Ch. 4 - Speaking Wedding Cakes and Praying Pregnancy Centers
Ch. 4 - Speaking Wedding Cakes and Praying Pregnancy Centers
Ch. 4 - Speaking Wedding Cakes and Praying Pregnancy Centers
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Columbia University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to In the Ruins of Neoliberalism
124
125
126
127
128
129
Owner or Artist?
130
131
Artist or Purveyor?
132
133
134
135
136
137
sphere. The court and much commentary tend to treat the two
claims separately and sequentially. In fact, they are crucially
bound together in a new antidemocratic constellation.
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
held beliefs.” The court also argues that the California law
does not impose factual disclosures, but a “viewpoint” in a
controversy. The treatment of CPCs as having free speech
rights is possible only by thoroughly identifying the “views” of
each center with its personnel—making shared belief constitu-
tive of their existence and purpose. Claiming that there is no
special meaning or class of “professional speech,” even while it
treats the centers as engaged in such speech, the court implic-
itly recognizes the belief-based status of the centers. The case is
a free speech case only because the court treats CPCs as com-
mitted to a position opposing abortion that the disclosures
potentially weaken, and yet does not identify this position with
religion. The court, like the CPCs, cares more about protect-
ing that political position, including protecting it from the
charge of offering faith-based care, than with protecting truth
in advertising, truth in medical provision, and the knowledge-
dependent autonomy of women seeking help with an unplanned
pregnancy. The court endorses the displacement of each by
traditional morality free from state interference and expanded
into the public sphere, precisely embodying the neoliberal
vision articulated in the three preceding chapters.
In fact, the majority opinion identifies abortion neither as a
right nor as a legally available medical procedure. Rather, it
depicts abortion as a subject of ethical controversy about which
the state has no right to impose its “viewpoint” or “preferred
message”; a topic on which dissenting views ought to be settled
in “the marketplace of ideas”; and a product to which the CPCs
object and should therefore not be required to “advertise.”
Together, these convert the disclosures required by the FACT
149
150
CPC personnel need not speak for the centers to comply with
the FACT Act, any more than individual workers “speak” the
messages contained in required postings about hygiene, safety,
or whistleblower protections hanging in their workplaces. Only
because center personnel are presumed committed to the duplic-
ity employed by the centers—only because they are part of the
staged deception— can the disclosures be considered to compel
their speech.
The argument that the disclosures compel speech also tacitly
confesses that the mission of CPCs is religious and political,
even as they purport to be health care providers. Were CPCs
to foreground their religion and politics (which would under-
mine their tactics), “professional speech” would not be at issue.
If they were forthrightly Christian antiabortion organizations
offering help to pregnant women seeking such help, discussion
of whether professional speech may be regulated would be irrel-
evant to the case. CPCs’ pretense that they are offering profes-
sional services to the public, however, requires the court to deal
with the question of whether professional speech may be sub-
jected to special restrictions, presumably comporting with the
ethics, knowledge, and responsibilities of the profession. The
court concludes that professional speech has the same First
Amendment protections as any other kind, a conclusion easy to
treat as simply animated by an antiregulatory spirit. This is what
Justice Breyer does in his dissent. While it unquestionably draws
on the majority’s impulses in this regard, the argument against
restricting professional speech does something far more signifi-
cant in permitting religiously animated antiabortion advocates
to front as unregulated purveyors of professional services.
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160