777 Philosophies and Pedagogies of Mathematics
777 Philosophies and Pedagogies of Mathematics
Boris Handal
Handal(at)ans.com.au
@ is replaced by (at) to stop the automatic garnering of email addresses by Spam factories - Editor
ABSTRACT
The philosophy of mathematics, as a discipline, has dealt for many centuries with
the issue of what is the nature of mathematics. This age-old discussion is far from
being conclusive, rather it is evolving as each thinker contributes his or her view of
looking at the different facets which mathematics presents as a discipline. This
philosophical debate is indispensable since teaching and learning mathematics is
influenced by the perspective adopted, and because mathematics has had such a
central role in the advancement of societies that defining its nature, role and
methodology has become a central, ideological and cultural issue.
In the last century, the nature of mathematics became a central issue for
educationalists as it had been before for the philosophers. An individual’s
philosophy of education was thought to determine how we live our lives. A
personal philosophy of mathematics education ascertains the way we learn and
teach mathematics within the classroom and the school environment (Southwell,
1999). If mathematics is, as the Platonist tradition suggested, just an entity out
there waiting to be discovered then it will be enough for schools to present the
curriculum instruction as a mere collection of facts, definitions and algorithms. In
that regard, teaching mathematics would be like just transmitting an immutable
body of knowledge that students have to accept as a perennial fact without any
reasoning. However, if mathematics is a cultural, creative and empirical activity
then learners are in the position of constructing their own mathematical knowledge
regardless of how different their methodology may be from the canon of orthodox
and classical mathematics.
Formalists share the logicist view that logic is necessary, however they argue that
mathematical knowledge is brought about through the manipulation of symbols
that operate by prescribed rules and formulas and whose understanding should be
accepted a priori. Formalism has been criticised because of the little space left for
creative thinking, the unfeasibility of creating an inclusive mathematical system
due to the need for a concomitant extensive list of definitions, properties, rules and
the like, and the reifying of the mastery of mathematical symbolism over
meaningful inference and intuition.
The transition from the foundationalist approach, with its emphasis on pure
mathematics, to the quasi-empirical approach was followed by a renewed interest
in the application of mathematics. As seen above, for the foundationalists the realm
of mathematics was made of abstract constructs, a fact that took them away from
an emphasis on application of mathematics (Robitaille & Dirks, 1982; Rogerson;
1989). If pure mathematics is to have any value by itself, however, then it cannot
be attained by sacrificing the value of and engaging in the application of
mathematics.
The formalist and logicist paradigms, as Hersh (1979) and Rogerson (1994) have
argued, have had a strong influence on mathematics education in this century and
therefore have shaped the way teachers and students have learned what
mathematics is. The New Mathematics wave, set theory, the emphasis on notation,
symbolism, functions and relations, more stress on analytical rather than
descriptive geometry, and behaviourist perspectives on education have certainly
been part of the foundationalist legacy which influenced the school mathematics
curriculum and models of teacher education in the world (Laurenson, 1995;
Moreira & Noss, 1995; Robitaille & Dirks, 1982; Thom, 1986).
As the second half of the last century continued to evolve, the international
mathematics education community was keener to consider and adopt the quasi-
empirical conception of mathematics, no matter how eclectic this view was. Major
reform documents such as the U.S. Curriculum and Evaluation Standards for
School Mathematics (National Council of Teachers of Mathematics, NCTM,
1989), Professional Standards for the Teaching of Mathematics (NCTM,
1991), Assessment Standards for School Mathematics (NCTM, 1995), Principles
and Standards for School Mathematics (NCTM, 2000), the U.K. Cockcroft
Report (Cockcroft, 1982), the National Statement on Mathematics for Australian
Schools (Australian Education Council, 1991), the Statement of Principles for
Mathematics K-12 and The Nature of Mathematics Teaching and Learning (Board
of Studies New South Wales, 1996) were inspired in different degrees by the
principle of “knowing mathematics is doing mathematics” (NCTM, 1989, p.
7) thus reflecting the quasi-empirical approach.
