Jurisprudence Mayank Sharma 051
Jurisprudence Mayank Sharma 051
Jurisprudence Mayank Sharma 051
Internal Submission –
JURISPRUDENCE
Mayank Sharma
FYLLB, Div. A (Sem 4)
Roll No. 051
JURISPRUDENCE
The word jurisprudence derives from the Latin term jurisprudentia, which means "the study, knowledge,
or science of law." In the United States jurisprudence commonly means the philosophy of law. Legal
philosophy has many aspects, but four of them are the most common. The first and the most prevalent
form of jurisprudence seeks to analyze, explain, classify, and criticize entire bodies of law. Law school
textbooks and legal encyclopedias represent this type of scholarship. The second type of
jurisprudence compares and contrasts law with other fields of knowledge such as literature,
economics, religion, and the social sciences. The third type of jurisprudence seeks to reveal the
historical, moral, and cultural basis of a particular legal concept. The fourth body of jurisprudence
focuses on finding the answer to such abstract questions as “What is law?” and “How do judges
(properly) decide cases?”
Apart from different types of jurisprudence, different schools of jurisprudence exist. Formalism, or
conceptualism, treats law like math’s or science. Formalists believe that a judge identifies the
relevant legal principles, applies them to the facts of a case, and logically deduces a rule that will
govern the outcome of the dispute. In contrast, proponents of legal realism believe that most cases
before courts present hard questions that judges must resolve by balancing the interests of the parties
and ultimately drawing an arbitrary line on one side of the dispute. This line, realists maintain, is
drawn according to the political, economic, and psychological inclinations of the judge. Some legal
realists even believe that a judge is able to shape the outcome of the case based on personal biases.
Apart from the realist-formalist dichotomy, there is the classic debate over the appropriate sources of
law between positivist and natural law schools of thought. Positivists argue that there is no
connection between law and morality and that the only sources of law are rules that have been
expressly enacted by a governmental entity or court of law. Naturalists, or proponents of natural law,
insist that the rules enacted by government are not the only sources of law. They argue that moral
philosophy; religion, human reason and individual conscience are also integral parts of the law.
There are no bright lines between different schools of jurisprudence. The legal philosophy of a
particular legal scholar may consist of a combination of strains from many schools of legal thought.
Some scholars think that it is more appropriate to think about jurisprudence as a continuum.
LEGAL POSITIVISM
Legal positivism is the thesis that the existence and content of law depends on social
facts and not on its merits. The English jurist John Austin (1790-1859) formulated
it thus: “The existence of law is one thing; its merit and demerit another. Whether
it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed
standard, is a different enquiry.” (1832, p. 157) The positivist thesis does not say
that law's merits are unintelligible, unimportant, or peripheral to the philosophy of
law. It says that they do not determine whether laws or legal systems exist. Whether
a society has a legal system depends on the presence of certain structures of
governance, not on the extent to which it satisfies ideals of justice, democracy,
or the rule of law. What laws are in force in that system depends on what
social standards its officials recognize as authoritative; for example, legislative
enactments, judicial decisions, or social customs. The fact that a policy would be
just, wise, efficient, or prudent is never sufficient reason for thinking that it is
actually the law, and the fact that it is unjust, unwise, inefficient or imprudent
is never sufficient reason for doubting it. According to positivism, law is a
matter of what has been posited (ordered, decided, practiced, tolerated, etc.); as we
might say in a more modern idiom, positivism is the view that law is a social
construction. Austin thought the thesis “simple and glaring.” While it is probably
the dominant view among analytically inclined philosophers of law, it is also
the subject of competing interpretations together with persistent criticisms and
misunderstandings.
Legal positivism has a long history and a broad influence. It has antecedents in
ancient political philosophy and is discussed, and the term itself introduced, in
mediaeval legal and political thought (see Finnis 1996). The modern doctrine,
however, owes little to these forbears. Its most important roots lie in the
conventionalist political philosophies of Hobbes and Hume, and its first full
elaboration is due to Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) whose account Austin
adopted, modified, and popularized. For much of the next century an amalgam of
their views, according to which law is the command of a sovereign backed by
force, dominated legal positivism and English philosophical reflection about law.
By the mid-twentieth century, however, this account had lost its influence
among working legal philosophers. Its emphasis on legislative institutions was
replaced by a focus on law-applying institutions such as courts, and its insistence
of the role of coercive force gave way to theories emphasizing the systematic and
normative character of law. The most important architects of this revised positivism
are the Austrian jurist Hans Kelsen (1881-1973) and the two dominating figures
in the analytic philosophy of law, H.L.A. Hart (1907-92) and Joseph Raz among
whom there are clear lines of influence, but also important contrasts. Legal
positivism's importance, however, is not confined to the philosophy of law. It can
be seen throughout social theory, particularly in the works of Marx, Weber, and
Durkheim, and also (though here unwittingly) among many lawyers, including
the American “legal realists” and most contemporary feminist scholars. Although
they disagree on many other points, these writers all acknowledge that law is
essentially a matter of social fact. Some of them are, it is true, uncomfortable with
the label “legal positivism” and therefore hope to escape it. Their discomfort is
sometimes the product of confusion. Lawyers often use “positivist” abusively, to
condemn a formalistic doctrine according to which law is always clear and,
however pointless or wrong, is to be rigorously applied by officials and obeyed by
subjects. It is doubtful that anyone ever held this view; but it is in any case false, it
has nothing to do with legal positivism, and it is expressly rejected by all leading
positivists. Among the philosophically literate another, more intelligible,
misunderstanding may interfere. Legal positivism is here sometimes associated
with the homonymic but independent doctrines of logical positivism (the meaning
of a sentence is its mode of verification) or sociological positivism (social
phenomena can be studied only through the methods of natural science). While
there are historical connections, and also commonalities of temper, among these
ideas, they are essentially different. The view that the existence of law depends on
social facts does not rest on a particular semantic thesis, and it is compatible with
a range of theories about how one investigates social facts, including non-
naturalistic accounts. To say that the existence of law depends on facts and not
on its merits is a thesis about the relation among laws, facts, and merits, and not
otherwise a thesis about the individual relata. Hence, most traditional “natural
law” moral doctrines--including the belief in a universal, objective morality
grounded in human nature--do not contradict legal positivism. The only influential
positivist moral theories are the views that moral norms are valid only if they
have a source in divine commands or in social conventions. Such theists and
relativists apply to morality the constraints that legal positivists think hold for law.
Every human society has some form of social order, some way of marking
and encouraging approved behavior, deterring disapproved behavior, and
resolving disputes. What then is distinctive of societies with legal systems and,
within those societies, of their law? Before exploring some positivist answers, it
bears emphasizing that these are not the only questions worth asking. While an
understanding of the nature of law requires an account of what makes law
distinctive, it also requires an understanding of what it has in common with other
forms of social control. Some Marxists are positivists about the nature of law
while insisting that its distinguishing characteristics matter less than its role in
replicating and facilitating other forms of domination. (Though other Marxists
disagree: see Pashukanis). They think that the specific nature of law casts little light
on their primary concerns. But one can hardly know that in advance; it depends on
what the nature of law actually is.
Imperatival theories are now without influence in legal philosophy (but see
Ladenson and Morison). What survives of their outlook is the idea that legal theory
must ultimately be rooted in some account of the political system, an insight that
came to be shared by all major positivists save Kelsen. Their particular conception
of a society under a sovereign commander, however, is friendless (except
among Foucauldians, who strangely take this relic as the ideal-type of what they
call “juridical” power). It is clear that in complex societies there may be no
one who has all the attributes of sovereignty, for ultimate authority may be
divided among organs and may itself be limited by law. Moreover, even when
“sovereignty” is not being used in its legal sense it is nonetheless a normative
concept. A legislator is one who has authority to make laws, and not merely
someone with great social power, and it is doubtful that “habits of obedience” is
a candidate reduction for explaining authority. Obedience is a normative concept.
To distinguish it from coincidental compliance we need something like the idea of
subjects being oriented to, or guided by, the commands. Explicating this will carry
us far from the power-based notions with which classical positivism hoped to work.
The imperativalists' account of obligation is also subject to decisive objections
(Hart, 1994, pp. 26 -78; and Hacker). Treating all laws as commands conceals
important differences in their social functions, in the ways they operate in practical
reasoning, and in the sort of justifications to which they are liable. For instance,
laws conferring the power to marry command nothing; they do not obligate
people to marry, or even to marry according to the prescribed formalities. Nor is
reductivism any more plausible here: we speak of legal obligations when there is
no probability of sanctions being applied and when there is no provision for
sanctions (as in the duty of the highest courts to apply the law). Moreover, we take
the existence of legal obligations to be a reason for imposing sanctions, not merely
a consequence of it.
Hans Kelsen retains the imperativalists' monism but abandons their reductivism. On
his view, law is characterized by a basic form and basic norm. The form of every
law is that of a conditional order, directed at the courts, to apply sanctions if a
certain behavior (the “delict”) is performed. On this view, law is an indirect system
of guidance: it does not tell subjects what to do; it tells officials what to do to its
subjects under certain conditions. Thus, what we ordinarily regard as the legal duty
not to steal is for Kelsen merely a logical correlate of the primary norm which
stipulates a sanction for stealing (1945, p. 61). The objections to imperatival
monism apply also to this more sophisticated version: the reduction misses
important facts, such as the point of having a prohibition on theft. (The courts are
not indifferent between, on the one hand, people not stealing and, on the other,
stealing and suffering the sanctions.) But in one respect the conditional sanction
theory is in worse shape than is imperativalism, for it has no principled way to fix
on the delict as the duty-defining condition of the sanction -- that is but one of a
large number of relevant antecedent conditions, including the legal capacity of the
offender, the jurisdiction of the judge, the constitutionality of the offense, and so
forth. Which among all these is the content of a legal duty?
Kelsen's most important contribution lies in his attack on reductivism and his
doctrine of the “basic norm.” He maintains that law is normative and must
understood as such. Might does not make right -
- not even legal right -- so the philosophy of law must explain the fact that law is
taken to impose obligations on its subjects. Moreover, law is a normative system:
“Law is not, as it is sometimes said, a rule. It is a set of rules having the kind of
unity we understand by a system” (1945, p. 3). For the imperativalists, the unity
of a legal system consists in the fact that all its laws are commanded by one
sovereign. For Kelsen, it consists in the fact that they are all links in one chain
of authority. For example, a by-law is legally valid because it is created by a
corporation lawfully exercising the powers conferred on it by the legislature,
which confers those powers in a manner provided by the constitution, which was
itself created in a way provided by an earlier constitution. But what about the very
first constitution, historically speaking? Its authority, says Kelsen, is
“presupposed.” The condition for interpreting any legal norm as binding is that
the first constitution is validated by the following “basic norm:” “the original
constitution is to be obeyed.” Now, the basic norm cannot be a legal norm -- we
cannot fully explain the bindingness of law by reference to more law. Nor can it be
a social fact, for Kelsen maintains that the reason for the validity of a norm must
always be another norm -- no ought from is. It follows, then, that a legal system
must consist of norms all the way down. It bottoms in a hypothetical,
transcendental norm that is the condition of the intelligibility of any (and all) other
norms as binding. To “presuppose” this basic norm is not to endorse it as good or
just -- resupposition is a cognitive stance only -- but it is, Kelsen thinks, the
necessary precondition for a non-reductivist account of law as a normative system.
There are many difficulties with this, not least of which is the fact that if we are
willing to tolerate the basic norm as a solution it is not clear why we thought there
was a problem in the first place. One cannot say both that the basic norm is the
norm presupposing which validates all inferior norms and also that an inferior
norm is part of the legal system only if it is connected by a chain of validity to the
basic norm. We need a way into the circle. Moreover, it draws the boundaries of
legal systems incorrectly. The Canadian Constitution of 1982 was lawfully
created by an Act of the U.K. Parliament, and on that basis Canadian law and
English law should be parts of a single legal system, rooted in one basic norm:
‘The (first) U.K. constitution is to be obeyed.’ Yet no English law is binding in
Canada, and a purported repeal of the Constitution Act by the U.K. would be without
legal effect in Canada.
A positivist account of the existence and content of law, along any of the above
lines, offers a theory of the validity of law in one of the two main senses of that
term (see Harris, pp. 107-111). Kelsen says that validity is the specific mode of
existence of a norm. An invalid marriage is not a special kind of marriage having
the property of invalidity; it is not a marriage at all. In this sense a valid law one
that is systemically valid in the jurisdiction -- it is part of the legal system. This is
the question that positivists answer by reference to social sources. It is distinct from
the idea of validity as moral propriety, i.e. a sound justification for respecting the
norm. For the positivist, this depends on its merits. One indication that these
senses differ is that one may know that a society has a legal system, and know what
its laws are, without having any idea whether they are morally justified. For example,
one may know that the law of ancient Athens included the punishment of ostracism
without knowing whether it was justified, because one does not know enough
about its effects, about the social context, and so forth.
No legal positivist argues that the systemic validity of law establishes its moral
validity, i.e. that it should be obeyed by subjects or applied by judges. Even
Hobbes, to whom this view is sometimes ascribed, required that law actually be
able to keep the peace, failing which we owe it nothing. Bentham and Austin,
as utilitarians, hold that such questions always turn on the consequences and both
acknowledge that disobedience is therefore sometimes fully justified. Kelsen
insists that “The science of law does not prescribe that one ought to obey the
commands of the creator of the constitution” (1967, p. 204). Hart thinks that
there is only a prima facie duty to obey, grounded in and thus limited by fairness
-- so there is no obligation to unfair or pointless laws (Hart 1955). Raz goes further
still, arguing that there isn't even a prima facie duty to obey the law, not even in a
just state (Raz 1979, pp. 233-49). The peculiar accusation that positivists believe
the law is always to be obeyed is without foundation. Hart's own view is that an
overweening deference to law consorts more easily with theories that imbue it
with moral ideals, permitting “an enormous overvaluation of the importance of
the bare fact that a rule may be said to be a valid rule of law, as if this, once
declared, was conclusive of the final moral question: ‘Ought this law to be
obeyed?” (Hart 1958, p. 75).
The most influential criticisms of legal positivism all flow, in one way or another,
from the suspicion that it fails to give morality its due. A theory that insists on the
facticity of law seems to contribute little to our understanding that law has
important functions in making human life go well, that the rule of law is a prized
ideal, and that the language and practice of law is highly moralized.
Accordingly, positivism's critics maintain that the most important features of law
are not to be found in its source-based character, but in law's capacity to advance
the common good, to secure human rights, or to govern with integrity. (It is a
curious fact about anti-positivist theories that, while they all insist on the moral
nature of law, without exception they take its moral nature to be something good.
The idea that law might of its very nature be morally problematic does not seem
to have occurred to them.)
It is beyond doubt that moral and political considerations bear on legal philosophy.
As Finnis says, the reasons we have for establishing, maintaining or reforming law
include moral reasons, and these reasons therefore shape our legal concepts (p.
204). But which concepts? Once one concedes, as Finnis does, that the existence
and content of law can be identified without recourse to moral argument, and
that “human law is artefact and artifice; and not a conclusion from moral premises,
(p. 205) the Thomistic apparatus he tries to resuscitate is largely irrelevant to
the truth of legal positivism. This vitiates also Lon Fuller's criticisms of Hart
(Fuller, 1958 and 1969). Apart from some confused claims about adjudication,
Fuller has two main points. First, he thinks that it isn't enough for a legal system
to rest on customary social rules, since law could not guide behavior without
also being at least minimally clear, consistent, public, prospective and so on -
- that is, without exhibiting to some degree those virtues collectively called “the
rule of law.” It suffices to note that this is perfectly consistent with law being
source-based. Even if moral properties were identical with, or supervened upon,
these rule-of-law properties, they do so in virtue of their rule-like character, and
not their law-like character. Whatever virtues inhere in or follow from clear,
consistent, prospective, and open practices can be found not only in law but in
all other social practices with those features, including custom and positive
morality. And these virtues are minor: there is little to be said in favour of a clear,
consistent, prospective, public and impartially administered system of racial
segregation, for example. Fuller's second worry is that if law is a matter of fact,
then we are without an explanation of the duty to obey. He gloatingly asks how
“an amoral datum called law could have the peculiar quality of creating an
obligation to obey it” (Fuller, 1958). One possibility he neglects is that it doesn't.
The fact that law claims to obligate is, of course, a different matter and is
susceptible to other explanations (Green 2001). But even if Fuller is right in his
unargued assumption, the “peculiar quality” whose existence he doubts is a
familiar feature of many moral practices. Compare promises: whether a society
has a practice of promising, and what someone has promised to do, are matters of
social fact. Yet promising creates moral obligations of performance or
compensation. An “amoral datum” may indeed figure, together with other premises,
in a sound argument to moral conclusions.
While Finnis and Fuller's views are thus compatible with the positivist thesis, the
same cannot be said of Ronald Dworkin's important works (Dworkin 1978 and
1986). Positivism's most significant critic rejects the theory on every conceivable
level. He denies that there can be any general theory of the existence and content
of law; he denies that local theories of particular legal systems can identify law
without recourse to its merits, and he rejects the whole institutional focus of
positivism. A theory of law is for Dworkin a theory of how cases ought to be decided
and it begins, not with an account of political organization, but with an abstract
ideal regulating the conditions under which governments may use coercive force
over their subjects. Force must only be deployed, he claims, in accordance with
principles laid down in advance. A society has a legal system only when, and to the
extent that, it honors this ideal, and its law is the set of all considerations that the
courts of such a society would be morally justified in applying, whether or not
those considerations are determined by any source. To identify the law of a given
society we must engage in moral and political argument, for the law is whatever
requirements are consistent with an interpretation of its legal practices (subject
to a threshold condition of fit) that shows them to be best justified in light of
the animating ideal. In addition to those philosophical considerations, Dworkin
invokes two features of the phenomenology of judging, as he sees it. He finds deep
controversy among lawyers and judges about how important cases should be
decided, and he finds diversity in the considerations that they hold relevant to
deciding them. The controversy suggests to him that law cannot rest on an official
consensus, and the diversity suggests that there is no single social rule that validates
all relevant reasons, moral and non- moral, for judicial decisions.
Dworkin's rich and complex arguments have attracted various lines of reply from
positivists. One response denies the relevance of the phenomenological claims.
Controversy is a matter of degree, and a consensus-defeating amount of it is not
proved by the existence of adversarial argument in the high courts, or indeed in
any courts. As important is the broad range of settled law that gives rise to few
doubts and which guides social life outside the courtroom. As for the diversity
argument, so far from being a refutation of positivism, this is an entailment of it.
Positivism identifies law, not with all valid reasons for decision, but only with
the source-based subset of them. It is no part of the positivist claim that the
rule of recognition tells us how to decide cases, or even tells us all the relevant
reasons for decision. Positivists accept that moral, political or economic
considerations are properly operative in some legal decisions, just as linguistic or
logical ones are. Modus ponens holds in court as much as outside, but not because
it was enacted by the legislature or decided by the judges, and the fact that
there is no social rule that validates both modus ponens and also the
Municipalities Act is true but irrelevant. The authority of principles of logic (or
morality) is not something to be explained by legal philosophy; the authority of
acts of Parliament must be; and accounting for the difference is a central task of
the philosophy of law.
It has to be said, however, that Hart himself does not consistently view legal
references to morality as marking a zone of discretion. In a passing remark in the
first edition of The Concept of Law, he writes, “In some legal systems, as in the
United States, the ultimate criteria of legal validity explicitly incorporate principles
of justice or substantive moral values …” (1994, p. 204). This thought sits
uneasily with other doctrines of importance to his theory. For Hart also says
that when judges exercise moral judgment in the penumbra of legal rules to suppose
that their results were already part of existing law is “in effect, an invitation to
revise our concept of what a legal rule is …” (1958, p. 72). The concept of a
legal rule, that is, does not include all correctly reasoned elaborations or
determinations of that rule. Later, however, Hart comes to see his remark about the
U.S. constitution as foreshadowing inclusive positivism (“soft positivism,” as he
calls it). Hart's reasons for this shift are obscure (Green 1996). He remained clear
about how we should understand ordinary statutory interpretation, for instance,
where the legislature has directed that an applicant should have a “reasonable
time” or that a regulator may permit only a “fair price:” these grant a bounded
discretion to decide the cases on their merits. Why then does Hart -- and even more
insistently, Waluchow and Coleman -- come to regard constitutional adjudication
differently? Is there any reason to think that a constitution permitting only a “just
remedy” requires a different analysis than a statute permitting only a “fair rate?”
One might hazard the following guess. Some of these philosophers think that
constitutional law expresses the ultimate criteria of legal validity: because unjust
remedies are constitutionally invalid and void ab initio, legally speaking they
never existed (Waluchow). That being so, morality sometimes determines the
existence or content of law. If this is the underlying intuition, it is misleading,
for the rule of recognition is not to be found in constitutions. The rule of recognition
is the ultimate criterion (or set of criteria) of legal validity. If one knows what
the constitution of a country is, one knows some of its law; but one may know
what the rule of recognition is without knowing any of its laws. You may know
that acts of the Bundestag are a source of law in Germany but not be able to name
or interpret a single one of them. And constitutional law is itself subject to the
ultimate criteria of systemic validity. Whether a statute, decision or convention
is part of a country's constitution can only be determined by applying the rule of
recognition. The provisions of the 14th Amendment to the U.S. constitution, for
example, are not the rule of recognition in the U.S., for there is an intra-systemic
answer to the question why that Amendment is valid law. The U.S. constitution,
like that of all other countries, is law only because it was created in ways provided
by law (through amendment or court decision) or in ways that came to be accepted
as creating law (by constitutional convention and custom). Constitutional cases
thus raise no philosophical issue not already present in ordinary statutory
interpretation, where inclusive positivists seem content with the theory of judicial
discretion. It is, of course, open to them to adopt a unified view and treat every
explicit or implicit legal reference to morality -- in cases, statutes, constitutions,
and customs -- as establishing moral tests for the existence of law. (Although at
that point it is unclear how their view would differ from Dworkin's.) So we should
consider the wider question: why not regard as law everything referred to by law?
Exclusive positivists offer three main arguments for stopping at social sources.
The first and most important is that it captures and systematizes distinctions we
regularly make and that we have good reason to continue to make. We assign blame
and responsibility differently when we think that a bad decision was mandated by
the sources than we do when we think that it flowed from a judge's exercise
of moral or political judgement. When considering who should be appointed to the
judiciary, we are concerned not only with their acumenasjurists, but also with
their morality and politics--and we take different things as evidence of these
traits. These are deeply entrenched distinctions, and there is no reason to abandon
them.
The second reason for stopping at sources is that this is demonstrably consistent
with key features of law's role in practical reasoning. The most important
argument to this conclusion is due to Raz (1994, pp. 210-37). For a related
argument see Shapiro. For criticism see Perry, Waluchow, Coleman 2001, and
Himma.) Although law does not necessarily have legitimate authority, it lays claim
to it, and can intelligibly do so only if it is the kind of thing that could have
legitimate authority. It may fail, therefore, in certain ways only, for example, by
being unjust, pointless, or ineffective. But law cannot fail to be a candidate
authority, for it is constituted in that role by our political practices. According
to Raz, practical authorities mediate between subjects and the ultimate reasons for
which they should act. Authorities' directives should be based on such reasons,
and they are justified only when compliance with the directives makes it more
likely that people will comply with the underlying reasons that apply to them. But
they can do that only if is possible to know what the directives require
independent of appeal to those underlying reasons. Consider an example. Suppose
we agree to resolve a dispute by consensus, but that after much discussion
find ourselves in disagreement about whether some point is in fact part of the
consensus view. It will do nothing to say that we should adopt it if it is indeed
properly part of the consensus. On the other hand, we could agree to adopt it if it
were endorsed by a majority vote, for we could determine the outcome of a vote
without appeal to our ideas about what the consensus should be. Social sources
can play this mediating role between persons and ultimate reasons, and because
the nature of law is partly determined by its role in giving practical guidance,
there is a theoretical reason for stopping at source-based considerations.
Law does not necessarily satisfy the conditions by which it is appropriately assessed
(Lyons 1984, p. 63, Hart 1994, pp. 185-6). Law should be just, but it may not
be; it should promote the common good, but sometimes it doesn't; it should protect
moral rights, but it may fail miserably. This we may call the moral fallibility thesis.
The thesis is correct, but it is not the exclusive property of positivism. Aquinas
accepts it, Fuller accepts it, Finnis accepts it, and Dworkin accepts it. Only a
crude misunderstanding of ideas like Aquinas's claim that “an unjust law seems to
be no law at all” might suggest the contrary. Law may have an essentially moral
character and yet be morally deficient. Even if every law always does one kind of
justice (formal justice; justice according to law), this does not entail that it does
every kind of justice. Even if every law has a prima facie claim to be applied or
obeyed, it does not follow that it has such a claim all things considered. The
gap between these partial and conclusive judgments is all a natural law theory
needs to accommodate the fallibility thesis. It is sometimes said that positivism
gives a more secure grasp on the fallibility of law, for once we see that it is a
social construction we will be less likely to accord it inappropriate deference and
better prepared to engage in a clear-headed moral appraisal of the law. This claim
has appealed to several positivists, including Bentham and Hart. But while this
might follow from the truth of positivism, it cannot provide an argument for it. If
law has an essentially moral character then it is obfuscating, not clarifying, to
describe it as a source-based structure of governance.
(iii) the best explanation for the content of a society's laws includes reference to
the moral ideals current in that society; and
(iv) a legal system cannot survive unless it is seen to be, and thus in some measure
actually is, just. All four claims are counted by the separability thesis as
contingent connections only; they do not hold of all possible legal systems -- they
probably don't even hold of all historical legal systems. As merely contingent
truths, it is imagined that they do not affect the concept of law itself. (This is a
defective view of concept-formation, but we may ignore that for these purposes.)
If we think of the positivist thesis this way, we might interpret the difference
between exclusive and inclusive positivism in terms of the scope of the modal
operator:
In reality, however, legal positivism is not to be identified with either thesis and
each of them is false. There are many necessary “connections,” trivial and non-
trivial, between law and morality. As John Gardner notes, legal positivism takes a
position only one of them, it rejects any dependence of the existence of law on its
merits (Gardner 2001). And with respect to this dependency relation, legal
positivists are concerned with much more than the relationship between law and
morality, for in the only sense in which they insist on a separation of law and
morals they must insist also--and for the same reasons--on a separation of law and
economics.
Kelsen writes, “Just as natural and positive law govern the same subject-matter, and
relate, therefore, to the same norm-object, namely the mutual relationships of men
-- so both also have in common the universal form of this governance, namely
obligation.” (Kelsen 1928, p. 34) This is a matter of the content of all legal
systems. Where there is law there is also morality, and they regulate the same
matters by analogous techniques. Of course to say that law deals with morality's
subject matter is not to say that it does so well, and to say that all legal systems
create obligations is not to endorse the duties so created. This is broader than Hart's
“minimum content” thesis according to which there are basic rules governing
violence, property, fidelity, and kinship that any legal system must encompass if it
aims at the survival of social creatures like ourselves (Hart 1994, pp. 193-200). Hart
regards this as a matter of “natural necessity” and in that measure is willing to
qualify his endorsement of the separability thesis. But even a society that prefers
national glory or the worship of gods to survival will charge its legal system with
the same tasks its morality pursues, so the necessary content of law is not
dependent, as Hart thinks it is, on assuming certain facts about human nature and
certain aims of social existence. He fails to notice that if human nature and life
were different, then morality would be too and if law had any role in that society,
it would inevitably deal with morality's subject matter. Unlike the rules of a health
club, law has broad scope and reaches to the most important things in any society,
whatever they may be. Indeed, our most urgent political worries about law and its
claims flow from just this capacity to regulate our most vital interests, and law's
wide reach must figure in any argument about its legitimacy and its claim to
obedience.
The law tells us what we must do, not merely what it would be virtuous or
advantageous to do, and it requires us to act without regard to our individual self-
interest but in the interests of other individuals, or in the public interest more
generally (except when law itself permits otherwise). That is to say, law purports
to obligate us. But to make categorical demands that people should act in the
interests of others is to make moral demands on them. These demands may
be misguided or unjustified for law is fallible; they may be made in a spirit that
is cynical or half-hearted; but they must be the kind of thing that can be
offered as, and possibly taken as, obligation-imposing requirements. For this
reason neither a regime of “stark imperatives” (see Kramer, pp. 83-9) nor a price
system would be a system of law, for neither could even lay claim to obligate its
subjects. As with many other social institutions, what law, though its officials,
claims determines its character independent of the truth or validity of those claims.
Popes, for example, claim apostolic succession from St. Peter. The fact that they
claim this partly determines what it is to be a Pope, even if it is a fiction, and even
the Pope himself doubts its truth. The nature of law is similarly shaped by the self-
image it adopts and projects to its subjects. To make moral demands on their
compliance is to stake out a certain territory, to invite certain kinds of support
and, possibly, opposition. It is precisely because law makes these claims that
doctrines of legitimacy and political obligation take the shape and importance that
they do.
In view of the normative function of law in creating and enforcing obligations and
rights, it always makes sense to ask whether law is just, and where it is found
deficient to demand reform. Legal systems are therefore the kind of thing that
is apt for appraisal as just or unjust. This is a very significant feature of law.
