History of Modern Mathematics
History of Modern Mathematics
History of Modern Mathematics
Copyright laws are changing all over the world. Be sure to check the
copyright laws for your country before downloading or redistributing
this or any other Project Gutenberg eBook.
This header should be the first thing seen when viewing this Project
Gutenberg file. Please do not remove it. Do not change or edit the
header without written permission.
Please read the "legal small print," and other information about the
eBook and Project Gutenberg at the bottom of this file. Included is
important information about your specific rights and restrictions in
how the file may be used. You can also find out about how to make a
donation to Project Gutenberg, and how to get involved.
Edition: 10
Language: English
*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HISTORY OF MODERN MATHEMATICS ***
MATHEMATICAL MONOGRAPHS
No. 1
HISTORY OF MODERN
MATHEMATICS.
BY
MATHEMATICAL MONOGRAPHS.
edited by
Mansfield Merriman and Robert S. Woodward.
No. 3. DETERMINANTS.
By Laenas Gifford Weld.
The volume called Higher Mathematics, the first edition of which was pub-
lished in 1896, contained eleven chapters by eleven authors, each chapter being
independent of the others, but all supposing the reader to have at least a math-
ematical training equivalent to that given in classical and engineering colleges.
The publication of that volume is now discontinued and the chapters are issued
in separate form. In these reissues it will generally be found that the mono-
graphs are enlarged by additional articles or appendices which either amplify
the former presentation or record recent advances. This plan of publication has
been arranged in order to meet the demand of teachers and the convenience
of classes, but it is also thought that it may prove advantageous to readers in
special lines of mathematical literature.
It is the intention of the publishers and editors to add other monographs to
the series from time to time, if the call for the same seems to warrant it. Among
the topics which are under consideration are those of elliptic functions, the the-
ory of numbers, the group theory, the calculus of variations, and non-Euclidean
geometry; possibly also monographs on branches of astronomy, mechanics, and
mathematical physics may be included. It is the hope of the editors that this
form of publication may tend to promote mathematical study and research over
a wider field than that which the former volume has occupied.
December, 1905.
iii
AUTHOR’S PREFACE.
This little work was published about ten years ago as a chapter in Merriman and
Woodward’s Higher Mathematics. It was written before the numerous surveys
of the development of science in the past hundred years, which appeared at
the close of the nineteenth century, and it therefore had more reason for being
then than now, save as it can now call attention, to these later contributions.
The conditions under which it was published limited it to such a small compass
that it could do no more than present a list of the most prominent names in
connection with a few important topics. Since it is necessary to use the same
plates in this edition, simply adding a few new pages, the body of the work
remains substantially as it first appeared. The book therefore makes no claim
to being history, but stands simply as an outline of the prominent movements
in mathematics, presenting a few of the leading names, and calling attention to
some of the bibliography of the subject.
It need hardly be said that the field of mathematics is now so extensive
that no one can longer pretend to cover it, least of all the specialist in any one
department. Furthermore it takes a century or more to weigh men and their
discoveries, thus making the judgment of contemporaries often quite worthless.
In spite of these facts, however, it is hoped that these pages will serve a good
purpose by offering a point of departure to students desiring to investigate the
movements of the past hundred years. The bibliography in the foot-notes and
in Articles 19 and 20 will serve at least to open the door, and this in itself is a
sufficient excuse for a work of this nature.
Teachers College, Columbia University,
December, 1905.
iv
Contents
AUTHOR’S PREFACE. iv
1 INTRODUCTION. 1
2 THEORY OF NUMBERS. 4
4 COMPLEX NUMBERS. 8
6 THEORY OF EQUATIONS. 12
8 DETERMINANTS. 18
9 QUANTICS. 20
10 CALCULUS. 23
11 DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS. 26
12 INFINITE SERIES. 30
13 THEORY OF FUNCTIONS. 33
15 ANALYTIC GEOMETRY. 40
16 MODERN GEOMETRY. 45
17 ELEMENTARY GEOMETRY. 49
v
CONTENTS vi
18 NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY. 51
BIBLIOGRAPHY. 54
GENERAL TENDENCIES. 59
INTRODUCTION.
1
ARTICLE 1. INTRODUCTION. 2
thought to include those from which considerable extracts have been made, the necessary
condensation of these extracts making any other form of acknowledgment impossible.
ARTICLE 1. INTRODUCTION. 3
2 For a list of current mathematical journals see the Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der
Mathematik. A small but convenient list of standard periodicals is given in Carr’s Synopsis
of Pure Mathematics, p. 843; Mackay, J. S., Notice sur le journalisme mathématique en
Angleterre, Association française pour l’Avancement des Sciences, 1893, II, 303; Cajori, F.,
Teaching and History of Mathematics in the United States, pp. 94, 277; Hart, D. S., History
of American Mathematical Periodicals, The Analyst, Vol. II, p. 131.
3 For a list of such societies consult any recent number of the Philosophical Transac-
tions of Royal Society of London. Dyck, W., Einleitung zu dem für den mathematischen
Teil der deutschen Universitätsausstellung ausgegebenen Specialkatalog, Mathematical Pa-
pers Chicago Congress (New York, 1896), p. 41.
4 Klein, F., The Present State of Mathematics, Mathematical Papers of Chicago Congress
THEORY OF NUMBERS.
The Theory of Numbers,1 a favorite study among the Greeks, had its renaissance
in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries in the labors of Viete, Bachet de
Meziriac, and especially Fermat. In the eighteenth century Euler and Lagrange
contributed to the theory, and at its close the subject began to take scientific
form through the great labors of Legendre (1798), and Gauss (1801). With
the latter’s Disquisitiones Arithmeticæ(1801) may be said to begin the modern
theory of numbers. This theory separates into two branches, the one dealing
with integers, and concerning itself especially with (1) the study of primes, of
congruences, and of residues, and in particular with the law of reciprocity, and
(2) the theory of forms, and the other dealing with complex numbers.
The Theory of Primes2 has attracted many investigators during the nine-
teenth century, but the results have been detailed rather than general. Tchébi-
chef (1850) was the first to reach any valuable conclusions in the way of ascer-
taining the number of primes between two given limits. Riemann (1859) also
gave a well-known formula for the limit of the number of primes not exceeding
a given number.
The Theory of Congruences may be said to start with Gauss’s Disquisitiones.
He introduced the symbolism a ≡ b (mod c), and explored most of the field.
Tchébichef published in 1847 a work in Russian upon the subject, and in France
Serret has done much to make the theory known.
Besides summarizing the labors of his predecessors in the theory of numbers,
and adding many original and noteworthy contributions, to Legendre may be
assigned the fundamental theorem which bears his name, the Law of Reciprocity
of Quadratic Residues. This law, discovered by induction and enunciated by
Euler, was first proved by Legendre in his Théorie des Nombres (1798) for
special cases. Independently of Euler and Legendre, Gauss discovered the law
about 1795, and was the first to give a general proof. To the subject have also
1 Cantor, M., Geschichte der Mathematik, Vol. III, p. 94; Smith, H. J. S., Report on the
theory of numbers; Collected Papers, Vol. I; Stolz, O., Grössen und Zahien, Leipzig. 1891.
2 Brocard, H., Sur la fréquence et la totalité des nombres premiers; Nouvelle Correspondence
4
ARTICLE 2. THEORY OF NUMBERS. 5
IRRATIONAL AND
TRANSCENDENT
NUMBERS.
The sixteenth century saw the final acceptance of negative numbers, integral
and fractional. The seventeenth century saw decimal fractions with the modern
notation quite generally used by mathematicians. The next hundred years saw
the imaginary become a powerful tool in the hands of De Moivre, and espe-
cially of Euler. For the nineteenth century it remained to complete the theory
of complex numbers, to separate irrationals into algebraic and transcendent, to
prove the existence of transcendent numbers, and to make a scientific study of
a subject which had remained almost dormant since Euclid, the theory of irra-
tionals. The year 1872 saw the publication of the theories of Weierstrass (by
his pupil Kossak), Heine (Crelle, 74), G. Cantor (Annalen, 5), and Dedekind.
Méray had taken in 1869 the same point of departure as Heine, but the theory is
generally referred to the year 1872. Weierstrass’s method has been completely
set forth by Pincherle (1880), and Dedekind’s has received additional promi-
nence through the author’s later work (1888) and the recent indorsement by
Tannery (1894). Weierstrass, Cantor, and Heine base their theories on infinite
series, while Dedekind founds his on the idea of a cut (Schnitt) in the system
of real numbers, separating all rational numbers into two groups having certain
characteristic properties. The subject has received later contributions at the
hands of Weierstrass, Kronecker (Crelle, 101), and Méray.
Continued Fractions, closely related to irrational numbers and due to Ca-
taldi, 1613),1 received attention at the hands of Euler, and at the opening of
the nineteenth century were brought into prominence through the writings of
Lagrange. Other noteworthy contributions have been made by Druckenmüller
(1837), Kunze (1857), Lemke (1870), and Günther (1872). Ramus (1855) first
1 But see Favaro, A., Notizie storiche sulle frazioni continue dal secolo decimoterzo al deci-
6
ARTICLE 3. IRRATIONAL AND TRANSCENDENT NUMBERS. 7
connected the subject with determinants, resulting, with the subsequent contri-
butions of Heine, Möbius, and Günther, in the theory of Kettenbruchdetermi-
nanten. Dirichlet also added to the general theory, as have numerous contribu-
tors to the applications of the subject.
Transcendent Numbers2 were first distinguished from algebraic irrationals
by Kronecker. Lambert proved (1761) that π cannot be rational, and that en
(n being a rational number) is irrational, a proof, however, which left much to
be desired. Legendre (1794) completed Lambert’s proof, and showed that π is
not the square root of a rational number. Liouville (1840) showed that neither
e nor e2 can be a root of an integral quadratic equation. But the existence of
transcendent numbers was first established by Liouville (1844, 1851), the proof
being subsequently displaced by G. Cantor’s (1873). Hermite (1873) first proved
e transcendent, and Lindemann (1882), starting from Hermite’s conclusions,
showed the same for π. Lindemann’s proof was much simplified by Weierstrass
(1885), still further by Hilbert (1893), and has finally been made elementary by
Hurwitz and Gordan.
2 Klein, F., Vorträge über ausgewählte Fragen der Elementargeometrie, 1895, p. 38; Bach-
COMPLEX NUMBERS.