The quasi-empirical approach parallels in many respects the main tenets of the
socio-constructivist theory, although it is worthy to note that while the former
constitutes a philosophical view on the nature of mathematics, the latter focuses its
attention on the psychological underpinnings of teaching and learning mathematics.
For many years, there has been a debate in education on the advantages and
disadvantages of socio-constructivism and behaviourism. These two philosophies
on teaching and learning mathematics can be depicted as two contrasting views
and both have influenced the way mathematics is being taught in schools (Marland,
1994).
In constructivist terms, learning depends on the way each individual learner looks
at a particular situation and draws his/her own conclusions. People therefore
determine their own knowledge based on their own way of processing information
and according to his/her own beliefs and attitudes towards learning (Biggs &
Moore, 1993). Constructivism therefore gives recognition and value instructional
strategies in which students are able to learn mathematics by personally and
socially constructing knowledge. Constructivist learning strategies include more
reflective oriented learning activities in mathematics education such as exploratory
and generative learning. More specifically, these activities include problem solving,
group learning, discussions and situated learning (Murphy, 1997; Wood, Cobb, &
Yackel, 1991).
In addition, behaviourists saw the student’s affective domain as different from the
cognitive domain. The Bloom Taxonomy, for example, classifies educational
objectives in cognitive, affective and psychomotor domains (Krathwohl, Bloom, &
Masia, 1964). They categorised emotions “as imaginary constructs” that are causes
of behaviour (McLeod, 1992). Consequently, behaviourists assume that certain
emotions and attitudes can influence behaviour, although, in general, affective
issues are neglected (McLeod, 1992). Teachers’ and students’ minds were seen as
“black-boxes” or machines (Shavelson & Stern, 1981) in which attitudes and
behaviour occur somehow or even are not relevant (Nespor, 1987).
Behaviourist Constructivist
Source
Perspective Perspective
Behaviourism Constructivism Candy (1991)
O’Laughlin & Campbell
Traditional Progressive
(1988)
Mimetic Transformational Jackson (1986)
Basic skills Higher order thinking Schmidt & Kennedy (1990)
Content Process Schmidt & Kennedy (1990)
Positivist Relativist Laurenson (1995)
Sosniak, Ethington, &
Subject-centred Child-centred
Varelas (1991)
Emphasis on qualitative
Transmission of factual and
transformations
procedural Sosniak et al. (1991)
in the character and outlook of
knowledge
the learner
Euclidean Quasi-empirical Lerman (1983)
Absolutist Fallibilist Lerman (1983)
Technical-Positivism Constructivism Taylor (1990)
Traditional Nontraditional Raymond (1997)
Perry, Howard, & Tracey
Transmission Child-centredness
(1999)
Transmission Constructivist Nisbet & Warren (2000)
Summary
This paper has reviewed the debate between foundationalism and quasi-empirical
supporters on the nature of mathematics and between constructivist and
behaviourist proponents on the nature of teaching and learning mathematics.
Foundationalism is represented by the logicism, formalism and intuitionism
movements that were very popular in the first half of the last century. These
philosophical and psychological stances, acting as macro beliefs, have in turn
influenced the way students, teachers, schools and the education system in general
have thought about what mathematics is and how it should be taught and
learned. It was also argued that educational processes have been largely influenced
by foundationalist and behaviourist ideas. Consequently, many teachers may
perceive mathematics as a discipline firmly grounded in a world of rules and
procedures and disembodied from personal experience. Such a view, once
translated to the classroom environment, leads the way to a type of instruction that
might have little to do with current constructivist oriented reform principles.
REFERENCES
Biggs, J., & Moore, P. (1993). The process of learning. Sydney: Prentice Hall.
Board of Studies NSW. (1996). Stage 5 support document for Advanced, Intermediate and
Standard Courses. Sydney: BOS.
Candy, P. C. (1991). Understanding the individual nature of learning. In Self-direction for lifelong
learning: A comprehensive guide to theory and practice. (pp. 249-278). San Francisco: Jossey-
Bass.
Elliot, S.N., Kratochwill, J., & Travers, J.F. (1996). Educational psychology: Effective teaching,
effective learning. Dubuque: Brown and Benchmark Publishers.
Hersh, R. (1979). Some proposals for reviving the philosophy of mathematics. Advances in
Mathematics, 31, 31-50.
Jackson, P.W. (1986). The practice of teaching. New York: Teachers College Press.
Krathwohl, D.L., Bloom, B.S., & Masia, B.B. (1964). Taxonomy of educational objectives:
Handbook II. Affective domain. New York: Longman.
Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematics discovery. London:
Cambridge University Press.
Laurenson, D.J. (1995). Mathematics and the drift towards constructivism: Are teacher beliefs
and teaching practice following the beat of the same drummer?. NCSSSMST Journal, 1(2), 3-7.
Marland, P.W. (1994). Teaching: Implicit theories. In T. Husen, & T.N. Postlewaite (Editors-in-
chief), The international encyclopaedia of education (pp. 6178-6183). New York: Pergamon.
McGinnis, J.R., Shama, G., McDuffie, A., Huntley, M.A., King, K., & Watanabe, T.
(1996). Researching the preparation of specialized mathematics and science upper
elementary/middle-level teachers: The 2nd year report. Proceedings of the Annual Conference of
the National Science Teachers Association, St. Louis, Missouri. (ERIC document ED 395 792.)
National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. (1989). Curriculum and evaluation Standards for
school mathematics. Reston: NCTM.
National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. (1991). Professional standards for the teaching of
mathematics. Reston: NCTM.
National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. (2000). Principles and standards for school
mathematics. Reston: NCTM.
Nespor, J. (1987). The role of beliefs in the practice of teaching. Journal of Curriculum
Studies, 19(4), 317-328.
Nisbert, S., & Warren, E. (2000). Primary school teachers’ beliefs relating to mathematics
teaching and assessing mathematics and factors that influence these beliefs. Mathematics
Education Research Journal, 13(2), 34-47.
O’Laughlin, M., & Campbell, M.B. (1988). Teacher preparation, teacher empowerment, and
reflective enquiry: A critical perspective. Teacher Education Quarterly, 15(4), 25-53.
Phillip, D.C. (1995). The good, the bad, and the ugly. The many faces of
constructivism. Educational Researcher, 24(7), 5-12.
Perry, B., Howard, P., & Tracey, D. (1999). Head mathematics teachers’ beliefs about the
learning and teaching of Mathematics. Mathematics Education Research. Journal, 11, 39-57.
Polya, G. (1986). Induction and analogy in mathematics. In T. Tymoczko (Ed.), New directions in
the philosophy of mathematics (pp. 99-102). Boston: Birkhauser.
Putnam, H. (1986). What is mathematical truth? In T. Tymoczko (Ed.), New directions in the
philosophy of mathematics (pp. 49-66). Boston: Birkhauser.
Raymond, A.M. (1997). Inconsistency between a teacher’s beliefs and practice. Journal for
Research in Mathematics Education, 28(5), 550-576.
Robitaille, D., & Dirks, M. (1982). Models for the mathematics curriculum. For the Learning of
Mathematics, 2(3), 3-21.
Rogerson, A. (1989). The human and social context for problem solving, modelling and
applications. In W. Blum, M. Niss & I. Huntley (Eds.), Modelling, applications and applied
problem solving: Teaching mathematics in a real context (pp. 49-55). England: Ellis Horwood.
Schmidt, W.H., & Kennedy, M.M. (1990). Teachers’ and teacher candidates’ beliefs about subject
matter and about teaching responsibilities. (ERIC document ED 320 902.)
Shavelson, R.J., & Stern, P. (1981). Research on teachers’ pedagogical thoughts, judgements,
decisions, and behavior. Review of Education Research, 51(4), 455-498.
Sosniak, L.A., & Ethington, C.A., & Varelas, M. (1991). Teaching mathematics without a coherent
point of view: Findings from the IEA Second International Mathematics Study. Journal of
Curriculum Studies, 23, 119-131.
Wilder, R. (1986). The cultural basis of mathematics. In T. Tymoczko (Ed.), New directions in the
philosophy of mathematics (pp. 185-200). Boston: Birkhauser.
Wood, T., Cobb, P., & Yackel, E. (1991). Change in teaching mathematics. American Educational
Research Journal, 28(3), 587-616.