the politician, who is above all
concerned to deny that which “differs,” so as to conserve or prolong an
established historical order, or to establish a historical order which already
calls forth in the world the forms of its representation. The two may
coincide in particularly agitated moments, but they are never the same.
(DR 53)
Both the poet and the politician know the necessity of destroying what is in the name of
what may be. But the politician does this in the name of what has already been, and what
can be predicted to be, based on the representable form of what has already been. The
artist, on the other hand, creates not a representation of what may be, but a simulacrum of
not a copy of a model, but a copy of a copy. It is a repetition, but not of an object or
paradigm, but of an image of that object or paradigm. What is crucial for Deleuze are the
simulacra has for its condition the breakdown of “major” or “recognizable” identities.
21
simulacra disrupts our categories of model and copy, truth and consequence, event and
effect.
Simulacra do this because they appear at places where at least two series of
identities and generalities (constituted by our memories, habits, and official histories)
blur into or open onto one another. Where at least two distinct orders enter into an
point to the real conditions of experience, conditions which are ordinarily occluded by
our sense of what is possible, a sense which derives from those habitual regularities
simulacra disrupt.
In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze defines the power of the simulacral in this
way:
originary, what is derived; what is cause, what is effect; what is deeply meaningful and
what is merely superficial ornament. But for Deleuze simulacra do this not merely in the
name of the destruction of represented identity, but in the name of re-creating the actual
22
For Deleuze this was the achievement of Pop Art, and of Andy Warhol, whose
serial works extract singularities from our habits of consumption and destruction (DR
294). What Warhol’s art achieves cannot be described in terms of representation. His art
breaks down our illusion that images—even the most stereotyped images—represent
things, rather than repeat things. If images represent things, then art imitates the world,
and the truth of art becomes subject to evaluation in terms of how well it imitates what is
already in the world.15 Bur for Deleuze, we do not depend on art to reveal to us what is
already there, but to extract a singularity, a difference, a simulacrum from the intersecting
By generating simulacra, art illuminates the times. Art does this not by
transcending the appearances, but by undermining our illusions about the origin and
meaning of “the way the world is.” This is what Francis Bacon called “putting some
Sahara” into the clichés of painting, inserting a desert space into habits of sensation
across which a nearly-imperceptible force can flash. By repeating stereotyped images (of
Marilyn, Mao and Christ, car wrecks, riots and pistols), Warhol’s work forces us to look
beyond what is figured toward percepts visible only through the decentering of the
This is how Deleuze describes art’s power, at the conclusion of Difference and
. . . does not imitate, above all because it repeats; it repeats all the
repetitions, by virtue of an internal power (an imitation is a copy, but art is
simulation, it reverses copies into simulacra). Even the most mechanical,
the most banal, the most habitual and the most stereotyped repetition finds
a place in the work of art, it is always displaced in relation to other
repetitions, and it is subject to the condition that a difference may be
extracted from it for these other repetitions. For there is no other aesthetic
problem than that of the insertion of art into everyday life. The more our
23
daily life appears standardized, stereotyped, and subject to an accelerated
reproduction of objects of consumption, the more art must be injected into
it in order to extract from it that little difference which plays
simultaneously between other levels of repetition, and even in order to
make the two extremes resonate—namely the habitual series of
consumption and the instinctual series of destruction and death . . . [art]
aesthetically reproduces the illusions and mystifications which make up
the real essence of this civilization. (DR 293)
As Deleuze conceives it, somewhat as a doctor or a shaman sees the body exhibiting
of joy—the artist sees the world in terms of symptoms, as well. This is how Warhol saw
advertisements, or as the French New Wave or Orson Welles saw the clichés of
Hollywood. But Warhol never rejects graphic design principles any more than Welles or
Goddard rejects the formulas of cinema. Art stays with, refashions, deals with the
symptoms—the illusions and mystifications—which give rise to art itself. This paradox
means that in creating, the artist is also analyzing. The studio is also a clinic. In an early
At the same time that the artist puts the world in the clinic, she puts herself there,
as well. This is why Deleuze claims that artistic style sometimes precipitates and
sometimes transforms the symptoms (DI 140). The artist’s own life is always at stake in
the world she is creating. We might say that for Deleuze, art is an attempt to read the
world’s vital signs. The greatest artists take the whole world as a symptom of life’s
24
creative effort. “Shakespeare’s characters say, ‘how goes it with the world?’,” Deleuze
writes in that same early essay (DI 140). In a Deleuzian aesthetics, Iago, Hamlet, Lear,
and Lady Macbeth are more than mere characters. They are vectors of energy. They
display the possible flows or what he later calls “lines of flight” (lignes de fuite, flow-
But the idea that art is an attempt to “understand” the world is somewhat
problematic, since this formula presumes precisely what Deleuze insists art does not: that
there is some pre-given truth or unity art stands underneath or supports—some truth
existing in the structure of our own minds if not in an absolute Mind, in terms of which
the world should be understood, to which it should be adequated, and by which it should
be measured.17 For Deleuze, what art teaches is that the essences constituting the world
whose signs we read and whose symptoms we trace are not available apart from the space
might have put it, the true is always already the made.19
The Birth of Tragedy, the tragic vision of life has often been theorized as the source of art
itself, since it reflects the inherent limits of the cosmic and social order. But for Deleuze
even the vision of a tragic world is, as a creation, a joyful affirmation. As he puts it in an
early interview, “there can be no tragic work because there is a necessary joy in creation;
art is necessarily a liberation that explodes everything, first and foremost the tragic. No,
there is no unhappy creation, it is always a vis comica” (DI 134).20 For Deleuze art offers
through its vis comica, a way to health—to that “great health” of which Nietzsche often
25
dreamt. This health does not ask us (or the world, or the earth, or our bodies) to conform
Thus the artist, for Deleuze as for Nietzsche, does not treat symptoms in terms of a given
totality or whole or world (such as “the body”) of which those symptoms would be partial
manifestations, but takes symptoms as indicating the presence of worlds unto themselves.
The worlds espied in artistic creation are, for Deleuze, like Leibniz’s monads:
ontological atoms around which subjects and objects form, and through which pass the
predicates or “manners” of various events.22 Monads are not fully formed subjects,
persons, or identities, but singular points around which identities coalesce. For Leibniz,
the best possible world, the one God created, is a world that pre-exists its expression in
monads and was selected by God for its maximal harmony or “compossibility” with itself
(DR 47-48).
As with Leibniz’ monads, the worlds of modern art, for Deleuze, are expressed in
simultaneously). The monads of modern art, however, are not subject to any prior
puts it in his late work on Leibniz, for Deleuze the singularities of the modern world must
26
multivalent and polysemic logics, logics not of substance and accident, but of events and
of the sense of various worlds that converge and diverge through those events, in a world
Later in his career Deleuze will call these worlds “assemblages.” As Deleuze
other configurations (ATP 503). Creating an assemblage thus always involves a de-
(neither given unities nor derived diversities) assemblages by definition express old
content in new forms, or new content in anachronistic forms. Assemblages mix and
combine parameters from other assemblages in order to put themselves into unforeseen
machines” that form along the border between the weapons of state powers and the
desires of nomadic people exemplify the notion of assemblage (ATP 351). Experimental
music is an assemblage at the limit between noise and traditional forms of composition.24
Francis Bacon’s paintings, for Deleuze, create figures that cannot be explained in terms
of figuration or narrative, but are nevertheless “diagrams” that capture chaos at the same
time that they allow chaos to invade painting and transform it.25
they often appear as “nonsense” relative to the “sense” of the milieus or systems of
significance with which they make their break or within which they find their “line of
flight” (ligne de fuite).26 Joyce’s Finnegan’s Wake and Lewis Carroll’s Alice
stories—with their words that each contain a world of sense despite their surface
27
nonsense—are two of Deleuze’s prime literary examples. Part of what Deleuze admires
in these literary art forms (and their parallels in cinema, theatre, music, and painting) is
that they “permit several stories to be told at once” (LS 260). The assemblage (of words,
elements from one another, a distance between elements that an artistic style both
measures and redoubles in its style. Style establishes an occult form of communication
between otherwise “incompossible” sets of affects and events. The nomadic world
implied by the coexistence or “alogical compatibility” of different series sets a major new
The kind of art that tells several stories at once matters so much for Deleuze
because for him, as for Giordano Bruno before him, there truly is no world apart from a
category can pre-determine, and no act of recollection can adequately grasp the uncanny
character of a singular event. The world of artistic creation, however, does capture the
sense of events. It is able to do so, however, because the world of an artistic style is
neither transcendentally given nor ideally recalled, but discovered through an actively
affirmed multiplicity. Art brings together strings or chains of singularities, but as these
28
series are constructed in art, singular differences are not synthesized but are rather further
power—its power to find life where we least expect it.28 What art shows is that, rather
than as mediated in “infinite concepts” of experience, the sense lurking in events must be
understood in terms of a field larger than any a priori condition can encompass, and pass
in the blink of an eye, in a time smaller than that in which consciousness can react. The
logic of reality is at one with the eventful emergence of new relations. Philosophy must
model itself on art because knowledge of these relations cannot be derived from a
pregiven whole or a gradual recollection of parts for the sake of a whole to come, but is
Beyond Representation
This is where Deleuze’s idea that art can be paradigmatic for philosophy must be
made clear, because it might seem as if Deleuze invites philosophy to follow art into a
world of delirious illusion.29 For Deleuze the forced resonances or “special effects” of
modern art—nonsense, the absurd, the surreal, pop pastiche, montage, and so on—only
appear as illusory and insubstantial when they are judged in terms of the common sense
aesthetics since Kant. Since Kant, Deleuze argues, aesthetics has suffered from a
29
“wrenching duality” in which the theory of sensation is divorced from the theory of
The problem, however, is that art does not appear to modern aesthetics (or philosophy) as
notes, Heidegger believed that art met its death at the hands of modern aesthetics, and
had to retreat from sensation in order to rediscover its authenticity.30 For Deleuze, this
same result is the Kantian tradition of aesthetics. In this tradition, which has dominated
the field, the possibilities of art have been thought to be pre-determined by what
“objectivities” can be represented in the sensible. In other words, the responses elicited
by art must refer to a real (i.e. possible) object of experience, in the Kantian sense of
possibility conforming to a priori categories of what can count as phenomenal (and not as
mere illusion).
This Kantian sense of possibility is the basis for the category of taste—a sensus
communis of the appropriate, the fitting, the pleasing form. Even the sublime, in Kant, is
still defined as the limit of representational possibility. As Deleuze candidly points out,
however, the alternative to Kant’s aesthetics does not seem all that promising. If we
reject the criteria of what is representationally possible for sensations to become in art,
30
For Deleuze, however, if Kant managed to salvage the objectivity of knowledge
by making the conditions of the objects of possible experience the same as the conditions
of possible experience, he did so at the cost of denying to mind access to the genesis of
the forms of experience, per se.32 For Kant the forms or categories hold because they
cannot be denied without contradiction. But for Deleuze, certain modern art forms have
an intuition not of logically possible experience, but of the limits of possible experience,
as such, which is simultaneously the limit of our collective sense of what is pleasing,
appropriate, or beautiful.
Experimental art, for Deleuze, collapses the two sides of the duality between the
theory of sensation and the theory of form. Under conditions of experimentation, such as
those outlined above in certain modern art forms, we apprehend directly in the sensible
what “can only be sensed, the very being of the sensible” (DR 57). As an experiment at
the limits of the sensible, art no longer passively reflects but rather actively reveals the
structure and limits of the sensible, per se. Art is therefore an exercise in empiricism,
with the added twist that what art “knows” is not a clear and distinct idea corresponding
to the limits of quantities and qualities, but rather a paradoxically distinct and yet obscure
idea of the real intensities manifest at the limit of quantities and qualities and relations.
Transcendental Empiricism
the irreducible differences that form the real limits of the representable world. Because
31
representational categories—the same, the identical, the analogous, the similar—present
difference in terms of sameness, for Deleuze representational thought and art cannot
capture the dynamics of a difference insubordinate to any concept. However, there are
certain art forms, those Deleuze usually calls “modern,” that are capable of putting into
relations are external to their terms. What does it mean to say that artists are
philosophically: discrete perceptions do not carry the rules of how those perceptions can
be associated. The principles of association are not derived from things, but from the
mind. 34 The principles of association do not constitute perceptions; rather they constitute
the human mind. It is the human mind that has the “univocal” and “constitutive” role,
and it is the mind that is constantly invented by the ever-renewed possibility of new
However, the sense that mind donates is never unified in a majestic self or
fragmented and partial. “Mind” is, as it were, only a vector of the set of relations in
which it partakes.35 For Deleuze this fragmented (as opposed to transcendentally unified)
32
character of mind is, if the limit, also the condition of real experimentation with relations
(as opposed to the conditions of possible experience of future objects). Relations are not
things.36 As John Rajchman explains it, for Deleuze we have an intuition of this in
certain forms of intense experience, experience of intensive spaces that cannot be defined
by extrinsic parameters (distances or other metric properties). Rajchman put is this way
merely empirical coordinates of space and time, but the transcendentally empirical forms
of intensive space, a space populated not be quantifiable distances but by singular points
“transcendental” to the extent that it is neither merely the possibilities of our bodies nor
This intensive world of singularities is broached not only in modern art but in
contrariety.” Here, the significance of sense impressions cannot be clarified on the basis
33
of sensibility alone.38 Contact is made with a presence that, while existing only in the
sensible, is not composed of any sensible quality, and is rather that intensive or singular
point that in any case organizes or deploys sensation, as such. Deleuze describes it in the
event (a Form) is invoked as being that in terms of which identity and difference can be
established, that on the basis of which qualitative contrariety can be explained. For
Deleuze, however, art demonstrates a form of recollection which one-ups Plato. While
ascertaining a singular form, art remains within time and contingency rather than
The paradox is that while remaining with contingency, art does not make its
knowledge arbitrary for making it constructed. The knowledge proper to art is thus a
kind of baroque “produced eternity.” However, the vaunted “eternal value” of art is an
intuition of the ways in which temporally dynamic and historically-emergent forces can
34
knowledge is therefore never an induction nor a deduction or the real, but a kind of
“abductive” genealogy which produces intuitions specific to the passion giving rise to
What is made visible in modern art, as Foucault might have put it, are the
and what is rendered visible, between condition and conditioned, between the intensive
and the merely qualitative, that forms the basis of modern art’s knowledge or illumination
of “possibility in the aesthetic sense.”41 The techniques of modern art extract the
singularities or differences which order (without resembling) affects and sensations. The
key point, here, is that modern art does not merely experiment with color and sound, but
with the categories and forms of habitual experience. The peculiar “thinking” done by a
film auteur or a literary author takes place at a level of pre-individual singularities and
impersonal affects. At this level, alone, for Deleuze, does empiricism—the science of
This brings me to a culminating formula for how I will read Deleuze in what follows:
task for philosophy is not to reflect on but to join with the rigorous experimentation,
which is also a rigorous enquiry in Hume’s sense, that is already taking place in art.
35
The paradox for philosophy, and why the aesthetic paradigm needs so much
justification, is that art knows something that cannot be explained apart from art, whereas
in some sense philosophy abstracts from and “logicizes” what art presents.42 Should
In what follows I will try to argue that the answer to this is yes, but it is necessary
to see the creative character of philosophical intervention, and the educational function of
art. For Deleuze, if philosophy intervenes in knowledge for the sake of genuine learning,
art intervenes in experience for the sake of that same learning. Art and philosophy are
not the same activity; one discipline produces affects, the other concepts. But insofar as
both disciplines invite us into transformative possibilities that are available only under the
sing in concepts. This paradigm does not reduce philosophy to stylism or textuality any
more than it would reduce art to didacticism. Rather, under this aegis both art and
philosophy (and in some cases scientific practice) are endless attempts to create in
response to the extraordinary events that befall us. In this, Deleuze writes, consists the
whole of an intellectual ethics: “not to be unworthy of what happens to us” (LS 149).
For Deleuze, the events of our lives come from a place the composer Samuel
Butler called “EREWHON,” everywhere and nowhere, “the nowhere of origins, and
‘now-here,’ the here and now turned upside down, displaced, disguised “ (DI 141). To
say that philosophy as much as art works in EREWHON is to say that philosophers are
36
categorically, memorially or even “intersubjectively communicate”44 such coherence (DR
7)45. Philosophy, for Deleuze, has to begin from a place of great interruptions. It must
think or “counter-actualize” the sense of great events—but not necessarily “big” events,
must be at the scene of life like a good detective, with the incisiveness of a Sherlock’s
eye. As Deleuze puts it in an interview “On Nietzsche and the Image of Thought,”
cruel in Artaud’s vision was not something mean or vicious, but was rather the way in
which cries, groans, props, masks, disguises, and even nonsense words continually
interrupted the expectations of the theatre goers. Artaud wanted a theatre that presented
not forms but fires through which spectator and actor alike could see signals of a life yet
to come.46 A “cruel” or experimental thought does not attempt to develop concepts that
would gather or enclose experience. Nor does genuine philosophy, for Deleuze, posit a
ground of sufficient reason or deduce a transcendental schema from which the conditions
of possible experience can be derived. Rather, for Deleuze, genuine thought creates
reflection nor communication (WIP 6). As he puts it, in his late work What is
37
Philosophy, “anyone (a scientist, an artist, a laborer) can reflect on what he or she
already does—it is a bad joke to call them philosophers when they do so” (WIP 17).47
Philosophy?,
What does this mean? First, it means that concept creation is not a species of relativism.
For Deleuze, not just any concept can adequate the differential forces acting on our lives,
and the perspectives into which we are drawn by those forces cannot be described ad hoc.
We cannot “pick and choose” out concepts. Deleuze’s notion of conceptual creation is in
fact a strange kind of realism,48 insofar as Deleuze seeks to analyze concepts in terms of
the singular events (i.e. the experiences, but not necessarily “human” experiences) that
call “territories” in another text) that cannot be mapped extensively, but are rather
traversed intensively. It is these intensive spaces which our most interesting concepts
Much ado has been made of Deleuze’s notion of creating concepts, and many
have accused him of a casual pragmatism and bland relativism—all Deleuze really
advocates, the critics say, is a set of advertising slogans for whatever has power over our
confused desires.50 The way to avoid this critique is to place the accent in the phrase
38
“creation of concepts” on creation, not simply on proliferation.51 What matters most to
Deleuze in thought is the response we make to a singularity which is itself the condition
of authentic creation. Singularities are never mere particularities. They are in fact the
which universals have been usually conceived. Universals, for Deleuze, are not self-
identical ipseities, but singularities which continually disguise themselves. The singular
is not an identity but a differential force that must be followed, tracked, and traced.
Proximity to a singularity is what creates a concept, and because we must keep recreating
concepts in response to the movement of the singular, the intense, the different, concept
Philosophy?,
pragmatism of a “commercial professional training,” which would attribute the merit of,
which consumers can recognize what they (already think they) want. It would also be
distinct from the post-Kantian idea that concepts are functions of the ongoing effort of
39
Concept creation is neither the sheerly mundane pragmatics of telling stories
about what works (or what sells), nor the lofty attempt to include, collect, or synthesize
(even transcendentally) the varieties of experience. Rather, for Deleuze all concepts
worthy of the name are forced creations that bear witness to certain events, struggles,
moments are always those which resist integration into a system of smooth exchange
(cultural or natural), and indeed into any system of speculative synthesis.53 We think, as
he puts it in his early work on Proust, only when we are forced to think.54
encounters that force us to think are “necessary conditions,” not merely an instance of
sensing or remembering. They are events which call sensibility or thought into being.
Singular events provoke sensation while being imperceptible, forcing thought while
doctrine of the faculties on its head: objects of possible experience do not come to the
fore when the faculties operate properly. Rather, certain kinds of intense experience
force our faculties to operate in spite of themselves, in spite of their inertia, habit, or
common sense. Confronting the singular forces faculties to function in strange, nomadic,
even monstrous ways, but always in the name of a life beyond what we imagine.
differently formed and developed relative to the different intensities and fields that give
rise to them. 55 This is why Deleuze claims, following Bergson, that “the first principle
of philosophy is that Universals explain nothing but must themselves be explained” (WIP
7). Thought is never the set of competing explanations of the same event, but already a
40
different way of experiencing or “selectively affirming” what is singular and what is
ordinary about an event. The “explanatory power” of a concept consists not only of the
Although this may seem like a kind of relativism, Deleuze is a deeply realist philosopher,
since any plurality of concepts refers, for him, not to different languages or cultures or
human “practices” but to different powerful dynamics: to real if occult differential and
The ontological basis of thought, therefore, lies not in any conception of a representable
given, but in the forced selection of a “problematic element,” and an act of creativity that
Despite the fact that authentic natural science can also be an experience of being
forced to think, for Deleuze it is the work of great artists that most clearly attests to what
it is to be forced to think, and to create in response to the events of life.58 Put briefly, this
is because artists tend to work much more closely to chaos than do most scientists.59
41
Science, as Deleuze put is, is determined to establish the set of possible solutions to
predictable orders. The goal of science is not to produce paradox but to explain it.
Although there are certainly conceptions of scientific activity and scientific imagination
science does not claim the discovery of singularities (what Deleuze calls here
“intensional conditions”) as the result of its work. Philosophical concepts, on the other
hand, preserve the inherently problematic singularity of experience. Its achievements are
This is what makes the paradoxical objects of art a model for concepts. Proust’s
vortices around which bodies decompose, Warhol’s displaced Brillo Boxes, Joyce’s
nonsense words, the portmanteau words of Lewis Carroll—these uncanny things, these
excessive features, these smiles without cats harbor the unconscious fixations or “dark
precursors” that imperceptibly motivate events. Art renders visible or sonorous these
Modern art thus proceeds as if it were possible to find the actual genetic elements
42
soup can in an art gallery. Only then do we see that red on the label as red. Only then do
the elements constrained to advertise a product advertise, even for a moment, nothing but
themselves. It is procedures such as this one used by Warhol, as well as the creative
processes of film makers, composers, and painters that inspired Deleuze to call his own
43
II. Minding Art: Platonism Overturned
Because art involves the drive to make new worlds out of the events of our lives,
and not the drive to include the meaning of events in a total representation of the world,
art offers a model for philosophy different from that of science (at least as traditionally
conceived).60 Art models not a representation but a repetition of the singular elements
that array themselves at the borders of various worlds. This repetition is, for Deleuze,
what philosophy should emulate. Philosophy, if it would be authentic, should not attempt
to make a representation of the world. Rather, it must like art dramatically repeat those
elements in experience from which new worlds can be made. To put this in a “Platonic”
idiom, for Deleuze this is how we make contact with what is most real in the world, even
ambulatory affair.61 An enquiry. Because in some sense to follow this path this means to
delve into the chaos of the world, our minds naturally resist the risk it takes to go where
artists go, down the rabbit hole, through the looking glass, across the tracks, out to the
deep grey sea.62 And yet we must follow, argues Deleuze, unless we wish to remain
attached to the tragedy and melodrama of our habitual conscious limitations and a
profound stupidity [betisement] which, he will argue is more dangerous to thought than
44
The Image of Thought
In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze argues that there has been, throughout the
history of philosophy in the West, an implicit “Image of Thought” that secretly pre-
determines what can count as genuine philosophy. 63 At the center of this image is what
Deleuze calls the figure of a “good will to thought:” an implicit presumption that in any
genuine act of thought, it is the good which connects thought to truth. Deleuze defines
this “good” will as the will to perpetually re-establish identity, order, continuity, and
stability. Under the auspices of this Image, thinking consists in a will to order the mind
against madness or idiocy and to order the world, against natural or demonic chaos, at
any price. The Image of Thought and its presuppositions are all ultimately geared to
protect human identity, natural order, and divine provenance from the potential of
continuity, stability, and order—and the strange becomings to which they might attest.
Fixated on the categories of representation, the Image of Thought blinds the mind to the
actually composed.
45
The Image is centered on the figure of a cogitatio natura universalis that
Descartes supposed was given in humanity. For Deleuze, the persuasive force of
Descartes’ identification of thought with subjective being, cogito ergo sum, depends on
the implicit presupposition that it is in the nature of thought itself, in its innate being, to
seek the truth with a good nature and a good will. This good will exercises “common
sense,” the harmonious and spontaneous distribution of what is sensical and nonsensical.
The good will, Descartes presupposes, uses its “good sense” to eliminate the confusion or
error that arises when we misapply our powers—when we use our imagination where we
should use our memory, or where we use memory where we should use reason, or reason
where we should use our sensibility, and so on. To think with “good sense” is to
eliminate the errors that arise from the competition of faculties or from their confusion in
madness. However, Deleuze points out, the cogency of an idea of naturally donated
“good sense” depends not on an explicit philosophical formulation, but on the implicit
the “natural state” of our good sense, and once more within philosophy as the a set of
presuppositions about how essences are reasonably determined (DR 167). For Deleuze
the problem with this situation is that the postulates of good and common sense implicitly
and explicitly legislate that the object of thought be something inherently recognizable,
even if that object is no one particular empirical object but an “object in general” (so that
philosophical reasoning can render the invisible Soul, the impassible God, the totalized
World). For Deleuze, it is the Image of Thought which prevents philosophy from ever
truly breaking with opinion, with the doxa, insofar as philosophy continues to fashion its
46
“metaphysical” ideas of things in terms of ordinary objects. Even if the essence of things
always fashioned in the image of the (apparently) visible, such that the uncanny
difference and repetition at the heart of nature and culture is perpetually occluded.
Deleuze argues that even in the great “critical” philosophies of Kant and Hegel,
the Image of Thought still dominates, to the detriment of the breakthroughs these thinkers
might otherwise have made. To begin with the latter, Deleuze’s complaint against
Hegel64 is that because Hegel insists that only contradiction signifies a movement of the
Absolute (i.e., of thought) the “differences” from which we might potentially learn the
nature of Spirit in the Phenomenology are, in essence, too large. As Deleuze puts it,
remains the infinitely large of theology, of the Ens quo nihil majus” (DR 45). For Hegel,
since all sensible difference dissolves into indeterminate particularity (this red can only
be defined as not every other red), only a concept in its totality or “absolute” reality (the
sublation of all reds) has the infinite power of a distinctive difference. Whatever makes
Deleuze, however, the true level of difference, and the truth of differences, lies beneath
what can be determined as a contrariety; beneath a difference that can be thought. For
Deleuze, the perpetual crisis of the Understanding, in Hegel, with its constant experience
and differential forces of which “contradictions” are only an after-effect, the illusion of a
consciousness that still imposes a model of difference onto difference itself (in this case
47
Even though Kant defined his critique in terms of a search for true and false
skepticism to be refuted, for Deleuze Kant’s pedagogy is not a true adventure of mind.
“Kant still defines the truth of a problem in terms of the possibility of its finding a
each case by this or that organization of common sense (to which the problem
corresponds)” (DR 161). In other words, Kant’s critique only teaches us how to correctly
return to the objects of common sense, and the “transcendental turn” only abstracts from
actual objects to possible ones in order to guarantee the possibility of objects whose
The real “Copernican Revolution,” Deleuze thinks, would be to critique the faculties not
in terms of their accord in objects of possible experience, but in terms of how faculties
are generated by certain intense experiences. This would be a quest of thought for
encounters which break with the form of the problems posed by common sense or
“ordinary” empirical experience. We will son see what Deleuze means exactly by such
Beyond the postulates of the Image of Thought lies a great risk, a confrontation of
philosophy with allies other than those of good and common sense in the quest of truth.
48
Allies who at first appear, somewhat as the “allies” did to Carlos Castaneda in his quest
. . . find its difference or its true beginning, not in an agreement with the
pre-philosophical Image but in a rigorous struggle against this Image,
which it would denounce as non-philosophical. As a result, it would
discover its authentic repetition in a thought without Image, even at the
cost of the greatest destructions and demoralizations, and a philosophical
obstinacy with no ally but paradox, one which would have to renounce
both the form of representation and the element of common sense. (DR
132)
For authentic thought to begin, Deleuze argues, we must become demoralized with the
possibilities open to us through the forms of representation and common sense. We must
develop a taste for paradox, or for what paradox reveals without transparency. And yet
this obscurity is not going to be a lapse into a vague relativism and empty sophistry. If
certain art models authentic thought because such art breaks with representation and the
cannons of recognition and good and common sense which undergird it, for Deleuze this
is not simply in the name of irreality or irrationality. Rather, it is because the philosophy
he seeks to construct would attest as much as art does to a reality that is too complex for
the Image of Thought to handle, too small and too large to be represented or recognized.
Deleuze calls for the destruction of the image of thought in the name of a richer if more
49
The Theatre of Repetition
In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze argues that nature does not truly repeat
itself, at least not as “nature” is understood to be the subject of observational science and
the incarnation of physical laws (DR 3). What is constructed in a laboratory is merely a
situation which resembles nature in its “free” state, and the results of experiment
represent generalities about factors that are equivalent only from the point of view of
general laws. Not only do experiments leave out a number of variables in any given
situation, they select elements to which phenomena are in some sense reduced. As
Deleuze puts it, “experimentation is thus a matter of substituting one order of generality
wants to make it clear that the order science reproduces is not, strictly speaking, a
repetition. A bird in flight and a bee in flight, a diving whale and a diving penguin, the
camouflage of a spider and that of a chameleon—these flights, dives, and masks may
resemble one another, and there may be elements involved that are equivalent. But what
would it mean to say that two flights repeat one another, or that two dives, two maskings,
let alone two home runs, basketball shots, car races, murders, thefts, or performances of
50
For Deleuze it does not suffice to say that these events resemble one another (DR
1). To say that two things resemble one another, even to an extreme degree, is not to say
that they repeat. As long as we are considering particularities, we are thinking in terms
of a general law that governs what can be substituted or changed within the act while the
action or event or thing “remains the same.” In fact, what can be repeated in any case
would have to be something that passed below or above the particularities involved
(muscles articulated, neurons fired, time, place, weather conditions, etc.). The paradox
here is that for an event to repeat itself exactly, there has to be something absolutely
irreplaceable in it, and this would have to be something other than a particularity or set
something singular. As Deleuze puts it, “repetition as a conduct and a point of view
Deleuze arrives at this claim in the following way. Since laws generalize about
resemblances, and about which particularities can change for resemblances to continue to
count as equivalences, repetition is not a matter of resemblance, and it does not follow
laws. “If repetition is possible,” Deleuze writes, “it is due to miracle rather than to law”
(DR 2). What repeats, Deleuze insists, is always something singular, irreplaceable,
irreducibly different from other things. If the whale and the penguin repeat the same
dive, or even if the penguin repeats his own dive 1+n number of times, this is because,
paradoxically, there is something about diving that is irreplaceable, something that has no
equivalent.
This is why Kant was right, Deleuze notes, to insist that we look in vain to the
order of nature for that on which we might model the authentic repetition for which
51
moral life seems to call.67 Kant was right, Deleuze argues, to think that the moral law is
something that comes from beyond all phenomena (all contingency and particularity) to
demand something of us beyond our natural habits (DR 4). The limitation of Kant’s
view, for Deleuze, is that it does not offer the possibility of establishing moral habits as
an authentic form of repetition. This is because the habits of the Kantian Man of Duty
are a form of generality. Even though the Man of Duty legislates for himself, deciding
each time what is right to be done, he does this in situations which resemble one another
or through a law that reads situations as analogous to one another. In the end the moral
law ends up looking very much like generalities of natural science, because the perfection
of intention (the moral will) takes place as a subsumption of particulars to a general rule,
(even if that rule originates in the regulative ideals of pure practical reason).
For Deleuze, we cannot look to morality any more than to science for the rule of
genuine repetition (DR 5). Neither moral nor natural law can capture the haecceity (this-
ness) of repetition. Science and morality can see a repetition only as a form of
for Deleuze, we must discover an order that operates without generality, a coherence that
holds without resemblance, and this coherence must subsist beyond all recognition.
Where are such haecceities, such an order and coherence found? For Deleuze they are
found in art. “The repetition of a work of art is like a singularity without a concept,”
Deleuze writes (DR 1). We must look to art, Deleuze suggests, because it is art that does
what morality and science cannot: it repeats the unrepeatable, and never establishes a
52
If repetition exists, it expresses at once a singularity opposed to the
general, a universality opposed to the particular, a distinctive opposed to
the ordinary, an instantaneity opposed to variation, and an eternity
opposed to permanence. In every respect, repetition is a transgression. It
puts law into question, it denounces its nominal or general character in
favor of a more profound and more artistic reality. (DR 2-3)
What art expresses is something morality and science cannot. In fact art, for Deleuze, is
something of a transgression against the laws governing morality and science. And by
way of this transgression art indicates a coherence beyond generality, resemblance, and
recognition.
For Deleuze it was Kierkegaard and Nietzsche who, despite their profound
the true nature of things—a universe of singularities this believer and this atheist both
argued was, in some sense, supremely artful. Kierkegaard argued this by showing that
the principles of faith (the unpredictability of divine mandate) were beyond the
generalities of the moral law, and called for a “theological suspension of the ethical” in
the name of the singular and the “impossible” invasion of eternity into time. Nietzsche’s
nature, an “interior of the earth” (DR 6) which serves its own “perverse ends” no matter
how law-governed it seems to be. For Deleuze, Kierkegaardian irony and Nietzschean
humor both point to a “theatre of repetition” where, in a new and uncanny morality,
humanity attempts to become equal to the inhuman events that befall it, and to will
something in nature and create something in culture that is unrepeatable, even if this
creation is unbearably painful, powerful, or sublime. Deleuze opposes their work to that
writes,
53
The theatre of repetition is opposed to the theatre of representation, just as
movement is opposed to the concept and to representation which refers it
back to the concept. In the theatre of repetition, we experience pure
forces, dynamic lines in space which act without intermediary upon the
spirit, and link it directly with nature and history, with a language which
speaks before words, with gestures that develop before organized bodies,
with masks before faces, with specters and phantoms before
characters—the whole apparatus of repetition as a “terrible power.” (DR
10)68
Both Nietzsche and Kierkegaard bring forces into philosophy which pass above or below
conceptualization, populating their texts with animals, pseudonyms, fables and myths that
present, that which repeats is always disguised. As Deleuze puts it, “repetition is truly
that which disguises itself in constituting itself, that which constitutes itself only by
abstracted from the repetition in which it was formed, but in which it is also hidden ” (DR
17). What, then, is the true power of repetition? If repetition is not something we can
recognize in nature or espy in ourselves, in our habits or in our memories which seem to
come to us “over and over” or in the moral consistency we attempt to develop, where
To use an example Deleuze will use in his work on music, repetition is hidden as
phrases, the redundance of the cadence hides the singularity of the rhythmic character
which plays the cadence. This hidden or disguised singularity of accents or imperceptible
values. Rather than being that which identifies different cadences as “the same” these
54
values create inequalities or micrological incommensurabilities between different, if
The inequality between the beats is not something negative or missing from the
cadence. It is something supremely positive, if silent, which orients the sound. These
intensive values cannot be heard, but can only “be” as masked sound. What Deleuze
means when he argues that the “unequal is the most positive element” (DR 21) is that
and thus no groove or swing of the otherwise monotonous refrain, without a compulsive,
difference peculiar to that cadence: a set of “rhythmic events that are more profound than
Thus the repetition that interests Deleuze always takes place in tandem with and
the stage established by the power of differences in themselves (rather than divergences
from “the same. “ Philosophy, for Deleuze, has historically attempted to represent
and negation—categories that subordinate difference to divergence from the same or the
similar. Thus the true positivity of difference in itself is always missed. A real
difference, for Deleuze, is never something in opposition to something else (red not blue),
is not the negation of something by something else (not-just, not-man, not-God), and is
not something that can be understood by analogy (two things unlike in some respect but
divergence from what is the same, and miss difference in and of itself.
55
Difference-in-Itself
Despite the fact that he creates a concept of difference that is not mere otherness
therefore not what Deleuze is getting at by the phrase “difference in itself.”69 Deleuze
continuity within genera and even within being itself (DR 31). Socrates and Plato are
both rational animals. What makes this man Socrates and not Plato is something that can
be recognized but not defined. Difference does not have its own concept, but is said
Difference of species (within genera) are not defined by a difference of the genera
in itself (say “in” the genera of mammals), but by a difference contained within genera,
as the genera of mammals contains all its “different” species. Collected differences, as it
differences between species stand for the most important or most significant difference
(indefinable) ways, but a “middling” contrast silently governs the image of difference,
per se. Even the difference between genera (of say, mammals and reptiles) is thought in
terms of the sameness of the Being they share, ineffable as this “analogy” may be (DR
33).
56
For Deleuze, this ineffable sameness of being in analogy is the secret enemy of a
true concept of difference.70 Deleuze’s reason for this has less to do with the notion of
analogy per se than with how it manifests, under the auspices of the Image of Thought, a
drive to unify generic difference and specific difference in a single coherent, “organic,”
representable Whole of being. For Deleuze even Leibniz and Hegel, who each attempted
in his own way to introduce infinity into this representable Whole, do so by allowing a
particular difference (the microscopic differential, in Leibniz’ case, and the macrological
contradiction, in the case of Hegel) to stand in for difference in itself. Thus difference, as
this difference without being able to say what it is that individualizes this being. For
subjects or accidents to essences, always “retains in the particular only that which
conforms to the general (matter and form), and seeks the principle of individuation in this
or that element of the fully constituted individuals” (DR 38). The identity of the essence
think it did (since, as he says, we look to the “specific difference” for the form),
various existents, since that always predetermines difference and, ironically, identity.
57
By contrast, for Deleuze, if we conceive of Being not as analogically but as
The point here is that, for Deleuze, to truly think difference as individuating, as a power
representable relationships between genera and species, matter and form, potentiality and
things, a derivation from the same. But for Deleuze, difference is what individuates.
This is so because for Deleuze it is Being which is Difference, and this difference is said
differently (or equivocally) of each individual (DR 39). For Deleuze Being is not a
genera not because all the categories share in it, but because being is substantially
Difference, and each particular difference “is not” in a sense that has no contrary, that is
not a negation, but a paradoxically positive non-being (DR 39). Identity, for Deleuze, is
thus always simulacral, but never in the sense that a simulacra is a degraded copy. If
Being is Difference, Socrates can be said to resemble his portrait, but only because of the
differential and repetitive power of a simulacra to which both the portrait and the man
attest. Thus there is something strangely “eternal” about difference, something like the
intransitivity (but not the impassibility) of Platonic ideas. Deleuze argues, in fact, that it
58
was Plato who came closest to a notion of difference in itself, prior to Aristotle’s attempt
Overturning Platonism
determine the species of different genera, but to select lineages: “suitors of the Good”
that the Socratic philosopher determines worthy of an Idea. When determining, for
non-winged animal, Plato does not explain how the difference between any two terms
sufficient reason,” as Aristotle correctly saw (DR 59). For the later Plato, there is a
distinct Idea for each thing, even for mud or hair. But ideas differ from one another,
according to the Sophist, not due to “material” contingency, but as an effect of the idea of
the Other. The difference the form of the Other makes is, to say the least, occult, and
“jumps from one singularity to another,” (DR 59), is precisely what is so important for
59
certain way, Plato does not subordinate difference to a representable divergence, or to
what will amount in later philosophy as subordination of difference to the powers of the
One, the Analogous, the Similar, or the Negative—all the ways in which difference is no
longer thought “in itself,” but always in relation to something else (DR 59).
As Deleuze puts it, in Plato “the Idea is not yet the concept of an object which
submits the world to the requirements of representation, but rather of a brute presence
which can be invoked in the world only in function of that which is not ‘representable’ in
things” (DR 59). Thus in Platonic dialectics the relation between an Idea (of, say, the
of those who, illumined by the invisible light of the Good, perceive ideas in things, even
if ideas or forms are not only beyond perception and representation but beyond concepts
analogically, in terms of other concepts and forms are ineffably self-same) (DR 59).
Faced with a host of “suitors” or “claimants” to the right to define and thus to
Socrates “tests” to see if the claim holds. But this test is always an enigma, a problem
posed to the claimant: do you know the nature of the question to which you are giving an
answer, the essence of the problem to which you are giving a solution? False claimants
contradict themselves, in the end, because they do not fully understand the ideal nature of
the problem they claim they can solve. If truth is not a matter of opinion, the best opinion
will not matter; if ruling is not a matter of coercion, the most noble form of coercion will
60
not count as ruling, and so on. The “ideal” status of the Forms, Deleuze argues,
what is problematic in embodied existence will one day no longer be so (DR 62).
But beneath this “metaphysical comfort,” Deleuze argues, lies the actual practice
of platonic division: an ordeal, a trial. For Deleuze this is why Plato’s dialectic is always
tinged with irony: “irony consists in treating things and beings as so many responses to
hidden questions, so many cases for problems yet to be resolved” (DR 63). Even if the
philosopher has assurance of the ultimately unproblematic nature of the Ideas to which
s/he belongs by right, the intuition of a Platonic idea is never a means of identifying
things in the world but a way of problematizing them, a manner of calling into question
For Deleuze this is the case in Plato not because ideas come in the form of “the
“reflexive” concepts, but because, as Deleuze puts it, for Plato there is a kind of non-
which is nevertheless not a negation but a positively problematic determination (DR 63).
This is the source of the irony of the philosopher’s discourse: her questions lead only to
other questions, her problems point not to solutions (which are always more than
knowledge. Rather, problematic Ideas constitute the possibility of learning, per se.
Deleuze writes,
61
Neither the problem nor the question is a subjective determination
marking a moment of insufficiency in knowledge. Problematic structure
is part of objects themselves, allowing them to be grasped as signs, just as
the questioning or problematizing instance is a part of knowledge allowing
its positivity and its specificity to be grasped in an act of learning. More
profoundly still, Being (what Plato calls the Idea) “corresponds” to the
essence of the problem or the question as such. (DR 64)
For Deleuze, Plato constantly tried to “tame” the problematic nature of Being by
describing Ideas as models from which icones or images of these ideas can or cannot be
derived, relative to the receptivity of the participant (DR 127). This is the point at which
Deleuze believes we must overturn the Platonic vision. Rather than suppose that Ideas
are problematic due to the contingency of the model-copy relationship, Deleuze asserts
that ideas are essentially and necessarily problematic due to relationships of non-
resemblance between simulacra. When Nietzsche declared that it was the task of modern
philosophy to “overturn platonism,” this does not mean, for Deleuze, to jettison the entire
platonic structure, but precisely to deny, from within the platonic vision, the priority of
model over copy, and the need for a guarantee of the “return” of copies to originals. This
Overturned platonism accepts the idea that there is an invisible, occult quality in
things, something in things that is more than our perceptions, memories, and cognitive
acts can grasp. But it resists the notion that this excessive nature in things is somehow
the shard of a lost transcendent stability, angels fallen from the heaven of ideas. For
determinations of a learning act which is also a cosmic becoming. This is a world not of
62
beings but of becomings: of events, actions, and affects rather than of substances,
properties, and causes. A world of pure transitions and modes whose only substance is a
art—is to release the play of simulacra, in their “eternal recurrence,” in their being
impossibly what they are: appearances without an appearing thing, accidents without
essences, images without realities. To say that being is difference is to say that being is
neither an original source nor a participating copy, but a simulacra. To reverse platonism
is to attribute the eternal status of Ideal Forms to the dynamics of a simulacral time, a
Simulacra Affirmed
traverse series, appearing (differently) in each of them as a kind of forced motion. This is
the sense in which the “modern” art that fascinates Deleuze is critical: it breaks down our
ordinary notion of identity, of time, of place, and substitutes for it (in a violent act, in a
locales. Certain forms of art, especially those that develop complicated series of images
or words or events that are connected in ways different from ordinary continuities in
space, time, and consciousness, thus model for Deleuze that “critical affirmation” which
63
What is this affirmation? Is it simply the self-assertion of various perspectives?
Yes, but only in the sense that perspectives are not the prerogative of a knowing,
conscious subject. For Deleuze, perspectives involve selves; selves do not choose
perspectives (DR 56). What we have in an art like Joyce’s or Francis Bacon’s or Lewis
Carroll’s is a self or a world that exists or insists only in and as it is torn asunder by the
various points of view which compose it, or complicate it. This is a serial art form, an art
that forces (through strange connections, nonsense, mantric rhythms, haptic colorations)
apparently unconnected or disparate lives, events, times, places, objects, words, colors
and sounds to resonate with “one clamor of being” (DR 304). In this kind of art, Deleuze
writes,
What would this mean for philosophy? In Plato, a chaos of simulacra confronts
the philosopher, a host of differences from which must be selected those that are in
conformity with the Idea. But what would thought be like if we overturned this situation?
collaborations and connections between and within the disparate, the irreducibly
different? Put abstractly, this would be to seek the conditions of real experience, not of
experimentation of modern art forms as redefining the limits of the sensible, per se. This
would bring together the two sides of aesthetics long sundered. Deleuze writes,
64
Everything changes once we determine the conditions of real experience,
which are not larger than the conditioned and which differ in kind from
the categories: the two senses of the aesthetic become one, to the point
where the being of the sensible reveals itself in the work of art, while at
the same time the work of art appears as experimentation. (DR 68)
Why? For Deleuze it was Plato who first conceived of philosophy as an encounter with
problems raised in sensation that cannot be solved by comparison with other sensations,
that there are two kinds of sensory experiences: those which provoke thought (or
“summon” it, as Reeve translates the word) and those which do not. At first Glaucon
thinks Socrates is referring to objects seen in the distance, or in trompe l’oeil paintings.
But Socrates has something else in mind: when we hold up three adjacent fingers, it is
the same sense that reports to us that one finger is, at the same time, both larger and
smaller than another. The report of the senses with respect to largeness and smallness is
“contradictory.” It says that a finger is both large and small simultaneously. The
understanding must intervene to separate out the large from the small.
In this way Glaucon learns that certain sense experiences lead us to realize the
abstract way—she will learn to conceive the one without simultaneously thinking of the
many, i.e., “2” (“the dyad” ) without simultaneously relating it to “1” (the monad) or to
“3” (the triad), and so on. The provocation to begin to undertake such training lies in a
very peculiar encounter with an apparently contradictory set of signs issuing from sense
65
propaedutic to knowledge: a heterogeneity or difference internal to sensation itself
feature of sensibility that cannot be described by any pair of opposing terms, whether
quantity or quality, matter or form. According to Deleuze, Plato tries to limit the
“summoning” power of the intensive to the accidental condition of our soul in the
material world. Plato offers the philosopher a kind of “metaphysical comfort” in the
doctrine that the forms re-learned by the soul in this life have their origin in a Unity and
Goodness beyond being to which the soul ultimately belongs and to which it is destined
resemblance and identity” (DR 66), it remains Plato, for Deleuze, who is “the exception”
in the history of philosophy (at least until Nietzsche) to those who subordinate the
What so inspires Deleuze here is that Plato’s theory of ideas is rooted in a theory
66
for recognition. We know what these things are because we have seen them before.
Even when perception is not immediately transparent, the memory or the intellect can
recall what an object is and apply it to the confusion (DR 139). None of this is yet
perceptions) are we confronted with an intensity or a “difference” which defies the power
of the senses to recognize discrete perceptions (DR 140). It is thus difference that forces
quantity, but an imperceptible difference within qualities. The hard is not hard without
also being soft (relative to something). The loud is not loud without also being quiet.
The just is not just without being unjust, the beautiful without being ugly, and so on (DR
141). In order to “recognize” things as being what they are, Socrates teaches that we
must resort to resources beyond sensation, beyond memory, beyond even thought itself.
Where would we find such things, such reference points? In the recollection of the
place full of unknowns, and back to that place it knows. But this Platonic myth, for
Deleuze, confuses the being of the past with a past being, the being of the sensible with
sensible being (what we are looking for in sensation is like a sensible quality), and the
form of thought with the form of the good (when we think of hardness in itself or justice
in itself, it has a self-identity derived from that Good whose perfect impassibility is
imparted to all the ideas). Reversing platonism, for Deleuze, means to free the being of
67
the sensible, the form of thought, and the nature of time itself from all resemblance with
sensible objects, self-identical forms, and all images of time that take the present moment
Because Plato does not yet subordinate difference to representation, we get a very
clear image of the simulacral nature of difference, of what for Deleuze is the
insubordination of difference to either the model or the copy. “The simulacral” is not,
simulacra make the being/non-being distinction problematic, somewhat in the way that
anti-matter makes problematic the distinction between what is material and what is
immaterial. A simulacrum is a non-being which does not distinguish itself from being.
In a way, the uncannily present simulacrum play for Deleuze the role that the ineffably
present One played in Neo-Platonism. But whereas it is the role of the One to mediate
difference and thus to relate it to a higher unity, the role of a simulacrum is to further
differentiate the merely diverse, to make distinct and singular an ordinary diversity.
Rather than say “there are simulacra,” we should say that “the many simulacrum produce
the effect of being.” Above all when simulacral forces are united (if not unified) in the
When the modern work of art develops its permutating series and its
circular structures, it indicates to philosophy a path leading to the
abandonment of representation. It is not enough to multiply perspectives
in order to establish perspectivism. To every perspective or point of view
there must correspond an autonomous work with its own self-sufficient
sense: what matters is the divergence of series, the decentering of circles,
“monstrosity” . . . it is in this direction that we must look for the
conditions, not of possible experience, but of real experience (selection,
repetition, etc.) It is here that we find the lived reality of a sub-
representative domain . . . always a difference of difference as its
immediate element. (DR 69)
68
The work of Marcel Proust serves as such a major cipher for Deleuze’s
philosophical enterprise precisely for its development of perspectives that are not
Proust’s apprenticeship to these signs thus models that form of learning which difference
and repetition require: encounter with the lived reality of a sub-representative domain
that can be known only as it is recreated, or repeated, in the signs of art. To Deleuze’s
69
III. Learning Signs: Recollection Without Recognition
In the preface to the English edition of Difference and Repetition, written in 1994,
Deleuze asserts that the project of that book had already begun in Deleuze’s earlier
monograph on the work of Marcel Proust, Proust and Signs.72 There Deleuze had first
espied, in Proust’s Search for Lost Time, a new conception of what it means to learn, a
conception that breaks decisively with an “Image of Thought” that would make learning
a matter of confirming and conforming to the dictates of common sense. For Deleuze,
Proust’s recherches break with the strictures of the Image of Thought in a way that is
instructive for philosophy. Deleuze’s epistemology, in a sense, began with his reflection
on Proust: “a liberation of thought from those images which imprison it: this is what I
In the classical image of thought, a thinker’s “good will” leads her to truth: there
is a presupposed natural alliance between the goodwill of the thinker and truth itself,
between common sense or good sense and the representable identity of the things we
wish to know. But in the recherches of Marcel Proust, truth cannot be sought with the
good will. It is rather that which befalls us, as a kind of blow. As Deleuze puts in Proust
and Signs, “philosophy, with all its method and goodwill, is nothing compared to the
secret pressures of the work of art” (PS 98). For Deleuze, it is only the secret pressures
of the world that force us to think, to learn, and to create. Thus it is to artists like Proust
that we must look for a paradigm of what philosophy might become beyond its
with concepts” by means of which it pre-ordains a natural affiliation of mind for truth.
70
As Deleuze reads it in Proust, the truth is not that which befriends us. Rather, is
that which disguises and betrays itself. And the true thinker is not the friend of the
representable concept, but the jealous lover of the elusive, imperceptible idea. It is the
indications of signs, and not the elucidation of the proposition, which is the home, or
better the “territory” of genuine thought and creation. As Deleuze puts it, “Creation, like
the genesis of the act of thinking, always starts from signs. The work of art is born from
signs as much as it generates them; the creator is like the jealous man, interpreter of the
god, who scrutinizes the signs in which the truth betrays itself” (PS ).73
In this chapter, reading Deleuze reading Proust will make clearer the paradigmatic
status of art for a thought that would break with the strictures of representation and, more
importantly, with the cannon of recognition: the unspoken dictate that thought recognize
confrontation with uncanny signs, and of conceptual creation as an art of learning those
signs. Ultimately the essences or ideas we learn, for Deleuze, are not the subjects of
consciously constructed knowledge but are rather the forces of unconscious provocations.
71
Apprenticed to Signs: Marcel Proust and the Art of Learning
adequating an action to a representation (say, the act of swimming and the movements of
(e.g. waves in water) with a possible response (what our body can and cannot do in
waves) (DR 23). We do not so much imitate the possible actions represented by our
teacher as repeat her real response to actual waves. As Deleuze puts it,
The movement of the swimmer does not resemble that of the wave, in
particular, the movements of the swimming instructor which we reproduce
on the sand bear no relation to the movements of the wave, which we learn
to deal with only by grasping the former in practice as signs . . . . When a
body combines some of its own distinctive points with those of a wave, it
espouses the principle of a repetition which is no longer that of the Same
but involves the Other—involves difference, from one wave and one
gesture to another, and carries that difference through the repetitive space
thereby constituted. To learn is indeed to constitute this space of an
encounter with signs, in which distinctive points renew themselves in each
other, and repetition takes shape while disguising itself. (DR 23)
The distinctive points which emerge in the space of the teacher’s movements are not
imitated by but repeated in the (different) body of the student. Thus, swimming is not a
transcendent idea from which action is deduced, but an immanent idea which insists in
our attempt to swim. Swimming is thus not a static being represented by the teacher to
72
the student, but a dynamic form of becoming that is transmitted and modulated across the
The key point in Deleuze’s account, here, is that it is only in the singularity
constituted by the real encounter with actual waves that the “essence” or “idea” of
swimming (at least not one from which anything could be learned). There is only an
event in which the distinctive points of a body combine with those of a wave. The
teacher does not represent but rather transmits a singular relation between her body and
the waves, a relation that must be repeated differently in the body of the student.
This transmission cannot happen through conscious imitation, because the relation
between the wave and the body is, each time, a unique singularity. The nature or essence
water. Rather, the idea of swimming, as an event, poses a problem or introduces the
“problematic field” in which we learn. As Deleuze explains this subtle but crucial point,
For Deleuze the fact that we can learn, at all, points to a complicity between
nature and mind. However, this complicity is not the one Kant determined as the set of
possible actions within the phenomenal world deduced from the categories of our
understanding. For Deleuze it is rather the body that unconsciously but continuously
73
creates real relations between action and perception, always on the basis of an encounter
not with stable objectivities consciously apprehended (“the possible”) but with
“problematic ideas” which appear, apart from their enactment, only as subliminal or
unconscious elements (as purely “virtual” elements). Learning happens when a new
mode of existence comes into being, a form of becoming that “actualizes” the virtual,
What Deleuze means when he claims that ideas are inherently problematic is that
idea of swimming inherently poses the problem of what it is to swim. The specificity of
the idea of swimming, its ipseity, cannot be known apart from acts of learning, or from
excess of itself, its essence located in a process of becoming rather than in a state of
being. Ideas are and remain problematic not because actual acts of swimming lack a
governing notion to unify them, but because the virtual does not exist apart from things
Another way of putting this would be that it is the act of learning, the event of its
actualization (and the virtualization of its idea) that is logically prior to the actual instance
or the virtual idea. While there are no a priori rules governing how actualization can
occur in that act, because ideas are always already a part of the structure of objects, there
74
are nevertheless material regimes of signs in terms of which ideas objectively emerge.
Proust and Signs. For Deleuze, when certain sensory experiences provoke Marcel Proust
to reminisce, what is recalled in the Search is never simply another past experience.
Rather, the Search finds an object (such as the city of Combray) which “is” only in
recollection—only its distribution across two series: one of a present, lived experience
and one of an unlivable encounter, a sensation given substance only in the style of
Deleuze calls Proust a “Platonist” because Proust seems to affirm the existence of
objectivities that are something like Platonic forms. For Deleuze the worlds Proust learns
are inherently problematic ideas, fraught with an ambiguity that is not due to any
deficiency on Proust’s part, but which is proper to the obscure nature of those worlds,
themselves. Far from occluding knowledge, however, this obscurity is what causes the
life of different times and places to exist in signs. The worlds Proust explores are
problematic in a positive sense: they do not exist as eternal ipseities but subsist or
“insist” in signs. For example, Proust’s idea of the city of Combray is neither in the taste
of the Madeline in the present nor in the past which that taste evokes, but in a pure
passage of time, always already past and always yet to come, a time which never actually
passes outside of the literary creation, and which is virtually present in the signs repeated
75
Combray is nothing but a difference which traverses two series, that of a past which is
immemorial outside of the Recherche itself and that of a present experience which forces
sensation (taste or sight or hearing) to confront an uncanny sign (DR 122). In this sense
For Deleuze, Proust’s worlds are constituted by a kind of obverse of the platonic
Idea. For Proust it is not we who recall the essence of things from the mythical past (in
which we dwelt fully with the ideas themselves), but in some sense the reverse: Proust’s
problematic worlds are like hieroglyphs that demand interpretation, and the varieties and
those inherently problematic ideas. Ideas, in Proust, are forces that call us or give us our
vocation.
But learning signs, for Deleuze, is not a derivation of our subjectivity, even in a
transcendental or critical realist sense of there not being anything to know apart from our
meaning-making behavior. For Deleuze signs are not conventional; they are expressive
of things themselves, even if what they express is obscure. For Deleuze signs are always
both distinct and obscure. Signs have this double status as part of a cosmic process of
generativity that is no less sign than thing, no more nature than culture, no less free than
determined.75 Because art models expression better than science and philosophy as
traditionally conceived, Deleuze turns to artists like Proust for a model of genuine
learning.
76
For Deleuze, the expressivism of the world is the true subject of the recherches of
Proust. Thus Proust’s method is not a simple reproduction of the past, or mere reverie,
but the recapitulation, indeed the anamnesis, of a form of time, or of becoming. Why is
this recapitulation so important to knowledge? Why must we in some sense remain with
the platonic model of reminiscence, even if in order to recall what we can no longer
recognize? Proust’s answer, to put it cryptically, is because our time is not our own.
The first time we experience anything, it is in a sense blind, mute, uncreated, void. But
as soon as it is repeated (paradigmatically in art), time itself, in all its multiplicity, comes
into focus, not as a whole but as a set of singularities. Art is thus a way of recollecting
not the past, but of what in the past can be realized only via the style of an artist who can
This is why, for Deleuze, repetition is closer to the essence of art than any notion
of representation. The singular elements inhabiting a great artists’ style have neither
analog nor allegory in any other world than the world of that style. If artists are able to
“recall” the truth of a given world (the countryside of Provence, the seas of the 19th
century, the aisles of 20th century supermarkets), this is not because the artist has created
a world analogous to the actual world. It is, rather, the unrecognizability of the
repetition, and appeals to us in art. This is why, Deleuze says, our only response to great
art is to make more of it, just as the only true response to love is more love. If art or love
have essences, that is only because essences magnify singular Differences as the only
77
For Deleuze, Proust teaches that the essence of a particular world, and the nature
essence which only is when invoked or evoked in the signs recreated in a style.76 As
Deleuze calls Proust’s art, like Plato’s education, an “apprenticeship.” What Proust is
apprenticed to are potentials in things that only stand out as potentials, or as signs, under
him, but it is not exactly “relative” to his capacities. Just as carpenters are peculiarly
sensitive to wood, and to the signs emitted by wood, and just as good doctors are
Yet signs are not constituted as such through subjective acts, and are not simply
relative to subjective dispositions. This is why Deleuze argues that signs populate worlds
(or what he will later call regimes), and does not hesitate to claim that the initiate or
ultimately these strangely “objective” worlds whose signs determine the nature and
possibility of the search, even though that search can be carried out only in the
In a somewhat Kantian fashion Deleuze understands the sign as the limit of both
our faculties and of various “worlds” (of love, of urban life, of a countryside, of art, of
politics, etc.). As Deleuze puts it, “instead of an indifferent perception, a sensibility that
78
apprehends and receives signs, the sign is the limit of this sensibility, its vocation, its
extreme exercise” (PS 99). To reverse Kant, the schema according to which the
understanding functions, for Deleuze, is not what is most common, sensible, and rational,
but what is most uncanny. On Deleuze’s view of mind, the shortest line is not a
In opposition to Kant’s taste for common sense and popular notions (which Kant
awards “civil rights” in his critique), for Deleuze what thought consists in is not the
harmonious functioning of our faculties but their autonomous and divergent exercise. As
he sees it operative in Proust, for Deleuze authentic thought always involves a “disjunct
use” and “involuntary exercise” of our faculties, the potentials of which Plato was more
aware of than was Kant.77 It is on this basis that Deleuze relates and yet differentiates
between Proust and Plato. The “objectivity” of different worlds (the salon, the city, the
work of art), with their different kinds of signs does indicate a set of essences proper to
involuntary memories are not so much perspectives on time, but the times (and signs)
belonging to a perspective. The signs of art reveal to us the different kinds of time we are
living. These are times “out-of-joint.” They are the times not of history, or of physical
and uncannily discerned relations. Proust’s art presents a time that cannot be experienced
directly but only in repetition. Thus Deleuze can claim that in Proust, time itself is the
79
true subject of the search, a time belonging neither to subjects nor objects, but to the
autonomy of artistic creation itself, the autonomy of style itself (PS 115).
If Platonic essences have always already been present even if they are occluded
here-and-now, Proustian essences are never pre-given, and are not found apart from a
creative act. In Proust the duplicity of sensation, the confusion in experience which
provokes the need for recollection, is not already oriented, as it seems usually to be for
Plato, toward an ideal mean or measure that will divide truth from apparent truth, illusion
from reality. Proustian recollection is oriented rather by a creative act: a repetition that
will only indicate essence or identify itself when that essence has been re-produced. In a
second time, in another place. As Deleuze puts it,“ the Search is oriented toward the
future, not to the past” (PS 4). For Deleuze, Proust is searching for a future that is
available only on the basis of a repetition which will release something from the past that
something that can live only in a repetition it provokes in the artist: a style.
which attempts to dialectically work toward a substance of things that is in some sense
eternally pre-given, and that mind has only to recollect, Proust’s version of recollection
80
evokes not a pregiven substance but the heterogeneity of sensation, itself: difference in
itself, repetition for itself. In Proust’s work, essence is not beyond sensation, but is rather
that which in sensation differs and repeats, or that which signals what it is only as
another sensation (or that which in memory cannot be remembered except as something
“hieroglyphic” discourse signs the presence of essences, but these cannot be recognized
in terms of ideal identities, and the mind “adequate” to essence does not come before but
after the advent of the sign. In The Search for Lost Time, all that was given to Proust has
become shards or traces, and the signs to which essence will have referred await their
What makes Proust’s work so important for Deleuze is the way in which it
displaces the problem of “the whole” of experience, moving it away from a problem of
recalling that which was given and towards that which remains to be created. As Deleuze
An artist like Proust models authentic thought because Proust has experienced where,
how, and to whom and in what degree experience breaks up, loses its normalcy, its
regularity, its predictability. And this not because Proust is a more self-involved ego or
81
more sensitive subject, but because in his style Proust experiences the Self as a viewpoint
various worlds.
To generalize, rather than seeking a narrative that will reunite what is broken in
experience, part of what makes art paradigmatic for thought is that the artist is able to
develop a “point of view” that does not summarize or encompass experience, but comes
alongside experience in a way that forces resonances and connections that would not
resound or be visible otherwise than as art. That is why it can be said that art “recalls” us
to experience or that the artist “reminisces” about experience, without for all that making
Proust does not proceed, as Socrates does, along the lines of a dialectic—he does not set
out, on the basis of any intuition of Forms, to divide legitimate from illegitimate signs,
reality from illusion, sophistry from wisdom. Rather, Proust is arrested by certain signs
(Vinteuil’s little phrase, the ankle boot, the madeleine) that force him to simultaneously
invent and (re)interpret. It is in this activity, for Deleuze, that mind consists, for it
be no larger than that which they condition—that experience itself, in its intensive and
singular becoming, provokes its own categories and its own evaluation.
82
Proust is learning an essence when forced to create, but essence is not what
Socrates would count as well defined in logos, in a true speaking.79 Socrates mocks the
Sophists by claiming that their form of questioning is that of children and the senile.
Sophists are childish by thinking that essence can be determined and definition found by
answering which one is beautiful; by giving an example. For Deleuze the Sophists have
The Sophist Hippias was not a child who was content to answer the
question ”which one?” when asked the question “what is?” He thought
that the question “which one?” was the best kind of question, the one most
suitable for determining essence. For it does not refer, as Socrates
believed, to discrete examples, but to the continuity of concrete objects
taken in their becoming, to the becoming-beautiful of all the objects
citable or cited as examples. Asking which one is beautiful, which one is
just, and not what beauty is, what justice is, was therefore the result of a
worked-out method, implying an original conception of essence and a
whole sophistic art which was opposed to the dialectic. An empirical and
pluralist art. (NP 76)
vision per se—not of the idea of their being essences at all, which many would take to be
Nietzsche’s critique. Deleuze insists that it is the form of the question itself (or the mode
of critique) which sets in motion Plato’s metaphysical distinctions between essence and
appearance, being and becoming. Deleuze insists that these oppositions depend
“primarily upon a mode of questioning, a form of question” (NP 76). For Deleuze what
distinguishes the “empirical and pluralist art” that would be, paradoxically, the true
therefore not any kind of axiomatic metaphysical supposition, but rather a certain form of
83
Thus it is through platonism and against it that Deleuze believes we should fulfill
“beings” in the platonic sense of self-identical points of reference but rather are strange
continuities in the world of becoming) philosophers must be, like modern artists, creators.
Socrates is unable to do this because the form of the question upon which he insists is not
thinker, in Nietzsche’s sense, even if he was the thinker, Nietzsche admits, who took the
Deleuze (with the later Nietzsche) affirms Plato’s radicality, that Plato was a
thinker of forces as much as Nietzsche: “Plato offers us an image of thought under the
sign of encounters and violences,” Deleuze writes.80 For Deleuze Proust is better than
Socrates, and a better Platonist, because Proust does not attempt to anticipate the
encounters that provoke him. Socrates, for Deleuze, still imagines that his
might provoke recollection. “The Socratic demon, irony, consists in anticipating the
encounters,” Deleuze writes (PS 101). The point here is that when Socrates says “no” to
an answer, this is because he has already organized the situation (the question) in an
intellectual way—the responses to the “what is . . .” questions that Socrates asks himself
and others are already ironized by the impossibility of answering that specific question in
develop in the meaning in order to be necessarily conceived” (PS 102). Essences do not
84
manner.82 The strange nature of essences is found or discovered only when we are forced
to respond to and indeed to recreate the difference to which they attest in becoming. As
. . . essence is precisely the accident, the event, the sense; not simply the
contrary of what is ordinarily called the essence, but the contrary of the
contrary: multiplicity is no more appearance than essence, no more
multiple than one. (DR 191)
The form of knowledge called for by the multiple character of being is one that
Proust’s art models well. There, a series of concrete objects undergo a transformation in
the recherche, even as those objects provoke a style of recollection that transforms them.
The essence of the objects of the recherche insist only in the performance of that
style—as Proust says of the musicians, they did not so much play Vinteuil’s “little
phrase” as perform the rites necessary for its invocation. Here the contrast should be
clear with the Socratic method of determining essence through elenchic procedure, whose
goal is the establishment of an ideal essence beyond all exemplification, beyond “which
one.” On the contrary, for Proust it is only the “counting” of each sensation, or of the
intensive encounter to which it attests, that renders a distinct essence, even while that
“One must be endowed for signs,” Deleuze writes (PS 101).83 But Socrates (at
least the Socrates Deleuze knew) is only partly endowed for signs. He only partly gives
himself over to the hieroglyph. The logos is kept in readiness. But for Deleuze, as for
Nietzsche, this poisons the intelligence. For Socrates, “the intelligence always comes
after; it is good when it comes after; it is good only when it comes after” (PS 101). The
afterthought of Socrates is always art. But an artistic Socrates, for Deleuze, would be the
85
truer Platonist. Because it is primarily through art that essences are evoked in their purest
Socrates is right to say, listen not to me but to something else, something that is
not reducible to communication. His error is to say that we should listen to a tale of
those encounters which interrupt the functioning of recognition, in encounter with the
is thus a Socrates who “can rightly say: I am Love more than the friend, I am the lover; I
am art more than philosophy; I am constraint and violence, rather than goodwill” (PS
101).
himself put it, “thanks to art instead of seeing a single world, our own, we see it multiply,
and as many original artists as there are, so many worlds will we have at our disposal,
more different from each other than those that circle in the void . . .” (PS 42). However,
art does not clue us in to some primordial or originary givenness of the world. Rather, art
86
draws out a quality, a disparity, a difference proper to a world that is created out of a
But the truth of a world, if singular, is not a premise from which other truths can
be derived. It is not a template for designing other worlds. It is not even a paradigm for
“Play it again, Sam.” The extraordinary difference elicited by art calls for its repetition.
This is why difference and repetition cannot be opposed. “Difference and repetition are
only apparently in opposition. There is no great artist who does not make us say, “the
The reason, perhaps even the “sufficient reason” why essences are what they are,
for Deleuze, is that properly speaking, essences are of the order of the unconscious, of
“unconscious themes and involuntary archetypes” (PS 47). That is why art always
involves partiality, or “partial objects,” in order to display and evoke essence. The unity
The essential point is that the parts of the search remain partitioned,
fragmented, without anything lacking: eternally partial parts, open boxes
and sealed vessels, swept on by time without forming a whole or
presupposing one, without lacking anything in this quartering, and
denouncing in advance every organic unity we might seek to introduce
into it. (PS 161)
Deleuze argues that when Proust compares his work to a gown or a cathedral, it is
not in order to insist on his own special form of unity and unification, his own special
form of logos. It is on the contrary to “emphasize his right to incompletion, to seams and
patches” (PS 161). The artist asserts his right against the metaphysical and organicist
87
temptation. She finds the power of her work in her ability not to unite what is sundered
from itself, but in her ability to evoke a resonance and a world of signs that resonates
only because the essence which the resonance evokes comes into being alongside the
elements we might mistakenly think are “unified” or “gathered” in the work. As Deleuze
puts it,
If “knowledge” refers to the generality of concepts or to the stability of a rule that can
standard, etc.), learning Differences does not exactly result in what we have traditionally
something Deleuze is not embarrassed to call a “profound complicity between nature and
our personal histories. Deleuze was convinced that Carl Jung was right to believe that the
unconscious not only recorded that which consciousness rejects or represses, but also
poses problems for desire. The unconscious is not merely those drives consciousness
cannot accept, but an autonomous regime of desire (DR 317). However, while Jung
identities, Deleuze sees the questions posed by the unconscious not as the overshadowing
88
of individual by the enormity of types, but as the differential and repetitive power of
Ideas themselves, of which the individual as much as the collective is only an echo.
unconscious, which appear as the uncanny images of our dreams (better, the sets of
problem-posing. They are the petits perceptions of Leibniz, on the basis of which we act
or react prior to conscious awareness, like a dog that winces before being struck. This is
contrary to the Freudian idea of the unconscious as a garbage dump or an inverted world
where we try to compensate for certain lacks or gaps in our experience. The Freudian
werden—there where id was, ego shall come to be—was Freuds formula for analysis.
singular points that territorialize or order ordinary points, and extend themselves as far as
another remarkable point (again analogous to Leibnizian space). Ideas are singularities
or events that determine the borders and limits of the sense of a thing. We intuit or grasp
the sense of something (a word, a phrase of music, a political movement) not so much by
analyzing its truth or falsity as by being confronted or arrested by the “ideal events” that
distinguish its idea. These ideal events or singularities prior to fully formed subjects,
Virtual as opposed to actual, not to real. The possible is always contrasted with
the real, but for Deleuze the virtual is much more real than the possible. It is as real as
the actual, surrounding the actual like a halo or a holographic double. That is why it is
89
not at all indeterminate even though it is unrepresentable in concepts. It “is real without
being actual, ideal without being abstract” (DI 101). The virtual has a neighborhood or a
distinctive variation. Considered as pure virtualities, ideas for Deleuze are distinct
differentials not yet clearly differentiated in the actual parts which will incarnate their
singularities. Ideas are virtually differenciated, but not yet actually differentiated. Ideas
are thus “distinct-obscure,” transcending things by being a (virtual) part of them or a side
of them, a side that does not resemble the other (the actual). Yet the idea is immanent to
things as the becoming or sense things more or less actualize in their “historicity” (all
It is because of an obscurity proper to Ideas that they are of the order of the
unconscious, of what is closed in on itself or reserved. “In this same sense,” Deleuze
writes, “the Idea is Dionysian: that zone of obscure distinction which it preserves within
drunkenness” (DI 101). However, the slurred speech of the Idea is not a deep mystery,
but an unconscious riddle. Not the unconscious as a graveyard or garbage dump, but the
unconscious as life’s provocateur. As Deleuze puts it, “in truth, the structure of the
The paradox of the unconscious is that it is a machine which has “chosen” what
has “befallen” us. It is connected to what psychoanalysis called the death drive: not the
desire for death, but the compulsion to repeat something to which we are erotically
attached to, in order to force that attachment to exceed itself toward other attachments.
90
This, for Deleuze, is what Nietzsche called the will to power’s affirmation of itself, the
“involuntary” moment, because we cannot consciously choose our problems, our ideas,
any more than the Greek gods could escape Ananke, necessity (DR 199). As Deleuze
puts it,
The imperatives and questions with which we are infused do not emanate
from the I: it is not even there to hear them. The imperatives are those of
being, while every question is ontological and distributes “that which is”
among problems . . . from the outset, however, what are these fiery
imperatives, these questions which are the beginning of the world? The
fact is that everything has its beginning in a question, but one cannot say
that the question itself begins. Might the question, along with the
imperative which it expresses, have no other origin than repetition? (DR
199-200)
What would the logic of such repetition look like? The repetition of the past in the
“eternal” present of art gives Proust entrée to the imperatives dominating his life. But
this process, though at its purest in art, also takes place in the emergence of thought itself.
To understand the genesis of thought from the point of view of those unconscious
imperatives that give rise to it requires a new logic. Deleuze’s The Logic of Sense
91
IV. Surfacing Bodies: The Adventures of Sense
In a certain way, it was the quest of Plato’s philosophy to identify the source of
sense. To whom does sense belong? Plato answers that it belongs to no one in
particular because it belongs to the Forms specifically and universally. This was a move
against the pre-Socratics who had attempted to claim it belonged to no one because it
belonged to the earth and the elements. The Enlightenment claimed that sense belonged
to the coherence of the rational individual, and Romanticism located sense in the
dialectical dynamics of the person (LS 138-139). In every case there is no answer to the
(making Nature internal to Spirit), for Deleuze this assumption is riddled by bad
consciousness insofar as some version of unity is still the goal. The romantic may have
experienced the death of God, but she has not yet survived the death of Man. What
modern literature and modern art only begin to realize is that it is impossible to judge
which is more ironic, the fractured presence of nature in humanity or the human shadow
To complete the move begun by modern art requires the abandonment of the
presupposition that events are reducible either to the ideas in which they are supposed to
participate or to the forces which they express. This, for Deleuze, was the achievement of
the Stoic school. “The autonomy of the surface, independent of, and against depth and
height; the discovery of incorporeal events, meanings, or effects, which are irreducible to
“deep” bodies and to “lofty” Ideas—these are the important Stoic discoveries against the
92
For Deleuze, the Stoics proposed a humorous or healthy philosophy, working
with “a new demarcation: between things and propositions themselves. It is the frontier
drawn between the thing such as it is, denoted by the proposition, and the expressed,
“which does not exist outside of the proposition,” and yet which has enough autonomy to
become the subject of art, humor, and experimentation (LS 132). In this neo-Stoic space,
which for Deleuze is a new surface of thought, a new wisdom speaks not in the name of
identities or natures, but in a voice Deleuze calls the “fourth person singular” (LS 141).
It is the voice of an “objectality” that cuts across the distinction between subject and
does not simply affirm that all ideas derive from sensory experience. Rather, Deleuze’s
empiricist claim is that, as Spinoza might have put it, there are as many things unknown
in the mind as in the body. There are as many ideas yet to be explored as there are times,
93
places, and events yet to be lived. Deleuze’s “superior” or “transcendental” empiricism
is thus the search for encounters with that which forces us to think and to act in
As Deleuze’s commentator and translator Dan Smith has shown, for Deleuze, as
for Spinoza, the test of an idea is always a practical test.86 Ideas like Justice are not
world.87 Rather, the idea of justice or beauty or love is infinite because we do not yet
know how and in what ways we might become just, how we may yet love, what we may
find beautiful—we do not yet know, as Spinoza put it, what our bodies can do. For
Deleuze as for Spinoza, there are as many unknown regions of the mind (and its ideas) as
What calls up the potentials of the body are the events that befall it. Something
solved, milk is pasteurized, the DNA code is cracked, the Buddha is enlightened, Christ is
resurrected, lightening strikes, Sting records “Every Breath You Take” in the middle of
the night, Kurt Cobain commits suicide, Captain Ahab is destroyed by Moby Dick, two
cats make fighting love in an alley, an unusual couple marries. What is the sense of any
of these events? Obviously the sense of events is different for those nearer to them or
farther from them, and different again for the different contours of the different bodies
directly or indirectly involved. But to say that there are different senses of different
events for different bodies is not to solve the problem but only to pose it.
bodies and events relate through a logic that is neither purely abstract nor completely
94
concrete, but an inherently problematic mixture of sense and nonsense. Deleuze begins
this book, which he calls a “logical and psychological novel,” by noting that the Stoics
divided the sense of interlocked corporeal causes, a totally determined Destiny shared by
all bodies, from the sense of incorporeal effects, which continually float or “insist” in
For the Stoics there is only a single, univocal causal stream or causal “language,”
but it is divided into substantives and adjectives (bodies-causes), on the one hand, and
verbs and adverbs on the other (events-effects). On the Stoic view, the event is a pure
“result” or pure verb. When we say “a tree is becoming green,” we are not, for the
Stoics, designating a quality to a substance. The “greening” that sunlight, proper soil
conditions, and water produce in the tree is not a new property of the tree but a new
attribute, a new event that the tree is undergoing. In saying, “the tree becomes green,” we
are not identifying a being, but attributing to the tree a way of being or a form of
becoming.
This sense of this becoming, housed in the intransitive verb, is paradoxical. The
sense of “I am growing,” is that at the same time I am larger than I was and smaller than I
become. Of course, I only grow in one direction. But the sense of “ to grow” is not
reducible to the good sense of something in successive moments going from small to
large. The proposition also includes the possible sense that in the present I am at once
larger than I was but also smaller than I am (LS 2). This duplicity violates our sense of
Lewis Carroll’s Alice stories dramatize the play of sense and nonsense, for
Deleuze, because Alice is constantly torn between two directions: “Which way? Which
95
way?”, Alice says. Her adventures through the looking glass and down the rabbit hole
are adventures in what Deleuze calls the “paradoxes of pure becoming,” where sense is
not restricted to one direction, but is “nomadically” distributed in an open space, and in a
time which continually evades the present—a time constantly divided into a past that
never stops arriving and a future that never comes—which is why sometimes, as on the
Red Queen’s chessboard, Alice has to run very fast to stay in place.
two different times: Chronos and Aion. Chronos is the oriented time that distributes past
and future into two opposing directions. It is the time of the marketplace, the time of
agriculture, the time of the body’s movements, and the time of historical linearity. It is
the thick or “lived” present of phenomenology. In Chronos we always go from the past
to the future, from what was to what will be, in successive presents (LS 162-163).
from what is more or less obscure and undifferentiated to that which is more and more
universal history, but more simply what is conceived of as the “march of civilization.”
elimination of multiple directions in favor of one or several directions possible for limited
and bounded material configurations (a house being built, a young girl going through
puberty, a nation struggling for independence, a song being played on the radio).
But within Chronos another kind of time is passing, or “subsisting.” This is what
Deleuze calls the time of Aion. Aion is unlike Chronos in that it cannot be limited to the
succession of presents. Aion’s characteristic, as Deleuze puts it, is to elude the present
96
(LS 77). Aion infinitely subdivides itself into both past and future at once, so it can be
identified with neither (LS 164). Yet, Deleuze argues, Aion insists in an instant that
perpetually divides the present from itself. Aion is not the “passing” of the present as we
live it, but an instant that marks the present as present without itself passing. As Deleuze
puts it,
Plato rightly said that the instant is atopon, without place. It is the
paradoxical instance or the aleatory point, the nonsense of the surface and
the quasi-cause. It is the pure movement of abstraction whose role is,
primarily, to divide and subdivide every present in both directions at once,
into past-future, upon the line of Aion. (LS 166)
The proposition “Alice becomes larger,” denotes an event taking place in time.
But from the point of view of Chronos, the point of view of the actual growth of Alice in
the present, the proposition is missing half of its sense, namely that intransitive sense of
“growing” as heading in two directions simultaneously: Alice smaller than she becomes
as well as larger than she is now. If there were only a chrono-logical time, there would
be no coherent sense of grow-ing, but only an abysmal, measureless present, where the
past and future would be locked into the “now.” Only the measureless instant of Aion
makes possible the abstraction necessary for there to be a true sense of becoming, or a
Deleuze claims that language is possible due to this special sense of abstract
The straight line [of Aion] traces the frontier between bodies and
language, states of affairs and propositions. Language, or the system of
propositions, would not exist without this frontier which renders it
possible. (LS 167)
Events happen to bodies, but the sense of events takes place in language, in a system of
propositions whose existence is not “caused” by the interactions of bodies, but by a third
97
element—an element that the event causes to exist but that only subsists or “persists” in
Sense and event are the same thing—except that now [in Aion’s instant]
sense is related to propositions. It is related to propositions as that which
is expressible or expressed by them, which is entirely different from what
they signify, manifest, or denote. It is also entirely different from their
sonorous qualities, even though the independence of sonorous qualities
from things and bodies may be exclusively guaranteed by the entire
organization of the sense-event. (LS 167)
actual, but counter-actual: “the present of pure operation, not of incorporation” (LS 168).
If our personal identity is the character or persona we are inhabiting in accordance with
the requirements of the continuous present—the role we are playing that relates us to
other players and other roles through bodily causes—there is also, for Deleuze, the
identity, or rather the difference of an actor or dancer or mime who is able to identify with
or “counter-actualize” the present in a way that can change or pervert its sense. This
mimeur animates that which it mimes just as the sense-event is not the cause but the
“quasi-cause” of the proposition. Just as sense always “others” itself in the proposition
(or doubles itself in its own nonsense), “the sage can ‘identify’ with the quasi-cause,
although the quasi-cause itself is missing from its own identity” (LS 168). The “wisdom”
of the actor-dancer is not an escape from the character she plays, but is rather her ability
to redouble the role, or, as Deleuze puts it to “duplicate the lining [redoubler la
doublure]” of sense, to selectively activate a nonsense that frees sense from its restriction
What we have to learn from Alice is how to grasp ourselves as events, events with
multiple senses constituted by populations of singular forces that define themselves not in
98
opposition to others, but through unexpected relations of intensive distance between
them, not in the present of Chronos but in the instant of Aion. Deleuze thus sees in
To grasp the events of our lives as collective yet anonymous sets of singularities would
be to move beyond the fixation of the individual on an identifiable sense of self. For
Deleuze, unless our fixation on identity or our ego is overcome, we cannot fully actualize
authenticity, the imposition of a noble form on a chaotic depth. Within the platonic
dualism of Ideal Forms and participants which more or less reflect or embody those
Forms, Deleuze discerns a hidden distinction that silently controls and secretly directs the
major distinction between invisible model and visible copy (LS 256). This is the
distinction between that which, due to an ineffable quality perceivable only by the true
philosopher, potentially receives or reflects the idea, and those things that, due to an
99
equally ineffable quality, is perceived by the true philosopher not to be a worthy “suitor”
of the Idea.
This distinction is not so much among different discrete objects or persons, but
within suitors as a distinction between that which is able to receive the imprint or power
of the Idea, and that which is too unruly or inchoate for it. Unworthy suitors can never be
true images [icones] of the forms, but only idolatrous imposters. Only an ineffable
connection with the Good enables certain participants to do more than mimic or parrot
with the Forms themselves, there is no true but only simulacral participation in the
Forms.
becoming lurks in the good sense of propositions.89 Simulacra harbor a power truth
cannot oppose, because simulacra in and of themselves are not opposed to the truth.90
“perverse” identification, like the identification of Warhol’s Brillo boxes with Brillo
boxes in supermarkets. Warhol’s boxes are not “false appearances” of the real, but are
rather appearances which cannot be judged as either true or false renderings. As Deleuze
Simulacra inhibit our ability to make the distinction between model and copy.
potential icon) of the Idea than it is to distinguish the Ideal Model from its various
100
the rhapsode’s power cannot be specified in terms of the truth his words represent. The
murmuring or stammering prior to language. For Socrates language should have power
due only to its presentation of the natures to which any logos should ultimately refer.
The power of the rhapsode is in his master of effects, of linguistic effects that are not
ascertainable in terms of what is being talked about—the subject matter, the to ti on.
nomadic space. This is the proper realm of sense and its effects prior (ontologically, not
If Plato placed the origin of sense in the “heights” of the Forms, his task was to
explain the presence of the Forms even at the lowest levels of existence. Socrates
famously wondered whether there would not be a Form of hair or of mud. With his
“overturning” of Platonism, where the intensive and the singular in the empirical play the
role that the Forms played in Plato, for Deleuze the problem is not participation, but the
101
genesis of an effect that is not reducible to the medium in which it is nevertheless
constrained. This would be an account of the genesis of sense beyond its inherence in the
Rather than locate this sense at the “depths” of things (where it partly escapes or
them not as Forms descended from the heights of the immutable and eternal, but as
simulacra arising from the depths of physis to create a surface that is nevertheless no
longer reducible to the forces which produced it. These “Platonic ideas on the surface”
constitute the surface of sense. This surface of sense is Deleuze’s way of thinking
through Spinoza’s claim that the order of ideas and the order of things is the same. The
same, but only differentiated as bodies repeat themselves (their difference) at the surface,
Because sense is neither purely ideal nor fully concrete, sense is double, and
involves all the disguises of doubling. This duplicity makes sense reducible neither to
physical causes nor to ideas. Sense is not a smile without a Cheshire cat, as it is “down”
in the “depths” of the rabbit hole. It is rather the “transcendental” possibility of there
being a sense to both a cat with a smile and a smile without a cat, a name of a song and
what the name of the song is called, and an entrance to another world indistinguishable
from the empty space between the synapses of our brain. As Deleuze puts it,
The fact is that the doubling up [of sense] does not at all signify an
evanescent and disembodied resemblance, an image without flesh—like a
smile without a cat. It is rather defined by the production of surfaces, their
multiplication and consolidation. This doubling is the continuity of
reverse and right sides, the art of establishing this continuity in a way
which permits sense, at the surface, to be distributed to both sides at once,
as the expressed which subsists in propositions and as the event which
occurs in states of bodies. (LS 125)
102
In Deleuze’s analysis, sense is a “pure effect” of the conjunction of bodies and
propositions, but at the same time sense is paradoxically a “quasi-cause” of what happens
on both levels (bodies and propositions). It is a cause in the sense that a surface tension
Deleuze puts it, sense is a pure surface effect effective without being separate from other
effects, “since a surface energy, without even being of the surface, is due to every surface
formation, and from it a fictitious surface tension arises as a force exerting itself on the
plane of surface” (LS 124). Surface effects are a function of certain forces without being
reducible to those forces. Surface tensions, though in a sense heuristic fictions, are
nevertheless totally real, in the same way that the boiling point of water only exists as a
can and does fail. Surfaces that are not plastic enough, not flexible enough, or are
expected to bear more than they can, fall apart. Words then become alienated from
things. At an extreme, this is the nightmare of schizophrenia, in which the body and
Mania and depression signify the breakdown of the surface, our falling into one side or
the other. “Which way, which way?” asks Alice. How do we come to inhabit the
surfaces, the metaphysical surfaces, on which our bodies themselves can experience the
event as more than a state of affairs? How is it that our body can distinguish speaking
103
and eating? What are the dynamics that make our bodies susceptible of the adventure of
sense, of being the avatars and not merely the victims of events? How do sounds
become separated from bodily affects, from groans and cries? How can we come to live
In The Logic of Sense Deleuze points out that psycho-analysis from Freud to
Kline and Lacan linked the development of language to the emergence of sexually
organized bodies. Accordingly, Deleuze ties the emergence of language and even of
this is the terrain of sublimation: the processes by which bodies are conformed to socially
viable patterns; and by which our drives to consume and our fears of being consumed
come to be regulated. The energies persist, but they exceed the body’s primary functions
For Deleuze and for psycho-analysis, all of this begins in sexuality. On the
Freudian view, sexuality itself is not something “natural” to the body, but something that
destructive activities to activities which, while connecting with the environment and with
104
others, and even taking from others, do not destroy but enjoy. Such is the transition from
suction to sucking in the oral zone, or from urination to insemination in the genital zone.
Melanie Klein proposed that at its earliest moments the infant experiences itself as
composed of fragmented objects (LS 187). Each child, she proposes, is originally a
paranoid schizophrenic (LS 187). What she means by this, according to Deleuze, is that
the child experiences the world initially as a void in which aliment and excrement
circulate without fixable reference point—the mouth, breast, anus, penis from which
things come and into which they go are only so many voids, given that the child does not
yet distinguish between her body and the body of the mother. This existence-in-void
makes all the “objects” of this early stage partial or “simulacral”— images without
Klein hypothesized that the child experiences partial objects as threats, as poisons
or toxins that threaten more than nourish, fragments of the mother’s body that rend and
tear the body from the inside more than restore its tissues and fibers. What comes out of
the mother fragments her; what I take into myself fragments me. Mother and child share
a Passion of direct bodily communication that is the endless Fracture of parts, bits, and
crumbs.
For Klein, if the child cannot move beyond the trauma of this “system of
introjection and projection,” she remains locked into cannibalistic and anally-fixated
that the way beyond the sufferings of this deep bodily identification (I and the Mother are
Vortex and Void) is the simultaneous discovery and production of an object that is whole
in and of itself. The image of this object becomes a source of consolation and inspiration,
105
a point around which the child can orient the adventures of the body, a surface which can
tie together the disparate organs. The name psychoanalysis in its sublime chauvinism has
given this image is “phallus.” Like a platonic form, the phallus is the ideal sexual organ
which all other organs (from penises to vaginas and every orifice in between) more or
Just as Hercules has to pacify the earth, so Oedipus has to pacify his body and the
bodies of his parents. But in the very act of having intentions, of developing an Idea such
as Oedipus did, lies the secret of thought itself and its liberating power. Oedipus makes a
phantasm, a work of art. Or at least, that is what the capabilities which ruined Oedipus
might amount to if we can pass from the problem of restoring our parents to something
else: “From the question ‘Shall I marry Albertine?’ to the problem of the work of art yet
to be made—this is the path of enacting the speculative coupling, beginning with the
sexual pair, and retracing the path of divine creation “ (LS 220). The paradox is that
immanent to the very dynamic of the Oedipal triangle and its castration complex are the
Art, or the literary-speculative work involves a leap from the sexualized surface
on which everything happens to the desexualized surface where everything insists. Art is
our complexes, something other than universal neurosis. For Deleuze it is art that
extracts a question from our lives, a question which exceeds all “tragic” insight into the
impossibility of narcissistic desire. The great Work leads us from “the cause of
symptoms to the quasi-cause of the oeuvre . . . the positive, highly affirmative character
106
investment” (LS 238). It is Oedipus’ phantasmatic energy itself, the desire to think, and
to create, that can be doubled by and in art; it is art that enables us to use the energy
otherwise than to restore the family (which is always to destroy it, to absorb it, and to
avenge ourselves upon it.) The mystery is how do we make the leap? How does a space
or a surface appear tertiary to the rumbling devouring depths of our bodies (and the
image of the wounded mother) and the absent Idea of good and complete objects (figured
in the removed and complete father)? How is it that this dualism of sense (to eat/to
speak) is traversed by a nonsense we enjoy for its own sake, and not for what it can do for
Again, it is art that best poses the question. As Deleuze puts it, “from the
perspective of Freud’s genius, it is not the complex with provides us information about
Oedipus and Hamlet, but rather Oedipus and Hamlet who provide us with information
about the complex” (LS 237). And the information Deleuze attempts to analyze in the
Logic of Sense is the way in which the absurd or obverse side of “meaning” is not at all a
body parts or orifices and to the way in which all “desexualized” thought also signifies a
sexual meaning at the same time. This is the “perverse” character of sense, but it is also
the logic of becoming who we are, as a self-engendering species. The Alice stories
diagram the splendid neutrality of the verb. Alice literally enters into a realm we
short, false wholes. The Phallus is the master of all phantasms, what Lacan called the
107
simultaneously being impossible to signify directly (no penis is ever the phallus) and
insinuating itself everywhere (all language has a perverse core of sexual reference). The
Oedipal drama is the phantasm par excellence. Despite the fact that incest, castration,
etc. really do happen, the imagined event, the phantasm, is not ever wholly derivative
from these bodily “states of affairs.” The phantasm has an autonomy as pure “result,”
signified by the neutrality of the sense of Oedipus’s adventures—by the fact that his
Deleuze argues that “to Oedipalize,” like “to live,” “to see,” “to be castrated,” are
events that remain superior to both the bodies which incarnate them and the propositional
language that expresses events as having taken place at various chronological points.
Psychoanalysis has power because it deals directly with phantasms as realities (even
though Freud often wrote as if empirical causes were more important in developmental
happens to us but how we have imagined, or how we have made sense of what has
happened. Far from weakening its diagnoses, the “mythological” terms or “archetypes” in
terms of which it enables us to approach our lives give us the only power we have to
change what is real for us, given that the ultimate form of experience is not a
implies. What is the nature of the reality, he wonders, in which we can only change
forms? What kind of world does the logic of psychoanalytic symptomology refer to?
108
Deleuze’s answer is that it is a world that is constructed not according to the logic
ontological problems and questions which correspond to language” (LS 215). This world
or regime of sense, superior to bodies while being the result of bodily affections,
irreducible to propositions while never existing apart from them, is more concrete than
any one body living, dying, eating, or speaking, and paradoxically more ideal than any
only as true as is the fact that it is not our body taken simply as organism or physical
system that undergoes destiny, but rather a particularized or singularized body, a body cut
or wounded in a specific way that is the “objective correlative” of sense. It is our body as
more or less sexualized, as more or less “normalized” or “integrated.” This is why the
image-surface that can coordinate, restore, and re-connect the absent father and the
wounded mother as effects or results of his own “good intentions.” This gesture is
equivalent to the “adsorption” of his phallus into the life of signs which will compensate
for the impossibility of having the mother and/or being the father.
It is the way we become able to surface and re-surface our bodies, or through our
bodies, that interests Deleuze, because for him this is what finally amounts to “thought.”
109
actualization.” It is an active engagement not so much with “the material world”
understood in a brutely concrete sense, nor an engagement with “the history of ideas” or
Thought is phantasmatic because only the phantasm gives us the power and
capacity to move beyond “what happens” without escaping into the heights of mania or
falling into the depths of depression. Oedipus had attempted to create a surface, but
insofar as this surface is directly or “literally” the restoration of either his own personal
body (the concrete Thing) or the restoration of the kingdom (the Idea of the family), the
result can only be a tragic failure. In order to achieve a humorous or healthy result, the
What is initially only the drive-energy of a narcisstic libido has to become “desexualized”
energy, energy available for symbolic activity. Deleuze talks about this in terms of the
development of a second screen, beyond that of the body, onto which phantasms may
become projected. This is the surface proper to thought and the site of cuts which do not
destroy but create—cuts like those made on a film or a canvas or on audio tape in a
studio.
This new or second screen emerges ex nihilo. The body itself, even the
sexualized body, cannot serve as the basis of thought, despite the fact that sexuality will
be the source of the energy of thought. “There is thus a leap,” Deleuze writes (LS 218).
void” (LS 218). To think is thus to play, but to play precisely with what is most serious:
our fate. What the thinker as much as the artist knows is how to do this without playing
110
For only thought finds it possible to affirm all chance and to make chance
into an object of affirmation. If one tries to play this game other than in
thought, nothing happens; and if one tries to produce a result other than
the work of art, nothing is produced. This game is reserved then for
thought and art. In it there is nothing but victories for those who know
how to play, that is, how to affirm and ramify chance, instead of dividing
it in order to dominate it, nor in order to wager, in order to win. This
game, which can only exist in thought and which has no other result than
the work of art, is also that which thought and art are real and disturbing
reality, morality and the economy of the world. (LS 60)
kingdom and lead it. He wants to wager, win, and dominate. So do our egos, which is
why “morality” has to pass beyond the terms in which it is traditionally conceived. This
comes to the heart of the problem: how is it that Oedipus’ narcissistic wound can come
to be a source of creativity and not of destruction? Insofar as we literally try to repair the
mother or avenge ourselves on the father—to substantiate our egos—we destroy the
world. We seem “forced” into this program by the castration complex itself. If we want
to heal ourselves, we have to return to the sword that cut us. But for Deleuze, “we are
character of the self is not the sign of impotence but of potential? What if its wound is
the aperture by which cosmic forces come into play and are unleashed? What if our
revenge?
For Deleuze, the whole of ethics consists, in away, of a refusal of revenge. Ethics
for Deleuze is a becoming-worthy of the peculiar adventures that befall us. Nietzsche
111
once called this amor fati (LS 149). For Deleuze this is an ethics of humor, not of irony.
For Deleuze, humor always involves active selection as opposed to passive reflection.
brings back the hell-hound and the celestial hound, the serpent of hell and the serpent of
the heavens. It is no longer a question of Dionysius down below or Apollo up above, but
of Hercules on the surface, in his dual battle against both depth and height: reorientation
in Lewis Carroll’s brand of nonsense, which plays superficially with the paradoxes of
language and sense. Even though this kind of nonsense seems “superficial” compared to
the deeper, seemingly more profound “absurd” of Camus or even the cries and groans of
Artaud, Carroll’s nonsense is a more important guide to a humorous and healthy thought.
In Camus’ existentialism, for Deleuze, there is never enough sense—sense has been
banished to the heights of an absent God (as opposed to being lost in the depths of a
Film auteurs such as Goddard and Fellini gave us a new sense of the surface, and
a new humor in a world where the link between body and mind seems ravaged by war
and traumatized by destruction. How does the film auteur restore the broken link
between humanity and world? Not by acting but by seeing. The images of the avant-
garde are not images of movement (of action, of emotions, even of memories). They are
112
images that have broken with the sensory-motor link, the link between perception and
action. Not originals, not representations: simulacra. Images that reveal to us the nature
of the time we are living even though we can no longer react to the bizarre, uncanny, and
situation—his need to act indirectly, through images, paradoxically makes him able to
restore our faith in the world. How? Because the images of the world he or she extracts
body, a subtle body, to replace (if not to recover) the bodies broken by the horrors of war
Our belief can have no other object than ‘the flesh,’ we need very special
reasons to make us believe in the body (‘the Angels do not know, for all
true knowledge is obscure . . .’). We must believe in the body, but as in
the germ of life, the seed which splits open the paving-stones, which has
been preserved and lives on in the holy shroud or the mummy’s bandages,
and which bears witness to life, in this world as it is. We need an ethic or
a faith, which makes fools laugh; it is not a need to believe in something
else, but a need to believe in this world, of which fools are a part. (C2
173)
Filmmakers like Resnais, Welles, Goddard, and Fellini enable us to pose a new
in the affirmations of human volition what was lost in the rejection of divine
benevolence, then for Deleuze (as for Foucault and Nietzsche) this only substituted for
the lost God a Man as limiting to life and expression as ever was the old divine Being.
To think in terms of this “man” is still the attempt to discern or receive a meaning that is
given apart from its production—whether this meaning is discerned beyond Man’s
betrayal of the gods or beyond the gods apparent indifference to humanity makes no
113
difference; in both cases we turn away from the real game, what Nietzsche called the
“ideal game,” which is played out by events that engender meaning, below God and
For Deleuze, the act of turning our attention to this surface—the achievement of
certain art forms—is more liberating and empowering than any attempt to plumb the
depths of the human personality or to scale the heights of contemplating the divine
attributes. Deleuze reserves some of his most passionate writing for this point.
And how could we not feel that our freedom and strength reside, not in the
divine universality nor in the human personality, but in these singularities
which are more us than we ourselves are, more divine than the gods, as
they animate concretely poem and aphorism, permanent revolution and
partial action? What is bureaucratic in these fantastic machines which are
peoples and poems? It suffices that we dissipate ourselves a little, that we
be able to be at the surface, that we stretch our skin like a drum, in order
that the “great politics” begin. An empty square for neither man nor God;
singularities which are neither general nor individual, neither personal nor
universal. All of this is traversed by circulations, echoes, events which
produce more sense, more freedom, and more strength than man has ever
dreamed of, or God ever conceived. Today’s task is to make the empty
square circulate and to make pre-individual and nonpersonal singularities
speak—in short, to produce sense. (LS 72-73)
In the next chapter, “Writing Power,” we will examine how Deleuze, along with his
collaborator Felix Guattari, analyzes the possibilities for the production of sense in the
context of capitalism. If capitalism co-opts the power of creativity and the logic of
surfaces, what power might art have to produce singularities that would escape the
machinations of marketeering? What aesthetic gesture could possibly thwart the re-
territorializing powers of capital? This is the question that will occupy us next.
114
V. Writing Power: Desire and the Signs of Life
and Bataille, to Foucault, Deleuze, and Derrida) starts with the notion that in modernity
the formalities of writing, or the structures and strictures of representation, generally, are
in a conflictual relationship with the forces words and images harbor. According to the
analysis of these thinkers (despite their variations) in modernity this conflict cannot be
which words and things are represented from being itself a matter of scrutiny. In the so-
called “postmodern” thought associated with these French names, the conflicts of
For Jacques Derrida, for example, the representational model breaks down due to
or forward (in time) to an order of connection between words and things that, if always
already interrupted by the binary paradigms constituting signifiers and making signs
and the promise of a significance always a venir, yet to come. For Derrida, the liberation
of a life dead within signs is an after-effect of meaning’s divergence from itself, of its
deferred and supplemental character, he does not see the partial or fragmented characters
master tongue. In fact the master tongue (institutional, bureaucratic, legalistic) is for
115
Deleuze but the parrot of a more profound writing power, a power proper to the ancient
shamans and priest-kings manifest in modern times in the anguished and tortured psyches
of schizophrenics, in the play of children, and in the exploits of experimental art forms.
This positive (if obscure) writing power comes to the fore, for Deleuze and his
collaborator Felix Guattari, as an effect of capitalism’s powerful grip over a level of our
psyches much deeper than the conscious ego. Although overtly an attack on fascism in
Oedipus is also a positive project, co-extensive with that begun in The Logic of Sense.
This positive project is an attempt to explicate the logic of a primitive (in the French
and effective without yet being despotic As we began to see in our reading of the Logic
regimes of signs that, though not yet significant in the sense of being tied to a master
signifier or centralized set of meanings nevertheless has a primitive and aboriginal power
of expression.
116
The Positive Unconscious
According to the “ethics” Deleuze constructs in The Logic of Sense, the problem
of health is a question of how to create livable surfaces. Not exactly the surface of the
“lived” body, nor the purely mental surface of abstract ideas, but a metaphysical surface
of sense. The creation of sense is a movement of “desexualization” that goes from the
connective relationships in the body to conjunctive series built up not through bodily
passes from a genital organization to an organization of surfaces that places the genital
series in the service of a guiding image that the sexual energies are meant to ramify or
realize. Here the Oedipal drama commences wherein the child attempts to restore the
image of the wounded mother and to retrieve the image of the absent father (which is
finally a way of attaining or achieving a phallus). But the adolescent affair, which issues
in the “choice of an external object” continually recalls the original adventures of the
primary order, whose traumatic emergence energizes the creation of the Oedipal surface
or “stage.”
The significance of this process, for Deleuze, is not so much the development of
the Oedipal phantasm per se, nor the achievement of the repetition of the family unit. For
Deleuze, Oedipus represents only what he calls a “negative” and “limitative” of the
disjunctive power (the desexualization process that enables the transmutation of inchoate
117
drive into explicit desire) (LS 229). With psychoanalyst Felix Guattari, Deleuze will
even claim that Oedipus is not the resolution of desire, but “an exploded triangle from
which the flows of desire escape in the direction of other territories” (AI 96). What
misrecognition, but the epic or even comic possibilities that also emerge at the “Oedipal
stage.” This is the potential of thought to positively and affirmatively use the disjunction
not just to restore the family trinity but to create other unforeseen relationships,
because the phantasmatic energies used up in the consolidation of Oedipus are cosmic or
better acosmic forces that always already exceed the familial triangle. The forces of
desire that are at first recognized in terms of mommy-daddy-me do not originate in that
triune enclosure, but come from and return to a cosmic outside of the triangle. To join
with these cosmic and world-historical forces, forces of desire which overflow Oedipal
materialist twist to perversion, arguing that, in the face of a capitalism that constantly co-
opts our representable desires, we must embrace a bit more the schizophrenia lurking
behind our everyday neuroses. “A schizophrenic out for a walk is a better model of than
a neurotic lying on the couch,” Deleuze and Guattari write (AO 2). Why schizophrenia,
schizoanalysis, rather than neurosis and psychoanalysis? Deleuze and Guattari justify
118
the problem is not resolved until we do away with both the problem and
the solution. It is not the purpose of schizoanalysis to resolve Oedipus, it
does not intend to resolve it better than Oedipal psychoanalysis does. Its
aim is to de-Oedipalize the unconscious in order to reach the real
problems. Schizoanalysis proposes to reach those regions of the orphan
unconscious—indeed “beyond all law”—where the problem of Oedipus
can no longer even be raised. (AI 82)
For Deleuze and Guattari, the “schizoid” form of organization, though more
volatile and uncanny than that of the neurotic, is closer to the real essence of the
unconscious. The unconscious, they argue, is populated not by precursors and ruins of
the Oedipal romance, the drama of restoring the mother and displacing the despotic
father, but the cosmic play of autonomous or “orphaned” realms of sense and nonsense.
The unconscious, for Deleuze and Guattari, is made of signs, but the signs are not
organized “like a language,” but like a jargon or an idiom missing the “master tongue” or
[signifiance], they argue, is actually a break. Thus the only direct connections in the
Bruno Bettleheim’s patient little Joey puts it, is the riddle of the unconscious (AO 37).
For Deleuze and Guattari, there is no negativity in the unconscious. On their view
even Freud’s famous supposition of a death instinct that pervades the unconscious is a
positive force or what Deleuze and Guattari will call a “desiring-machine.” Deleuze and
119
machine and the system of its energetic conversions, and not as an
abstract principle. (AO 332)
For Deleuze and Guattari, death is not a force of negativity but an autonomous principle
which, along with other principles, plays a role in those “desiring machines” in which the
a homogeneity of effects of the death instinct while arguing over its one true cause,
Deleuze and Guattari claim that what must be realized is precisely the multiplicity of the
For traditional psychoanalysis, “everybody knows” that the death instinct shows
different types (sadistic, masochistic, depressive) achieve this pleasure, in a given case.
For Deleuze and Guattari, on the contrary, the unconscious presents us with an
overabundance of “sufficient reasons” for the death drive in dreams, in art, in obsessions,
in repetitions. “As the authors of horror stories have understood so well,” they write, “it
is not death that serves as a model for catatonia, it is catatonic schizophrenia that gives its
model to death” (AO 329). Or, as Deleuze puts it in the Logic of Sense, it was Freud’s
genius to realize that Hamlet and Oedipus do not show us the meaning of neurosis,
“neurosis” explains something of Hamlet and Oedipus. What must be evaluated are the
uses to which the death drive is put, relative to different bodies, different arrangements of
view of the unconscious, forces are not seen as typified or allegorized in the figures of
desire.
120
Capitalism and Schizophrenia
For Deleuze and Guattari, the “evil genius” of capitalism is that it knows the
secret of unconscious identification, which consists not in the struggle for recognition but
in the ecstasy of production. As Marx put it, capitalism is the society of producers. In
capitalism, the ultimate terms of social representation, the countable identity, is no longer
a function of recognition in an Other (the Nation, the Family, the Father) but a function of
aspect of identity (i.e. its “natural resource”) need no longer be conceived in terms of the
Hegel had already posited the idea that desire is inherently relational: my desire
for an object is motivated by another’s desire for the same object. We are all either
Misrecognition is built as it were, into our conatus essendi. For a Christian like Rene
Girard, this is a consequence of the Fall, but even an atheist Hegelian like Slavoj Zizek
agrees that the “deadlock” of desire, in terms of which we are bound to desire that which
is prohibited to us, can only be undone by a kind of grace (even the grace of analytical
121
In Anti-Oedipus, Deleuze and Guattari set out to deny not that desire is relational,
but to deny that its drama need be played out in the way imagined by Hegel and Freud, in
terms of a struggle for recognition by an Other. For Deleuze and Guattari, this struggle is
neither ontologically nor psychologically basic, as both Hegel and Freud thought it was.
For Deleuze and Guattari, capitalism exposes the fact that recognition is not mediated
reflection but a produced effect. In capitalism, desire does not fill in for but rather
continuously re-produces a gap within. This gap is not between subjectivities but a gap
within objects themselves, creating an ambiguity or lure in things that is their potential as
a commodity. This is the sense in which everything on the market is a “partial object,” a
intensive rather than either qualitative or quantitative, a hook-up point for styles and
It is not to the depressed or the neurotic that advertising is addressed, but to the
schizophrenic best exemplifies both the suffering and the ecstasy of desire. That which
the schizo eats rots into words, that which she says cuts her mouth like a sharp tin can.
The schizo has lost the surface of sense, the metaphysical screen between words and
things. Fallen into the depth of words and lost in the heights of objects, the schizo lives
on, in, and by the flows of partial objects. This is her ecstasy and her terror.
form common to the discourse of schizophrenics: this burger is a burger. What becomes
obvious to all in the advertisement is what is obvious to the schizo: when you eat that
burger you are eating McDonald’s, when you drink that coffee you are drinking
122
Starbucks. You don’t blow your nose with a tissue but with a Kleenex. You don’t drive
a car, you drive a Honda). You eat food, but more importantly you eat the label. Or the
label eats you, which is why the schizo feels like her mouth is being cut up when she says
“knife.” Instead she says “cateau” (couteau would be too close to the real thing).
The schizophrenic has a magical (if terrorized) relationship with reality, where the
word is the thing.93 At the heart of schizoid experience is what Deleuze and Guattari call
the experience of a “body without organs.” This does not mean that the schizo has no
organs, but that the schizo does not refer the organs to one another in terms of an
“organism.” Rather, for the schizo the organs are “partial objects.” Developmentally
speaking, schizophrenics are frozen in that phase where children experience objects not
can be a flow of love or desire, or it can be a physical flow (of urine, of food, of toys
given and received, etc.) None of these things contain their being in and for themselves.
Feces is a partial object: it does not contain the essence of its being in itself, but in
something else. It must be referred to a mouth or an anus to be what it is. Therefore its
being is constantly in flux. Partial objects are flows, becomings, “multiplicities” in the
sense that their being is constantly being differentiated and repeated (or as Derrida would
say, “supplemented”) along a series of actions or events. An organ like the mouth is a
partial object when it functions in connection with other organs or other objects in ways
123
that are not dominated by its “proper” role in the organism (i.e. the anorexic shits through
her mouth).
Considered with respect to the organism, the organs represent quantitative and
extensive limits to how energy can flow in, out, and between parts of the body.
Considered in relative autonomy from the organism (an autonomy taken to extremes by
the paranoiac schizo), the organs are intensive quantities defined only by how those
intensives connect, disjunct, and combine. For Deleuze and Guattari, the body without
organs (BwO) is the “place” or the “field” (complexe) where nonorganized, noncenetered
flows take place. As the “matter” that fills in and flows between partial objects, the BwO
is also the “raw material” of the organs (AO 326). The BwO is the “whole” of the flows,
rather a glorious or astral body that exists alongside the partial objects, the flows. If
partial objects are like the phrases of a song, the body without organs (the “immobile
motor” [AO 327]) is like the limit of the various ways in which the song can be
Although there are different strategies for composing on the BwO, its composition
always begins with a decoding of dominant or “master” codes. The BwO constitutes
minor or molecular chains or regimes of sings, opposed to the despotic chains linking
124
body without organs and as yet form no structured configuration—or
rather, they form one no longer.” (AO 328)
But this is not pure anarchy or pure chaos. It is anarchy crowned, and a chaosmos
constructed not from the logic of essence but of accident, not of being but of becoming.
Is there a naming or a language proper to the flows on the BwO, or is the “proper”
autochthonous code on the BwO? Much is at stake for Deleuze and Guattari in this
On the BwO, an intensive space with which the schizophrenic is tragically familiar,
proper names do not refer to but in some sense are regions, thresholds, or effects in a
Shaman operates a healing ritual. Here names are never references to static entities, but
125
Force and Signification
seems to deny the possibility of this kind of naming, a “proper” naming of the force of
becoming. In an early and important essay, “Form and Signification,” Derrida writes:
Derrida’s argument here is essentially that “force” and “phenomenon” can be tautologies,
but “force” and “signification” cannot. On Derrida’s view, force is the “other” of
signification. This means that signification distinguishes itself by not being force (being
pure sense), but only by denying its own inherent force, a force which appears only
For Deleuze and Guattari, the immanent codes of becoming indeed appear as the
For Derrida, the history of both natural and human sciences in the West is the story of
how dualistic oppositions such as those between “force” and “signification” (as well as
between essence and accident, form and content, speech and writing) are held in place by
126
a logic of “supplement.” Every manifest dualism in signification is subject to a logic
whereby the identity of the superior or master term (male, essence, form, signification,
term (female, accident, content, force, etc.) which leaves that term with no inherent
Derrida’s premise, at least in his early works, is that the cornerstone of this
unstable dualistic edifice in Western thought is a dualism between writing and speech
that in some sense causes all the other dualisms, in the sense that an unconscious trauma
causes conscious mishaps. There is thus a “symptom” of Western discourse that makes it
“absence” encoded in writing and the “presence” presumed in speech. If the “presence”
death of being in signs. For Derrida, this problematic can be traced not only in Platonic
anxiety about writing, but in “onto-theological” anxiety about the relationship between
God and the signs of revelation (for Derrida, why we don’t see the platonic forms directly
philosophy per se, Derrida sees the entire history of Western thought as governed by the
notion that writing fails to capture the essence of being. Following Heidegger, Derrida
argues that we will never know whether there is a being outside of our conception of
being, and we cannot conceive of being without “writing” it. Since the only being we
among signs. Signs can never be what they say. Signs are inherently violent to
127
themselves and do violence to “things” in such a way that there are no things before or
For Derrida, This violence inherent to signification (and repressed by it) has a
repose or a settling of the “Dionysian” forces that give rise to thought, then the impulse to
structure), the force of thought itself is always somehow betrayed or abused by its own
self-presentation. For Derrida, writing can never be purely Dionysian: if the force that is
Dionysian unity of force “in itself” is something always already lost in reflection, in a
seeing that is always already a tearing out of the eyes, a dismembering of what
that “all is Dionysus” can be true only in the sense that force is internally castrated and
128
Beyond the Despotic Regime: Incantatory Signs
For Deleuze and Guattari, force and signification are not opposed: it is a matter
of two kinds of what they dub “vocal-graphic power.” According to its magical and
invocational powers, the voice retains the dominance proper to it, its power to tattoo or
cut into reality, but not to survey or represent it. This power is opposed to (or doubled
by) a despotic graphism that dominates the voice (the song, the refrain, the chant). As
In one case there is a dynamic, magical interplay between vocal and graphic powers,
mediated by the eye or by a vision that sees the effect of the word on things, on the other
hand a reading of the effect of things-as-words (AO 204).95 But the graphism that
remains subordinate to voice (although not necessarily a human voice, but a voice
despotic form of representation, in which the eye no longer sees but reads the world (AO
206). With despotism there is an absorption (as opposed to the positive, magical
“adsorption”) of the voice by writing, and a reduction of things to signs which makes
writing present in the voice at the cost of making the voice absent when it speaks. As
129
In the first place, graphism aligns itself on the voice, falls back on the
voice and becomes writing. At the same time it induces the voice no
longer as the voice of alliance, but as that of a new alliance, that of direct
filiations . . . Then there occurs a crushing of the magic triangle; the voice
no longer sings but dictates, decrees; the graphy no longer dances, it
ceases to animate bodies, but is set into writing on tablets, stones, and
books, the eye sets itself to reading. (AO 203)
In other words, in despotic signification writing buries the voice while the voice haunts
writing—it is this situation that Jacques Derrida found interminable, original, and
irreducible (AI 203).96 If for Derrida writing perennially repeats the loss of the magic
triangle (connecting voice, graphy, and eye), for Deleuze and Guattari this is not an
eyes on him,” to make the magic of meaning the despotic consolidation of magic. Under
desire, we never had: a circuit between desire and object without reference to the desire
of the Other, the despotic Other. As in Sophocles’ Antigone, incestuous desire, where
desire for the sister or the brother comes to name the suicidal hallucination of (com)union
But because Deleuze and Guattari distinguish between historically emergent and
contingently structured orders of representation, they can bypass the Derridean (and
Oedipal) crux. Deleuze and Guattari need not reduce all graphism to writing or all desire
to desire of the Other’s desires. For Deleuze and Guattari, desire only becomes the
other’s desire (and the unconscious only becomes Oedipal) under despotic conditions of
representation.
130
As Deleuze and Guattari will analyze it in A Thousand Plateaus, all societies
societies these binary machines never operate for their own sake. It is only in modern
state societies that a form of organization emerges that takes the development of binary
oppositions as a goal and not as the means of various activities. It is true that the shaman
plants a tree between his legs, and draws power to himself. But the circles of activity
The segmentarity becomes rigid, to the extent that all centers resonate in,
and all black holes fall on, a single point of accumulation that is like a
point of intersection somewhere behind the eyes. The face of the father,
teacher, colonel, boss, enter into redundancy, refer back to a center whose
center is everywhere and whose circumference is nowhere. There are no
longer n eyes in the sky, or in becomings-animal and
-vegetable, but a central computing eye scanning all of the radii. (ATP
211)
The modern, bureaucratic form of organization tends to force all the circles to resonate
with each other. For Deleuze and Guattari, what is important is not that primitive
societies don’t have power centers, but that the apparatuses of primitive power resist or
“inhibit” translations of one form of power into another. The power is as different as the
things which concern it (“depending on the task and the situation” [ATP 209]), even if it
centralized and a segmented society, but between two different organizing principles, two
131
But there is another graphism, that of the “primitive territorial sign.” This sign is
In territorial sign-making, glyphs establish a nexus between peoples and milieus. But
societies become set on forming networks of mobile signs, equivocal and analogical
signs, that no longer require re-enactment for their meaning (AO 204).97 In territorial as
opposed to imperial signs, what is at stake is perpetual and collective work, not the
“expression” of a national consciousness which “reflects” its essence. However, with the
development of nations all performance, all ritual, and all magic becomes transformed
into arbitrarily erected structures of “meaning” which offer not the things we desire but
The way that Jose Gil described his anthropological research into how human
Deleuze’s project of reading power in this way. In his Metamorphoses of the Body, Gil,
. . .the relationship between signs and the forces that underpin them has
not been sufficiently studied, and yet, whether it is a question of stories,
rituals, art, or raptures, their signs appear to be shot through with
particularly intense investments of affectivities, to the point where one is
tempted to take their affectivities as their characteristic traits. (Gil 88)
In Gil’s study of the signs used in healing rituals, he finds that force and signification
cannot be opposed. Why are signs forceful? Why do we speak of them as “arresting”
132
us? Are we forced to make meaning? Is meaning itself a force? These questions arise
whenever we abandon the idea that meaning or interpretation is something cultures and
individuals do for its own sake, rather than for the sake of doing work.
But what if the plurality of sign systems, of systems of “meaning,” is due neither
to the sheer contingencies of nature (physical energy or force) nor to the arbitrary
necessities of cultural concepts (ideas or concepts), but to a power specific to the manner
in which and the purposes for which signs are produced or emitted? This would point to
a third term between nature and culture that would nevertheless not be a “mediator” but
rather an “operator,” what Deleuze calls the “quasi-cause.” It would be a matter not of
discovering what signs refer to (functions, structures, meaning systems), or what coerces
them (arbitrary will), but rather a matter of asking how signs are meant to direct and
redirect the work of bodies, never for its own sake (Hegel’s master) or simply for the
sake of work itself (Hegel’s slave), but for the sake of other work. Here is how Gil
explains it.
Now, what “work” does the operator do? It acts on a force and on its
internal features and places it in communication with other forces. The
first aspect refers to another characteristic of forces: their intensity has the
property of being able to grow or diminish without changing in nature.
This means it has the capacity to work with internal differentiations or
rhythmic heterogeneities without losing its wholeness or even creating a
division in its heart. The intensity of a force is not enough to give birth to
meaning (force would not have this privilege of being able to produce
meaning all by itself). For that to come about, some other limitation
would have to apply to the intensity of forces. This limitation would be
the result of its opposition to external force, and the “remainder” would
add to the internal gap a double determination. It gives the force an
orientation and, coming from the outside with an absolute limit,
recalibrates the system of internal gaps around (while opening it up to)
another system of references.
As precipitate of the remainder, the sign thus refers both to another
system of signs and to a relation of forces. It refers to a relation of forces
because it is the result of whatever flies off from the struggle between two
133
specific forces. It refers, by itself, to a body of signs because it is the
result of a transformation of determinations which are internal to force. In
starting up this transformation in this way the operator paradoxically
makes a force meaningful for a force of the same type, and at the same
time makes it susceptible to the actions of other external operators. This is
where the translatability of the sign comes from, why it is treated
“fetishistically,” giving it the power to mean all by itself (Thesis) and
making it dependent on forces (Antithesis). (MB 12)
Why is the power of a sorcerer or magician to give or take life described in a set of signs
that belong to magic or sorcery alone? Why is the ethnologist’s attempt to reduce the
always frustrated? Is this the weakness of words or the power of force? What if this is
because forces are already meaningful, paradigmatically in magic and sorcery, where
“forces don’t have to be signified; they signify” (M 18)? Gil hypothesizes that “the
discourses of the magician and the bewitched draw their powers and their effectiveness
from the region where the surplus of meaning becomes mingled with the surplus of
force” (18). This is a magical space, a space of healing as much as destructive power.
But both territorial and despotic forms of signification are immanent “planes of
consistency.” The imperial despot as much as the territorial leader makes use of the
subordinates all connections to connection with or through the despot, the desire of the
despot, the desire which, like the voice, can no longer be experienced as belonging to
anyone, and even more importantly cannot directly connect with things.
134
Writing Without Other: Unconscious Magic, Pragmatic Signs
partial objects and decoded flows does not necessarily deny Derrida’s insistence that
Dionysus is a terrifying, even violent passage into membra disjecta. The Body without
Organs certainly consists in decoded flows and asignifying chains of signs, the passage
into which is fraught with danger and suffering. But the point of Anti-Oedipus is not to
revel in that violence or that suffering per se, but rather to show that there is a level of
signification that cannot be captured by the dualism between being and writing, force and
signification.
writing has an archaic model in ritual magic, as Jose Gil shows, but it also resonates in
the practice of making certain forms of contemporary art. In essence, the artist or
sorcerer “writes” or emits signs in a way that Derrida’s theory denies: as a form of
signification that is evidently force, as a force that is only as sign.99 It is precisely this
Oedipus precludes magic for the same reason that deconstruction obscures the
constructivist or pragmatic view of signs. Both the Oedipal paradigm and Derridean
every level of the emission or reproduction of signs. In the same way that for Freud,
135
every desire is always already either a precursor to or a failure of desire to be the father or
to restore the mother, for Derrida, every signification is always already either a violent
interruption of difference by the sign or a trace of that violence. Both Freud and Derrida
remain under the spell of Hegel’s opposition of Nature and Spirit. Nature is nothing but
am not yet the father; I both have and do not have the mother as my own; I say what I
mean but I distort what I refer to: meaning and/or desire is only ever remainder. The
refractions of familiar, familial forms. Even if it admits that other images become
present, “in the beginning” all the images are derived or derivative of parental images.
In Anti-Oedipus, Deleuze and Guattari argue that it was colonialism, our great
“excavation of the other” that exposed this “It is strange that we had to wait for the
dreams of colonized peoples,” Deleuze and Guattari write, “in order to see that, on the
vertices of the pseudo-triangle, mommy was dancing with the missionary, daddy was
being fucked by the tax collector, while the self was being beaten by a white man” (AO
96). For Deleuze and Guattari, the adventures of early childhood (no less than of the
unconscious itself) cannot be reduced to the family romance. Children already produce
(rather than represent or reflect) scenarios that use the parents in larger dramas, dramas
including the dreams and misfortunes of entire civilizations. As Deleuze and Guattari put
it,
136
Go back through the course of the ages, you will never find a child caught
in a familial order that is autonomous, expressive, or signifying. Even the
nursing child, in his games as in his feedings, his chains, and his
meditations, is already caught up in an immediate desiring-production
where the parents play the role of partial objects, witnesses, reporters, and
agents, in a process that outflanks them on all sides, and places desire in
an immediate relationship with a historical and social reality. It is true that
nothing is pre-oedipal, and that we must take Oedipus back to the earliest
age, but within the order of a repression of the unconscious. It is equally
true that everything within the order of production is anoedipal, and that
there are non-oedipal, anoedipal currents that begin as early as Oedipus
and continue just as long, with another rhythm, in a different mode of
operation, in another dimension, with other uses of syntheses that feed the
autoproduction of the unconscious—unconscious-as-orphan, the playful
unconscious, the meditative and social unconscious. (AO 100, emphasis
mine)
instructive, here. Lawrence (an orphan if ever there was one) fantasizes Arabian nights,
has homoerotic desire for Turks and turbans, has private dreams of vast empty sands and
epic adventures, and a masochistic love of pain. Yet these are not private delusions, but
with which they are equivocal. For Lawrence it is never “mommy-daddy-me.” It is Brit-
put it, “it is the function of the libido to invest the social field in unconscious forms,
thereby hallucinating all history, reproducing in delirium entire civilizations, races, and
continents, and intensely “feeling” the becoming of the world “ (AO 98).
political consequences of the Dreyfus Affair and of World War I other than in terms of
the Guermantes family, Proust shows the direct consequence of politics on the libidinal
scenario. Homosexual and heterosexual dynamics in a family are altered by the trauma
137
of world wars, and the wars are “sexualized” accordingly. The private is immediately the
public: the unconscious reality or virtuality of the events cuts across the distinctions
For Deleuze and Guattari, a new form of analysis is required to complete the
the distinction between public and private, ego histrionics and social history. It is the
schizophrenic who becomes all the names of history. The schizo’s private names (his
impossible words) are public things (the partial objects of the real). The family is only a
provoked by the family, but the response to the family “always comes from another
direction” (AO 98). The real forces of the unconscious, for Deleuze and Guattari, are
various social forms. This makes the questions children ask irreducible: Why are there
poor people? Why be rich? Who can be king? Why is Australia so far away?
King is your father, Australia is your mother, you’re poor because you’ve displeased
everything. Deleuze and Guattari protest: “rather a society of neurotics than one
successful schizophrenic who has not been made autistic” (AO 102). Reducing our
desires to Oedipal formations is how we are all kept gregarious, sociable, and how we are
138
convinced that all our energies belong to the attempt, however tragic, to become father to
ourselves.
But as long as we are trapped in “interpretation,” we are not yet thinking from the
point of view of the multiplicity, of the multiple desires and the varieties of productions
that Oedipus precludes. It is not Oedipus that determines its “reflections” in culture (the
boss as father, the Madonna as mother). Rather, Deleuze and Guattari write, “it is not the
father who is projected onto the boss, but the boss who is applied to the father, either in
order to tell us ‘you will not surpass the father’ or ‘you will surpass him to find our
Schizoanalysis looks for those places where our energies have been arbitrarily and
artificially consolidated under Oedipal constraints, and seeks to release desire that “cuts
across the interest of the dominated exploited classes, and causes flows to move that are
capable of breaking apart both the segregations and their Oedipal applications—flows
continents ablaze. No, I am not of your kind, I am the outsider and the deterritorialized,
“I am of a race inferior for all eternity . . . . I am a beast, a Negro” (AO 105). The Word
deterritorialized on the voice, the Logos deterritorialized on the hieroglyph, the opaque
pyramid become the translucent triangle. Schizoanalysis calls for a nomadic and
139
The Subtle Difference of Immanence
that “mimetic desire,” the desire of the other’s desire, as the root of all cultural and
political evil, and once wrote a passionate review of Anti-Oedipus which accused
Deleuze and Guattari of utopianism.101 As if they were asking us simply to break with
marked and tattooed, as the earth’s body is also transmuted by the events (cataclysms,
storms, upheavals, plate shifts) that traverse it. As if invited to an originary passivity, to
move back from represented States to territorial milieus, from the unconscious fixated on
But to think that Deleuze and Guattari are simply celebrating delirium, let alone a
“return to the mother” is a massive over-simplification of their point, and is also one they
take pains to specifically repudiate.103 For artists as much as politicians are involved in
contemporaneous and immediate de-and re-territorialization, and the delirium of the artist
pontifications of pundits. The ethics of the earth called for by Deleuze and Guattari is an
extremely subtle art of knowing how and when and where and why and under what
conditions to impose a little order on chaos, to do the same thing the despot does, but
differently. The paradox of the artist, and the child, is the practice of a non-despotic
imperialism. “A little order,” says Nietzsche.104 Artists especially must guard against the
fascist within (one thinks of the comic megalomania of Orson Welles as opposed to the
tragedy of Howard Hughes). As Deleuze and Guattari put it, “that is why the material
140
problem confronting schizoanalysis is knowing whether we having it within our means to
make the selection, to distinguish the BwO from its doubles: empty, vitreous bodies,
cancerous bodies, totalitarian and fascist” (ATP 165). The magical-Artaudian cruelty (or
manager, as Andy Warhol’s life, played out hysterically between these two poles, well
attests. The tragedy and comedy of our day is played out between these two figures.
They write “the test of desire: not denouncing false desires, but distinguishing within
destratification, and that which pertains to the construction of the plane of consistency
(keep an eye out for all that is fascist, even inside us, and also for the suicidal and the
demented)” (ATP 165).105 Two varieties of violence, two versions of cruelty, as in the
recent Russian film Night Watch, where the forces of light and darkness have the same
means at their disposal, and the distinction between them is nearly untraceable.106
This brings us to what is both the strongest and weakest aspect of Deleuze’s
experiment with concepts: “doubtless, anything is possible” (ATP 166). Deleuze heralds
the untrammeled power of materiality and demands that modern philosophy, rather than
developing transcendental logics, invent a set of immanent criteria that can be neither
formulated nor expressed apart from the experiment to which they give rise. But he also
speaks as if the totality of the BwO’s, the totality of our experiments, our plane(s) of
141
eventually (in some non-linear sense of eventual) only “non-cancerous” BwO’s would
remain. In an ambitious claim Deleuze and Guattari insist that “the plane is the totality of
the full BwO’s that have been selected (there is no positive totality including the
Parmenidean necessity, that has no alternate term (cannot be opposed by the contingent
or the arbitrary)? Once again we are confronted with the paradox that thinking through
assemblages and the planes on which they insist will be healthy or cancerous: we cannot
clarify the obscurity of their potentials; they cannot clarify our desire to actualize them in
the ways we do. In immanence, are we abandoned or free? This is the ambiguity of
not exactly a matter of chance, and not exactly fated.109 But it is a matter of being
materials themselves.
142
VI. Being Assembled: Creating the Planes of Immanence
(between states and families) and their equivocal problematics (are you a man or a really
develop and devolve prior to and beyond all recognizable identity. On this plan(e),
Nothing develops, but things arrive late or early, and form on this or that
assemblage depending on their composition of speed. Nothing
subjectifies, but haecceities form according to compositions of
nonsubjectified powers or affects. We call this plane, which knows only
longitudes and latitudes, speeds and haecceities, the plane of consistency
or composition (as opposed to the plan(e) of organization or
development). It is necessarily a plane of immanence and univocality.
We therefore call it the plane of Nature, although nature has nothing to do
with it, since on this plane there is no distinction between the natural and
the artificial. (ATP 266)
On these planes, which are also cartographies or plans, new worlds are
constituted. When philosophy intuits these new sets of possibilities, it creates concepts
that do not transcend those consistencies but rather remain immanent to them.
Immanence, for Deleuze, is a rule for keeping philosophical creations closer to the
exploits of art (and the most experimental forms of science). Immanence is, in a way,
the rule of rules for forming concepts. It is less a perceived feature of things, an attribute
how a painter prepares a surface to receive paint in a process different in kind from
143
For Deleuze, this creation of a new geography, or geo-philosophy, is a peculiarly
modern problem. Michel Foucault, in his early works on the emergence of modernity,
framed it in terms of the issue of the place of “the human” in dynamics (tectonic, astral,
microbial) that surpass have been discovered to surpass our categories of identity on both
the macrological and micrological levels. No one has perhaps yet understood the subtlety
and cruelty and missed potentials of the modern situation as well as Foucault. As
essential disparity, almost an alienation by rights, separated from itself by its words, its
works, and by its desires” (DI 91). This auto-alienation it is what Foucault called the
power that will not be reduced to our reflection upon it or our attempt to adjudicate its
adventures.110
While modernity, with its voracious quest for freedom and autonomy and novelty,
calls for a life beyond identity and the calculations of a unified self, Foucault’s early
works show how the human sciences, in league with the consolidation of power in
nation-states, constantly back-fill the “empty square” of our subjectivity with old images
of kings, great men, geniuses, matrons, in order to develop “essences of man” that
arbitrarily limit the possibilities for life. In a way, Deleuze’s pluralism attempts to make
good on the modern situation by not filling in the empty square, or better, by filling it
As modernity has clearly shown, all great politicians are in some sense fallen
consistency, but do so only for the sake of consolidating the status quo and coordinating
144
desire with what is recognizable, with what resembles (the face of the father, the girl
next door, etc.). There is a hair’s breadth of difference between the demagogue and the
avant-garde. There is a fascist lurking within every great artist, as much as it is true that
the fascist employs all the power of art. Witness the genius of media manipulation by
American politicians, let alone the extraordinary fetishization of desire managed by Adolf
Hitler’s Nazi regalia. Politicians are artists who work in a medium that has been
sets up the terms for a political economics of such dynamisms as Bush’s grin, A
we facialize our bodies and “landscapize” the earth (ATP 181). George Bush’s political
success is inseparable from his cocky grin, the Baptist-preacher swagger that also did so
much for Bill Clinton. We follow the face before we follow the policy (or lack thereof).
subjectify the earth and subjugate ourselves, artists and children develop another
consistency than that proper to the colonization of the earth: becomings-other and
cosmic dynamisms from orders intended to corral and crush them. As Deleuze puts it, “it
is the wolf itself, and the horse, and the child, that cease to be subjects to become events,
in assemblages that are inseparable from an hour, a season, an atmosphere, an air, a life”
(ATP 262). Artists, like children and schizophrenics, but more like shamans and
145
magicians, are able to develop plan(e)s of consistency that enable the earth to speak on its
own terms, no longer in terms of discrete objects but of compositions of forces. Here,
“the street enters into composition with the air, and the beast and the full moon enter into
composition with each other” (ATP 262). Artists find themselves mimicking or repeating
traits (animal traits, sonic traits, visual traits) in a way that tears them away from all
affects, affects that cross the divide between human, plant, animal, and star. If there is
Don Juan teaches Carlos Castaneda to make friends with his death, to know its
specificity. Or in Blanchot’s sense that writing is death. Or, perhaps most of all, in the
sense of Shamanistic initiation in which organs are removed, washed, and replaced in the
experimental mandate also means that the concepts philosophy creates are not the
consolidation of philosophy, but the point at which thought becomes other than itself.
Crossing the divide between gods and man, immanence establishes the field for a game
apocalypse and metamorphosis, as Norman O. Brown once put it, where the fate of the
146
Multiple Matters: Inventing the Anexact Essence
This is partly because multiplicities do not obey the rules of representation and partly
because multiplicities are “eventful” – they are “happenings,” to use the term current to
1960’s and 1970’s guerilla art. In the same way that events pose questions to us,
historical event (the assassination of JFK, the attack on the World Trade Center, Gandhi’s
walk across India) does not decide some issue but rather raises latent issues or questions
to a certain surface, a surface of possible sense. Here it should be clear why the
is not an “historicist” – he would never admit that philosophical concepts are reducible to
forces of a given historical milieu. Transcendental empiricism allies itself not with
tradition, which always supposes a correspondence between the truth of a linguistic (or
otherwise semantic) “account of the facts” and “the way the world is out there.” For
Deleuze such a realism is at least arbitrary and at most incoherent, because on his view
the true being of things is inherently problematic, from both an epistemological and an
ontological perspective. For Deleuze, multiplicities embody virtual problems that are
147
irreducible to cases of solution. In other words, sense is irreducible to the propositions
reality can only state a case of possible solution, it cannot be such a description that
Delanda puts it in his work Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy, Deleuze’s realism
is one of an isomorphism between the problems humans pose and the problems (virtually)
existing in life.111 Delanda even goes so far as to say that the equipment in a physicist’s
laboratory, the practice of using these machines, and the activity that includes those
Even if the dynamics (physical properties, possibilities, field states, etc.) of some
system can eventually be explained in simple linear causal terms which are no longer
problematic, this is the case only if it is assumed that matter itself is inherently
our account of nature. On a Deleuzian view of the matter, the scientific assemblage (i.e.
the “practice”) of science resonates with the real intensive (i.e. problematically self-
148
The nature of what has gone by the name of “matter” in the history of philosophy
is a fundamental problem for a philosophy that posits the co-genesis of thought and
being. Despite evidence that matter at its deepest levels functions according to dynamics
in which what it is depends upon how it is observed, there remains much resistance to the
view of an animate matter. For Deleuze, however, the presupposition of a dead and
lines of flight like a metallurgist follows flows of ore. Whereas traditional anthropology
had defined the cultural status of the metallurgist or smith in terms of a difference from or
contrast with either the sedentary farming culture or nomadic people groups (essentially
how the smith is evaluated by an “other”), Deleuze and Guattari insist (following the
work of anthropologists like Griaule and Childe) that this middle or “mixed” personage
of the smith, existing between the “smooth” or “deterritorialized” flow of ore and the
bastardized or impure amalgam of Others, but as something Husserl might have called an
“anexact essence.”
The itinerant or vagabond smith differs (differently) from both the nomad and the
farmer. Mines must be near mountains or deserts, on frontiers and not in the rich
and stable food supply from those same farms. However, the identity of the smith is not
a negative derivation from these two positive variables. This is because the metallurgist
is defined above all by the peculiarities of the space proper to metallic ore itself, a space
149
Deleuze and Guattari call “holey space.” This space, as they put it, is connected with
nomad space and conjoined with sedentary space (ATP 415)—metallurgists are not of the
There is something strange about the space of the metallurgist. Rather than
dividing the earth up into striated, criss-crossed fields or herding animals across smooth,
unbounded plateaus, smiths transpierce mountains and excavate lands. They bore holes
and set up caves or workshops that connect to other workshops, the storehouses of
empire, other mines. Rather than imposing forms on the earth (farmers) or subjecting
themselves totally to its material ebb and flow (nomadic herders), metallurgists follow
the flow of a specific material. They ambulate with it. They therefore create “lines of
flight” or “rhizomes” that blur the lines between art and nature. A whole network of
holey spaces whose inhabitants have an ambiguous political status: are smiths slaves (to
the metals, to the empire)? Demigods (lords of the underworld)? Heroes (weapon
makers)? Demons (consorts with fire)? And how do they manage to live so close to the
uncanny forest, from which they get their charcoal—do they speak the language of
On Deleuze and Guattari’s view, the “marginal” status of the smith cannot be
explained in terms of its negative relationship with either of the two others.114 It has an
autonomy proper to it, the autonomy of a vagabond or itinerant person, neither sedentary
nor nomadic. “Their relation to others results from their internal itinerancy, from their
own vague essences, and not the reverse,” they insist (ATP 415). What a smith is, in
terms of her identity cannot be explained in terms either of the plight of a form or the
pure potencies of a material. For Deleuze, Edmund Husserl had some notion of this
150
“ambulant coupling” of matter with itself that cannot be understood in terms of “fixed
essence-properties.”
Anexact essence, for Husserl, is not prime matter, nor is it a sensible object. It is
something between those two, an “affect-event”: something taking place in matter that is
not yet the imposition of a form, but which is inseparable from expressive or intensive
qualities—“singularities” that are prolonged or extend over features of objects that would
singularities or affects-events are related in what Deleuze calls the machinic phylum: “a
make the operations converge, upon one or several assignable traits of expression” (ATP
406). As Deleuze puts it here, in A Thousand Plateaus, “this operative and expresssive
flow is as much artificial as it is natural: it is like the unity of human beings and Nature”
(ATP 406).
Specific operations allow the flow to come to the fore as a flow, and not as a
“form” distinct from matter. The farmer, the nomad, the smith, and even the merchant
seem in their own ways to follow the ebb and flow of a peculiar material assemblage.
But only the artisan, and the smith in an exemplary way, truly follows the flow of the
material. Whereas the farmer follows the seasons, changes crops in rotation, etc., this is
always to bring the labor back to a certain fixed point from which the process can begin
again. What is expected from the land is wholly determined by what it has produced in
the past in accordance with the form imposed upon it, with preconceived ideals. The
farmer is not truly itenerant, nor is the merchant, who is bound to a flow of goods that
must depart from and return to the same fixed point. These “transhumants” (ATP 409)
151
do not so much follow a flow as much as continually draw a circuit which takes only the
The artisan, on the other hand, is the true itinerant, the true ambulator. The
carpenter-artisan follows the flow not only of the grain of the wood with which s/he is
working, but also the supply of wood itself, the whole entire earthly adventure and
vicissitude proper to wood itself, from his or her “prospects” as a carpenter. S/he must go
where it goes. Whereas the nomad holds a smooth space and the farmer and the
merchant bind flows to rotation, the artisan is bound most intimately to the flow of the
material itself. Although all artisans exist in this manner, it is above all the metallurgist
It has to do, again, with peculiarities of material. In metals more than any other
sphere it is unclear where a potency ends and a form begins. As Deleuze and Guattari put
it, “an energetic materiality overspills the prepared matter, and a qualitative deformation
or transformation overspills the form” (ATP 410). Quenching, which finishes the
forging, takes place after the form has been fixed. The existence of ingots, which are
prepared potentials, cannot be reduced to mere potentials or stocks. Even though it seems
like the distinction between form and matter is clearer nowhere else than metallurgy,
152
or covered, rendered unrecognizable, dissociated by the hylomorphic
model. (ATP 411)
The music of the smith is not just the sound of his hammer, but a transformational
relation with the ore: the smith plays through the malleability of the ore; the musician
impose forms but transform: they only ever deal with forms in and as transitions. These
arts reveal “a life proper to matter,” but this life is not organic, not exactly natural (and
not exactly an “autopoiesis” which would rigorously distinguish the alive and the
dead).115
Deleuze’s view of matter cuts against the grain of the hylomorphic assumptions
measurable thresholds determining when potencies are or can become matters that can be
considered as potencies to be actualized, or used as form—i.e., why some sounds and not
others can be composed to make a symphony. All this would be well and good except
that hylomorphism misses the passages proper to the materials themselves that are vague
there are intermediate forms, but these are always constricted to being “intermediaries” or
On the Husserlian view the essence of a circle emerges from vague roundness into
sensible, clear roundness, achieving an eidos. But Deleuze insists that there is an
autonomy to roundness (or to music) itself which is a “threshold affect” (neither flat nor
pointed, neither silence nor noise) or “limit process” (becoming rounded, becoming
153
music). Deleuze is thinking here in terms of the ancient Epicurean view of nature as
inherently flux-based or “in becoming,” where all transformation, growth, and death are
the results of the clinamen or minimal diversion of an atom from a straight line. These
minimal deviations or “lines of flight” are not the unruliness of matter resisting formal
order. They are autonomous forces inhabiting “problematic figures”: not circles but
forms—the stuttering, the glitchy, the funky; not organisms but bodies—bands, packs,
tribes. Whereas the traditional or “Statist” impulse is to account for these variations as
essences are distinct from both the things that incarnate them (wheels, glasses, songs,
“anexact yet rigorous (“essentially and not accidentally inexact”), Husserl always
considered them stopping points on the way to complete eidetic substance (ATP 367).
For Deleuze anexact essences are found in and as “passages to the limit” or “thresholds”
in material flows that cannot appear via “reflection upon the object,” even under
conditions of the epoche. The singularity of a material flow, for Deleuze, becomes
evident only when mind ambulates along with matter in an ambulant state that is not
That is why, for Deleuze, the “essences” of art, ritual, therapy, and magic are the
subject of a minor or nomad science, proper not to the State but to a kind of “war
themselves. Only here, “at the limit” do we perceive what Deleuze calls
154
A single phylogenetic lineage, a single machinic phylum, ideally
continuous: the flow of matter-movement, the flow of matter in
continuous variation, conveying singularities and traits of expression.
This operative and expressive flow is as much artificial as natural: it is
like the unity of human beings and Nature. But at the same time, it is not
realized in the here and now without dividing, differentiating. We will
call an assemblage every constellation of singularities and traits deducted
from the flow—selected, organized, stratified—in such a way as to
converge (consistency) artificially and naturally; an assemblage, in this
sense, is a veritable invention. (ATP 406)
The “minor knowledge” of these flows is the knowledge required to, for instance,
square stones without prefabricated templates, a procedure used in the making of the
Gothic cathedrals. Here “one does not represent, one engenders and traverses” (ATP
364). Or to make something round, a procedure involving not just the knowledge of a
form but of immanent material requirements (millstones, lathes, spinning wheel sockets,
etc.). State science, with its methodism, always fails to ambulate: “the State is
perpetually producing and reproducing ideal circles, but a war machine is necessary to
themselves. There is a sieve or interweave between mind and materials, where what the
material will have been becoming is known only as I artfully accompany or trace its
trajectory over time. This is why Deleuze and Guattari always think of true change and
its dynamics in terms not of “objective” or Natural lineages, but in terms of a “machinic
phylum” that is strictly speaking neither natural nor cultural, but artful, inventive. Major
155
of knowledge, but rhizomatic surfaces of connection between extraordinary points and
singular traits that are not so much given in nature as “naturally” available under
shamanic ritual.
There is thus a peculiarly affective dimension to minor science. But these affects
bring into play not “unreason” but immanent forms of determination. This is why
space, time, and the categories schematizing things, something like the reverse is true:
time, space, and the categories are “out of joint,” untimely, a function of affects in flux.
This is what it means that the artisan belongs to the stone, the composer is led by the
music, the painter feels her way along the canvas, the shaman’s body becomes the body
movement he is tracing in art is not what flows through the soul of the composer who
hears the silent cry of his people’s heart, but the forced movement that occurs as a result
of art: the flow that appears (as simulacra) in the baroque interior, where it appears that
pillars supporting the ceiling are hanging from the painted clouds. Deleuze’s theory of
music is that it is not the music itself, its formal purity, that gives it power, but rather its
represents emotions or characters, but that it mobilizes forces that are shared affects
156
moving across various forms of life. As Deleuze puts it “music [here, Mozart’s] takes as
its content a becoming-animal; but in that becoming-animal the horse, for example, takes
as its expression soft kettledrum beats, winged like hooves from heaven or hell; and the
birds find expression in gruppeti, appogiaturs, staccato notes that transform them into so
Notes do not represent but in some sense become horse-steps, bird-flight, or love-
making. But this is only because, says Deleuze, in this process horses, birds, and love
magnified or diffused into something else yet again—fear, or joy, or yet more music.
This occurs not because of any imitative power in art, but because of a transmutation that
cuts across life as much as art. As Deleuze puts it, “the painter and the musician do not
imitate the animal, they become-animal at the same time as the animal becomes what
they willed, at the deepest level of their concord with Nature” (ATP 305). Music does
not imitate life or even suggest its representable figures. It captures and releases affects
cutting across both organic and nonorganic life. Drum n’ bass beats, for instance, are as
much the affect of electricity through silicone chips as they are the untamed rampage of
buffaloes and the eerie longing of hyenas. We do not dance to it to understand the “spirit
of our times,” but to connect over time and space affects that can blend and even
transform one another: the becoming-digital of the herd.118 This singular affect crossing
human, animal, and machine does not reflect the times as much as extract what is most
The dance of the tarantella is supposed to magically cure its victims of tarantula
bites. But it works, Deleuze and Guattari emphasize, not because the dancer imitates a
157
spider but because there are affects of the spider that cross it or traverse it and that
become available in a dance that connects to these more or less mobile affects. We don’t
dance the spider, we dance the spider’s color, mood, or timbre. As Deleuze puts it, “the
victim, the patient, the person who is sick, becomes a dancing spider only to the extent
that the spider itself is supposed to become a pure silhouette, pure color and pure sound
This sheds light on why Deleuze’s theory of art is not an “aesthetics of qualities,”
or a theory that all sensible qualities have inherent eternal essences that provoke
reminiscence or phantasm (ATP 306). Whereas it does seem as if for Deleuze the
extraordinary signs Proust encounters had the status of eternal Ideas (the idea of
Vinteuil’s phrase, of the madeleine’s taste, of the church’s steeple), Deleuze insists that
even in Proust, as much as in Melville or Kafka, the sensations are functional blocs,
assemblage to another” (ATP 306). And even there he insisted on as much by making
the “essences” Proust learns a function of a signs that can only be taken as signs (of love,
betrayal, fidelity, hatred) for someone subject to the vicissitudes of the colliding worlds,
the disasters and delights of a given machinic flow, the adventures of a deterritorialized
of earth.
The earth Deleuze thinks art reveals is not the earth of sensations, but of
supersensible forces which are found at the limits of sensation. These limits are found in
the intensity of experimental art and actual science, as well as in great love and
experimental faith. The paradigmatic role of art for thought is not due to the fact that
art’s materials are platonic forms of the real. Rather, it is the function art
158
paradigmatically plays (in its “modernity,” at least) as an experimentation in becomings,
and the function sensations play in those becomings, that ultimately matters to Deleuze.
While art deals in sensation, the virtue of art, for Deleuze and Guattari, is that art
Artists are sorcerers, Deleuze writes, because the animal is the only party to whom they
feel beholden.119 That is to say, artists want to be in their created worlds as animals are in
their “natural” ones. For Deleuze, constituting a territory is nearly the birth of art: in
making a territory, it is not merely a matter of defecatory and urinary markings, but also a
series of postures (standing/sitting for an animal), a series of colors (that an animal takes
on), a song [un chant]. These are the three determinants of art: colors, lines, song, says
This animal art and artistic animality has nothing to do with imitation,
not imitate anything, does not resemble anything, but captures imperceptible flows,
develops a complex, “gothic” variation within his world—a world that is not a Whole, a
“collection” of lines, but a world that is, in itself, an abstract line of which the fish is like
a piece of a puzzle.
Artists are animals in the sense that they, too, de-and re-territorialize their milieus
as experimental forms of life. The artist wills to de- and re-territorialize to the infinite, to
become everything and everybody (as did Woolf, Kerouac, even Artaud): “to be present
at the dawn of a world” (ATP 280).121 But this world is built not through a grand
159
synthesizer (ATP 342-343).122 The figures or phrases, strokes or beats of an artist are not
so many parts seeking a whole, or exiles seeking home, but machines for extracting
affects from nature the way that synth oscillators divide and recombine sound waves.
Just as synth sounds do not resemble the sounds of other instruments, but draw of
principles from their timbres, the principle of art, generally, is always to first eliminate
resemblance and analogy between clichéd figures and stereotyped narratives in order to
capture the imperceptible and the indiscernible, and to make a new world from them.
What Deleuze means by a “haptic” form of thought is one which would join with
Perspectives as the only Ideas worthy of repetition. This is a form of thought that results
in concepts that embody, perform, or entertain the very material dynamisms that provoke
its formation. It is what Bacon is able to do with his mastery of color: the knowledge of
how to bring colors together in a way that results not from their optical value but from a
“pure internal rapport.” The image of thought distances us from the intensive and
thought. To think haptically does not mean merely to deconstruct123 given forms of
sensibility and forms of life. It means to get closer to the real genesis of thought than is
What a haptic philosophy would share most profoundly with art is the cultivation
of figures—for Deleuze, concepts are to philosophers what figures are to art. Both
160
philosophy and art, for Deleuze, “crosscut the chaos and confront it,” even if not in the
same way or with the same results. Philosophy develops concepts from the same matter
What is a figure, for Deleuze? Deleuze writes, “figures have nothing to do with
resemblance or rhetoric but are the conditions under which the arts produce affects of
stone and metal, of strings and wind, of line and color, on a plane of composition of a
universe “ (WIP 66). For art to cultivate a figure is for it to develop one particular affect
or percept to such a degree that such an affect causes others to coalesce around them in a
For Deleuze both Francis Bacon’s painting and Marcel Proust’s literature share a
common quest for a Figure that is neither abstractly apprehended nor concretely narrated.
Bacon paints “portraits” of humans that are organized by chaotic or random traits (marks)
through which parts (eyes, mouths), places (butcheries and living rooms), and states
(being meat, being the Crucified) are related in ways they could not be otherwise (they
are elongated, truncated, etc.). Proust would give us not an “impression” of Combray
through descriptive flourish, nor a “day in the life” of a person living there, but Combray
This [connection] is perhaps because Bacon, when he refuses the double way of a
figurative painting and an abstract painting, is put in a situation analogous to that
of Proust in literature. Proust did not want an abstract literature that was too
voluntary (philosophy), any more than he wanted a figurative, illustrative, or
narrative literature that merely told a story. What he was striving for, what he
wanted to bring to light, was a kind of Figure, torn away from figuration and
stripped of every figurative function: a Figure-in-itself, for example, the figure-
in-itself of Combray. (FB 56)
161
Deleuze analyzes the paintings of Bacon in terms of their ability to create
informal diagrams that map intensive spaces of coloration that cannot be understood in
either optic or manual terms alone. Diagrammatic transformations are those which start
with a formalized set or regime of signs (in this case, the clichés of painting), and proceed
to extract from them—or make a “machine” capable of extracting from them—a new set
of potential traits or “particles-signs” (ATP 145).124 Once the diagrammatic moment has
occurred, an abstract machine can be established that organizes or fully actualizes the
new regime: in this case, the new regime is Bacon’s finished painting.
In Three Studies for Figures on Bends (1972), for example, Bacon’s diagram-
smudge becomes a hip bone that joins all three bodies in an “impossible” new human-
animality. The diagram (the “random” trait with which Bacon starts) is not the final
“matter of fact” or “brute fact” painted; rather, the diagrammatic-chaotic trait is what
enables the entire painting to render a brutality or a “cruelty” (in Artaud’s sense) of fact
that it would not be able to do without that trait (meaning in French a line but also a
characteristic). The chaos introduced by the diagram allows for the breakdown of pre-
becoming-imperceptible is never the goal in itself. Rather the goal is to create something
Save the contour—nothing is more important for Bacon than this. A line
that delimits nothing still has a contour or outline itself. Blake at least
understood this. The diagram must not eat away at the entire painting; it
must remain limited in space and time. It must remain operative and
controlled. The violent methods must not be given free reign, and the
necessary catastrophe must not submerge the whole. The diagram is a
possibility of fact—it is not the Fact itself. Not all the figurative givens
have to disappear; and above all, a new figuration, that of the Figure,
should emerge from the diagram and make the sensation clear and precise.
To emerge from the catastrophe . . . (FB 89)
162
We emerge from the catastrophe not into transcendence, not into a governing
purview, a judgment seat, a transcendental Archimedean point, but into immanence. The
machine for being, a new regime of signs relating a new set of possible actions, along
new lines of territorialization. But again, if this is the goal, it is not the end: it is only the
beginning.
plane” as opposed to the plane of a universe (where science works). The planes are
sometimes even as the masks a philosopher puts on in order to think. But Plato’s
Socrates, Kierkegaard’s Don Juan, Nietzsche’s Zarathustra, even Bergson’s runner are
are idiosyncrasies without which the thought of a peculiar philosopher cannot occur.
This is why sometimes truly brilliant philosophers like Plato or Nietzsche will allow their
texts to be populated by characters that are antipathetic to themselves (Christ and/or the
priest for Nietzsche, Gorgias or others for Plato). The greatest philosophers thus display,
like great artists, a kind of “athleticism . . . like acrobats torn apart in a perpetual show of
163
of her work125. Great philosophers, like great artists, are like animals (and great
inasmuch as their animality succeeds) in de- and re-territorializing. This is why Deleuze
calls the philosophy of the future “geophilosophy”: not because truth is relative to
different regions of the earth, but because there is no truth that is not an assemblage, and
In this way animals sometimes seem “truer” than self-conscious man, even though
humanity constantly de- and re-territorializes itself even more than do animals with their
delineation of various locales as friends and of their family pack as a “mobile home.”
dad’s hammer, and then my drumstick. First, as a child, I deterritorialize the hammer as a
drumstick, playing primitive beats on my toy box (it was very important that it be my
Dad’s “real” hammer and not a toy). Later on, when the hammer is re-territorialized as a
tool, the drumstick is deterritorialized as a hammer when I learn to speak on the drums, to
build beats, to nail the groove, but to speak with hammer blows. In which case language
becomes deterritorialized for me (as it always already was due to my hearing loss) as
pure rhythm and bodily sensation, sensation which is re-territorialized as the song I am
playing, today.
Philosophers can complete and carry out these becomings, these “lines of flight.”
They deterritorialize not only themselves—the preconceptual life they live—but also the
concepts with which they deal and the “history of reception” of those concepts. To use
an example Deleuze gives in What is Philosophy? (WIP 64-65), Descartes’ “idiot” is the
indispensable frame of the cogito, without which the idea of the cogito (everyone knows
what it means to think) is unintelligible. But then the idiot, emergent in Nicholas of Cusa
164
(deterritorializing itself from St. Augustine’s idea of learned ignorance, in which we
forgo our possible specification of the finite in view of God’s elaboration of the finite at
infinity) and used again in Descartes, becomes deterritorialized in the Slavic world when
Dostoyevsky takes it up as his theme. The idiot passes from the faith of “learned
doubt to the absurd, to the absurd affirmation of nonsense as itself the only truth, of the
“ruins of history” the unforgettable, the irreplaceable. From impiety to piety (Augustine
to Cusa), tragic madness to profound comic insight (Descartes to Dostoyevsky), the idiot
becomes perverse, fixated in the real, refusing not concepts but refusing the idea that the
exceptional, the obscene, etc. does not have its own concept.
The tracing of these kinds of lineages and trajectories is what Deleuze calls
affirmation of the superiority of territory over truth, insofar as genuinely new and
different territories are wrested from chaos. “To think is to experiment,” Deleuze writes,
“but experimentation is always that which is in the process of coming about—the new,
remarkable, and interesting that replace the appearance of truth and are more demanding
than it is” (WIP 111). And geophilosophy is not any more relative to time than it is to
place; time and place only become significant as the peculiar or distinctive locales
(neighborhoods, milieus) they can be when made subject to the power of concepts, which
occurrence: “it is born in History and falls back into it, but is not of it” (WIP 110).
Philosophy is not of history, but of the earth, of the earth in a sense that can only
be (re)created in an alliance between the earth and philosophy. “The philosopher must
165
become nonphilosopher so that nonphilosophy becomes the earth and people of
philosophy” (WIP 109). Why is philosophy connected to the idea of a new earth?
Because the immanence or the univocity philosophy attempts and more or less succeeds
to establish is not a homeland, not a heim, but an/other earth—we write not to imagine a
new earth, but to imagine this earth otherwise. The attraction of philosophy should be
like the attraction of science fiction—as if the only way we can solve the “problems” of
picked up with his famous quip that truth has the structure of a fiction. For Deleuze
History teaches nothing, which is why Hegel’s Phenomenology fails insofar as it attempts
to wed itself to an historical narrative. History itself is a hollow echo of more profound
on the different milieus of thought and the events corresponding to them, depending on
An example: the birth of the French and Italian New Wave film schools after
World War II. World War II forced these auteurs to think in a different way, a way that
reflected the way in which WWII had interrupted temporal continuity and destroyed
connections between places and traditions. But their thinking is not reducible to history.
The films are not “reflections on World War II,” but experiments that take the conditions
of post-War life (its event or advent) as the real conditions of a new idea. With Fellini
and Goddard and others, a new way of making films comes into being along with a new
166
way of conceiving: the time-image, as opposed to the movement image, an image not
The paradox is that while this emergence happens as a result of history, it is more
accurate to say that the real consequences of World War II, what is truly new and
extraordinary about the post-war world, can best be seen (if not exactly “understood”) as
uncanny, the displaced, etc.) are not “examples” of “how people felt after World War II.”
history is only a kind of negative image or chaotic suggestion. As Deleuze puts it,
all experimentation, like all experience, take a time that can be marked as historical,
“history” is only one rendering, one possible reading, just as the “ego” is only one
possible rendering of the self. And the goal for Deleuze in getting beyond this
perspective is not to escape the self or history but to make something other of those
perspectives.
child,” and “becomings-molecular” which happen in and as art, but it is also how and
what he envisions as the true definition of philosophy itself: philosophers do not write to
167
consolidate their identity as philosopher but in order to become something else, to think
for those who cannot, to speak for the dumb, to hear for the deaf, to become wolf or
snake or rat so that these animals, or those mountains, or that painful family romance
becomes something else: becomes an abstract line, a figure, a painting, a piece of music.
Man only becomes animal if the animal, for its part, becomes sound, color,
or line. It is a bloc of becoming which is always asymmetrical. It is not
that the two are exchanged, for they are not exchanged at all, but the one
only becomes the other if the other becomes something yet other, and if
the terms disappear. As Lewis Carroll says, it is when the smile is without
a cat that man can effectively becomes cat as soon as he smiles. It is not
man who sings or paints, it is man who becomes animal, but at exactly the
same time as the animal becomes music, or pure color, or an astonishingly
simple line: with Mozart’s birds it is the man who becomes a bird,
because the bird becomes music. Melville’s mariner becomes albatross
itself becomes extraordinary whiteness, pure vibration of white (and
Captain Ahab’s whale-becoming forms a bloc with Moby Dick’s white-
becoming, pure white wall). (D 72)
What we seek in these experiences, these experiments, is not simply the destruction of
our egos or the “ruin of representation,” although this is part of its effect. We seek
Entity, the nameless intellectual beast,” all the less intellectual for writing with its
wooden clogs, with its dead eye, its antennae and mandibles, its absence of face, a whole
How can philosophy be such an experience? What kind of thought rides the
witch’s wind? It has to do with following the flow of a matter of expression in order to
select and affirm something within it that, as John Rajchman put it, we must become
168
VII. Immanence, Challenged: Politics, Art, and the Fourth World War
After the September 11, 2001 terrorist attacks on the World Trade Center, French
sociologist Jean Baudrillard declared that what took place that day was not an isolated act
of insanity by deranged outlaws, but the symptom of a global phenomena he called the
“Fourth World War.”128 For Baudrillard, after the wars of Europe against itself (WWI),
of the free world against fascism (WWI), of the West against communism (a third
“world” war, if a cold one), this fourth or “global war on terror” is in fact a war of the
entire world against itself.129 We might think this war has always been going on—for as
long as history can remember, a succession of empires has swept across the globe; for as
long as myth can imagine, the gods have been at war. But perhaps in an unprecedented
way it is indeed the earth itself that is threatened by our current war on terror. For
into a single marketplace, and the absorption of all human languages and meanings into a
single univocal stream of incandescent images—is in some sense a war of the earth
against the earth itself. As he puts it, “it is the globe itself which resists globalization.”130
169
This cryptic statement, as well as Baudrillard’s essay, were by and large
dismissed by American critics. Perhaps his thesis, that there is a symbolic or ritual action
that took place on 9/11 which is not reducible to the actions of “others” (acts of war,
murder, sabotage, etc.) about which we might make condemnations and for which we
might seek redress, seemed to glib and abstract for a wounded populace. Baudrillard
believes that the terrorists sought to enter into a duel with Western capitalism, and that
the only way for them to do so was to play a card unrecognizable to the Western system,
with its “culture of life”: the card of their own deaths. The fact that this play was
monstrously successful, for Baudrillard, can be read in the fact that the relatively
bombing of Afghanistan, the invasion of Iraq) which resulted in very little. For
Baudrillard, if death for death is ultimately an immaterial exchange, this makes a little
What Baudrillard means to signify by “the earth,” by that globe that resists
globalization (as much our own dream of destroying this perfection we’ve achieved as it
is the terrorists’) is in fact closely related to death, or the “death drive”—what in us or our
species persists beyond our individual preferences, hopes, dreams, predilections; it is all
that cannot be recognized by a system that depends on pacification and rectification of its
organic life in the name of which Deleuze had hoped to philosophize by affirming
creativity. But what can be powerful about creativity in the age of terror ushered in by
170
the struggle of the earth against capitalism? Globalized capitalism seems to be nothing if
not eminently creative, endlessly able to produce something where there was nothing,
able to shape and reshape materials with seemingly effortless grace, to connect disparate
times and places with the magic of transportation, communication, and microcomputing.
between the despotism of the artist and the politician, then should we consider human
creativity to be something which might end or at least ameliorate this war of the earth
against itself? But why look to art to end the slow and subtle terror which is now taking
the shape of the militant marshalling of all cultures and religions against one another,
reducing the surface of the earth to an advertising screen where all human languages
become a single univocal stream of advertisements? What can the creation of more
Since at least the mid-1990’s the growing anxiety of liberal intellectuals over the
instability of global life and the reality of religious and ideological warfare has put a
quick end to “postmodern” taste for proliferating creative differences (and the “culture
studies” which tried to identify more and more differences). This anxiety has ushered in
a new taste for a fighting, unilateral bid for universal truths that would cut across
religious, ethnic, and cultural differences. In Wars of Position, for instance, Timothy
Brennan laments the way that cultural studies, much of which was inspired by Capitalism
Brennan’s thesis is that instead of developing a truly radical political position, cultural
studies in the 80’s and 90’s enshrined “subaltern” subject positions in lieu of active
171
engagements in politics: resistant subjectivities rather than militant subjects. In
Brennan’s story, marginalized intellectuals within the West and ostracized third-worlders
without it came to mirror one another in their abject difference from the entitled and
included citizen.
representation.” For postmodern leftism, the terms of representation are always already
decided by the subterfuge of positive law operating at the sole behest of market interests
and the so-called “human rights” the imperial markets require. Cultural studies, as not
only Brennan but Zizek, Jameson and others have shown, created a sterile academic
game of “resistance” to the “hegemony” all positive discourses of identity within politics
imply. For Brennan (as for Zizek and others), the problem with contemporary culture
studies that the subaltern position is not a political, but an aesthetic one.
The problem, the critics of the “aestheticization of politics” argue, is that the
aesthetic or subjective or even religious discourse in terms of which the difference of the
subaltern is presented turns out to have no properly political demands.132 This “voice of
the other” demands, according to Brennan, something inherently apolitical and therefore
publicly unanswerable. Cultural studies for Brennan turns out to be nothing but the
attempt of an intellectual elite to console themselves for their inability to build a popular
consensus within empire by mirroring their impotence in those without it, in the spectral
half-lives of those who suffer and die in the desert of the third world.
of US academics. As Slavoj Zizek has shown, it is not the powers that be that need to
recognize the authenticity of others; it is the oppressor who must realize what is wrong
172
with herself. But Brennan’s argument is limited by its own horizon of what it takes as the
site of political contestation: liberal democracy. He faults (and rightly) the US academic
left for its inability to bring the radicality of the insights of Althusserian-Gramscian
theory to bear in a way that can build a genuine alternative to the “managerial” fight
unquestionable forward march of empire. But Brennan is wrong, I will argue here, in
thinking that the positions occupied by those in popular politics should not come under
“subjective” forms of critique. Those who occupy “political” positions can be in the
business of avoiding politics as much as is anyone else, and liberal democracy may be a
a Deleuzian “culture studies,” understanding the ruses and devices of the politician in a
way that links them to those of the artist may help us address much larger issues than
how to make a difference within the confines of liberal democracy, which after all is only
one form of power and not the ultimate horizon of experience on earth. Deleuze and
Guattari do not aestheticize politics, but they do politicize art in a way that makes is
Deleuze and Guattari see, and rightly, it seems to me, that liberal democratic
subject is always the economically privileged one. Capitalism is the ultimate horizon of
politics in our day and age, not liberalism or democracy. Deleuze and Guattari would
173
insist that the politics of the future is beyond the topic of the rights of Man, the autonomy
of the Subject, the voice of the Citizen, etc., and therefore true politics must include
and Guattari, Alain Badiou and Slavoj Zizek have in some sense once again taken up,
unrepresentable can nevertheless revolutionize the very terms in which current debates
take place. However, both Badiou and Zizek ultimately reject Deleuze’s philosophical
idiom in favor of what each claims, in his own way, to be a more truly materialist and
For Badiou, Deleuze’s ontology is that of a nature mystic. That is to say, for
univocal but there are symptoms or “cases” of the presence of ideas that are analogically
related and participate in the singularity of the idea. As Badiou puts it, for Deleuze both
Bartleby and Spinoza are participating analogues of Christ, tuber plants and wolf packs
are analogous rhizomes, metallurgists and composers both participate in the singularity of
“ambulant” and so on. For Badiou, this analogizing undermines the project of a thought
of the univocal and the singular, the thought of the truth of an Event that can never be
reduced to its historical vicissitudes, and thus have revolutionary power to change.
I share with Deleuze the conviction (which I think is political) that every
genuine thinking is thinking of singularities. But since for Deleuze actual
multiplicities are always purely formal modalities, and since only the
Virtual univocally dispenses sense, I have argued that Deleuze has no way
of thinking singularity other than by classifying the different ways in
which singularity is not ontologically singular; in other words, by
174
classifying the different modes of actualization. After all, this was already
the cross borne by Spinozism, whose theory of “singular things” oscillates
between a schematism of causality (a thing is a set of modes producing a
single effect) and a schematism of expression (a thing bears witness to the
infinite power of substance). Similarly, for Deleuze, singularity oscillates
between a classificatory phenomenology of modes of actualization (and
virtualization), on the one hand, and an ontology of the virtual, on the
other.
I maintain that the “link” between these two approaches is not
compatible with either univocity or immanence. It is this incompatibility
that furnishes the clue as to why Deleuze’s texts swarm with analogies,
which are required in order to determine the descriptive Ideas for which
singularities provide the cases. That these Ideas (Fold, Rhizome, Dice-
throw, etc.) aim at configurations in becoming, at differentiations, counter-
movements, interlacings, etc., changes nothing. I have always claimed
that Deleuzian singularities belong to a regime of actualization or
virtualization, and not to one of ideal identity. But the fact that only
concrete becomings provide the descriptive models for a schema in no
way precludes the latter from being an Idea to which the models are
isomorphic. (TR 79)
Badiou’s own view is that multiplicities are internally defined by their inherently
certain sets. What singularizes a multiplicity is not a virtual element that renders it open
but an actual part that is indiscernibly present/absent. For Deleuze, on the other hand, the
inconsistency or excess that renders an assemblage problematic and makes each one
“open” is a function external to each ensemble. This is why, for Deleuze the “senses” of
politics, art, science, love, and so on, all contaminate one another, whereas for Badiou the
“evental” power of each of these “truth procedures” is internal to each one. For Deleuze,
conjunctions. This is why sense is always virtual, not inherent in the interplay of the
parts of any one milieu or regime, and the subject of a “transcendental” empiricism as
175
For Badiou, Deleuze’s view is problematic because transcendental empiricism
The attempt to subvert the “vertical” transcendence of the One through the
play of the closed and the open, which deploys multiplicity in the mobile
interval between a set (inertia) and an effective multiplicity (line of flight),
produces a “horizontal’ or virtual transcendence which, instead of
grasping singularity, ignores the intrinsic resources of the multiple,
presupposes the chaotic power of the One, and analogizes the modes of
articulation. When all is said and done, we are left with what could be
defined as a natural mysticism. (TR 80)
To summarize Badiou here, his complaint is that Deleuze does not see the
assemblage of actual parts of a multiplicity, what Badiou will call its “count-as-one,” as
what Badiou here calls “inertia” as a consequence of the contamination of discrete things
in one another. The consequence, for Badiou, is that the event of sense, as Deleuze
describes it, fails to be fully different, univocal, and immanent to itself. The Deleuzian
fails, Badiou claims to mobilize “the intrinsic resources of the multiple.” Deleuze’s
multiplicity, Badiou argues, manifests the same chaotic power of the One resounding
or immanence.
“verificationism" of his own in the form of “logic of worlds,” I would argue that Deleuze
lines of flight or intensities. This is what Badiou tries to develop with his notion of life as
176
being that which exists in the service of an idea.135 Deleuze’s “contaminated” notion of
But in order to clearly see this point, it is necessary to clarify how the
what I will investigate in my next and final chapter as a form of natural magic. There I
will argue that what Deleuze calls concept creation only fully realizes itself not in a
unlimited pedagogy in the life of the intense, the vital, and the singular. This magic
As we have briefly seen in the work of Jose Gil, ritual magic exemplifies the
notion of a powerful, transformative sign. And a brief look in my final chapter at the
transformability will help expand and clarify the nature of the transformations Deleuze
saw happening in authentic art (and also, though less frequently, in science and
philosophy). This is where I will begin my concluding chapter. There I will argue that
admired magic for its sophisticated view of the relationship between an ultimately
unknowable depths of nature and a surface of images that nevertheless give entrée to an
177
Badiou contra Deleuze
Multiplicity,”136 Badiou praises Deleuze’s early notion that the singular is a simulacral
effluvia of the always different and wholly abstract One (the univocal sense of eternal
return). This early notion seems to place the generative force of events purely in ideal
Deleuze’s later collaborations with Felix Guattari, Badiou argues, Deleuze lapses from
Deleuze, Badiou argues, creating a concept amounts to verifying whether some intuition
(of a rhizome or war machine or becoming-other) has been fulfilled (TR 78). For
Badiou, Deleuze’s early notion of a static sense of difference in itself that does not
Why Badiou objects to an “emergent” reading of the event, and why he himself
rigorously distinguishes being and event, has to do with the fact that Deleuze’s notion of
the empirical. A multiplicity “emerges” for Deleuze, not simply when the virtual is
added to the actual or insofar as it exceeds the actual, but when a certain conjunction of
work with Guattari, it seems that an Event emerges only in case certain configurations
tare constructed in a way that makes them susceptible of intersecting with other
178
(weaponry, music, architecture, etc.) did not achieve the particular, historically
For Badiou this ruins Deleuze’s philosophy because it makes the power of the
vague, whereas for Badiou, the singular event is always exacting and prescriptively
determinate. Badiou accuses those of us still attracted to this empirical side of Deleuze’s
itself to each and everyone’s animal disquiet, to our confused desires, to everything that
makes us scurry about blindly on the desolate surface of the earth” (TR 69).
This anti-naturalism arises from Badiou’s reading of Lacan: being and the letter
are the only two adequate things: l’etre c’est la lettre. In other words, mathematics is the
only ontology. Badiou’s argument for this seems to be a kind of reductio: if ontology is
anything other than mathematics, there is no way to escape mystification and ultimate
idolization of “the given”—what Deleuze calls the full body of the earth. This false idol
of singularity can be erected by any particular tribe into its private fetish. The ultimate
charge here is that Deleuze’s intuitionism (his “vision” of the various ways in which
a covert “holism” which has the double fault of being mathematically impure (it’s not
formal enough, because it allows the matters of expression to in some sense cause/quasi-
cause singularity) and politically impotent (singularity always remains virtual, so a truly
disruptive political event—a revolution, a love—would always fail to fully subtract itself
179
But Deleuze’s “contaminated” notion of singularity, I would argue, is much more
interesting than Badiou gives it credit for.140 Badiou claims that Deleuze betrays
the “same” ideal dynamic (form of becoming). But it should be clear, if my argument has
been convincing in earlier chapters, that the nexus between virtual and actual which
comes to be through creative processes (natural and cultural, but not necessarily
“mystically vital”), does not mediate univocity from virtuality into actuality, but rather
invents a consistency. The event of invention, in Deleuze, is always split between causal
and quasi-causal features. On my reading this is actually a break with the vitalist
and empowered modes might lie (for Spinoza) or where a dualism of matter and memory
might persist (as for Bergson). For Deleuze, we must create concepts in order to
continually connect sense and nonsense, being and becoming, and it is the pragmatic
include both form and matter, as all Figures do, it will not have that absolute, eternal,
infinite claim to truth that number does. But what if it is neither Number nor that which
is counted that is the source of infinite truth, but rather the contingently universal figure
that remains exemplary? This is, I think, what Deleuze is ultimately claiming, even if he
does not exactly articulate it in this way until late in his career (in the works on cinema,
the works on Leibniz and Francis Bacon, and in Essays Critical and Clinical). For
Deleuze it is not that ideas are singular and their incarnations can be spoken of as
180
“analogical” due to the idea’s permutational power. It is rather that being’s eventfulness
universal singularity is. Badiou denies that this can be done in the “poetics of natural
Plateaus and the writings on art. Badiou’s reason for rejecting this “empiricist” or
“materialist” Deleuze is his claim that while Deleuze has accurately realized that the
wealth of the empirical consists in the problems it poses, Deleuze is wrong in thinking
that the contours of the problem posed by a multiplicity are inherent in its materiality:
wrong to think that we can take any concrete assemblage as a starting point for analyzing
the power of singular ideas, wrong to think that a tuber plant is as good a place as a pack
of wolves to analyze a rhizome (TR 77). What Badiou presumes about philosophy, and
that is immanent to the limits of perception, memory, and thought which that assemblage
presents along its line of flight, for Badiou the singularity of any configuration can only
181
the event, and so avoids “contamination” by Being, to which the Event is always
opposed.
For Slavoj Zizek, Being is already contaminated by its own internal self-
inconsistency. There is no need for Badiou’s Kantian dualism between schema and
content. This is because, following the later Lacan’s formula y’a de l’un (there is
something of the one),143 Zizek conceives of the “singularizing” force of being (that
which makes it open) as “not the totalizing One of the master signifier, but the
supplementary partial object (organ without a body) that functions as the enabling
Y’a de l’un is thus strictly correlative to il n’y a de rapport sexuel: the two
sexual partners are never alone, since their activity has to involve a
fantasmatic supplement that sustains their desire (and can ultimately be
just an imagined gaze observing them while they are engaged in sexual
intercourse). Y’a de l’un means that every erotic couple is a couple of
three: 1 + 1 + a, the “pathological” stain that disturbs the pure immersion
of the couple. In short this “one” is precisely that which prevents the
fusion of the amorous couple into One . . . Furthermore, not only is this
Real of the One not opposed to freedom—it is its very condition. The
shocking impact of being affected or “seduced” by the enigmatic message
of the Other derails the subject’s automaton, opens up a gap that the
subject is free to fill in with his (ultimately failed) endeavors to symbolize
it. Freedom is ultimately nothing but the space opened up by the traumatic
encounter, the space to be filled in by its contingent/inadequate
symbolizations/translations. (OwB 99)
idea than Badiou’s. This is the case because as for Zizek, for Deleuze being and event
182
are not opposed. Ideas, as Deleuze puts it in Difference and Repetition, have a double
status of transcendence (as virtual events) and immanence (as actually existing assembled
haecceities). Or, to put it in the language of The Logic of Sense, simulacra are distributed
on a surface constructed from a sense shared by bodies and propositions. And to put it in
the language of A Thousand Plateaus, assemblages are multiplicities due not to their form
or their content, their materiality or their “expressivity,” but due to the intense creativity
Zizek’s resistance to Badiou’s dualism of being and event thus has much in
common with Deleuze, at least on a formal level. Zizek’s insistence (following the late
called the “dark precursor” or “object = x”), a supplement that links any two discrete
series of terms by being excessively signified by one series and a signifier missing from
the other series.144 For both Deleuze and Zizek, the intensity which certain assemblages
Zizek, in fact, gives a good reason for not clinging to Badiouian mathematical
mandate for philosophy). In fact Zizek accuses Badiou, an avowed Maoist revolutionary
a truly Marxist vision of emancipation to a violent Jacobean view. This comes out, not
unexpectedly, in the rift between the form of a prescription and the content which it
informs. We may univocally demand the equal rights of all workers, but equal rights to
183
what? Is not the notion of equal rights always already compromised by the hidden
content of its message: equal rights to inequality in the form of being enslaved to their
The dilemma Zizek poses for Badiou seems to be this: if Being and Event are absolutely
opposed to one another, and the presence of events can only be described in non-
empirical terms (i.e. in terms of set theory), then the presence of a truth-event is either an
illusion or we are always in a position of having to claim full reality for the Event without
ever being able to specify its point of full “incarnation” or substantial “mode” of presence
(OwB 107).
Badiou definitely sides with the latter option145. But the consequence of this is
that Badiou encourages us to vigilantly guard the “purity” of the distance between the
undecidable event and the “situation” of being, the “alterity” of the event to the generic
process it opens up.146 For, as Badiou himself admits, to claim that an event has fully
realized itself in being amounts to totalitarianism: fidelity must remain open-ended. 147
This means that, just as the Kantian Man of Duty can never know exactly how or when
he is finitely instantiating the infinity of moral truth (which can never be realized fully),
184
the Badiouian Man of Truth can never claim that his truth is being realized concretely.
He can only know (based on the paradigm of mathematics) that his truth has the correct
As Zizek correctly points out, this is what prevents Badiou, in his penetrating look
at the 20th century, Le Siecle, from accounting for the two opposed forms of the 20th
century’s “passion for the Real”: the politics of purification (Stalinism) and the politics
the opposition between the “error” of purification (Stalinist purges, etc.) and the “correct”
procedure of subtraction (Badiou’s “fidelity”) can be overcome if we admit that the Real
(the singularity of the event, its unnamable sense) is simply the formal inconsistency of
Being.
disaster) that the correct procedure of subtraction “creatively repeats.” Badiou cannot
claim, as Zizek more consistently does (a la Hegel), that the “empirical” disaster is a
necessary moment in the process of truth. For Zizek the possibility of freedom is already
inscribed in a formal antagonism in being, already in place before the alternative between
of truth, when faced with a given attempt at fidelity Badiou will always be caught
between advocating the destructive process of purification, and a lapse into a kind of
Levinasian or Derridean ethics of “not deciding.” His injunction to us not to “force the
unnamable” seems to indicate that Badiou chooses the latter option, remaining at a level
185
For Zizek, any contemporary theory that celebrates the “disappearance of the big
controlling much “postmodern” cultural theory, is that in our day and age, there is no
longer any need to think of the deadlock of freedom in terms of the absence of a master
signifier of freedom or a “Big Other” who is the absent subject supposed to know the
riddles of desire. Where Zizek’s own materialism fails, I would argue, is when he insists
that we must remain with the deadlocks of Oedipal formations (castration, lack, stain,
identifying) emerge that need not pass through the Oedipal triangle. As we saw earlier
(Chapter 3), in the Logic of Sense Deleuze agrees that the Oedipus “complex” is what
enables us to begin to experiment with sense, to begin to move beyond our “literalist”
infancy (lit. in-fans, “unspokenness”) into the playful (if also dangerous) space of the
metaphysical surface. But Deleuze came to think that psychoanalysis had artificially
limited its capacities for analysis by “fixating” on reducing all subjective experimentation
to more or less failed attempts at achieving Oedipus. Deleuze and Guattari try to expand
psychoanalysis into schizoanalysis as a way of doing what Reich wanted to do: cause a
As Zizek admits, the later Lacan himself insists that Oedipus is only Freud’s
peculiar “dream” of how to solve the problem of the relationship between brute drives
(animal forces) and sublimated mental life.150 The debate between Deleuze and Zizek
186
really hinges on the fact that Zizek will not give up the binary model of differentiation:
the idea that, on the model of the male-female “impossible” rapport, all other
antagonisms are formed, and on the basis of this “tragicomic” gap alone can we hope for
insight into our disasters. Deleuze’s less Hegelian or “contradictive” model, is that
different assemblages have different ways of passing into the intensity which singularizes
them, and so we have to think desire without a model for itself but with “things for
desire (or truth, or freedom, or power) cannot be analyzed as a system apart from the
things (i.e. the machines) which instantiate different desires and powers. Zizek’s own
about healing that wound, in every area from love to politics) is something like a tribute
What I would argue is that the fact that “singularity” and “univocity” are not pure
but contaminated by traces of their material actualization is not a mark against but for the
power of Deleuze’s approach to philosophy. Deleuze may have indeed failed to preserve
expression, providing immanence “analogically” across various forms of life), but this for
me is its strong suit, not its weakness. Singularity is ontological in Deleuze, because it is
around singular points that planes of consistency (art) or immanence (philosophy) form.
imagine: the figure of the philosopher not as transcendental logician successful (Badiou)
187
of pataphysical technologies, where the sign shows the thing rather than indicating or
even describing it. This was Deleuze’s dream of language pushed to its “nth” power, its
stammering, its apocalypse, its art. As Deleuze puts it in an essay that describes the
surrealist Alfred Jarry, with his impossible machines and his science of imaginary
Material Forms
If we take the debate between Badiou and Deleuze seriously, as more than the
mere attempt of Badiou to clarify his own position and stake new ground, what comes to
the fore is a very important question about the status of materiality, or the status of our
earthliness as subjects. The debate over materialism that I am tracing here should be
distinguished from other, more classical debates. There are at least three levels of this
2. Dialectical Materialism. Sense and the causes of sense are related such that one
reciprocally conditions the other: the cause of meaning does not exist
independently from the meaning it produces.
188
3. Problematic Materialism. Sense is a cause of the non-closure of any set of causes
(or of the inability, specific to each event, of that event to be fully self-consistent).
Badiou, Zizek, and Deleuze all want to situate themselves at the third or what I
call “problematic” level. The multiple (Badiou), or the specters (Zizek), or multiplicities
singularity). How these three thinkers differ is in the descriptive account they give of
what it is that is singular about the singularity of a multiplicity. Badiou wants us to make
nothing of the fact that we are animals scurrying about on earth. Zizek wants to make
something rather more of it, but that some Thing ends up looking as ghostly and
is the thought of an ascetic or purified multiple as opposed to the thought of a One that is
contaminated or transversed by its matter of expression, Deleuze and Zizek differ over
the pragmatics required to evoke or “force” (Badiou’s term) the event. Zizek works with
a Hegelian and dialectical vision of materiality, which means that each “turn of the
consists in “tarrying with the negative” of these remainders/stains/gaps (Zizek never tires
of inventing new names for it), incessantly pointing out the gaps or contradictions in
189
every material configuration passing itself off as whole, complete, coherent, substantial.
For Deleuze, on the other hand, all negativity is only the after-effect of a more
fundamental and positive expressive force, a different force relative to different matters
for intensive flows of affects, for experimentation, when it might seem that concrete
situations should require us to decide in each case whether we need more difference or
What Badiou is sensitive to is the way in which the language of art plays into what Zizek
calls “the plague of fantasies.” Badiou thinks that we are appealed by the decision for
intensity simply because of our animal discontent and our confused morass of desires. It
feels good to have someone affirming that we should all follow “lines of flight” that
would finally liberate our animals and clarify our desires. But Badiou is wrong to think
that this is simply the preference of an elite culture. It is rather a call to every culture to
cultivate that which is difficult and rare for it. In what follows I will argue that what
needs all our art, for Deleuze, can best be understood as a kind of magic.
190
VIII. Immanence, Transformed: Modernity, Magic, and Metamorphosis
The thought suggests itself that we may have completed a gigantic cycle
of language from Homer’s time, where the word evokes the thing, to our
own day, where the thing evokes the word, and are now about to go
around the cycle again, as we seem to be confronted once again with an
energy common to subject and object which can be expressed verbally
only through some form of metaphor.
avatar of certain Renaissance Neo-Platonist ideas about the poetic nature of reality, and
Cartesian poetic, creative, even “magical” conception of the human mind as not merely a
knower but a transformer of universally expressive being. Although Deleuze does not
share the neoplatonic taste for a transcendent One that hierarchically orders or
worlds. From this unstable, problematic immanence of life to itself, creation is born.
simply an aesthetic and metaphysical gesture, but also ethical and political. The quest of
certain Renaissance philosophers to validate the knowledge of the magician took place in
a period of deep questioning about the nature of the human, a period which has much in
common with our own postmodern day. The Renaissance saw a deep shaking of
191
political communities, about where religion ended and science began, and about what a
new and unbounded sense of nature entailed for the categories of philosophical thought.
While humanist rhetoricians attempted to sidestep the depth of the peripatetic crisis, those
who held onto a real relation between the substance of the nonhuman world and the
structure of the human mind turned to the paradigm of magical interactions—bonds and
rituals—with nature. For the Renaissance thinkers that we will briefly cover here, homo
magus is both more and less than human(ist): his way of knowing puts him in a liminal
space between animal and human, elemental and cosmic, earth and heaven—a space
constituted by precisely the kind of rapport between mind and matter that peripatetic
logic had tended to obscure, would soon be undermined by Cartesian skepticism and
finally rendered opaque by Kantian transcendental dialectics, where mind resigns itself to
validating its own operations, with or without things themselves. Nature is abandoned to
obscurity. But what the magus knows is a rhetoric worthy of nature’s gift: philosophy,
rites and incantations—that might work with natural energies to bring about the
God, or powers amenable to our needs, underwrites the laws of nature—at least not
through any “experience” Kant can legitimate in his critiques.152 We can only know the
extent to which our faculties of understanding, sensation, and reason are functioning
properly, or are “resolving” objects in accordance with the rules of possible experience,
192
determined by a priori categories. The knowledge of the magus does not answer to the
transcendental limits Kant delineated for experience. The magician, or shaman, or ritual
healer, can think across the categories of space and time, as well as across the other
categories, because the ritual space is one where knowledge of the power of images,
signs, and ideas is at one with the transformations they make real.
As anthropologist and philosopher Jose Gil puts it in his study of the power of the
“Magical” knowledge, such as the knowledge involved in the construction and execution
of a healing ritual, performatively passes beyond the Kantian division of phenomena and
neumena. This is because, under the correct ritual conditions, words are actions, time is
space, forms are materials, and the “loose and overcoded” energy of divine powers
constrains itself in ways that humans can, as Gil puts it, “treat” (MB 84).
dialectically) enables judgment, but never transformation. But in the pre-Kantian era,
prior to Cartesian dualism and before the rise of Baconian science, certain philosophers in
193
the Renaissance, from Cusa and Ficino to Pico della Mirandola and Giordano Bruno
considered that the idea that the knowledge implied by certain forms of magic (especially
mathematical and ritual magic) might hold the key to the unification of not only science
and art, but of heaven and earth. For in magic they saw, as does Gil, a form of knowing
that blurs the distinction between nature and art, subject and object, matter and memory,
powers human and divine. Insofar as Deleuze has invented concepts that once again
cross the thresholds of Kantian antinomies, Deleuze in a sense re-poses problems about
the nature of the human mind that modern philosophy pre-empted and postmodern
“human” is no longer anthropomorphic, and the earth is no longer “in its place,” but is
understood as a set of mobile cosmic forces, a set of elemental powers that are not
truly known.
magic in the Renaissance, the problems Deleuze is concerned with become clearer than
they do when understood, as they usually are, against the background of post-Kantian
Deleuze’s thought, a renaissance of renaissance problems. What philosophy does not yet
has an immanent principle of selection, a poetic-magical principle that works toward the
increase of life. In this thesis I suggest that reading Deleuze in this way, the problematic
ideas existing in the uncanny relations between the Renaissance epoch and our own can
194
become distinct, if not fully clear. These problems can only be re-posed here, between
Deleuze and a few of the Renaissance avatars of his work. I will not be attempting to
solve the problems, but to clarify what problems are really being posed.
Deleuze’s aesthetics, and why we seem to lack to categories for it, and why he insists that
us to think without or beyond modern assumptions. But there are many aspects of his
work that do not fit the postmodern mold. If postmodernism represents the breakdown or
undoing of modernity, and the either raucous or melancholy playing among modernity’s
ruins, Deleuze’s inherently constructive thought is better situated in what we might call a
Bruno Latour’s We Have Never Been Modern analyzes the modern era as a kind
of hypocrisy. On the one hand, we moderns systematically attempt to separate out what
is natural from what is cultural, what is mental from what is material, what is fact from
what is value, what is illusion from what is real. On the other hand, we systematically
live and work with objects that in and of themselves mediate between these realms. Our
dilemma is that while we insist that mind and matter, nature and culture, are ontologically
195
to the other in order to render our arbitrary system of representation “grounded” in some
way, either in a theory of which categories are valid a priori or in a positivistic theory
that reduces one side of the duality to the other, a posteriori. Latour sees postmodernity
For Latour, the solution is not to give up the process of “modernizing” by simply
pointing out the incoherence of the dualities (deconstructionism) but to realize that we
generate modern dualisms as an effect of our attempt to succeed at what we are already
doing, which is to involve ourselves in processes that both precede and exceed us, but
also completely involve us. For Latour, the act (we are always already engaged in) of
“delegating” a series of objects (machines, religions, rituals, styles) to bear the weight of
reality is not the creation of “hybrids” of the two sides of the modern story, but is rather
the generation of “transcendent” things that can no longer be opposed to things immanent
to one side or the other of the great post-Cartesian divide. Here is how Latour puts it.
196
angels, lieutenants, spokespersons, and cherubim. What sort of world is it
that obliges us to take into account, at the same time and in the same
breath, the nature of things, technologies, sciences, fictional beings,
religions large and small, politics, jurisdictions, economies and
unconsciousnesses? Our own, of course. That world ceased to be
modern when we replaced all essences with mediators, delegates and
translators that gave them meaning. That is why we do not yet recognize
it. It has taken on an ancient aspect, with all those delegates, angels and
lieutenants. (M 129)
The last time philosophy had such an “ancient” aspect was in the eclectic
neoplatonic philosophies of the Italian Renaissance. Prior to the laying down of the great
Cartesian grid over matter, and before Cartesian ambivalence about the role of the
mind serving exactly that angelic or lieutenant or delegational role Latour insists we
moderns have not yet acknowledged as that which we already practice. These 15th- and
16th- century thinkers, including Nicholas of Cusa, Marsilio Ficino, Pico della Mirandola,
and Giordano Bruno, were all inspired by a “materialist” strand of Neo-Platonism whose
between materiality and mind, seeing matter as inherently fallen and duplicitous, a
chaotic depth from which the soul hopes to emerge and of which the soul hopes to purify
itself. Iamblichus begged to differ. For Iamblichus, rather than the material world being
contemplation, material multiplicity is seen as the occasion of the One to display the
magnificence of its powers. The paradigm for this display is theurgy, the act in which
mathematical forms and material elements ritually combine to make the world a suitable
seat for divinity.153 The one who knows the proper theurgies is nothing less than one
197
who has mastered philosophy not only in its contemplative or reflective dimension, but in
its active, incantatory, and transformative powers. A new figure of the “knower”
contemplative.
This is the figure of the magus man, a figure whose history in the West goes back
at least to the Corpus Hermetica, and whose legacy inspires the esoteric research of
of the Corpus only came to the fore briefly, during the Italian Renaissance. This
happened partly because of the Catholic Platonist Marsilio Ficino’s attempt to recover the
prisca theologica—an ancient pagan theology dating from Egypt and constituting a kind
of justifiably universal pagan natural religion that could be sanctified by Catholic faith in
In the words of Ficino’s student Pico della Mirandola, nothing proved the divinity
of Christ as much as magic and the cabala. Pico could claim this because both the
esoteric sciences (divination, astrology, etc.) depend on the principle of “as above, so
below.” For Pico, the created world, though fallen, can be restored through “magical”
knowledge of its true forms, available through processes first espied by the Egyptian
sorcerers and the Chaldean oracles, transmitted to the West through Plato and the Corpus
Pico’s mentor Ficino, took a rather more reserved, contemplative, and “aesthetic”
interest in magic, one that had little interest in real operations of transformation,
198
divination, or sorcery. Ficino attempted to “neoplatonize” the magic of the Asclepius in
his Pymander by making magical talismans correspond to the celestial hierarchies of the
through ranks of divine names or angelic hierarchies, for the express purpose of
worshipping the Triune God. But there was evidence in both the pseudo-Dionysus and
the Corpus Hermetica that some forms of practical and ritual magic might be reconciled
In this vein, Pico della Mirandola added a kind of practical cabala which gave the
magus a much more active relationship with the angelic world (Ficino’s was ultimately a
left undebated due to the censors of Pope Innocent, Pico della Mirandola defined (and
was willing to defend) natural or practical magic (as opposed to purely contemplative
Given any practical object, the operation that acts on it (quae eum practicat) is
nobler than that which contemplates it [Thesis 3>46].
No power exists in heaven or earth seminally and separated that the magician
cannot actuate and unite [Thesis 9>5].
The form of all magical power comes from the soul of man standing, and not
falling [Thesis 9>12].
To operate magic is nothing other than to marry the world [Thesis 9>13].156
in fact taught that this connection was the key to reconciling various wisdom traditions
199
with Christianity, and that certain healing and divining magics would be the logical and
glorious outcome of the synthesis of all philosophies in one system. In his preface to the
I have proposed theorems about magic, too, wherein I have signified that
magic is twofold. The first sort is put together by the work and authorship
of demons, and is a thing, as God is true, execrable and monstrous. The
other sort is, when well explored, nothing but the absolute consummation
of the philosophy of nature.157
Pico thus went far beyond Ficino in reviving the mythic figure of homo magus, the idea
of a human “operator” who is able, through moral purity and mental acumen, to ascend
through the levels of natural, mathematical, and finally divine orders, finally reaching a
parity with divine mens that makes him a co-creator with God.
Pico’s cosmology was Christian and neoplatonic. For Pico the sympathies
between things—that “knowledge things have of each other”—is an effect of their being
hierarchically ordered in a divine economy of exchange whereby the lower (i.e. animal)
is disposed to receive what the higher (i.e. human) gives, just as that higher (human) in
turn receives from that on which it depends (the angelic or rational). The practice of
magic is thus a process of spiritual ascent and descent “on” the hierarchies, and this
analogical, hierarchical order legitimates the link between natural philosophy and
200
In the century that followed, however, Giordano Bruno developed a view of
magical sympathies that set the possibility of transformation not in the interlocking
hierarchy of forms but in the fecundity of matter itself. He writes, in Cause, Principle,
and Unity,
. . . forms do not exist without matter, in which they are generated and
corrupted, and out of whose bosom they spring and into which they are
taken back. Hence, matter, which always remains fecund and the same,
must have as the fundamental prerogative of being the only substantial
principle; as that which is, and forever remains, and the forms together are
to be taken merely as varied dispositions of matter, which come and go,
cease and renew themselves, so that none have value as principle. This is
why we find philosophers who, having pondered thoroughly the essence
of natural forms, such as one may see in Aristotle and his kind, have
finally concluded that they are only accidents and peculiarities of matter,
so that, according to them, it is to matter that we must accord the privilege
of being act and perfection, and not to the things of which we can truly say
that they are neither substance nor nature, but relative to the substance and
nature—that is to say, in their opinion, matter, which for them is a
necessary, eternal and divine principle, as it is to Avicebron, the Moor,
who calls it “God who is in everything” (CPU 61).
Ultimately the idea that matter is God comes out of Nicholas of Cusa’s idea of
If the universe is infinite, the divine can no longer be conceived as the limit of the finite,
but must be envisaged as that which the finite “complicates” in itself. “God” is the fully
explicated aspect of that same infinity. Both Cusa and Bruno attempted to construe a
paradigm of natural process in the universe that exceeded the medieval image of fixed
and essential cosmic hierarchies, or visibly fixed limits (from the primum mobile, through
angelic mens, down to all other forms of order. Cusa achieved this new epistemology, a
docta ignoranta, by inserting a cosmic Word at the center of a world that no longer had a
center and whose circumference was nowhere. The invasion and insinuation everywhere
201
of the Word made Flesh could be discerned by the “holy fool” whose perceptions were
in the event of the God-Man, Christ. Giordano Bruno emptied this Christological center
and made transformation or the vinculum [bonds] of transformability, in all their manifest
and magical variety, the only guarantee of metamorphosis.159 Bruno anticipates both the
monadology of Leibniz and the Deus, sive natura of Spinoza. But unlike the metaphysics
of his post-Cartesian cousins (and this is crucial for the connection with Deleuze),
Bruno’s thought is neither perfectly “geometrical” nor the object of an infinite calculus.
Unlike Spinoza and Leibniz after him, Bruno was no mathematician and considered the
thought must always entertain an empirical and pragmatic moment of attention to things
in their contingency and volatility, and never take nature as the manifestation of
formalizable objects. Bruno thought that even Aristotle, for all the power of his thought
of substance, obscured nature with his logic of potential and actual, and his subordination
of accident to essence.
of accidental vicissitudes has much in common with the ontology of Gilles Deleuze.160
The plurality of becomings, the life of mater materia, is not an entity given to reflection,
but is espied only in an active, incantational, and even “magical” science, a science
driven by a certain kind of passion or love. This is, for Bruno, a passionate or “frenzied”
202
experience of inventing finite images of being that penetrate the secrets of nature only
insofar as they suffer their own limitations. This, at least, is how it is ultimately
allegorized as the continually (failed) quest of the lover to hymn the beloved.
How is this passion of the image a way of knowing (a question we could also put
to Deleuze)? For Bruno, what ultimately what distinguishes a true image of nature from
a false one is not a matter of whether it correctly imitates nature, but whether it invents a
passage beyond the “shadows” of nature which we perceive. This is why in the critical
perceived as a proto-Hegelian). The difference, here, is that the “rules” for constructing
It is the poetry that makes the rules, not the rules that makes the poetry.161 Ultimately
“magic” for Bruno is the poetic act with which knowledge of nature begins. We can only
know through images of nature, despite their ultimate “inadequacy.”162 Bruno’s view of
mind is that it is immanent to the fecundity of the infiniti universi i mondi—he believed
consort with nature’s infinity forced him to become other than himself, to undergo the
Whereas for Pico, God is still communicated in the universe on the basis
transcendence, for Bruno it is the immanence of the divine in matter itself which enables
that he names “love,” a kind of Leibnizian communicates of each and each to all. As
. . . the love by which we love, and the tendency by which all things
desire, are intermediaries between good and evil, between the ugly and the
203
beautiful (not themselves being ugly or beautiful). And so they are good
and beautiful because of a sort of sharing and participation, for the bond of
love has a nature which is both active and possible. And by this, things
act, or are acted upon, or both, as they desire to be ordered, joined, united
and completed, insofar as it is within the nature of each nothing to be
occupied with order, joining, union, and completion. Without this bond
there is nothing, just as without nature there is nothing. Because of this,
therefore, love is not a sign of imperfection when it is considered in matter
and in the chaos before things were produced. For indeed, anything which
is considered in the chaos and in brute matter, and is also said to be love,
is simultaneously said to be a perfection. And whatever is said to be
imperfect, disordered and not to be, is understood not to be love. Thus, it
is established that love is everywhere a perfection, and this bond of love
gives witness everywhere to perfection. When an imperfect thing desires
to be perfected this, indeed takes place in something which is imperfect,
but not because it is imperfect. Rather, this happens because of a
participation in a perfection and in a divine light and in an object having a
more eminent nature, which it desires more strongly inasmuch as the
object is more vivacious. That which is more perfect burns with greater
love for the highest good than that which is imperfect. Therefore, that
principle is most perfect which wishes to become all things, and which is
not oriented to any particular form but to a universal form and universal
perfection. And this is universal matter, without which there is no form, in
whose power, desire, and disposition all forms are located, and which
receives all forms in the development of its parts, even though it cannot
receive two forms at the same time. Hence matter is in a sense divine, just
as form, which is either a form of matter or nothing, is also in a sense
divine. There is nothing outside of matter or without matter, otherwise the
power to make and to be made would be one and the same thing, and
would be grounded in one undivided principle, because the power to make
anything and the power of anything to be made would be either present or
absent together. There is only one potency taken absolutely and in itself…
it is not a foolish opinion which was defended by David of Dinant and by
Avicebron in his Fons vitae, who cited the Arabs who also ventured to
assert that God is matter. (CPU 173)
For Bruno this takes place in an unbounded cosmos, an infinite universe and
worlds. Despite his enthusiasm for the Copernican move beyond Ptolemaic geocentrism,
Bruno famously reproached Copernicus for having “studied mathematics more than
nature,” just as he criticized Aristotle for never tiring of dividing in reason that which is
unified in nature.163 For Bruno, the ultimate power of nature is not its formal attributes,
204
but its energy, an energy which in an infinite universe full of infinite worlds—much like
types, no matter how pleasing to geometry and mathematics such a vision may be.
Historian of science Fernand Hallyn formulates Bruno’s move well. Hallyn writes, in
Despite the impossibility of imaging the infinity of the cosmos, we must do so. Bruno’s
quest in the On the Composition of Images, Signs, and Ideas is a mannerist one: a
speculative quest for an image of that which is beyond form. This puts Bruno on the
edge of the world Foucault defined, in the Order of Things, as the epistemic world of
similitude, a world where things and words resemble one another and relate through
images—of, say, Saturn as an old man with camel’s feet and a sickle—in order to work
205
Augustine also mentions this in the eighth book of his City of God. For
such is the concordance of the world that celestial things draw super-
celestial things, and natural things, supernatural things, through the virtue
running through all and the participation in it of all species.165
In this Renaissance magus images are indispensable for thought: they are not
illustrations or examples but talismans and emblems of reality. For magic requires
thinking in and through images because it takes the world itself as shadow or simulacrum
of God’s absolute infinity, and views natural philosophy as active practice in which the
final goal is not contemplation but dynamic action, a revolutionary science of love that is
This is, anyway, how it was for Bruno, who used images not only to remember
(by constructing Lullian memory theatres) but also to access that which had not yet been
seen. The image is both where knowledge is housed and also where it reaches its own
limits, a limit that only the heroic will can cross. As Agrippa puts it,
. . .you must know that these kind of figures are nothing unless they are
vivified so that there is in them . . . a natural virtue, or a celestial virtue, or
a heroic, animistic, demonic, or angelic virtue. But who can give soul to
an image, life to stone, metal, wood, or wax? And who can make
children of Abraham come out of stones? Truly this secret is not know to
the thick-witted worker . . . and no one has such powers but he who has
cohabited with the elements, vanquished nature, mounted higher than the
heavens, elevating himself above the angels to the archetype itself, with
whom he then becomes co-operator and can do all things.166
Who can be magical? Who can be the co-operator of nature? Who is worthy?
Only certain minds can “vivify” the images. Only certain images pass from imitation to
invention.167 What, then is the criteria for a worthy image? What is the criteria for
magic? How do we know who the good poet is? We repeat her poetry. How do we
know good magic? If the possibility of knowing nature is the possibility of constructing
an inventive image of nature, then the possibility of true magic is also the possibility of
206
true art. And how do we recognize true poetry? Because, as Bruno’s Tansilio says in
But also because true poetry like true magic loves life. In his commentary on love
in Plato’s Symposium. Ficino had already argued that love is the essence of magical
power. “Why is Love called Magus?” he asks. “Because all the force of Magic consists
in Love. The work of Magic is a certain drawing of one thing to another by natural
similitude. The parts of this world, like members of one animal, depend all on one Love,
and are connected together by natural communion” (Commentary, Oratio VI, cap. 10).
This is the theme Bruno takes up in his account of bonding, De Vinculum. But its
ultimate source is in the Pimander, one of the texts of the Corpus Hermetica. The Magus
Man comes down to earth from above because he loves nature and is passionately drawn
to her beauty. The magus has a fundamentally erotic relationship with nature.168
descent into the depths of nature. This remains neoplatonic in the Iamblichan sense,
where it is not contemplative ascent of the one but theurgical descent of the “ones,”
ritually evoked, that transform matter into a worthy seat of divine life.169 This is what
Bruno explores in his Heroic Frenzies. Knowledge of nature itself is impossible, but
through the construction of images we experience the limits of our own minds. This limit
experience causes us to press further and further into the depths of nature, until the maker
becomes the un-made and re-made, the hunter the hunted, the knower the known, and the
bonder the one who is bonded. It is the beauty of Diana which seduces the philosopher.
Bruno writes,
I say very few are the Acteons to whom destiny gives the power to
contemplate Diana naked, and the power to become so enamored of the
207
beautiful harmony of the body of nature, so fallen beneath the gaze of
those two lights of the dual splendor of goodness and beauty, that they are
transformed into deer, inasmuch as they are no longer the hunters but the
hunted. For the ultimate and last end of this chase is the capture of a
fugitive and wild prey, through which the hunter becomes the hunted, the
pillager becomes the pillaged. Because in all the other species of the
chase undertaken for particular things, it is the hunter who seeks to capture
those things for himself, absorbing them through the mouth of this
particular intelligence; but in that divine and universal chase he comes to
apprehend that it is himself who necessarily remains captured, absorbed,
and united. (HF 225)
How does this vision connect to Deleuze? It has to do with the activation-affirmation
relationship between life and thought. If this relationship has been distorted by
categorical and representational habits of mind, the effect of this distortion is, essentially,
to preclude a magical rapport between mind and matter. Deleuze’s epistemology takes a
step toward restoring this rapport by making the adventure of mind equivocal with the
difference and repetition of elemental powers, and our life of learning equivocal with the
208
This notion of a knowledge that transforms is obviously where Deleuze connects
to the Renaissance. But it is also obvious that we no living any longer in that episteme.
Michel Foucault traced the difference between our time and the Renaissance in terms of a
contrast between a world entirely written and a world constituted by a gap between the
tables on which knowledge was represented and the represented things. In “The Prose of
the World,” Foucault explains how the Renaissance could accept the idea of a nature
writes,
For it was very possible that before Babel, before the Flood, there had
already exited a form of writing composed of the marks of nature itself,
with the result that its characters would have the power to act upon things
directly, to attract them or repel them, to represent their properties, their
virtues, and their secrets. A primitively natural writing, of which certain
forms of esoteric knowledge, and the cabala first and foremost, may
perhaps have preserved the scattered memory and were now attempting to
retrieve its long-dormant powers . . .
. . . And indeed, when one goes back to take a look at the Historia
serpentum et draconum, one finds the chapter, ‘On the serpent in general’
arranged under the following headings: equivocation (which means the
various meanings of the word serpent), synonyms and etymologies,
differences, form and description, anatomy, nature and habits,
temperament, coitus and generation, voice, movements, places, diets,
physiognomy, antipathy, sympathy, modes of capture, death and wounds
caused by the serpent, modes and signs of poisonings, remedies, epithets,
denominations, prodigies and presages, monsters, mythology, gods to
which it is dedicated, fables, allegories, and mysteries, hieroglyphics,
emblems and symbols, proverbs, coinage, miracles, riddles, devices,
heraldic signs, historical facts, dreams, simulacra and statues, use in
human diet, use in medicine miscellaneous uses . . . And indeed for
Aldrovandi and his contemporaries, it was all legenda—things to be read.
But for this reason for this was not that they preferred the authority of en
to the precision of an unprejudiced eye, but that nature, in itself, is an
unbroken tissue of words and signs, of accounts and characters, of
discourse and forms [my emphasis]. . . to know an animal or a plant, or
any terrestrial thing whatever, is to gather together the whole dense layer
of signs with which it may have been covered; it is to rediscover also the
209
constellations of forms from which they derive their value as heraldic
signs Aldrovandi was neither a better nor a worse observer than Buffon;
he was neither more credulous than he, nor less attached to the faithfulness
of the observing eye or the to the rationality of things. His observation
was simply not linked to thing in accordance with the same system or by
the same arrangement of the episteme. For Aldrovandi was meticulously
contemplating a nature which was, from top to bottom, written.170
The possibility of a unified “prose of the world” lay, for Renaissance Neo-
an atheist, but he nevertheless re-poses the possibility of a prose of the world—this time
in terms of the artful immanence of things to themselves. What happens to the status of
the sign when we accept the possibility that things signify themselves—that sign
structures are not “overlayed” on things by human consciousness, that language is not
“papered onto” things, but that things have a power to signify all their own? This is the
When the Classical period began to attempt to purify and clarify what was
those places or conditions under which things might signify themselves. Latour has
brilliantly and clearly explicated this as the attempt to empty out the true locus of being
(which is mediation, transition, translation, and transformation) into two isolatable and
opposed poles. But the solution, for Latour, is not to “go back” to primitive magic and
sorcery, but to see how already in our times there are masked, diverted, overcoded, or de-
and re-territorialized conditions under which objects and subjects are not isolated into
opposed dimensions. There are already practices vibrant in our own day which give us, if
only in perverse or hysterical or schizoid forms, the truly complicated nature of things.
These spaces, situations, and activities are those Deleuze analyzes in terms of the
210
achievement of “immanence,” an achievement, in our day, that is unfortunately more and
(which is why it is, in a way better to think of Deleuze as a kind of pantheist than an
Despite some evidence to the contrary, the experimental modernism of Gilles Deleuze,
assemblages, the plan(e) established by those delegates, angels and lieutenants (Latour
themselves across different assemblages of being, it is not that we return to the world of
similitude and analogy, but that under certain conditions the world of similitude
uncannily returns to us, developing analogies that, if aesthetic (rather than natural) are
211
It is in this combined erotic, pragmatic and poststructuralist semiotic that this
Deleuzian lieutenant, this angel takes command: she is an artist whose creativity cannot
art and science and philosophy are indistinct in their ways and means, but because the
makers and physicists. We lack terms for what philosophy produces because we situate
concepts outside of their referents, ideas outside of things, signs in opposition to forces,
in keeping with the modern dichotomy of inchoate nature and rationalized society. Above
all we oppose identification (this is that) and creation (this becomes that), still caught in
the “transcendentalist” illusion, or even the “Socratic” one, that the essence of mind is the
right judgment of a world from which it is de facto or de jute separated. But Deleuze
shows us that this is driven by the habitual presumption that thought is a matter of good
and common sense—that truth is the opposite of error or mistakes in judgment, when it is
in fact the opposite only of the blank and sterile repetitions of habit. The truth worth
apprehending, for Deleuze, cannot be opposed to falsity, but only to the ordinary, and the
real error of thought is not falsehood but stupidity, that betiment in which we slumber.
is no longer its task to give laws. Concepts can no longer be thought of as generalities in
the way that law “covers” different sets of experiences or different sets of objects. If
genuine concepts and singular events emerge together, as Deleuze insists they always do,
the intuitions to which these sense-events give rise cannot be larger than discrete sense-
events. We are, as Latour puts it, “weavers of morphisms” (M 137). We make (and
break) alliances and exchanges between things (that are never merely inert objects). The
212
Deleuzian philosopher is magical in the sense that she inhabits the modern world as a
“weaver of morphism,” and not as a judge or even an inquirer. The peculiar magic of
philosophy is that its concepts, like the affects of art render the world of a singular thing.
It does this in a way that immediately transforms the philosopher into a “conceptual
This means that the philosophical concepts worth creating are those that function
like signs in a healing ritual: no longer descriptions or deductions of the world, but
transformations of it through acts that are located at a place where signs and powers are
synthetic a priori judgment. The synthesis of such a thought, writes Deleuze, “is of the
molecular and the cosmic, material and force, not form and matter, Grund and territory.
make thought travel, make it mobile, make it a force of the Cosmos (in the same way as
Astral travel, but to a star called this world, not another. The great film-makers of
the Italian neo-realism and the French new-wave sought to make us believe again in this
world. They did this by synthesizing our experience in ways that made our lives much
more mobile, our affects much more impersonal, our self-conceptions much more plastic
and pliable than we though possible. As he puts it in the second volume of his work on
cinema, Cinema 2: The Time-Image, it is the quest of the film auteur to address the fact
that “we no longer believe in this world” (C2 171). Yet we film the world in order to
213
create links within it: “the less human the world is, the more it is the artist’s duty to
believe and produce belief in a relation between man and the world, because the world is
Bruno once said that the creation of new worlds always involve the disintegration
This is the most important and most fundamental and of all the principles
which provide an explanation of the marvels found in nature; namely, that
because of an active principle and universal soul, nothing is so incomplete,
defective or imperfect, or, according to common opinion, so completely
insignificant that it could not become the source of great events. Indeed,
on the contrary, a very large disintegration into such components must
occur for an almost completely new world to be generated from them.
(CPU 111).
“Magical” knowledge, like the magic of a cinema working with time images, knows that
the seemingly meager elements (or disjointed times) into which things dissolve are closer
to the genetic elements of new worlds than the “molar” or “arborescent” forms (or
movement images) around which our habits and memories tend to ossify.
And the magically productive knowledge of modern art is never merely a matter
(ATP 344). “The sobriety of the assemblages is what makes for the richness of the
Machine’s effects,” Deleuze writes (ATP 344). This means that there must be a
fuzzy, this is not because we force them to be so but because, by delight, by instinct, by
attraction, we find fuzzy aggregates that have the necessary consolidation or consistency.
All good magicians know which images to work with, how much chaos to let into
the trance, how many spirits are required. If children and the mad sometimes indicate the
214
direction we should go towards finding assemblages, they are not exemplary for the truly
modern translator or mediator or transmuter: “the modern figure is not the child or the
lunatic, still less the artist [in the Romantic sense of the genius] but the cosmic artisan . . .
To be an artisan and no longer an artist, creator, or founder, is the only way to become
cosmic, to leave milieus and the earth behind. The invocation to the Cosmos does not at
all operate as a metaphor; on the contrary, the operation is an effective one, from the
345).
Like Bruno, Deleuze saw philosophy, painting, and poetry as a common act.
There is also an intense connection between a world that is infinite, unbounded, even
chaotic and certain signs, images, and ideas through which that infinity can be known.
that it is the series of finite figures that is the ultimate ontological term, or what Aristotle
would call first in the order of being. Not a substance, but an act. A pure transition. An
What, in Deleuze’s terms, is the magic of the event? It lies in the image of itself.
Or, as he puts it in his late work on Leibniz, the magic of events is that they are “folded”
An event does not just mean “a man has been run over.” The Great
Pyramid is an event, and its duration for a period of one hour, thirty
minutes, five minutes . . ., a passage of nature, of God, or a view of God.
215
What are the conditions that make an event possible? Events are
produced in a chaos, in a chaotic multiplicity, but only under the
conditions that a sort of screen intervenes.
Chaos does not exist; it is an abstraction because it is inseparable
from a screen that makes something—something rather than
nothing—emerge from it. Chaos would be a pure Many, a purely
disjunctive diversity, while the something is a One, not a pregiven unity,
but instead the indefinite article that designates a certain singularity. (F
76).
event. There is always a Figure or Diagram or Image (cinematic, musical, even animal)
that brings the event with it, which gives us the singular distinctions between form and
Logic of Sense, thought is never just of the event, but of the sense-event, and the counter-
character combining the openness to chance of a Zen Master, the courage of a Stoic, and
Deleuze, those things he calls the machinc or, following the humorist and surrealist
Alfred Jarry, “the pataphysical.” Whereas irony sees the failure of the machine as the
impossibility of life, humor sees the machinc as life itself: life is a special effect of
certain machinc functions. Certain modern art forms help us see this. Transformative
transpersonal and transindividual permutation of affects across the subjects and objects of
literature in T.E. Lawrence, Joyce, Melville, Kafka, and Proust . . . all these “machinic
216
functions” extract something in sensation that is not sensibility but simultaneously the
limit of sensibility and the real condition of creating new worlds of experience.
This is why philosophy’s relationship to art is not for Deleuze the one of
articulating the conditions of possibility for the effects of art upon our subjectivity. It is
rather a thinking along with art, an extrapolating of the real conditions under which life
whose service philosophy works. Whereas Deleuze enthusiasts like Keith Ansell Pearson
and Manuel Delanda have seen in this what is most “revolutionary” about Deleuze’s
thought, Badiou and Zizek have found Deleuze’s notion of Life his most naïve and
counter-productive moment. But neither side of the debate, it seems to me, takes
Deleuze thinks of life in artistic terms—life is an art form for Deleuze. But it is
not a representational art form, nor an organic life. It is an abstract art and a non-organic
life. The life that interests Deleuze is a twisting, free, and fragile line that passes between
the inertia of matter and the rigidity of form. Philosophy, as much as art or science,
comes to have an intuition of these “machinic” lines (that are not mechanized, as they
were for 17th- and 18th-century physics) when it invents concepts along with those
becomings or trajectories that pass between the categorical dualisms of form and matter,
content and expression. This was how Worringer described the Northern or “Gothic”
217
line. As Deleuze puts it, in a passage that summarizes the research of A Thousand
The Greek organic line, which subordinates volume and spatiality, takes
over from the Egyptian geometrical line, which reduced them to the plane.
The organic, with its symmetry and contours inside and outside, still refers
to the rectilinear coordinates of a striated space. The organic body is
prolonged by straight lines that attach it to what lies in the distance.
Hence the primacy of human beings, or of the face: We are this form of
expression itself, simultaneously the supreme organism and the relation of
all organisms to metric space in general. The abstract, on the contrary,
begins only with what Worringer presents as the “Gothic” avatar. It is this
nomadic line that he says is mechanical, but in free action and swirling; it
is inorganic, yet alive, and all the more alive for being inorganic. It is
distinguished both from the geometrical and the organic. It raises
“mechanical” relations to the level of intuition. Heads (even a human
being’s when it is not a face) unravel and coil into ribbons in a continuous
process; mouths curl in spirals. Hair, clothes . . . This streaming, spiraling,
zigzagging, snaking, feverish line of variation liberates a power of life that
human beings had rectified and organisms had confined, and which matter
now expresses as the trait, flow, or impulse traversing it. If everything is
alive, it is not because everything is organic or organized but, on the
contrary, because the organism is a diversion of life. In short, the life in
question is inorganic, germinal, and intensive, a powerful life without
organs, a Body that is all the more alive for having no organs, everything
that passes between organisms (“once the natural barriers of organic
movement have been overthrown, there are no more limits”). (ATP 499)
“poetic” process is the role of mind in ritual magic.175 When the operators of magical
rituals establish symbols, signs, and movements, this is not in order to realize what it
would take for a result to be produced, but in fact to produce that result. This is
accomplished when the operators in some sense become the signs (of healing, of
divination, of necromancy, etc.) that they have made. When Deleuze calls philosophy to
become-other in thought, this can happen because the signs of things are in things, but
force us to think only when they (creatively) intersect with or diverge from other things
and the signs they emit. In this way Deleuze does not think of what is signified in a sign
218
(or what is reflected in concepts) as being “immaterial” as opposed to the materiality of
the affects and percepts of art and science. On the contrary, affects and percepts are
limits of what can be felt and sensed, as much as signs are the limits of what can be
which is a form of “intense” life, would look for ways in which affects, percepts, and
concepts continually push beyond what we have habitually accepted as reality, for the
This is why Deleuze is not a materialist in the classical sense, and in fact it is easy
to read him as an idealist, since he often writes in his early work as if ideal dynamisms of
becoming, or what he later calls abstract machines, were somehow the foundation or
ground of reality. The misapprehension here is that what is basic and fundamental for
Deleuze is not a substance of any kind, whether ideal or real, but an event which is
always an act of creation. These events have specific structures, but it is the structure
which depends on the event and not vice versa—as he says in Anti-Oedipus, “structures
Deleuze’s is thus a monism of becomings that has only a pragmatic and semiotic
possibilities for transmutation). But much like Spinoza’s 3rd-order knowing, the real
being of these structures is apprehended only under certain conditions, under essays or
assays critical and clinical, which I will explore in the next five chapters. That we should
arguing for a “return” to a premodern sensibility that sees the world as enchanted. It is
219
enough, already, to remark the affinity between Deleuze’s metaphysical vision, which is
an encounter with a transformative signs that requires the special conditions of art,
science and philosophy, with the magical vision of certain Italian philosophers who, on
the cusp of “modern” philosophy, also envisaged the intuitions of a genuine first
philosophy as being available only under the intense, ecstatic, and ritualized conditions of
magical enactment.176 What magic there may be left for modern times is a question we
can only pose along with Deleuze. The answer depends upon possibilities of life we may
still need to admit we truly desire before they can become as real as they are.
220
Notes
1
Both “real” and “experience” here are highly contested terms in philosophy. What Deleuze
means by reality and by experience will become clear only gradually and by contrast with other
positions (Aristotelian, Kantian, Hegelian, and phenomenological).
2
As in Foucault, where the visibility of the visible is not a secret but is hidden on the surface of
things. See Rajchman’s Michel Foucault: The Freedom of Philosophy (New York: Columbia
UP, 1985), p. 15.
3
See Foucault’s essay on Klossowski’s own “Acteonism,” his vertiginous descent into the world
of simulacra which inspired Deleuze, “The Prose of Acteon” in James D. Faubion, ed., Foucault:
Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology (New York: The New Press, 1998), pp. 103-124. This is
of course the preface to a novel, The Baphomet (Trans. Sophie Hawks and Stephen Sartarelli.
New York: Marsilio, 1988), about perverted modern magicians, the templars, who can do
nothing in 20th century life but make real those sexual perversions and inhuman violences of
which they were accused in the 17th century. Klossowski depicts the predicament of those who
experience magic as lost, and the world as simulacral. To some degree Deleuze is able to
transform or counter-actualize this predicament (being as simulacra) into a positive opportunity
(for potentially boundless—if still selective—becomings). One of the most important ethical
questions of our time is how to bring magicians, who can only be marginalized and ostracized
subjectivities, into positions of power where their arts become healing and giving rather than self-
destructive.
4
What the new defenders of transcendence and universality really object to, in Deleuze, is the
way in which he does not allow an isolated logophonic or logographic axiom to stand as a self-
sufficient form of thought. For Deleuze, thought is not thought until it is connected with
something else, another activity, other events. The power of any one interruption or interruptive
performance by any one group cannot constitute an event, because for Deleuze it is of the nature
of singularities (which “are” universals) to exist in the transits between various events, in a
peculiar hapticity or tangibility which blurs eye and hand, or “situation” and “unnamable” (to put
it in Badiou’s language). This is why Deleuze asks us to experience his concepts like we
experience the tangibility of a work of art—a tangibility that exists or insists across the medium,
materials, and characters the work involves on its way to establishing an extraordinary Figure.
5
What is meant exactly by magic here will become clear in the concluding chapter.
6
I use “critical” here in the sense common to Marxism, psycho-analysis, structuralism, and the
Frankfurt School. For all of these schools of thought, philosophy is first and foremost a critique
(of ideology, of consciousness, of sense, etc.). Deleuze’s thought is also primarily critical in the
sense of such “critiques” of the history of Western philosophy, per se, as Foucault’s archaeology,
Nietzsche’s genealogy, Bataille’s “excessive” thought, Heidegger’s Destruktion, Derrida’s
deconstruction, Gadamer’s critique of historicism, and Wittgenstein’s “therapy.” Deleuze’s is
part of a vast movement in 20th century thought (both analytic and continental) to renew the
possibility of thought in spite of philosophical presuppositions, yet within philosophical discourse
itself.
7
Affirmation is a technical term in Deleuze. It is linked to the idea that being is inherently
expressive—that, as Deleuze critic Dan Smith put it at a recent conference, being and event are
221
one and the same expression (Villanova University Graduate Student Conference, April 2006).
Artists affirm the nature of the world, but the nature of the world is available only in and through
that expressive affirmation. As I will emphasize in my concluding chapter, affirmation has a
sense captured not only by the “yes” of Nietzsche and of Joyce, but also in the “magical” theories
of complicatio coming out of Nicholas of Cusa and culminating in Giordano Bruno (Deleuze
acknowledges Bruno as the “master of complicatio” at Difference and Repetition, 57). For the
magical tradition in Neo-Platonism (which begins in Iamblichus and comes to Bruno through
Marsilio Ficino and Pico della Mirandola), the universe as God’s essence in complicatio is
“operable” (if not fully “knowable”) through certain powerful images, signs, and ideas.
Deleuze’s notion that art “evokes” or, as he quotes Proust, “performs the rites necessary” for the
essences of worlds to insist in artful signs, has deep resonances with this pre-modern magical
view of an “operable” nature. In “Learning Signs,” I will show how Deleuze sees this at work in
the art of Marcel Proust.
8
Readers of Nietzsche will immediately recognize the “anti-ressentiment” flavor of Deleuze’s
work. For Deleuze as for Nietzsche, critique is not just a matter of resisting the ossifications or
stratifications of (modern, bourgeois, fascist) life, but of a much more global attack on the types
or forms of life—human, animal, social, mechanical—that tend to resist life’s unpredictable and
uncanny dimension, since for them it is only (or primarily) through that dimension that creativity,
the life of life, is encountered.
9
Deleuze’s procedure has resonances with Nietzsche’s method of genealogy and Foucault’s
method of archaeology.
10
For Deleuze’s use of Nietzsche’s “untimely,” see The Logic of Sense, 265 ff.
11
See Michel Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History.” In Faubion, James D., ed. Foucault:
Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology (New York: The New Press, 1998), pp. 369-389.
12
Deleuze sees a profoundly “empiricist” tendency in Spinoza, since freedom in Spinoza arises
not through our will but through our essence—an essence which must pass through the modes of
our existence, or be practiced. As Deleuze writes in Spinoza: Expressionism in Philosophy, for
Spinoza “one is never free through one’s will and through that on which it patterns itself, but
through one’s essence and through that which follows from it” (149).
13
This is a paradox Deleuze confronts again and again in his work, posed as a question early in
his career: “How can a subject transcending the given be constituted in the given?” (ES 86). We
will continually return to this topic.
14
It is not only in modern art, but also already in the baroque that Deleuze finds a “subordination
of the true to what is singular and remarkable” (The Fold, 91).
15
It also becomes subject to those moral and epistemological criticisms Socrates levies against
the poets in the Ion and the Republic. For Socrates, if artists are striving to reproduce the essence
or idea of a man or a war in an image of that man or war, s/he has already failed by looking not to
the invisible truth of that thing but to an inherently limited and flawed appearance (of virtue or
courage). But if art does not imitate, but rather repeats the world, then images are not
representations of supersensible ideals, and the authenticity of art can no longer be a matter of
222
how well it figures the True or demonstrates the superiority of the Good, at least as “platonically”
conceived.
16
But it is not so much in the solutions (heroic virtues or villainous exploits), but in the problems
these characters pose: that is the “rub,” that is where we learn from art.
17
Romanticism might be defined at least in part as the quest for contact with the sublime origins
of nations, peoples, and destinies—the quest for a life beneath or beyond the illusions of state,
class, and creed. A romantic genius who apprehends a vital source might seem like Deleuze’s
ideal artist. But Romantic art (particularly German and English) attempts to subsume or include
or synthesize the intense differences and uncanny repetitions of life into a unified shape or form
(even if one that is only “tragically” present). Romantic art is the art of the “people” who rise up
to declare what the true world should be, even if it is impossible, and of the genius who speaks in
the name of that impossibility. For Deleuze, however, c’est la peuple qui manque—the people
are always missing from art, the people always remain to be conceived, created, born from the
elements art transforms, the signs art reads.
True creation or “genesis” for Deleuze is not Romantic because for Deleuze creativity is
not a synthesis but a synthesizer that channels current through different modulators to make
sound, forcing differences and resonances of sound not available apart from that experimentation.
Synthesizers are used as key exemplars of how to form “planes of immanence” in both A
Thousand Plateaus and in Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation. In the latter, Deleuze
contrasts analogical with digital synthesizers (FB 95). Analog synths (which, interestingly, have
experience a revival even after the ascendance of “superior” digital technology) operate with an
immediacy that is similar to the “brute fact” of Bacon’s painting methods, which forces paint
through modulators or “diagrams.” Bacon’s diagram is immediately present in his painting in the
same way that analog synthesizers create sound. Rather than converting electrical energy into
digital information (binary code) and then back into actual sound waves, analog synths operate
directly on the waves, in “real time.” The possibilities of analog synths are at one with their
operations, whereas in digital synths the possibilities for transformation are on another plane (in
computer “modules,” not in physical modulators). This makes a massive difference in the
tonality of the instrument. While digital synths can “imitate” other instruments (trumpets, flutes,
organs) better than analog synths, the analog synth sound is overwhelmingly preferred by
professional keyboard players to its digital counterpart. In Deleuzian terms, the analog
synthesizer has an “immanence” to itself that the digital does not, and this has obvious effects and
ramifications in the sound medium.
18
For Deleuze, the “chaosmos” in which the artist works in some sense is the work itself.
Deleuze here depends on his novel and controversial interpretation of Nietzsche’s doctrine of the
eternal recurrence of the same. Nietzsche insisted, that “eternal return” and chaos are the same
affirmation. For Deleuze, modern art attempts to “make” the affirmation of the eternal return.
This is an affirmation which, according to Deleuze’s reading of Nietzsche, causes only “positive”
differences—the true if hidden powers of life—to return (see Deleuze’s Nietzsche and Philosophy
for elaboration of this point). As Deleuze is careful to note, Nietzsche never clearly explains
what eternal return amounts to. Yet there are indications in Nietzsche’s texts (especially in Thus
Spoke Zarathustra) that “attaining to” the insight of the truth of eternal return, “living up to” the
truth of the doctrine, has to do with the activity of a creative will, or a principle of selection, that
is neither natural nor cultural, but can only be ascribed to an “overhuman” sensibility that, like the
Greek god Dionysius identifies itself fully (without pity or resentment) with chaotic processes of
creation and destruction.
223
Although this Dionysian sensibility, with its appetite for destruction and aggression, is
part of the “revenge” of simulacra and the attempt of modern art to liberate itself from
representation, I downplay throughout this thesis the connection of Dionysianism with eternal
return. This is because, in my view, Deleuze’s claims about the knowledge art makes possible
become harder and harder to defend the more they are linked to a doctrine of immanence and
univocity that is expounded as if immanence and univocity were “cosmic givens”—as if art, as
much as science or philosophy, tapped into a resource of sense that was pre-given or in principle
available, as if thought could be divorced from what forces us to think. What I emphasize,
instead, is that Deleuze always coordinates the donating of sense (the presence of the virtual, or
ideas, or ideal dynamics that, themselves a part of history and becoming, are nevertheless not
reducible to sensible qualities or measured quantities) with the achievement of a creative
endeavor. This makes Deleuze’s project primarily epistemological and ethical rather than
metaphysical—a theory of relations rather than of natures. Reading Deleuze this way helps
Deleuze avoid the charge of panentheistic vitalist mysticism with which he is often saddled.
Although, following Whitehead and Bergson, Deleuze has an intuition about how apparently
mechanistic evolutionary and bio-social processes are inherently creative, this intuition, I will
argue throughout, emerges where and when Deleuze sees dynamics at work in the world as
artfully rendered. This is the point I try to make clear in Chapter VI, “Being Assembled:
Creating the Planes of Immanence.”
19
Although of course, for Vico, the truth of any making is ultimately tied to a transcendent
paradigm of beneficent divine creation. See The New Science. (Marsh, trans. New York:
Penguin, 2001).
20
For Deleuze, Nietzsche’s Zarathustra is a comic opera about terrible things, and the
übermensch is a comic actor, a kind of buffoon (DR 9). And in an important passage of
Difference and Repetition, Deleuze takes issue with Marx’s notion, from the Eighteenth
Brumaire, that in history comic farce follows tragic metamorphosis. For Deleuze there is a comic
repetition, “once for all” that lurks beneath the apparent “education” (Bildung) which tragedy
seems to represent. As he puts it,
Comic repetition works by means of some defect, in the mode of the past properly so
called. The hero necessarily confronts this repetition so long as “the act is too big for
him:” Polonius’ murder by mistake is comic, as is Oedipus’ enquiry. The moment of
metamorphosis, tragic repetition, follows. It is true that these two moments are not
independent, existing as they do only for the third moment beyond the comic and the
tragic: the production of something new entails a dramatic repetition which excludes
even the hero. However, once the first two elements acquire an abstract independence or
become genres, then the comic succeeds the tragic as though the failure of
metamorphosis, raised to the absolute, presupposed an earlier metamorphosis already
completed. (DR 92)
21
For the issue of health and sickness in relationship to knowledge in Nietzsche, see Klossowski,
Pierre. Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle. (Trans. Dan Smith. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1997). Deleuze’s reading of Nietzsche owes much to the work of Klossowski, who, a
painter and novelist, emphasized the necessity of a willed or attained insight of the truth of the
eternal return—an insight that depends on the strength of a new and uncanny kind of health.
224
22
For Deleuze’s reading of Leibniz as a baroque “mannerist,” see his The Fold: Leibniz and the
Baroque. Trans. Tom Conley. Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1993.
23
Hence there is always something “catastrophic” about creation in Deleuze, as James Williams
makes clear in “Deleuze on J.M.W. Turner: Catastrophism in Philosophy?” (Deleuze and
Philosophy: The Difference Engineer. Keith Ansell Pearson (ed.), London: Rutledge, 1997, pp.
233-46). Williams notes that in Deleuze’s work the affirmation of catastrophe is linked to a
critical function, as it is in Spinoza. Affirming catastrophe reverses the idea of a judgment of god
or the gods: catastrophic events must be affirmed and embraced in order that we do not fall into
the illusion that they are punishments meted out by divine anger (see Spinoza, Baruch. Ethics.
Ed. E. Curley, Princeton: Princeton University Press, p. 111). Catastrophe, for Deleuze, is the
occasion of re-creation beyond social stratification and psychological fixation. The “ethics” of
catastrophe, for Deleuze, consist in constantly testing and contesting the limits of our individual
and collective ability to be flexible, to be in a dynamic transformation in response to catastrophes
large and small, rather than in a stupid [betise] insistence upon identity and representable
difference from that identity.
24
In A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze shows how musical refrains perform a special
“territorializing” function between chaos and pre-established (oppressive or stultifying) order.
See “1837: Of the Refrain.” A Thousand Plateaus. Trans. Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: Univ.
of Minnesota Press, 1987), pp.310-350.
25
Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation. Trans. Dan Smith. (Minneapolis: Univ. of
Minnesota Press, 2003), pp. 81-90.
26
A concept from A Thousand Plateaus.
27
For Joyce’s use of Bruno, see Gose Jr., Elliot B. The Transformation Process in Joyce’s
Ulysses. (Toronto: Univ. of Toronto Press, 1980). See also Boldereef, Frances M. Hermes to
his Son Thoth: being Joyce’s Use of Giordano Bruno in Finnegan’s Wake. (Woodward: Classic
Non-Fiction Library, 1968).
28
Manuel Delanda makes this point very clear in the glossary to his Intensive Science and Virtual
Philosophy (London: Continuum, 2002).
29
Rene Girard accused Deleuze and his collaborator Felix Guattari of making delirium into a
systematic approach to thought in his “Delirium as System.” “To Double Business Bound” :
Essays on Literature, Mimesis and Anthropology. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1978), pp. 84-
120. In this scathing critique, Girard misses much of the subtlety of the aesthetic paradigm, but
his criticisms of Deleuzian ethics is important and will be addressed in Chapter V, "Writing
Power.”
30
John Rajchman, The Deleuze Connections (Cambridge: MIT, 2000), p. 127.
31
This is precisely why Deleuze’s philosophy cannot consist in merely the ruin of representation.
32
See also Alain Badiou’s “Kant’s Subtractive Ontology” in Alain Badiou: Theoretical Writings.
Ed.. and trans. Ray Brassier and Alberto Toscano. London: Continuum, 2004.
225
33
Ian Buchanan clarifies this point in “Deleuze and Cultural Studies” in South
Atlantic Quarterly 96(3) (1997), 483-97.
34
For a fine exposition of this point see Ian Buchanan’s “Deleuze and Cultural Studies.”
35
Deleuze’s is a rather Peircian view of mind. See Peirce’s “How to Make our Ideas Clear” in
Philosophical Writings of Peirce. Ed. Justus Buchler. New York: Dover, 1955, pp. 23-41.
36
Deleuze, Empiricism and Subjectivity, 107-108.
37
John Rajchman, The Deleuze Connections (Cambridge: MIT, 2000), p.131
38
Plato, Republic 510.
40
See Foucault’s famous reflection on the structure of visibility in Velazquez’ painting Las
Meninhas that opens Foucault’s history of systems of representation, The Order of Things (New
York: Random House, 1970), pp. 3-16.
41
John Rajchman points out that although phenomenology also attempted to free art from pre-
given representational forms, it still does so in the name of judgment and not in the name of
experimentation. He writes,
The relation between Deleuze and phenomenology has many aspects, and is beyond the scope of
my argument. However, it is as decisive for me as it is for Rajchman that, because
phenomenology as traditionally conceived (and as Deleuze by and large knew it through Husserl
and Merleau-Ponty) remains a quest for an appropriate basis for judgment rather than an adequate
platform for experimentation, it is not yet an exercise in the creation of concepts. There are
exceptions to this, especially the work of Alphonso Lingus. See for example his “Phantom
Equator.” Eds. Busch and Gallagher. Merleau-Ponty, Hermeneutics, and Postmodernism.
Albany: SUNY Press, 1992, pp. 227-239. If Lingus’ philosophical goal is ultimately a reflection
on experiences had elsewhere, his reflections are nevertheless always geared toward a further
experiment of sensation, of life.
42
See Alain Badiou’s beautiful essay, “Language, Thought, Poetry,” on this point. In Trans.
Brassier and Toscano. Badiou: Theoretical Writings (London: Continuum, 2004), pp. 233-241.
43
In “Language, Thought, Poetry” Badiou (a sometime student of Deleuze’s) writes, “What is
philosophically opposed to the poem is not philosophy itself directly, but dianoia, the discursive
thinking that connects and argues, a thinking whose paradigm is mathematical . . . what
disconcerts philosophy, is not illusion and imitation [Plato’s—apparent—objections to poetry as
“untruths”]. Rather, it’s the fact that the poem might indeed be a thought without knowledge, or
226
even this—a properly incalculable thought” (240). For Badiou as for Plato, poetry represents a
temptation that philosophy must resist in the name of allegiance to a mathematical paradigm.
Deleuze, as much as Heidegger or Derrida, has “fallen prey” to the temptation to model
philosophy on poetic forms of reasoning—the thoughts of a transcendental empiricism are forced
or “incalculable thoughts” that cannot be explained apart from intense experimentation. In my
concluding chapters here I will try to justify Deleuze’s blending of poetry and philosophy against
Badiou’s objections.
44
I take this point to refer to the work of Jurgen Habermas and to all versions of faith—liberal,
communitarian, transcendentalist—in a “communicative” rationality. The only communication
that interests Deleuze, at least from a truly ethical (and at once truly “aesthetic”) perspective, is
strictly speaking unconscious. For Deleuze (as for Spinoza and Nietzsche), we may debate and
pass laws about what we will tolerate from one another as conscious intention, but the true law
that is operative in social formations (in inventions, or in what Foucault called regimes of
seeability and sayability) is the law governing unconscious ideas and the forces of which they are
the archetypes. Deleuze’s ethics is, as we will see, essentially a Spinozist ethics-as-physics, with
the added twist that Spinozist naturalism is supplemented by a strange or paradoxical “realism”
or reversed “platonism” about certain features of experience. Deleuze takes as fully real certain
features of life (signs, images, diagrams, etc.) that Spinoza would have subordinated to a
temporary, imaginative detour within reason. For Deleuze these fixations carry an ontological
weight they do not in Spinoza. As Julie Klein and others have shown this is a complex issue in
Spinoza, and the imagination may have more weight in his thought than has been traditionally
realized by Spinoza’s critics. See Spinoza’s Theologico-Political Treatise. S. Shirley, Trans.
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1998) p. 12 ff for his critique of imaginary formations, here in the context
of Biblical interpretation.
45
“Oppose repetition to the generalities of habit but also to the particularities of memory” (DR
7). What repeats is not a “past present,” but a present that is also a present past. The only
dimension of the past that repeats is its virtual dimension, which is the presence, for instance, of a
past taste of the madeleine, the taste that it was, immediately with or adjacent to the same present
taste (that it is). See Deleuze, Cinema 2: The Time-Image, for the idea of a multi-dimensional
time appearing in cinema as “sheets of past, points of present” (C2 98-102).
46
Antonin Artaud, The Theatre and its Double. Trans. Richards. (New York: Grove Press,
1958), p. 13.
47
Contemplation, for Deleuze, is what happens once we have already created a concept.
Communication, as well, is something that comes after the fact, and only serves, along with
reflection and contemplation, as a machine for producing Universals through which philosophy
dreams of dominating other disciplines, other ways of knowing. A description of “what goes on
out there” is not philosophy, for Deleuze.
48
This is why Deleuze was often asked whether he was a Platonist. As we will see in the next
two chapters, Deleuze is a Platonist in the sense that he thinks that differences are real, positive
multiplicities irreducible to sense experience or “actuality.” But Deleuze is not a Platonist
because the extraordinary or dramatic ideas that befall us or happen to us like a great crime or a
great love are not ahistorical entities. Ideas must be traversed or incarnated or evoked, to exist.
They must be counted, “in history,” one by one or two by two. That is why Deleuze seeks to
analyze the real conditions of what forces us to think, and to learn, and to keep learning, in a
227
process that is in principle and in fact endless. What is it that forces us to think? It is a
Difference, something different every time (it repeats), a non-identical repetition, a dynamism
inhabiting and
constituting a world.
49
Nicholas of Cusa’s “idiot,” Dostoyevsky’s idiot, the character of Job in the Bible, and Plato’s
Socrates are all examples of conceptual personae. Conceptual personae are constituted by the
implicit presuppositions or affective traits upon which those concepts depend. When it comes to
the history of philosophy, for Deleuze, the question is not, What are the objective presuppositions
of such-and-such a concept (Platonic forms, Aristotelian substances, the Cartesian cogito, the
Leibnizian monad, the Nietzschean will-to-power), but rather, What are the real conditions of the
appearance of this kind of character, this character who creates a concept in response to those real
conditions in which she lives? (WIP 69). This approach puts the emphasis on the
“extraordinary” or even hyperbolic aspects of a philosophical system, the singularities and
intensities which a philosopher’s concepts include and upon which her propositions and
“statements” (in the Foucaultian sense) depend for their sense (rather than their truth). Again, it
is imperative to see that this is not a relativistic or subjetivistic move on Deleuze’s part. If
Deleuze makes concepts into “nominal” entities, this is in the name of a deeper, pre-propositional
realism of force, affect, and event. What is “objective” in Deleuze is not knowledge per se but
the project in whose service that knowledge stands (which is why Deleuze owes so much to
empiricism). As we will see later, this affects Deleuze’s semiotic theory, which as Bogue and
others have pointed out does not analyze signs in terms of their placement in codes or chains, but
in terms of their expression of a socially and historically constitutive force that determines, all at
once, both a form and matter of content and a form and matter of expression. For a concise
explanation of Deleuze’s semiotics see Ronald Bogue’s “Word, Image and Sound: The Non-
Representational Semiotics of Gilles Deleuze. Mimesis in Contemporary Theory: An
Interdisciplinary Approach, Volume 2: Mimesis, Semiosis, and Power, Ronald Bogue (ed.),
(Philadelphia: John Benjamins, 1991), pp.77-97.
50
This is the critique of Rene Girard, as well as of Alain Badiou and Slavoj Zizek. For Zizek, see
his Organs Without Bodies: On Deleuze and Consequences (London: Rutledge, 2004).
Badiou’s critique is in his monograph on Deleuze, Deleuze: “La Clameur de l’Etre. Paris:
Hachette, 1997, and in “One, Multiple, Multiplicities” (Trans. Brassier and Toscano. Badiou:
Theoretical Writings. London: Continuum, 2004), pp.67-80.
51
I owe this point to Rocco Gangle (in conversation, December 2005).
52
This formulation is deliberately casual and suggestive, aiming at a general tone or tenor of
much “mainstream” or “academic” philosophical work going on in Deleuze’s time and in the
present, especially as that work conforms to what Deleuze will call the “Image of Thought.” As I
will explain in the next chapter, under this image of thought concepts should ultimately conform
to a good and common sense, to a recognizability that for Deleuze is precisely the enemy of
genuine thought.
53
Hegel in particular is in view here, as well as Schelling, but also to some extent Husserlian
phenomenology, with its idea of “infinite tasks,” is viewed by Deleuze as generating concepts
which are, ultimately, reflective and not truly generative of ideas, and part of the entire post-
Kantian attempt to substitute a unified (if transcendental) I for the absence of an objective world.
228
54
“Proust, for example, has the idea that every thought is an aggression, appearing under the
constraint of a sign, and that we think only when we are forced and constrained to think.” (“On
Nietzsche and the Image of Thought,” in Ed. Lapoujade, trans. Taormina. Desert Islands and
Other Texts: 1953-1974. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2004, p. 139).
55
In the non-traditional sense Deleuze gives the term. As Bruce Baugh emphasizes, Deleuze’s
empiricism is not a doctrine of the essence of mind or nature or reality, nor is it the idea that the
“source” of knowledge is the sensible. On the contrary, the sensible for Deleuze is not knowable
but thinkable. This thought occurs in and as the intuition of the sensible. As Baugh puts it,
“Deleuze’s intuition is not governed by concepts, and yet is still rational insofar as it tries to grasp
empirical actuality through determinate causal processes which constitute actualities as the
singular results of singular encounters between forces, and so as determinate singularities”
(Baugh, Bruce. “Deleuze and Empiricism.” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology
24(1) (1993): p. 31).
56
Deleuze variously calls these forces ideal dramas, sense-events, folds and “machinic
assemblages.”
57
Deleuze writes,
If the concept is a solution, the condition of the philosophical problem are found
on the plane of immanence presupposed by the concept (to what infinite
movement does it refer in the image of thought?), and the unknowns of the
problem are found in the conceptual personae that it calls up (what persona,
exactly?). A concept like knowledge has meaning only in relation to an image of
thought to which it refers and to a conceptual persona that it needs; a different
image and a different persona call for other concepts (belief, for example, and the
Investigator). (WIP 81)
58
Deleuze puts art, science, and philosophy on an equal plane. And art as much as science and
philosophy has often fallen prey to the strictures of what he will call the “image of thought.” For
my purposes, art is a clearer paradigm, even though Deleuze is as inspired by differential
calculus, molecular biology, plate tectonics, and certain concepts from physics (strange attractors,
phase space, etc.) as he is by art. But as I read it, the first and final term of endearment to
Deleuze is an aesthetic one, and he is taken by science where it seems to resonate with what he
sees in certain forms of “modern” (and baroque) artistic practice.
59
See What Is Philosophy, pp. 205-206. For Deleuze, science only fails to create concepts when
it submits is program to “opinion,” which manifests in science as the drive to reduce chaos to “the
elementary” from which “composites” are formed. What science truly seeks are phase states or
successions of filters or “attractors” which are not “initial conditions” but which determine which
initial conditions will be (probabilistically) selected. Manuel Delanda has explained this point in
Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy.
60
Be that as it may, Deleuze’s conception of the superiority of problems to solutions, of
singularities to the trajectories they determine, and his interpretation of forces points to a different
conception of science, one that breaks with the dogmatic image of thought, as Manuel Delanda
has elegantly shown in Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy.
229
61
See A Thousand Plateaus for a description of the miner/metallurgist as an ambulant or itinerant
model of a thinker “at the borders” (of sedentary and nomadic identities).
62
According to Deleuze, immanence carries concepts “back to the sea” (WIP 208).
63
In a chapter which his preface to the English edition (1994) singles out as being “the most
necessary and the most concrete, and which serves to introduce subsequent books up to and
including the research undertaken with Guattari” (DR xvii),
64
There is currently a debate in the literature about whether Deleuze and Hegel’s positions are as
different as Deleuze makes them out to be.
65
There are multiple refs to Castaneda in A Thousand Plateaus, and Deleuze explicitly invokes
the figure of the sorcerer as a model for thought not only in that text but also in his invocation, in
The Logic of Sense, of a figure that would combine the traits of a Zen master with that of stoic
humor and the playfulness of Carroll’s Alice.
66
In “The Method of Dramatization” (DI 105), Noël Mouloud says that he considers
mathematical concepts to be shattering to intuition, but this is not what Deleuze means by being
forced to think. Simply moving beyond empirical intuition toward mathematical truth is not
enough, because there is still a coherent order (even if we cannot “image” it without computer
modeling) that revolves around a self-identical object (represented by the fixed variables of an
equation). For Deleuze we are forced to think because things are not identical with themselves
but are simulacra, becomings, virtual-actual complexes, multiplicities that remain stranger than
the strangest mathematics—they are those “strange attractors” which determine which initial
conditions will tend to be selected in a given field.
67
Deleuze would deny that there could be anything “natural” about natural law, at least in the
sense that the moral law might be grounded in anything consistent in “life” other than misleading
generalities. Deleuze is definitely on the side of Kierkegaard’s idea that the right or good is
something ultimately uncanny and unrecognizable.
68
Or a divine power, for Kierkegaard. Deleuze wonders whether Kierkegaard’s dismissal of the
“aesthetic” actually dismisses the great repetition of a work of art. Deleuze is also suspicious of
Kierkegaard’s placement of authentic repetition in an “alliance between God and a self
rediscovered,” (DR 11), which is a spiritual movement. Slavoj Zizek has pointed out, however,
that when one passes from the ethical to the religious, in Kierkegaard, this movement takes the
form of an “aesthetic” choice. Perhaps this would be the way in which, for Kierkegaard, the
rediscovered self is itself a great work of art (and not a recollected soul).
69
See Nathan Widder’s excellent explanation in “The rights of simulacra: Deleuze and the
univocity of being” in Continental Philosophy Review (Kluwer, 2001) 34: 437-453.
70
Although, Deleuze admits, it may ultimately be possible to reconcile the univocity he wishes to
attribute to being with a certain refined notion of analogy (see DR 38).
71
Leibniz came close to conceiving of a series of differences such as Deleuze conceives it, but
falls short by making the monads harmonize (even if the harmony is known only by God) (DR
47). Hegel seems to be thinking through difference in his dialectic of Spirit which is constituted
230
by a series of contradictions, but for Deleuze the differences which result in contradiction are
epiphenomena: conflict is an effect of deeper, positive forces which persist in their difference
prior to any negativity (DR 46). Both Leibnizian and Hegelian “infinite representations” of the
world remain beholden to an orienting point (the world or the self). It was Nietzsche, for Deleuze,
who most fully conceived of an ungrounded world of differences that, as the subject of a certain
kind of affirmation, persists beneath our conscious “conflicts.” Deleuze interprets Nietzsche’s
notion of a “will to power” as a cosmic force that, as affirmation, selects from the eternal
recurrence of the Same those forces which are truly differential, which truly make
difference—which are truly alive. And even more than Nietzsche it is the art of Mallarme, Joyce,
Proust, Carroll, Goddard, Resnais, and Klee that truly is able to make being univocal, make things
resound with one another without subordinating them to a synthetic or pregiven identity.
72
Proust et les Signes first appeared in French in 1964.
73
The contrast here is with Hegelianism. If the Phenomenology is a reflection “on” the world’s
forces (history as the ruse of reason), it is not yet, for Deleuze, a repetition of the world, or of the
infinitesimally small, sub-representational ideas that are truly at work in the world. If what truly
moves Spirit are secret, subterranean pressures that cannot be represented, but only repeated, then
Hegel’s “mediation,” which occurs only through “large” contradictions (instead of small
differences), is not truly that which “forces” thought. The Phenomenology remains an after-
thought. For the forces of difference to come to mind, Deleuze argues, we had to await
Kierkegaard and Nietzsche. They were the ones who introduced a truly radical theatre of ideas
into philosophy. “They do not reflect on theatre in the Hegelian manner,” Deleuze writes, in
Difference and Repetition, “neither do they set up a philosophical theatre. They invent an
incredible equivalent of the theatre in philosophy” (DR 8).
In what does this theatre consist? More even than being a theatre “without
representation,” (although it is certainly that) it is a theatre of immediate encounters between
mind and the movements of material forces. Like the theatre of Antonin Artaud, which was
meant to assault the sensibilities of his audience. Deleuze believed the Kierkegaardian-
Nietzschean theatre should be a model for how to create a theatre not so much of but in
philosophical texts. He writes,
. . . it is a question of producing within the work a movement capable of
affecting the mind outside of all representation; it is a substituting direct signs for
mediate representations; of inventing vibrations, rotations, whirlings,
gravitations, dances, or leaps which directly touch the mind. (DR 8)
The theatres Nietzsche and Kierkegaard introduce, through their disguises, pseudonyms, animals,
masks, and dances, a response to and a recreation of powerful signs of life, signs that force
thought and that cannot be thought apart from repetition: disguise, displacement, diversion,
divertissement. For Deleuze this is how we contact (if not communicate with) forces that go
directly from physis to psyche, without mediation in concepts (DR 8).
74
The French word for experience, experiment, also contains the sense of the English
“experiment.”
75
Where Deleuze departs from Spinoza is that for Deleuze, the order of ideas and the order of
things really interact (which entails that thought and extension are really distinct). For Deleuze,
the order and connection of both body and mind can be attributed to a “quasi-causal operator”
that transverses thought and extension in reverse, “counter-actualizing” all events or forcing them
231
to resonate in ways which would at first appear, on a Spinozistic view, to be the errors of the
imagination (nonsense). For Deleuze, however, this uncanny source of distributions of sense and
nonsense is ultimately the prerogative of a creativity or an artfulness that is the true co-generator
of thought and being. For Deleuze the paradox is that this “free” counter-actualization is
ontologically prior to both the actual and virtual regimes of sense and nonsense (which are both,
in their own ways, historically or efficiently determined). Perhaps this is the insight to which
Spinoza’s famous third order of knowledge attains, where events are finally seen “sub specie
aeternitatis.”
76
Is this a subjective or an objective affair (to put it in somewhat dated language)? Both. It is as
if those who are sensitive to the signs of a given world or territory or patrie come into existence
with that world itself—it is as if the reality of a world were something paradoxically producing
both an objectivity and subjectivity proper to it. The model here is the Leibnizian monad, but
without any prearranged harmony between monads guaranteed by God—only a resonance which
yields “epiphanies” of forces beyond our ken. The “harmony” of perspectives is something
external to every conceivable “whole,” be it History, Man, God or Geist. It arises from a
paradoxical element or “dark precursor” that belongs to no one series but insists at and as the
resonance of any two discontinuous lines, or worlds, constantly displaced with relation to itself
and constantly disguised in the series to which it gives rise.
77
Although Slavoj Zizek, perhaps, might disagree, insofar as the sublimity of the Kantian Ding
an sich can be said to correspond to the “real” of psychoanalytic experience.
78
This is why Platonic ideas rather than Aristotelian generic concepts excite Deleuze, even if
Aristotle’s notions seem to originate in the material world in a way closer to Deleuze’s idea that
the virtual emerges from the actual. For Plato’s ideas, at least as Plato begins to admit in his later
works, only encompass or unify to the extent that they violently carve up or divide experience.
Platonic ideas are therefore of more use to artists than Aristotelian genera, again despite the fact
that Aristotle’s Poetics attributes a much more sophisticated type of knowledge to the poet than
does Plato’s Ion or Republic. It is because Plato is in competition with artists that he interests
Deleuze, as he haunted Nietzsche, because Plato is trying to outdo them, whereas Aristotle is
merely reflecting on the “nature” of art understood from the point of view of his concepts
(discerning what is potential and actual, discerning how potentials are actualized in art). See
ATP, where the plane of consistency has a “platonic” status in relation to that of the plane of
organization or development. In the end, for Deleuze, Aristotelian ideas of evolution, genesis,
and so on, are all subscript to the order of representation. Platonic forms ineffably or magically
appear in materials that have been specially prepared to receive them, as the theurgist Neo-
Platonists realized. Plato is not really dualist but triplist—there must be a screen prepared for
matter to receive its form.
79
Deleuze’s image of Socrates is controversial relative to more recent scholarship by Vlastos,
Nehamas, Brogan and others.
80
In “The Image of Thought” chapter of Proust and Signs.
81
Again, Deleuze’s view of Socrates is a product of the scholarship of his time. Vlastos,
Nehemas, Foucault and others have shown that Socrates’ irony may be more complex than
Deleuze realizes: Socrates may know in advance that the views of others are incorrect, but he
232
may not yet know if his own views are sound, healthy, etc., and may be truly “encountering”
himself, if not others.
82
Deleuze uses the Neo-Platonist notion of explicatio here to both stay with the Platonist register
but also to further illuminate how the “eternity” in which essences reside is not a static extension
of limitless existence but “the complicated state of time itself.” The Word was the supreme
example of this unity of contradictories, this unstable opposition in essences (which Deleuze says
is the Heraclitean animal still untamed at the heart of Plato’s thought, the source of the
simulacral). Deleuze’s own notion of expression owes much to the complicatio-explicatio
pairing. Deleuze’s affinity with Bruno is in part an affinity with the idea of an infinite world or
worlds that are held together in a coexistence of contraries that are not dialectically related to one
another. Hence the absence of a “logos” for the all—it can only come to us hieroglyphically, in
signs, because that is its nature. This is where Deleuze moves beyond that German Idealism
which still tries to make a logos (Schelling) even of the aporetic mythos.
83
Heidegger had a way of criticizing the history of metaphysics that is similar to the approach
used by Deleuze. For Heidegger the prejudices of modern scientism and those of platonism are at
one . . . For Deleuze also, because of the energy Plato exerts to eliminate not difference but
certain kinds of difference or a certain image of difference from the field of thought. The sophist
is auto-disqualified by being a dissembler, by willfully attempting to be what s/he is not. So also
the false statesman. What the philosopher sees or knows is not so much the brilliance of the Ideas
per se but the differential lineage or heritage that can properly manifest itself—he knows which
copies of the idea are idols and which are icons. The dialectic can only bring us to the point at
which Socrates and the sophist appear identical in all respects except the one the philosopher can
recognize.
84
This is why Deleuze’s platonism is allied to that of the Iamblichan, Ficinian, and ultimately
Nolan forms of theurgic magic. In this neoplatonic tradition, ideas are understood magically or
alchemically as being seeds and sources of possible material transformations. For Iamblichus,
and for Ficino and Bruno, the destiny of the material world is not so much to be purified or
distilled by the work of the ideas as it is the work of the ideas to incarnate themselves in the
depths of material configurations. Philosophy is only initially dialectical purification, it is only
initially an attempt to eliminate confusion or illusion. Transcendental philosophy stops at this
level, or pushes this level of mental activity into the deepest recesses of being. Deleuze’s move
past transcendental philosophy is to bracket its “transcendentality” as being superficial (we might
say, overly “cognitive”).
85
Cf. Umberto Eco’s skepticism about what Joyce has to “give” us, claiming that Joyce’s
relationship to his own “chaosmos” is tinged with the irony of one who is fascinated by a form
but unattached to its content: “materials whose form captivates him but whose content does not
solicit his belief” (The Aesthetics of Chaosmos: The Middle Ages of James Joyce. Trans.
Ellen Esrock. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989. p. 84).
86
See Dan Smith’s article in Between Deleuze and Derrida (Patton and Protevi, 2003), pp. 62-63.
87
in the Derridean sense that nothing can ever fully be just, beautiful, a gift, etc. (see Derrida’s
Given Time I).
233
88
Deleuze does not speak to that intuition many people have that something is tragically missing
from the world, something (i.e., God) that would if present change everything, make everything
better, everything whole. This is part of why Deleuze has been so slowly received by continental
philosophy in America which has traditionally been the bastion of those philosophers who require
the idea of a tragic absence to begin thinking, at all.
90
Klossowski’s list of attributes of the simulacral include, according to Foucault, “a vain image
(as opposed to the reality), a representation of something (in which this thing designates and
manifests itself, but withdraws and in a sense conceals itself), a falsehood that causes one to take
one sign for another, a sign of the presence of a deity (and the converse possibility of taking this
sign for its opposite, the simultaneous coming of the Same and the Other (originally, to simulate
meant to come together)” (“Prose of Acteon” in Faubian, 127).
91
This is where it becomes possible to see where Deleuze departs from Spinoza. For Deleuze the
attributes of substance are real, if fictive. They are “quasi-causes.”
92
Even if this creativity is a perverse play or masochistic ritual. See Deleuze’s Masochism:
Coldness and Cruelty. Trans. Jean McNeil. New York: Zone Books, 1989.
93
Deleuze and Guattari wonder if it is terrorizing for the schizo only because the schizo is already
institutionalized, already judged (AO 88). What if the flow were not interrupted? What if we
only go too far on the body without organs because we get scared by the specter of mommy and
daddy?
94
Derrida’s is obviously a very different way of overturning Platonism, involving the tracing of
simulacral “invasions” of the idea, or the “haunting” of language by “the thing itself” (what
Deleuze calls partial objects or objects=x). As Derrida puts it,
This state of being haunted, which keeps the city from returning to nature, is
perhaps the general mode of the presence or absence of the thing itself in pure
language. The pure language that would be housed in pure literature, the object
of pure literary criticism. Thus it is in no way paradoxical that the structuralist
consciousness is catastrophic consciousness, simultaneously destroyed and
destructive, destructuring, as is all consciousness, or at least the moment of
decadence, which is the period proper to all movement of consciousness. (“FS”
in WD 6)
“Structuralism” names for Derrida the moment at which we realized we have lost what it is a pure
language, a pure literary language, would offer us if we did not imagine that there was something
outside of that language. In other words, structuralism (the reduction of the imaginary to the
symbolic) is the “archive fever” of a dispossessed romanticism. It is protest or critique par
excellence. Its “synchronicity” is the ressentiment of those who have no more events, no more
genetic powers at their disposal. But structuralism only manifests or brings to clarification (if not
finality) the tragedy of western reason, besotted by the loss of the thing in language, the loss
whose written symptom is supplemented by the quest for immediacy in the voice. Deleuze and
Guattari interrupt the Derridean meditation on this tragic scene. They do this in a gesture that
Derrida might have suspected to be a new romanticism: they insist on a primitive sign that is not
significative, that is not subject to the laws of signifiance (the “signifyingness” that the despotic
or “transcendental signifier” gives to all the signs.)
234
95
Cf. ATP 237 on the sorcerer and becomings as super-mythic, irreducible tales not reducible to
mythical formulas and borderings.
96
In A Thousand Plateau’s “1933: Micropolitics and Segmentarity,” Deleuze and Guattari argue
that despite the fact that binary oppositions are very strong in primitive societies, these binaries
are produced from multiple centers of power and not from a single despotic center whose effects
are everywhere the same. Only in modern societies, they argue, are such dualisms as
man/woman, ruler/ruled elevated to the level of a self-sufficient organization (ATP 210).
97
Cf. Bergson on magical language, here. Two Sources of Morality and Religion.
98
See John Milbank’s essay in “On Complex Space” in The Word Made Strange (London:
Blackwell, 1997).
99
If in certain practices forces are already significant, and being is already writing, then why do
we have to chose, as Derrida insists we must, between writing and dance (between force and
signification)? According to Derrida, even Nietzsche despairs of being able to write as a dancer:
Nietzsche recommends a dance of the pen in vain: ’ . . .need I add that one must also be
able to dance with the pen—that one must learn how to write?’ . . . but Nietzsche was
certain that the writer would never be upright; that writing is first and foremost something
over which one bends. Better still when letters are no longer figures of fire in the
heavens” (WD 29).
But there is an alternative Derrida does not see. This is the sorcerer, who draws figures of fire not
in the heavens but on the earth. On what Deleuze calls the plane of immanence.
To his credit, in a passage of writing that is extremely Deleuzian, Derrida sees that even
his own notion of history as the history of metaphysics (the unstable attempt to prioritize being
over writing in writing) leaves open the option of either a nostalgic “Rousseauistic” desire for a
state of nature before writing or a joyous, “Nietzschean” affirmative stance toward the play of
chance. If the emergence of structuralism in the human sciences was caused by a loss of
meaning, by a crisis in meaning, then Derrida is with Deleuze in agreeing that this loss is not
something that happened recently, but is something (something like Foucault’s death of Man) that
we are finally waking up to.
However, what forces the necessity of interpretation, or of these two interpretations of
interpretation—what Derrida calls difference—while yet to be fully understood is still viewed as
a meta-historical force that encloses us within a history that disables the possibility of choosing
between nostalgia and affirmation. This is Derrida at his most honest: he cannot write from
without writing, and writing is always subject to the slippage between writing and being, the
slippage which prevents writing from being dancing, which prevents signification from being
force, which prevents signs from being what they say.
100
See Felix Guattari, The Anti-Oedipus Papers (Trans. Kalina Gottman. New York:
Semiotext(e), 2006), pp. 201-279.
101
Rene Grirard, “Delirium as System,” in To Double Business Bound: Essays on Literature,
Mimesis, and Anthropology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1978), pp.84-119.
235
102
As if like new-ager's in 1980’s Hollywood we thought we could do a little yoga and usher in
world peace. Girard perhaps inaugurated this misread.
103
“The BwO is not “before” the organism; it is adjacent to it and is continually in the process of
constructing itself. It is tied to childhood, not in the sense that the adult regresses to the child and
the child to the Mother, but in the sense that the child, like the Dogon twin who takes a piece of
the placenta with him, tears from the organic form of the Mother an intense and destratified
matter that on the contrary constitutes his perpetual break with the past, his or her present
experience, experimentation . . . it is the strict contemporaneousness of the adult and the child,
their map of comparative densities and intensities, and all of the variations on that map”
(ATP164). Deleuze and Guattari only seem to narrate this in “earth goddess cult” terms, as if our
True Origin were in the body of a Mother Earth whose things (original, positive, non-parsed
fetishism of desire) we are organically and symbiotically in communion with. Zizek and Badiou
both mistake Deleuze for thinking in this way about the One. But Deleuze insists that things
begin in the middle so it is never a matter of moving backwards to the origin but of inventing
right now.
104
See especially ATP 163-164 for the difficulties of the” three-body problem”—making yourself
susceptible of sorcery, making yourself a body without organs, using your egg, is extremely
difficult process of trial and error. “How can we fabricate a BwO for ourselves without its being
the cancerous BwO of a fascist inside us, or the empty BwO of a drug addict, paranoiac, or
hypochondriac? How can we tell the three bodies apart? . . . Even if Artaud did not succeed for
himself, it is certain that through him something has succeeded for us all” (ATP 161-64).
105
Part of the current retreat to Kantianism in some “continentalist” circles (which is possibly the
most reactionary force modernity has ever seen) is an attempt to restore a non-materialist criteria
by which one of the doubles could be eliminated as an illusion or an hallucination, or even as
“radically evil.” Not only is this tendency gnostic, it is practically impossible under the present
circumstances. George Bush is as artful as ever Warhol was. Prior to the effects of their
enterprises, there is no criteria to distinguish between the fascist and the magic flute. Welcome to
pragmatism, welcome to the experiment, welcome to the desert of the real.
106
John Milbank has been right to notice that all philosophies of immanence (from Plato to
Spinoza to Heidegger to Deleuze) culminate in dualisms of this kind. In my view, whether this is
a drawback of these philosophies depends upon whether the specific dualities produced in any
case has the potential to facilitate acts of healing and experiments of creation.
107
Cf. Deleuze’s work on Nietzsche’s eternal return and its selective power, here.
108
In James Wetzel’s understanding of the term as he articulates it in “Splendid Vices” in the
Journal of Religious Ethics. (London: Blackwell. 32:2), pp. 271-300.
109
Probably without some theory of providence by which freedom and determinism is mitigated
in a mythico-theological drama, it is simply not an answerable question, and is probably a poorly
posed problem, already “viewing” or “reflecting upon” reality from an unreal and arbitrary
standpoint. One of the most sophisticated versions of such an ideal drama is put forth by the
Radical Orthodoxy school of theology. Their metanarrative depends on the thesis that thought
(meaning, sense, teleology) is unintelligible apart from liturgical formations and praxis. Without
236
this claim theology, too, falls into a Kantian transcendentalism that leaves a rupture between form
and content, finite and infinite, concept and intuition.
110
This is what Pico della Mirandola already saw and embraced in the Renaissance because he
saw the plurality of world religions and wisdoms as already announcing our homelesness “by
right” on earth.
111
Manuel Delanda, Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy (London: Continuum, 2002).
112
Ibid., p. 135.
113
However, holey space is not a utopian space: there are no smiths without imperial prospectors
who have gone before and imperial merchants which come after the work (ATP 415).
114
Unlike Levinas, Deleuze is not interested in the fantasy of a pure transcendent other. He is
intrigued by the smith as another, an (internally doubled) double.
115
Eliot Ross Albert has exhaustively covered the topic of the great distance between Deleuze’s
vitalism and any form of “autopoetic” thinking in his dissertation, Towards a Schizogenealogy of
Heretical Materialism: Between Bruno and Spinoza, Nietzsche, Deleuze and other Philosophical
Recluses (University of Warwick Dissertation, 1999), Ch. II.
116
But also ritual, therapeutic, even magical.
117
The Romantics thought of the Genius as in some sense the mouthpiece of the Object or the
Thing desired by the People. Rock stars are often thought of in this way. Deleuze’s “minor”
epistemology might seem like an epistemology of genius or inspiration, or at least of intuition
(Badiou reads him as an intuitionist). And Deleuze does speak of artists like Proust, Melville,
Kleist, minor scientists like Archimedes, Desargues, Perronet, and “minor” philosophers like
Nietzsche, Foucault, Chatelet, and Democritus as being “inspired.” But what differs Deleuze’s
epistemology from that of the Romantics is that the “special connections” these figures entertain
are not enjoyed in the name of a synthesizing or “tragic” vision. They do not speak for the
Whole, although they do in some sense speak of the All of “our” experience. Again, what is
distinctive is the different objects to which these subjects become beholden, the Difference
constituted by a peculiar perspective into which an artist, scientist, or philosopher is pulled or
toward which s/he is carried by the materials themselves.
118
Then a second thing that distinguishes an animal is that it also has a territory (Deleuze
indicates that with Guattari, he developed a nearly philosophical concept about territory).
Constituting a territory is nearly the birth of art: in making a territory, it is not merely a matter of
defecatory and urinary markings, but also a series of postures (standing/sitting for an animal), a
series of colors (that an animal takes on), a song [un chant]. These are the three determinants of
art: colors, lines, song --, says Deleuze, art in its pure state.” Paraphrase of interview with Claire
Parnet; trans. Stivale. (http://www.langlab.wayne.edu/CStivale/D-G/ABC1.html#anchor540856)
119
ATP 240.
120
Cf. Bogue, “Natura Musicans: Territory and the Refrain,” in Deleuze on Music, Painting, and
the Arts.
237
121
The rule of artful becoming is to be always present, accompanying, ambulating rather than
identifying, imitating, or representing. How is this possible? By forcing what we can perceive
and experience to speed up, slow down, be cut up, compacted, put alongside things it doesn’t
belong next to. Montage, cinema. But also theatre, not only Artaud’s theatre of cruelty but also
the theater of Le Coq which Artaud inspired. In the Le Coq method, character is built from the
outside in, from gesture, and above all from the “neutral mask”: an impersonal, indiscernible,
nearly imperceptible double of a face that is put on and must be animated by the body of the
actor. Seeing an actor in a neutral mask forces us to wait much longer than normal for the
revelation of psychological states (fear, joy, etc.) because the entire body must work through it or
distill it in a time much longer than the actual “consciousness” of the emotion. At the same time
what the actor is doing (running, jumping, hitting, pointing) happens much faster than it would if
we could slow it down through the face-machine, through reference to the “personality” from
which we could imagine the action derived. Le Coq’s methods make linguistic self-
consciousness subordinate to massive or microbial affects which continually provoke and
interrupt the superficial continuity of intentional activity—hence his emphasis on clowning and
its almost unbearable witness to the real. See Lecoq’s Lettre a mes eleves (Paris: Ecole Jacques
Lecoq, 1995).
122
Psychoanalysis reduced artistic becoming-everything and -everybody to a narcissism gone
wild. But it has missed the boat, missed the true plane, the true surface. “They see the animal as
a representative of drives, or a representation of the parents. They do not see the reality of a
becoming-animal, that it is affect in itself, the drive in person, and represents nothing. There exist
no other drives than the assemblages themselves” (ATP 259). In Peter Schaffer’s Equus, the
young man Allen who has put out the eyes of five horses is cured by a psychoanalyst of the
religious mania which drove him to worship horses and to fear their witness to his “infidelity” to
them when he nearly succumbs to the seduction of his girlfriend in their stable. In a deeply
moving speech at the play’s end, the analyst effectively condemns the value of his own ability to
cure or work through the trauma with the boy, because now that it has been narrated and reduced
to meaning, or interpreted, the passion—the line of flight—connecting the boy’s body to Equus
(his god/horse) is effectively destroyed. He re-enters normalcy at the cost of his desire, his
passion.
Perhaps Lacan (and certainly Zizek) would revel in this “traversal of the fantasy,” since
for them the boy-horse-god assemblage, with its absolute tactility and nonverbal or nonsensical
sense (chinkle chankle) is wholly imaginary and simply compensates for (is the mirror image of)
the excessively verbal, hysterical father. The real victory on the Lacanian view would be in the
fact that the boy has realized the vulnerability of his father and is now ready to give up his idol of
an Absolute Good Power opposed to the Absolute Evil Power of his father. But the problem here
is that it is the horse who pays. It is the earth who pays, not just the literal material world, but our
magical connection with it, the singularity of the boy-horse-god connection, as such. And
psychoanalysis might say yes, indeed, we must all give up our Jungian alchemical fantasy of a
spiritual matter or mother as the true seat of desire. However, this (imagined) solution is deeply
problematic, from a Deleuzian perspective. It says nothing of the earth.
123
Although deconstruction can be something like a prelude to conceptual creation. There does
not have to be an either-or relation between creation and deconstruction. Derrida seems to have
well understood that.
238
124
Deleuze locates Bacon’s gesture at the third position in his four-part schema of sign-creation.
As Deleuze analyzes it in A Thousand Plateaus, signs pass through at least four moments (which
are not necessarily distinct): generative, transformational, diagrammatic, and machinc.
125
This is in keeping with the theory of ideas which are superior to concepts.
126
As in Frank Herbert’s Dune chronicles, which pose all the problems of capitalism, politics,
and religion on the plane of immanence of a cosmic desert and the plane of consistency of
addiction to the spice mélange.
127
The Deleuze Connections (Cambridge: MIT, 2000), p. 75.
128
Jean Baudrillard. The Spirit of Terrorism (London: Verso, 2002), p. 20
129
Ibid., pp. 11-12.
130
Ibid., p. 15
131
Timothy Brennan, Wars of Position (New York: Columbia, 2006).
132
Agamben, after Derrida, thinks of the marginalized in “messianic” terms, in terms of a passive
potentiality that cannot be dialectically exploited. See Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare
Life. Trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998).
133
It seems the only non-alternative non-position Brennan can imagine for those against whom he
complains is an “obviously failed” eurocommunism. Given that liberal democracy is the political
game of the day, Brennan may have a point that the left should marshal a narrative that is more
compelling than the story of ostracized or abject subjetivities, or at least one that more explicitly
attempts to bring “subaltern” aspects of subjectivity under the purview of legal and legislative
action. Martha Nussbaum’s recent book in a way attempts to do this when she augments the
Rawlsian/liberal notion of justice by pointing out its failure to include non-human animals, the
disabled, and migrants in its concept of who can be recognized as a bearer of rights.
134
See Alain Badiou, Being and Event (London: Continuum, 2005), p. 504.
135
In the closing pages of Logique des Mondes (Paris: Seuil, 2006).
136
In Ray Brassier and Alberto Toscano, eds. and trans., Theoretical Writings (London:
Continuum, 2004), pp. 67-80.
137
Zizek has similar praise for the notion that events that are not emergent from material
processes but are static, intransitive, and quasi-causal . . . a nonsense inherent to sense that gives
body to the incompleteness of all causal chains. See Organs without Bodies (London: Rutledge,
2004), p. 28.
138
See “One, Multiple, Multiplicity,” in Theoretical Writings (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 70,
where Badiou claims that Deleuze lags behind the development of mathematics, and that his
notion of multiplicity is impoverished by comparison with that of the Multiple which is only
available through Badiou’s notion of a wholly “subtractive” view of events.
239
139
The real crux of Badiou’s critique seems to be that Deleuze fails to distinguish parts and
elements (ibid., 76), which set theory does. This is a distinction between elementary belonging
and partative inclusion. Badiou thinks the whole question of what a universal singularity is, is in
the relation between these two ways of “being-in.”
140
Zizek’s rehabilitation of Hegel’s “concrete universal” as the deficiency of materiality plus its
“undead” fiction of hideous eternity is very close to Deleuze’s notion. See especially his
Tarrying With the Negative (Raleigh: Duke, 1993).
141
Because Badiou takes the quest of his own philosophy to be an attempt to instruct the times
about what it may yet be able to do, I find it highly limiting that he allows only mathematically-
minded souls to intuit when and where truth has taken hold of us. Why, in our times,
mathematics, rather than molecular biology, or particle physics, or film, or music? William S.
Burroughs as much as Deleuze thought that biological experimentation was the key to showing
our times what it would be capable of, and Burroughs’s question was whether we could become
capable of loving something that we alone can take responsibility for creating.
Deleuze seems a much more adroit reader of the power of our times precisely because,
unlike Badiou, Deleuze does not take the success of global capitalism to be a case of massive
self-deception, as Badiou and even Zizek seem to think it is. Deleuze realizes that the genius of
capital times, which is surely an evil genius, consists in how we have abandoned the illusion of
the big other, and submitted ourselves to the reality of our drives, or the “plague of fantasies,” as
Zizek puts it. The only way out of our current state is through it, for Deleuze.
142
Badiou claims he is going for something like this in reading truth as an excess of any actual
multiplicity (which makes it a “multiplicity” in the technical sense and not merely a collection or
coagulation of parts). However, Badiou claims not to need to category of the virtual in order to
explain “undecidability” or what Deleuze calls the “ambulatory” or “mobile” aspect of
multiplicity. As Badiou puts it,
What Badiou denies here is any importance to the “shape” in which the aleatory appears (its
slogan, its emblem, its declarative form).
143
Remarkably, this formula fits the pattern of what the theurgic Neo-Platonists claimed about the
ability of certain material formations (those with the correct geometry) to invoke the One by
activating the “ones” latent in the material world. This was the view of Iamblichus, as Gregory
Shaw explains it in Theurgy and the Soul: the Neo-Platonism of Iamblichus (University Park:
Pennsylvania State University Press), p. 162. Pre-Kantian sources such as Neo-Platonism are not
acknowledged by Badiou and Zizek, but in his early work Deleuze welcomes the insights of
certain Neo-Platonists, especially Cusa and Bruno, on the nature of complicatio.
144
Despite the shift over time in Deleuze’s discursive strategy, this basic “structuralism” of
Deleuze’s approach never really goes away. Rather, it takes on a less and less “binary” mode of
explication—signs, Deleuze comes to think after his encounter with Guattari, are better though to
240
as coming in regimes and not in series. But his later concepts of time images in cinema,
Leibnizian “folds” in being, of diagrams in painting, and machinic phylum’s in various matters of
expression (linking tools and weapons, or steppes and deserts, or animal behavior and musical
sounds) all maintain the theme of the necessity of Figures or “partial objects” that, while
seemingly external to the nature or being of things, are the actual image of their (virtual) inability
to maintain homogeneous consistency (i.e. to attain to the status of an “All” or a completed
“Whole”).
145
For this see Badiou’s “Truth: Forcing and the Unnamable” in Theoretical Writings, pp. 119-
134.
146
As Zizek rather cheekily puts it, this makes truth resemble something like the Levinasian
absolute other, before which I can only have a kind of abject relationship of fealty.
147
At a conference of the European Graduate School in Saas-Fee, at which I happened to be
present, along with Zizek (August, 2002).
148
In Le Siecle (Paris: Seuil, 2005), ch.5 “Passion du reel et montage du semblant.”
149
As Deleuze and Guattari put it,
241
154
Pico della Mirandola, “Oration on the Dignity of Man,” 26-29.
155
Frances Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1965), p.123.
156
In S.A. Farmer, Syncretism in the West: Pico’s 900 Theses (1486) (Tempe: Medieval and
Renaissance Texts and Studies, 1998).
157
Pico della Mirandola, On the Dignity of Man and Other Works (Ed. Charles
Glen Wallis. New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965), p.26
158
Ibid., p.28
159
See Hans Blumenberg, The Legitimacy of the Modern Age Trans. Robert M. Wallace.
(Cambridge: MIT Press, 1983), for the importance for modern culture of the shift from Cusa to
Bruno.
160
Albert’s Warwick dissertation is entitled “Toward a Schizogenealogy of Materialism: Deleuze
and Bruno, Spinoza, Nietzsche.”
161
See Nuccio Ordine, Le Seuil de l’ombre: litterature, philosophie, et peinture chez Giordano
Bruno (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2003), pp. 309 ff.
162
“Inadequate” should not be thought of as “incomplete” or “finite,” and should be translated
into Deleuzian terms. Each figure embodies a distance proper difference in itself, a bounded but
unlimited intensive quantity proper to each multiplicity of sense.
163
Hallyn, The Poetic Structure of the World: Copernicus and Kepler (Trans. Donald M. Leslie.
New York: Zone Books, 1990) p. 155.
164
Fernand Hallyn, The Poetic Structure of the World: Copernicus and Kepler (Trans.
Donald M. Leslie. New York: Zone Books, 1990), p.160.
165
Cornelius Agrippa, De Occulta Philosophia, I, 38 ed. Cit., p. 53 in Frances Yates, Giordano
Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition.
166
Ibid., l, 50, ed. Cit., pp. 230-1 in Frances Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition.
167
See Ordine, Seuil de l’ombre. Literature, philosophie et peinture chez Giordano Bruno.
Trans. Luc Hersant. (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2003).
168
See Frances Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition.
169
See Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul: the Neo-Platonism of Iamblichus.
170
Michel Foucalt, The Order of Things. An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (New York:
Random House, 1970), p.40
171
Even though it is very easy to read much of Deleuze’s work in this way.
242
172
The reason we can think of a Deleuzian “Renaissance” is thanks to the semiotics of Peirce and
the linguistics of Hjemslev, and generally to the “poststructuralist” movement, which complicated
the relationship between signifier and signified and enabled us to see the projective or
“abductive” nature of certain signs—a diagrammatic function wherein mind pre-figures the real
in signs according to motives that, if not clearly assignable (to empirical or ideal forces),
nevertheless produce distinct results
173
Note the almost Vicoean perspective, here.
174
See Nuccio Ordine, Le Seuil de l’ombre (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2003), pp. 310-311.
175
Because it goes beyond language, per se, into that which would be considered “extra
linguistic.”
176
For someone like Zizek, this takes too much time to realize. He calls for dramatic and
immediate performative hegemony, and for the eruption of truth and resistance in dramatic and
immediately intiuitable reversals. The eruption of the uncanny, the strange. Deleuze calls for this
as well, but he is willing to see or to attempt to see the emergence of the new as a larger, more
“geological” process rather than as the invasion of an uncanny unworldliness (a return of the
undead).
243
Bibliography
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Trans. Daniel Heller-
Roazen. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.
Artaud, Antonin. The Theatre and its Double. Trans. Mary Caroline Richards. New
York: Grove Press, 1958.
Badiou, Alain. Being and Event. Trans. Oliver Feltham. London: Continuum, 2005.
---. “Language, Thought, Poetry.” Alain Badiou: Theoretical Writings. Ed. and trans.
Ray Brassier and Alberto Toscano. London: Continuum, 2004.
---. “Truth: Forcing and the Unnameable.” Alain Badiou: Theoretical Writings. Ed. and
trans. Ray Brassier and Alberto Toscano. London: Continuum, 2004.
Baudrillard, Jean. The Spirit of Terrorism. Trans. Chris Turner. London: Verso Press,
2002.
Baugh, Bruce. “Deleuze and Empiricism.” Journal of the British Society for
Phenomenology 24(1) (1993): p. 31.
Bergson, Henry. Matter and Memory. Trans. N.M. Paul and W.S. Palmer. New York:
Zone Books, 1991.
---. Two Sources of Morality and Religion. Trans. R. Ashely Audra and Cloudesley
Brereton. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977.
Blumenberg, Hans. The Legitimacy of the Modern Age. Trans. Robert M. Wallace.
Cambridge: MIT Press, 1983.
Bogue, Ronald. Deleuze on Music, Painting, and the Arts. London: Rutledge, 2003.
---. “Word, Image and Sound: The Non-Representational Semiotics of Gilles Deleuze.”
Mimesis in Contemporary Theory: An Interdisciplinary Approach, Volume 2:
Mimesis, Semiosis, and Power. Ronald Bogue, ed. Philadelphia: John
244
Benjamins, 1991, pp.77-97.
Boldereef, Frances M. Hermes to his Son Thoth: being Joyce’s Use of Giordano Bruno
in Finnegan’s Wake. Woodward: Classic Non-Fiction Library, 1968.
Brassier, Ray and Toscano, Alberto, eds. and trans. Alain Badiou: Theoretical Writings.
London: Continuum, 2004.
Bruno, Giordano. The Ash Wednesday Supper. Ed. and trans. Edward A. Gosselin and
Lawrence S. Lerner.
---. The Cabala of Pegasus. Trans. Sidney L. Sondergard and Madison U. Sowell. New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2002.
---. Cause, Principle, and Unity. Ed. Richard J. Blackwell and Robert de Lucca.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
---. The Expulsion of the Triumphant Beast. Trans. Arthur D. Imerti. New Brunswick:
Rutgers University Press, 1964.
---. The Heroic Frenzies. Trans. Eugene Memmo, Jr. Chapel Hill: University of North
Carolina Press, 1964.
---. On the Composition of Images, Signs and Ideas. Trans. Charles Doria. New York:
Willis, Locker, and Owens, 1991.
Buchanan, Ian. “Deleuze and Cultural Studies.” South Atlantic Quarterly 96(3) (1997):
483-97.
Copjec, Joan. Imagine There’s No Woman: Ethics and Sublimation. Cambridge: MIT
Press, 2002.
De Cusa, Nicolas. Unity and Reform: Selected Writings of Nicolas de Cusa. Ed. John P.
Dolan. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1962.
Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema I: The Movement-Image. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara
245
Habberjam. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996.
---. Cinema II. The Time-Image. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997.
---. Desert Islands and Other Texts (1953-1974). Ed. David Lapoujade. Trans. Michael
Taormina. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2004.
---. Difference and Repetition. Trans. Paul Patton. New York: Columbia, 1994.
---. Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature. Trans.
Constantin Boundas. New York: Columbia, 1991.
---. Essays Critical and Clinical. Trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Greco.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997.
---. Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza. Trans. Martin Joughin. New York: Zone
Books, 1990.
---. Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation. Trans. Dan Smith. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota, 2003.
---. The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque. Trans. Tom Conley. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 1993.
---. Foucault. Trans. Sean Hand. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988.
---. Kant’s Critical Philosophy. Tran. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1984.
---. The Logic of Sense. Trans. Mark Lester and Charles Stivale. New York: Columbia,
1990.
---. Masochism: Coldness and Cruelty. Trans. Jean McNeil. New York: Zone Books,
1989.
---. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson. New York: Columbia, 1983.
---. Proust and Signs. Trans. Richard Howard. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 2000.
---. Pure Immanence: Essays on a Life. Trans. Anne Boyman. New York: Zone
Books, 2001.
---. Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975-1995. Ed. David Lapoujade.
Trans. Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e),
246
2006.
Deleuze, Gilles and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. Trans. Brian Massumi.
Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1987.
---. Anti-Oedipus. Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1983.
---. What Is Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell. New York:
Columbia, 1994.
Deleuze, Gilles and Claire Parnet. Dialogues. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara
Habberjam. New York: Columbia Press, 1987.
--Dialogues II. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. New York: Columbia,
2002.
Derrida, Jacques. Writing and Difference. Trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1978.
Dischner, Gisela. Giordano Bruno: Denker, Dichter, Magier. Tübingen & Basel: A.
Francke Verlag, 2004.
Eco, Umberto. The Aesthetics of Chaosmos: The Middle Ages of James Joyce. Trans.
Ellen Esrock. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989.
Farmer, S.A. Syncretism in the West: Pico’s 900 Theses (1486). The Evolution of
Traditional Religious and Philosophical Systems. Tempe: Medieval and
Renaissance Texts and Studies, 1998.
Faubion, James D., ed. Foucault: Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology. New York:
The New Press, 1998.
---. The Order of Things. An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New York: Random
House, 1970.
Freud, Sigmund. The Freud Reader. Ed. Peter Gay. New York: W.W. Norton, 1989.
247
Girard, Rene. “Delirium as System.” “To Double Business Bound” : Essays on
Literature, Mimesis and Anthropology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1978, 84-120)
Gose Jr., Elliot B. The Transformation Process in Joyce’s Ulysses. Toronto: Univ. of
Toronto Press, 1980
Guattari, Felix. The Anti-Oedipus Papers. Trans. Kalina Gottman. New York:
Semiotext(e), 2006.
Hallyn, Fernand. The Poetic Structure of the World: Copernicus and Kepler. Trans.
Donald M. Leslie. New York: Zone Books, 1990.
Hegel, G.W.F. Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. A.V. Miller. Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1980.
Jarry, Alfred. Selected Works of Alfred Jarry. Ed. Roger Shattuck and Simon Watson
Taylor. New York: Grove Press, 1965.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman Kemp Smith. London:
Macmillan, 1978.
Kierkegaard, Soren. Fear and Trembling and Repetition. Trans. and ed. H.V. and E.H.
Hong. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983.
Klossowski, Pierre. The Baphomet. Trans. Sophie Hawkes and Stephen Sartarelli. New
York: Marsilio, 1988.
---. Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle. Trans. Dan Smith. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1997.
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern. Trans. Catherine Porter. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1993.
Lecoq, Jacques. Lettre a mes eleves. 1956-1996. Paris: Ecole Jacques Lecoq, 1996.
Leibniz, G.W. Philosophical Writings. Ed. G.H.R. Parkinson. London: Dent, 1973.
248
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Basic Writings. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Modern
Library, 2000.
---. The Portable Nietzsche. Ed. and trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Penguin,
1982.
Milbank, John. “On Complex Space.” The Word Made Strange. London: Blackwell,
1997.
Ordine, Nuccio. Giordano Bruno and the Philosophy of the Ass. Trans. Henryk Baranski
and Arielle Saiber. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1996.
Patton and Protevi, eds. Deleuze and Derrida. New York: Continuum, 2003.
Pearson, Keith Ansell. Germinal Life: The Difference and Repetition of Deleuze.
London: Rutledge, 1999.
Peirce, Charles. “How to Make our Ideas Clear.” Philosophical Writings of Peirce. Ed.
Justus Buchler. New York: Dover, 1955, pp. 23-41.
Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni. On the Dignity of Man and Other Works. Ed. Charles
Glen Wallis. New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965.
---. Michel Foucault: The Freedom of Philosophy. New York: Columbia UP, 1985.
Scott. W. Ed. and Trans. Corpus Hermetica. The Ancient Greek and Latin Writings
Which Contain Religious or Philosophic Teachings Ascribed to Hermes
Trismegistus. Vol. I. London: Dawsons of Pall Mall, 1968.
Shaw, Gregory. Theurgy and the Soul: the Neoplatonism of Iamblichus. University
Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995.
249
Spinoza, Baruch. Ethics. Ed. E. Curley, Princeton: Princeton University Press
Spruit, Leen. “Giordano Bruno and Astrology.” Giordano Bruno, Philosopher of the
Renaissance. Ed. Hilary Gatti. Hants: Ashgate, 2002, pp. 229-250.
Vico, Giambattista. The New Science. Trans. Marsh New York: Penguin, 2001.
Widder, Nathan. “The rights of simulacra: Deleuze and the univocity of being.”
Continental Philosophy Review. Kluwer, 2001. Vol. 34: 437-453
Yates, Frances A. Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1965.
---. Tarrying With the Negative: Kant, Hegel, and the Critique of Ideology. Durham:
Duke University Press, 1993.
250