Not all human practices are justice-apt. It makes no sense to ask whether a certain
fugue is just or to demand that it become so. The musical standards of fugal
excellence are preeminently internal -- a good fugue is a good example of its
genre; it should be melodic, interesting, inventive etc. -- and the further we get
from these internal standards the less secure evaluative judgments about it
become. While some formalists flirt with similar ideas about law, this is in fact
inconsistent with law's place amongst human practices. Even if law has internal
standards of merit -- virtues uniquely its own that inhere in its law-like character
-- these cannot preclude or displace its assessment on independent criteria of
justice. A fugue may be at its best when it has all the virtues of fugacity; but law
is not best when it excels in legality; law must also be just. A society may therefore
suffer not only from too little of the rule of law, but also from too much of it.
This does not presuppose that justice is the only, or even the first, virtue of a legal
system. It means that our concern for its justice as one of its virtues cannot be
sidelined by any claim of the sort that law's purpose is to be law, to its most
excellent degree. Law stands continuously exposed to demands for justification,
and that too shapes its nature and role in our lives and culture.
These three theses establish connections between law and morality that are both
necessary and highly significant. Each of them is consistent with the positivist
thesis that the existence and content of law depends on social facts, not on its
merits. Each of them contributes to an understanding of the nature of law. The
familiar idea that legal positivism insists on the separability of law and morality
is therefore significantly mistaken.
The necessary content thesis and the justice-aptitude thesis together establish that
law is not value- neutral. Although some lawyers regard this idea as a revelation
(and others as provocation) it is in fact banal. The thought that law could be value
neutral does not even rise to falsity -- it is simply incoherent. Law is a normative
system, promoting certain values and repressing others. Law is not neutral between
victim and murderer or between owner and thief. When people complain of the law's
lack of neutrality, they are in fact voicing very different aspirations, such as the
demand that it be fair, just, impartial, and so forth. A condition of law's achieving
any of these ideals is that it is not neutral in either its aims or its effects.
Positivism is however sometimes more credibly associated with the idea that legal
philosophy is or should be value-neutral. Kelsen, for example, says, “the function
of the science of law is not the evaluation of its subject, but its value-free
description” (1967, p. 68) and Hart at one point described his work as “descriptive
sociology” (1994, p. v). Since it is well known that there are convincing
arguments for the ineliminability of values in the social sciences, those who have
taken on board Quinian holisms, Kuhnian paradigms, or Foucauldian
espistemes, may suppose that positivism should be rejected a priori, as promising
something that no theory can deliver.
There are complex questions here, but some advance may be made by noticing
that Kelsen's alternatives are a false dichotomy. Legal positivism is indeed not an
“evaluation of its subject”, i.e., an evaluation of the law. And to say that the
existence of law depends on social facts does not commit one to thinking that
it is a good thing that this is so. (Nor does it preclude it: see MacCormick and
Campbell) Thus far Kelsen is on secure ground. But it does not follow that legal
philosophy therefore offers a “value-free description” of its subject. There can
be no such thing. Whatever the relation between facts and values, there is no
doubt about the relationship between descriptions and values. Every description is
value-laden. It selects and systematizes only a subset of the infinite number of facts
about its subject. To describe law as resting on customary social rules is to omit
many other truths about it including, for example, truths about its connection to the
demand for paper or silk. Our warrant for doing this must rest on the view that
the former facts are more important than the latter. In this way, all descriptions
express choices about what is salient or significant, and these in turn cannot be
understood without reference to values. So legal philosophy, even if not directly
an evaluation of its subject is nonetheless “indirectly evaluative” (Dickson,
2001). Moreover, “law” itself is an anthropocentric subject, dependent not merely
on our sensory embodiment but also, as its necessary connections to morality
show, on our moral sense and capacities. Legal kinds such as courts, decisions,
and rules will not appear in a purely physical description of the universe and
may not even appear in every social description. (This may limit the prospects for
a “naturalized” jurisprudence; though for a spirited defense of the contrary view,
see Leiter)
It may seem, however, that legal positivism at least requires a stand on the so-
called “fact-value” problem. There is no doubt that certain positivists, especially
Kelsen, believe this to be so. In reality, positivism may cohabit with a range of
views here -- value statements may be entailed by factual statements; values may
supervene on facts; values may be kind of fact. Legal positivism requires only
that it be in virtue of its facticity rather than its meritoriousness that something is
law, and that we can describe that facticity without assessing its merits. In this
regard, it is important to bear in mind that not every kind of evaluative statement
would count among the merits of a given rule; its merits are only those values that
could bear on its justification.