Horace and His Fathers - Schlegel
Horace and His Fathers - Schlegel
Horace and His Fathers - Schlegel
6
Author(s): Catherine Schlegel
Source: The American Journal of Philology, Vol. 121, No. 1 (Spring, 2000), pp. 93-119
Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1561648
Accessed: 28-09-2018 08:51 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The American Journal of Philology
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS:
SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6
Catherine Schlegel
Fere nulli alii sunt homines qui talem in filios suos habe
qualem nos habemus.
?Gaius Institutiones Iuris Civilis 1.55
xSee Satire 2.1.30-34, where he implicitly identifies his own habit with that of Lu?
cilius, who, he says, confided his secrets to his books, so that his whole life is there
vealed as if laid out on votive tablets.
2Levi's Horace: A Life (1997) is the most recent instance, in a very long English tra?
dition, of Horace's capacity to elicit fond biographizing from otherwise shrewd and so-
phisticated readers.
American Journal of Philology 121 (2000) 93-119 ? 2000 by The Johns Hopkins University Press
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
94 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
3Sat. 2.6.17, quid prius illustrem saturis musaque pedestri? Freudenburg (1993, 153)
notes the Stoic precept that speech ought to reflect and be consistent with life, and to f
vor a rough-hewn, authentic style of speech (and person) over "smooth-fitting word
which suggest dishonesty, "flash versus substance," and he contrasts this with the carefu
style of Horace. My view is that Horace does present that type of consistency in thi
poem, by rendering his life as if it were as carefully wrought as his speech.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 95
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
96 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
7See Nagy 1979, 223-32: blame-speech in turn attracts blame and ridicule to i
speaker.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 97
8On the literary theory at issue in the mock debate of lines 38-62 see Freudenburg
1993,119-52.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
98 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 99
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
100 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
... liberius si
dixero quid, si forte iocosius, hoc mihi iuris
cum venia dabis: insuevit pater optimus hoc me,
ut fugerem exemplis vitiorum quaeque notando. (1.4.103-6)
"If I speak a little too freely (liberius), too merrily (iocosius), it is only
so much as you would forgive, for the best father instilled this in me in
order that, by noting examples of faults (vitiorum), I might flee from
them." The verb notare describes the activity of both progenitors of
satire in this poem; Lucilius is the offspring, as it were, of the writers of
Old Comedy who noted with great liberty the failings of others (multa
cum libertate notabant, 5), and Horace is the offspring of a father who
likewise noted faults.12 The poem gives the two satirists, Lucilius and
Horace, separate genealogies.
Horace suggests that the activity of liberally noting faults, which
Lucilius inherited from Old Comedy, was the pedagogic cornerstone of
his own upbringing (insuevit pater optimus hoc me, ut fugerem exemplis
vitiorum quaeque notando, 105-6), one that was practiced by Horace Sr.
with the explicit aim of teaching his son how to avoid the moral failings
the poet has enumerated in the poem (25-102 passim). This effort was a
success, and Horace now, having internalized his father, goes about the
12Leach (1971, 630) notes that the comparative liberius, "rather free," tones down
the multa cum libertate (5) of Old Comedy and Lucilius. Anderson (1963, 4-5) sees a por?
trait of Lucilius in the drunken dinner guest.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 101
BLeach (1971, 619) notes that Horace Sr., having been a slave, has no ancestors of
his own, so refers to the whole tradition of Roman virtue for pedagogic use with his son.
I would go farther and note that Horace suggests in this poem that he in some sense has
no literary ancestors: whereas Lucilius is descended from Greek Old Comedy, Horace is
the product of a biological/material influence which he himself makes into a literary one.
14The phrase recalls too the compressed Horatian poetic style. As Bramble says
(1974, 22), Horace implies that "his virtuous self-questioning leaves a desirable mark on
his style."
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
102 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 103
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
104 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 105
15As Leach says, "Horace has constructed a purely literary background for L
cilius, but attributes his own artistry to a non-literary source" (1971, 618). Leach's fine
ticle on this poem demonstrates the similarity of the portrait of Horace's father in 1.4
Demea, the father in Terence's Adelphoe. She argues, however, that because Dem
proved foolish in Terence's play, the similarity to Horace's father indicates irony in Ho
ace's pietas toward his father, and that the self-irony thus implied allows Horace to ap
gize for Lucilian elements in his own work. While I agree with Leach that the portra
Horace's father operates to divide Horace from Lucilius, and that Horace is never
tirely free of irony, I think that the pietas of the portrait is sincere; the pater ardens
vides a foil to the "real" father in the satire, giving Horace an ethical edge over Luciliu
his satiric practice.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
106 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 107
self, you resent their mastery, their wholeness next to your incom
ness, their confidence next to your hesitation. You look for w
mitigate your own fear by diminishing them; you find ways to be
pointed in them so that you have a chance, a space to enter. I
wonder that Horace is kinder to Lucilius at the end of his first book of
satires, in 1.10,16 and can be wholly generous to him at the beginning
the second book, when he has accomplished something, a whole book
of satires finished, and can begin to trust his own powers. He has roo
to praise Lucilius and to grant him his due as the inventor of satire
when the virtue of his predecessor no longer threatens to overwhel
his own efforts. It is very like a parent's power over a child: the parent is
loved and longed for but occupies the place of power the child wishes
enter. Growing up means finding one's own place, and at the same tim
assigning a new place to one's parent.17 To write in the inherited genr
is to use the predecessor's substance; the son is the material of the fa
ther in a new version.
l6Sat. 1.10.46-48: hoc erat, experto frustra Varrone Atacino atque quibusdam aliis,
melius quod scribere possem, inventore minor, "this [the genre of satire], which Varro of
Atax tried in vain, as did some others, was what I might write with more success, though
lesser than its inventor."
17Most mythic representations of sons killing fathers reflect, it seems to me, not the
offspring's defiance but the parent's fear, the fear of the one who feels his authority di-
minish as the child's strength increases.
The infuriating and elegiac (in the sense of lament) work by Harold Bloom on the
issue of poetic fathers and sons was not, I confess, either an influence or an anxiety in my
thinking on Satires 1.4 and 1.6, but his Anxiety of Influence (1973), in the idiom of the
twentieth century, voices some of Horace's concerns in our two satires here. I find intrigu-
ing, for example, his recurrent use of "flowing" and "flooding" metaphors to describe the
activity of a precursor's poetic influence on the poet, precisely the metaphor Horace de-
ploys to criticize Lucilius: cumflueret lutulentus, erat quod tollere velles (1.4.11); dixifluere
hunc lutulentum, saepe ferentem plura quidem tollenda relinquendis (1.10.50-51). "The
word 'influence,'" Bloom writes, "had received the sense of 'having a power over an?
other' as early as the Scholastic Latin of Aquinas, but not for centuries was it to lose its
root meaning of 'inflow'" (26). And, again: "The anxiety of influence is an anxiety in ex?
pectation of being flooded. ... The ephebe [Bloom's locution for the younger, influenced
poet] who fears his precursors as he might fear a flood is taking a vital part for a whole,
the whole being everything that constitutes his creative anxiety, the spectral blocking
agent in every poet. Yet this metonymy is hardly to be avoided; every good reader prop?
erly desires to drown, but if the poet drowns, he will become only a reader" (57). Horace
has traditions of his own (see, e.g., Scodel 1987, 204; Freudenburg 1993, 189) for speaking
of poetic "flooding" in reference to overabundant words, but it is interesting to note, in
light of Bloom's thesis that the poetic father is a block to the poet's creativity, that Bloom
speaks, as Horace does, of what needs to be removed.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
108 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
18On the phrase naso suspendis adunco Wickham says (ad loc): "the suggestion
that the purpose of curling the nose is to hang on it the object of contempt is a comic
touch of Horace's." There is, however, the modern taunt (derived from Yiddish?) "it
should hang from your nose." See too Henderson's remark on the nose: "that favourite
organ of Satire" (1989, 91).
19The phrase appears three times in 1.6 (at 6, 45, and 46) and also in variant forms:
quali sit quisque parente natus (6-7); ingenuo . . . non . .. patre natus (21); "quo patre na-
tus?" (29); quo patre sit natus (36); non ego me claro natum patre (58); non patre praeclaro
(64). Williams's recent (1995) argument that the label libertinus for Horace's father is
deeply misleading?that Horace's father was in fact a well-heeled and well-connected
member of the Sabine aristocracy who got into political trouble and briefly suffered the
customary punishment of enslavement?makes Horace's choice of his father's portrait in
1.6 all the more interesting. Although Williams suggests that the "essential falsity" of the
portrait in 1.6 "would be immediately apparent" (312), Horace has successfully fooled
most of his readers, as the need for Williams's reconstruction demonstrates.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 109
20Sat. 1.6.46: rodunt omnes libertino patre natum, "they all carp at me bec
a freedman's son." Horace uses the term rodunt, "(they are) biting" or "gnawi
is also the verb describing the activity of the faithless friend in 1.4.81, absentem
amicum, who serves to demonstrate that Horace is, by contrast, a satirist w
harm. Nagy (1979, 225) points out that in archaic Greek "blaming is made par
ing" and that the language of blame is correlated to the language of devouring m
ace, liking to have it both ways, is here the victim of satire as well as its practi
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
110 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
21 See White 1978, 85, on the role of the literary amicus as providing a readership
for the poet and the far greater importance of that over material support, which in most
cases was not necessary?certainly not in Horace's?despite the generically useful notion
of his poor background.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 111
22Rudd (1966, 43) links pudicum to the previous lines (81-82), which describe how
Horace's father chaperoned his son on his school rounds, and suggests that the word
refers specifically to protecting the boy from the sort of sexual naughtiness which Juvenal
and Quintilian allude to as a danger in classrooms. The word pudicus, however, can also
denote a more general sense of modesty, decency, or bashfulness (LSJ s.v.; OLD s.v. 2),
and I suspect Horace exploits both senses here.
23 Johnson 1993, 28.
24Rudd 1966, 41; Williams 1995, 298; Oliensis 1998, 30-36. Horace elsewhere has no
trouble confessing his poetic excellence?for example, exegi monumentum aere perennius
(Odes 3.30.1), or, within the first book of the Satires, the unconvincing modesty of his
hopes for his poetic audience (1.10.81-91), from which he explicitly excludes those he
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
112 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
25Lacey 1986,124: "An acceptance of this idea [the inequality of citizens] lies at the
root of the patron-client relationship, since this relationship also illustrates the Romans'
acceptance of inequalities between free men, and relationships in which one man has a
claim on another inherited from a paterfamilias by his heres or heredes. This hereditabil-
ity of the relationship, based though it was on fides, and not on the total subservience in
property matters of those in potestas, nevertheless shows the Roman notion that inequal?
ity was acceptable."
26OLD s.v. patronus?[pater...]; the suffix -nus (-onus) indicating "enlarge-
ment"; cf. colonus.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 113
27See Lacey 1986, 133: "It was also perhaps because of patria potestas that the Ro?
mans acknowledged the fact that all citizens were not equal."
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
114 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
28On the satirist as an excluded figure see, e.g., Witke 1965, on the characteristic
solitude of the satirist?in this instance in a laudatory comment on Wiesen's (1964) por?
trait of Saint Jerome as "one of the world's most lonely and learned men" (1964, 19).
29Bramble (1974, 22) links Horace's Callimacheanism to his depiction of his mate?
rial world in 2.6: "the satirist's modest Callimachean professions are matched by similarly
modest social and economie conditions." In this view Callimacheanism puts the low genre
of satire on high poetic ground.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 115
30Bramble 1974, 163: "stylistic ideology is now tailored to piog, most notably in
Horace."
31 And, as Oliensis points out (1998, 34), the starkness of the father's social am
tion for his son is cloaked in the most moral desire that Horace have a good educa
Johnson (1993, 28-31) perceives fissures in Horace's portrait of his life and his father
considers the psychological effect upon the young Horace of the father's vaulting
tion, the son's resentment at being made a tool of his father's ambition, and the c
quent unmitigated, authentic yearning for freedom which Johnson sees informing
ace's poetic life and work.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
116 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 117
cenas, the patron who made Horace's life as a poet possible. The pr
cessor and the patron are each put into competition with the actu
ther, always to the advantage of Horace, pere etfils.
Horace transfers to both Maecenas and Lucilius a certain nega
aspect of the fatherly role. The distance a son needs from his fath
the formulation of his own identity is accomplished by Horace in
ous way: he takes his distance from the two figurative fathers, Lu
and Maecenas, by emphasizing that his actual father is the first ca
himself, the precursor without whom he would have no relation
with either Lucilius or Maecenas. Horace constructs Lucilius and Mae?
cenas as father figures to his poetic life, and then points out that his bio
logical father is the prior poetic cause. This subtle rebellion against
the two profound influences of Lucilius and Maecenas leaves the orig
nal biological and socially vexatious father-son relationship free of t
strain of competition and tyranny it traditionally carries. Horace po
trays a relationship with his father that epitomizes the Roman ide
one free of the notorious tensions which Roman comedy so boister
ously exploits.32 The relation between Horace and his "real life" fath
is the only relationship Horace could evoke in order to distance him
without reproach from his two "poetic fathers"; and the quality of t
father-son relation invests the satirist's voice with an authority no
amount of moralizing could accomplish.33
I here express my gratitude to Henry Weinfield and Deirdre von Dornum, who
were generous readers of this essay in its early stages. I also thank my colleague Tadeu
Mazurek for organizing the panel on satire for the 1998 meeting of the American Phi
logical Association, at which I presented a version of this paper. The anonymous refer
for AJP and the copyeditor have been prudent and kind with the present draft.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
118 CATHERINE SCHLEGEL
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Segal, Erich. 1968. Roman Laughter: The Comedy of Plautus. Cambridge: Har?
vard University Press.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HORACE AND HIS FATHERS: SATIRES 1.4 AND 1.6 119
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 08:51:49 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms