Florida State University Department of Philosophy Social Theory and Practice
Florida State University Department of Philosophy Social Theory and Practice
Florida State University Department of Philosophy Social Theory and Practice
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Concept of Alienation and Feminism
Sandra Bartky has pointed out that many socialist feminists do not
agree on what their subject matter should be called. In some part this
is due to the differing degrees of allegiance these writers exhibit
towards Marx and Marxist interpretation of categories that socialist
feminists find relevant to women's experience. Bartky describes
some of the shortcomings of Marxist orthodoxy these feminist
theorists have analyzed.1
In addition to these, Professor Bartky finds Marx's theory of
alienation inadequate to express women's special alienation which
shows itself in the male domination of culture, in sexual suppres
sion, sexual objectification, and estrangement from bodily poten
tial.2 The fragmentation of the person and prohibition against ex
pressing human creativity that these forms of estrangement express
present a paradigmatic case of Marxian alienation. Using body parts
and functions to represent and evaluate women is parallel to repre
senting, by the products and activities of coerced production, the
value of laborers. Women, as genitally sexualized bodies, and
workers, as machines for production, are equally prevented from
realizing their full humanity (Marx's "species-being"), from pro
ducing freely and reciprocally, for their own needs.
Having argued for the condition of women in contemporary
society as a special example of alienation, Bartky considers
whether, in fact, women's alienation counts when many women
apparently find their lot satisfying. Women, unlike workers, seem to
love their chains. In order to complete the account of alienation
begun with Marx, Bartky turns to Simone de Beauvoir's existential
analysis of alienation for a credible account of the feminine es
trangement that displays itself as chain-worship.
Copyright © 1982 by Social Theory and Practice Vbl 8. No. 2 (Summer 1982)
155
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
156 Social Theory and Practice
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Alienation and Feminism 157
making us like the other natural species who produce only for
immediate need. Estranged labor reduces us to animals because it
robs us of free access to nature. When we are reduced to seeing our
activity as merely the means of staying alive and not as the source
that produces more life, we are alienated. So, though Marx says,
"That man's physical and spiritual life is linked to nature means
simply that nature is linked to itself, for man is a part of nature,"9
his emphasis is on the fact that nature helps us realize our nature.
Estrangement from nature is a component of human alienation,
and a theory of feminine alienation would be incomplete without an
account of it. The analysis of the character of human alienation from
nature needs to broadened, made more comprehensive. The discus
sion of alienation from nature benefits from being set in the context
of what is not a product nor an object of our labor, as well as from
what is. (I think it is the latter that Marx considered.) The tendency
has been to collapse these two categories into one and conceive of
all of nature as at our disposal, as designed for human manipulation.
The quality of air and water and soil that has resulted pays tribute to
our efforts. In becoming focused on production, we (European
based cultures) have lost the power of our peripheral vision10 to
encompass the setting in which production takes place. Many resi
dents of urban centers find the open country dangerous, threatening,
and alien, but distrust of uncultivated, unsettled places pre-dates
industrial society; it appears, for example, in our conception of
"wilderness," a description of feeling vulnerable in relation to
untamed natural spaces. Such feelings have been part of our con
sciousness since Roman times.11
As we are alienated from nature, so are we alienated from our
animal natures. The forces of capital and patriarchy, puritanism, and
a kind of consumer-hedonism (as well as the dualistic metaphysical
heritage that Bartky referred to) combine to estrange us from bodily
well-being. We generally regard our "work" as what we get paid
for, what we do in order to survive. Since our work does not involve
all our physiological, intellectual, and artistic capacities, our powers
are diminished.
Since this is the case, for women (as well as men) to seek to
cultivate physical development is not narcissistic in character, but
health-producing and thereby freedom-producing. A being with
greater physical strength, flexibility, and range of movement lives a
qualitatively different life, with a broader range of possible choices,
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
158 Social Theory and Practice
than a being with less strength and agility. To move to gain or regain
physical power is integrating, anti-alienating. It is to move away
from over-indulgence in certain life-threatening goods and services.
What seems to have happened in contemporary society is that alien
social forces have been developing the means to take over health
affirming motives and make them serve the needs of patriarchal
capitalism. Physical fitness is made over into something to be
consumed, into products and services and images without which,
we are told, our goal cannot be reached. The capitalist patriarchs
have many of the eggs in their basket. We are used to taking the
consumer pathway to reach our ends; for them, it is merely a matter
of changing the products we turn out. The fashion-beauty complex
is partner to the military-industrial complex in this business venture.
Our desire for physical freedom is channeled towards serving the
ends of the enemy. Our quest for physical competence will, they tell
us, make us better: better mothers, lovers, wives, workers, insur
ance risks, and more pleasing to behold. They create a market for
products and services to counteract the ones which have brought us
to a debilitated state in the first place.
Perhaps it would be accurate to say that a woman's participation
in a program of physical exercise is narcissistic when she undertakes
it not for the purpose of defining her own goal but in order to please
the Other, to coincide with an externally originated measure that she
has internalized. It is, of course, a problem to determine in a given
situation whether a woman is exercising for herself or in response to
an Other, and requires deciphering the jumble of cultural messages
and psychic codes that affect, if not determine, being-in-the-world.
Weight-lifting presents an example. Several years ago, as a large
number of women began lifting weights, articles in icon-building
magazines emphasized that women should train for muscle tone and
"plastic beauty. " These magazines sold us images of this (accept
able) kind of woman to serve as our guides. Many women, however,
set their own goals and have chosen to develop strength or muscular
ity or both. Now the same magazines have co-opted these goals and
present us with a much more muscular prototype.
Sandra Bartky denounces "punishing exercises. " From my view
point exercises punish women in three ways. Exertion of any kind is
punishing to an individual who was socialized into being passive
and is unfamiliar with the experience of challenging her physical
abilities. By being directed to perform specialized tasks, in both the
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Alienation and Feminism 159
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
160 Social Theory and Practice
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Alienation and Feminism 161
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
162 Social Theory and Practice
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Alienation and Feminism 163
Notes
Ibid., p. 51
Ibid., p. 52.
Karl Marx, The Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844,
trans, by Martin Milligan, ed., with an Introduction by Dirk J. Struik
(New York: International Publishers, 1965), p. 112.
Ibid., p. 113.
Ibid., p. 112.
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
164 Social Theory and Practice
Roderick Nash, Wilderness and the American Mind (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1967).
Nancy Chodorow, The Reproduction of Mothering (Berkeley: Univer
sity of California Press, 1978), p. 40.
Ibid., p. 41.
Ann Foreman, Femininity as Alienation (New York: Pluto Press,
1980), p. 46.
Chodorow, The Reproduction of Mothering, p. 44.
Ibid., p. 45.
Ibid., p. 142.
Ibid., p. 153.
Ibid., p. 154. Juliet Mitchell, who is the other major socialist-feminist
writer to discuss psychoanalysis, comes out in defense of Freud. See
her Psychoanalysis and Feminism (New York: Random House, 1975).
She thinks Freud's view of the unconscious should be read as descrip
tive of the sexual relations of a particular epoch, not as universal, and
that a restructuring of social relations could remove the repression of
the unconscious. For Chodorow's criticisms, see p. 81 (footnote) and
pp. 141-42. In Femininity as Alienation, Foreman also criticizes
Mitchell's defense of Freud, pp. 46-50.
Ibid., pp. 44-49.
Beauvoir, The Second Sex, p. 40.
Ibid., p. 113.
Bela Grunberger, Narcissism, trans, by Joyse S. Diamant (New York:
International Universities Press, 1971), p. 103.
Ibid., p. 106.
George W. Linden, "Dakota Philosophy," in American Studies, 18
(1977): 20.
Ibid., pp. 20-21.
An earlier version of this paper was first read as a response to
Professor Bartky's paper at a session sponsored by the Society for
Women in Philosophy at the Western Division meetings of the Ameri
can Philosophical Association, April 1981. Ann Garry also read a
response to the paper.
This content downloaded from 132.239.1.231 on Wed, 06 Apr 2016 23:51:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms