Mind and World - John McDowell
Mind and World - John McDowell
Mind and World - John McDowell
·WORLD
• • •
John
McDowell
Cambridge, Massachusetts
London, England
Copyright <0 1994, 1996 by the President and Fellows
of Harvard College
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
Fifth printing, 2000
121'.4-<lc20 96-22268
Contents
Preface vii
Introduction xi
Lecture I. Concepts and Intuitions 3
Afterword
Index 189
Preface
The main text of this book is a sort of record of the John Locke Lec
tures that I delivered in Oxford in Trinity Term, 1 991. I have done
some recasting of the lectures from the form in which I gave them. I
have tried to make improvements in clarity and explicitness. I have also
eliminated phrases like "next week" and "last week", which it seemed
absurd to leave standing in a version meant to be taken in through the
eye, perhaps-at least for the texts of the lectures-at a single sitting.
But apart from correcting one inessential falsehood at the end of the
last lecture, the texts I offer here, headed "Lecture I" and so on through
" Lecture VI", aim to say just what I said in Oxford.
They aim, moreover, to say it with a mode of organization and in a
tone of voice that reproduce those of the lectures as I gave them. There
are at least three points here.
First, even where I have made revisions at the level of phrases and
sentences, I have preserved the order of the lectures, as I delivered
them, at the level of paragraphs and sections. In particular, I have not
tried to eliminate, or even lessen, repetitiveness. I hoped that frequent
and sometimes lengthy recapitulations would be helpful to hearers,
and I hope they will be helpful to readers too.
Second, in a brief set of lectures, it seemed sensible to try to pursue
a reasonably linear train of thought, and I have not tried to make the
revised texts any less two-dimensional. The footnotes, in so far as they
go beyond merely bibliographical information, and the Afterword are
meant to give some indication of what a more rounded treatment of
these issues might look like. But they are no more than an adjunct to
the record of the lectures, more or less as I gave them.
viii Preface
1. Both now reprinted in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Clarendon Press, Ox
ford, 1984 ).
2. The Bounds of Sense (Methuen, London, 1966). I should also mention Individuals: An
Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (Methuen, London, 1959).
3. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1982.
Preface ix
pher (if any) I would have been now if it had not been for him. He is
one of the two people now gone with whom I most wish I could dis
cuss this work.
The other is Wilfrid Sellars. His classic essay "Empiricism and the
Philosophy of Mind"4 began to be central for me long before I ever
thought of coming to the University of Pittsburgh, and it is an abiding
regret for me that I became a colleague of his too late in his life to
profit from talking to him as I have profited from reading him.
Robert Brandom's writings, and conversations with him, have been
very important in shaping my thinking, usually by forcing me to get
clear about the differences, small in themselves, that transform for me
the look of our wide measure of agreement. The way I put things here
bears substantial marks of Brandom 's influence. Among much else, I
single out his eye-opening seminar on Hegel's Phenomenology of
Spirit, which I attended in 1 990. Thoughts Brandom elicited from me
then show up explicitly at a couple of places in these lectures, but the
effect is pervasive; so much so that one way that I would like to con
ceive this work is as a prolegomenon to a reading of the Phenomeno
logy, much as Brandom's forthcoming Making It Explicit: Reaso11ing,
Representing, and Discursive Commitment5 is, among many other
things, a prolegomenon to his reading of that difficult text. I am also
deeply indebted to Brandom for detailed help and support while I was
preparing the lectures.
Many other people have helped me with this work . I try to mention
specific debts in the footnotes, but I am sure there are many places
where I have forgotten who first taught me to say things as I do, and
I am sorry about that. Here I want to thank James Conant, john
Haugeland, and Danielle Macbeth for special help and encourage
ment.
4. In Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven, eds., Mitmesota Studies in the Philosophy oi
Science, vol. 1 {University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1 956), pp. 253-329.
5. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1 99+.
6. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1 979.
ous that Rorty's work is in any case central for the way I define my
stance here.
I used those first formulations in lectures in Oxford in that aca
demic year, my last ther�, and in my Whitehead Lectures at Harvard
in the spring of 1986. That initial work was done while I was a Rad
cliffe Philosophy Fellow, and even though this fruit of my Fellowship
is rather belated, I want to record gratefully that this book owes a
great deal to the generosity of the Radcliffe Trust. I also thank the
Master and Fellows of University College, Oxford, for giving me per
mission to accept the Fellowship.
I am very grateful to the Sub-Faculty of Philosophy in the Univer·
sity of Oxford for doing me the great honour of inviting me to give the
John Locke Lectures, and to many friends in England for their kind
ness during my stay.
Introduction
attempts to make up our minds about how things are. But consider a
stage at which reflection is subject to such a pair of pressures, but not
self-consciously enough for it to be clear that what they generate is an
antinomy. With an inexplicit awareness of the tension between such a
pair of tendencies in one's thinking, one could easily fall into an anx
iety of a familiar philosophical sort, about that directedness of mind
to world that it seemed we would have to be able to gloss in terms of
answerability to how things are. In such a position, one would find
oneself asking: "How is it possible for there to be thinking directed at
how things are?" This would be a "How possible?" question of a fa
miliar philosophical kind; it acquires its characteristic philosophical
bite by being asked against the background of materials for a line of
thought that, if made explicit, would purport to reveal that the
question's topic is actually not possible at all.
4. What is the pressure oo our .thinking that makes it hard to see how
experience could function as a tribunal? I can bring it to light by re
hearsing a central element in Wilfrid Sellars's attack on "the Myth of
the Given".
Sellars insists that the concept of knowledge belongs in a normative
context. He writes: "In characterizing an episode or a state as that of
knowing, we are not giving an empirical description of that episode or
state; we are placing it in the logical space of reasons, of justifying and
being able to justify what one says."2 It is a way of repeating what I
have just been urging (§3 above) to say this: though Sellars here
speaks of knowledge in particular, that is just to stress one application
of the thought that a normative context is necessary for the idea of
being in touch with �orld at all, whether knowledgeably or not.
..-one way of putting what Sellars is driving at IS to say that epiSte
mology is liable to fall into a naturalistic fallacy.31n the more general
version I have insisted on, the thought is that the risk of a naturalistic
fallacy besets reflection about world-directedness as such, whether
knowledgeable or not. If we put Sellars's point this way, we are iden
tifying the natural-as indeed Sellars sometimes does-with the sub
ject matter of "empirical description"; that is, with the subject matter
of a mode of discourse that is to be contrasted with placing something
in the normative framework constituted by the logical space of rea
sons. Sellars separates concepts that are intelligible only in terms of
how they serve to place things in the logical space of reasons, such as
the concept of knowledge, from concepts that can be employed in
"empirical description". And if we read the remark as a warning
against a naturalistic fallacy, we are understanding "empirigl
description" as placing things in the logical space of nature, to coin a
-
p!lr'aSe' that is Sellarsian at least m spmt.
What would the logical space of nature be? I think we capture the
essentials of Sellars's thinking if we take it that the logical space of
2. "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind", in Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven, eds.,
Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy ofScience, vol. 1 (University of Minnesota Press, Min
neapolis, 1956), pp. 253-329, at pp. 298 -9.
3. See p. 257 of "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind" for a formulation on these
lines.
XV
mainly Donald Davidson who figures in the role I have here cast Sell
ars in: as someone whose reflection a bout experience disqualifies it
from intelligibly constituting a tribunal. For these purposes, Sellars
and Davidson are interchangeable. Sellars's attack on the Given corre
sponds, in a way I exploit in my first lecture, to Davidson's attack on
what he calls "the third dogma of empiricism"-the d ualism of con
ceptual scheme and empirical "content". And Davidson explicitly sug
gestS that the thought dislodges even a minimal empiricism; he de
scribes the third dogma of empiricism as "perhaps the last", on the
ground that "if we give it up it is not clear that there is anything dis
tinctive left to call empiricism" .4
4. "On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme", in Donald Davidson, Inquiries into
Truth and Interpretation (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1984), pp. 183-98, at p. 189.
Introduction xvii
have given leaves various options available for doing that. In this
book I recommend one way of resolving this tension. Here I shall
briefly locate it by distinguishing it from a couple of others.
5. See especially "Mental Events", in Donald Davidson, E ssays on Actions and Events
(Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1 9 8 0), pp. 207-25; the quoted phrase is from p. 223.
istic, but not thereby shown to be fallacious. Thus we can accept that
the concept of experience belongs in the logical space of nature, but
that does not debar experience, so conceived, from being intelligible as
a tribunal. So there is no need to explain away the attractions of em
piricism.
I shall say a little more about bald naturalism shortly (§9 below),
but first I want to outline the different way of resolving the tension
that I recommend.
comes into view. And (the same point in different terms) Davidson is
right that "the constitutive ideal of rationality" governs concepts that
are for that reason quite special, in comparison with the conceptual
apparatus of the nomothetic sciences. But it is one thing to acknowl
edge this-in Sellarsian terms, to single out a logical space that is to be
contrasted with the logical space of reasons. It is another to equate
that logical space, as Sellars at least implicitly does, with the logical
space of nature. That is what makes it seem impossible to combine
empiricism with the idea that the world's making an impression on a
perceiving subject would have to be a natural happening. The mistake
here is to forget that nature includes second nature. Human beings
acquire a second nature in part by being initiated into conceptual ca
pacities, whose interrelations belong in the logical space of reasons.
Once we remember second nature, we see that operations of nature
can include circumstances whose descriptions place them in the logical
space of reasons, sui generis though that logical space is. This makes
it possible to accommodate impressions in nature without posing a
threat to empiricism. From the thesis that receiving an impression is a
transaction in nature, there is now no good inference to the conclu
sion drawn by Sellars and Davidson, that the idea of receiving an im
pression must be foreign to the logical space in which concepts such as
that of answerability function. Conceptual capacities, whose interre
lations belong in the sui generis logical space of reasons, can be oper
ative not only in judgements-results of a subject's actively making up
her mind about something-but already in the transactions in nature
that are constituted by the world's impacts on the receptive capacities
of a suitable subject; that is, one who possesses the relevant concepts.
Impressions can be cases of its perceptually appearing-being
apparent-to a subject that things are thus and so. In receiving im
pressions, a subject can be open to the way things manifestly are. This
yields a satisfying interpretation for the image of postures that are
answerable to the world through being answerable to experience.
6. The label "bald naturalism" is perhaps infelicitous for a position with a sophisticated
motivation on these lines; that is what I acknowledge � the footnote on pp. 88-9. I took
myself to be stuck with the label even so, since I had given it a thematic prominence in the
lectures of which the book is a version.
swers, the ones that figure in inquiries into the machinery of minded
ness.
I have tried to make it plausible that the anxieties I aim to exorcize
issue from the thought..Loften no doubt only inchoate-that the struc
ture of the logical space of reasons is sui generis, as compared with
the logical framework in which natural-scientific understanding is
achieved. On this view, it emerges as unsurprising that the period in
which dealing with these supposed difficulties came to seem the dom
inant obligation of philosophy coincides with the rise of modern sci
ence, in which natural-scientific understanding, as we are now
equipped to conceive it, was being separated out from a hitherto un
differentiated conception of understanding in general. According to
my picture, an important element in this clarification of the proper
target of natural science was an increasingly firm awareness that we
must sharply distinguish natural-scientific understanding from the
kind of understanding achieved by situating what is understood in
the logical space of reasons; that is, precisely, that the structure of the
logical space of reasons is sui generis, as I have read Sellars, and in
different terms Davidson, as claiming it is.
Now bald naturalism has it that that perhaps inchoate sense of a
conceptual divide was simply wrong; it would be revealed to be wrong
by a reconstruction of the structure of the logical space of reasons in
terms that belong in the logical space of natural-scientific understand
ing. This claim is programmatic, but that is not my ground for finding
bald naturalism unsatisfying. The point is rather one that I mentioned
at the beginning of this Introduction (§1 above). It is easy-and not
because we are merely stupid-to be captivated by the kind of philo
sophy I aim to exorcize. That means that a proposed exorcism is more
satisfying to the extent that it enables us to respect, as insights, the
driving thoughts of those who take the familiar philosophical anxie
ties to pose real intellectual obligations (our driving thoughts when we
find ourselves beset by the anxieties), even while we unmask the sup
posed obligations as illusory. Now my picture is unlike bald natural
ism in just that way. I acknowledge as an insight the basic conviction
that generates the anxieties, in combination with the �car5f1r.sues
tionable conception of impressions as occurrences in nature. In my
picture, those who take it that philosophy has to answer (rather than
exorcize) questions about how minds can be in touch with the world
are not wrong in supposing that the logical space of reasons is sui
generis, in just the way that seems to lead to problems about how
1 ntroattctron XXIII
does not quite understand the predicament that seems to motivate it.
If the frame of mind is left in place, one cannot show how whatever it
is that one is asking about is possible; if the frame of mind is dis
lodged, the "How possible?" question no longer has the point it
seemed to have. Either way, there is no prospect of answering the
question as it was putatively meant. So if I am right about the charac
ter of the philosophical anxieties I aim to deal with, there is no room
for doubt that engaging in "constructive philosophy", in this sense, is
not the way to approach them. As I have put it, we need to exorcize
the questions rather than set about answering them. Of course that
takes hard work: if you like, constructive philosophy in another sense.
And of course that is what I offer in this book.
Mind and World
LECTURE
would be for there to be nothing that one thinks when one thinks it;
that is, for it to lack what I am calling "representational content".
That would be for it not really to be a thought at all, and that is surely
Kant's point; he is n ot, absurdly, drawing our attention to a special
kind of thoughts, the empty ones. Now when Kant says that thoughts
without content are empty, he is not merely affirming a tautology:
"without content" is not just another wording for "empty", as it
would be if "content" simply meant "representational content".
"Without content" points to what would explain the sort of empti
ness Kant is envisaging. And we can spell out the explanation from the
other half of Kant's remark: "intuitions without concepts are blind."
Thoughts without content-which would not really be thoughts at
all-would be a play of concepts without any connection with intu
itions, that is, bits of experiential intake. It is their connection with
experiential intake that supplies the content, the substance, that
thoughts would otherwise lack.
So the picture is this: the fact that thoughts are not empty, the fact
that thoughts have representational content, emerges out of an inter
play of concepts and intuitions. "Content" in Davidson's dualism cor
responds to intuitions, bits of experiential intake, understood in terms
of a dualistic conception of this interplay.
ference be given over the other. Without sensibility no object would be given to us, without
understanding no object would be thought. Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions
without concepts are blind."
4. "In characterizing an episode or a state as that [better: one] of knowing, we are not
giving an empirical description of that episode or state; we are placing it in the logical space
of reasons, of justifying and being able to justify what one says." This is from pp. 298-9 of
Sellars's classic attack on the Myth of the Given, "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind",
in Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven, eds., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science,
vol. 1 (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1956), pp. 253-329. In much of the rest
of these lectures, I shall be concerned to cast doubt on Sellars's idea that placing something
in the logical space of reasons is, as such, to be contrasted with giving an empirical descrip
tion of it. But the theme of placing things in the space of reasons is of central importance
for me.
I say that the space of concepts is at least part of the space of reasons in order to leave it
open, for the moment, that the space of reasons may extend more widely than the space of
concepts; see the text below for this idea.
5. For a thoughtful discussion of this idea, see Robert Brandom, "Freedom and Con
straint by Norms", American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (1979), 187-96.
6 M I N D A N D W O R L D
scheme and Given, is a response to this worry. The point of the dual
ism is that it allows us to acknowledge an external constraint on our
freedom to deploy our empirical concepts. Empirical justifications de
pend on rational relations, relations within the space of reasons. The
putatively reassuring idea is that empirical justifications have an ulti
mate foundation in impingements on the conceptual realm from out
side. So the space of reasons is made out to be more extensive than the
space of concepts. Suppose we are tracing the ground, the justifica
tion, for a belief or a judgement. The idea is that when we have ex
hausted all the available moves within the space of concepts, all the
available moves from one conceptually organized item to another,
there is still one more step we can take: namely, pointing to something
that is simply received in experience. It can only be pointing, because
ex hypothesi this last move in a justification comes after we have ex
hausted the possibilities of tracing grounds from one conceptually or
ganized, and so articulable, item to another.
I began with the thought that is expressed in Kant's remark: the
very idea of representational content, not just the idea of judgements
that are adequately justified, requires an interplay between concepts
and intuitions, bits of experiential intake. Otherwise what was meant
to be a picture of the exercise of concepts can depict only a play of
empty forms. I have modulated into talking about how the idea of the
Given figures in a thought about the grounding that entitles some em
pirical judgements to count as knowledgeable. But this explicitly epi
stemological idea is straightforwardly connected with the more gen
eral idea I began with. Empirical judgements in general-whether or
not they reflect knowledge, and even whether or not they are justified
at all, perhaps less substantially than knowledge requires-had better
have content of a sort that admits of empirical justification, even if
there is none in the present case (say in a quite unsupported guess).
We could not begin to suppose that we understood how pointing to a
bit of the Given could justify the use of a concept in judgement
could, at the limit, display the judgement as knowledgeable-unless
we took this possibility of warrant to be constitutive of the concept's
being what it is, and hence constitutive of its contribution to any
thinkable content it figures in, whether that of a knowledgeable, or
less substantially justifiable, judgement or any other.
This supposed requirement would bear immediately on observa
tional concepts: concepts suited to figure in judgements that are di-
Lecture I. Concepts and Intuitions 7
3. I have tried to explain what makes the idea of the Given tempting.
But in fact it is useless for its purpose.
The idea of the Given is the idea that the space of reasons, the space
of justifications. or warrants, extends more widely than the conceptual
sphere. The extra extent of the space of reasons is supposed to allow
it to incorporate non-conceptual impacts from outside the realm of
thought. But we cannot really understand the relations in virtue of
which a judgement is warranted except as relations within the space
of concepts: relations such as implication or probabilification, which
hold between potential exercises of conceptual �apacities. The attempt
to extend the scope of justificatory relations outside the conceptual
sphere cannot do what it is supposed to do.
a role for spontaneity but refusing to acknowledge any role for recep
tivity, and that is intolerable. If our activity in empirical thought and
judgement is to be recognizable as bearing on reality at all, there must
be external constraint. There must be a role for receptivity as well as
spontaneity, for sensibility as well as understanding. Realizing this,
we come under pressure to recoil back into appealing to the Given,
only to see all over again that it cannot help. There is a danger of
falling into an interminable oscillation.
But we can find a way to dismount from the seesaw.
8. Of course this is not to deny that experiencing the world involves activity. Searching
is an activity; so are observing, watching, and so forth. (This sort of thing is usefully stressed
by people who think we should not conceive experience as passive reception at all, such as
J. ]. Gibson; see, for instance, The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems (George Allen
and Unwin, London, 1 968).) But one's control over what happens in experience has limits:
one can decide where to place oneself, at what pitch to tune one's attention, and so forth,
but it is not up to one what, having done all that, one will experience. This minimal point
is what I am insisting on.
Lecture I. Concepts and Intuitions 11
1 0. For an elaboration of points of this kind, see Sellars, " Empiricism and the Philosophy
of Mind", § § 10-20.
Lecture l. Concepts and Intuitions 13
it is no good pointing out that the appearance is illusory, that the idea
of the Given does not fulfil its apparent promise, if the worry that can
make the idea nevertheless seem inescapable remains urgent, or is even
exacerbated. The effect: is simply to bring out that neither of the two
positions that we are being asked to choose between is satisfying.
Davidson does nothing to discourage us from taking his coherentist
rhetoric in terms of confinement imagery. On the contrary, he posi
tively encourages it: At one point he says, "Of course we can't get
outside our skins to find out what is causing the internal happenings
of which we are aware" (p. 3 1 2). This is, as it stands, a very unsatis
factory remark. Why should we suppose that to find out about exter
nal objects we would have to get outside our skins? (Of course we
cannot do that.) And why should we suppose that we are interested in
finding out what is causing internal happenings of which we are
aware, rather than that we are simply interested in the layout of the
environment? Of course getting outside our skins is not the same as
getting outside our thoughts. But perhaps we can understand how D a
vidson can be so casual in this remark if we take it that our literal
confinement inside our skins strikes him as an analogue to a meta
phorical confinement inside our beliefs, which he is happy to let his
coherentism imply. Davidson's picture is that we cannot get outside
our beliefs.
Of course Davidson knows that such confinement imagery tends to
prompt a recoil to the idea of the Given, the idea that truth and
knowledge depend on rational relations to something outside the con
ceptual realm. He thinks he can allow free rein to confinement imag
ery, but pre-empt the recoil by arguing, within his coherentist frame
work, for the evidently reassuring thesis that "belief is in its nature
veridical" (p. 3 14). Davidson argues for that thesis by connecting be
lief with interpretation, and urging that it is in the nature of interpre
tation that an interpreter must find her subjects mostly right about the
world with which she can observe them causally interacting.
I do not want to dispute that argument. But I do want to raise the
question how effectively it can reassure us, if we are worried about
whether Davidson's coherentist picture can incorporate thought's
bearing on reality. Suppose one feels the worry in this familiar form:
so far as the picture goes, one might be a brain in a mad scientist's vat.
The Davidsonian response seems to be that if one were a brain in a
vat, it would be correct to interpret one's beliefs as being largely true
Lecture 1. Concepts ana lntutttons ll
beliefs about the brain's electronic environment.13 But is that the reas
surance we need if we are to be immunized against the attractions of
the Given? The argument was supposed to start with the body of be
liefs to which we are supposed to be confined, in our active efforts to
suit our thinking to the available justifications. It was supposed to
make the confinement imagery unthreatening by reassuring us that
those beliefs are mostly true. But the response to the brain-in-a-vat
worry works the wrong way round. The response does not calm the
fear that our picture leaves our thinking possibly out of touch with the
world outside us. It j ust gives us a dizzying sense that our grip on what
it is that we believe is not as firm as we thought.14
I think the right conclusion is chis: whatever credence we give to
Davidson's argument that a body of belief is sure to be mostly true,
the argument starts too late to certify Davidson's position as a genuine
escape from the oscillation.
The only motivation for the Myth of the Given that figures in
Davidson's thinking is a shallow scepticism, in which, taking it for
granted that one has a body of beliefs, one worries about their creden
tials. But the Myth of the Given has a deeper motivation, in the
thought that if spontaneity is not subject to rational constraint from
outside, as Davidson's coherentist position insists that it is not, then
we cannot make it intelligible to ourselves how exercises of spontane
ity can represent the world at all. Thoughts without intuitions are
empty, and the point is not met by crediting intuitions with a causal
impact on thoughts; we can have empirical content in our picture only
if we can acknowledge that thoughts and intuitions are rationally con-
1 3 . We have this on the testimony of Richard Rorty; see p. 340 of his "Pragmatism,
Davidson, and Truth" , in LePore, ed., Truth and Interpretation, pp. 3 33-55.
14. It takes care to say precisely why the response is unsatisfying. It is not that we are
being told we may be egregiously wrong about what our beliefs are about. If I protest that
some belief of mine is not about electronic impulses or whatever but a bout, say, a book, the
reply can be: "Certainly your belief is about a book-given how 'a book' as you use the
phrase is correctly interpreted. " The envisaged reinterpretation, to suit the hypothesis that I
am a brain in a vat, affects my higher-level beliefs about what my first-level beliefs are about
in a way that precisely matches its effect on my first-level beliefs. The problem is that in the
argument Rorry attributes to Davidson, we ring changes on the actual environment (as seen
by the interpreter and brought into the interpretation) without changing how things strike
the believer, even while the interpretation is supposed to capture how the believer is in
touch with her world. This strikes me as making it impossible to claim that the argument
traffics in any genuine idea of being in touch with something in particular. The objects that
the interpreter sees the subject's beliefs as being about become, as it were, merely noumenal
so far as the subject is concerned.
18 M I N D A N D W O R L D
1 7. I have said a little more about this reading of Wittgenstein in "One Strand in the
Private Language Argument", Grazer Phi/osophische Studien 33/34 ( 1 989), 285-303. See
also my " Intentionality and Interiority in Wittgenstein", in Klaus Puhl, ed., Meaning Scep
ticism (De Gruyter, Berlin, 1991), pp. 148-69.
20 M I N D A N D W O R L D
only to introduce the suggestion that we should read the Private Lan
guage Argument as an attack on the Given.
The Unboundedness
of the Conceptual
ing in the Given will strike her as slighting the independence of reality.
Bur the point of the third option, the option I am urging, is precisely
that it enables us to acknowledge that independent reality exerts a
rational control over our thinking, but without falling into the confu
sion between justification and exculpation that characterizes the ap
peal to the Given.
one can think, a phobia of idealism can make people suspect we are
renouncing the independence of reality_:_as if we were representing
the world as a shadow.of our thinking, or even as made of some men
tal stuff. But we might just as well take the fact that the sort of thing
one can think is the same as the sort of thing that can be the case the
other way round, as an invitation to understand the notion of the sort
of thing one can think in terms of a supposedly prior understanding of
the sort of thing that can be the case. 5 And in fact there is no reason to
look for a priority in either direction.
If we say that there must be a rational constraint on thought from
outside it, so as to ensure a proper acknowledgement of the indepen
dence of rea lity, we put ourselves at the mercy of a familiar kind of
ambiguity. "Thought" can mean the act of thinking; but it can also
mean the content of a piece of thinking: what someone thinks. Now if
we are to give due acknowledgement to the independence of reality,
what we need is a constraint from outside thinking and ;udging, our
exercises of spontaneity. The constraint does not need to be from out
side thinkable contents. It would indeed slight the independence of
reality if we equated facts in general with exercises of conceptual ca
pacities-acts of thinking-or represented facts as reflections of such
things; or if we equated perceptible facts in particular with states or
occurrences in which conceptual capacities are drawn into operation
in sensibility-experiences-or represented them as reflections of such
things. But it is not idealistic, as that would be, to say that perceptible
facts are essentially capable of impressing themselves on perceivers in
states or occurrences of the latter sort; and that facts in general are
essentially capable of being embraced in thought in exercises of spon
taneity, occurrences of the former sort.
The fact that experience is passive, a matter of receptivity in opera
tion, should assure us that we have all the external constraint we can
reasonably want. The constraint comes from outside thinking, but not
from outside what is thinkable. When we trace j ustifications back, the
last thing we come to is still a thinkable content; not something more
5. The Tractatus is often read on these lines; for a recent version, see David Pears, The
False Prison, vol. I (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1 9 87). Opponents of the kind of reading
Pears gives sometimes tend to find in the Tractatus a thesis of priority in the opposite dircc·
tion, or at least not to distinguish their interpretations clearly from this kind of thing. (That
might merit a protest of idealism.) But I doubt w hether either claim of priority is to be foun d
in t h e Tractatus.
Lectltre II. The Unbounded11ess uf tiJe Cm:t"eptual 29
ultimate than that, a bare pointing t o a bit of the Given. But these final
thinkable contents are put into place in operations of receptivity, and
that means that when we appeal to them we register the required con
straint on thinking from a reality external to it. The thinkable con
tents that are ultimate in the order of justification are contents of ex
periences, and in enjoying an experience one is open to manifest facts,
facts that obtain anyway and impress themselves on one's sensibility.
(At any rate one seems to be open to facts, and when one is not misled,
one is.} To paraphrase Wittgenstein, when we see �at such-and-such
is the case, we, and our seeing, do not stop anywhere short of the fact.
What we see is: that such-and-such is the case.
the " seen" colour to the apparent environment. Now I have been urg
ing that experiences in general are states or occurrences in which con
ceptual capacities are passively drawn into operation. That had better
hold for these "inner experiences" of colour as much as for any other
experiences. And I believe we should understand the role of colour
concepts in these " inner experiences" derivatively from their role in
"outer experience" . The concept of red gets a grip, in characterizing
an "inner experience" of "seeing red " , because the experience is in the
relevant respect subjectively like the experience of seeing chat some
thing-some " outer" thing-is red, or at least seeming to.
It can be tempting to take things the other way round: to suppose
that the "inner" role of colour concepts is autonomously intelligible,
and to try to explain their " outer" role in terms of the idea that for an
" outer" object to fall under a colour concept is for it to be such as to
cause the appropriate visual " inner experience" in suitable viewing
conditions. We can be encouraged into this by the thought that if
being red and looking red are intelligible only in terms of each other,
that makes it a mystery how anyone can break into this circle: a mys
tery we might hope to dissipate by explaining both being red and
looking red in terms of the " inner" experience of " seeing red" .
But we should resist this temptation. If the " inner" role o f colour
concepts were a self-standing starting point, " outer experience" of
colour would become impossible to comprehend. By what alchemy
could an " inner experience" be transmuted into an " outer experi
ence " ? If a colour first figures, in the development of our understand
ing, as a feature of " inner experience", not an apparent property of
objects, how could our understanding contrive to project that out into
the world? Starting from there, we might manage to externalize at best
a propensity to induce the relevant feature of " inner experience" in us.
But it is quite doubtful whether the idea of possessing such a propen
sity adds up to the idea of being appropriately coloured: that requires
precisely that our experience and thought locate something phenome
nal in the external world, whereas the "propensity" conception keeps
what is phenomenal in the mind.7 And anyway the circle-the mutual
dependence of the concepts of being red and looking red-is quite
innocent. It is no threat, for instance, co a sane view of how colour
concepts are acquired; we simply have to suppose they come only as
elements in a bundle of concepts that must be acquired together.8 So I
propose to focus on the role of colour concepts, and more generally
concepts of secondary qualities, in " outer experience " , taking it that
that is what is fundamental.
In "outer experience" , a subject is passively saddled with concep
tual contents, drawing into operation capacities seamlessly integrated
into a conceptual repertoire that she employs in the continuing activ
ity of adjusting her world-view, so as to enable it to pass a scrutiny of
its rational credentials. It is this integration that makes it possible for
us to conceive experience as awareness, or at least seeming awareness,
of a reality independent of experience. We can a ppreciate this point by
continuing to consider the way colours figure in the content of experi
ence. Even here, where the linkages into the whole system are mini
mal, the relevant conceptual capacities are integrated into spontaneity
at large, in a way that enables the subject to understand experiences in
which those conceptual capacities are drawn into operation as
7. It is one thing to gloss being red in terms of being such as to look red, and quite
another to gloss it in terms of being such as to induce a certain "inner experience" in us.
Note that "redft in " looking red" expresses a concept of "outer experience" no less than
does "red" in " being redft, in fact the very same concept. (Sellars insists on this point in
"Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind".)
8. See Sellars, "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Migd", S S 1 8-ZO.
32 M I N D A N D W O R L D
9. This is a way of putting something Gareth Evans urges in "Things without the Mind
a Commentary upon Chapter Two of Strawson'$ Individuals", in Zak van Straaten, ed.,
Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson (Clarendon Press, Oxford,
1 980), pp. 76- 1 1 6.
Lecture II. The Unbound, dness of the C mceptual 33
reveals. The capacities that are pas ively drawn ir to operation in ex
perience can be recognized as cone :ptual capacit es only because we
can get the idea of spontaneity to fit . And we do r.ot genuinely get the
idea of spontaneity to fit if we try to picture a practice of thinking that
distances itself from actual cases of the passivity of experience only so
far as to contemplate more of the same, including merely possible
cases. That way, we entitle ourselves at most co the idea of an orderly
sequence of "inner experiences". In fact I do not believe we entitle
ourselves even to that, because we cannot make sense even of " inner
experience" in the absence of a world; but it will not be clear why I
say that until much later (Lecture V), and perhaps not even then. The
point for now is just this: if we try to picture a mode of, say, colour
experience with only this slight an integration into a practice of active
thinking and judgement, it is mysterious how what we are picturing
could amount to "outer experience" of colour-how the colour expe
rienced could be experienced as a feature of an "outer" reality.
The point about how experience is rationally linked into the activity
of adjusting a world-view is even clearer when we stop restricting our
selves to concepts of secondary qualities. Of course other concepts
figure in experience too. It would be quite wrong to suppose that ex
perience takes in only features of reality whose concepts are inextrica
bly tied to concepts of modes of appearance, in the way that is exem
plified by the tie between what it is to be red and what it is to look red.
(As if other aspects of the world could come to mind not in experi
ence, but only in theoretical thinking.) Experiences themselves take in
more of the thinkable world than qualities that are phenomenal in
that sense.
Generalized, the remark of Wittgenstein that I started from says
that thinking does not stop short of facts. The world is embraceable in
thought. What I have been urging is that that constitutes a back
ground without which the special way in which experience takes hold
of the world would not be intelligible. And the dependence is not only
in that direction. It is not that we could first make sense of the fact that
the world is thinkable, in abstraction from experience, and proceed
from there to make sense of experience. What is in question could not
be the thinkable world, or, to put it another way, our picture of the
understanding's equipment could not be what it needs to be, a picture
of a system of concepts and conceptions with substantial empirical
content, if it were not already part of the picture that the system is the
34 ' M I N D A N D W cf R L D
6. I have been talking about how the conceptual capacities that are
drawn into operation in experience are integrated into spontaneity at
large. I have suggested that it is this integration that makes it possible
for a subject to understand an " outer" experience as awareness of
something objective, something independent of the experience itself.
The object of an experience, the state of affairs experienced as obtain
ing, is understood as part of a whole thinkable world. Since the whole
is independent of this particular experience, we can use the linkage
into the mostly unexperienced whole to hold the object of this partic
ular experience in place, while we ask how things would have been if
the experience had not occurred. This depends on a specific way in
which concepts are integrated into spontaneity at large, a way that, as
I have claimed, is minimally exemplified by colour concepts.
Now in my first lecture (§7) I said that the object of an " inner ex
perience" does not have this independence from the experience itself.
An object of " inner experience" , I said, has no existence indepen
dently of the awareness that the experience constitutes.
This can put a strain on our understanding of " inner experience " .
lt is easy to think we cannot preserve the claim that a n " inner experi
ence" has no object independent of the experience, unless we construe
the objects of " inner experience" as bits of the Given, somehow con
stitutively related to the occurrences of their reception-that is, a s
" private objects " . I f we are persuaded by Wittger'stein's polemic
against that supposed conception, we come under pressure either to
deny that " inner experience" is a matter of awareness at all, which
would dispense us from worrying about a relation between events in
the stream of consciousness and putative objects of such events, but
which looks like the embarrassing philosophical strategy of " feigning
anaesthesia";12 or else, keeping awareness in play, to give up the claim
14. The second half of this contrast is somewhat fragile. We might say that the sensuous
specificity of an object of "inner experience" is equally understood exclusively through
what it is like to experience it. It cannot be someone else's pain that I embrace in thought
unless what I have in mind is what her experience is like for her. When I say that the circum
stance of someone's being in pain is thinkable otherwise than through her "inner experi
ence" of it, I do not mean to imply that the circumstance is thinkable in abstraction from
her "inner experience" of it, for instance in behaviouristic terms. But in the case of second·
ary qualities there is no parallel to the play between first-person and third-person stand
points. This footnote responds to a comment by Danielle Macbeth.
Lecture 11. The Unboundedness of the Conceptual 39
8. People sometimes object to positions like the one I have been urg
ing on the ground that they embody an arrogant anthropocentrism, a
baseless confidence that the world is completely within the reach of
40 M I N D A N D W O R L D
should like to take this further, but for several reasons, of which the
fact that I have said enough for one lecture is perhaps the least serious,
I cannot do that now.
Non-conceptual Content
1. It is worth noting, since it helps to bring out how demanding the relevant idea of the
conceptual is, that this openness to reflection implies self-consciousness on the part of the
thinking subject. But I relegate the point to a footnote at this stage, since issues about self
consciousness will not be in the foreground until later (l�ture V).
48 M I N D A N D W O R L D
but simply endorses the conceptual content, or some of it, that is al
ready possessed by the experience on which it is grounded.6
It is important not to misconceive this divergence. In Evans's view,
experiences are states of the informational system, and as such they
have content that is non-conceptual. But he does not equate the idea
of an experience with the idea of a perceptual informational state,
produced independently of spontaneity by the operations of the infor
mational system. On the contrary, he insists that perceptual informa
tional states, with their non-conceptual content, "are not ipso facto
perceptual experiences-that is, states of a conscious subject"
(p. 1 57). According to Evans, a state of the perceptual informational
system counts as an experience only if its non-conceptual content is
available as "input to a thinking, concept-applying, and reasoning
system" (p. 158); that is, only if its non-conceptual content is avail
able to a faculty of spontaneity, which can rationally make or with
hold judgements of experience on the basis of the perceptual state. So
a non-conceptual informational state, produced by the perceptual ele
ment of the informational system in a creature that lacks a faculty of
spontaneity, does not count as a perceptual experience, even though a
state that does count as a perceptual experience, by virtue of its avail
ability to spontaneity, is in itself just such a non-conceptual informa
tional state, endowed with its non-conceptual content independently
of the coming into play of the faculty of spontaneity.
thinking. But now w e come t o the other side o f the standing difficulty:
we must avoid conceiving the external constraint in such a way that it
could at best yield exculpations where we needed justifications. One
might simply refuse to address this difficulty, by refusing to give any
place, in an account of experience, to anything like the idea of sponta
neity. But as I have just stressed, that is not a line that Evans takes.
To acknowledge the required external constraint, we need to ap
peal to receptivity. I have urged that the way to introduce receptivity
without merely tipping the seesaw back to the Myth of the Given is
this: we must not suppose that receptivity makes an even notionally
separable contribution to its co-operation with spontaneity.
Now Evans does not respect this rule. In Evans's account of experi
ence, receptivity figures in the guise of the perceptual element of the
informational system, and his idea is that the perceptual system pro
duces its content-bearing states independently of any operations of
spontaneity. It is true that the content-bearing states that result count
as experiences, in the somewhat Kantian restricted sense that Evans
employs, only by virtue of the fact that they are available to spontane
ity. But spontaneity does not enter into determining their content. So
the independent operations of the informational system figure in
Evans's account as a separable contribution made by receptivity to its
co-operation with spontaneity.
In that case, the way experiences are related to conceptual capaci
ties in Evans's picture is j ust the way intuitions are related to concepts
in the picture of empirical knowledge that Kant, as I am reading him,
displays as hopeless, at least as a picture of how things are from the
standpoint of experience. It is true that Kant tries to allow a kind of
correctness for a picture with that shape at the transcendental level,
but Evans's account of experience is not meant to be only transcen
dentally correct, whatever indeed that might mean. So unless there is
something wrong with the Kantian considerations I rehearsed in my
first two lectures, Evans's account of experience ought to be demol
ished by them.
It may be hard to believe that Evans's view of experience is a ver
sion of the Myth of the Given. Evans's smoothly naturalistic account
of perceptual informational states shows no sign of the epistemologi
cal obsessions that are usually operative in motivating the Myth of the
Given. What usually underlies the Myth is a worry that spontaneity's
involvement in our picture of empirical thO\lght makes it mysterious
52 .\1 I .-.: iJ A S CJ \t 0 f<. L iJ
7. Why can we not acknowledge that the relations berween experience and judgements
have to be rational, and therefore within the scope of spontaneity, without being thereby
committed to a concession about experience itself? I have claimed that it is hard to see how
this combination could work, but as long as Evans's position looks innocent it will seem
quite easy. Rather than radically recasting this lecture from the form in which I delivered it,
I postpone further discussion of this matter to the Afterword.
54 M I N D A N D W O R L D
10. For a clear and engaging exposition of this welling-up picture, see Daniel Dennen,
"Toward a Cognitive Theory of Consciousness", in his Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays
on Mind and Psychology (Bradford Books, Montgomery, Vt., 1978), pp. 149-73. Dennett
suggests that the role of content at the personal level is to be understood in terms of our
access to some of the content that figures in a sub-personal story about our internal ma
chinery. I think Dennen's own discussion strongly suggests that something is wrong with
this picture: it leads Dennett into the highly implausible claim that perceptual awareness is
a matter of presentiments or premonitions, differing from what are ordinarily so called only
in that they are not isolated (see pp. 165-6). I discuss this in "The Concept of Perceptual
Experience", Philosophical Quarterly 44 (1994), 190-2()5.
56 M I N D A N D W O R L D
1 5. Peacocke is an exception; see A Study of Concepts, pp. 83-4. But notice that even
though Peacocke there in effect acknowledges that fineness of grain is no threat to the thesis
that the content of experience is conceptual, he is not above claiming, in an earlier passage,
an advantage for his different view in the fact that "writers on the objective content of
experience have often remarked that an experience can have a finer-grained content than
can be formulated by using concepts possessed by the experiencer" (p. 67). If this claim that
writers have often made is false, why should accommodating it be an advantage for
Peacocke's view?
Lecture III. Non-conceptual Content 59
16. In another sense, the capacity to have that particular shade in mind is a standing one,
which requires no more than possession of the concept of a shade together with the subject's
standing powers of discrimination. Experience raises this standing potential to a degree of
actuality; the capacity to have that shade in mind as that shade is actually operative in the
experience, and potentially operative subsequently in thoughts that exploit recall of the
experience.
60 M I N D A N D W O R L D
1 7. The main lines of what I say in this section date from a seminar I gave in Oxford in
1 986 (with Colin McGinn). But my thinking on these issues has since been enriched by
discussions with Sonia Sedivy, who independently arrived at similar thoughts, in reaction to
the Sellarsian idea that the sensuous specificity of perceptual experience needs to be ac
counted for in terms of impressions as opposed to concepts. See her 1990 University of
PittSburgh dissertation, "The Determinate Character of Perceptual Experience" .
Lecture III. Noll-conceptual Content 61
But the point does not touch the position I am recommending. Ac
cording to the position I am recommending, conceptual capacities are
already operative in experience itself. It is not that actual operations
of conceptual capacities first figure only in actualizations of disposi
tions to judge, with which experiences are identified-so that experi
ence is connected with concepts only by way of a potentiality. Having
things appear to one a certain way is already itself a 'mode of actual
operation of conceptual capacities.
This mode of operation of conceptual capacities is special because,
on the side of the subject, it is passive, a reflection of sensibility. In the
context of that claim, it takes work to ensure that the capacities are
recognizable as genuinely conceptual capacities-that the invocation
of the conceptual is not mere word-play. What is needed is that the
very same capacities can also be exploited in active j udgements. And
what secures this identification, between capacities that are operative
in appearances and capacities that are operative in j udgements, is the
way appearances are rationally linked into spontaneity at large: the
way appearances can constitute reasons for judgements about objec
tive reality-indeed, do constitute reasons for j udgements in suitable
circumstances ("other things being equal" ).
Now this link between experience and spontaneity is similar in
some ways to the link that is effected, in the position Evans attacks, by
conceiving experiences as dispositions to judge. But the link I envis
age, unlike that one, is a link that connects experiences to judgements
as reasons for them. That means my picture does not have the feature
that Evans complains of: that when there is an inclination to make a
judgement of experience, the inclination seems to float mysteriously
free of the situation, taking on the look of an unaccountable convic
tion that some concept " has application in the immediate vicinity" .
On the contrary, when one does have such a conviction, m y picture
allows it to be satisfactorily grounded in how things appear to one.
In my first lecture ( § 6 ), I suggested that Davidson's coherentism
reflects an obstacle in the way of seeing that operations of conceptual
capacities can be passive. The same obstacle seems to be at work in
Evans's argument from the fact that experience is " belief-indepen
dent" . In fact Davidson and Evans represent the two horns of a di
lemma posed by that obstacle. If one fails to see that conceptual ca
pacities can be operative in sensibility itself, one has two options:
either, like Davidson, to insist that experience is only causally related
Lecture III. Non-conceptual Content 63
to empirical thinking, not rationally; or else, like Evans, to fall into the
Myth of the Given, and try to credit experience, conceived as extra
conceptual, with rational relations to empirical thinking. Davidson
holds that the Myth of the Given can be avoided only by denying that
experience is epistemologically significant. Evans, for good reasons,
cannot stomach that denial, and he shows that he shares Davidson's
view of the possibilities by accordingly embracing a form of the Myth
of the Given. My point is that we need not confine ourselves within
this framework of possibilities. I shall return to this in the next lecture.
erful influence over the cast of our thinking that tends to obliterate the
very possibility of the right picture. The difficulty comes out in ques
tions like this: how can spontaneity permeate our lives, even to the
extent of structuring those aspects of them that reflect our natural
ness-those aspects of our lives that reflect what we share with ordi
nary animals? The thought is that the freedom of spontaneity ought to
be a kind of exemption from nature, something that permits us to
elevate ourselves above it, rather than our own special way of living
an animal life. I shall come back to these issues in the next lecture.
L E C T U R E I V
1. See Lecture I, §2. Of course depictions of nature are linked by relations of justification.
The point is that there are no such linkages in what is depicted.
Lecture I V. Reason and Nature 71
2. The crucial contrast here is between the internal organization of the space of reasons
and the internal organization of nature, on a conception that modern natural science invites
.us to hold. This contrast echoes the Kantian contrast between the realm of freedom and the
realm of nature. It sets the agenda for much post-Kantian philosophy, and it is central to
Sellars's thinking.
In the text, I avoid a gloss that some of Sellars's followers put on what stands opposed to
the space of reasons: Rorty, for instance, speaks on Sellars's behalf of a distinction between
the logical space of reasons and the logical space of "causal relations to objects" (Philoso
phy and the Mirror of Nature [Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1979), p. 1 57). I think
this reflects a disputable picture of how modern natural science most fundamentally orga
nizes its subject matter: one that Russell protested against in his essay "On the Notion of
Cause", in Bertrand Russell, Mysticism and Logic (George Allen and Unwin, London,
1 9 1 7), pp. 1 32-51 in the 1 963 paperback edition. Russell suggested that the idea of causa
tion should be replaced, in the role of basic organizing principle for the world as viewed by
natural science, with something like the idea of law-governed processes. So the right con
trast for the space of reasons is not the space of causes but, as in my text, the realm of law.
(This leaves untouched the fact, which I exploited in my Sellarsian explanation of why the
Myth of the Given is a myth [Lecture I, S3), that a merely causal relation cannot do duty for
a justificatory relation.)
It is not just that this reading of the contrast is wrong about science; it is also disputable
in its implication that the idea of causal connections is restricted to thinking that is not
framed by the space of reasons. On my reading, the contrast leaves it possible for an area of
discourse to be in the logical space of causal relations to objects without thereby being
shown not to be in the logical space of reasons. Contrary to what Rorty's contrast implies,
reasons might be causes.
�
3. See chap. 1 of Charles Taylor, Hegel ( Cambridge Un versity Press, Cambridge, 1 975).
72 M I N D A N D W O R L D
6. So a reason can be a cause, though it is not by virtue of its rational relationships that
it stands in causal relations.
76 M I N D A N D W O R L D
trouble on the idea that spontaneity is sui generis, but that is not the
only possible target of suspicion. There is also the naturalism that
equates nature with the realm of law. We need that background to
make it appear that we can acknowledge a sui generis character for
spontaneity only by locating ourselves in the framework of possibili
ties that Davidson and Evans move in.
It would be a cheat, a merely verbal manoeuvre, to object that nat
uralism about nature cannot be open to question. If we can rethink
our conception of nature so as to make room for spontaneity, even
though we deny that spontaneity is capturable by the resources of
bald naturalism, we shall by the same token be rethinking our concep
tion o f what it takes for a position to deserve to be called "nat
uralism".
7. I usc the lower case to stress that I mean the label "platonismh in something like the
sense that it bears in the philosophy of mathematics. I imply no connection with Plato,
beyond the general resemblance in imagery that underlies the usc of the term in the mathe·
matical context. I shall say something against connecring the position with Plato in Lecture
VI (SlJ.
78 M I N D A N D W O R L D
we wanted was a naturalism that makes room for meaning, but this is
no kind of naturalism at all. 8
But there is a way out. We get this threat of supernaturalism if we
interpret the claim that the space of reasons is sui generis as a refusal
to naturalize the requirements of reason. But what became available
at the time of the modern scientific revolution is a clear-cut under
standing of the realm of law, and we can refuse to equate that with a
new clarity about nature. This makes room for us to insist that spon
taneity is sui generis, in comparison with the realm of law, without
falling into the supernaturalism of rampant platonism.
To reassure ourselves that our responsiveness to reasons is not su
pernatural, we should dwell on the thought that it is our lives that are
shaped by spontaneity, patterned in ways that come into view only
within an inquiry framed by what Davidson calls "the constitutive
ideal of rationality" . Exercises of spontaneity belong to our mode of
living. And our mode of living is our way of actualizing ourselves as
animals. So we can rephrase the thought by saying: exercises of spon
taneity belong to our way of actualizing ourselves as animals. This
removes any need to try to see ourselves as peculiarly bifurcated, with
a foothold in the animal kingdom and a mysterious separate involve
ment in an extra-natural world of rational connections.
This does not require that we blur the contrast between the space o f
reasons a n d the realm of law. T o see exercises o f spontaneity as natu
ral, we do not need to integrate spontaneity-related concepts into the
structure of the realm of law; we need to stress their role in capturing
patterns in a way of living. Of course there would be no contrast here
if the idea of lives and their shapes belonged exclusively or primarily
within the logical space of the realm of law, but there is no reason to
suppose that that is so.
8 . Davidsonian monism is no help here. It is no comfort to reflect that all the items we
speak of figure in nature, if we are still stuck with truths about some of them that look
supernatural. The problem posed by the contrast berween the space of reasons and the
realm of law, in the context of a naturalism that conceives nature as the realm of law, is not
ontological but ideological.
Lecture 1 V. Reason and N.l t u rc 7 ')
9. Nicomachean Ethics 6. 1 3.
1 0. That of Sir David Ross, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle (Oxford University
Press, London, 1 954). Terence Irwin's translation (Hackett, Indianapolis, 1985) has "intd·
ligence". (Aristotle's word is "phronesis ".)
1 1. For a reading of this sort, see chap. 3 of Bernard Williams, Ethics a11d tl>e Limits of
Philosophy (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1985). There is something similar
in chap. 9 of Alasdair Macintyre, After Virt11e (Duckworth, London, 1 98 1 ) .
•
80 M I N D A N D W O R L D
12. Compare the worries of epistemology as we know it, which are widely acknowledged
to be distinctively modern. At root the point is the same. Sellars traced the anxieties of
modern epistemology to the fact that the idea of knowledge is the idea of a position in a
justificatory network; this was the context in which he mentioned the space of reasons.
Anxiety about knowledge, of the familiar modern kind, results when that fact is juxtaposed
wirh the threatened extrusion of the space of reasons from nature. It is not that the idea of
knowledge as a position in the space of reasons was new-as if it was not until around the
seventeenth century that people hit on the thought that becomes so pregnant in modern
epistemology, thar knowledge is a normative status. But before the modern era, the idea that
knowledge is a normative status was not felt to stand in tension with, say, the idea that
knowledge might be the result of an exercise of natural powers. A naturalism that responds
to this tension by setting out to ground the normative connections that constitute the space
of reasons, after all, within nature, conceived in the very way that threatens the tension, is
quite different from a naturalism like Aristotle's, which never feels a tension here, and has
no need for imagery of grounding or foundations. (l discuss this further in �Two Sorts of
Naturalism • , forthcoming in a Festschrift for Philippa Foot edited by Rosalind Hursthouse
and Gavin Lawrence.)
1 3 . He shows no interest in addressing such doubts; he stipulates that he is addressing
only people in whom that ethical outlook has been inculcated (Nicomachean Ethics 1 .4,
1 095 b4-6 ).
Lecture IV. Reason and Nature 81
To focus the way this conception can serve as a model for us, con
sider the notion of second nature. The notion is all but explicit in
Aristotle's account of how ethical character is formed.16 Since ethical
character includes dispositions of the practical intellect, part of what
happens when character is formed is that the practical intellect ac
quires a determinate shape. So practical wisdom is second nature to its
possessors. I have been insisting that for A,ristotle the rational de
mands of ethics are autonomous; we are not to feel compelled to val
idate them from outside an already ethical way of thinking. But this
autonomy does not distance the demands from anything specifically
human, as in rampant platonism. They are essentially within reach of
human beings. We cannot credit appreciation of them to human na
ture as it figures in a naturalism of disenchanted nature, because
disenchanted nature does not embrace the space of reasons. But
human beings are intelligibly initiated into this stretch of the space
of reasons by ethical upbringing, which instils the appropriate shape
into their lives. The resulting habits of thought and action are second
nature.
This should defuse the fear of supernaturalism. Second nature
could not float free of potentialities that belong to a normal human
organism. This gives human reason enough of a foothold in the realm
of law to satisfy any proper respect for modern natural science.
The point is clearly not restricted to ethics. Moulding ethical char
acter, which includes imposing a specific shape on the practical intel
lect, is a particular case of a general phenomenon:. initiation into con
ceptual capacities, which include responsiveness to other rational
demands besides those of ethics. Such initiation is a normal part of
what it is for a human being to come to maturity, and that is why,
although the structure of the space of reasons is alien to the layout of
nature conceived as the realm of law, it does not take on the remote
ness from the human that rampant platonism envisages. If we gener
alize the way Aristotle conceives the moulding of ethical character, we
arrive at the notion of having one's eyes opened to reasons at large by
acquiring a second nature. I cannot think of a good short English ex
pression for this, but it is what figures in German philosophy as
Bildung.
1 6 . See Book 2 of Nicomachean Ethics. For an excellent discussion, see M. F. Burnyeat,
" Aristotle on Learning to Be Good", in Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, ed., Essays on Ari.;tot/e's
Ethics (University of California Press, Berkeley, 1 980), pp. 69-92.
Lecture IV. Reason and Nature 85
ture, we can say that the way our lives are shaped by reason is natural,
even while we deny that the structure of the space of reasons can be
integrated into the layotlt of the realm of law. This is the partial re-en
chantment of nature that I spoke of.
This is not to lapse into a rampant platonism. In rampant platon
ism, the structure of the space of reasons, the structure in which we
place things when we find meaning in them� is simply extra-natural.
Our capacity to resonate to that structure has to be mysterious; it is as
if we had a foothold outside the animal kingdom, in a splendidly non
human realm of ideality. But thanks to the notion of second nature,
there is no whiff of that here. Our Bildung actualizes some of the po
tentialities we are born with; we do not have to suppose it introduces
a non-animal ingredient into our constitution. And although the
structure of the space of reasons cannot be reconstructed out of facts
about our involvement in the realm of law, it can be the framework
within which meaning comes into view only because our eyes can be
opened to it by Bildung, which is an element in the normal coming to
maturity of the kind of animals we are. Meaning is not a mysterious
gift from outside nature.
These considerations should undermine one attraction of what I
have called " bald naturalism" . If we refuse to naturalize spontaneity
within the realm of law, it can seem that we are trapped in the philo
sophical impasse I began with, the forced choice between coherentism
and the Myth of the Given. But the refusal to naturalize spontaneity
does not generate the impasse all by itself. There is also the naturalism
that equates disclosing how something fits into nature with placing it
in the realm of law. Apart from that naturalism, we would not have
to conclude that since the operations of sensibility are, as such, natu
ral goings-on, considered in themselves they can only be intuitions
without concepts. So once the idea of second nature is in place, the
impasse need no longer look like a recommendation for bald natural
ism. We can claim both that the notion of spontaneity functions in a
conceptual framework that is alien to the structure of the realm of
law, and that it is needed for describing actualizations of natural pow
ers as such. If nature had to be identified with the realm of law, that
combination would be incoherent. But once we allow that natural
powers can include powers of second nature, the threat of incoherence
disappears.1
I. Perhaps "bald naturalism" is nO[ a good label for a position adopted on the grounds I
consider here. Someone who thought on these lines would be alive to the case for supposing
Lecture V. Action, Meaning, and the Self 89
2 . The second option, with its counterpart i n philosophical reflection about other aspects
of the mental, fits Cartesian philosophy of mind, at least on a certain familiar reading (the
one given currency by Gilbert Ryle in The Concept of Mind [Hutchinson, London, 1 949]).
We can understand Cartesian philosophy of mind, on that reading, as reflecting an inchoate
awareness of what only later comes into focus as the s11i generis character of the space of
reasons. It is intelligible that at an early stage in the formation of the conception of place
ment in nature by comparison with which the space of reasons is s11i generis-the concep
tion that, when it comes into focus, is seen as excluding what is done by concepts that
function in the space of reasons-there should be an inclination to suppose that what is
special about those concepts is that they place their satisfiers in a special traer of nature,
with nature understood according to a rudimentary form of the very conception that sets up
the strain.
3. Like anything else, they can conform to a specification, which might give the content
of an intention. But on this view intention cannot be more intimately involved in move
ments of an agent's limbs than it is in, say, some failings of trees. In both cases, we can have
an evenr conforming to a specification framed by an agent, and occurring in consequence of
the framing of the specification. Intention has only an external bearing on the event itself.
Lecture V. Action, Meaning, and the Self 91
This withdrawal of agency from nature, at any rate from the ordi
nary nature in which the movements of our bodies occur, strains our
hold on the idea that the natural powers that are actualized in the
movements of our bodies are powers that belong to us as agents. Our
powers as agents withdraw inwards, and our bodies with the powers
whose seat they are-which seem to be different powers, since their
actualizations are not doings of ours but at best effects of such do
ings-take on the aspect of alien objects. It comes to seem that what
we do, even in those of our actions that we think of as bodily, is at
best to direct our wills, as it were from a distance, at changes of state
in those alien objects.4 And this is surely not a satisfactory picture of
our active relation to our bodies. Just as the exclusion of spontaneity
from sentient nature obliterates anything we can recognize as empir
ical content, so here the withdrawal of spontaneity from active na
ture eliminates any authentic understanding of bodily agency.
Here too, we can return to sanity if we can recapture the Aristote
lian idea that a normal mature human being is a rational animal, with
its rationality part of its animal, and so natural, being, not a mysteri
ous foothold in another realm. The way to do that is to realize that
our nature is largely second nature.5
4. "At best" because such a picture is unstable. What are supposed to be willings are
distanced from any occurrence in ordinary nature, in a way that ultimately undermines the
very idea of willing.
5. My aim in these remarks about agency is only ro bring out that the philosophical
anxieties I have been exploiting are general: the application to experience is just one case.
Much more could be said about the application ro action. In particular, I think the way
certain bodily goings-on are our spontaneity in action, nor just effects of it, is central to a
proper understanding of rhe self as a bodily presence in the world, something that comes to
the fore later in this lecture (§5). But I shall not expanq on that.
92 .\ 1 I :\ D .\ :-.; D \\ 0 R L D
would leave even the last dualism not seeming to call for constructive
philosophy. The bare idea of Bildung ensures that the autonomy of
meaning is not inhuman, and that should eliminate the tendency to be
spooked by the very idea of norms or demands of reason. This leaves
no genuine questions about norms, apart from those that we address
in reflective thinking about specific norms, an activity that is not par
ticularly philosophical. There is no need for constructive philosophy,
directed at the very idea of norms of reason, or the structure within
which meaning comes into view, from the standpoint of the natural
ism that threatens to disenchant nature. We need not try to get mean
ing into view from that standpoint.
Of course the category of the social is important. Bildung could not
have its place in the picture if that were not so. But the point is not
that the social constitutes the framework for a construction of the
very idea of meaning: something that would make the idea safe for a
restrictive naturalism, the sort that threatens to disenchant nature.
Wittgenstein says, " Commanding, questioning, recounting, chatting,
are as much part of our natural history as walking, eating, drinking,
playing" . 10 By "our natural history", he must mean the natural history
of creatures whose nature is largely second nature. Human life, our
natural way of being, is already shaped by meaning. We need not con
nect this natural history to nature as the realm of law any more tightly
than by simply a ffirming our right to the notion of second nature.
I am crediting Wittgenstein with an " ism" , naturalized platonism.
Am I myself flouting his insistence that he is not in the business of
offering philosophical doctrine? No. Recall what I said at the end of
the last lecture { § 8 ) about Rorty and "the discovery that gives philoso
phy peace". "Naturalized platonism" is not a label for a bit of con
structive philosophy. The phrase serves only as shorthand for a "re
minder", an attempt to recall our thinking from running in grooves
that make it look as if we need constructive philosophy . 1 1
realm of law, the idea that came into focus with the rise of modern
science. Consider Kant's response to Hume. Hume had responded
with excessive enthusiasm to the disenchanting effect of modern nat
uralism; he thought nature had to be denied not only the intelligibility
of meaning but also the intelligibility of law. Against Hume, Kant
aims to regain for nature the intelligibility of law, but not the intelligi
bility of meaning. For Kant, nature is the realm of law and therefore
devoid of meaning. And given such a conception of nature, genuine
spontaneity cannot figure in descriptions of actualizations of natural
powers as such.
The point here is one of some delicacy. For Kant, the ordinary em
pirical world, which includes nature as the realm of law, is not exter
nal to the conceptual. In view of the connection between the concep
tual and the kind of intelligibility that belongs to meaning, l have
suggested that defending that Kantian thought requires a partial re
enchantment of nature. (See Lecture IV, §§3, 4. ) But it does not re
quire us to rehabilitate the idea that there is meaning in the fall of a
sparrow or the movement of the planets, as there is meaning in a text.
It is a good teaching of modernity that the realm of law is as such
devoid of meaning; its constituent elements are not linked to one an
other by the relations that constitute the space of reasons. But if our
thinking about the natural stops at an appreciation of that point, we
cannot properly comprehend the capacity of experience to take in
even the meaningless occurrences that constitute the realm of law. We
cannot satisfactorily splice spontaneity and receptivity together in our
conception of experience, and that means we cannot exploit the Kant
ian thought that the realm of law, not just the realm of meaningful
doings, is not external to the conceptual. The understanding-the
very capacity that we bring to bear on texts-must be involved in our
taking in of mere meaningless happenings.13
Kant's lack of a pregnant notion of second nature explains why the
right conception of experience cannot find a firm position in his think
ing. But it does not explain how, even so, he comes so close to the
right conception. At this point I think we must simply marvel at his
insight, especially in view of how the transcendental framework pre
vents the insight from taking proper form. And it is not that the tran
scendental framework is a gratuitous afterthought. In the absence of a
pregnant notion of second nature, the insight can appear only in that
distorted form.
If we conceive intuitions as products of disenchanted nature, and
spontaneity as non-natural, the closest we can get to the conception
we need is the Davidsonian position I discussed in my last lecture (§4):
spontaneity characterizes what are in fact operations of sentient na
ture, but it does not characterize them as such. That leaves us in our
familiar dilemma: either we must see our way to supposing that, even
so, operations of sentient nature can stand in rational relations to
thought (the Myth of the Given), or we must accept that sensibility
has no epistemological significance at all (a radical coherentism). In
effect Kant sees that this choice is intolerable. So spontaneity must
structure the operations of our sensibility as such. Since he does not
contemplate a naturalism of second nature, and since bald naturalism
has no appeal for him, he cannot find a place in nature for this re
quired real connection between concepts and intuitions. And in this
predicament, he can find no option but to place the connection out
side nature, in the transcendental framework.
Kant is peculiarly brilliant here. Even though he has no intelligible
way to deal with it, he manages to hold on to the insight that a merely
notional connection of concepts with intuitions will not do. That
forces him into a way out that is unintelligible by his own lights. The
real connection has to be that spontaneity is involved in the transcen
dental affection of receptivity by the supersensible. And now the good
thought that our sensibility opens us to a reality that is not external
to the conceptual can show up only in a distorted form, as if the
ordinary empirical world were constituted by appearances of a reality
beyond.
Alongside this strain to which Kant's thinking is subject, when he
tries to find a place for the essential insight about experience in the
lethal environment of a naturalism withou t second nature, we should
note another historical influence: the rise of Protestant individualism.
That brings with it a loss or devaluation of the idea that immersion in
a tradition might be a respectable mode of access to the real. Instead
it comes to seem incumbent on each individual thinker to check every
thing for herself. When particular traditions seem ossified or hide
bound, that encourages a fantasy that one should discard reliance on
tradition altogether, whereas the right response would be to insist that
Lecture V. A ction, Meaning, and the Self 99
5. If we could equip Kant with the idea of second nature, that would
not only free his insight about experience from the distorting effect of
the framework he tries to express it in; it would also allow the connec
tion between self-consciousness and consciousness of the world,
which figures in an equivocal way in his thinking, to take a satisfac
tory shape.
In the Transcendental Deduction, Kant seems to offer a thesis on
these lines: the possibility of understanding experiences, " from
within", as glimpses of objective reality is interdependent with the
subject's being able to ascribe experiences to herself; hence, with the
subject's being self-conscious.14
Now it would be satisfying if the self that is in question here were,
in the end at least, the ordinary self. But it is hard to make that cohere
with what Kant actually says. When he introduces the self-conscious
ness that he argues to be correlative with awareness of objective real
ity, he writes of the "I think" that must be able "to accompany all my
representations" .15 In the Paralogisms of Pure Reason, he claims that
if we credit this "I" with a persisting referent, the relevant idea of
identity through time is only formal. It has nothing to do with the
substantial identity of a subject who persists as a real presence in the
world she perceives. 1 6 The subjective temporal continuity that is a
14. For this reading of the Transcendental Deduction, see pp. 72-1 1 7 of Strawson, Tbe
Bounds of Sense.
1 5 . Critique of Pure Reason, B 1 3 1 .
1 6 . A363: "The identity of the consciousness o f myself a t different times i s . . . only a
formal condition of my thoughts and their coherence, and in no way proves the numerical
identity of my subject."
1 00 M I N D A N D W O R L D
the ego.
Consider Locke's account of what a person is: "a thinking intelli
gent being, that has reason and reflection, and can consider itself as
itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places" . 1 8 Locke
is talking about what he calls "consciousness" ; we might call it "self
consciousness" . "Consciousness" can hold together, in a single sur
vey, states and occurrences that are temporally separated; they are
conceived as belonging to the career of a continuant, a thinking thing.
To put the point in Kant's terms: in the "I think" that can "accom
pany all my representations", the reference of the "I" is understood as
reaching into the past and future. But Kant's point in the Paralogisms
is that the flow of what Locke calls "consciousness" does not involve
applying, or otherwise ensuring conformity with, a criterion of iden
tity.19 In the continuity of "consciousness" through time, there is what
appears to be knowledge of an identity, the persistence of an object
over a period; part of the content of the flow of "consciousness" is the
idea of a persisting referent for the "I" in the "I think" that can "ac
company all my representations". But when a subject makes this ap
plication of the idea of persistence, she needs no effort to ensure that
her attention stays fixed on the same thing. For a contrast, consider
keeping one's thought focused on an ordinary object of perception
over a period. That requires the ability to keep track of things, a skill
whose exercise we can conceive as a practical substitute for the ex
plicit application of a criterion of identity. Continuity of "conscious
ness" involves no analogue to this, no keeping track of the persisting
self that nevertheless seems to figure in its content.20
Varieties of Reference, p. 237. Evans (or more probably his editor) seems to slip when he
suggests that the point can be captured in terms of the idea of "immunity to error through
misidentification" , which he exploits elsewhere (pp. 179-9 1 ), in connection with perceptu
ally based demonstrative thinking. We have " immunity to error through misidentification"
when a predication is not attached to its subject by way of a judgement of identity. But as
Evans points out on p. 236, " identification-freedom" in that sense is consistent with a
j udgement's depending on keeping track of its object, the very thing he denies in the case of
self-consciousness. Keeping track serves as it were instead of an " identification compo
nent", in what underlies continuing demonstrative thought about objects of perception. The
point about the self is a peculiarly strong form of "identification-freedom".
1 02 M I N D A N D W O R L D
21. The Varieties of Reference, chap. 7 . Evans's thinking here can be seen as an elabora
tion of Strawson's remark, in his reading of the Paralogisms (The Bounds of Sense, p. 1 65 ) :
"'I' can b e used without criteria o f subject-identity a n d yet refer t o a subject because, even
in such a use, the links with those criteria are not severed."
22. This is what Strawson finds, at least in germ, in the Paralogisms.
Lecture V. Action, Meaning, and the Self 103
ferent for "I" (which is already a peculiar notion), how could it come
to appropriate a body, so that it might identify itself with a particular
living thing? Perhaps we can pretend to make sense of the idea that
such a subject might register a special role played by a particular body
in determining the course of its experience. But that would not pro
vide for it to conceive itself, the subject of its experience, as a bodily
element in objective reality-as a bodily presence in the world.
If Kant's connection between self-awareness and awareness of the
world is to leave it open to us to regain the idea that the subjects of
our experience are our ordinary selves, then the merely formal persis
tence of the I, in the "I think" that can "accompany all my represen
tations" , had better be only an abstraction from the ordinary substan
tial persistence of the living subject of experience. 23 It had better not
be something free-standing, which we might hope to build on in re
constructing the persistence of the ordinary self. But this does not
seem to fit Kant's conception of what he is doing. Kant takes himself
to be laying bare a necessary connection that is knowable a priori.24
And it would be hard to make the idea of an abstraction from the
persistence of the ordinary self cohere with the temporal connotations
he gives to "a priori", as when he suggests that transcendental self
consciousness "precedes all data of intuitions" (A107).
It is not surprising if Kant cannot get his thinking into the right
light. Why can there not be a free-standing idea of formal subjective
continuity? The answer is this: the idea of a subjectively continuous
series of states or occurrences in which conceptual capacities are im
plicated in sensibility-or, more generally, the idea of a subjectively
continuous series of exercises of conceptual capacities of any kind,
that is, the idea of a subjectively continuous series of " representa
tions" , as Kant would say-is just the idea of a singled out tract of a
life. The idea of a subjectively continuous series of " representations"
could no more stand alone, independent of the idea of a living thing in
whose life these events occur, than could the idea of a series of diges
tive events with its appropriate kind of continuity. But in the absence
of a serious notion of second nature, this exploitation of the concept
of life, which is a quintessentially natural phenomenon, to make sense
23. See Strawson's appeal to abstraction at pp. 103-4 of The Bounds of Sense.
24. See, for instance, Critique of Pure Reason, Al l6: "We are conscious a priori of the
complete identity of the self in respect of all representations which can ever belong to our
knowledge, as being a necessary condition of the pos!ii bility of all representations."
.. : _,
cent thinking about singular reference. There was a time when the
standard view of reference was inspired by Russell's Theory of De
scriptions. The idea was that whenever a thought is directed at a par
ticular object, part of its content is given by a specification of the ob
ject in general terms: conceptual terms, the equation I am considering
would lead us to say. The trend is to recoil from this.28 There are kinds
of object-directedness in thoughts that cannot easily be made to fit
that mould. For instance, a perceptual demonstrative thought surely
homes in on its object not by containing a general specification, with
the object figuring in the thought as what fits the specification, but by
virtue of the way this sort of thinking exploits the perceptible presence
of the object itself. If the conceptual is equated with the predicative,
this resistance to the general application of the Theory of Descriptions
takes the form of saying that in the cases that warrant the resistance,
singular reference is, or rests on, an extra-conceptual relation between
thinkers and things.29 So the picture is that the conceptual realm does
have an outside, which is populated by particular objects. Thought
makes contact with objects, from its location within the conceptual
realm, by exploiting relations such as perception, which are conceived
as penetrating the outer boundary of the conceptual.
This picture fits a contemporary view of singular reference that per
haps deserves to be counted as an orthodoxy. As I said, it can seem to
be Kantian. But in fact it is not Kantian at all. In Kant, the conceptual
realm has no outside; not unless we shift to the transcendental story,
and nobody thinks the objects that, say, demonstrative thoughts focus
on are noumenal. And in any case, the picture is really incoherent,
unless "conceptual" is serving as a mere synonym for "predicative" .
Circumscribing the conceptual realm can seem t o make interesting
sense only if the circumscribed realm is singled out as the realm of
28. Influential early proponents of this trend include Saul A. Kripke, "Naming and Ne
cessity", in Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, eds., Semantics of Natural Language
( Reidel, Dordrecht, 1 972), pp. 253-355, 763-9, reissued as a monograph by Basil Black
well, Oxford, 1980; and Keith S. Donnellan, " Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions",
ibid., pp. 356-79. See also, predating the trend, Ruth Barcan Marcus, " Modalities and In
tensional Languages", Synthese 27 ( 1962), 303-22.
29. For a striking exposition of a position on these lines, long predating the works usu
ally cited as initiating the contemporary trend, see. Geach, Mental Acts, S 15. For a more
recent expression of the idea that the relation between thought and individual things, in the
relevant sorts of case, is extra-conceptual, see Tyler Burge, "Belief De Re", Journal of Phi
losophy 74 (1 977), 338-62.
1 06 M I N D A N D W O R L D
30. See chap. 8 of Intentionality (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983). I dis·
cuss Searle's view of singular thought in "Intentionality De Re", in Ernest LePore and Rob
ert Van Gulick, eds., John Searle and His Critics (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1 99 1 ), pp. 2 1 5-
25. See also my "Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space", in Philip Pettit and John
McDowell, eds., Subject, Thought, and Context (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986), pp. 1 37-
68, for a more extensive consideration of the issues that are in play here.
3 1 . So it is quite wrong to lump Frege in with Russell as a target for the recoil from the
generalized Theory of Descriptions.
Lecture V. Action, Meaning, and the Self 1 07
ture of the space of reasons is sui generis, in comparison with the or
ganization of the realm of law. The spontaneity of the understanding
cannot be captured in terms that are apt for describing nature on that
conception, but even so it can permeate actualizations of our animal
nature. If we can see our way to accepting that, we can avoid the
philosophical difficulties while fully appreciating what makes them
gripping.
In Aristotle's conception of human beings, rationality is integrally
part of their animal nature, and the conception is neither naturalistic
in the modern sense (there is no hint of reductiveness or foundational
ism) nor fraught with philosophical anxiety. What makes. this possible
is that Aristotle is innocent of the very idea that nature is the realm of
law and therefore not the home of meaning. That conception of na
ture was laboriously brought into being at the time of the modern
scientific revolution.
I am not urging that we should try to regain Aristotle's innocence.
It would be crazy to regret the idea that natural science reveals a spe
cial kind of intelligibility, to be distinguished from the kind that is
proper to meaning. To discard that part of our intellectual inheritance
would be to return to mediaeval superstition. It is right to set a high
value on the kind of intelligibility we disclose in something when we
place it in the realm of law, and to separate it sharply from the intelli
gibility we disclose in something when we place it in the space of
reasons.
But instead of trying to integrate the intelligibility of meaning into
the realm of law, we can aim at a postlapsarian or knowing counter
part of Aristotle's innocence. We can acknowledge the great step for
ward that human understanding took when our ancestors formed the
idea of a domain of intelligibility, the realm of natural law, that is
empty of meaning, but we can refuse to equate that domain of intelli
gibility with nature, let alone with what is real.
The notion of second nature needs no particular emphasis in the
context of Aristotle's innocence, but it takes on a special significance
in this attempt to achieve a knowing counterpart. We are looking for
a conception of our nature that includes a capacity to resonate to the
structure of the space of reasons. Since we are setting our faces against
bald naturalism, we have to expand, nature beyond what is counte
nanced in a naturalism of the realm of law. But the expansion is lim
ited by the first nature, so to speak, of human animals, and by plain
1 10 M I N D A N D W O R L D
1. In view of how I exploited Strawson's reading of Kant in my last lecture, this remark
implies that Strawson's Kant is more Hegel than Kant. For a reading of Hegel that takes
very seriously Hegel's own idea that his philosophy completes a Kantian project, see Rohert
•
B. Pippin, Hegel's Idealism.
1 12 M I N D A N D W O R L D
mere animals are not genuinely sentient? To deal with this, I want to
borrow from Hans-Georg Gadamer a remarkable description of the
difference between a merely animal mode of life, in an environment,
and a human mode of life, in the world.4 For my purposes, the point
of this is that it shows in some detail how we can acknowledge what
is common between human beings and brutes, while preserving the
difference that the Kantian thesis forces on us.
In mere animals, sentience is in the service of a mode of life that is
structured exclusively by immediate biological imperatives. That is
not to imply that the life is restricted to a struggle to keep the individ
ual and the species going. There can be immediate biological impera
tives that are at most indirectly connected with survival and reproduc
tion: for instance, the impulse to play, which is found in many
animals.5 But without falling into that kind of restrictiveness, we can
recognize that a merely animal life is shaped by goals whose control of
the animal's behaviour at a given moment is an immediate outcome of
biological forces. A mere animal does not weigh reasons and decide
what to do. Now Gadamer's thesis is this: a life that is structured only
in that way is led not in the world, but only in an environment. For a
creature whose life has only that sort of shape, the milieu it lives in can
be no more than a succession of problems and opportunities, consti
tuted as such by those biological imperatives.
When we acquire conceptual powers, our lives come to embrace
not just coping with problems and exploiting opportunities, consti
tuted as such by immediate biological imperatives, but exercising
spontaneity, deciding what to think and do. A naturalism of second
nature allows us to put it like that; we can take in our stride something
that is problematic in the context of a different sort of naturalism, that
these exercises of freedom are elements in our lives, our careers as
living and therefore natural beings. Of course it had better not be that
our being in charge of our lives marks a transcendence of biology; that
looks like a version of the rampant platonist fantasy. But we do not
fall into rampant platonism if we say the shape of our lives is no
longer determined by immediate biological forces. To acquire the
7. I shall cite from the translation of David Mclellan, in Karl Marx: Early Texts (Basil
Blackwell, Oxford, 1 972), pp. 1 33-45.
8 . The convergence is surely not a coincidence. It reflects a Hegelian influence on both
texts.
1 18 M I N D A N D W O R L D
ent sensory and practical reach: as where one happens to be, in con
trast with other places where one might be.
And of course there is more than that to coming to possess the
world. For instance, possessing the world shows also in the pointless
knowable detail that one's current environment typically makes avail
able to one. Consider the richness of a normal adult human being's
visual field, which is far beyond anything that could matter for a ca
pacity to cope with merely animal needs. Marx says man is unique in
producing "according to the laws of beauty " (p. 1 40), and the point
he is making in that remark shows up also here, in a distinctive feature
of our consciousness. Our very experience, in the aspect of its nature
that constitutes it as experience of the world, partakes of a salient
condition of art, its freedom from the need to be useful.
problem about bats is that our imagination cannot extend to how the
conversion into conceptual form would go, in the case of the content
yielded by the echo-locating capacity. So the picture is that mere ani
mals only receive the Given, whereas we not only receive it but are
also able to put it into conceptual shape. To think like that is to set
one's foot on a familiar philosophical treadmill. 1 1
7 . How has i t come about that there are animals that possess the
spontaneity of understanding? That is a perfectly good question.
There was a time when there were no rational animals. Suppose we
had a credible account of how forces that are intelligibly operative in
nature might have led to the evolution of animals with conceptual
powers. That would definitively avert a form of rampant platonism:
the idea that our species acquired what makes it special, the capacity
to resonate to meaning, in a gift from outside nature. If we took that
seriously, we would have to suppose that when succeeding genera
tions are initiated into responsiveness to meaning, what happens is
that upbringing actualizes a potential for the development of an extra
natural ingredient, a potential implanted in the species in the sup
posed extra-natural evolutionary event.
But this request for an evolutionary story need not look very press
ing. Evolutionary speculation is not a context in which rampant
platonism is somehow particularly tempting. Reflection about the
Bildung of individual human beings should be enough to distinguish
the naturalized platonism I have recommended from rampant platon
ism. And in this reflection we can regard the culture a human being is
initiated into as a going concern; there is no particular reason why we
should need to uncover or speculate about its history, let alone the
origins of culture as such. Human infants are mere animals, distinctive
only in their potential, and nothing occult happens to a human being
in ordinary upbringing. If we locate a variety of platonism in the con
text of an account of Bildung that insists on those facts, we thereby
ensure that it is not a rampant platonism. Mere ignorance about how
1 1 . Nagel could have made many of the points he wanted without leaving the domain of
subjectivity properly so called (by my lights). Perhaps Martians have an echo-locating ca
pacity, which ligures in the rational basis of their world-view in the way our senses do in the
basis of ours. I have no need to deny that there might be concepts anchored in sensory
capacities so alien to ours that the concepts would be unintelligible to us. What I am object
ing to is only the way this point gets focused, in the case of bats, on a supposed non-concep
tual content that we cannot convert inro conceptual shape.
... � .. '
. . -
human culture might have come on the scene in the first place is hardly
a plausible starting point for an argument that initiation into it must
actualize an extra-natural• potential in human beingsY
And in any case, if we do speculate about how animals might have
evolved into a way of living that includes initiating their young into a
culture, we must be clear that that is what we are doing. It would be
one thing to give an evolutionary account of the fact that normal
human maturation includes the acquisition o ( a second nature, which
involves responsiveness to meaning; it would be quite another thing to
give a constitutive account of what responsiveness to meaning is. I
have been granting that it is reasonable to look for an evolutionary
story. This is not a concession to the sort of constructive philosophical
& account of meaning that I discussed in my last lecture (§3): something
whose point would be to make the relevant sort of intelligibility safe
for a naturalism without second nature. That is a misbegotten idea,
and there is no comfort for it here.
1 2. It is true, however, that the good questions we can raise in the evolutionary context
come as dose as good questions can to the philosophical questions I want to exorcize.
13. See "Can Analytical Philosophy be Systematic, and Ought lr to Be?", in his Truth
mrd Other Enigmas (Duckworth, London, 1 978), pp. 437-5 8. At p. 442 Dummett writes:
" for frege, as for all subsequent analytical philosophers, the philosophy of language is the
foundation of all other philosophy beca use it is only by the ana lysis of language that we can
ana lyse thought."
1 4. Critique of Pure Reason. A51/B7 5.
Lecture VI. Rational and Other Animals 1 25
Davidson in Context
only for whole systems, and that means that the "empirical
significance" of a world-view cannot amount to its empirical content
in the sense of how, in• adopting the world-view, one takes things to
be in the empirical world. That requires the other factor, the endo-
genous one, also.
So far, this might be merely a terminological oddity about Quine's
use of the phrase "empirical significance". It is Quine's own point that
"empirical significance" does not amount t� content, in the sense of
what stand one takes on how things are in the empirical world. In the
thesis that translation is indeterminate, which is meant to elaborate
the moral of "Two Dogmas", his aim is to stress "the extent of man's
conceptual sovereignty" in the formation of world-views:2 that is-to
put it in a way that brings Quine into explicit contact with Kant-the
extent to which the content of world-views is a product of spontaneity
operating freely, uncontrolled by the deliverances of receptivity. And
from Quine's point of view, it is a merit of the notion of "empirical
significance" that it stands on the wrong side of the descendant dual
ity to be a descendant of the old notion of meaning. Quine is no friend
to the old notion of meaning, and the descendant notion, the notion
of "language" as the endogenous factor, bound up as it is with "man's
conceptual sovereignty", retains in Quine's thinking some of the in
tellectual dubiousness of its ancestor. In contrast, "empirical signifi
cance" is an intellectually respectable notion, because it is explicable
entirely in terms of the law-governed operations of receptivity, un
tainted by the freedom of spontaneity. To put it in a more Quinean
way, "empirical significance" can be investigated scientifically. "The
extent of man's conceptual sovereignty", the extent to which the con
tent of a world-view goes beyond its "empirical significance", is just
the extent to which such a notion of content lies outside the reach of
science, and therefore outside the reach of first-rate intellectual en
deavour.
It is not just a verbal point that "empirical significance" is on the
wrong side of the duality to be a descendant of the notion of meaning.
We have to discount the rhetoric that makes it look, at first sight, as if
Quine's notion corresponds to the Kantian notion of empirical con
tent. Quine speaks of facing the tribunal of experience, which seems
2. Word and Object (MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1 960), p. 5. For the indeterminacy
thesis, see chap. 2 of that work.
Afterword, Part I 1 33
sensory receptors is all the evidence anybody has had to go on, ultimately, in arriving ;lt his
picture of the world." This sentence begins with a formulation that would lit onI)· 'om<··
thing outside the order of j ustification, but continues ( " has had to go on . . . in arrivin�: at
his picture of the world") in a way that would make sense only of something within the
order of justification. What one goes on in arriving at one's picture of the world is not the
stimulation of one's sensory receptors, experience as Quine officially conceives it, but how
things appear to one, which belongs in a quite different conception of experience.
6. For a much fuller discussion of Quine's thinking on these lines, see chap. 6 of Barry
Stroud, The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1 984 ), to
which I am much indebted.
7. This is how Rorty reads Quine; see chap. 4 of Philosophy and the Mirror of Nuture.
(I capitalize "Given", as throughout, to contrast the problematic conception with one that
is innocuous; see Lecture I, §4.)
8. "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind", p. JQO.
136 .\1 I � D A N D W 0 R L D
its freedom of play, but it operates within limits set from outside its
domain.
1 1 . Christopher Hookway and, in a different way, Aryeh Frankfurter urged this on me.
Afterword, Part I 139
12. The poinr does not turn on the detail of Quine's conception of experience, as stimu
lation of sensory surfaces . There can be less resolut.ly ami-mentalistic conceptions of expc·
rience that nevenh.less match Quine's conception at a more a bstract level, in that they take
.experiences to be deliverances of receptiviry. Davidson's general thought is that if experi
ence is understood as what receptiviry provides us with, then, whatever the details of the
conception, experience is eo ipso understood in a way that removes it from the space of
reasons.
1 40 M I N D A N D W O R L D
distinguish impressions from bits o f the Given, and Sellars effects this
by carefully refusing to attribute any direct epistemological
significance to impressions. They have an indirect epistemological
significance, in that without them there could not be such directly
significant circumstances as seeing that things are thus and so, or hav
ing it look to one as if things are thus and so. But it is only in that
indirect way that impressions enter into the rational responsiveness of
empirical thinking to the course of experience. We can have an inno
cent interpretation of the idea that empirical thinking is rationally re
sponsive to the course of experience, but only by understanding "the
course of experience" to mean the succession of appearings, not the
succession of impressions.
Impressions are, by definition we might say, receptivity in opera
tion. So the picture that is common to Sellars and Davidson is this.
Receptivity figures in the explanatory background of circumstances
that belong together with evolving world-views in the order of
justification. But receptivity itself cannot rationally interact with
spontaneity, in the way that Quine's rhetoric implies, though his offi
cial conception of receptivity precludes such interaction.
Against this, I claim that although Quine's half-hearted attempt to
picture world-views as products of a rational interaction between
spontaneity and receptivity is unacceptable, as Davidson sees, that is
no reason to discard the very idea of such an interaction. The trouble
lies not in the idea itself, but in the half-heartedness-in the fact that
while the rhetoric depicts the interaction as rational, Quine conceives
receptivity in such a way that it cannot impinge rationally on any
thing. We can have a whole-hearted version of the idea if we can see
our way to saying that the impressions of the world on our senses, the
deliverances of our receptivity, are-as such-the appearings (or at
least some of them) that, as Davidson and Sellars agree, can inno
cently be taken to belong together with our world-views in the space
of reasons, since they are already in the space of concepts. That way,
we can hold on to the attractive thought that Quine only half
heartedly embraces. There really is a prospect of finding empirical
content, as possessed by exercises of spontaneity, unmysterious if we
can think of it on the lines that Davidson and Sellars disallow, and
that Quine is officially committed t'o disallowing. We ought to have
no problem about how an exercise of "conceptual sovereignty" can
bear on the empirical world-can constitute taking a stand on how
1 42 M I N D A N D W O R L D
17. "Entitle" matters here. Rorty (whom I shall come to shortly) is very good at debunk
ing the moves that are available if we suppose there are such problems for philosophy.
Perhaps the uselessness of the moves indicates, as it were from the outside, that this concep
tion of philosophy's task must be mistaken. But this external approach can easily leave the
philosophical questions still looking as if they ought to be good ones, and then the result is
continuing philosophical discomfort, not an exorcism of philosophy. Exorcism requires a
different kind of move, which Rorty is much less good at.
Afterword, Part I 1 43
But that is quite distinct from saying, as my picture allows and the
picture common to Sellars and Davidson does not, that the belief that
an object has an observable property can be grounded in an impres
sion itself: the fact's impressing itself on the subject. In my picture
impressions are, so to speak, transparent. In the picture common to
Sellars and Davidson they are opaque: if one knows enough about
one's causal connections with the world, one can argue from them to
conclusions about the world, but they do not themselves disclose the
world to one. They have an epistemological significance like that of
bodily feelings in diagnosing organic ailments. And my claim is that
that undermines Davidson's aim of eliminating mystery. If we cannot ·
conceive impressions as transparent, we distance the world too far
from our perceptual lives to be able to keep mystery out of the idea
that our conceptual lives, including appearings, involve empirical con
tent.
In the style of thinking I have been attacking, impressions need not
be separated from appearings as causes and effects. Another version
of the picture might allow one form of the claim that appearings (at
least some of them) are impressions. What would make this still a
version of the picture that I am attacking would be an insistence that
something's being an appearing must be at a conceptual remove from
something's (perhaps, in this version of the picture, the same thing's)
being an impression. The identification of one and the same thing as
both an impression and an appearing would straddle the boundary
between two radically different modes of conceptualization; we
would have to insist that it is not by virtue of being the impression it
is that an item is the appearing it is. This version of the picture might
be more congenial to Davidson than the version I have been working
with, according to which impressions belong in the explanatory back
ground of appearings; that seems to be Sellars's line.
As my counting it a version of the same picture implies, I do not
believe identifying appearings with impressions in this way makes any
difference to the main point. It will still be true, in the context of the
identification understood like this, that impressions as such are
opaque. If an item that is an impression is credited with empirical con
tent, because it is said to be also an appearing, it is not supposed to be
by virtue of being the impression it · is that it possesses that content.
This is just another way of refusing to countenance a rational engage
ment between spontaneity and receptivity as such, and I think it still
146 M I N D A N D W O R L D
20. The point here is of a piece with something I suggest in Lecture IV, §4.
2 1 . In M Afterthoughts, 1 987" (in Alan Malachowski, ed., Reading Rorty [Blackwell,
Oxford, 1 990]), Davidson attributes to Rorty the claim that Ml should not pretend that I am
answering the skeptic when I am really telling him to get lost", and says Ml pretty much
concur with him " .
Afterword, Part I 147
23. From p. 51 of "True to the Facts", in Inquiries into Truth atrd Interpretation,
pp. 37-54; quoted by Rorry at p. 343.
24. For the generalization, see pp. 10-13 of Quine's Philosophy of Logic (Prentice-Hall,
Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1 970).
Afterword, Part I 1 49
stories are there to be told; the worry is precisely about the thesis that
they cannot be told together. That implies that if we occupy a stand
point from which our beliefs are in view along with their objects and
our causal engagements with the objects, then we cannot, from that
standpoint, bring the beliefs under the norms of inquiry. And
Putnam's worry about this is well placed: the result is to make it a
mystery how what we are talking about can be beliefs, stances with
respect to how things are in the world, at all. It does not help to insist,
as Rorty does, that there is another standpoint from which beliefs are
seen as subject to the norms of inquiry. If the view from this second
standpoint is not allowed to embrace the causal interactions between
believers and the objects of their beliefs-since those interactions are
the preserve of the outside view, which has to be held separate-then
it simply becomes mysterious how we can be entitled to conceive what
organizes the subject matter of the second standpoint as the norms of
mqmry.
The point comes out vividly in the way Rorty deals with disquota
tion. There is an obvious connection between disquotation, whether
in the strict or in the extended sense, and a straightforward notion of
getting things right. It is because "La neige est blanche" is true in
French if and only if snow is white that, since snow is indeed white, I
shall be getting things right if I express a belief in French by saying " La
neige est blanche". Rorty's remarks about disquotation give the field
linguist, the occupant of the outside point of view, responsibility for
the question whether beliefs achieve truth in the sense of disquotabil
ity. The question whether a belief achieves disquotability is supposed
to be descriptive as opposed to normative, and Rorty's picture keeps
it apart from any question we address in our capacity as "earnest
seekers after truth"-in our efforts to be responsive to what we
should like to think of as the norms of inquiry. But this severs what
we want to think of as responsiveness to the norms of inquiry from
any connection with that unproblematic notion of getting things right.
And the effect is to make it unintelligible how it can be norms of in
quiry that are in question. Norms of inquiry are normative for the
process of inquiry precisely because disquotability is the norm for its
results.
Amazingly enough, Rorty seems to think it is merely routine to sep
arate what we want to think of as norms of inquiry from the straight
forward notion of getting things right that is connected with the no-
Afterword, Part I 151
27. I echo the engaging title of Rorty's "The World Well Lost" , in his Consequences of
Pragmatism (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1982), pp. 3-1 8. Tha t paper
stands to Davidson's "On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme" much as " Pragmatism,
Davidson, and Truth" stands to "A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge".
1 52 M I N D A N D W O R L D
tions. But in another sense the refusal is arbitrary, since Rorty's own
thinking, so far from being shaped so that the questions cannot arise,
positively exacerbates theic apparent pressingness.
Rorty's assignment of truth as disquotability to the outside point of
view is also quite unsatisfying as a reading of Davidson.
It is true that the data available to a Davidsonian field linguist,
when she begins on radical interpretation of a l�nguage, are restricted
to vocal or otherwise putatively linguistic behaviour, with its causal
connections to the environment. As long as the language, if that is
what it is, has not been interpreted, the linguist has no handle on
what, if anything, its speakers count as a reason for what, though she
can observe which environmental circumstances are likely to prompt
them to which vocalizations or other putatively linguistic actions.
While the interpreter is in this position, it cannot yet stand quite firm
for her that what is in question is linguistic behaviour at all; that de
pends on the behaviour's turning out to be interpretable-that is, ca
pable of being intelligibly placed in the space of reasons.
But that is how it is only at the outset of radical interpretation. The
field linguist's aim is not merely to codify those causally connected
data, or to construct a theory that postulates further connections of
the same kind, so as to make the data intelligible in the way a theory
in the natural sciences makes intelligible the data it is based on. Ex
actly not: Davidson's field linguist aims to work into an appreciation,
as from within, of the norms that constitute the language she investi
gates: the specific sense of when it is right to say what according to
which that language-game is played. That is what she aims to capture
in a theory for the language that is disquotational in the extended
sense. She begins as an occupant of the outside standpoint, but if she
succeeds in her aim, she ends up equipped to give expression in her
own terms to part of how things look from the inside standpoint her
su bjects occupied all along. When Rorty suggests that the results of
the field linguist's endeavours employ a notion of truth unconnected
with norms, and hence separated-by the supposed gulf between the
two standpoints-from, for instance, a conception in which the truth
is seen as what ought to be believed ("the normative uses seized upon
by James" ), he obliterates the significance of the transition from start
ing predicament to achieved interpretation.
The outside standpoint as Rorty conceives it is a standpoint from
sideways on. (For that image, see Lecture II, §4.) Davidson's radical
Afterword, Part I 1 53
7. When Rorty insists that the two points of view must be kept sepa
rate, that is an expression of a dualism of nature and reason. In this ver
sion of the dualism, nature figures as the subject matter of the outside
view, and the space of reasons figures as the normative organization that
things have when they are seen from the inside view; what is dualistic is
insisting that the two modes of organization cannot be combined.
In the lectures, I point to the dualism of nature and reason as the
source of the merely apparent difficulties confronted by traditional
philosophy. I find the dualism operative in Davidson's thinking: it ac
counts for his attitude to the idea that spontaneity interacts rationally
with receptivity. So I am not in a position to dissent outright from
Rorty's reading of Davidson. But in my reading, Davidson's vulnera
bility to the dualism is a defect; it is out of line with his better thinking
on interpretation, and it ensures failure in the aim of exorcizing tradi
tional philosophical anxieties. In contrast, Rorty centres his reading of
28. Rorty is not alone in supposing that the sideways-on character of the radical
interpreter's starting orientation-what makes the interpretation radical-persists into the
results of radical interpretation. See Charles Taylor, "Theories of Meaning", in his Human
Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers, 1 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
1 985), pp. 248-92, especially pp. 273-82. Taylor takes it that Davidson's thinking ex
cludes Gadamer's idea of a fusion of horiwns. (See Lecture II, S4.) Like Rorty, Taylor
thinks Davidson's approach to interpretation is inextricably committed to an outside point
of view. And Cora Diamond seems to suggest something similar, at pp. 1 1 2-3 of "What
Nonsense Might Be", in her The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind
(MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1 99 1 ), pp. 95- 1 1 4. I think such readings miss the distance
between Davidson and Quine. (Davidson may be partly to blame for this, because of the
way he systematically understates that distance. I say something about this at p. 73 of my
"In Defence of Modesty", in Barry Taylor, ed., Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philo
sophy [Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, 1 987], pp. 59-80.)
1 54 M I N D A N D W O R L D
It is ironic that I can put things like this. Rorty begins "Pragmatism,
Davidson, and Truth" with an admiring description of pragmatism,
into which he wants to enrol Davidson, as "a movement which has
specialized in debunking dualisms and in dissolving traditional prob
lems created by those dualisms" _{p. 333). But Rorty's own thinking is
organized around the dualism of reason and nature, and that means
he can be at best partly successful in being a pragmatist in his own
sense. No wonder his attempt to dissolve traditional problems has the
aspect of refusing to listen to questions that still stubbornly look as if
they ought to be good ones, rather than supplying a way of thinking
within which the questions genuinely do not arise.
Of course Rorty does not cast his view about nature and reason as
a dualism. He speaks, for instance, of "patiently explaining that
norms are one thing and descriptions another" (p. 347). That sounds
like calmly drawing a distinction; it is not the obsessive mode of utter
ance characteristic of a philosopher insisting on a dualism. But I have
been urging that if we try to think as Rorty says we must, we are stuck
with the philosophical anxieties that he wants to avoid. Cultivating a
non-obsessive tone of voice is not enough to ensure that philosophical
obsessions are out of place.
I cited Rorty's suggestion that Putnam wants "a synoptic vision
which will somehow synthesize every other possible view, will some
how bring the outside and the inside points of view together". Rorty
means to accuse Putnam of the grandiose aspirations of traditional
philosophy, which he thinks we should discard: thought is to be
brought into alignment with its objects, minds with reality. My sug
gestion has been that bringing the outside and the inside points of
view together (not " somehow", which suggests a mystery) is exactly
the sort of dualism-debunking and problem-dissolving move for
which Rorty himself admires pragmatism. So what I recommend in
29. I do not mean to suggest that we can easily isolate the dualism's role in motivating
Davidson's coherentism. It is also at work elsewhere in his thinking: notably in the thesis
that causal relations can hold between occupants of the space of reasons only because they
can be identified with elements in the realm of law. (Compare Rorty's analogue to this
thesis: it is only in the inside view that items are placed in the space of reasons, and causal
relations are not present in that view at all.) This Davidsonian thesis is at issue in Lecture
IV, S4.
Afterword, Part I 1 55
30. This might give one pause about Rorty's attitude to such thinkers. Moves in the
language of traditional philosophy can be aimed at having the right not to worry about its
· problems, rather than at solving those problems. I think Rorty is insufficiently alive to this
possibiliry.
3 1 . The idea of a transcendental constitution of consciousness sounds harder to reha bi 1-
itate, but perhaps even that would not be impossible; see the previous footnote .
•
1 56 M I N D A N D W O R L D
tradition figures at the end of Lecture VI.) Rorry suggests (p. 344) that
" intentionalistic notions'� just as such breed unhealthy philosophical
worries ("inserting imaginary barriers between you and the world");
in the context of a pragmatism less half-baked than Rorty achieves,
that suggestion can stand exposed as absurd. 32
32. No doubt Rorty is encouraged here by the example of Quine. But to the extent that
Quinean suspicion of the intentional is more than mere scientism, its basis is thorou11hly
undercut by the debunking of the third dogma. See S9 below.
Afterword, Part I 1 57
34. See "Leaving the World Alone", Journal of Philosophy 79 ( 1 982), 382-403.
35. Perhaps this is the category in which we should place at least some of the "hinge
propositions" to which Wittgenstein attributes a special significance in On Certainty (Basil
Blackwell, Oxford, 1969).
Afterword, l'art 1
1 . See, for instance, p. 7: "The thinker must . . . be disposed to form the belief for the
reason that the object is so presented." Here it is not something with non-conceptual con
tent that is said to lie further out than a belief on my in-out dimension. But when, in a
context in which non-conceptual content is in play, Peacocke writes of "perceptual experi
ences that give good reasons for judging . . . (certain conceptual) contents" (p. 66), he must
mean that the judging is done for those reasons, as in the formulation on p. 7.
2. Similarly with " for the reason that" at p. 7, where it is not non-conceptual content
that is supposed to figure further out than belief on my in-out dimension. A parallel defence
of "for the reason that" here would require the subject to have the concept of sensational
properties of regions of the visual field. Peacocke is sketching a candidate account of what
it is to possess the concept red, and he would not dream of suggesting that anyone who
possesses that concept must have the concept of sensational properties of regions of the
visual field.
Afterword, Part II 1 65
reason might have to be less specific, perhaps " Because of the way it
looks" . But this makes no difference to the essential point. Here, too,
the reason is articulable (even if only in the form " It looks like that"),
s o it must b e no less conceptual than what it i s a reason for.
The routine point is really no more than that there can be rational
relations between its being the case that P and its being the case that
Q (in a limiting case what replaces " Q " can simply be what replaces
"P"). It does not follow that something whose content is given by the
fact that it has the correctness condition that P can eo ipso be
someone's reason for, say, j udging that Q, independently of whether
the content is conceptual or not. We can bring into view the rational
relations between the contents-its being the case that P and its being
the case that Q-only by comprehending the putatively grounding
content in conceptual terms, even if our theory is that the item that has
that content does not do its representing in a conceptual way. A the
ory like Peacocke's does not credit ordinary subjects with this compre
hensive view of the two contents, and I think that leaves it unintelligi
ble how an item with the non-conc.::p tual content that P can be
someone's reason for judging that Q.3
what someone thinks when she thinks that something is red. And
Peacocke wants his accoutits to bear on such questions. That is why
an account of an observational concept must place employments of
the concept in the space of reasons, even though the non-circularity
requirement compels Peacocke to hold that the experiences that con
stitute the rational basis of employments of such concepts are outside
the space of concepts.
What is at issue here is whether it is in general possible to give side
ways-on accounts of concepts, in the sense that figures in Lecture II,
§4, and in my discussion of Rorty earlier in this Afterword (Part I,
§6). The non-circularity requirement is in effect an insistence on side
ways-on accounts. In Lecture II, I deny, in effect, that sideways-on
accounts of concepts are in general possible. I cannot see that
Peacocke gives any reason to suppose that is wrong. In fact this seems
to work the wrong way round for him. In § 1 above, I urged that it is
difficult to see how experiences, conceived as Peacocke conceives
them, could constitute a believer's reasons for believing something.
This suggests I was right to deny that sideways-on accounts are possi
ble; the problem for the motivated thought tends to undermine the
• motivating thought.
Peacocke's proposed accounts are indeed offered as accounts of
what it is to possess this or that concept, and they talk of beliefs or
judgements, which figure in the accounts as having contents that em
ploy the concepts in question. But that does not mean that the ac
counts are not from sideways on in my sense. What is true is that the
accounts explicitly represent themselves as being about thinkers, users
of the concepts in question. But they do not say-indeed they carefully
refrain from saying-what the thinkers think when they use the con
cepts in question. Avoidance of circularity requires the accounts to
come at what the thinkers think only from the outside, identifying it
as something that one thinks when . . . , where what follows "when"
is a condition external to possession of the concept. The accounts em
body the claim that there is an inside view, but they are not given from
it. Peacocke is responsive to the suspicion that this externality threat
ens the project of capturing content. He thinks he can meet the threat
by linking the external condition to the thinking not j ust with "when"
but also with " for the reason that". However, I have urged, in § 1
above, that the required externality undermines the very intelligibility,
here, of "for the reason that". So I see no reason to give up, or qualify,
Afterword, Part II 1 69
the claim I made in Lecture II. I see no reason to suppose, and plenty
of reason not to suppose, that it is always possible to give accounts of
concepts in conformity with the non-circularity requirement.6
Non-circular accounts might be available, so far as these consider
ations go, in cases where what follows "when and for the reason
that . . . " can be a mention of conceptual states whose content in
volves concepts other than the one of which an account is being given;
that is, cases in which a concept can be captured in terms of how em
ployments of it are rationally grounded in employments of other con
cepts. But that is of course exactly not how it is with observational
concepts. These non-circular accounts would be given not from a side
ways-,on orientation to the whole conceptual realm, but only from
outside the conceptual capacities of which they are accounts; whereas
Peacocke's proposed accounts of observational concepts would be
given from outside the conceptual realm altogether.
Is my scepticism about accounts that do everything Peacocke wants
some kind of obscurantism? Peacocke makes a suggestion to that ef
fect at pp. 3 5-6:
Theories are developing in the literature of what it is to possess certain
specific concepts: the first person, logical notions, and many others.
While there is much that is still not understood and not all of what has
been said is right, it is hard to accept that the goal of this work is com
pletely misconceived. On the contrary, there are often phenomena
specific to the concept treated that are explained by these accounts.
McDowell would not let us say that these accounts are theories of what
it is to possess these concepts. But I cannot see what else they can be, and
we can hardly just dismiss them.
A lot depends here on what "the goal of this work" really is. We are
not restricted to just two options: either accepting that the presuppo
sitions of this undismissable work are made explicit in Peacocke's de
siderata for a theory of concepts, avoidance of circularity and all; or
6. What I was driving at in "In Defence of Modesty" was this denial that the sideways-on
perspective can capture concepts. I cannot recognize my side of the debate in Peacocke's
representation, at pp. 33-0. As Peacocke puts what he takes to be my point, it ought to be
satisfiable by a sideways-on story, so long as the story announces itself as being about
thoughts. My point was that one cannot fix what is thought from the outside, identifying it
only as something that one thinks when . . . ; and I do not believe it helps to add " for the
reason that. . . (Dummett makes much of the claim that the connections are rational in
w.
his response to me: see pp. 260-2 of " Reply to McDowell", in Taylor, ed., Michael
Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy, pp. 253-68 . )
1 70 M I N D A N D W O R L D
3. Evans claims that we do not have enough concepts of, say, colours
for it to be possible that the content of our visual experience is concep
tual. In Lecture III, §5, I urge, against that, that we can express all the
concepts we need, in order to capture the finest detail of our colour
experience, by utterances of "that shade ". We do not have all these
concepts in advance, but we do have whichever we need, exactly when
we need them.
An utterance of " that shade" depends for its meaning on the iden
tity of a sample shade. We might lay down the rule that something
counts as having that shade j ust in case it is indiscriminable in colour
from the indicated sample. (Of course we can actually say something
in these terms only in the presence of a sample.)
Now there is a familiar pitfall here. It may be tempting to lay down
a second rule as well: that something counts as having a shade if it is
indiscriminable in colour from something else that counts as having
that shade. ·But if we say that, we run afoul of a sorites paradox: we
undermine the idea that utterances of "that shade" can express a de
terminate meaning at all, because indiscriminability in colour is not
A{terwura, (urt 11
7. I see no need for the apparatus Peacocke introduces in response to the sorites threat,
pp. 83-4.
1 72 .\ ! ! :-; D A :-.; D \\ 0 R L D
8. "I see it in my mind's eyeH embodies a picture. The proper attitude to it is like the one
Wittgenstein expresses, in Philosophical Investigations, §427, to the picture embodied in
saying things like "While I was speaking to him I did not know what was going on in his
head. H Wittgenstein says: "The picture should be taken seriously. We should really like to
see into his head. And yet we only mean what elsewhere we should mean by saying: we
should like to know what he is thinking. H Taking this picture literally, and even supposing
it is somehow intellectually obligatory to do so, is depressingly common in contemporary
philosophy of mind.
9. A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Clarendon
Press, Oxford, 1978), 1 . 1 . 1 .
1 74 M I N D A N D W O R L D
Postscrip t to Lecture V
which it looks like a task for philosophy to shoehorn into the world
something as close as we can get to our previous conception of
meaning. But philosophy's task is rather to dislodge the assump
tions that make it look difficult to find a place for meaning in the
world. Then we can take in our stride meaning's role in shaping our
lives. We do not need a constructive legitimizing of its place in our
conception of ourselves.
Wittgenstein aims to cast suspicion on an aura of mystery that cer
tain thoughts about meaning acquire in an uncongenial environment.
The thoughts are thoughts like this: the meaning o f, say, an instruc
tion that specifies an arithmetical series, for instance the instruction
"Add 2", " determines the steps in advance" (compare Philosophical
Investigations, § 1 90), in such a way that-to bring the thought into
direct connection with Wright's concerns-the fact that such-and
such a move is the correct one at a certain point in the expansion of
the series does not depend on ratification by the relevant community,
those who count as understanding the instruction. Such a thought
can seem uncanny, as if it credited meaning with magical powers.
Wright's mistake is to take it that Wittgenstein means to cast suspi
cion on such thoughts themselves. But Wittgenstein's target is the at
mosphere of uncanniness. The thought itself is all right. 1
The contrast between rampant and naturalized platonism helps to
bring out this possibility. The relevant thoughts are platonistic, and if
we can envisage only a rampant platonism the aura of uncanniness is
inescapable; our only recourse is a philosophical construction in
which we pull in our horns, about objectivity or whatever. But the
2. I elaborate a reading on these lines, with more detailed reference to Wittgenstein than
seemed appropriate in these lectures, in � Meaning and Intentionality in Wittgenstein's Later
Phi!osophyft, in Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., an-1 Howard K. Wettstein, eds.,
Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vo!. 17: The Wittgenstein Legacy (University of Notre
Dame Press, Notre Dame, 1992), pp. 42-52. For kindred thoughts, see Cora Diamond, The
Realistic Spirit. At p. 6, she describes one of her targets like this: "Wittgenstein's criticism
of . • . mythology or fantasy-in particular, his criticism of the mythology attached to logi
cal necessity-is read as if it were rejection of the mythology as a false notion of how things
are."
3. I have been persuaded here by James Conant and Lisa Van Alstyne.
1 78 M I N D A N D W O R L D
could ever have such a frame of mind as a permanent and stable pos
session. Even so, this identification of a source for our apparent diffi
culties can be one of our resources for overcoming recurrences of the
philosophical impulse: recurrences that we know there will be.
Postscript to Lecture VI
way that disenchants it. But for him that reflects a merely optional
and, from his intellectual standpoint, not very well supported-view
of the most fundamental understanding. He does not have to resist a
temptation to let the label " nature" affix itself to something that he is
anyway intellectually committed to countenancing as what is compre
hended by scientific understanding. Aristotle has no inkling of a per
fectly correct thought that we can formulate like this: if we identify
nature as the topic of scientific understanding, we must see it as disen
chanted.1
3. Not just the respect due to an effective instrument, which is enough to account for
recoiling when people misuse words like "disinterested" or "careen". The respect I mean is
the respect that is due to something to which we owe our being what we are. (Of course
what we do with our language can change it; for instance, what was misuse can cease to be
misuse. But that does not undermine the sense in which the language is independent of us.)
Afterword, Part I V 1 85
4. See "A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs", in LePore, ed., Truth and Interpretation:
Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, pp. 43�6. The germ of the thought
is already present in Davidson's claim that "all understanding of the speech of another
involves radical interpretation ": p. 125 of "Radical Interpretation", in Inquiries into Truth
and Interpretation, pp. 1 25-39.
1 86 M I N D A N D W O R L D
5. See "Meaning, Truth, and Evidence", in Robert B. Barrett and Roger F. Gibson, eds.,
Perspectives on Quine (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1 990), pp. 68-79. Davidson had sketched
this exploitation of "triangulation" at the end of "Rational Animals", in Ernest LePore and
Brian McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald
Davidson (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1 985), pp. 473-80.
Afterword, Part IV 1 87