8
ARTICLE 4. COMPLEX NUMBERS. 9
labors of Cauchy and Abel, and especially the latter, who was the first to boldly
use complex numbers with a success that is well known.
The common terms used in the theory are chiefly due to √ the founders. Ar-
gand called cos φ + i sin φ the “direction factor”, and r = a2 + b2 the “mod-
ulus”; Cauchy (1828) called √ cos φ + i sin φ the “reduced form” (l’expression
réduite); Gauss used i for −1, introduced the term “complex number” for
a + bi, and called a2 + b2 the “norm.” The expression “direction coefficient”,
often used for cos φ + i sin φ, is due to Hankel (1867), and “absolute value,” for
“modulus,” is due to Weierstrass.
Following Cauchy and Gauss have come a number of contributors of high
rank, of whom the following may be especially mentioned: Kummer (1844),
Kronecker (1845), Scheffler (1845, 1851, 1880), Bellavitis (1835, 1852), Peacock
(1845), and De Morgan (1849). Möbius must also be mentioned for his numerous
memoirs on the geometric applications of complex numbers, and Dirichlet for
the expansion of the theory to include primes, congruences, reciprocity, etc., as
in the case of real numbers.
Other types2 have been studied, besides the familiar a + bi, in which i is
the root of x2 + 1 = 0. Thus Eisenstein has studied the type a + bj, j being a
complex root of x3 − 1 = 0. Similarly, complex types have been derived from
xk − 1 = 0 (k prime). This generalization is largely due to Kummer, to whom
is also due the theory of Ideal Numbers,3 which has recently been simplified by
Klein (1893) from the point of view of geometry. A further complex theory is
due to Galois, the basis being the imaginary roots of an irreducible congruence,
F (x) ≡ 0 (mod p, a prime). The late writers (from 1884) on the general theory
include Weierstrass, Schwarz, Dedekind, Hölder, Berloty, Poincaré, Study, and
Macfarlane.
New York Mathematical Society, Vol. I, p. 150; Study, E., Aeltere und neuere Untersuchungen
über Systeme complexer Zahlen, Mathematical Papers Chicago Congress, p. 367; bibliogra-
phy, p. 381.
3 Klein, F., Evanston Lectures, Lect. VIII.
Article 5
QUATERNIONS AND
AUSDEHNUNGSLEHRE.
10
ARTICLE 5. QUATERNIONS AND AUSDEHNUNGSLEHRE. 11
(1893). On the Continent Hankel (1867), Hoüel (1874), and Laisant (1877,
1881) have written on the theory, but it has attracted relatively little attention.
In America, Benjamin Peirce (1870) has been especially prominent in develop-
ing the quaternion theory, and Hardy (1881), Macfarlane, and Hathaway (1896)
have contributed to the subject. The difficulties have been largely in the nota-
tion. In attempting to improve this symbolism Macfarlane has aimed at showing
how a space analysis can be developed embracing algebra, trigonometry, com-
plex numbers, Grassmann’s method, and quaternions, and has considered the
general principles of vector and versor analysis, the versor being circular, elliptic
logarithmic, or hyperbolic. Other recent contributors to the algebra of vectors
are Gibbs (from 1881) and Heaviside (from 1885).
The followers of Grassmann3 have not been much more numerous than those
of Hamilton. Schlegel has been one of the chief contributors in Germany, and
Peano in Italy. In America, Hyde (Directional Calculus, 1890) has made a plea
for the Grassmann theory.4
Along lines analogous to those of Hamilton and Grassmann have been the
contributions of Scheffler. While the two former sacrificed the commutative law,
Scheffler (1846, 1851, 1880) sacrificed the distributive. This sacrifice of funda-
mental laws has led to an investigation of the field in which these laws are valid,
an investigation to which Grassmann (1872), Cayley, Ellis, Boole, Schröder
(1890-91), and Kraft (1893) have contributed. Another great contribution of
Cayley’s along similar lines is the theory of matrices (1858).
THEORY OF
EQUATIONS.
The Theory of Numerical Equations1 concerns itself first with the location of the
roots, and then with their approximation. Neither problem is new, but the first
noteworthy contribution to the former in the nineteenth century was Budan’s
(1807). Fourier’s work was undertaken at about the same time, but appeared
posthumously in 1831. All processes were, however, exceedingly cumbersome
until Sturm (1829) communicated to the French Academy the famous theorem
which bears his name and which constitutes one of the most brilliant discoveries
of algebraic analysis.
The Approximation of the Roots, once they are located, can be made by
several processes. Newton (1711), for example, gave a method which Fourier
perfected; and Lagrange (1767) discovered an ingenious way of expressing the
root as a continued fraction, a process which Vincent (1836) elaborated. It
was, however, reserved for Horner (1819) to suggest the most practical method
yet known, the one now commonly used. With Horner and Sturm this branch
practically closes. The calculation of the imaginary roots by approximation is
still an open field.
The Fundamental Theorem2 that every numerical equation has a root was
generally assumed until the latter part of the eighteenth century. D’Alembert
(1746) gave a demonstration, as did Lagrange (1772), Laplace (1795), Gauss
(1799) and Argand (1806). The general theorem that every algebraic equation
of the nth degree has exactly n roots and no more follows as a special case of
Cauchy’s proposition (1831) as to the number of roots within a given contour.
Proofs are also due to Gauss, Serret, Clifford (1876), Malet (1878), and many
1 Cayley, A., Equations, and Kelland, P., Algebra, in Encyclopædia Britannica; Favaro,
A., Notizie storico-critiche sulla costruzione delle equazioni. Modena, 1878; Cantor, M.,
Geschichte der Mathematik, Vol. III, p. 375.
2 Loria, Gino, Esame di alcune ricerche concernenti l’esistenza di radici nelle equazioni
12
ARTICLE 6. THEORY OF EQUATIONS. 13
others.
The Impossibility of Expressing the Roots of an equation as algebraic func-
tions of the coefficients when the degree exceeds 4 was anticipated by Gauss
and announced by Ruffini, and the belief in the fact became strengthened by
the failure of Lagrange’s methods for these cases. But the first strict proof is
due to Abel, whose early death cut short his labors in this and other fields.
The Quintic Equation has naturally been an object of special study. La-
grange showed that its solution depends on that of a sextic, “Lagrange’s resol-
vent sextic,” and Malfatti and Vandermonde investigated the construction of
resolvents. The resolvent sextic was somewhat simplified by Cockle and Harley
(1858-59) and by Cayley (1861), but Kronecker (1858) was the first to establish
a resolvent by which a real simplification was effected. The transformation of
the general quintic into the trinomial form x5 + ax + b = 0 by the extraction of
square and cube roots only, was first shown to be possible by Bring (1786) and
independently by Jerrard3 (1834). Hermite (1858) actually effected this reduc-
tion, by means of Tschirnhausen’s theorem, in connection with his solution by
elliptic functions.
The Modern Theory of Equations may be said to date from Abel and Galois.
The latter’s special memoir on the subject, not published until 1846, fifteen years
after his death, placed the theory on a definite base. To him is due the discovery
that to each equation corresponds a group of substitutions (the “group of the
equation”) in which are reflected its essential characteristics.4 Galois’s untimely
death left without sufficient demonstration several important propositions, a
gap which Betti (1852) has filled. Jordan, Hermite, and Kronecker were also
among the earlier ones to add to the theory. Just prior to Galois’s researches
Abel (1824), proceeding from the fact that a rational function of five letters
having less than five values cannot have more than two, showed that the roots
of a general quintic equation cannot be expressed in terms of its coefficients
by means of radicals. He then investigated special forms of quintic equations
which admit of solution by the extraction of a finite number of roots. Hermite,
Sylvester, and Brioschi have applied the invariant theory of binary forms to the
same subject.
From the point of view of the group the solution by radicals, formerly the
goal of the algebraist, now appears as a single link in a long chain of ques-
tions relative to the transformation of irrationals and to their classification.
Klein (1884) has handled the whole subject of the quintic equation in a sim-
ple manner by introducing the icosahedron equation as the normal form, and
has shown that the method can be generalized so as to embrace the whole
theory of higher equations.5 He and Gordan (from 1879) have attacked those
equations of the sixth and seventh degrees which have a Galois group of 168
substitutions, Gordan performing the reduction of the equation of the seventh
degree to the ternary problem. Klein (1888) has shown that the equation of the
3 Harley, R., A contribution of the history . . . of the general equation of the fifth degree,
SUBSTITUTIONS AND
GROUPS.
The Theories of Substitutions and Groups1 are among the most important in
the whole mathematical field, the study of groups and the search for invariants
now occupying the attention of many mathematicians. The first recognition of
the importance of the combinatory analysis occurs in the problem of forming
an mth-degree equation having for roots m of the roots of a given nth-degree
equation (m < n). For simple cases the problem goes back to Hudde (1659).
Saunderson (1740) noted that the determination of the quadratic factors of a
biquadratic expression necessarily leads to a sextic equation, and Le Sœur (1748)
and Waring (1762 to 1782) still further elaborated the idea.
Lagrange2 first undertook a scientific treatment of the theory of substitu-
tions. Prior to his time the various methods of solving lower equations had
existed rather as isolated artifices than as unified theory.3 Through the great
power of analysis possessed by Lagrange (1770, 1771) a common foundation was
discovered, and on this was built the theory of substitutions. He undertook to
examine the methods then known, and to show a priori why these succeeded
below the quintic, but otherwise failed. In his investigation he discovered the
important fact that the roots of all resolvents (rśolvantes, réduites) which he ex-
amined are rational functions of the roots of the respective equations. To study
the properties of these functions he invented a “Calcul des Combinaisons.” the
first important step towards a theory of substitutions. Mention should also be
made of the contemporary labors of Vandermonde (1770) as foreshadowing the
coming theory.
1 Netto, E., Theory of Substitutions, translated by Cole; Cayley, A., Equations, Encyclopæ-
Leipzig, 1878.
16
ARTICLE 7. SUBSTITUTIONS AND GROUPS. 17
The next great step was taken by Ruffini4 (1799). Beginning like Lagrange
with a discussion of the methods of solving lower equations, he attempted the
proof of the impossibility of solving the quintic and higher equations. While
the attempt failed, it is noteworthy in that it opens with the classification of
the various “permutations” of the coefficients, using the word to mean what
Cauchy calls a “système des substitutions conjuguées,” or simply a “système
conjugué,” and Galois calls a “group of substitutions.” Ruffini distinguishes
what are now called intransitive, transitive and imprimitive, and transitive and
primitive groups, and (1801) freely uses the group of an equation under the
name “l’assieme della permutazioni.” He also publishes a letter from Abbati to
himself, in which the group idea is prominent.
To Galois, however, the honor of establishing the theory of groups is generally
awarded. He found that if r1 , r2 , . . . rn are the n roots of an equation, there is
always a group of permutations of the r’s such that (1) every function of the
roots invariable by the substitutions of the group is rationally known, and (2),
reciprocally, every rationally determinable function of the roots is invariable by
the substitutions of the group. Galois also contributed to the theory of modular
equations and to that of elliptic functions. His first publication on the group
theory was made at the age of eighteen (1829), but his contributions attracted
little attention until the publication of his collected papers in 1846 (Liouville,
Vol. XI).
Cayley and Cauchy were among the first to appreciate the importance of the
theory, and to the latter especially are due a number of important theorems. The
popularizing of the subject is largely due to Serret, who has devoted section IV
of his algebra to the theory; to Camille Jordan, whose Traité des Substitutions
is a classic; and to Netto (1882), whose work has been translated into English
by Cole (1892). Bertrand, Hermite, Frobenius, Kronecker, and Mathieu have
added to the theory. The general problem to determine the number of groups
of n given letters still awaits solution.
But overshadowing all others in recent years in carrying on the labors of
Galois and his followers in the study of discontinuous groups stand Klein, Lie,
Poincaré, and Picard. Besides these discontinuous groups there are other classes,
one of which, that of finite continuous groups, is especially important in the
theory of differential equations. It is this class which Lie (from 1884) has studied,
creating the most important of the recent departments of mathematics, the
theory of transformation groups. Of value, too, have been the labors of Killing
on the structure of groups, Study’s application of the group theory to complex
numbers, and the work of Schur and Maurer.
4 Burkhardt, H., Die Anfänge der Gruppentheorie und Paolo Ruffini, Abhandlungen zur
Geschichte der Mathematik, VI, 1892, p. 119. Italian by E. Pascal, Brioschi’s Annali di
Matematica, 1894.
Article 8
DETERMINANTS.
The Theory of Determinants1 may be said to take its origin with Leibniz (1693),
following whom Cramer (1750) added slightly to the theory, treating the sub-
ject, as did his predecessor, wholly in relation to sets of equations. The recurrent
law was first announced by Bezout (1764). But it was Vandermonde (1771) who
first recognized determinants as independent functions. To him is due the first
connected exposition of the theory, and he may be called its formal founder.
Laplace (1772) gave the general method of expanding a determinant in terms
of its complementary minors, although Vandermonde had already given a spe-
cial case. Immediately following, Lagrange (1773) treated determinants of the
second and third order, possibly stopping here because the idea of hyperspace
was not then in vogue. Although contributing nothing to the general theory,
Lagrange was the first to apply determinants to questions foreign to elimina-
tions, and to him are due many special identities which have since been brought
under well-known theorems. During the next quarter of a century little of im-
portance was done. Hindenburg (1784) and Rothe (1800) kept the subject open,
but Gauss (1801) made the next advance. Like Lagrange, he made much use
of determinants in the theory of numbers. He introduced the word “determi-
nants” (Laplace had used “resultant”), though not in the present signification,2
but rather as applied to the discriminant of a quantic. Gauss also arrived at
the notion of reciprocal determinants, and came very near the multiplication
theorem. The next contributor of importance is Binet (1811, 1812), who for-
mally stated the theorem relating to the product of two matrices of m columns
and n rows, which for the special case of m = n reduces to the multiplication
theorem. On the same day (Nov. 30, 1812) that Binet presented his paper to
the Academy, Cauchy also presented one on the subject. In this he used the
1 Muir, T., Theory of Determinants in the Historical Order of its Development, Part I,
1890; Baltzer, R., Theorie und Anwendung der Determinanten. 1881. The writer is under
obligations to Professor Weld, who contributes Chap. II, for valuable assistance in compiling
this article.
2 “Numerum bb − ac, cuius indole proprietates formæ(a, b, c) imprimis pendere in sequen-
18
ARTICLE 8. DETERMINANTS. 19
word “determinant” in its present sense, summarized and simplified what was
then known on the subject, improved the notation, and gave the multiplication
theorem with a proof more satisfactory than Binet’s. He was the first to grasp
the subject as a whole; before him there were determinants, with him begins
their theory in its generality.
The next great contributor, and the greatest save Cauchy, was Jacobi (from
1827). With him the word “determinant” received its final acceptance. He early
used the functional determinant which Sylvester has called the “Jacobian,” and
in his famous memoirs in Crelle for 1841 he specially treats this subject, as well
as that class of alternating functions which Sylvester has called “Alternants.”
But about the time of Jacobi’s closing memoirs, Sylvester (1839) and Cayley
began their great work, a work which it is impossible to briefly summarize, but
which represents the development of the theory to the present time.
The study of special forms of determinants has been the natural result of the
completion of the general theory. Axi-symmetric determinants have been stud-
ied by Lebesgue, Hesse, and Sylvester; per-symmetric determinants by Sylvester
and Hankel; circulants by Catalan, Spottiswoode, Glaisher, and Scott; skew de-
terminants and Pfaffians, in connection with the theory of orthogonal transfor-
mation, by Cayley; continuants by Sylvester; Wronskians (so called by Muir)
by Christoffel and Frobenius; compound determinants by Sylvester, Reiss, and
Picquet; Jacobians and Hessians by Sylvester; and symmetric gauche determi-
nants by Trudi. Of the text-books on the subject Spottiswoode’s was the first.
In America, Hanus (1886) and Weld (1893) have published treatises.
Article 9
QUANTICS.
der deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, Vol. I, 1890-91; Berlin 1892, p. 97. See also the
review by Franklin in Bulletin New York Mathematical Society, Vol. III, p. 187; Biography
of Cayley, Collected Papers, VIII, p. ix, and Proceedings of Royal Society, 1895.
2 See Art. 2.
20
ARTICLE 9. QUANTICS. 21
upon which later writers have largely built, as well as most of the terminology
of the subject.
Meanwhile in Germany Eisenstein (1843) had become aware of the simplest
invariants and covariants of a cubic and biquadratic form, and Hesse and Grass-
mann had both (1844) touched upon the subject. But it was Aronhold (1849)
who first made the new theory known. He devised the symbolic method now
common in Germany, discovered the invariants of a ternary cubic and their
relations to the discriminant, and, with Cayley and Sylvester, studied those
differential equations which are satisfied by invariants and covariants of binary
quantics. His symbolic method has been carried on by Clebsch, Gordan, and
more recently by Study (1889) and Stroh (1890), in lines quite different from
those of the English school.
In France Hermite early took up the work (1851). He discovered (1854) the
law of reciprocity that to every covariant or invariant of degree ρ and order r
of a form of the mth order corresponds also a covariant or invariant of degree
m and of order r of a form of the ρth order. At the same time (1854) Brioschi
joined the movement, and his contributions have been among the most valuable.
Salmon’s Higher Plane Curves (1852) and Higher Algebra (1859) should also be
mentioned as marking an epoch in the theory.
Gordan entered the field, as a critic of Cayley, in 1868. He added greatly to
the theory, especially by his theorem on the Endlichkeit des Formensystems, the
proof for which has since been simplified. This theory of the finiteness of the
number of invariants and covariants of a binary form has since been extended
by Peano (1882), Hilbert (1884), and Mertens (1886). Hilbert (1890) succeeded
in showing the finiteness of the complete systems for forms in n variables, a
proof which Story has simplified.
Clebsch3 did more than any other to introduce into Germany the work of
Cayley and Sylvester, interpreting the projective geometry by their theory of
invariants, and correlating it with Riemann’s theory of functions. Especially
since the publication of his work on forms (1871) the subject has attracted
such scholars as Weierstrass, Kronecker, Mansion, Noether, Hilbert, Klein, Lie,
Beltrami, Burkhardt, and many others. On binary forms Faà di Bruno’s work
is well known, as is Study’s (1889) on ternary forms. De Toledo (1889) and
Elliott (1895) have published treatises on the subject.
Dublin University has also furnished a considerable corps of contributors,
among whom MacCullagh, Hamilton, Salmon, Michael and Ralph Roberts, and
Burnside may be especially mentioned. Burnside, who wrote the latter part of
Burnside and Panton’s Theory of Equations, has set forth a method of trans-
formation which is fertile in geometric interpretation and binds together binary
and certain ternary forms.
The equivalence problem of quadratic and bilinear forms has attracted the at-
tention of Weierstrass, Kronecker, Christoffel, Frobenius, Lie, and more recently
of Rosenow (Crelle, 108), Werner (1889), Killing (1890), and Scheffers (1891).
The equivalence problem of non-quadratic forms has been studied by Christof-
3 Klein’s Evanston Lectures, Lect. I.
ARTICLE 9. QUANTICS. 22
fel. Schwarz (1872), Fuchs (1875-76), Klein (1877, 1884), Brioschi (1877), and
Maschke (1887) have contributed to the theory of forms with linear transforma-
tions into themselves. Cayley (especially from 1870) and Sylvester (1877) have
worked out the methods of denumeration by means of generating functions.
Differential invariants have been studied by Sylvester, MacMahon, and Ham-
mond. Starting from the differential invariant, which Cayley has termed the
Schwarzian derivative, Sylvester (1885) has founded the theory of reciprocants,
to which MacMahon, Hammond, Leudesdorf, Elliott, Forsyth, and Halphen
have contributed. Canonical forms have been studied by Sylvester (1851), Cay-
ley, and Hermite (to whom the term “canonical form” is due), and more recently
by Rosanes (1873), Brill (1882), Gundelfinger (1883), and Hilbert (1886).
The Geometric Theory of Binary Forms may be traced to Poncelet and his
followers. But the modern treatment has its origin in connection with the the-
ory of elliptic modular functions, and dates from Dedekind’s letter to Borchardt
(Crelle, 1877). The names of Klein and Hurwitz are prominent in this connec-
tion. On the method of nets (réseaux), another geometric treatment of binary
quadratic forms Gauss (1831), Dirichlet (1850), and Poincaré (1880) have writ-
ten.
Article 10
CALCULUS.
The Differential and Integral Calculus,1 dating from Newton and Leibniz, was
quite complete in its general range at the close of the eighteenth century. Aside
from the study of first principles, to which Gauss, Cauchy, Jordan, Picard,
Méray, and those whose names are mentioned in connection with the theory
of functions, have contributed, there must be mentioned the development of
symbolic methods, the theory of definite integrals, the calculus of variations, the
theory of differential equations, and the numerous applications of the Newtonian
calculus to physical problems. Among those who have prepared noteworthy
general treatises are Cauchy (1821), Raabe (1839-47), Duhamel (1856), Sturm
(1857-59), Bertrand (1864), Serret (1868), Jordan (2d ed., 1893), and Picard
(1891-93). A recent contribution to analysis which promises to be valuable is
Oltramare’s Calcul de Généralization (1893).
Abel seems to have been the first to consider in a general way the question
as to what differential expressions can be integrated in a finite form by the
aid of ordinary functions, an investigation extended by Liouville. Cauchy early
undertook the general theory of determining definite integrals, and the subject
has been prominent during the century. Frullani’s theorem (1821), Bierens de
Haan’s work on the theory (1862) and his elaborate tables (1867), Dirichlet’s
lectures (1858) embodied in Meyer’s treatise (1871), and numerous memoirs of
Legendre, Poisson, Plana, Raabe, Sohncke, Schlömilch, Elliott, Leudesdorf, and
Kronecker are among the noteworthy contributions.
Eulerian Integrals were first studied by Euler and afterwards investigated
by Legendre, by whom they R 1 were classed as Eulerian
R ∞ integrals of the first and
second species, as follows: 0 xn−1 (1 − x)n−1 dx, 0 e−x xn−1 dx, although these
were
R ∞ −xnot the exact forms of Euler’s study. If n is integral, it follows that
0
e xn−1 dx = n!, but if n is fractional it is a transcendent function. To
1 Williamson, B., Infinitesimal Calculus, Encyclopædia Britannica, 9th edition; Cantor,
M., Geschichte der Mathematik, Vol. III, pp. 150-316; Vivanti, G., Note sur l’histoire de
l’infiniment petit, Bibliotheca Mathematica, 1894, p. 1; Mansion, P., Esquisse de l’histoire
du calcul infinitésimal, Ghent, 1887. Le deux centième anniversaire de l’invention du calcul
différentiel; Mathesis, Vol. IV, p. 163.
23
ARTICLE 10. CALCULUS. 24
it Legendre assigned the symbol Γ, and it is now called the gamma function. To
the subject Dirichlet has contributed an important theorem (Liouville, 1839),
which has been elaborated by Liouville, Catalan, Leslie Ellis, and others. On
the evaluation of Γx and log Γx Raabe (1843-44), Bauer (1859), and Gudermann
(1845) have written. Legendre’s great table appeared in 1816.
Symbolic Methods may be traced back to Taylor, and the analogy between
successive differentiation and ordinary exponentials had been observed by nu-
merous writers before the nineteenth century. Arbogast (1800) was the first,
however, to separate the symbol of operation from that of quantity in a dif-
ferential equation. François (1812) and Servois (1814) seem to have been the
first to give correct rules on the subject. Hargreave (1848) applied these meth-
ods in his memoir on differential equations, and Boole freely employed them.
Grassmann and Hankel made great use of the theory, the former in studying
equations, the latter in his theory of complex numbers.
The Calculus of Variations2 may be said to begin with a problem of Johann
Bernoulli’s (1696). It immediately occupied the attention of Jakob Bernoulli
and the Marquis de l’Hôpital, but Euler first elaborated the subject. His con-
tributions began in 1733, and his Elementa Calculi Variationum gave to the
science its name. Lagrange contributed extensively to the theory, and Legendre
(1786) laid down a method, not entirely satisfactory, for the discrimination of
maxima and minima. To this discrimination Brunacci (1810), Gauss (1829),
Poisson (1831), Ostrogradsky (1834), and Jacobi (1837) have been among the
contributors. An important general work is that of Sarrus (1842) which was
condensed and improved by Cauchy (1844). Other valuable treatises and mem-
oirs have been written by Strauch (1849), Jellett (1850), Hesse (1857), Clebsch
(1858), and Carll (1885), but perhaps the most important work of the century
is that of Weierstrass. His celebrated course on the theory is epoch-making, and
it may be asserted that he was the first to place it on a firm and unquestionable
foundation.
The Application of the Infinitesimal Calculus to problems in physics and
astronomy was contemporary with the origin of the science. All through the
eighteenth century these applications were multiplied, until at its close Laplace
and Lagrange had brought the whole range of the study of forces into the realm
of analysis. To Lagrange (1773) we owe the introduction of the theory of the
potential3 into dynamics, although the name “potential function” and the fun-
damental memoir of the subject are due to Green (1827, printed in
1828). The name “potential” is due to Gauss (1840), and the distinction
between potential and potential function to Clausius. With its development
are connected the names of Dirichlet, Riemann, Neumann, Heine, Kronecker,
Lipschitz, Christoffel, Kirchhoff, Beltrami, and many of the leading physicists
of the century.
2 Carll, L. B., Calculus of Variations, New York, 1885, Chap. V; Todhunter, I., History of
the Progress of the Calculus of Variations, London, 1861; Reiff, R., Die Anfänge der Varia-
tionsrechnung, Mathematisch-naturwissenschaftliche Mittheilungen, Tübingen, 1887, p. 90.
3 Bacharach, M., Abriss der Geschichte der Potentialtheorie, 1883. This contains an exten-
sive bibliography.
ARTICLE 10. CALCULUS. 25
It is impossible in this place to enter into the great variety of other appli-
cations of analysis to physical problems. Among them are the investigations
of Euler on vibrating chords; Sophie Germain on elastic membranes; Poisson,
Lamé, Saint-Venant, and Clebsch on the elasticity of three-dimensional bod-
ies; Fourier on heat diffusion; Fresnel on light; Maxwell, Helmholtz, and Hertz
on electricity; Hansen, Hill, and Gyldén on astronomy; Maxwell on spherical
harmonics; Lord Rayleigh on acoustics; and the contributions of Dirichlet, We-
ber, Kirchhoff, F. Neumann, Lord Kelvin, Clausius, Bjerknes, MacCullagh, and
Fuhrmann to physics in general. The labors of Helmholtz should be especially
mentioned, since he contributed to the theories of dynamics, electricity, etc.,
and brought his great analytical powers to bear on the fundamental axioms of
mechanics as well as on those of pure mathematics.
Article 11
DIFFERENTIAL
EQUATIONS.
The Theory of Differential Equations1 has been called by Lie2 the most impor-
tant of modern mathematics. The influence of geometry, physics, and astron-
omy, starting with Newton and Leibniz, and further manifested through the
Bernoullis, Riccati, and Clairaut, but chiefly through d’Alembert and Euler,
has been very marked, and especially on the theory of linear partial differen-
tial equations with constant coefficients. The first method of integrating linear
ordinary differential equations with constant coefficients is due to Euler, who
dn y dn−1 y
made the solution of his type, dx n + A1 dxn−1 + · · · + An y = 0, depend on that
Theorie der linearen Differentialgleichungen, Vol. I, 1895, an excellent historical view; review
by Mathews in Nature, Vol. LII, p. 313; Lie, S., Zur allgemeinen Theorie der partiellen
Differentialgleichungen, Berichte über die Verhandlungen der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften
zu Leipzig, 1895; Mansion, P., Theorie der partiellen Differentialgleichungen ter Ordnung,
German by Maser, Leipzig, 1892, excellent on history; Craig, T., Some of the Developments in
the Theory of Ordinary Differential Equations, 1878-1893, Bulletin New York Mathematical
Society, Vol. II, p. 119 ; Goursat, E., Leçons sur l’intégration des équations aux dérivées
partielles du premier ordre, Paris, 1895; Burkhardt, H., and Heffier, L., in Mathematical
Papers of Chicago Congress, p.13 and p. 96.
2 “In der ganzen modernen Mathematik ist die Theorie der Differentialgleichungen die
wichtigste Disciplin.”
26
ARTICLE 11. DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS. 27
of which he gave an analysis. Soon after, Cauchy (1819) gave a simpler method,
attacking the subject from the analytical standpoint, but using the Monge char-
acteristic. To him is also due the theorem, corresponding to the fundamental
theorem of algebra, that every differential equation defines a function express-
ible by means of a convergent series, a proposition more simply proved by Briot
and Bouquet, and also by Picard (1891). Jacobi (1827) also gave an analysis of
Pfaff’s method, besides developing an original one (1836) which Clebsch pub-
lished (1862). Clebsch’s own method appeared in 1866, and others are due to
Boole (1859), Korkine (1869), and A. Mayer (1872). Pfaff’s problem has been
a prominent subject of investigation, and with it are connected the names of
Natani (1859), Clebsch (1861, 1862), DuBois-Reymond (1869), Cayley, Baltzer,
Frobenius, Morera, Darboux, and Lie. The next great improvement in the the-
ory of partial differential equations of the first order is due to Lie (1872), by
whom the whole subject has been placed on a rigid foundation. Since about
1870, Darboux, Kovalevsky, Méray, Mansion, Graindorge, and Imschenetsky
have been prominent in this line. The theory of partial differential equations of
the second and higher orders, beginning with Laplace and Monge, was notably
advanced by Ampère (1840). Imschenetsky3 has summarized the contributions
to 1873, but the theory remains in an imperfect state.
The integration of partial differential equations with three or more variables
was the object of elaborate investigations by Lagrange, and his name is still
connected with certain subsidiary equations. To him and to Charpit, who did
much to develop the theory, is due one of the methods for integrating the general
equation with two variables, a method which now bears Charpit’s name.
The theory of singular solutions of ordinary and partial differential equations
has been a subject of research from the time of Leibniz, but only since the
middle of the present century has it received especial attention. A valuable
but little-known work on the subject is that of Houtain (1854). Darboux (from
1873) has been a leader in the theory, and in the geometric interpretation of
these solutions he has opened a field which has been worked by various writers,
notably Casorati and Cayley. To the latter is due (1872) the theory of singular
solutions of differential equations of the first order as at present accepted.
The primitive attempt in dealing with differential equations had in
view a reduction to quadratures. As it had been the hope of eighteenth-
century algebraists to find a method for solving the general equation of the nth
degree, so it was the hope of analysts to find a general method for integrating
any differential equation. Gauss (1799) showed, however, that the differential
equation meets its limitations very soon unless complex numbers are introduced.
Hence analysts began to substitute the study of functions, thus opening a new
and fertile field. Cauchy was the first to appreciate the importance of this
view, and the modern theory may be said to begin with him. Thereafter the
real question was to be, not whether a solution is possible by means of known
functions or their integrals, but whether a given differential equation suffices for
the definition of a function of the independent variable or variables, and if so,
3 Grunert’s Archiv für Mathematik, Vol. LIV.
ARTICLE 11. DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS. 28
question of the existence of integrals in any differential system and given a brief
summary of the history to 1895.6 The number of contributors in recent times is
very great, and includes, besides those already mentioned, the names of Brioschi,
Königsberger, Peano, Graf, Hamburger, Graindorge, Schläfli, Glaisher, Lommel,
Gilbert, Fabry, Craig, and Autonne.
6 Riquier, C., Mémoire sur l’existence des intégrales dans un système differentiel quelconque,
INFINITE SERIES.
The Theory of Infinite Series1 in its historical development has been divided
by Reiff into three periods: (1) the period of Newton and Leibniz, that of its
introduction; (2) that of Euler, the formal period; (3) the modern, that of the
scientific investigation of the validity of infinite series, a period beginning with
Gauss. This critical period begins with the publication of Gauss’s celebrated
α.(α+1).β.(β+1) 2
memoir on the series 1 + α.β 1.γ x + 1.2.γ.(γ+1) x + · · ·, in 1812. Euler had
already considered this series, but Gauss was the first to master it, and under
the name “hypergeometric series” (due to Pfaff) it has since occupied the at-
tention of Jacobi, Kummer, Schwarz, Cayley, Goursat, and numerous others.
The particular series is not so important as is the standard of criticism which
Gauss set up, embodying the simpler criteria of convergence and the questions
of remainders and the range of convergence.
Gauss’s contributions were not at once appreciated, and the next to call
attention to the subject was Cauchy (1821), who may be considered the founder
of the theory of convergence and divergence of series. He was one of the first to
insist on strict tests of convergence; he showed that if two series are convergent
their product is not necessarily so; and with him begins the discovery of effective
criteria of convergence and divergence. It should be mentioned, however, that
these terms had been introduced long before by Gregory (1668), that Euler
and Gauss had given various criteria, and that Maclaurin had anticipated a
few of Cauchy’s discoveries. Cauchy advanced the theory of power series by his
expansion of a complex function in such a form. His test for convergence is still
one of the most satisfactory when the integration involved is possible.
Abel was the next important contributor. In his memoir (1826) on the series
m(m−1) 2
1+ m 1 x+ 2! x + · · · he corrected certain of Cauchy’s conclusions, and gave
a completely scientific summation of the series for complex values of m and x.
He was emphatic against the reckless use of series, and showed the necessity of
1 Cantor, M., Geschichte der Mathematik, Vol. III, pp. 53, 71; Reiff, R., Geschichte der
unendlichen Reihen, Tübingen, 1889; Cajori, F., Bulletin New York Mathematical Society,
Vol. I, p. 184; History of Teaching of Mathematics in United States, p. 361.
30
ARTICLE 12. INFINITE SERIES. 31
Schröter, Glaisher, and Kummer. Fourier (1807) set for himself a different
problem, to expand a given function of x in terms of the sines or cosines of
multiples of x, a problem which he embodied in his Théorie analytique de la
Chaleur (1822). Euler had already given the formulas for determining the co-
efficients in the series; and Lagrange had passed over them without recognizing
their value, but Fourier was the first to assert and attempt to prove the general
theorem. Poisson (1820-23) also attacked the problem from a different stand-
point. Fourier did not, however, settle the question of convergence of his series,
a matter left for Cauchy (1826) to attempt and for Dirichlet (1829) to handle
in a thoroughly scientific manner. Dirichlet’s treatment (Crelle, 1829), while
bringing the theory of trigonometric series to a temporary conclusion, has been
the subject of criticism and improvement by Riemann (1854), Heine, Lipschitz,
Schläfli, and DuBois-Reymond. Among other prominent contributors to the
theory of trigonometric and Fourier series have been Dini, Hermite, Halphen,
Krause, Byerly and Appell.
Article 13
THEORY OF
FUNCTIONS.
The Theory of Functions1 may be said to have its first development in Newton’s
works, although algebraists had already become familiar with irrational func-
tions in considering cubic and quartic equations. Newton seems first to have
grasped the idea of such expressions in his consideration of symmetric functions
of the roots of an equation. The word was employed by Leibniz (1694), but in
connection with the Cartesian geometry. In its modern sense it seems to have
been first used by Johann Bernoulli, who distinguished between algebraic and
transcendent functions. He also used (1718) the function symbol φ. Clairaut
(1734) used Πx, Φx, ∆x, for various functions of x, a symbolism substantially
followed by d’Alembert (1747) and Euler (1753). Lagrange (1772, 1797, 1806)
laid the foundations for the general theory, giving to the symbol a broader mean-
ing, and to the symbols f , φ, F , · · ·, f 0 , φ0 , F 0 , · · · their modern signification.
Gauss contributed to the theory, especially in his proofs of the fundamental
theorem
of algebra, and discussed and gave name to the theory of “conforme Abbil-
dung,” the “orthomorphosis” of Cayley.
Making Lagrange’s work a point of departure, Cauchy so greatly developed
the theory that he is justly considered one of its founders. His memoirs ex-
tend over the period 1814-1851, and cover subjects like those of integrals with
imaginary limits, infinite series and questions of convergence, the application of
the infinitesimal calculus to the theory of complex numbers, the investigation of
1 Brill, A., and Noether, M., Die Entwickelung der Theorie der algebraischen Functionen in
alterer und neuerer Zeit, Bericht erstattet der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, Jahres-
bericht, Vol. II, pp. 107-566, Berlin, 1894; Königsberger, L., Zur Geschichte der Theorie der
elliptischen Transcendenten in den Jahren 1826-29, Leipzig, 1879; Williamson, B., Infinitesi-
mal Calculus, Encyclopædia Britannica; Schlesinger, L., Differentialgleichungen, Vol. I, 1895;
Casorati, F., Teorica delle funzioni di variabili complesse, Vol. I, 1868; Klein’s Evanston Lec-
tures. For bibliography and historical notes, see Harkness and Morley’s Theory of Functions,
1893, and Forsyth’s Theory of Functions, 1893; Eneström, G., Note historique sur les symboles
. . . Bibliotheca Mathematica, 1891, p. 89.
33
ARTICLE 13. THEORY OF FUNCTIONS. 34
the fundamental laws of mathematics, and numerous other lines which appear
in the general theory of functions as considered to-day. Originally opposed to
the movement started by Gauss, the free use of complex numbers, he finally
became, like Abel, its advocate. To him is largely due the present orientation of
mathematical research, making prominent the theory of functions, distinguish-
ing between classes of functions, and placing the whole subject upon a rigid
foundation. The historical development of the general theory now becomes so
interwoven with that of special classes of functions, and notably the elliptic and
Abelian, that economy of space requires their treatment together, and hence a
digression at this point.
The Theory of Elliptic Functions2 is usually referred for its origin to Landen’s
(1775) substitution of two elliptic arcs for a single hyperbolic arc. But Jakob
Bernoulli (1691) had suggested the idea of comparing non-congruent arcs of the
same curve, and Johann had followed up the investigation. Fagnano (1716)
had made similar studies, and both Maclaurin (1742) and d’Alembert (1746)
had come upon the borderland of elliptic functions. Euler (from 1761) had
summarized and extended the rudimentary theory, showing the necessity for a
convenient notation for elliptic arcs, and prophesying (1766) that “such signs
will afford a new sort of calculus of which I have here attempted the exposition
of the first elements.” Euler’s investigations continued until about the time of
his death (1783), and to him Legendre attributes the foundation of the theory.
Euler was probably never aware of Landen’s discovery.
It is to Legendre, however, that the theory of elliptic functions is largely
due, and on it his fame to a considerable degree depends. His earlier treatment
(1786) almost entirely substitutes a strict analytic for the geometric method.
For forty years he had the theory in hand, his labor culminating in his Traité
des Fonctions elliptiques et des Intégrales Eulériennes (1825-28). A surprise
now awaiting him is best told in his own words: “Hardly had my work seen the
light–its name could scarcely have become known to scientific foreigners,–when
I learned with equal surprise and satisfaction that two young mathematicians,
MM. Jacobi of Königsberg and Abel of Christiania, had succeeded by their own
studies in perfecting considerably the theory of elliptic functions in its highest
parts.” Abel began his contributions to the theory in 1825, and even then was
in possession of his fundamental theorem which he communicated to the Paris
Academy in 1826. This communication being so poorly transcribed was not
published in full until 1841, although the theorem was sent to Crelle (1829)
just before Abel’s early death. Abel discovered the double periodicity of elliptic
functions, and with him began the treatment of the elliptic integral as a function
of the amplitude.
Jacobi, as also Legendre and Gauss, was especially cordial in praise of the
delayed theorem of the youthful Abel. He calls it a “monumentum ære peren-
nius,” and his name “das Abel’sche Theorem” has since attached to it. The
functions of multiple periodicity to which it refers have been called Abelian
2 Enneper, A., Elliptische Funktionen, Theorie und Geschichte, Halle, 1890; Königsberger,
L., Zur Geschichte der Theorie der elliptischen Transcendenten in den Jahren 1826-29, Leipzig,
1879.
ARTICLE 13. THEORY OF FUNCTIONS. 35
Functions. Abel’s work was early proved and elucidated by Liouville and Her-
mite. Serret and Chasles in the Comptes Rendus, Weierstrass (1853), Clebsch
and Gordan in their Theorie der Abel’schen Functionen (1866), and Briot and
Bouquet in their two treatises have greatly elaborated the theory. Riemann’s3
(1857) celebrated memoir in Crelle presented the subject in such a novel form
that his treatment was slow of acceptance. He based the theory of Abelian in-
tegrals and their inverse, the Abelian functions, on the idea of the surface now
so well known by his name, and on the corresponding fundamental existence
theorems. Clebsch, starting from an algebraic curve defined by its equation,
made the subject more accessible, and generalized the theory of Abelian inte-
grals to a theory of algebraic functions with several variables, thus creating a
branch which has been developed by Noether, Picard, and Poincaré. The in-
troduction of the theory of invariants and projective geometry into the domain
of hyperelliptic and Abelian functions is an extension of Clebsch’s scheme. In
this extension, as in the general theory of Abelian functions, Klein has been a
leader. With the development of the theory of Abelian functions is connected a
long list of names, including those of Schottky, Humbert, C. Neumann, Fricke,
Königsberger, Prym, Schwarz, Painlevé, Hurwitz, Brioschi, Borchardt, Cayley,
Forsyth, and Rosenhain, besides others already mentioned.
Returning to the theory of elliptic functions, Jacobi (1827) began by adding
greatly to Legendre’s work. He created a new notation and gave name to the
“modular equations” of which he made use. Among those who have written trea-
tises upon the elliptic-function theory are Briot and Bouquet, Laurent, Halphen,
Königsberger, Hermite, Durège, and Cayley, The introduction of the subject into
the Cambridge Tripos (1873), and the fact that Cayley’s only book was devoted
to it, have tended to popularize the theory in England.
The Theory of Theta Functions was the simultaneous and independent cre-
ation of Jacobi and Abel (1828). Gauss’s notes show that he was aware of the
properties of the theta functions twenty years earlier, but he never published
his investigations. Among the leading contributors to the theory are Rosen-
hain (1846, published in 1851) and Göpel (1847), who connected the double
theta functions with the theory of Abelian functions of two variables and es-
tablished the theory of hyperelliptic functions in a manner corresponding to
the Jacobian theory of elliptic functions. Weierstrass has also developed the
theory of theta functions independently of the form of their space boundaries,
researches elaborated by Königsberger (1865) to give the addition theorem. Rie-
mann has completed the investigation of the relation between the theory of the
theta and the Abelian functions, and has raised theta functions to their present
position by making them an essential part of his theory of Abelian integrals.
H. J. S. Smith has included among his contributions to this subject the theory of
omega functions. Among the recent contributors are Krazer and Prym (1892),
and Wirtinger (1895).
Cayley was a prominent contributor to the theory of periodic functions. His
3 Klein, Evanston Lectures, p. 3; Riemann and Modern Mathematics, translated by Ziwet,
Bulletin of American Mathematical Society, Vol. I, p. 165; Burkhardt, H., Vortrag uber
Riemann, Göttingen, 1892.
ARTICLE 13. THEORY OF FUNCTIONS. 36
5 Bôcher, M., A bit of mathematical history, Bulletin of New York Mathematical Society,
PROBABILITIES AND
LEAST SQUARES.
necticut Academy, 1877, Vol. IV, p. 151, with complete bibliography; Todhunter, I., History
of the Mathematical Theory of Probability, 1865; Cantor, M., Geschichte der Mathematik,
Vol. III, p. 316.
2 Eneström, G., Review of Cantor, Bibliotheca Mathematica, 1896, p. 20.
38
ARTICLE 14. PROBABILITIES AND LEAST SQUARES. 39
ANALYTIC GEOMETRY.
The History of Geometry1 may be roughly divided into the four periods: (1) The
synthetic geometry of the Greeks, practically closing with Archimedes; (2) The
birth of analytic geometry, in which the synthetic geometry of Guldin, Desar-
gues, Kepler, and Roberval merged into the coordinate geometry of Descartes
and Fermat; (3) 1650 to 1800, characterized by the application of the calcu-
lus to geometry, and including the names of Newton, Leibnitz, the Bernoullis,
Clairaut, Maclaurin, Euler, and Lagrange, each an analyst rather than a ge-
ometer; (4) The nineteenth century, the renaissance of pure geometry, charac-
terized by the descriptive geometry of Monge, the modern synthetic of Poncelet,
Steiner, von Staudt, and Cremona, the modern analytic founded by Plücker, the
non-Euclidean hypothesis of Lobachevsky and Bolyai, and the more elementary
geometry of the triangle founded by Lemoine. It is quite impossible to draw the
line between the analytic and the synthetic geometry of the nineteenth century,
in their historical development, and Arts. 15 and 16 should be read together.
The Analytic Geometry which Descartes gave to the world in 1637 was con-
fined to plane curves, and the various important properties common to all al-
gebraic curves were soon discovered. To the theory Newton contributed three
celebrated theorems on the Enumeratio linearum tertii ordinis2 (1706), while
others are due to Cotes (1722), Maclaurin, and Waring (1762, 1772, etc.). The
scientific foundations of the theory of plane curves may be ascribed, however,
to Euler (1748) and Cramer (1750). Euler distinguished between algebraic and
transcendent curves, and attempted a classification of the former. Cramer is
1 Loria,G., Il passato e il presente delle principali teorie geometriche. Memorie Accademia
Torino, 1887; translated into German by F. Schutte under the title Die hauptsächlichsten
Theorien der Geometrie in ihrer früheren und heutigen Entwickelung, Leipzig, 1888; Chasles,
M., Aperçu historique sur l’origine et le développement des méthodes en Géométrie, 1889;
Chasles, M., Rapport sur les Progrès de la Géométrie, Paris, 1870; Cayley, A., Curves, Ency-
clopædia Britannica; Klein, F., Evanston Lectures on Mathematics, New York, 1894; A. V.
Braunmühl, Historische Studie über die organische Erzeugung ebener Curven, Dyck’s Katalog
mathematischer Modelle, 1892.
2 Ball, W. W. R., On Newton’s classification of cubic curves. Transactions of London
40
ARTICLE 15. ANALYTIC GEOMETRY. 41
MODERN GEOMETRY.
45
ARTICLE 16. MODERN GEOMETRY. 46
for the first time in its general form in Carnot’s Géométrie de Position (1803),
and supplemented in his Théorie des Transversales (1806). In these works he
introduced negative magnitudes, the general quadrilateral and quadrangle, and
numerous other generalizations of value to the elementary geometry of to-day.
But although Carnot’s work was important and many details are now common-
place, neither the name of the theory nor the method employed have endured.
The present Geometry of Position (Geometrie der Lage) has little in common
with Carnot’s Géométrie de Position.
Projective Geometry had its origin somewhat later than the period of Monge
and Carnot. Newton had discovered that all curves of the third order can be
derived by central projection from five fundamental types. But in spite of this
fact the theory attracted so little attention for over a century that its origin is
generally ascribed to Poncelet. A prisoner in the Russian campaign, confined at
Saratoff on the Volga (1812-14), “privé,” as he says, “de toute espèce de livres et
de secours, surtout distrait par les malheurs de ma patrie et les miens propres,”
he still had the vigor of spirit and the leisure to conceive the great work which
he published (1822) eight years later. In this work was first made prominent the
power of central projection in demonstration and the power of the principle of
continuity in research. His leading idea was the study of projective properties,
and as a foundation principle he introduced the anharmonic ratio, a concept,
however, which dates back to Pappos and which Desargues (1639) had also
used. Möbius, following Poncelet, made much use of the anharmonic ratio in his
Barycentrische Calcül (1827), but under the name “Doppelschnitt-Verhältniss”
(ratio bisectionalis), a term now in common use under Steiner’s abbreviated
form “Doppelverhältniss.” The name “anharmonic ratio” or “function” (rapport
anharmonique, or fonction anharmonique) is due to Chasles, and “cross-ratio”
was coined by Clifford. The anharmonic point and line properties of conics
have been further elaborated by Brianchon, Chasles, Steiner, and von Staudt.
To Poncelet is also due the theory of “figures homologiques,” the perspective axis
and perspective center (called by Chasles the axis and center of homology), an
extension of Carnot’s theory of transversals, and the “cordes idéales” of conics
which Plücker applied to curves of all orders, He also discovered what Salmon
has called “the circular points at infinity,” thus completing and establishing the
first great principle of modern geometry, the principle of continuity. Brianchon
(1806), through his application of Desargues’s theory of polars, completed the
foundation which Monge had begun for Poncelet’s (1829) theory of reciprocal
polars.
Among the most prominent geometers contemporary with Poncelet was Ger-
gonne, who with more propriety might be ranked as an analytic geometer. He
first (1813) used the term “polar” in its modern geometric sense, although Ser-
vois (1811) had used the expression “pole.” He was also the first (1825-26) to
grasp the idea that the parallelism which Maurolycus, Snell, and Viete had no-
ticed is a fundamental principle. This principle he stated and to it he gave the
name which it now bears, the Principle of Duality, the most important, after
that of continuity, in modern geometry. This principle of geometric recipro-
cation, the discovery of which was also claimed by Poncelet, has been greatly
ARTICLE 16. MODERN GEOMETRY. 47
elaborated and has found its way into modern algebra and elementary geome-
try, and has recently been extended to mechanics by Genese. Gergonne was the
first to use the word “class” in describing a curve, explicitly defining class and
degree (order) and showing the duality between the two. He and Chasles were
among the first to study scientifically surfaces of higher order.
Steiner (1832) gave the first complete discussion of the projective relations
between rows, pencils, etc., and laid the foundation for the subsequent devel-
opment of pure geometry. He practically closed the theory of conic sections,
of the corresponding figures in three-dimensional space and of surfaces of the
second order, and hence with him opens the period of special study of curves
and surfaces of higher order. His treatment of duality and his application of the
theory of projective pencils to the generation of conics are masterpieces. The
theory of polars of a point in regard to a curve had been studied by Bobillier
and by Grassmann, but Steiner (1848) showed that this theory can serve as the
foundation for the study of plane curves independently of the use of coordinates,
and introduced those noteworthy curves covariant to a given curve which now
bear the names of himself, Hesse, and Cayley. This whole subject has been ex-
tended by Grassmann, Chasles, Cremona, and Jonquières. Steiner was the first
to make prominent (1832) an example of correspondence of a more complicated
nature than that of Poncelet, Möbius, Magnus, and Chasles. His contributions,
and those of Gudermann, to the geometry of the sphere were also noteworthy.
While Möbius, Plücker, and Steiner were at work in Germany, Chasles was
closing the geometric era opened in France by Monge. His Aperçu Historique
(1837) is a classic, and did for France what Salmon’s works did for algebra
and geometry in England, popularizing the researches of earlier writers and
contributing both to the theory and the nomenclature of the subject. To him
is due the name “homographic” and the complete exposition of the principle
as applied to plane and solid figures, a subject which has received attention in
England at the hands of Salmon, Townsend, and H. J. S. Smith.
Von Staudt began his labors after Plücker, Steiner, and Chasles had made
their greatest contributions, but in spite of this seeming disadvantage he sur-
passed them all. Joining the Steiner school, as opposed to that of Plücker,
he became the greatest exponent of pure synthetic geometry of modern times.
He set forth (1847, 1856-60) a complete, pure geometric system in which met-
rical geometry finds no place. Projective properties foreign to measurements
are established independently of number relations, number being drawn from
geometry instead of conversely, and imaginary elements being systematically
introduced from the geometric side. A projective geometry based on the group
containing all the real projective and dualistic transformations, is developed,
imaginary transformations being also introduced. Largely through his influ-
ence pure geometry again became a fruitful field. Since his time the distinction
between the metrical and projective theories has been to a great extent oblit-
erated,3 the metrical properties being considered as projective relations to a
3 Klein, F., Erlangen Programme of 1872, Haskell’s translation, Bulletin of New York Math-
fundamental configuration, the circle at infinity common for all spheres. Unfor-
tunately von Staudt wrote in an unattractive style, and to Reye is due much of
the popularity which now attends the subject.
Cremona began his publications in 1862. His elementary work on projective
geometry (1875) in Leudesdorf’s translation is familiar to English readers. His
contributions to the theory of geometric transformations are valuable, as also
his works on plane curves, surfaces, etc.
In England Mulcahy, but especially Townsend (1863), and Hirst, a pupil of
Steiner’s, opened the subject of modern geometry. Clifford did much to make
known the German theories, besides himself contributing to the study of polars
and the general theory of curves.
Article 17
ELEMENTARY
GEOMETRY.
Trigonometry and Elementary Geometry have also been affected by the general
mathematical spirit of the century. In trigonometry the general substitution
of ratios for lines in the definitions of functions has simplified the treatment,
and certain formulas have been improved and others added.1 The convergence
of trigonometric series, the introduction of the Fourier series, and the free use
of the imaginary have already been mentioned. The definition of the sine and
cosine by series, and the systematic development of the theory on this basis,
have been set forth by Cauchy (1821), Lobachevsky (1833), and others. The
hyperbolic trigonometry,2 already founded by Mayer and Lambert, has been
popularized and further developed by Gudermann (1830), Hoüel, and Laisant
(1871), and projective formulas and generalized figures have been introduced,
notably by Gudermann, Möbius, Poncelet, and Steiner. Recently Study has
investigated the formulas of spherical trigonometry from the standpoint of the
modern theory of functions and theory of groups, and Macfarlane has general-
ized the fundamental theorem of trigonometry for three-dimensional space.
Elementary Geometry has been even more affected. Among the many con-
tributions to the theory may be mentioned the following: That of Möbius on
the opposite senses of lines, angles, surfaces, and solids; the principle of duality
as given by Gergonne and Poncelet; the contributions of De Morgan to the logic
of the subject; the theory of transversals as worked out by Monge, Brianchon,
Servois, Carnot, Chasles, and others; the theory of the radical axis, a property
discovered by the Arabs, but introduced as a definite concept by Gaultier (1813)
and used by Steiner under the name of “line of equal power”; the researches of
Gauss concerning inscriptible polygons, adding the 17- and 257-gon to the list
1 Todhunter, I., History of certain formulas of spherical trigonometry, Philosophical Maga-
zine, 1873.
2 Gunther, S., Die Lehre von den gewöhnlichen und verallgemeinerten Hyperbelfunktionen,
49
ARTICLE 17. ELEMENTARY GEOMETRY. 50
below the 1000-gon; the theory of stellar polyhedra as worked out by Cauchy,
Jacobi, Bertrand, Cayley, Möbius, Wiener, Hess, Hersel, and others, so that
a whole series of bodies have been added to the four Kepler-Poinsot regular
solids; and the researches of Muir on stellar polygons. These and many other
improvements now find more or less place in the text-books of the day.
To these must be added the recent Geometry of the Triangle, now a promi-
nent chapter in elementary mathematics. Crelle (1816) made some investiga-
tions in this line, Feuerbach (1822) soon after discovered the properties of the
Nine-Point Circle, and Steiner also came across some of the properties of the
triangle, but none of these followed up the investigation. Lemoine3 (1873) was
the first to take up the subject in a systematic way, and he has contributed
extensively to its development. His theory of “transformation continue” and his
“géométrographie” should also be mentioned. Brocard’s contributions to the
geometry of the triangle began in 1877. Other prominent writers have been
Tucker, Neuberg, Vigarié, Emmerich, M’Cay, Longchamps, and H. M. Taylor.
The theory is also greatly indebted to Miller’s work in The Educational Times,
and to Hoffmann’s Zeitschrift.
The study of linkages was opened by Peaucellier (1864), who gave the first
theoretically exact method for drawing a straight line. Kempe and Sylvester
have elaborated the subject.
In recent years the ancient problems of trisecting an angle, doubling the cube,
and squaring the circle have all been settled by the proof of their insolubility
through the use of compasses and straight edge.4
3 Smith, D. E., Biography of Lemoine, American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. III, p. 29;
NON-EUCLIDEAN
GEOMETRY.
51
ARTICLE 18. NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY. 52
and on Johann Bolyai through the father Wolfgang, who was a fellow student
of Gauss’s. But it is now certain that Gauss can lay no claim to priority of
discovery, although the influence of himself and of Kant, in a general way, must
have had its effect.
Bartels went to Kasan in 1807, and Lobachevsky was his pupil. The latter’s
lecture notes show that Bartels never mentioned the subject of the fifth postulate
to him, so that his investigations, begun even before 1823, were made on his
own motion and his results were wholly original. Early in 1826 he sent forth
the principles of his famous doctrine of parallels, based on the assumption that
through a given point more than one line can be drawn which shall never meet
a given line coplanar with it. The theory was published in full in 1829-30, and
he contributed to the subject, as well as to other branches of mathematics, until
his death.
Johann Bolyai received through his father, Wolfgang, some of the inspira-
tion to original research which the latter had received from Gauss. When only
twenty-one he discovered, at about the same time as Lobachevsky, the principles
of non-Euclidean geometry, and refers to them in a letter of November, 1823.
They were committed to writing in 1825 and published in 1832. Gauss asserts
in his correspondence with Schumacher (1831-32) that he had brought out a
theory along the same lines as Lobachevsky and Bolyai, but the publication of
their works seems to have put an end to his investigations. Schweikart was also
an independent discoverer of the non-Euclidean geometry, as his recently recov-
ered letters show, but he never published anything on the subject, his work on
the theory of parallels (1807), like that of his nephew Taurinus (1825), showing
no trace of the Lobachevsky-Bolyai idea.
The hypothesis was slowly accepted by the mathematical world. Indeed it
was about forty years after its publication that it began to attract any consid-
erable attention. Hoüel (1866) and Flye St. Marie (1871) in France, Riemann
(1868), Helmholtz (1868), Frischauf (1872), and Baltzer (1877) in Germany,
Beltrami (1872) in Italy, de Tilly (1879) in Belgium, Clifford in England, and
Halsted (1878) in America, have been among the most active in making the
subject popular. Since 1880 the theory may be said to have become generally
understood and accepted as legitimate.3
Of all these contributions the most noteworthy from the scientific standpoint
is that of Riemann. In his Habilitationsschrift (1854) he applied the methods of
analytic geometry to the theory, and suggested a surface of negative curvature,
which Beltrami calls “pseudo-spherical,” thus leaving Euclid’s geometry on a
surface of zero curvature midway between his own and Lobachevsky’s. He thus
set forth three kinds of geometry, Bolyai having noted only two. These Klein
(1871) has called the elliptic (Riemann’s), parabolic (Euclid’s), and hyperbolic
(Lobachevsky’s).
Starting from this broader point of view4 there have contributed to the
subject many of the leading mathematicians of the last quarter of a century,
3 For an excellent summary of the results of the hypothesis, see an article by McClintock,
The Non-Euclidian Geometry, Bulletin of New York Mathematical Society, Vol. II, p. 1.
4 Klein. Evanston Lectures. Lect. IX.
ARTICLE 18. NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY. 53
including, besides those already named, Cayley, Lie, Klein, Newcomb, Pasch,
C. S. Peirce, Killing, Fiedler, Mansion, and McClintock. Cayley’s contribution
of his “metrical geometry” was not at once seen to be identical with that of
Lobachevsky and Bolyai. It remained for Klein (1871) to show this, thus sim-
plifying Cayley’s treatment and adding one of the most important results of
the entire theory. Cayley’s metrical formulas are, when the Absolute is real,
identical with those of the hyperbolic geometry; when it is imaginary, with the
elliptic; the limiting case between the two gives the parabolic (Euclidean) geom-
etry. The question raised by Cayley’s memoir as to how far projective geometry
can be defined in terms of space without the introduction of distance had al-
ready been discussed by von Staudt (1857) and has since been treated by Klein
(1873) and by Lindemann (1876).
BIBLIOGRAPHY.
The following are a few of the general works on the history of mathematics in
the nineteenth century, not already mentioned in the foot-notes. For a com-
plete bibliography of recent works the reader should consult the Jahrbuch über
die Fortschritte der Mathematik, the Bibliotheca Mathematica, or the Revue
Semestrielle, mentioned below.
54
BIBLIOGRAPHY. 55
expectation was duly fulfilled, and numerous addresses and memoirs testify to
the interest recently awakened in the subject. Among the contributions to the
general history of modern mathematics may be cited the following:
Pierpont, J., St. Louis address, 1904. Bulletin of the American Mathe-
matical Society (N. S.), Vol. IX, p. 136. An excellent survey of the century’s
progress in pure mathematics.
Günther, S., Die Mathematik im neunzehnten Jahrhundert. Hoffmann’s
Zeitschrift, Vol. XXXII, p. 227.
Adhémar, R. d’, L’œuvre mathématique du XIXe siècle. Revue des questions
scientifiques, Louvain Vol. XX (2), p. 177 (1901).
Picard, E., Sur le développement, depuis un siècle, de quelques théories fon-
damentales dans l’analyse mathématique. Conférences faite à Clark University
(Paris, 1900).
Lampe, E., Die reine Mathematik in den Jahren 1884-1899 (Berlin, 1900).
Mention should also be made of the fact that the Bibliotheca Mathematica,
a journal devoted to the history of the mathematical sciences, began its third
series in 1900. It remains under the able editorship of G. Eneström, and in its
new series it appears in much enlarged form. It contains numerous articles on
the history of modern mathematics, with a complete current bibliography of
this field.
Besides direct contributions to the history of the subject, and historical and
bibliographical notes, several important works have recently appeared which are
historical in the best sense, although written from the mathematical standpoint.
Of these there are three that deserve special mention:
The opening of the nineteenth century was, as we have seen, a period of pro-
found introspection following a period of somewhat careless use of the material
accumulated in the seventeenth century. The mathematical world sought to
orientate itself, to examine the foundations of its knowledge, and to critically
examine every step in its several theories. It then took up the line of discovery
once more, less recklessly than before, but still with thoughts directed primarily
in the direction of invention. At the close of the century there came again a
period of introspection, and one of the recent tendencies is towards a renewed
study of foundation principles. In England one of the leaders in this move-
ment is Russell, who has studied the foundations of geometry (1897) and of
mathematics in general (1903). In America the fundamental conceptions and
methods of mathematics have been considered by Bôcher in his St. Louis ad-
dress in 1904,5 and the question of a series of irreducible postulates has been
studied by Huntington. In Italy, Padoa and Bureli-Forti have studied the funda-
mental postulates of algebra, and Pieri those of geometry. In Germany, Hilbert
has probably given the most attention to the foundation principles of geometry
(1899), and more recently he has investigated the compatibility of the arith-
metical axioms (1900). In France, Poincaré has considered the rôle of intuition
and of logic in mathematics,6 and in every country the foundation principles
have been made the object of careful investigation.
As an instance of the orientation already mentioned, the noteworthy ad-
dress of Hilbert at Paris in 19007 stands out prominently. This address reviews
the field of pure mathematics and sets forth several of the greatest questions de-
manding investigation at the present time. In the particular line of geometry the
memoir which Segré wrote in 1891, on the tendencies in geometric investigation,
has recently been revised and brought up to date.8
There is also seen at the present time, as never before, a tendency to coöper-
ate, to exchange views, and to internationalize mathematics. The first interna-
tional congress of mathematicians was held at Zurich in 1897, the second one
5 Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society (N. S.), Vol. XI, p. 115.
6 Compte rendu du deuxième congrès international des mathématiciens tenu à Paris, 1900.
Paris, 1902, p. 115.
7 Göttinger Nachrichten, 1900, p. 253; Archiv der Mathematik und Physik, 1901, pp. 44,
59
GENERAL TENDENCIES. 60
at Paris in 1900, and the third at Heidelberg in 1904. The first international
congress of philosophy was held at Paris in 1900, the third section being devoted
to logic and the history of the sciences (on this occasion chiefly mathematics),
and the second congress was held at Geneva in 1904. There was also held an
international congress of historic sciences at Rome in 1903, an international
committee on the organization of a congress on the history of sciences being at
that time formed. The result of such gatherings has been an exchange of views
in a manner never before possible, supplementing in an inspiring way the older
form of international communication through published papers.
In the United States there has been shown a similar tendency to exchange
opinions and to impart verbal information as to recent discoveries. The Amer-
ican Mathematical Society, founded in 1894,9 has doubled its membership in
the past decade,10 and has increased its average of annual papers from 30 to
150. It has also established two sections, one at Chicago (1897) and one at San
Francisco (1902). The activity of its members and the quality of papers pre-
pared has led to the publication of the Transactions, beginning with 1900. In
order that its members may be conversant with the lines of investigation in the
various mathematical centers, the society publishes in its Bulletin the courses in
advanced mathematics offered in many of the leading universities of the world.
Partly as a result of this activity, and partly because of the large number of
American students who have recently studied abroad, a remarkable change is
at present passing over the mathematical work done in the universities and col-
leges of this country. Courses that a short time ago were offered in only a few of
our leading universities are now not uncommon in institutions of college rank.
They are often given by men who have taken advanced degrees in mathematics,
at Göttingen, Berlin, Paris, or other leading universities abroad, and they are
awakening a great interest in the modern field. A recent investigation (1903)
showed that 67 students in ten American institutions were taking courses in
the theory of functions, 11 in the theory of elliptic functions, 94 in projective
geometry, 26 in the theory of invariants, 45 in the theory of groups, and 46 in
the modern advanced theory of equations, courses which only a few years ago
were rarely given in this country. A similar change is seen in other countries,
notably in England and Italy, where courses that a few years ago were offered
only in Paris or in Germany are now within the reach of university students at
home. The interest at present manifested by American scholars is illustrated by
the fact that only four countries (Germany, Russia, Austria, and France) had
more representatives than the United States, among the 336 regular members
at the third international mathematical congress at Heidelberg in 1904.
The activity displayed at the present time in putting the work of the masters
into usable form, so as to define clear points of departure along the several lines
of research, is seen in the large number of collected works published or in course
of publication in the last decade. These works have usually been published un-
der governmental patronage, often by some learned society, and always under
9 It was founded as the New York Mathematical Society six years earlier, in 1888.
10 It is now, in 1905, approximately 500.
GENERAL TENDENCIES. 61
the editorship of some recognized authority. They include the works of Galileo,
Fermat, Descartes, Huygens, Laplace, Gauss, Galois, Cauchy, Hesse, Plücker,
Grassmann, Dirichlet, Laguerre, Kronecker, Fuchs, Weierstrass, Stokes, Tait,
and various other leaders in mathematics. It is only natural to expect a number
of other sets of collected works in the near future, for not only is there the remote
past to draw upon, but the death roll of the last decade has been a large one.
The following is only a partial list of eminent mathematicians who have recently
died, and whose collected works have been or are in the course of being pub-
lished, or may be deemed worthy of publication in the future: Cayley (1895),
Neumann (1895), Tisserand (1896), Brioschi (1897), Sylvester (1897), Weier-
strass (1897), Lie (1899), Beltrami (1900), Bertrand (1900), Tait (1901), Her-
mite (1901), Fuchs (1902), Gibbs (1903), Cremona (1903), and Salmon (1904),
besides such writers as Frost (1898), Hoppe (1900), Craig (1900), Schlömilch
(1901), Everett on the side of mathematical physics (1904), and Paul Tannery,
the best of the modern French historians of mathematics (1904).11
It is, of course, impossible to detect with any certainty the present ten-
dencies in mathematics. Judging, however, by the number and nature of the
published papers and works of the past few years, it is reasonable to expect a
great development in all lines, especially in such modern branches as the the-
ory of groups, theory of functions, theory of invariants, higher geometry, and
differential equations. If we may judge from the works in applied mathematics
which have recently appeared, we are entering upon an era similar to that in
which Laplace labored, an era in which all these modern theories of mathemat-
ics shall find application in the study of physical problems, including those that
relate to the latest discoveries. The profound study of applied mathematics in
France and England, the advanced work in discovery in pure mathematics in
Germany and France, and the search for the logical bases for the science that
has distinguished Italy as well as Germany, are all destined to affect the char-
acter of the international mathematics of the immediate future. Probably no
single influence will be more prominent in the internationalizing process than
the tendency of the younger generation of American mathematicians to study
in England, France, Germany, and Italy, and to assimilate the best that each of
these countries has to offer to the world.
11 For students wishing to investigate the work of mathematicians who died in the last two
We are now trying to release all our eBooks one year in advance
of the official release dates, leaving time for better editing.
Please be encouraged to tell us about any error or corrections,
even years after the official publication date.
Please note neither this listing nor its contents are final til
midnight of the last day of the month of any such announcement.
The official release date of all Project Gutenberg eBooks is at
Midnight, Central Time, of the last day of the stated month. A
preliminary version may often be posted for suggestion, comment
and editing by those who wish to do so.
http://www.ibiblio.org/gutenberg/etext05 or
ftp://ftp.ibiblio.org/pub/docs/books/gutenberg/etext05
Or /etext02, 01, 00, 99, 98, 97, 96, 95, 94, 93, 92, 92, 91 or 90
Just search by the first five letters of the filename you want,
as it appears in our Newsletters.
We produce about two million dollars for each hour we work. The
time it takes us, a rather conservative estimate, is fifty hours
to get any eBook selected, entered, proofread, edited, copyright
searched and analyzed, the copyright letters written, etc. Our
projected audience is one hundred million readers. If the value
per text is nominally estimated at one dollar then we produce $2
million dollars per hour in 2002 as we release over 100 new text
files per month: 1240 more eBooks in 2001 for a total of 4000+
We are already on our way to trying for 2000 more eBooks in 2002
If they reach just 1-2\% of the world’s population then the total
will reach over half a trillion eBooks given away by year’s end.
1 1971 July
10 1991 January
100 1994 January
1000 1997 August
1500 1998 October
2000 1999 December
2500 2000 December
3000 2001 November
4000 2001 October/November
6000 2002 December*
PROJECT GUTENBERG ”SMALL PRINT”
We have filed in all 50 states now, but these are the only ones
that have responded.
As the requirements for other states are met, additions to this list
will be made and fund raising will begin in the additional states.
Please feel free to ask to check the status of your state.
http://www.gutenberg.net/donation.html
***
(Three Pages)
INDEMNITY
You will indemnify and hold Michael Hart, the Foundation,
and its trustees and agents, and any volunteers associated
with the production and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm
texts harmless, from all liability, cost and expense, including
legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the
following that you do or cause: [1] distribution of this eBook,
[2] alteration, modification, or addition to the eBook,
or [3] any Defect.
[1] Only give exact copies of it. Among other things, this
requires that you do not remove, alter or modify the
eBook or this "small print!" statement. You may however,
if you wish, distribute this eBook in machine readable
binary, compressed, mark-up, or proprietary form,
including any form resulting from conversion by word
processing or hypertext software, but only so long as
*EITHER*:
WHAT IF YOU *WANT* TO SEND MONEY EVEN IF YOU DON’T HAVE TO?
Project Gutenberg is dedicated to increasing the number of
public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed
in machine readable form.