Waxman Kants Analogies
Waxman Kants Analogies
Waxman Kants Analogies
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Review of Metaphysics
fully fledged objective reality that was Kant's goal. The theory out
lined here, by contrast, weaves together the Transcendental Aesthetic,
the Analytic of Concepts, and the entire System of All Principles of
Pure Understanding to yield a genuine refutation of the Humean skep
tical thesis that principles like "every beginning of existence must have
a cause" can at most be known to be necessary conditions for thought
of objects, while we must remain ignorant of whether they are likewise
necessary conditions for the objects themselves.
3 See Kant's Inaugural Dissertation of 1770; KGS, vol. 20. Kant's awak
ening is generally thought to have occurred sometime in 1771 or 1772 (the
"dogmatic slumber" remark is from the Prolegomena's Preface). Kant's first
acquaintance with Hume's analysis of cause and effect probably dates back
to the late 1750s or early 1760s, shortly after the appearance of a translation
of Hume's Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding; this however seems
to have made no great impression on him at the time. That Hume's critique
of the metaphysical employment of the concepts of cause and substance first
struck Kant as the great philosophical challenge of the age not when he ini
tially encountered it but only after his reflections on space and time had led
him to transcendental idealism suggests that the transcendentally ideal nature
of space and time and the objective validity of a priori concepts became
inextricably linked in his mind quite early. See also my discussion of Kant's
notion of epig?nesis in Wayne Waxman, Kant's Model of the Mind: A New
Interpretation of Transcendental Idealism (hereafter, KMM) (Oxford: Ox
ford University Press, 1991), chap. 7. For a detailed examination of Hume's
views on causality, with an emphasis on their proximity to Kant's own, see
my forthcoming book, Hume's Theory of Consciousness (Cambridge: Cam
bridge University Press, forthcoming), pt 2.
4 The motives behind Kant's choice of varying modes of designation for
nonrepresentational reality are difficult to fathom. My own view is that his
terminology is generally determined by the correlative faculty of representa
Texts like this put two things quite beyond doubt. First, principles of
pure understanding like the Analogies are supposed not simply to be
valid of nature but actually to create it; that is, they not only hold of
our experience of objects (as with Hume) but are constitutive of the
objects themselves which make such experience possible. Second,
this creative, constitutive role premises transcendental idealism in the
notion that nature (that is, the entire spatiotemporal cosmos) is noth
ing but our own representation, subject a priori to the faculties of
sensibility and understanding. The pure concepts involved in the
Analogies find their place in this scheme as the source of the time in
which appearances exist (that is, of objective time, as distinct from
the subjective time which is merely the form of their apprehension in
intuition).15 They are thus constitutive specifically of that which Kant
calls experience: the ordered whole of appearances in which each ap
pearance has determinate time-relations of duration, succession, and
simultaneity (one Analogy per mode of time)16 with respect to every
other. (Experience, in this sense, involves inference and should be con
trasted with immediate intuition and perception.)17 Yet, any such cre
ative, constitutive role for understanding is precluded by the standard
interpretation of transcendental idealism, according to which appear
ances already exist in relations of time, simply by virtue of the forms
of sensibility in accordance with which sensations originally present
themselves in the mind, and so prior to and independently of their
apprehension by imagination in intuition. What need is there then for
constitutive principles of pure understanding to endow appearances
with existence in time? Any would-be objective time the understand
ing and imagination might fashion for epistemic purposes would then
laws no more exist in the appearances but only relatively to the sub
ject . . . insofar as it has understanding, than appearances exist in them
selves but only relatively to this same being insofar as it has senses"; CPR,
B163-4.
15 "By means of these rules the existence of every appearance can be
determined in respect of the unity of time"; CPR, A176/B219.
16 There are three Analogies not only because there are three categories
of relation but also so that objective time may be constituted in each of its
three modes: duration, succession, simultaneity.
17 The Analogies hold only "under the condition of empirical thought in
one experience, and thence only mediately and indirectly"; CPR, A160/B200.
Following Hume, Kant situates necessary connection not in perception but in
empirical thought: "no necessity determining their connection is or can be
revealed in the perceptions themselves"; CPR, B219. Intuition and percep
tion have their own constitutive principles of pure understanding: the Axioms
of Intuition and the Anticipations of Perception (see section II-B below).
II
While there are at least two passages in the A edition of the Transcen
dental Deduction (1781) where the careful reader can discern Kant's
view that space and time are original a priori synthetic unities founded
on pure understanding,22 it is only in the B edition (1787) that one finds
it spelled out explicitly and unequivocally. The first such occasion is
the following:
Space and time, and all their parts, are intuitions, and are thus, with their
manifold, singular representations (see the Transcendental Aesthetic).
They are thus not mere concepts, through which the very same con
sciousness is contained in many representations, but, on the contrary,
contain many representations in one, and in the consciousness of that
representation. . . . The unity of that consciousness is therefore syn
thetic and yet also original.2*
Kant could not have been plainer: the pure space and time of the Tran
scendental Aesthetic could not even be given as intuitions did the un
derstanding not impart synthetic unity to the manifold offered by sense
by means of the transcendental synthesis of imagination.
The identification of space and time (but particularly time since
only to it are all appearances subject, outer no less than inner) with
the synthetic unity of apperception in the Transcendental Deduction
is the single most crucial, yet in recent times most widely overlooked,
element in Kant's system of experience. In my view, we can follow
his reasoning through each stage in the unfolding of that system only
when we have conditioned ourselves to read "time" whenever he
states that, in the absence of synthetic unity of apperception, expe
rience would be impossible. A particularly illuminating example, with
37 CPR, A143/B182.
38 CPR, A143/B182. Wille, and Kemp Smith after him, add a "not", thus
reversing the sense of this text to bring it into accord with their conception
of transcendental idealism. See also Kant, Prolegomena, pt. 1, remark 3;
Immanuel Kant, First Principles of Natural Science-, KGS, vol. 4, Ak. 481;
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, Intro. VII (2d ed.) and ?1, and note
7 above.
39 See CPR, A30/B45. The only other transcendentally real constituent
of our representation is spontaneity (see CPR, B422-3n; KMM, chap. 7).
40 CPR, A166.
41 See CPR, B147, A225/B272-3, and A373ff.
42 CPR, B208. See also Kant, Prolegomena, ?24, ?26; KGS, vol. 4.
43 CPR, A160/B200; see also note 17 above. It should be noted that the
Axioms and Anticipations are principles not of the form and matter of ap
pearances per se (as pure space and time are, vis-?-vis their form) but only
of their judgment in discursive understanding. The Axioms concern the con
ceptualization of intuition, for instance, its construction in accordance with
a previously obtained concept of space or time; it thus yields cognizable ob
jects of intuition, where "object" is understood as an object of a concept (in
the sense of B137: that in the concept of which the manifold is united). Like
wise, the Anticipations concern the conceptualization of perception, and
252-3): both portray what inferential thought finds before it, before it sets to
work conjoining perceptions in relations of necessary connection. Kant al
most certainly came across this passage in the German translation of Beattie's
Essay on the Nature and Immutability of Truth (1772), of which there is a
modern edition by F. Wolf (Stuttgart-Bad Constatt: Friedrich Neumann, 1973).
The passage is quoted almost in entirety in Beattie's Essay.
51 CPR, A146/B185.
52 See KMM, chap. 3.
53 See esp. Kant, Prolegomena ?28 and ?39; KGS, vol. 4.
54 CPR, A244-5; see also A242-5, A248-9, B305, A321/B378, A349, B378,
B428, and B431. The logical dimension of Kant's theory of experience is
perhaps the most important of all, yet also the least satisfactorily treated and
most neglected. The only study of the Transcendental Analytic I know which
gives full due to Kant's logic, especially his metaphysical deduction of the
categories from the logical forms of judgment, is B?atrice Longuenesse, Kant
et le pouvoir d?juger (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1993). It is a
welcome antidote to the generally prevailing tendency to diminish or ignore
the metaphysical deduction and derive the categories from Newtonian sci
ence by way of principles of time-determination, as well as to those of an
ahistorical bent who pour scorn on Kant's logic without troubling to obtain
the information necessary to understand and evaluate it (by a study especially
of Christian Wolff and Georg Meier, together with KGS, vol. 14, and Kant's
students' lecture notes).
55 See CPR, A143-4/B183-4. I translate Zugleichsein by "simultaneity"
in preference to Kemp Smith's "coexistence"; see note 98 below.
56 See CPR, A138/B177. Keep in mind that the time intuition is nothing
more than a form of synthesis; see sections I and II-A above.
Ill
64 CPR, B225.
65 CPR, B224-5; see also A182-3.
66 CPR, A183/B226. The advent of a new substance implies that some
thing comes into existence that is not a determination of any substrate but is
itself a substrate of determinations. There would thus be a first state of that
substance, that is, a determination without any predecessor. Since this de
termination could not be referred to any other determination as its successor,
it would be temporally indeterminate, that is, (since time itself is not percep
tible) its existence could not be determined in relation to synthetic unitary
time. To suppose that this determination could be effected simply by refer
ring it to the state of another substance begs the question: it assumes that
the second substance exists in time relations of precedence and simultaneity
with respect to the first, and so presupposes that both substances already
exist in one and the same time?yet it is precisely because any such time
(that is, an objective time prior to and independent of categories of necessary
connection) is lacking that conceptual exponents are necessary at all.
Hence, an object of perception without a predecessor is not a possible ex
perience. See CPR, A188/B231.
67 CPR, A156/B195-6.
68 CPR, A183/B226. "Since this substrate thus does not change in its
existence, its quantum in nature can be neither increased nor diminished";
B225.
69 CPR, A90/B122.
70 CPR, A160/B200.
71 For Hume, the objects that appear are one and all perceptions. He
held that, for all we are able to know of self-subsistence by pure reason alone,
it makes just as much sense to regard perceptions themselves as self-subsis
tent as any supposed substrate they may be thought to have. See Hume,
Treatise, 207, 233-34, 244, 252.
72 See CPR, A184/B227-8, A736/B764-5.
73 Kant, of course, believed he had demonstrated that representations do
not exist as a flux (they are merely apprehended as such in intuition), espe
cially through the use made of the First Analogy to refute Cartesian skeptical
idealism (see note 33 above). Thus the notion, current through Hume and
beyond, that the time in which appearances exist exactly mirrors the succes
siveness of their apprehension is denied by Kant. Kant's expressed opposi
tion is converted to full agreement if his transcendental idealism is interpreted
in the usual manner.
74 Paul Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cam
bridge University Press, 1987), 244; see also pp. 248-9. This formulation is
his, but the assumption it expresses seems to me quite general.
75 This is why, until they are subordinated to the principle of the Second
Analogy, appearances "are in no way differentiated from their apprehension,
i.e., their being taken up into the synthesis of imagination"; CPR, A190/B235.
Apprehension, as we have seen, concerns merely the ideal form of appear
ances in their intuition, not their reality as objects of perception; hence, as
realities (as defined in the Anticipations), they are not in time at all.
76 Again Guyer: "The manifold of subjective states occurs or is given
successively. . . . That is, any pair or series of distinct representations,
whether they represent states of affairs which coexist but are successively or
states which succeed one another and thus comprise the several states of an
actual event or alteration, themselves succeed one another"; Guyer, Kant and
the Claims of Knowledge, 171, 243-4). Although this assumption is usually
implicit, I have never seen it denied and an interpretation of the Second Anal
ogy built thereon.
77 Strawson's phrase (echoing Lovejoy).
then attempts to reckon with the problem of inferring from their tem
poral order the imperceptible order of the objects they represent is,
in essence, Descartes' predicament. The Cartesian (or, in Kant's ter
minology, skeptical or problematic)78 idealist holds that the only ob
jects ever given to us are our own perceptions, and that their situation
and relations alone are perfectly known. Since the objects percep
tions represent are, by contrast, never directly given to us, how matters
stand with them can only be known by inference from the perceptions
whose cause we presume them to be. Now, these unperceived objects
are supposed to come in two varieties?momentary events and en
during things?and the problem is how to distinguish one from the
other via their representations. If representations truly mirrored their
objects, we should expect momentary perceptions to represent events
and abiding ones to represent enduring things; yet since all apprehen
sion is successive,79 this simply is not the case. (For instance, it is
impossible to distinguish successively apprehending one enduring per
ception from apprehending a succession of exactly resembling ones,
each representative of a distinct event.) The more pressing question
thus becomes, How can fleeting perceptions represent enduring
things? One possibility is that, by displaying a qualitative identity
over time, a series of perceptions warrants our inferring the numerical
identity of their object. But were that so, then, as soon as the quali
tative identity were broken (as by a mere blink of the eyes), we would
have to infer that the object had, at that moment, ceased to exist; nor
would it follow from a qualitative change in its perception that the
represented object must have ceased to exist (Descartes's beeswax,
for instance) or even have changed (the change may only have been
in the lighting, angle of view, or the like). Finally, one must ask what
feature it is of perceptions themselves that prompts us to suppose that
they are merely mental representations of things unperceived outside
the mind; that is, how do they convey to us the idea that not they but
things we never perceive are the true reality?
It is generally supposed that Kant's own questions in the Second
Analogy were of this type, and that he believed the key to their solution
lay in the subordination of perceptions a priori to the law of cause and
effect (as that which can alone permit "the justification, verification,
or confirmation of the judgments about empirical objects that we
make on the basis of our representations of them").80 The category
of cause and effect is conceived not as originally bestowing temporal
order on our representations but as determining the order they already
have (in virtue of being given by the senses as a flux), that is, fixing
it, rendering it necessary. Thus, once I determine that X is the cause
of Y, I know not only that Y succeeds X but that it must succeed it, so
that even if the representation of Y should sometimes precede that of
Xin apprehension, I still know that the objects?or event as may now
be called?precedes the event Y. Since the objective temporal order
may thereby diverge from the subjective order of apprehension, the
supposed purely epistemol?gica! goal of the Second Analogy is, in this
manner, achieved.
Since Cartesians distinguish representations from the objects they
represent as two distinct kinds of entity?mental and material?they
could find such an account acceptable. Kant's transcendental ideal
ism, however, led him to regard material objects themselves as mere
representations, indeed as "nothing but the sum (Inbegriff) of [suc
cessively apprehended] representations."81 The Kantian idealist is
therefore obliged to assign to one and the same series of representa
tions not one but two distinct, potentially divergent temporal order
ings: their immediately intuited subjective succession in apprehend
ing imagination and their inferred objective succession in discursive
understanding. This means that, with the Cartesian option of distrib
uting these divergent sequences among different sets of existents ex
cluded, the Kantian has no choice but to regard one time series as real
and the other as fictitious whenever they diverge (for instance, when
I see or smell the smoke before seeing the fire). Which is it to be: the
existents we immediately apprehend, or those never given to us and
known only by inference from those which are? Hume's answer is
well known;82 and the fact that the standard account of the Second
83 Hume, Treatise, 225. Kant was well aware that Hume recognized the
indispensability of the principle of cause and effect to human understand
ing?see the Preface to the Prolegomena.
84 Ibid., 168.
89 CPR, A144/B183.
and signification, are the solution. Thus, the only way the realities of
perception may be set into relations of space (that is, endowed with
existence in space) is by means of a principle of necessary connection,
and in particular a principle constitutive of an objective simultaneity
distinct from and independent of the successiveness of apprehension.
That is, while the pure space intuition alone can render such simul
taneity representable, nothing save a principle of necessary connec
tion from which simultaneity may be inferred can objectify space (see
section II-D above).
While the Third Analogy is as much an account of objective space
as of objective time, Kant chooses to restrict his focus mainly to the
latter since time alone is a form of all appearances, outer no less than
inner (space enters into the account of universal self-consciousness
only insofar as its objectivization is a condition for that of time). Now,
prior to empirical thought and the introduction of a principle of nec
essary connection, simultaneity relations, like the modes of time con
sidered in the previous Analogies, apply only to the form of our ap
prehension of appearances (their intuition as simultaneous in
imagination),100 not to the appearances themselves (their existence as
realities of perception). The Third Analogy is therefore not a principle
of empirical laws enabling us to discover the unknown simultaneity
relations that appearances already have (that is, in which they sup
posedly already exist), but a principle of laws originally constitutive
of these relations (as derivable from laws of necessary connection).
What sort of principle is required? Just as unidirectional neces
sary connection forms the basis of objective succession, bidirectional
necessary connection, according to Kant, is the basis of objective
simultaneity. That is, there must be reciprocal determination mini
mally, a circle of determination (community) maximally: X and Y are
simultaneous substances if at least one state of each is an effect of the
other; even if this is not the case, if a state of each is an effect of some
other substance at least one state of which is itself an effect (direct or
indirect) of the other. Either way, it is crucial that the causal de
pendence go in both directions so that at least one state of X and
one of Y is directly or indirectly dependent on a state of the other,
as only reciprocity of determination permits inference to objective
simultaneity.
The Third Analogy, like the First, concerns substances, not their
states: bidirectional causal determination (reciprocity) makes possible
an inference from objectively successive states to the objective si
multaneity (coexistence) of the substances to which they pertain; it
does not permit us to conclude anything as to the simultaneity of dif
ferent states.101 The fact that Kant did not include a principle of the
simultaneity of states in his system of principles suggests that he did
not deem it a condition for objectifying synthetic unitary time and
space. Three Analogies apparently sufficed: one conceptual surrogate
(exponent) for the permanence of time, another for time-order (suc
cessiveness), and a third to ensure its uniqueness; for if any two per
manents failed to be determinable as simultaneous, there would be
two unconnected time-surrogates, and thence two distinct times.
Since this is all that Kant deemed necessary for the constitution of
objective time and space, and since these are all he deemed necessary
for the unity of apperception and the possibility of experience, the
transcendental philosopher has no brief (nor remaining categories) to
formulate a principle of the simultaneity of states; this has instead to
be discovered in actual experience through reliance on empirical con
cepts and laws.102
101 That Kant's concern was the simultaneity of substance is clear from
the formulation of the principle in each edition and from his conclusion to
the B edition proof: "Thus the simultaneity of substances in space cannot be
cognized in experience save on the assumption of their reciprocal interac
tion"; B258. It is, moreover, a necessary consequence of the fact that the
category of community, on account of the logical function from which it is
derived, is not subordinative like that of cause and effect, but coordinative.
For this means there can never result from this category anything but a com
munity of equals, independent of one another; it thus can only apply to sub
stances, never to their states (which, in the Second Analogy, are subordinated
to their predecessors). See CPR, Bl 12-13.
102 It is worth remarking that since the Third Analogy is concerned not
with the simultaneity of transitory things but that of absolutely permanent
substances, it may well be reconcilable with the relative (and empirical)
space and time of twentieth-century physics. Indeed, the same seems to be
true of the Second Analogy as here interpreted. For in science too cause
and effect relations are generally thought to determine time-order and not
vice versa; and even if (contrary no doubt to Kant's own expectations) such
relations fail to yield a single, fixed, universal time series, this poses no prob
lem for Kant's system so long as (1) both the uniqueness and unicity of space
and time are preserved and (2) there remains only a single dynamical com
munity of (permanent) substances. So far as I am aware, nothing in contem
porary science either postulates or implies the absence of such a community;
indeed, insofar as all present-day matter is traced back to a "Big Bang" (not
IV
106 "Together [the Analogies] therefore say: all appearances lie, and must
lie, in one nature, because without this a priori unity, no unity of experience,
and thence no determination of objects in experience, would be possible";
CPR, A216/B263. Kant distinguished "world" from "nature," with the former
designating the quantitative whole, or magnitude, of the real, the latter the
qualitative whole, or dynamical unity, of the real; see CPR, A418-9/B446-7.
In his view, the world has no magnitude, and, therefore, is neither infinite nor
finite but indeterminate (see A503-4/B531-2 and A518-23/B546-51); thus,
while the sphere of reality is a qualitative unity of apperception (see B131),
it is not a quantitative unity (only that contained within the world, which must
be conceived as extensive magnitudes, has determinate quantitative unity).
107 See CPR, B67, A265/B321. Intrinsic denominations refer to proper
ties founded in the thing denominated; extrinsic denominations to properties
outside the thing denominated (that is, to relations). Leibniz, in his meta
physics, reduces all relations to properties of objects, while Kant, in his tran
scendental philosophy, reduces all properties to relations. (Only the reality
corresponding to sensations may be deemed an exception, but this cannot be
cognized a priori beyond the principle of the Anticipations of Perception it
self; see CPR, A175-6/B217-8.)
111 See esp. KGS, vol. 20, p. 419; quoted in KMM, 81-2.
112 See CPR, A733-4/B761-2.
113 See note 93 above.
114 See Prolegomena ?38; KGS, vol. 4.; and CPR, A714-5/B741-2. Mi
chael Friedman argues, quite persuasively in my view, that Kant's notion of
pure intuition should not be construed as a kind of insight or seeing; see
Michael Friedman, Kant and the Exact Sciences (Cambridge: Harvard Uni
versity Press, 1992), pt. 1, esp. pp. 89-93. He fails, however, to consider the
possibility outlined here that we are, if not wrong, then without sufficient
warrant to read Euclideanism, or any definite position in what we would call
"philosophy of mathematics" and "philosophy of physics" into Kant's remarks
on geometry. I also differ with him on arithmetic and on logic. I believe
that, for Kant, the relation of arithmetic to pure time is essentially the same
as that of geometry to pure space. I hold too that Kant would have regarded
modern quantificational logic just as he did number: as presupposing the sche
matism of the category of quantity, and so as involving sensibility. He thus
would likely have deemed it a branch of mathematics rather than of pure
logic, which, in his sense, is delimited by the understanding taken in isolation.
I plan to develop these and related views in a future paper.
115 The historical conditionedness pertaining to mathematics holds also,
in my view, for Kant's applications of transcendental philosophy in the meta
physical first principles of natural science and the transition to physics. For
example, since its central concept of matter must be derived from actual
experience and so is a product of empirical reflection (see, for instance, CPR,
A847-8/B875-6), a metaphysical first principle can only be as good as the
concept of matter attained at a given time, and a different such work would
have to be written today from that of the seventeenth or eighteenth century,
or the fourth century b.c. As with mathematics, however, this does not com
promise its a priori necessity; it merely qualifies and restricts it.) See also
Buchdahl, Kant and the Dynamics of Reason, 35-6.
116 There is today considerable controversy regarding the nature and pur
pose of Kant's final, unfinished opus, the Transition to Physics, in KGS, vols.
21-2, especially the aether deduction. In my view, its relation with the work
of the 1780s, as elucidated here, is the following: Although the Critique of
Pure Reason furnishes a warrant for affirming a priori the existence of a
community of substances (given that the objectification of space and time is
a condition for possible experience), neither it nor the Metaphysical First
Principles of Natural Science (1786) permit one to say anything about the
nature of these substances, and, in particular, whether they are heterogeneous
matters or all one and the same kind of reality (quality). For the Anticipa
tions of Perception enable us to anticipate only that the empirically real has
a magnitude (and that this magnitude is intensive), but nothing as to the
quality of this reality (including its homogeneity or heterogeneity). How
ever, in the wake of Lavoisier, Kant came (temporarily, perhaps) to believe
that he could deduce a priori, as a condition of possible experience, the ho
mogeneous nature (as aether, caloric) of the substances that objectively re
alize space and time. Since this proof is not offered as part of transcendental
philosophy per se but only as a link between the system of nature outlined in
the Metaphysical First Principles and actual physics, it should, in my view,
be regarded as no less historically conditioned than the latter work (see pre
vious note); thus, transcendental philosophy does not stand or fall according
to the validity of the aether deduction. For a detailed study of the issues
involved and a somewhat similar approach to dealing with them see Fried
man, Kant and the Exact Sciences, pt. 2, esp. pp. 310-15.