75TexLRev989 2
75TexLRev989 2
75TexLRev989 2
Citations:
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
The Economics of Improvement in Intellectual
Property Law
Mark A. Lemley*
* Assistant Professor, University of Texas School of Law; of counsel, Fish & Richardson P.C.,
Austin, Texas. I would like to thank Julie Cohen, Mark Gergen, Rose Hagan, Paul Heald, Doug
Laycock, Jessica Litman, Peter Menell, Robert Merges, Neil Netanel, Samuel Oddi, David Post, Chris
Wood, and the editors of the Texas LawReview for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this Article,
and Barbara Parvis and Nicole Stafford for research assistance. Copyright 1997 by Mark A. Lemley.
990 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
1. See generally Jeremy Waldron, From Authors to Copiers: IndividualRights andSocial Values
in IntellectualProperty, 68 CHI.-KENT L. REv. 841, 842 (1993) (arguing that a neutral treatment of
the morality of copying must incorporate the perspectives of both the author and the copier); Laurie
Steams, Comment, Copy Wrong: Plagiarism, Process, Property and the Law, 80 CAL. L. REV. 513
(1992) (distinguishing plagiarism, which emphasizes the creative process, from copyright infringement,
which emphasizes the creative result).
1997] Economics of Improvement
This problem is not new. Even before the United States adopted its
patent and copyright laws, Lord Mansfield said the following in an English
case involving a copyright claim against improved navigational charts:
The rule of decision in this case is a matter of great consequence to
the country. In deciding it we must take care to guard against two
extremes equally prejudicial; the one, that men of ability, who have
employed their time for the service of the community, may not be
deprived of their just merits, and the reward of their ingenuity and
labor; the other, that the world may not be deprived of
improvements, nor the progress of the arts be retarded.'
Unfortunately, there has not been much improvement in the law of
improvements since 1785.
A number of doctrines in modem copyright and patent law attempt to
strike some balance between the rights of original developers and the rights
of subsequent improvers. Both patents and copyrights are limited in dura-
tion and in scope. Each of these limitations provides some freedom of
action to subsequent improvers. Improvers are free to use material that is
in the public domain because the copyright or patent has expired. They are
free to skirt the edges of existing intellectual property rights, for example
by taking the ideas but not the expression from a copyrighted work,3 or
by "designing around" the claims of a patent. However, improvers cannot
always avoid the intellectual property rights of the basic work on which
they wish to improve. Some improvements fall within the scope of the
preexisting intellectual property right, either because of an expansive
definition of that right4 or because economic or technical necessity requires
that the improver hew closely to the work of the original creator in some
basic respect.5 Here, the improver is at the mercy of the original intel-
lectual property owner, unless there is some separate right that expressly
allows copying for the sake of improvement.
Patent and copyright law differ in how they treat improvements that
fall within the scope of the original intellectual property right. Patent
doctrines such as the rule of blocking patents and the reverse doctrine of
equivalents offer some protection to the developers of significant or radical
2. Sayre v. Moore, 102 Eng. Rep. 139, 140 (1785) (Lord Mansfield, C.J.), cited in Cary v.
Longman, 102 Eng. Rep. 138, 140 n.(b) (1801) (Lord Kenyon, C.J.). Lord Mansfield instructed the
jury to distinguish between a new chart, which corrected the errors in the plaintiff's work, and a "mere
servile imitation" of the plaintiff's chart. Only the latter work was actionable under copyright. The
jury found for the defendant. Id.
3. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(b) (1994); Baker v. Selden, 101 U.S. 99, 102-03 (1879).
4. See infra notes 53-69 and accompanying text (discussing how improvements can still fail within
the literal scope of a patent claim).
5. See infra notes 178-80 and accompanyingtext (discussing market factors that may require exact
duplication of an original work, particularly in the computer software or parody contexts).
Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
6. For a discussion of the meaning of these terms, see infra notes 85-98 and accompanying text.
7. See infra notes 80-106 and accompanying text.
8. 17 U.S.C. § 106 (1994).
9. 1 MELVILLE B. NIMMER & DAVID NIMMER, NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 3.06 (1996); see also
infra notes 154-62 and accompanying text.
10. 17 U.S.C. § 107 (1994).
11. See, e.g., Pierre N. Leval, Toward a Fair Use Standard, 103 HARV. L. REV. 1105, 1105
(1990) (criticizing courts for failing to develop a consistent set of principles or values to govern fair
use).
1997] Economics of Improvement
12. Noneconomic theories of copyright tend to center around a natural law or moral rights
approach, suggesting that authors have some sort of preexisting entitlement to control their works. For
discussions of these approaches, see, for example, Wendy J. Gordon, A Property Right in Self-
Expression:Equality and Individualism in the NaturalLaw of Intellectual Property, 102 YALE L.J.
1533, 1535 (1993) (arguing that courts have mistakenly interpreted the natural law theory of copyright
and afforded too much protection to authors at the expense of free speech interests); Alfred C. Yen,
Restoring the NaturalLaw: Copyright as LaborandPossession, 51 OHIO ST. L.J. 517,529-39 (1990)
(stressing that natural law concepts are inherent in copyright law); cf. Steven Cherensky, Comment,
A Pennyfor Their Thoughts: Employee-Inventors, PreinventionAssignmentAgreements, Property, and
Personhood, 81 CAL. L. REV. 595, 644-53 (1993) (applying Margaret Radin's theory of personal
investments of self in property to intellectual property). For what might be termed a "utilitarian but
noneconomic" view of copyright as designed to further the development of a democratic civil society,
see Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyrightand a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-48
(1996).
13. For a discussion of reward-based and even natural law theories of scientific invention, see, for
example, A. Samuel Oddi, Un-Unified Economic Theories of Patents-The Not-Quite-Holy Grail, 71
NOTRE DAME L. REv. 267, 274-77 (1996); Kevin Rhodes, Comment, The Federal Circuit's Patent
NonobviousnessStandards:TheoreticalPerspectiveson RecentDoctrinalChanges, 85 Nw. U. L. REV.
1051, 1077-84 (1991); cf. Lawrence C. Beecker, Deserving to Own IntellectualProperty, 68 CHI.-KENT
L. REV. 609 (1993) (arguing that desert-based arguments for patent law are intuitively appealing, but
do not necessarily justify the scope of current patent doctrine). An alternative to classical incentive
theory is the prospect theory of patents, advanced by Edmund Kitch in an important article 20 years
ago. See Edmund W. Kitch, The Nature and Function of the Patent System, 20 J.L. & ECON. 265
(1977). Kitch offers a property-based vision of patents as entitlements to innovate within a particular
field, granted to those who have already started such innovation. For a refinement of Kitch's approach
that takes account of rent-seeking, see Mark F. Grady & Jay I. Alexander, Patent Law and Rent
Dissipation,78 VA. L. REV. 305 (1992).
14. U.S. CoNSr. art. I, § 8, cl. 8.
Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
Mazer v. Stein,"5 "'[the copyright law, like the patent statutes, makes
reward to the owner a secondary consideration' .... The economic
philosophy behind the clause empowering Congress to grant patents and
copyrights is the conviction that it is the best way to advance public wel-
fare through
16
the talents of authors and inventors in 'Science and useful
gArts."
To understand why the Framers thought exclusive rights in inventions
and creations would promote the public welfare, consider what would
happen absent any sort of intellectual property protection. Invention and
creation require the investment of resources-the time of an author or
inventor, and often expenditures on facilities, prototypes, supplies, and the
like. In a private market economy, individuals will not invest in invention
or creation unless the expected return from doing so exceeds the cost of
doing so-that is, unless they can reasonably expect to make a profit from
the endeavor. To profit from a new idea or a work of authorship, the
creator must be able either to sell it to others for a price, or to put it to
some use which provides her with a comparative advantage in a market. 7
But ideas (and writings, for that matter) are notoriously hard to
control. Even if the idea is one that the creator can use herself, for
example to boost productivity in her business, she will reap a reward from
that idea only to the extent that her competitors do not find out about it.
A creator who depends on secrecy for value therefore lives in constant
peril of discovery and disclosure. Competitors may steal the idea, or learn
of it from an ex-employee. They may be able to figure it out by watching
the creator's production process, or by examining the products she sells.
Finally, they may come upon the idea on their own, or discover it in the
published literature. In all of these cases, the secrecy value of the idea will
be irretrievably lost. 8
The creator who wants to sell her idea is in an even more difficult
position. Selling information requires disclosing it to others. Once the
information has been disclosed outside a small group, however, it is
extremely difficult to control. Information has the characteristics of what
economists call a "public good"-it may be "consumed" by many people
without depletion, and it is difficult to identify those who will not pay and
19. See Kenneth J. Arrow, Economic Welfare and the Allocation of Resourcesfor Invention, in
THE RATE AND DIRECTION OF INvENTIvE ACTIvITY: ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL FACTORS 609, 614-16
(1962).
20. To some extent this oversimplifies the problem by ignoring possible second-order distorting
effects. In practice, if I taught several hundred million people to fish, the result might be depletion of
a physical resource (fish) that otherwise would not have occurred. Similarly, wide dissemination of
information-may have particular effects on secondary markets, depending on what the information is.
Nonetheless, the general point remains accurate.
21. See, e.g., F.M. SCHERER, INDUSTRIALMARKET STRUCTURE AND ECONOMIC PERFORMANCE
444 (2d ed. 1980) ("If pure and perfect competition in the strictest sense prevailed continuously...
incentives for invention and innovation would be fatally defective without a patent system or some
equivalent substitute."). Scherer goes on to note, however, that natural market imperfections may give
advantages to first movers, reducing the need for intellectual property protection. Id. at 444-45.
22. See, e.g., MICHAEL LAVER, THE POLITICS OF PRIVATE DEsIRES 30-31 (1981) (giving
examples of "collective consumption" goods).
23. But see Ronald H. Coase, TheLighthouse in Economics, 17 J.L. & ECON. 357 (1974) (casting
doubt on the assumption that lighthouses must always be publicly provided).
24. For example, government provision of all books or all ideas is probably inefficient if there is
a way to encourage competition between authors or inventors. Competition is a better spur to new
Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
ideas than government mandate. Further, government control over new publications is fundamentally
inconsistent with the diversity of viewpoints and freedom of speech inherent in a democratic society.
See, e.g., Vincent Blasi, The Checking Value in FirstAmendment Theory, 1977 AM. B. FOUND. RES.
J. 521.
25. Glynn Lunney offers a second set of costs, which are not normally considered in economic
analyses of intellectual property. He suggests that incentives for creation distort allocative efficiency
by encouraging the inefficient shifting of resources from other sectors of the market into the production
of works of intellectual property. See Glynn S. Lunney, Jr., Reexamining Copyright's Incentives-
Access Paradigm, 49 VAND. L. REV. 483 (1996). While Lunney's critique of the copyright system,
if valid, is fundamental, a detailed analysis of his paper is beyond the scope of this Article.
26. This does not mean that intellectual property rights automatically confer market power or
create "monopolies" in an economic or antitrust sense, as some courts have erroneously presumed.
See, e.g., Jefferson Parish Hosp. Dist. No. 2 v. Hyde, 466 U.S. 2, 16 (1984) (assuming that a patent
on a product may confer market power on the seller); United States v. Loew's, Inc., 371 U.S. 38, 45
(1962) (finding the economic power necessary for a tying violation may be assumed where the tying
product is patented or copyrighted); Digidyne Corp. v. Data Gen. Corp., 734 F.2d 1336, 1344 (9th
Cir. 1984) (holding that a computer company's copyright created a presumption of economic power
for theproduct). While some intellectual property rights may in fact give their owner power in an eco-
nomically relevant product market, most do not; they merely prevent others from competing to sell
copies of a particular product, not from selling different products that compete with the original. See,
e.g., PHILLIP AREEDA & Louis KAPLOW, ANTITRUST ANALYSIS 441-42 (1988); HERBERT
HOVENKAMP, ECONOMICS AND FEDERAL ANTITRUST LAW § 8.3, at 219 (1985); Mark A. Lemley,
Comment, The Economic Irrationalityof the PatentMisuse Doctrine, 78 CAL. L. REV. 1599, 1626-28
(1990); Russell Lombardy, Comment, The Myth ofMarket Power: Why Market Power Should Not Be
PresumedWhen ApplyingAntitrust Principlesto the Analysis of lying Agreements Involving Intellectual
Property, 8 ST. THOMAS L. REv. 449, 453-55 (1996); William Montgomery, Note, The Presumption
of Economic Powerfor Patented and CopyrightedProducts in 7ying Arrangements, 85 COLum. L.
REV. 1140, 1156 (1985).
Whether the intellectual property owner can take advantage of his right to exclude to raise prices
on his product depends largely on two factors: whether perfect competition prevails in the industry and
whether his invention gives him a cost advantage over competitors. See SCHERER, supra note 21, at
444.
27. See SCHERER, supra note 21, at 450-51 (documenting instances of patent holders pricing in
excess of cost).
19971 Economics of Improvement
property rights impose costs on the public, the intellectual property laws
can be justified by the public goods argument only to the extent that they
do on balance encourage enough creation and dissemination of new works
to offset those costs. One of the reasons that intellectual property rights
are limited in scope, in duration, and in effect?' is precisely in order to
balance these costs and benefits.'
The situation becomes more complex when we consider not
just the market for a particular work, but the market for new works in
general. Creation does not occur in a vacuum. Rather, knowledge is
cumulative-authors and inventors must necessarily build on what came
before them.' Indeed, if they did not do so, the societal costs in terms
of reinvention would be enormous.3 1 Try to imagine building something
as complex as a car, without using any ideas from anyone who came before
you (including such things as the wheel, nuts and bolts, screws, glass, and
the combustion engine). As countless economists have demonstrated,
efficient creation of new works requires access to and use of old works.3'
And since "improvements" may in many cases dwarf the original work in
terms of their practical significance,33 dynamic market efficiency over dif-
ferent generations demands such access as well.
But intellectual property limits the public's ability to access and use
old works. The creators of old works can, if they choose, refuse to distri-
28. See infra notes 38-47 and accompanying text (briefly describing a few of the ways in which
intellectual property rights are limited).
29. For efforts to strike the optimal balance between these costs and benefits, see, for example,
WILLIAM D. NoRDHAus, INVENTION, GROWTH AND WELFARE: A THEORETICAL TREATMENT OF
TECHNOLOGICAL CHANGE (1969). On the indeterminacy of the whole endeavor, see Louis Kaplow,
The Patent-Antitrust Intersection: A Reappraisal, 97 HARV. L. REV. 1813 (1984). Cf. TED
O'D6NOGHUE ET AL., PATENT BREADTH, PATENT LIFE AND THE PACE OF TECHNOLOGICAL
IMPROVEMENT (Univ. of Cal. at Berkeley Dep't of Econs. Working Paper No. 95-242, Oct. 1995)
(asserting that effective patent life is a function not only of statutory term, but also of patent breadth,
which affects the period within which the patent will be superseded by a noninfringing invention).
30. The most famous formulation of this phenomenon is credited to Sir Isaac Newton, who
reportedly said, "If I have seen further it is by standing on the shoulders of giants." THE OXFORD
DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS 362 (3d ed. 1979). This is occasionally referred to in computer law as
the OTSOG ("On the Shoulders of Giants") principle.
31. Cy. Mark A. Lemley & David O'Brien, EncouragingSoftware Reuse, 49 STAN. L. REV.
(forthcoming Jan. 1997) (documenting costs of partial reinvention in the software industry).
32. See, e.g., PAUL DAVID, NEW TECHNOLOGY, DIFFUSION, PUBLIC POLICY, AND INDUSTRIAL
COMPETITIVENESS20 (Center for Econ. Policy Research, Publication Policy Paper No. 46, Apr. 1985);
MORTON I. KAMIEN & NANCY L. SCHWARTZ, MARKET STRUCTURE AND INNOVATION 3-9 (1982);
RICHARD R. NELSON & SIDNEY G. WINTER, AN EVOLUTIONARY THEORY OF ECONOMIC CHANGE 130
(1982); Robert P. Merges & Richard R. Nelson, On the Complex Economics of Patent Scope, 90
COLUM. L. REV. 839, 908 (1990); Nathan Rosenberg, FactorsAffecting the Dison of Technology,
10 EXPLORATIONS ECON. HIST. 3, 3 (1972); SuzanneScotchmer, Standingon the Shoulders of Giants:
Cumulative Research and the PatentLaw, J. ECON. PERSP., Winter 1991, at 29, 30-31.
33. See, e.g., John L. Enos, A Measure of the Rate of TechnologicalProgressin the Petroleum
Refining Industry, 6 J. INDUS. ECON. 180, 188-89 (1958); James Mak & Gary M. Walton, Steamboats
and the Great Productivity Surge in River Transportation, 32 J. ECON. HIST. 619, 625 (1972).
Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
bute them to anyone at all, at any price, during the duration of intellectual
property protection.' While most creators will not prevent access alto-
gether, they can and do exercise control over who can use their creation,
the purposes for which they can use it, and the price they must pay. Intel-
lectual property owners may use these rights not only to obtain a return on
their investment in research and development, but also to exercise content
control over subsequent uses of their works or to prevent the development
of a competitive market for their products.35 Even if the intellectual
property owner is willing to license his rights on reasonable terms, or even
if the work turns out to be in the public domain, someone who wants to
use the work must expend time and resources identifying intellectual
property owners and negotiating with them. Improvers also bear the risk
of failing to identify every intellectual property owner and unknowingly
infringing on a prior intellectual property right. In each of these
circumstances, the existence of preexisting intellectual property rights
imposes a positive cost on improvers that they would not otherwise face.36
It is not enough to say that intellectual property law favors "creators"-for
here we have creators on both sides of the equation, and the law must
choose between them.37
Because original developers and improvers will not always find each
other and agree to license the original work ex ante, the intellectual
property rules governing improvements are important in understanding the
extent to which protection for first-generation innovation will impede
improvement in subsequent generations. The more absolute the property
right given to original authors and inventors, the more critical efficient
34. See 35 U.S.C. § 271(d)(4) (1994) (providing that patent owner may refuse to license patent);
Salinger v. Random House, Inc., 811 F.2d 90, 94 (2d Cir. 1987) (allowing J.D. Salinger to prevent
Random House from publishing his letters); Continental Paper Bag Co. v. Eastern Paper Bag Co., 210
U.S. 405, 424 (1908) (holding that a patentee is entitled to suppress a patent entirely). In some cases,
such as trademarks and trade secrets, the duration of the intellectual property right may be indefinite.
See 15 U.S.C. §§ 1058(a), 1059(a) (1994) (trademarks); Warner-Lambert Pharm. Co. v. John 3.
Reynolds, Inc., 178 F. Supp. 655, 661 (S.D.N.Y. 1959) (trade secrets), aff'd, 280 F.2d 197 (2d Cir.
1960).
35. The circumstances in which an intellectual property owner might refuse to license his idea are
explored in detail infra Part V.
36. See Merges & Nelson, supra note 32, at 868-70; Scotchmer, supra note 32, at 38; Stewart E.
Sterk, Rhetoric and Reality in Copyright Law, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1197, 1207-08 (1996); Brian R.
Landy, Comment, The Two Strands of the FairUse Web: A Theoryfor Resolving the Dilemma ofMusic
Parody, 54 OHIO ST. LJ. 227, 227 (1993).
37. For a discussion of the parameters of this choice, see Glynn S. Lunney, Jr., Lotus v. Borland:
CopyrightandComputer Programs,70 TUL. L. REv. 2397,2418-22 (1996). Paul Goldstein describes
a paradox wherein "every infringer of a derivative right is, by definition, itself the potential copyright
owner of a derivative work, with an equal claim on copyright's system of investment incentives." Paul
Goldstein, Derivative Rights and Derivative Works in Copyright, 30 J. COPYRIGHT Soc'y 209, 211
(1983). He is certainly correct that this fact "seriously complicates" the task of establishing optimal
infringement rules. Id.
1997] Economics of Improvement
Robert Merges and Richard Nelson have modeled the scope of patent
rights in detailed economic terms.4 8 In this Article, I deal with a subset
of the broader question of the proper scope for intellectual property
rights-what happens in those cases in which an improvement falls squarely
within the scope of an intellectual property right still in force? In those
cases, the improver is at the mercy of the original intellectual property
owner, unless the intellectual property laws offer improvers relief from
infringement actions in certain circumstances. It is to that latter issue that
I turn in Parts II and III.
more lenient treatment to accused infringers who designed around the patent in an effort to avoid
infringement. See Roton Barrier, Inc. v. Stanley Works, 79 F.3d 1112, 1127 (Fed. Cir. 1996); Hilton
Davis Chem. Co. v. Wamer-Jenkinson Co., 62 F.3d 1512, 1520 (Fed. Cir. 1995) (en bane) (both
holding that evidence of designing around a specific patent gives rise to an inference of no
infringement). However, the Supreme Court's recent decision in Warner-JenkinsonCo. v. HiltonDavis
Chemical Co., 65 U.S.L.W. 4162 (U.S. Mar. 3, 1997), appears to foreclose such favorable treatment.
48. Merges & Nelson, supra note 32.
49. By contrast, every other form of intellectual property vests at least partial rights in the owner
upon creation of the work or satisfaction of the requirements of protection.
50. See 35 U.S.C. §§ 101-103, 112 (1994).
51. An inventor can obtain a patent on a device without having ever built that device, so long as
it is described sufficiently that one skilled in the art could build it. See Hazeltine Corp. v. United
States, 820 F.2d 1190, 1196-97 (Fed. Cir. 1987).
52. 35 U.S.C. § 112 para. 2 (1994) ("The specification shall conclude with one or more claims
particularly pointing out and distinctly claiming the subject matter which the applicant regards as his
invention.").
53. See DatascopeCorp. v. SMEC, Inc., 879 F.2d 820, 824 (Fed. Cir. 1989) ("[I]t is claims, not
commercial embodiments, that are infringed." (emphasis in original)).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1001
matter that the accused product is different from the inventor's product, or
even that the inventor could not possibly have built the accused product.
The defendant must avoid any infringement on the territory covered by the
claim.
For this reason, an inventor can expand the reach of his patent by
drafting claims as broadly as possible. For example, the inventor of a
pencil will be better off claiming an "instrument for writing" than a
"hexagonal cylinder constructed of wood, the center of which is hollow
and filled with graphite, and which is capable of being sharpened for use
in marking on paper." The former claim will capture more ground for the
patent owner. Not only will octagonal or round pencils fall within the
scope of the first claim, but so too might pens, mechanical pencils, and
signature machines.
There are two basic limits on the ability of inventors to draft broad
claims. First, because novelty and nonobviousness are tested with respect
to the language of the claims," a claim must not cover something already
invented, or which is merely an obvious extension of prior work. Thus,
the scope of a patentee's claims is limited by the "prior art" in the field.
The effect of the novelty rule is clear-you are not entitled to a patent on
something that someone else has already invented or described. If your
"invention" duplicates another's, then in theory you have not added any
social value to justify obtaining an exclusive right.55 The nonobviousness
rule requires still more from the patentee than an invention no one else has
come up with. What is required is an inventive leap-some quantum of
improvement over what has come before.56 In effect, the nonobviousness
requirement sets a minimum threshold social value the invention must con-
tribute in order to make it worth the trouble of issuing and enforcing a
patent. It also prevents patentees from overclaiming their invention. For
example, the inventor of the pencil cannot get away with claiming an
54. See RCA Corp. v. Applied Digital Data Sys., Inc., 730 F.2d 1440, 1444 (Fed. Cir. 1984).
55. Reality is not that simple. An inventor may add value in the way he describes the invention,
in making it known to a greater segment of the public, or in taking the steps necessary to commer-
cialize it. But these aspects of innovation are not normally protected by patent law if the invention
itself is already in the public domain. For a proposal to protect commercialization efforts directly, see
William Kingston, The Innovation Warrant, in DIRECT PROTECTION OF INNOVATION 59 (William
Kingston ed., 1987), and for criticism thereof, see, for example, Thomas Mandeville & Stuart
Macdonald, Innovation Protection Viewed from an Information Perspective, in DIRECT PROTECTION
OF INNOVATION, supra, at 157; Andrd Piatier, Innovation Patent, Invention Patent, or Both?, in
DIRECT PROTECTION OF INNOVATION, supra, at 125; and Gordon Tullock, Intellectual Property, in
DIRECT PROTECTION OF INNOVATION, supra, at 171.
56. See ROBERT PATRICK MEROES, PATENT LAW AND POLICY 379 (1992) ("Nonobviousness can
be thought of as a kind of 'nontriviality' requirement ... [that] attempts to measure an even more
abstract quality than novelty or utility: the technical accomplishment reflected in an invention. This
requirement asks in essence whether an invention is a big enough technical advance to merit the award
of a patent." (emphasis in original)).
1002 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
invention.' It has since been expanded by the courts into an integral part
of the infringement analysis of every patent,' though the scope and
application of the doctrine remain a matter of some dispute. As presently
conceived, the doctrine of equivalents provides that accused products or
processes that do not fall within the literal scope of the patent claims
nonetheless infringe the patent if they are only "insubstantially different"
from the patent claims.' The effect is to create a "penumbra" around the
literal scope of the claims, and therefore to expand the protection given to
patent owners.' Figure 1 diagrams the scope of patent protection in
simple terms.
Figure 1
invention
range of equivalents
non-infringing products
63. See Graver Tank & Mfg. Co. v. Linde Air Prods. Co., 339 U.S. 605, 607-08 (1950);
Westinghouse v. Boyden Power Brake Co., 170 U.S. 537, 569 (1898).
64. See Hilton Davis Chem.Co. v. Warner-Jenkinson Co., 62 F.3d 1512 (Fed. Cir. 1995) (en
banc) (per curiam) (holding that in every infringement case the trial judge must apply the doctrine of
equivalents), rev'd on other grounds, 65 U.S.L.W. 4162 (U.S. Mar. 3, 1997); Peter K. Schalestock,
Comment, Equityfor Whom? Defining the Reach of Non-Literal PatentInfringement, 19 SFAiTE U.
L. REV. 323 (1996) (criticizing this change).
65. Hilton Davis, 62 F.3d at 1521-22. The court in Hilton Davis provided significant guidance
as to what factors should be used in determining the substantiality of a difference. The court stated that
while the "function-way-result" test developed by the Supreme Court in Graver Tank will often be suf-
ficient to show the extent of differences between the patented product and the accused device, the ulti-
mate test of infringement under the doctrine of equivalents is whether the differences between the
claims and the accused device are "insubstantial." Id. The court also recognized the utility of other
factors, including evidence of copying and designing around. Id.
The Supreme Court's recent decision in Warner-JenkinsonCo. v. Hilton Davis Chemical Co.,
65 U.S.L.W. 4162 (U.S. Mar. 3, 1997), is largely consistent with this approach. The Court concluded
that "the particular linguistic framework used is less important than whether the test is probative of the
essential inquiry" of equivalence between each element. Id. at 4168. It did modify the Federal
Circuit's opinion in some respects, rejecting the use of copying and design-around and strengthening
the role of prosecution history estoppel. Id. at 4167-68.
66. HiltonDavis, 62 F.3d at 1534.
19971 Economics of Improvement 1005
B. EvaluatingInfringement by Improvers
Changes in products and processes occur all the time. Trying some-
thing new in the hope of improving on an existing product or process is an
integral part of the competitive process. Sometimes these changes will
actually improve the existing product or make its production more efficient,
and therefore contribute to social value. Other changes may be value-
neutral (that is, the new product may be just as good or as efficient as the
existing product), or they may actually be inefficient (producing less useful
products, or products that cost more than the existing ones).
Where the existing product is patented, improvers must avoid the
literal scope of the patent claims and equivalents thereof in order to sell a
competing product. Not every change from the actual product invented by
the patent owner will avoid infringement, since some will fall within the
literal scope of the patent claims. In Figure 1, these changes will fall
within circle C-D, although they are not within the actual scope of what the
inventor created (A-B). Still other changes will fall outside the literal
scope of the patent claims, but within the somewhat amorphous range of
67. Cf. Diamond Rubber Co. v. Consolidated Rubber Tire Co., 220 U.S. 428, 435-36 (1911)
(holding that a patentee need not understand why or how his invention works, so long as it does);
Eames v. Andrews, 122 U.S. 40, 55 (1887) (holding that a patent is no less valid simply because the
inventor neither knows nor includes the scientific principle on which the invention is based).
68. 717 F.2d 1351 (Fed. Cir. 1983).
69. Id. at 1365; accord Laser Alignment, Inc. v. Woodruff& Sons, Inc., 491 F.2d 866 (7th Cir.
1974) (holding that the use of a laser to align pipe segments infringed a patent for using ordinary
beams of light to align pipe).
1006 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
trical patents based on analog technology have been asserted against new
(and in most cases dramatically improved) digital implementations.7 6 At
the other end of the spectrum, changes with little or no social value may
be sufficient to avoid infringement of a patent, especially if the claims are
narrowly drafted. For example, the narrow claim for a pencil described
above might not be infringed by a seven-sided cylinder, or a cylinder made
of plastic, even though changing the shape or composition of the pencil has
no impact on its performance. Indeed, in some cases competitors may be
encouraged to adopt inefficient solutions in order to avoid infringement.
The only clear way to avoid infringing on a patent is to use a product that
was in the prior artl--an approach which does not capture any of the
value of the patented invention.
C. Mechanismsfor ProtectingImprovers
Patent law does, however, provide two doctrines which encourage
improvements, even when those improvements infringe on the underlying
patent. It is useful to distinguish three general cases, that I will call here
the minor improver, the significant improver, and the radical improver.
76. See Decca Ltd. v. United States, 544 F.2d 1070, 1081 (Ct. Cl. 1976).
77. See Wilson Sporting Goods Co. v. David Geoffrey & Assocs., 904 F.2d 677, 684 (Fed. Cir.
1990) ("[Slince prior art always limits what an inventor could have claimed, it limits the range of
permissible equivalents of a claim."). This rule seems an obvious and necessary extension of the gene-
ral principle that patent claims which cover, even in part, material that was in the prior art are invalid.
See, e.g., Malta v. Schulmerich Carillons, Inc., 952 F.2d 1320, 1342 (Fed. Cir. 1991); Intel Corp.
v. United States Int'l Trade Comm'n, 946 F.2d 821, 842 (Fed. Cir. 1991); see also Paul M. Janicke,
Heat of Passion: lfha Really Happened in Graver Tank, 24 AIPLA QJ. 1, 91 n.329 (1996) (citing
over 30 cases and commentators in agreement). Even this seemingly obvious rule has been called into
question, however. See Baxter Healthcare Corp. v. Spectramed, Inc., 49 F.3d 1575, 1583 (Fed. Cir.)
(holding that accused device may infringe patent even though accused device is obvious in view of the
prior art), cert. denied, 116 S. Ct. 272 (1995). The approach taken in Baxter seems both incorrect as
a matter of policy and flatly inconsistent with Wilson Sporting Goods.
78. This need not be the case. The requirement that a patented invention be "useful" is only laxly
enforced. See Tol-O-Matic, Inc. v. Proma Produkt-Und Marketing G.m.b.H., 945 F.2d 1546, 1553
(Fed. Cir. 1991); Moleculon Research Corp. v. CBS, Inc., 793 F.2d 1261, 1269 (Fed. Cir. 1986);
cf. United States Steel Corp. v. Phillips Petroleum Co., 865 F.2d 1247 (Fed. Cir. 1989) (holding that
a finding of infringement compels a finding of utility). It is therefore theoretically possible to obtain
a patent on a nonobvious but inefficient (relative to the prior art) way of doing things. Nonetheless,
this hypothetical case need not detain us, since infringement of such a patent would presumably be rare.
1008 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
79. On the value of first mover advantages, see Richard C. Levin et al., Appropriatingthe Returns
from Industrial Research and Development, 3 BROOKINGS PAPERS ON ECON. ACTIVITY 783, 816
(1987). On the limitations of such advantages, particularly in industries where copying is easy, see
William L. Baldwin & Gerald L. Childs, The FastSecond and Rivalry in Research and Development,
36 S. ECON. 1. 18, 21 (1969); Janusz A. Ordover, Economic Foundations'andConsiderationsin
ProtectingIndustrialand Intellectual Property, 53 ANTITRUST L.J. 503, 507 (1985).
80. I discuss factors relevant to setting the proper upper value for "significant" improvements in
Part VI.
81. By hypothesis, the improvement is nonobvious-it has contributed more than the minimum
social value required for patentability. Naturally, the minimum social value test is highly stylized.
Improvers must meet other requirements, such as enablement and utility, in order to qualify for a patent
on their improvement. Still, these factors should not concern us unduly. Enablement is generally
1997] Economics of'Improvement 1009
within the control of a patent applicant, and an improvement to an existing patent with significant social
value will normally clear the utility hurdle with ease.
82. 236 F. 942 (S.D.N.Y. 1916), aftd, 243 F. 560 (2d Cir. 1917).
83. On this problem, see Robert P. Merges, Rent Control in the PatentDistrict: Observationson
the Grady-AlexanderThesis, 78 VA. L. REV. 359, 379 n.73 (1992).
84. 79 F.2d 20, 22 (2d Cir. 1935).
85. See supra note 74. But see Zygo Corp. v. Wyko Corp., 79 F.3d 1563 (Fed. Cir. 1996)
(suggesting that an improvement's patentability is evidence of noninfringement).
86. See 35 U.S.C. § 154 (1994) (providing only the right to exclude others from working the
invention, rather than an affirmative right to practice the invention). Cases involving blocking patents
1010 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
patents."" The original patent owner can prevent the improver from
using his patented technology, but the improver can also prevent the
original patent owner from using the improvement. Unless the parties
bargain, no one gets the benefit of the improvement."
include Cantrellv. Wallick, 117 U.S. 689, 694 (1886); Cochranev. Deener, 94 U.S. 780, 787 (1877);
Atlas Powder Co. v. E.L du PontDe Nemours & Co., 750 F.2d 1569, 1576 (Fed. Cir. 1984); Ziegler
v. Phillips Petroleum Co., 483 F.2d 858, 871-72 (5th Cir. 1973); and Bryan v. Sid W. Richardson,
Inc., 254 F.2d 191, 194 (5th Cir. 1958), as well as those cited above.
87. For general treatments of blocking patents in the literature, see, for example, Robert Merges,
Intellectual PropertyRights and BargainingBreakdown: The Case ofBlocking Patents, 62 TENN. L.
REV. 75 (1994); Merges & Nelson, supra note 32, at 860-62. For our purposes, patents on comple-
mentary goods owned by different parties might also be thought to be "blocking" in a limited sense.
If I own the patent on a hammer and you own the patent on an anvil, each of us is free to make our
own products, so the patents are not strictly "blocking." However, absent a license agreement neither
of us may be able to exploit our patents to maximum advantage, because of the synergy between the
two. See Michael A. Sanzo, Antitrust Law and PatentMisconduct in the ProprietaryDrugIndustry,
39 ViLL. L. REV. 1209, 1245-46 (1994); David S. Taylor, Note, The Sinking of the United States
Electronics Industry Within JapanesePatent Pools, 26 GEO. WASH. J.INT'L L. & ECON. 181, 201
(1992).
88. This is strictly true only if the patents are completely rather than partially blocking. Because
of the way a particular pair of patent claims is written, it is possible that the overlap between the two
claims will be only partial. For example, a claim on an improvement might prevent the original inven-
tor from using that improvement only in a certain way or in combination with some but not all other
products. Such situations may be thought of as involving "partially blocking patents."
89. See supra notes 30-33 and accompanying text.
90. This last example is not exactly hypothetical. Texas Instruments, for example, has asserted
its basic calculatorpatent against a variety of modem products containing integrated circuits. See, e.g.,
Texas Instruments, Inc. v. United States Int'l Trade Comm'n, 805 F.2d 1558 (Fed. Cir. 1986)
(asserting Texas Instruments' patent rights against importers of modem calculators).
91. See Phillips Petroleum Co. v. United States Steel Corp., 673 F. Supp. 1278 (D. Del. 1987),
aft'd, 865 F.2d 1247 (Fed. Cir. 1989) ("[Tlhe mere fact that the accused products are superior does
not, in and of itself, permit Defendants to escape liability under the reverse doctrine of equivalents.").
92. On the reverse doctrine of equivalents generally, see SR[ Internationalv. MatsushitaElectric
Corp., 775 F.2d 1107 (Fed. Cir. 1985); Laura A. Handley, Refining the Graver Tank Analysis with
Hypothetical Claims: A Biotechnology Exemplar, 5 HARV. J.L. & TECH. 31, 40-41 (1991); C.F.
Pigott, Jr., Equivalents in Reverse, 48 J. PAT. & TRADEMARK OFF. SOc'Y 291 (1966); Michael S.
Greenfield, Note, RecombinantDNA Technology. A Science Struggling with the PatentLaw, 44 STAN.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1011
Despite its name and its origin,' the reverse doctrine of equivalents
is not merely the "flip side" of the doctrine of equivalents used in infringe-
ment analysis.' The reverse doctrine protects from infringement a
product "so far changed in principle from a patented article that it performs
the same or a similar function in a substantially different way, but
nevertheless falls within the literal words of the claim."' While the
reverse doctrine offers relief from infringement for radical improvers, its
application by the courts to excuse literal infringement is rare.' Unlike
the doctrine of equivalents, which can apply both to technology known at
the time of the patent application and to subsequently developed
technology,' the only application of the reverse doctrine is to protect
subsequent improvements from infringement if they are sufficiently
radical.98 An example of the reverse doctrine at work is Scripps Clinic
& Research Foundationv. Genentech, Inc." In that case, Scripps had a
patent for a blood clotting product, human Factor VIII:C, which it purified
from human blood. Genentech produced identical Factor VIII:C from
laboratory bacteria using recombinant DNA processes. Genentech argued
that its recombinant Factor VIII:C was "changed in principle" from
Scripps's purified Factor VIII:C.1 ° The Federal Circuit held that
L. REV. 1051, 1078-79 (1992); and Jonathan Geld, Back Upi-Using the Reverse Doctrine of
Equivalents to Halt the Advance of Functionally Claimed Software 3-24 (1996) (unpublished
manuscript, on file with the Texas Law Review).
93. Westinghouse v. Boyden Power Brake Co., 170 U.S. 537 (1898) is generally cited as the first
case establishing the reverse doctrine of equivalents. In Graver Tank, the Supreme Court referred to
the doctrine of equivalents as a unified phenomenon that included within its scope the reverse doctrine
of equivalents. See Graver Tank & Mfg. Co. v. Linde Air Prods. Co., 339 U.S. 605, 608-09 (1950).
Nonetheless, the development of the doctrines has not been entirely parallel.
94. See Mark D. Janis, Unmasking Structural Equivalency: The Intersection of § 112, 6
Equivalentsandthe Doctrine ofEquivalents, 4 ALE. L.J. Sa. & TECH. 205,213-15 (1994) (identifying
differences in the two analyses).
95. Graver Tank, 339 U.S. at 608-09; see also Handley, supra note 92, at 41 (comparing the
"different in principle" test to the function-way-resulttest traditionally applied in doctrine of equivalents
cases).
96. See Geld, supra note 92, at 9 (observing that only five reported decisions accept a reverse
doctrine of equivalents argument and the vast majority of courts reject the argument when it is pre-
sented to them). Merges and Nelson suggest that the doctrine must be rarely used in order to preserve
the certainty (and therefore the incentive effect) associated with the patent. Merges & Nelson, supra
note 32, at 867 n.120.
97. See, e.g., Pennwalt Corp. v. Durand-Wayland, Inc., 833 F.2d 931, 941-42 n.4 (Fed. Cir.
1987) (en banc) (Bennett, J., dissenting); Texas Instruments, Inc. v. United States Int'l Trade Cormm'n,
805 F.2d 1558, 1563 (Fed. Cir. 1986); Merges & Nelson, supra note 32, at 855.
98. It is also worth noting that the reverse doctrine of equivalents seems to involve evaluating
equivalence between the claimed invention and the accused product viewed as a whole, as opposed to
the element-by-element approach used in the doctrine of equivalents. CompareTexas Instruments, 805
F.2d at 1571 (discussing the reverse doctrine of equivalents), vith Pennwalt, 833 F.2d at 935-39
(discussing the doctrine of equivalents).
99. 927 F.2d 1565 (Fed. Cir. 1991).
100. Id. at 1581.
1012 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
101. Id.; see also Leesona Corp. v. United States, 530 F.2d 896, 906 (Ct. Cl. 1976); Precision
Metal Fabricators, Inc. v. Jetstream Sys. Co., 693 F. Supp. 814, 819 (N.D. Cal. 1988); Beloit Corp.
v. J.M. Voith, G.m.b.H., 626 F. Supp. 991, 1007-08 (E.D. Va.), aff'd, 802 F.2d 471 (Fed. Cir.
1986) (all finding no infringement based on reverse doctrine of equivalents). But see Kevin J.
McGough & Daniel P. Burke, A Casefor Expansive Patent Protectionof Biotechnology Inventions, 6
HARv. J.L. & TECH. 85, 97-98 (1992) (arguing that Scripps provides weak precedent for the reverse
doctrine of equivalents, since the court also noted possible differences between the products produced
by the two methods).
102. See Greenfield, supra note 92, at 1090-91. For a general discussion of the patentability of
ESTs, and a brief review of past efforts to patent them, see Rebecca S.Eisenberg & Robert P. Merges,
OpinionLetter as to the Patentabilityof CertainInventions Associatedwith the Identificationof Partial
eDNA Sequences, 23 AIPLA Q.J. 1 (1995).
103. Eisenberg and Merges raise this point obliquely when they suggest that patents on research
tools are more troubling than patents on end products because of the danger that research patents will
restrict further productive uses of those research tools. However, they do not treat the problem
explicitly under the reverse doctrine of equivalents. The debate over patents on research tools is played
out in a recent issue of the AIPLA Quarterly Journal. See Eisenberg & Merges, supra note 102, at
19; Scott A. Chambers, Comments on the Patentabili of Certain Inventions Associated with the
Identification of PartialcDNA Sequences, 23 AIPLA Q.J. 53, 53-54 (1995) (arguing that patents on
research tools are no more dangerous than other patents because they remove nothing from the public
domain); Rebecca S.Eisenberg& Robert P. Merges, Reply to Comments on the Patentabilityof Certain
InventionsAssociated with the Identification of PartialcDNA Sequences, 23 AIPLA Q.J. 61, 62 (1995)
(arguing that patents on research tools will restrict the dissemination of these tools to other researchers).
104. For a discussion of how to calibrate these values in practice, as well as the economic impli-
cations of the reverse doctrine of equivalents, see infra Part V.
105. Radical improvers who do not fall within the literal language of the claims do not, strictly
speaking, benefit from the reverse doctrine of equivalents, which applies only in cases of literal
infringement. See Merges & Nelson, supra note 32, at 867 n.120. In practical terms, however, the
effect of applying the reverse doctrine is the same as failing to find infringement under the doctrine of
equivalents-in either case, the question is whether there are substantial differences between the
patented method and the accused product. Thus, in some sense all findings of nonequivalencehave the
same basis.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1013
106. For an interesting suggestion that application of the reverse doctrine of equivalents may
actually benefit patentees in some circumstances by cementing the validityof the patent claims, see Karl
Bozicevic, The "Reverse Doctrine of Equivalents" in the World of Reverse Transcriptase,71 J. PAT.
& TRADEMARK OFF. Soc'Y 353, 354 (1989).
107. One caveat is in order here. Under U.S. copyright law, registration of the copyrighted work
is a prerequisite to filing suit for copyright infringement. See 17 U.S.C. § 411(a) (1994). In that
limited sense, a copyright in a work is only a potential right until it is registered.
108. Section 102(a) provides a nonexclusive list of the types of works eligible for copyright pro-
tection. Id. § 102(a).
109. See Feist Publications, Inc. v. Rural Tel. Serv. Co., 499 U.S. 340, 345 (1991) ("Original,
as the term is used in copyright, means only that the work was independently created by the author...
and that it possesses at least some minimal degree of creativity.").
110. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(a) (1994). The requirement is satisfied when the embodiment of the
work "issufficiently permanent or stable to permit it to be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise
communicated for a period of more than transitory duration." Id. § 101. The fixation requirement is
quite easily satisfied, at least under certain modem cases. See MAI Sys. Corp. v. Peak Computer,
Inc., 991 F.2d 511, 518 (9th Cir. 1993) (holding that the loading of copyrighted software into a
computer's RAM for diagnosis of computer problems creates a copy that is sufficiently permanent to
be fixed).
111. The term of a copyright depends on who creates it. In the case of individual authors, it
extends for the life of the author plus 50 years. See 17 U.S.C. § 302(a) (1994). In the case of works
made for hire, the term is 75 years from the date of publication, or 100 years from creation, whichever
is shorter. See id. § 302(c). Legislation currently pending before Congress would extend each of these
terms by 20 years. See Copyright Term Extension Act of 1997, H.R. 604, 105th Cong. § 2.
1014 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
112. The fair use defense to infringement is a third significant limitation on copyright. Fair use
is discussed in more detail below. See infra notes 171-96 and accompanying text.
113. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(b) (1994).
114. See Feist, 499 U.S. at 347-51.
115. See, e.g., Nicholsv. Universal Pictures Corp., 45 F.2d 119, 121 (2d Cir. 1930).
116. See Mazer v. Stein, 347 U.S. 201, 212-13 (1954).
117. See Computer Assocs. Int'l, Inc. v. Altai, Inc., 982 F.2d 693, 714 (2d Cir. 1992).
118. See generally A. Samuel Oddi, An Uneasier Casefor Copyrightthanfor PatentProtection
of Computer Programs, 72 NEB. L. Rsv. 351 (1993); Pamela Samuelson et al., A Manifesto
Concerningthe Legal Protection of Computer Programs,94 COLUM. L. REV. 2308 (1994) (both dis-
cussing the limitations of copyright protection of computer programs).
119. Subject to the narrow limitation discussed supra notes 89-106 and accompanying text.
120. See 2 PAUL GOLDSTMIN COPYRIGHT § 7.2.2, at 7:19 (2d ed. 1996).
121. Because direct evidence of copying is typically unavailable, courts allow evidence that a
defendant had access to the copyrighted work and that the two works are substantially similar to serve
as a surrogate for proof of copying. See, e.g., Sid & Marty Krofft Television Prods., Inc. v.
McDonald's Corp., 562 F.2d 1157, 1162 (9th Cir. 1977); Arnstein v. Porter, 154 F.2d 464, 468 (2d
Cir. 1946).
122. See 17 U.S.C. § 106 (1994) (providing that a copyright gives the owner the exclusive right
to copy, adapt, distribute, and in some cases publicly perform or display the work). The exception to
1997] Economics of Improvement 1015
B. EvaluatingInfringement by Improvers
Unlike patents, copyrights do not have claims. Infringement is tested
by comparing the accused work to the copyrighted work to determine
whether substantial copying has occurred." z The simplest case is one in
which the entire copyrighted work has been copied verbatim. This of
course constitutes infringement, 124 just as copying the patent owner's in-
vention infringes the patent. Beyond this point, however, the patent and
copyright infringement tests diverge. For one thing, it is possible to
infringe a copyright by copying only a small portion of the copyright
owner's work. Copying even a few hundred words from a book,"z or
a few seconds of music from a song,12 may be enough to infringe the
copyright in the entire work. By contrast, copying part but not all of a
claimed invention is not patent infringement, since every element of the
this rule is digitized information, where the courts have effectively enabled the copyright owner to
control private uses of the work by defining any use in a computer or computer network as involving
the creation of a copy. See, e.g., MAI Sys. Corp. v. Peak Computer, Inc., 991 F.2d 511, 519 (9th
Cir. 1993) (holdingthat the transfer of a computer program from a permanent storage device to a com-
puter RAM creates a copy for copyright purposes). For criticism of this approach, see, for example,
Fred H. Cate, Law in Cyberspace, 39 HOwARD L.J. 565, 575-77 (1996); Margaret Chon, New Wine
Burstingfrom Old Bottles: Collaborative InternetArt, Joint Works, and Entrepreneurship,75 OR. L.
REV. 257,260-63 (1996); Niva Elkin-Koren, Copyright Law andSocial Dialogue on the Information
Superhighway:The Case Against CopyrightLiability of Bulletin Board Operators, 13 CARDOZO ARTS
& ENT. L.J. 345, 381-83 (1995); Mark A. Lemley, Dealing with Overlapping Copyrights on the
Internet, 22 U. DAYTON L. REV. (forthcoming 1997) (manuscript at 5-6, on file with the Texas Law
Review); Jessica Litman, Revising Copyright Lawfor the Information Age, 75 OR. L. REv. 19, 21
(1996); Jessica Litman, The Exclusive Right to Read, 13 CARDozO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 29, 41-43
(1994); Charles R. McManis, Taking TRIPs on the InformationSuperhighway:InternationalIntellectual
Property Protection and Emerging Computer Technology, 41 VILL. L. REV. 207, 263-68 (1996);
Barbara Cohen, Note, A ProposedRegime for Copyright Protectionon the Internet,22 BROOKLYN J.
INT'L L. 401, 412 (1996); Michael E. Johnson, Note, The Uncertain Future of Computer Software
Users' Rights in the Aftermath of MAI Systems, 44 DuKE L.J. 327, 333-36 (1994); Katrine Levin,
Note, MAI v. Peak: Should Loading Operating System Software into RAM Constitute Copyright
Infringement?, 24 GOLDEN GATE U. L. REv. 649 (1994); James V. Mahon, Note, A Commentary on
ProposalsforCopyrightProtectionon the NationalInformationInfrastructure,22 RUTRmS COMPUTER
& TECH. L.J. 233, 240-45 (1996); Carol G. Stovsky, Note, MAI Systems Corp. v. Peak Computer,
Inc.: Using CopyrightLaw to ProhibitUnauthorizedUse of ComputerSoftware, 56 OHIO ST. L.J. 593,
600-09 (1995); and compare David Nimmer, Brains and Other Paraphernalia of the Digital Age, 10
HARV. J.L. & TECH. 1, 10-12 (1996) (endorsing the result of MAI under existing law, but proposing
statutory changes to ameliorate its effects).
123. While courts often confuse the issue of "substantial similarity" between two works as evi-
dence of copying with the issue of whether substantial protected expression has in fact been taken, the
two issues are analytically distinct. See Cohen, supra note 44, at 735-39 (criticizing courts for con-
flating the determination that a work was actually copied with the determination that such copying went
so far as to constitute improper appropriation).
124. The finding of infringement is subject to the fair use defense. See Sony Corp. v. Universal
City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 433 (1984) (holding, in the context of videotaping television shows
for later viewing, that even verbatim copying of an entire work can be fair use in some circumstances).
125. See Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 548-49 (1985).
126. See Jarvis v. A & M Records, 827 F. Supp. 282, 288-93 (D.N.J. 1993); Grand Upright
Music Ltd. v. Warner Bros. Records, Inc., 780 F. Supp. 182, 183-85 (S.D.N.Y. 1991).
1016 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
127. See Permwalt Corp. v. Durand-Wayland, Inc., 833 F.2d 931, 939 (Fed. Cir. 1987) (en
bane).
128. There are a number of defenses in the Copyright Act permitting various acts of copying for
certain public interest purposes, or allowing certain acts on the payment of a compulsory license fee.
See 17 U.S.C. §§ 107-120 (1994). One of these defenses, the fair use doctrine, is discussed in greater
detail infra notes 171-96 and accompanying text.
129. Nichols v. Universal Pictures Corp., 45 F.2d 119, 121 (2d Cir. 1930).
130. See, e.g., Sheldon v. Metro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp., 309 U.S. 390, 396-98, 397 (1940)
(confirming that the appropriation of a story line beyond the "mere use of [the] basic plot" could
amount to copyright infringement).
131. See Whelan Assocs., Inc. v. Jaslow Dental Lab., Inc., 797 F.2d 1222, 1248 (3d Cir. 1986);
Computer Assocs. Int'l, Inc. v. Altai, Inc., 982 F.2d 693, 702-12 (2d Cir. 1992).
132. See Roth Greeting Cards v. United Card Co., 429 F.2d 1106, 1110 (9th Cir. 1970); see also
Sid & Marty Krofft Television Prods., Inc. v. McDonald's Corp., 562 F.2d 1157, 1167 (9th Cir.
1977); Arnstein v. Porter, 154 F.2d 464, 469-73 (2d Cir. 1946) (both applying the "total concept and
feel" test).
133. See Sheldon, 309 U.S. at 409 (enjoining a successful movie based in part on a copyrighted
play, even though only a small part of the movie literally infringed the script); see also Abend v. MCA,
Inc., 863 F.2d 1465, 1478-80 (9th Cir. 1988) (noting the potential availability of damages on remand
for the continued use of the movie Rear Window, a derivative work based on plaintiff's original short
story, but refusing to make available an injunction against continued distribution because of a valid
license existing when the movie was made), aff'd on other grounds sub nom. Stewart v. Abend, 495
U.S. 207 (1990).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1017
141. In his treatise, Nimmer refers to § 106(2) as "completely superfluous." 2 NIMMER &
NIMMER, supra note 9, § 8.09[A], at 8-123; see also Sterk, supra note 36, at 1215-16 (arguing that
in most cases derivative rights are pure economic rents to copyright owners).
142. Section 106(2) does not require that a derivative work be fixed in order to be infringing.
CompareMidway Mfg. Co. v. Artic Int'l, Inc., 704 F.2d 1009, 1014 (7th Cir. 1983) (holding that cir-
cuit boards that speed up copyrighted video games create unlawful derivative works), with Lewis
Galoob Toys, Inc. v. Nintendo of Am., Inc., 780 F. Supp. 1283, 1291 (N.D. Cal. 1991) (holding that
game devices that speed up copyrighted video games do not create unlawful derivative works), aft'd,
964 F.2d 965 (9th Cir. 1992). The Ninth Circuit's decision in Galoob acknowledged that an accused
work did not need to be "fixed" within the meaning of the Copyright Act in order to infringe, but did
hold that it must incorporate the copyrighted material in some concrete or permanent form. Galoob,
964 F.2d at 967-69. It is not clear how this incorporationwould differ from fixation, which has been
given an expansive interpretation by other decisions. See, e.g., MAI Sys. Corp. v. Peak Computer,
Inc., 991 F.2d 511,517-19 (9th Cir. 1993); see also Carol S. Curme, Note, Derivative Works of Video
Game Displays: Lewis Galoob Toys, Inc. v. Nintendo of Am. Inc., 61 U. CINN. L. REv. 999, 1022-27
(1993) (criticizing the Galoob court's treatment of the derivative works issue).
143. See Mirage Editions, Inc. v. Albuquerque A.R.T. Co., 856 F.2d 1341, 1344 (9th Cir. 1988);
Mufioz v. Albuquerque A.R.T. Co., 829 F. Supp. 309,314-15 (D. Alaska 1993); National Geographic
Soc'yv. Classified Geographic, Inc., 27 F. Supp. 655, 660 (D. Mass. 1939) (all permitting the copy-
right owner to restrict purchasers of copies from cutting up magazines or books and reassembling them
in different form). The first sale doctrine generally permits a purchaser to dispose of the purchased
copy at his discretion, but it does not apply to derivative works. See 17 U.S.C. § 109(a) (1994).
144. See Lee v. Deck the Walls, Inc., 925 F. Supp. 576, 579-80 (N.D. 1l1. 1996) (reaching the
opposite conclusion from the Mirage court); 2 GOLDsTEIN, supra note 120, § 5.3, at 5:81 (condemning
Mirage as an unwarranted extension of the Copyright Act).
145. Of course, § 103 (which provides that derivative works containing new original expression
are separately copyrightable) is arguably sufficient to take care of this by itself. It is not clear what
§ 106(2) adds to the "chain of copyright" theory.
19971 Economics of Improvement 1019
C. Mechanismsfor ProtectingImprovers
One thing that the derivative works right does do is make it clear that
copyright law is intended to reach improvers as well as counterfeiters. The
copyright owner's control over works in markets other than the one he
entered is no accident, but part of the scheme of copyright protection.
Nonetheless, there are a few legal rules that function to protect improvers
in copyright law. To compare these rules to analogous doctrines in patent
law, let us once again hypothesize three types of improvers: minor
improvers, significant improvers, and radical improvers.'"
146. See Worlds of Wonder, Inc. v. Veritel Learning Sys., Inc., 658 F. Supp. 351, 356 (N.D.
Tex. 1986); Worlds of Wonder, Inc. v. Vector Intercontinental, Inc., 653 F. Supp. 135 (N.D. Ohio
1986). For criticism of these decisions, see Christian H. Nadan, Comment, A Proposal to Recognize
Component Works: How a Teddy Bears on the Competing Ends of Copyright Law, 78 CAL. L. REV.
1633 (1990).
147. See, e.g., Bateman v. Mnemonics, Inc., 79 F.3d 1532, 1542 (11th Cir. 1996); Sega Enters.
Ltd. v. Accolade, Inc., 977 F.2d 1510, 1527-30 (9th Cir. 1992);Lewis Galoob Toys, 964 F.2d at 970-
72.
148. Glynn Lunney attempts a somewhat similar taxonomy. See Lunney, supra note 37, at 2428-
1020 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
improvements will qualify as a fair use, particularly if they are done in the
context of copies made for a public benefit and do not harm the market for
the original work.149 But most copies that contain only minor improve-
ments will not qualify as fair uses. And while it is theoretically possible
that the changes made to the original work by the minor improver will
cause the improved work to be noninfringing, in practice the likelihood of
a change being both sufficiently minor as not to qualify for copyright pro-
tection and sufficiently major as to preclude a finding of substantial
copying (or infringement of the derivative works right) is minimal. Minor
improvers are therefore likely to be guilty of copyright infringement. As
with minor improvements that infringe patents,1 improvements that
infringe copyrights are effectively captured by the copyright owner, since
anyone copying the new work would similarly be guilty of infringing the
copyright on the original work. 1
149. See, e.g., Sony Corp. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 454-56 (1984).
150. See supra notes 78-79 and accompanying text.
151. See Lipton v. Nature Co., 71 F.3d 464, 471 (2d Cir. 1995) (holding that innocent copying
of a work will not protect the copier from infringement if the copied work itself infringed another
work); 2 NIMMER& NIMMmI, supra note 9, § 8.01[C].
152. Because there is no equivalent in copyright to the "nonobviousness" and "utility" require-
ments in patent law, even changes with a negative social value might fall into the category of significant
improvements. See, e.g., Dallas Cowboys Cheerleaders, Inc. v. Pussycat Cinema, Ltd., 604 F.2d 200
(2d Cir. 1979) (discussing the copyright implications of an "improvement" consisting of a pornographic
movie portraying the plaintiffs).
153. See supra notes 85-88 and accompanying text.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1021
covered by the original patent without permission, but the original patent
owner similarly could not use the new material contributed by the
improver. Perhaps surprisingly, there is no analogous doctrine of
"blocking copyrights" granting copyright infringers the rights to their own
improvements. 1" Instead, section 103 of the Act provides that original
works of authorship contributed as part of the creation of a derivative work
are copyrightable only by the original copyright owners or their
licensee.155 This means, for example, that if an improver makes a movie
which is later determined to have infringed the copyright on the book on
which it was based, the improver may not be entitled to any copyright
protection for the movie-even those portions of the movie which were
contributed by the improver. 56 Indeed, in one case the fact that a script-
writer used the "Rocky Balboa" character from a prior film in creating an
154. See, e.g., MARSHALL LEAFFER, UNDERSTANDING COPYRIGHT LAW 47 (2d ed. 1995) ("A
derivative work copyright can only be obtained when the author legally used the material on which the
derivative work was based."); Goldstein, supra note 37, at 244 (explaining the logical consistency of
linking protection of a derivative work to authorization for use of the underlying work, but criticizing
the sometimes harsh results); Wendy J.Gordon, Toward a Jurisprudenceof Benefits: The Norms of
Copyrightand the Problem of Private Censorship, 57 U. CHI. L. REV. 1009, 1019, 1018-20 (1990)
(reviewing PAUL GOLDSTEIN, COPYRIGHT: PRINCIPLES, LAW AND PRACTICE (1989)) (describing the
status of unauthorized derivative works and contrasting it to the blocking patent, which yields a "more
equitable result"); Robert P. Merges, Of PropertyRules, Coase,andIntellectualProperty, 94 COLUM.
L. REV. 2655, 2659 n.15 (1994) (suggesting that "copyright law's policy favoring the reputational
interests of authors" offers the best explanation for the lack of a "blocking-copyright" doctrine). The
rule against blocking copyrights is sometimes obscured by the line the Copyright Act draws between
those who create a derivative work with the original permission of the copyright owner and those who
do not. See 17 U.S.C. § 103(a) (1994); see also JBJ Fabrics, Inc. v. Brylane, Inc., 714 F. Supp. 107,
110 (S.D.N.Y. 1989) ("[flf plaintiff did indeed have informal authorization ... to use the painting in
its fabric design, such as a non-exclusive license, then it is not using the painting unlawfully and may
not face any limits on the scope of its [derivative] copyright protection."); Goldstein, supra note 37,
at 239-40 (distinguishing these situations). Those who prepare a derivative work with permission are
presumably entitled to copyright their original contribution in the derivative work, and thus might be
thought to have a right to "block" the original copyright owner from using their added expression in
violation of the terms of the license. See JAY DRATLER JR., INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY LAW:
COMMERCIAL, CREATIVE, AND INDUSTRIALPROPEPTY § 6.01[2][c][iii] (1993) (describing the potential
for "standoffs" between licensors and licensees who have created derivative works). Even then,
though, the derivative work creator-licensee may face unexpected limits on his ability to commercialize
his derivative work, as cases like G. Ricordi & Co. v. ParamountPictures,Inc., 189 F.2d 469 (2d Cir.
1951), make clear. See generally I NIMMER & NIMMER, supra note 9, § 3.07[A][1] (illustrating
Ricordi's repudiation of the theory that a derivative-right licensee gains a property right in the new
work that is independent of the underlying work); Peter Jaszi, When Works Collide:Derivative Motion
Pictures, UnderlyingRights, and the Public Interest, 28 UCLA L. REV. 715 (1981).
155. Section 103(a) provides that "[tihe subject matter of copyright as specified by section 102
includes compilations and derivative works, but protection for a work employing preexisting material
in which copyright subsists does not extend to any part of the work in which such material has been
used unlawfully.' 17 U.S.C. § 103(a) (1994).
156. See Gracen v. Bradford Exch., 698 F.2d 300, 302-03 (7th Cit. 1983); Pamfiloff v. Giant
Records, Inc., 794 F. Supp. 933, 938 (N.D. Cal. 1992); Dynamic Solutions, Inc. v. Planning &
Control, Inc., 646 F. Supp. 1329, 1340 (S.D.N.Y. 1986); Gallery House, Inc. v. Yi, 582 F. Supp.
1294, 1297 (N.D. Ill. 1984); 1 NIMMER & NIMMER, supra note 9, § 3.06.
1022 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
unauthorized sequel to Rocky caused the court not only to find that the
scriptwriter was infringing the copyright in the "Rocky" character,15 7but to
invalidate the scriptwriter's derivative work copyright completely.
Because section 103 of the Act denies copyright only in the "part of
the work" that incorporates infringing material, some infringing derivative
works may nonetheless be copyrightable in part. This is particularly true
in the case of compilations, where the infringing material can be separated
easily from other parts of the work. Thus, the House Report accom-
panying the 1976 Act provides that "an unauthorized translation of a novel
could not be copyrighted at all, but the owner of copyright in an anthology
of poetry could sue someone who infringed the whole anthology, even
though the infringer proves that publication of one of the poems was
unauthorized."15 This limitation on section 103 may provide significant
improvers with solace in some cases, notably where the copied material is
easily separated from the improver's contribution. In other cases, how-
ever, where the material is inextricably intertwined, the improver loses the
entire value of her contribution. This is the case with regard to movies or
plays based on a book. It is also likely to be the case with many improve-
ments in the field of computer software. Finally, the promise of digital
information-that it can easily be altered, translated between media, and
transformed-now seems to be its peril as well. 59
The effect of this rule is to allow the original copyright owner to cap-
ture the value of even significant improvements made by others. While the
improvements themselves are nominally in the public domain, no one can
use those improvements in conjunction with the original work without
infringing the copyright on that work.1" Further, the existence of this
157. See Andersonv. Stallone, 11 U.S.P.Q.2d (BNA) 1161, 1167-69 (C.D. Cal. 1989).
158. H.R. REP. No. 94-1476, at 57-58 (1976), reprintedin 1976 U.S.C.C.A.N. 5659,5671. One
might analogize the latter situation to the case of "partially blocking patents," discussed supra note 87.
159. See Chon, supra note 122, at 266-72 (illustrating the inadequacy of current joint-author doc-
trine in copyright law when dealing with collaborative Internet art); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlawand
Social Change:A DemocraticApproach to CopyrightLaw in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT.
LJ. 215, 278-81 (1996) (pointing to the fluidity of works in the digital medium as one of the principal
problems copyright law must face in cyberspace, and noting that a broad derivative-works right will
reduce the usefulness of the digital medium).
160. See Russell v. Price, 612 F.2d 1123, 1128 (9th Cir. 1979) (holding that the public screening
of a film in the public domain violates the performance rights of the original play on which the film
was based); Central Point Software, Inc. v. Nugent, 903 F. Supp. 1057, 1060 (E.D. Tex. 1995)
(stating that upgrades to copyrighted software made without permission were infringing derivative
works and fell within the scope of the original copyright grant); Grove Press, Inc. v. Greenleaf Publ'g
Co., 247 F. Supp. 518, 527 (E.D.N.Y. 1965) (holding that the copyright owner of an original French
novel could prevent the copying of English translations of his work, even though the English translation
had fallen into the public domain, since copying the public domain translation would infringe the copy-
right owner's right to prepare derivative works); see also Francis M. Nevins, The Doctrine of
CopyrightAmbush:Limitations on the Free Use of Public DomainDerivative Works, 25 ST. LOUIS U.
L.J. 58 (1981). A more familiar example to many people is the film It's a Wonderful Life, which
1997] Economics of Improvement 1023
entered the public domain in the 1970s because the copyright owner failed to renew it. The movie was
shown freely by numerous broadcasters until the 1990s, when Republic Films bought the rights to the
short story on which the film was based. Armed with the copyright in the short story, they were able
to "lock up" the right to show the film, even though it was nominally in the public domain. See, e.g.,
James Bates, A Not-So-Wonderful Copyright Issue, L.A. TIMES, Mar. 26, 1996, at D6; 'Life' to Air
Once This Season, PALM BEACH PosT, Dec. 4, 1994, at TV POST 2, available in LEXIS, Regnws
Library, Arcnws File.
161. For more discussion on this point, see infra Part V.
162. For criticism of this result, see Goldstein, supra note 37, at 244; Gordon, supra note 154,
at 1019; Nadan, supra note 146, at 1639-40, 1651-54.
The rule that derivative copyrights must be authorized to be valid creates other problems as well.
Consider the situation of a translator who translates a copyrighted work without permission. Under
the legislative history to § 103, there seems no question that the translator loses her copyright in the
translation because it was unauthorized. The creative effort that went into the translation falls into the
public domain. But suppose that aftershe createsthe translation,the translator obtains authorization
from the underlying copyright owner. One might argue that the translation is now lawful, entitling the
translator to retroactively claim copyright in it. But that would take material out of the public domain
by private agreement, which seems an odd result.
At least one decision offers protection to the creators of derivative works, though that protection
is razor thin. In Lewis Galoob Toys, Inc. v. Aintendo ofAmerica, Inc., 964 F.2d 965 (9th Cir. 1992),
the Ninth Circuit held that individual consumers of Nintendo game cartridges who used the plaintiff's
device to speed up or alter the parameters of their Nintendo games were not guilty of copyright
infringement, both because the temporarily altered games did not qualify as derivative works and
because the private home use of the Galoob device was a fair use. Id. at 965. However, this decision
cannot be read to offer solace to the creators of derivative works in more permanent form who wish
to market those works.
163. See Sheldon v. Metro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp., 309 U.S. 390 (1940).
164. See Harper& Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539 (1985).
165. See Arnstein v. Porter, 154 F.2d 464 (2d Cir. 1946). But see id. at 475 (Clark, J.,
dissenting) (arguing that the overall musical impression, rather than the comparative technical analysis
of the particular notes or patterns of the accused work, should determine a finding of plagiarism).
1024 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
166. See 1 GOLDSTMIN, supra note 120, § 5.3, at 5:79 (noting that derivative rights may extend
to derivations "that will sometimes contain only the faintest trace of the underlying work"). To be
sure, the value contributed by the improver may be a disputed issue in any given case. See Harper&
Row, 471 U.S. at562 (characterizing The Nation's review as relying for its value largely on the under-
lying work). But the value of the improvement does not affect the outcome of the case. See infra note
182.
167. 223 F. Supp. 219 (E.D.N.Y. 1963).
1,68. Id. at 220. Goldstein describes this case as residing at the "speculative outer edges of the
derivative right." 1 GOLDSTEIN, supra note 120, § 5.3, at 5:80.
169. 920 F. Supp. 62 (S.D.N.Y. 1996).
170. Id. at 63-65. To be fair, the chair at issue appears to have been extremely distinctive, and
its surroundings were copied as well. Id.
171. Section 107 provides a list of four nonexclusive factors to consider in determining whether
a particular use is fair. 17 U.S.C. § 107 (1994). Those factors are the purpose and character of the
use, the nature of the copyrighted work, the amount of the copyrighted work taken, and the potential
market impact on the copyright owner. It is clear that fair use protects the creators of derivative works
as well as those who make more traditional copies. See, e.g., Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc.,
510 U.S. 569, 579-80 (1994) (holding that "parody, like other comment or criticism, may claim fair
use under § 107"); Lewis Galoob Toys, Inc. v. Nintendo of Am., Inc., 964 F.2d 965, 969-72 (9th Cir.
1992) (holding that the use by an individual Nintendo game consumer of a device that alters the charac-
teristics of the games was a fair use).
172. See Sony Corp. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 447-55 (1984) (holding that
the creation of verbatim copies of movies for private use was a fair use, since the movies were broad-
cast for free over a television network, and the plaintiffs therefore suffered no economic harm).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1025
173. Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 566 (1985); see also
Campbell, 510 U.S. at 590 (observing that a defendant claiming fair use "would have difficulty
carrying the burden of demonstrating fair use without favorable evidence about relevant markets");
Wendy J. Gordon, Fair Use as Market Failure:A Structuraland Economic Analysis of the Betamar
Case and Its Predecessors, 82 COLUM. L. REV. 1600, 1615 (1982) (explaining that "one of the
necessary preconditions for premising fair use on economic grounds is that market failure must be
present").
174. See I NIMMER& NIMMER, supra note 9, § 1.10[D], at 1-92.
175. Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 566-67 (quoting 1 NIMMER & NIMMER, supra note 9,
§ 1.10[DI).
176. See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 592-93.
177. See American Geophysical Union v. Texaco Inc., 60 F.3d 913, 929-31 (2d Cir. 1994). The
Sixth Circuit had taken a contrary position in Princeton University Press v. Michigan Document
Services, Inc., 74 F.3d 1512(6th Cir. 1996), but the opinion was withdrawn for en bane consideration,
74 F.3d 1528 (6th Cir. 1996). The en banc court then issued an opinion that followed American
Geophysical. See Princeton Univ. Press v. Michigan DocumentServs., Inc., 99 F.3d 1381, 1387-88,
1391 (6th Cir. 1996) (en banc), petitionfor cert.filed, 65 U.S.L.W. 2324 (U.S. Jan. 31, 1997) (No.
96-1219).
178. 64 F.3d 1330, 1336 (9th Cir. 1995).
179. Id. at 1336-37. It is reasonableto disagreewith the court's conclusionthata computeropera-
ting system copyright extends to the service market for that system, allowing the copyright owner to
capture the entire market for such service. See generally David McGowan, Regulating Competition
in the Information Age: Computer Software as an Essential Facility Under the Sherman Act, 18
HASTINGS COMM. & ENT. L.J. 771, 808-16 (1996) (discussing the extension of copyright law as a bar-
rier to competition). Triad's conclusion is at odds with the Ninth Circuit's earlier holding in Sega
EnterprisesLtd. v. Accolade, Inc., 977 F.2d 1510, 1527-28 (9th Cir. 1992), which allowed a com-
petitor to copy Sega computer cartridge codes in order to design video game cartridges which were
compatible with Sega's video game consoles. The Triad decision may also be inconsistent with the
antitrust laws. See Eastman Kodak Co. v. Image Technical Servs., Inc., 504 U.S. 451, 469 (1992)
1026 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
the improvement itself will not help the improver if those sales are taken
away from the original copyright owner, at least under the rationale of
cases like Triad."°
Second, the focus of the fair use analysis is on the material taken from
the original copyright owner, not on the material added by the improver.
Numerous courts have held that a defendant cannot "excuse the wrong by
showing how much of his work he did not pirate."' In fair use, the
focus of the third factor-amount copied-has primarily been on the portion
of the original copyrighted work taken, not on the percentage of the
infringing work that contains copyrighted material." The one notable
exception to this rule, the Supreme Court's decision in Harper & Row
Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enterprises,"8 uses the percentage of the
defendant's work that consists of copies to defeat rather than to support a
fair use claim."8 4 Thus, the contributions made by an infringer are not
directly considered in this factor of the fair use analysis.
Finally, the traditional focus of fair use doctrine on the purpose of the
use is unlikely to benefit radical improvers, except perhaps incidentally.
Traditional applications of this first factor in fair use analysis have tried to
distinguish between uses that served some public (generally nonprofit)
interest, such as education, research, or news reporting, and those that
were commercially motivated."a The Supreme Court has even gone so
(finding an antitrust violation for tying the sale of equipment parts to an agreement not to purchase ser-
vices from a competitor). For an argument that RAM should almost always qualify as fair use, see
Chad G. Asarch, Note, Is Turn About Fair Play? Copyright Law and the Fair Use of Computer
Sofiware Loaded into RAM, 95 MIcH. L. REv. 654, 660-61 (1996).
180. This situation should be distinguished from cases where the effect of a defendant's work is
to suppress demand for the copyrighted work on its merits. For example, a critical book review may
reduce sales of the book it criticizes, but that is not the sort of market loss relevant to the fourth factor
of fair use doctrine. See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 592 (noting that there is no observable derivative mar-
ket for criticism); Fisher v. Dees, 794 F.2d 432, 438 (9th Cir. 1986) (distinguishing between biting
criticism which suppresses demand for the original and copyright infringement which replaces it).
181. Sheldon v. Metro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp., 81 F.2d 49, 56 (2d Cir. 1936); see also Harper
& Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 565 (1985).
182. See 17 U.S.C. § 107(3) (1994) (referring to the amount of the copyrighted work taken);
Harper& Row, 471 U.S. at 565 ("[A] taking may not be excused merely because it is insubstantial
with respect to the infringingwork." (emphasis in original)); see also Meeropol v. Nizer, 560 F.2d
1061, 1069 (2d Cir. 1977) (stating that "the amount and substantiality of the work used" is a factor
in determining whether fair use applies); Roy Export Co. v. CBS, Inc., 503 F. Supp. 1137, 1145
(S.D.N.Y. 1980) (finding that even where the portion of the work used is quantitatively small, it may
still be quantitatively substantial, thus militating against a finding of fair use), aff'd, 672 F.2d 1095 (2d
Cir. 1982); Woods v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 920 F. Supp. 62, 65 (S.D.N.Y. 1996) (determining
that the relevant inquiry is not whether an infringement is de minimis in the infringing work, but
whether it is de minimis in the infringed work).
183. 471 U.S. 539 (1985).
184. Id. at 565-66. In that case, the defendant's story on the Ford memoirs took only a tiny por-
tion (less than 1%) of the plaintiff's book, but the excerpts taken represented a more significant percen-
tage of the defendant's story (around 13 %). Id.
185. See, e.g., American Geophysical Union v. Texaco Inc., 60 F.3d 913,921-22 (2d Cir. 1994)
(characterizing the photocopying of copyrighted articles by Texaco research scientists as an
1997] Economics of Improvement 1027
"intermediate use" indirectly benefitting Texaco's commercial performance); Sega Enters. Ltd. v.
Accolade, Inc., 977 F.2d 1510, 1522 (9th Cir. 1992) (deciding that copying for commercial purposes
favors the copyright owner in fair use analysis); Basic Books, Inc. v. Kinko's Graphics Corp., 758 F.
Supp. 1522 (S.D.N.Y. 1991) (holding that the reproduction of copyrighted materials by a "copy shop"
for sale to university students was commercially motivated and therefore unfair). This analysis of the
first factor finds support in § 107, which requires the courts to determine "the purpose and character
of the use, including whether such use is of a commercial nature or is for nonprofit educational
purposes.' 17 U.S.C. § 107(1) (1994).
186. See Sony Corp. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 449 (1984) ("If the Betamax
were used to make copies for a commercial or profit-making purpose, such use would presumptively
be unfair.").
187. See Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 584 (1994) (finding that the Court
of Appeals erred by "giving virtually dispositive weight to the commercial nature' of the use under
Sony). The Campbell Court held that "[t]he language of the statute makes clear that the commercial
or nonprofit educational purpose of a work is only one element of the first factor enquiry into its
purpose and character.' Id. For academic criticism of the Court's reliance on the commercial nature
of a use, see Robert A. Kreiss, Accessibility and Commercialization in Copyright Theory, 43 UCLA
L. REv. 1, 62-63 (1995) (theorizing that because the aim of copyright is to allow competitors to learn
and use the ideas of others, the commercial purpose of a competitor "would seem to be either a strike
in favor of fair use or irrelevant to the fair use analysis"); William F. Patty & Shira Perlmutter, Fair
Use Misconstrued:Profit, Presumptions,and Parody, 11 CARDOZo ARTS & ENT. L.J. 667, 667-708
(1993) (arguing that the artificial distinctions between commercial and noncommercial uses should be
replaced with a sensitive balancing of interests test).
188. The origin of the concept of transformative versus superseding uses is generally attributed
to Justice Story's statement in Folsom v. Marsh, 9 F. Cas. 342 (C.C.D. Mass. 1841) (No. 4901), that,
in approaching a question of fair use, one must "look to ... the degree in which the use may prejudice
the sale, or diminish the profits, or supersede the objects, of the original work." Id. at 348. See
generally Leval, supra note 11, at 1111-16 (elaborating on the concept of transformative use and its
importance in evaluating a secondary use's purpose and character).
1028 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
189. Campbell, 510 U.S. at 579 (citations omitted) (quoting Folsom, 9 F. Cas. at 348).
190. But see Roxana Badin, Comment, An Appropriate(d) Place in Transformative Value:
AppropriationArt's Exclusionfrom Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 60 BROOK. L. REV. 1653,
1653-54 (1995). Badin reads Campbell as having carved out only a narrow exception for commercial
parodies that will hurt the fair use case for other forms of appropriative art. Id. She goes on to sug-
gest that an expansive reading of Campbell is more desirable, however. Id. at 1654.
Commentators have debated the wisdom of the transformative use doctrine. Those endorsing
some form of transformative use analysis include Jay Dratler, Jr., Distilling the Witches' Brew of Fair
Use in Copyright Law, 43 U. MIAMi L. REV. 233, 291-93 (1988); William W. Fisher I,
Reconstructingthe Fair Use Doctrine, 101 HARV. L. REv. 1661, 1730 (1988); and Leval, supranote
11, at 1111. Those opposed to its use, or at least to certain aspects of the way it has been applied,
include Laura G. Lape, Transforming Fair Use: The Productive Use Factorin Fair Use Doctrine, 58
ALB. L. REV. 677,712-22 (1995); L. Ray Patterson, FreeSpeech, Copyright, andFairUse, 40 VAND.
L. REV. 1, 45-46 n.149 (1987); and Lloyd L. Weinreb, Fair'sFair: A Comment on the Fair Use
Doctrine, 103 HARV. L. REV. 1137, 1143-44 (1990).
191. Cf. Douglas J. Ellis, Comment, The Right ofPublicity andthe FirstAmendment: A Comment
on Why Celebrity Parodies Are Fair Game for Fair Use, 64 U. CIN. L. REv. 575, 611 (1996)
(suggesting that uncertainty regarding the theoretical basis for copyright means that "transformative
use will have a checkered and inconsistent application"). For discussion of the role of theoretical
approaches to copyright in treating radical improvers, see infra Part IV.
192. See Pamela Samuelson, Modifying Copyrighted Software: Adjusting Copyright Doctrineto
Accommodate a Technology, 28 JURIMETRICS J. 179, 195 (1988) (noting that fair use is unlikely to pro-
tect those who modify software, because of the Court's emphasis on harm to both original and potential
derivative markets); Stephen B. Thau, Copyright, Privacy, and FairUse, 24 HOFSTRA L. REv. 179,
189-90 (1995) ("While the Court often purports to use fair use 'to avoid rigid application of the
copyright statute when, on occasion, it would stifle the very creativity which that law is designed to
foster,' in actuality the analysis always turns on the economic harm suffered by the plaintiff." (quoting
Stewart v. Abend, 495 U.S. 207, 236-38 (1990) (quoting Iowa State Univ. Research Found., Inc. v.
American Broad. Cos., 621 F.2d 57, 60 (2d Cit. 1980)))); see also Lape, supra note 190, at 715-16
(arguing against giving primacy to the market harm factor).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1029
The Supreme Court's statement in Harper& Row that "to negate fair
use one need only show that if the challenged use 'should become
widespread, it would adversely affect the potential market for the
copyrighted work'" 1" certainly suggests that market harm is already the
de facto test for fair use. Even Campbell itself may represent only an
illusory victory for the transformative use doctrine, since the Court in that
case indicated that the defendants bore the burden of proving the absence
of harm to the market for derivative works on remand, notwithstanding the
transformative nature of their use. 1" Further, the "commercial use"
prong of factor one is not dead, and at least one court has used it to negate
the impact of transformative use-in effect holding that transformative but
commercial uses cancel each other out, leaving the first factor neutral.' 95
In either case, fair use protection appears effectively to be foreclosed to
transformative works designed to compete with the original or its derivative
progeny."'
193. Harper& Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 568 (1985) (emphasis added
by the Harper & Row Court) (quoting Sony Corp. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 451
(1984)).
194. Campbell, 510 U.S. at 590-94. Justice Kennedy's concurring opinion would limit the deci-
sion even further, giving it virtually no application outside the parody context. Id. at 596-600
(Kennedy, J., concurring).
195. See College Entrance Examination Bd. v. Pataki, 889 F. Supp. 554, 568 (N.D.N.Y.),
modified, 893 F. Supp. 152 (N.D.N.Y. 1995). The neutrality of the first factor in that case allowed
the copyright owner to prevail by showing market harm. Id. at 575.
196. Of course, where a use both is transformative and does not harm the market for the original
work (or licensed derivatives thereof), it will likely be found to be fair. This was the court's
conclusion, for example, in New York Tunes Co. v. Roxbury Data Interface, Inc., 434 F. Supp. 217,
223-25 (D.N.J. 1977). But many of the most important transformative uses of a work will compete
with the work, or at least will compete in markets which the original copyright owner could foreseeably
enter. In these cases, fair use will be ineffective to protect such transformations.
197. But see John Shepard Wiley Jr., Copyrightatthe School ofPatent, 58 U. CHI. L. REV. 119,
180-81 (1991) (arguing that because patent law and copyright law share the same purposes, their doc-
trines and procedures should also be consistent).
198. See supra notes 107-11 and accompanying text.
1030 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
199. Thus, arguments that seek to justify the copyright rule, but would also justify the same rule
in patent cases, are treated in Part V rather than this Part, because they are not arguments in favor of
differential treatment.
200. At the outset, one can quite easily reject a potential argument from history-an argument that
says, in effect, that the differences are justified because they have always been there. This argument
fails because copyright's strong power over derivative works is in fact a relatively recent innovation.
Early cases not only did not give the original creator strong power over exploitation of derivative
works, but in fact held that alteration of a copyrighted work excused infringement. See, e.g., Stowe
v. Thomas, 23 F. Cas. 201 (C.C.E.D. Pa. 1853) (No. 13514); Folsom v. Marsh, 9 F. Cas. 342
(C.C.D. Mass. 1841) (No. 4901); Burnett v. Chetwood, 35 Eng. Rep. 1008 (Ch. 1817); Gyles v.
Wilcox, 26 Eng. Rep. 489 (Ch. 1740); Ralph S. Brown, The Widening Gyre: Are Derivative Works
Getting Out of Hand?, 3 CARDozo ARTS & ENT. LJ. 1, 2 (1984); Goldstein, supra note 37, at 211-
14; Gordon, supra note 154, at 1018. It is also worth noting the "historical kinship" between patent
and copyright law remarked upon by the Supreme Court in Sony Corp. v. UniversalCity Studios, Inc.,
464 U.S. 417, 439 (1984).
The history of the Semiconductor Chip Protection Act (SCPA), 17 U.S.C. §§ 901-914 (1994),
provides yet another reason to reject this interpretation. The SCPA, which is included in the copyright
statute and is modeled on the Copyright Act in significant respects, nonetheless has a very different rule
regarding improvements. Improvers are not held liable under the SCPA if they (1) engaged in reverse
engineering and (2) contributed their own innovation resulting in an "original" product. The effect of
this rule is to make it harder for an SCPA plaintiff to show infringement if the defendant has engaged
in any significant improvementto the original chip. See Brooktree Corp. v. Advanced Micro Devices,
Inc., 977 F.2d 1555 (Fed. Cir. 1992) (affirming a judgment in favor of a plaintiff claiming patent
infringement of semiconductor mask registrations despite the defendant's claims of reverse engineering
and innovation).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1031
201. Even what Samuel Oddi calls the "reward theory" of patent law is essentially incentive-based:
inventors must be rewarded in order to (a) encourage more inventions, or (b) prevent "free-riding."
See Oddi, supra note 13, at 275-77 (discussing the reward theory). A rare example of a natural law
justification in patent law is the French patent statute of 1791, which was premised on the belief that
.every novel idea whose realization or development can become useful to society belongs primarily to
him who conceived it, and that it would be a violation of the rights of man in their very essence if an
industrial invention were not regarded as the property of its creator." STAFF OF SENATE SUBCOMM.
ON PATENTS, TRADEMARKS AND COPYRIGHTS, 85TH CONG., AN ECONOMIC REVIEW OF THE PATENT
SYSTEM, STUDY No. 15, at 22 (Comm. Print 1958) (Fritz Machlup, author) (quoting the French patent
statute). Even this example, while it suggests a natural law basis for patents, does not justify the
equivalent of the moral rights of attribution and integrity found in the copyright context.
202. Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works, Sept. 9, 1886, art.
S. TREATY Doc. No. 99-27, at 5 (1986), 828 U.N.T.S. 221,235.
203. See, e.g., Edward J. Damich, The Right of Personality: A Common-Law Basis for the
Protection ofthe MoralRightsofAuthors, 23 GA. L. REv. 1 (1988) (arguing that while U.S. law does
not protect moral rights to the extent required by the Berne Convention, expansion of existing common-
law precepts could achieve such protection); Roberta Rosenthal Kwall, Copyrightandthe MoralRight:
Is an American Marriage Possible?, 38 VAND. L. REV. 1 (1985) (urging an amendment of the
Copyright Act to implement the moral rights of authors). But cf. 3 GOLDSTEIN, supra note 120,
§ 15.23, at 15:181 n.10 ("Congress' position on moral rights reflects neutrality, not antipathy.").
While the United States did adopt limited moral rights protection in the Visual Artists Rights Act of
1990, Pub. L. No. 101-650, tit. VI, 104 Stat. 5089, 5128-33 (codified in scattered sections of 17
U.S.C., with the specific rights of attribution and integrity in § 106A), that section is by no means a
general moral rights statute. See 3 GOLDSTEIN, supra note 120, § 15.23, at 15:179 (finding no sys-
"
tematic protection of moral rights in either federal or state law, [alpart from the closely circumscribed
rights" in § 106A). Section 106A is limited to works of visual art, does not give protection to the artist
if the work is made for hire, and is subject to numerous exceptions. 17 U.S.C. § 106A (1994).
Furthermore, the rights granted in § 106A are limited to the life of the author, and may be waived by
the author in writing. Id.
204. Some commentators have taken this position. See, e.g., 2 GoLDSTEIN, supra note 120,
§ 5.3, at 5:80 & n.12 ("The broad scope of derivative rights enables them to secure reputational
interests as well as strictly economic interests by protecting authors against disfigurement of their works
.... The derivative right is in this respect akin to the moral right against distortion of an author's
work."); cf. I.H. Reichman, Electronic Information Tools-The Outer Edge of World Intellectual
PropertyLaw, 17 U. DAYTON L. REv. 797, 813 (1992) ("[T]he recent expansion of derivative work
1032 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
rights in United States law has helped to align the 'copyright' countries and the 'authors' rights'
countries without necessarily sacrificing the utilitarian ethos to which the former subscribe."). For an
argument that trademark law might have a similar effect, providing indirect moral rights protection,
see Mark A. Lemley, Rights ofAttribution and Integrity in Online Communications, 1995 3. ONUNE
L. art. 2, 14-16 (June 1995) <http://www.wm.edu/law/publicationsljol/lemley.html>.
205. This debate is long-standing and complex; I do not propose to resolve it here, or indeed to
do more than touch briefly on some of the important issues at stake.
206. Certainly adherents to the Chicago view would seem unlikely to support a strong version of
moral rights, since they are by their nature rights personal to the author that cannot be transferred. See
generally Neil Netanel, Alienability Restrictions and the Enhancementof Author Autonomy in United
States and ContinentalCopyrightLaw, 12 CARDOZO ARTS& ENT. LJ.1 (1994) (explaining that moral
rights in most continental countries are not alienable, though they can be waived in particular
circumstances). But others have criticized moral rights claims on political and artistic grounds. Beyer,
for example, argues that the moral rights position "at its root is actually one of cultural conservatism,
inhibited expression, and unnecessary deference to creators' intentions," as it gives original artists the
power to restrict subsequent interpretations and critiques of their work. Lawrence Adam Beyer,
Intentionalism, Art, and the Suppressionof Innovation:Film Colorizationand the Philosophy of Moral
Rights, 82 Nw. U. L. REV. 1011, 1018 (1988); see also Thomas J.Davis, Jr., Fine Art and Moral
Rights: The Immoral Triumph of Emotionalism, 17 HoFsTRi L. Rfv. 317, 358-59, 363 (1989)
(contending that the public interest is short-changed by allowing authors to assert claims of moral
rights); Geri J.Yonover, The PrecariousBalance:MoralRights, Parody andFair Use, 14 CARDOZO
ARTS & ENT. L.J. 79 (1996); Note, An Author's Artistic Reputation Under the Copyright Act of 1976,
92 HARV. L. REV. 1490, 1494 (1979) (both arguing that the law must balance the rights of original
artists against adaptors and parodists).
207. Consider the few cases brought to date under state and federal moral rights statutes. Most
have involved efforts to move or take down site-specific sculpture years after it was installed in a
building, and frequently when ownership of the building had changed since the art was installed. See,
e.g., Carter v. Helmsley-Spear, Inc., 71 F.3d 77 (2d Cir. 1995); Serra v. United States Gen. Servs.
Admin., 667 F. Supp. 1042 ($.D.N.Y. 1987), affid, 847 F.2d 1045 (2d Cir. 1988); see also Eric M.
Brooks, Comment, "Tilted" Justice: Site-Specific Art and Moral Rights After U.S. Adherence to the
Berne Convention, 77 CAL. L. REV. 1431 (1989) (examining the development and protection of the
moral rights of site-specific visual artists in the United States).
While compelling building owners to display works of art might seem to raise constitutional
problems of compelled speech under cases like Wooley v. Maynard,430 U.S. 705 (1977), and West
Virginia Board ofEducation v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943), courts have generally dismissed First
Amendment claims in the copyright context rather summarily. See, e.g., Harper & Row Publishers,
Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 555-60 (1985); Los Angeles News Serv. v. Tullo, 973 F.2d 791,
1997] Economics of Improvement 1033
795-96 (9th Cir. 1992); Sid & Marty Krofft Television Prods., Inc. v. McDonald's Corp., 562 F.2d
1157, 1171 (9th Cir. 1977). See generally Melville B. Nimmer, Does CopyrightAbridge the First
Amendment Guaranteesof Free Speech and Press?, 17 UCLA L. REV. 1180 (1970).
208. But see Netanel, supra note 206, at 6 (suggesting that strong moral rights may be tempered
in practice by an informal social norm against asserting them too strongly).
209. On the distinction between parody and satire in copyright law, see Campbell v. Acuff-Rose
Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 580-81 (1994).
210. See Beyer, supra note 206, at 1016 & n.9. Davis points to proponents of moral rights who
explicitly assert the "right to be free from excessive criticism, to publish a reply to such criticism, and
to be protected from 'a whole category of unpredictable injuries to .. .honor and reputation'" as
elements of the moral right. Davis, supra note 206, at 319 (quoting Martin A. Roeder, The Doctrie
of Moral Right: A Study in the Law of Artists, Authors and Creators, 53 HARV. L. REV. 554, 573
(1940)). Certainly the recognition of such rights would interfere directly with political, literary, and
artistic freedom by giving artists and authors control over what is said about them, whether or not it
was held to violate the First Amendment.
211. It is possible to take some steps toward such a calibration by creating a fair use exception to
the moral rights doctrine. The United States has done so. See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (1994). Nonetheless,
the discussion in Part m suggests that as currently constituted, the fair use doctrine does not effectively
distinguish radical from minor improvements. See supra subpart 11(C). Further, some cases suggest
that the failure to comply with the moral rights of the original author, for example by refusing to
attribute an author's work to her, will weigh heavily against a claim of fair use. See, e.g., Robinson
v. Random House, Inc., 877 F. Supp. 830 (S.D.N.Y. 1995). To the extent that this is true, the fair
use defense to claims of infringement on moral rights may be largely illusory.
212. According to a 1958 study, approximately 40% of all copyrights were works made for hire.
See STAFF OF SENATE SUBCOMM. ON PATENTS, TRADEMARKS & COPYRIGHTS, 86TH CONG., WORKS
MADE FOR HIRE AND ON COMMISSION, STUDY No. 13, at 139 n.49 (Comm. Print 1960) (Borge
Varmer, author). It is reasonable to assume that that percentage has increased as computer programs
havejoined the list of copyrighted works. While the copyright act defines the "author" as the employer
in such a circumstance, see 17 U.S.C. § 201(b) (1994), that is merely a convenient fiction-the actual
authors are almost invariably individual employees. Further, even works for which authorship vests
initially in an individual are frequently assigned to other individuals or to corporations. See, e.g.,
Elkin-Koren, supra note 159, at 280, 279-80 ("The vast majority of copyrighted materials that are on
the market are not owned by the actual author."); Mark A. Lemley, Romantic Authorship and the
Rhetoric ofProperty,75 TEXAs L. REv. 873, 883 (1997) (book review) (recognizing that the doctrines
1034 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
of assignment and transfer ensure that a majority of intellectual property rights end up "not in the hands
of authors or investors, but in the hands of corporate economic interests"); Robert G. Sugarman &
Joseph P. Salvo, Whose Rights? Sampling Gives Law a New Mix, NAT'L L.J., Nov. 11, 1991, at 21,
22 ("Most recording [and publishing] contracts provide that rights in a sound recording inure to the
record label....").
213. Even proponents of moral rights concede that the 1976 Copyright Act is primarily concerned
with the economic incentives of copyright owners, rather than the moral rights of authors. See Kwall,
supra note 203, at 37-3 8.
214. Cf. MARGARET JANE RADIN, REiNTERPRETING PROPERTY 12 (1993) (questioning the effec-
tiveness of the standard ideology of property-individual ownership of land-when applied broadly to
a society in which "the largest proportion of holdings are owned by institutions or entities other than
persons").
215. See supra notes 149-62 and accompanying text.
216. 2 GOLDSTEIN, supra note 120, § 5.3, at 5:79.
217. Some critics of the economic approach to copyright make a different claim-that economic
analysis is nondeterministic. See Alfred C. Yen, When Authors Won't Sell: Parody, Fair Use and
Efficiency in CopyrightLaw, 62 U. COLO. L. REv. 79, 82-83 (1991). This criticism must be taken
with a grain of salt, given that the alternatives to economic analysis generally advanced-Yen's moral
rights approach, or Lloyd Weinreb's ad hoc "fairness" analysis, see Weinreb, supra note 190, at
1137-are hardly more likely to result in a deterministic outcome.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1035
218. See J.H. Reichman, Legal HybridsBetween the Patentand CopyrightParadigms,94 COLUM.
L. REV. 2432, 2448-50 (1994) (documenting this division). As Reichman observes, this division has
never been strictly observed in practice. There have always been certain categories of protection that
crossed over or fell between the bipolar patent-copyright paradigms. See id. at 2453-500.
219. Wiley makes a somewhat different argument along the same general lines. He contends that
the procedural differences between copyright and patent stem from the fact that copyrightable works
are so much more common than patentable works. He points to the fact that while less than six million
patents havebeen issued in the history of the United States, people create millions of "original works
of authorship" every day. Wiley, supra note 197, at 182-83. On the implications of this difference
in the improvement context, see infra notes 231-33 and accompanying text.
220. John Wiley wrote in 1991 that the legal cultures of patent and copyright
divide at the wall of mathematics. High-tech inventors and their lawyers generally
perceive themselves as having little in common with the stylishly literate world of novels,
publishing, and studios, and vice versa. Artists think engineers are nerds. Inventors
think fiction and movies are fun but ultimately useless. You never see anyone wearing
both Gucci loafers and a plastic pocket protector.
Wiley, supra note 197, at 181. Ironically, 1991 is perhaps the last year in which those statements
could have been made with a straight face. If it accomplishes nothing else, the well-hyped convergence
of computers and entertainment media during the 1990s should explode the myth that invention and
creation have nothing in common. See Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, A Wiseguy's Approach to
Information Products:Muscling Copyrightand Patentinto a Unitary Theory of Intellectual Property,
1992 Sup. CT. REv. 195, 221-22 ("[A]dvances in production and reproduction make it increasingly
clear that the distinctions that seemed to be inherent in the terms 'patent' and 'copyright' are in fact
illusory becausethey fail to captureanything that is significant about the products of human intellect.").
Dreyfuss suggests that the differences between copyright and patent rules most likely "developed
fortuitously." Id. at 222.
221. See, e.g., Mazer v. Stein, 347 U.S. 201, 219 (1954) (mentioning that copyright law makes
the reward to the owner a secondary consideration); Hoehling v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 618 F.2d
972, 978 (2d Cir. 1980) (holding that copyright law should not be stretched to chill authors from
writing about historical issues or events). To be sure, copyright does not extend to pure collections
of facts which lack originality in the compilation, see Feist Publications, Inc. v. Rural Tel. Serv. Co.,
499 U.S. 340 (1991), or to the separable utilitarian aspects of works that are both useful and artistic,
see Carol Barnhart Inc. v. Economy Cover Corp., 773 F.2d 411, 419 (2d Cir. 1985). See also 17
1036 Texas Law Review [[Vol. 75:989
U.S.C. § 101 (1994). But the very difficulty that courts have had in drawing these lines illustrates one
problem with basing doctrinal differences on them.
222. See Reichman, supra note 218, at 2455-59,2488-90.
223. Id.
224. For example, the Patent and Trademark Office's recently adopted Guidelines for the
Examination of Computer-Related Inventions, 61 Fed. Reg. 7478, 7481 (1996), work hard to dis-
tinguish patentable from copyrightable subject matter, but ultimately fail. Neither an artistic-utilitarian
distinction nor a writing-invention distinction is supportable in the context of computer code, in which
writing is functional in the most basic sense. A full discussion of this convergencebetween the doc-
trines is beyond the scope of this Article. See generally Mark A. Lemley, Convergencein the Law of
Software Copyright?, 10 HIGH TECH. L.J. 1 (1995); Oddi, supra note 118; Samuelson et al., supra
note 118.
225. As the authors of the Manifesto point out, the incentives intellectual property law seeks to
foster in the software industry are for the creation of new and useful software design features.
Samuelson et al., supranote 118, at 2318-19. These design features lie somewhere in between the tra-
ditional subject matter of patent and copyright, and possess some elements of each. Id. at 2351-53.
Thus, the problem is not simply one of disentangling the patent incentives for the production of
software inventions from the copyright incentives for the production of software creations-the two laws
serve to promote the same incentives. Cf. Samuelson, supra note 192, at 210 (suggesting that copy-
right law should be modified to adopt patent law's rules regarding improvements in the software context
because software is more like a patentable invention than it is like other copyrighted works).
226. Some scholars have challenged this assumption. Applying the now-familiar techniques of
literary deconstruction, they argue that all creations are largely a product of communal forces.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1037
Dividing the stream of intellectual discourse into discrete units-each owned by, and closely associated
with, a particular author-is therefore a logically incoherent exercise subject more to the political force
of asserted authors' groups than to recognition of inherent claims of "personhood." See, e.g., JAMES
BOYLE, SHAMANS, SOFTWARE, AND SPLEENS: LAW AND THE CONSTRUCTION OF THE INFORMATION
SoCIETY (1996); THE CONSTRUCTION OF AUTHORSHIP: TEXTUAL APPROPRIATION IN LAW AND
LITERATURE (Martha Woodmansee & Peter Jaszi eds., 1994); James Boyle, A Theory of Law and
Informadon: Copyright, Spleens, Blackmail, and InsiderTrading, 80 CAL. L. REV. 1413 (1992); Peter
Jaszi, Toward a Theory of Copyright: The Metamorphoses of "Authorship," 1991 DUKE L.J. 455.
While this view is inconsistent with the idea that an author can simply create from scratch, one need
not subscribe to this radical critique of authorship in order to doubt the premise that improvement is
unimportant in the copyright context.
227. Murray Gell-Mann analogizes the situation to traveling over uncertain terrain. SeeMURRAY
GELL-MANN, THE QUARK AND THE JAGUAR: ADVENTURES IN THE SIMPLE AND THE COMPLEX 266-67
(1994). If your goal is to climb as high as possible, you will not be well served by a rule of decision
which says "always travel upwards." That rule may bring you to the top of a low hill and strand you
there, in sight of a much larger mountain. He suggests that some combination of improvement on exis-
ting ideas and the creative use of "noise" will produce the most innovative ideas. Ironically, in such
a case a broad construction of the patent system would seem most conducive to innovation, but only
because it forced subsequent work to deviate from improving on the original work into more productive
avenues. C. Kitch, supra note 13, at 267-71 (arguing for a broad "prospect" theory of patents).
228. TOM STOPPARD, ROSENCRANTZ& GUILDENSTERN ARE DEAD (Henry Popkin ed., 1967).
229. See Elkin-Koren, supra note 159, at 282-83 (stating that copyright's goal of encouraging a
broad range of expression argues for a limited right to control improvements).
230. Cf. Netanel, supra note 12, at 363-64 (asserting that copyright must underwrite and protect
deliberation and debate in the political sphere in order to promote a democratic civil society). Netanel
argues that in the copyright context, "our strong interest in expressive diversity overrides any possible
efficiency advantage in giving one person broad control over all transformative uses of an existing work
of authorship." Id. at 318.
1038 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
distinction between the two, the different nature of the works involved
cannot justify different categorical rules regarding the treatment of
improvements.
Finally, let us consider John Wiley's point that copyright and patent
differ in large part because so many more things are copyrightable than
patentable."1 Certainly this is true. Wiley uses this difference to explain
why patents face strict and time consuming examination procedures, while
copyrights do not; it would simply not be feasible to examine every new
"work of authorship" for novelty, nonobviousness, and the like." Can
the same fact be used to justify the difference in rules regarding
improvement? It is hard to see how. If anything, one would expect that
the more common a right was, the less each right would constrain the
behavior of subsequent developers. The rarer a right is, and the harder it
is to acquire, the more powerful we should expect it to be. Vesting greater
control over improvement in copyright than in patent runs counter to this
expectation.23
It is certainly true that copyright and patent protect different kinds of
works, though the dichotomy is not as clear as one might initially believe.
But there is no reason to think that those differences can explain the dif-
ferential treatment of improvement between the two statutes.
Use, 56 U. CHi. L. REv. 1017, 1019 (1989); Jordan P. Karp, Note, Experimental Use as Patent
Infringement: The Impropriety ofa BroadException, 100 YALE L.J. 2169, 2172-74 (1991).
237. C. Ralph S. Brown, Eligibilityfor CopyrightProtection:A Searchfor PrincipledStandards,
70 MINN. L. REv. 579, 588-89 (1985) (suggesting that the weaker rights conferred by copyright help
justify "the relatively casual approach to granting copyright as opposed to the more searching tests for
patentability").
238. Compare 17 U.S.C. § 302 (1994), with 35 U.S.C. § 154(a)(2) (1994).
239. See supra notes 49-52, 107-10 and accompanying text.
240. Registration with the Copyright Office is not required for copyright protection, but is still
required before bringing an infringement action. See 17 U.S.C. § 411(a) (1994). However, the copy-
right owner need only fill out a simple form to apply for registration-even if the Copyright Office
rejects the application, he can still file suit. See id.
241. See Mark A. Lemley, An EmpiricalStudy of the Twenty-Year PatentTerm, 22 AIPLA Q.J.
369, 386 (1994) (noting that the average patent spends over two years in prosecution).
242. Section 106 enumerates the exclusive rights of a copyright owner. 17 U.S.C. § 106 (1994).
The most significant rights absent from that list are the rights to control use and resale of the work once
1040 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
copyright infringement are sometimes more severe than those for patent
infringement.4 3 Taking all of these factors into account, at the very least
it is not clear that the "balance of power" is shifted strongly in favor of
patents without the compensating effect of the differing improvement rules.
Finally, I am dubious of the claim that improving on someone else's
work is somehow more culpable than independent development of a work
that happens to be similar. Copyright infringement is a strict liability
offense. It is no defense that the copying was unconscious, or even that
the defendant was merely quoting or selling material that he had no way
of knowing was itself copied from another source.' 4 Copyright
infringers are not necessarily any more at fault than patent infringers,
despite the requirement of "copying" in the former, at least if by fault we
mean mens rea. Both patent and copyright infringement can be willful, or
they can be completely innocent. Instead, the argument seems to be that
taking material from another (as copyright does require) is inherently worse
than developing it on your own.
In the context of improvements, this argument seems misguided. The
value of improvements is precisely that they allow developers to build on
what others have done before them, rather than having to start from
scratch. It would be perverse indeed to require that "improvers" not make
any use of the material they are supposedly improving. It would also be
inefficient, putting improvers to a significant duplication of effort for no
appreciable societal gain. Whatever one thinks is the appropriate treatment
it has first been sold by the copyright owner or a licensee. However, copyright owners have recently
acquired those rights in a backhanded way in the context of digital information, as recent court
decisions have held that any use or transfer of a work in electronic form involves the making of
multiple copies. See, e.g., Triad Sys. Corp. v. Southeastern Express Co., 64 F.3d 1330, 1336-37 (9th
Cir. 1995), cert. denied, 116 S. Ct. 1015 (1996); MAI Sys. Corp. v. Peak Computer, Inc., 991 F.2d
511, 517-19 (9th Cir. 1993); cf. COMMERCE DEP'T INFORMATION INFRASTRUCTURE TASK FORCE,
INTELLECrUAL PROPERTY AND THE NATIONAL INFORMATION INFRASTRUCTURE: THE REPORT OF THE
WORKING GROUP ON INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS 106-07 (1995) (endorsing this result). The
result has been to give copyright owners control over the use of their works even after sale, and to
circumvent the first-sale doctrine by precluding resale of electronic works. See Litman, Revising
CopyrightLawfor the Information Age, supra note 122, at 42-44.
By contrast, patent law's prohibitions on "using" and "selling" patented technology are tempered
by implied license and the doctrine of patent exhaustion, which provide that a license to a supplier to
"make" and "sell" a patented product permits the purchaser of that product to use and resell it. See
Intel Corp. v. United States Int'l Trade Comm'n, 946 F.2d 821, 826-27 (Fed. Cir. 1991); Unidisco,
Inc. v. Schattner, 824 F.2d 965, 967-68 (Fed. Cir. 1987). But see Mallinckrodt, Inc. v. Medipart,
Inc., 976 F.2d 700, 708-09 (Fed. Cir. 1992) (holding that the exhaustion of a patent right can be
limited by licensing agreements). The result is that the patentee has less control over post-sale use of
his patented goods than does the owner of the copyright in works in digital form.
243. For example, willful copyright infringement for commercial gain is a crime punishable by
imprisonment. See 17 U.S.C. § 506(a) (1994). There is no similar criminal penalty for patent
infringement.
244. See, e.g., Lipton v. Nature Co., 71 F.3d 464, 471 (2d Cir. 1995).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1041
of improvements under the law, surely its goal cannot be to encourage the
recreation of identical works by competitors from scratch.
D. Market PowerArguments
A final justification for treating improvements differently under copy-
right law than under patent law might stem from the belief that copyrights
confer less market power than patents. Under this argument, made to me
by Paul Heald, among others, the cost of allowing a copyright owner to
control improvements to his own work is less than the cost of a similar rule
in the patent context because more perfect substitutes usually exist in the
copyright context. If newcomers can compete effectively with an original
creator by designing their own works, they arguably have little or no need
to improve on the original creator's work. By contrast, it may be that
newcomers in patent markets must improve on existing works in order to
compete at all. Thus, giving newcomers rights to their improvements is
more important in patent than in copyright law.
Let me begin by pointing out the limits of the market power rationale.
The argument cannot be that patents always confer market power and copy-
rights never do; that is simply wrong as an empirical matter. Most patents
do not confer market power,' 5 and so the need to allow improvements
should not arise in most patent cases. Further, some copyrights do confer
market power.' More generally, the market power argument is vul-
nerable to many of the same criticisms I have leveled at the "Different
Works" argument above. It is impossible to distinguish "patentable" from
"copyrightable" works cleanly by reference to subject matter, and it is even
harder to distinguish innovations which confer market power from those
that do not by reference to the "patent" or "copyright" label.
Nonetheless, Paul Heald is surely correct that more patents than copy-
rights confer power in an economically relevant market, at least as a statis-
tical matter. I do not think that fact justifies the current legal rules,
however. In the first place, the legal rules that pay attention to market
power-the antitrust laws and the misuse doctrines-already take account
of this difference. The patent misuse doctrine, for example, is much
more vibrant than its copyright counterpart. t 7 And the federal antitrust
Where property rights theory assigns broad initial rights and then
leaves the parties to bargain to an efficient outcome, the tailored incentives
approach pays closer attention to the particular allocation of rights that is
made. Merges and Nelson's approach, if valid, undermines the fundamen-
tal tenets of a property rights approach to intellectual property, since
(as noted above) invention and creation are unquestionably cumulative
activities."56 My argument diverges from theirs in that my argument
does not depend upon the relative value of competition and property in
motivating invention. I argue in this Part that even if the property rights
approach is efficient in theory, in practice it faces insurmountable
obstacles. Those obstacles can best be overcome by a scheme of divided
entitlements similar to that which currently exists in patent law. The value
of this argument is twofold: it is not highly dependent on one's theory of
the innovation process, and (in part for that reason) it is generalizable to
copyright as well as patent cases.
I will begin to address these issues in subpart A by taking a closer
look at the property rights argument supporting the copyright rule, and
some of the assumptions on which it relies. In subpart B, I will examine
what happens when we relax some of the less realistic assumptions in pro-
perty rights theory.
A. PropertyRights Theory
In 1977, Edmund Kitch offered a new theory of the patent system, one
that he said would "reintegrate[] the patent institution with the general
theory of property rights." 7 The property rights theory of intellectual
property is rooted in many of the same economic traditions as incentive
theory, but its focus is on the ability of intellectual property ownership to
force the efficient use of inventions and creations through licensing."5
The fundamental economic bases of this approach are the "tragedy of the
commons" and the hypothetical Coasean world without transaction costs.
The tragedy of the commons is a classic economic story, in which common
property will be over-used by people who have access to it, since each
individual reaps all of the benefits of his personal use, but shares only a
STUD. 325, 326 (1989); see also Peter Jaszi, Caught in the Net of Copyright, 75 OR. L. REv. 299, 300
(1996) (stating that the property rationale does not accurately characterize intellectual property).
256. See supra note 32 (collecting sources); KENNETH W. DAM, INTELLECTUALPROPERTY IN AN
AGE OF SoFTWARsAND BIOTECHNOLOGY 4 (Chicago Law & Economics Working Paper No. 35, 1995)
("[Iln the overwhelming majority of instances each innovation builds on past innovations.").
257. Kitch, supra note 13, at 265.
258. See Wendy J. Gordon, Of Harms andBenefits: Torts, Restitution, and IntellectualProperty,
21 J. LEGAL STUD. 449, 473 (1992); Kitch, supra note 13, at 276-79; Merges, supra note 154, at
2661.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1045
small portion of the costs.5 9 Thus, lakes open to the public are likely
to be over-fished, with negative consequences for the public (to say nothing
of the fish!) in future years. Common fields will be over-grazed, with
similarly unfortunate consequences. The economic solution to the tragedy
of the commons is private property.m° If everyone owns a small piece
of land (or lake), and can keep others out of it (with real or legal
"fences"), then the private and public incentives are aligned. People will
not over-graze their own land, because if they do they will suffer the full
consequences of their actions. 1 Further, if dealmaking between neigh-
bors is costless, as Coase postulated but did not believe,' transactions
will allow neighbors with large cattle herds to purchase grazing rights from
others with smaller herds. Such transactions should occur until each piece
of land is put to its best possible use.'
In the context of intellectual property, Kitch's article remains one of
the most significant efforts to integrate intellectual property with property
rights theory.' Kitch argues that the patent system operates not (as tra-
ditionally thought) as an incentive-by-reward system, giving exclusive
rights to successful inventors in order to encourage future inventors, but
as a "prospect" system analogous to mineral claims. Of course, one of the
characteristics of ideas is that because they are public goods, there is no
problem of "over-use" analogous to the commons in real property. Rather,
259. See Garrett Hardin, The Tragedy of the Commons, 162 SCIENCE 1243, 1244 (1968).
260. See id. at 1245.
261. While in theory it is possible for cattle owners to agree to limit their grazing in the public
interest, any such effort at agreement is likely to run into insurmountable problems. Not only will
organizing and policing such an agreement take effort that will not be rewarded, but individual grazers
have an incentive to free ride, reaping the benefits of reduced grazing by others while refusing to
reduce their own grazing. For more on these problems, see MANCUR OLSON, JR., THE LoGIc OF
COLLECTIVE ACTION (rev. ed. 1971). One commentator views this internalization of (positive) exter-
nalities as a key function of property. See Harold Demsetz, Toward a Theory of PropertyRights, 57
AM. ECON. REV. 347, 348 (1967).
On the other hand, for a rejection of the tragedy of the commons approach in certain contexts,
see Carol Rose, The Comedy of the Commons: Custom, Commerce, and Inherently Public Property,
53 U. CHI. L. REV. 711, 718-19 (1986). Rose is surely correct that private division of land is not
always efficient. Consider how problematic the task of walking through your neighborhood would be
if every piece of sidewalk were privately owned by a different person, and you were required to obtain
permission to take each step. See also ELINOR OSTROM, GOVERNING THE COMMONS: THE EVOLUTION
OF INSTITUTIONS FOR COLLECTIVE ACTION (1990) (offering examples of successful communal gover-
nance of common spaces).
262. See R.H. Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, 3 J.L. & ECON. 1, 2-7, 15 (1960).
263. See Calabresi & Melamed, supra note 254, at 1095 (discussing this implication of Coase's
theorem).
264. For other property-based views of intellectual property, see, for example, DAM, supra note
256; Trotter Hardy, Property (and Copyright) in Cyberspace, 1996 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 217, 264;
Edmund W. Kitch, Patents:Monopolies or PropertyRights?, 8 RES. L. & ECON. 31 (1986); Michael
Wurzer, Note, Infringement of the Exclusive Right to PrepareDerivative Works: Reducing Uncertainty,
73 MINN. L. REv. 1521, 1544-45 (1989) (delivering an extreme example of the property approach,
under which any part of a work with significant economic value is classed as property).
1046 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
265. See Kitch, supra note 13, at 271-75 (making the analogy to mineral claims explicit).
266. Id. at 276.
267. Id.
268. See Anastasia P. Winslow, Rapping on a Revolving Door:An EconomicAnalysis of Parody
and Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 69 S. CAL. L. REV. 767, 780 (1996) (noting that the Coase
1997] Economics of Improvement 1047
theorem suggests that the initial assignment of property rights between original creators and improvers
is irrelevant). For a discussion of what happens when we relax these unrealistic assumptions, see infra
subpartV(B). On the importance of efficient licensing to the case for intellectual property protection,
see Wendy J. Gordon, Asymmetric Market Failure and Prisoner'sDilemma in Intellectual Property,
17 U. DAYTON L. REv. 853, 857 (1992) (arguing that unless markets for protected works develop,
generally through licensing, the economicjustification for protection of intellectual property collapses).
269. It is not possible to price intellectual property at its marginal cost and still stay in the business
of producing new works, since developing those new works requires a fixed investment of resources,
such as time and research money, that frequently dwarfs the marginal cost of making and distributing
copies of the idea once it has been developed.
270. See Kitch, supra note 13, at 274. This is not the same as conceding that demand curves are
always horizontal in patent cases. Compare Oddi, supra note 13, at 281 ("Kitch argues that the normal
assumption of a negatively sloped demand curve should not be made; rather the demand curve should
be substantially horizontal, indicating competitionwith thepatented invention."), with Kitch, supranote
13, at 274-75 ("[ T~he patent case is always visualized as one of a demand curve with a negative slope
and its attendant monopoly effects [when in fact] the demand conditions faced by particular ... patents
vary widely.").
271. SeeKenneth W. Dam, Some Economic Considerationsin the IntellectualPropertyProtection
of Sofiware, 24 J. LEGAL STUD. 321,332 & n.44 (1995); Frank H. Easterbrook, Intellectual Property
Is Still Property, 13 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 108, 113 (1990); Hardy, supra note 264, at 218
1048 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
(arguing for property rights in eyberspace and noting that "something like property rights" already
exists in copyright law). Wendy Gordon also points to detailed similarities between copyright law and
common-law property. See WendyJ. Gordon, An Inquiry into the Merits ofCopyright: The Challenges
of Consistency, Consent, and Encouragement Theory, 41 STAN. L. REV. 1343, 1354-77 (1989)
[hereinafter Gordon, Inquiry]; cf. Gordon, supra note 258, at 460 (arguing that the traditional
reluctance to recognize restitutionary claims in the common law of real property should not be
applicable to intellectual property). To be sure, Gordon's position on this issue is complex. She
acknowledges that the common law places limits on the power of property owners to control their
property. See Gordon, Inquiry, supra, at 1361-64. In addition, her ultimate reasons for favoring
strong copyright protection do not track Kitch's economic arguments. See id. at 1465-68. Further,
in other articles Gordon has suggested that strong copyright protection may not be appropriate in
circumstances where it may inhibit rather than promote improvements by others. See Wendy J.
Gordon, On Owning Information:IntellectualPropertyandthe RestitutionaryImpulse, 78 VA. L. REV.
149, 167, 247 (1992) [hereinafter Gordon, On Owning Information] ("A culture could not exist if all
free riding were prohibited within it."); Gordon, supra note 173, at 1633, 1631-35 (observing that the
owner of a copyright "may not be willing to exploit all of the possible derivative works over which his
copyright would ordinarily give him control," even though such derivative works may have social
value).
Other scholars who adopt the property rights view of copyright, at least in part, include Landes
4 Posner, supra note255, at 354-55 (describing economic distortions, such as the timing of the release
of the original work and transaction costs, as reasons for giving the author exclusive control of
derivative rights).
272. See Coase, supra note 262, at 15.
273. See Kitch, supra note 13, at 276.
19971 Economics of Improvement 1049
awarding patents to those who have identified an invention but might not
yet have commercialized it makes sense, because making those inventors
property owners will give them the right incentive to improve and commer-
cialize their invention.274 But if it is the property incentive that is criti-
cal, why wait for a first inventor to file a detailed patent application, which
after all must reduce the invention to practice and enable others to make
it?275 After all, mineral claims on private land belong to the private land-
owner, whether or not he is the first to discover them.276 In many other
contexts, we assign property rights virtually arbitrarily, and expect trans-
actions to take care of the rest: we did not wait to see who would build a
high-rise building during the Oklahoma land rush, for example. Assigning
property rights in advance of any invention-perhaps to the first person
to request them in a particular field, even if they have not yet invented
anything-seems perfectly consistent with the prospect theory.'m Indeed,
it should be preferable to the current patent system on this theory, since it
will allow efficient investment in initialresearch as well as improvements,
and prevent wasteful races to be the first to invent the initial
technologyY8
The problem with handing out property rights in advance of invention
is the same problem with Kitch's prospect theory-it is unrealistic to expect
that property owners will be uniquely good at identifying potential future
inventors or improvers. Even if assigning property rights ex ante gives the
property owner the proper financial incentives to invest in research (or to
search for the "right" inventor),2 79 there is more to invention than
research dollars. Modern economic literature is replete with evidence of
how hard it is to predict invention in advance, or even to replicate an
invention once it has been made. 2' Further, even companies that
274. See id. at 247, 246-47 ("Absent a patent, firms have less than the optimal incentive to invest
in providing information about and techniques for using the new technology.").
275. See 35 U.S.C. § 112 (1994); Fiers v. Revel, 984 F.2d 1164, 1169 (Fed. Cir. 1993).
276. Kitch discusses mining claims on public rather than private land. See Kitch, supra note 13,
at 271-75.
277. For a proposal along these lines, see Kingston, supra note 55, at 59-86 (proposing an
"innovation warrant" to be awarded in advance of promised innovation); see also Ben T. Yu, A
Contractual Remedy to Premature Innovation: The Vertical Integration of Brand-Name Specific
Research, 22 ECON. INQUIRY 660 (1984) (suggesting that manufacturers might contract with potential
inventors before they invent); Ben T. Yu, PotentialCompetition and Contractingin Innovation, 24 I.L.
& ECON. 215 (1981) (arguing that prior contracting should be adopted to promote competition in
innovation).
278. On wasteful races to invent, see Merges & Nelson, supra note 32, at 868-79.
279. It is not clear that even this assumption is reasonable. Merges points to economic literature
suggesting that a company with a successful invention will choose to focus on one or two basic applica-
tions of that invention, rather than investing money and effort in researching implications of its inven-
tion that lie outside its core competencies. See Merges, supra note 83, at 371-73.
280. For more detail on this issue, see, for example, Steven A. Lippman et al., Heterogeneity
Under Competition, 29 ECON. INQUIRY 774 (1991) (noting factors that may prevent firms that have
innovated successfully from replicating their invention on a broader scale); Michael E. Porter, The
1050 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
Structure Within Industries and Companies' Performance, 51 REv. ECON. & STAT. 214 (1979)
(discussing mobility barriers in specific markets that restrict the ability to innovate or to replicate
successful strategies); David I. Teece, Profiting from Technological Innovation: Implications for
Integration, Collaboration,Licensing and Public Policy, 15 REs. POL. 285 (1986) (theorizing that
successful innovation may depend on a firm's ability to control complementary assets).
281. According to one report, the full commercial potential of many major inventions is not
immediately recognized by the inventor or the marketplace. Nathan Rosenberg cites a number of
examples of such unrecognized potential: Marconi expected the radio to be used for point-to-point
communication, not broadcasting; the transistor was expected to be used primarily in hearing aids for
the deaf; Bell called his telephone a mere "improvement[] in telegraphy."
Kathleen O'Toole, The Future Was 'Obviously Not Obvious," STAN. OBSERVER, May-June 1994, at
13 (recounting a lecture delivered by Nathan Rosenberg).
282. See Kitch, supra note 13, at 276; see also Gordon, supra note 258, at 472-74. Gordon
argues that giving intellectual property rights to creators will encouragethose who wish to use an inven-
tion to come to the intellectual property owner for a license. While this is no doubt true of most users,
the situation is somewhat different in the case of improvers, as explained below.
283. Alternatively, the patent grant may serve a marketing function, identifying original inventors
to companies that might wish to acquire the invention outright, perhaps because they are in a better
position to develop or commercialize it. See Willard F. Mueller, The Origins of the Basic Inventions
UnderlyingDu Pont's Major Product and Process Innovations, 1920 to 1950, in THE RATE AND
DIRECTION OF INVENTIVE AcTivITY (Nat'l Bureau of Econ. Research ed., 1962) (noting that Du Pont
purchased many inventions from outside creators); Roberto Mazzoleni & Richard R. Nelson, Economic
Theories About the Benefits and Costs of Patents 15-16 (1996) (unpublished manuscript, on file with
the Texas Law Review). This is unquestionably a "prospect"-related benefit of the patent system.
However, it does not deal directly with the improvements issue, and, in particular, does not offer any
justification for a rule that gives original inventors the automatic right to control the work of improvers.
284. Rochelle Dreyfuss suggests another option-that potential improvers may simply work on a
different product in the same field, wastefully building from scratch rather than working from the
original invention. See Dreyfuss, supra note 220, at 228.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1051
285. See Arrow, supra note 19, at 614-16; see also Gordon, supra note 258, at 475-76
(identifying this problem, though in the analogous context of intellectual property creators trying to
license their work in a world without legal protection). It is worth noting that the problem is signifi-
cantly worse in the intellectual property context than it is in the context of real property. In certain real
property contexts, such as oil and gas leases, oil exploration companies may find it rational to drill first
and negotiate rights later. The transaction costs of signing agreements with multiple property owners
of an unexplored field outweigh the risk of losing the drilling rights should the field be valuable. By
contrast, in the intellectual property context, potential improvers are less likely to win the rights after
disclosure to original inventors, since the original inventor (unlike the real property owners above) pre-
sumably has its own facilities and could develop the improvement in-house. (By way of comparison,
oil exploration companies do not do their exploratory drilling in a competitor's field without an agree-
ment in place.) Further, the value of the improvement is information which would have to be
disclosed, while the value of an oil strike may be partially appropriable by the drilling firm.
286. See Merges, supra note 87, at 81-82. While there are partial solutions to Arrow's paradox
in this context, they all involve giving the improver some sort of legal control over the improvement.
These solutions are described in more detail infra notes 382-87.
287. See Merges & Nelson, supra note 32, at 875 ("In our own research, we have not found a
single case where the holder of a broad patent used it effectively through tailored licensing to coordinate
the R&D of others."). Instead, patent owners sometimes use as a proxy for possible improvers the sub-
set of companies that take a license to work the original patent. By employing a "grantback clause,"
the original inventor can obtain ownership rights to all improvements by licensees, whether or not the
improvement would infringe the original patent. See Timothy J. Engling, Improvements in Patent
Licensing, 78 J. PAT. & TRADEMARK OFF. Soc'Y 739, 740-41, 744-45 (1996) (describing grantback
clauses).
1052 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
288. The mechanics of such bargaining are considered further in the next section.
289. A proponent of property rights might point to two alternative means of achieving the same
result even when the original inventor controls all rights to improvements. First, one might try to
avoid Arrow's paradox by vesting actual improvers with a trade secret right in their improvement.
Thus improvers might be able to negotiate a confidentiality agreement with the original patent owner
prior to disclosing their invention. Unfortunately, such agreements have proven difficult to enter into
and enforce. Many companies refuse to sign such agreements under any circumstances, because they
fear that the "improver" will disclose an idea that the company has already been working on, and will
later sue for misappropriation. See Whitfield v. Lear, 751 F.2d 90, 93 (2d Cir. 1984) (noting a
general practice of rejecting unsolicited movie scripts); Davis v. General Foods Corp., 21 F. Supp. 445
(S.D.N.Y. 1937) (describing a form letter by which a company reserved all rights to determine if an
unsolicited recipe was deserving of compensation). On the other hand, if the confidentiality agreement
permits such independent development, it arguably does not provide particularly robust protection to
the improver disclosing the information, since it is often hard to prove that an idea was stolen rather
than developed independently.
Alternatively, a patent owner might try to license any and all potential improvers by granting
them a limited property right in whatever they later invent. This would in effect mimic the blocking
patents rle by contract. While in a strict Coasean world such broad agreements would be equivalent
to giving patents to improvers by legal rule, in fact they impose significant and unnecessary transaction
costs (as discussed in the next section) to achieve the same result patent law already does.
290. See Goldstein, supra note 37, at 252 (suggesting that the creators of unauthorized derivative
works should have rights in their original creations). While the interests at stake are somewhat dif-
ferent in copyright cases, where the "improvement" is more likely to consist of a number of small
expressions rather than a single idea, the same problem with predisclosure bargaining still occurs.
Indeed, the existence of Hollywood script registries testifies to one copyright-driven industry's attempts
to deal with the problem. See generallyRobert M. Winteringham, Note, Stolen from StardustandAir:
Idea Theft in the EntertainmentIndustry anda Proposalfora ConceptInitiator Credit,46 FED. COMM.
L.J. 373 (1994).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1053
mission in exchange for a royalty based upon the value of the new
improvement. In practice, however, efficient licensing negotiations will
not always take place, for a number of reasons.
291. See JAY DRATLER, JR., LICENSING OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY § 1.01(2), 1-6 to 1-7
(1996).
292. See id. § 1.04(1).
293. See supra notes 273-87 and accompanying text.
294. SeeJ. PeterKilling, TechnologyAcquisition:License Agreement orJoint Venture, 15 COLUM.
J. WORLD Bus., Fall 1980, at 38, 44-45 ("Neither buyers nor sellers of technology seem to have a
clear idea of the value of the commodity in which they are trading."); David J. Teece, The Marketfor
Know-How and the Efficient InternationalTransfer of Technology, 458 ANNALS AM. ACAD. POL. &
SOC. Sl. 81, 87-88 (1981).
295. But see Dam, supranote 271, at 353 n.108 (assuming that transaction costs are relatively low
in the software arena and that likely new developers can easily be identified, but offering no evidence
to support this assumption).
1054 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
estimated that cost at as much as twenty percent of the total value of the
underlying technology license, 2' or in excess of $100,000 per trans-
action.2' These data are of limited value, since they are taken from
international technology licenses, where the costs are no doubt higher than
for the average license." Nonetheless, even the average transaction
costs associated with an intellectual property license are unlikely to be
trivial.
To be sure, there are institutions such as the American Society of
Composers, Authors and Publishers (ASCAP) that have developed to
reduce the transaction costs of intellectual property licensing, normally by
licensing in bulk. 2' There have also been attempts to reduce the per-unit
cost through standardization of contracts, notably in the distribution of
computer software through "shrinkwrap licenses."" But these mecha-
nisms for reducing transaction costs are far more effective at licensing
standard end uses than at licensing the creation of improvements. Improve-
ments are hard to categorize and assign set fees; different uses will incor-
porate different amounts of the original work and will occur in different
markets. Further, copyright owners are likely to want the power to review
each individual use by an improver, while they may be willing to waive
such rights in the case of standardized, consumptive end uses. Thus, an
"improvers' ASCAP" may well face insurmountable problems. Further,
to the extent such a standard "improver's license" is created, it will likely
be accompanied by a standardized "per-image" or "per-use" fee, one
which is suboptimal because it does not reflect the value of the use pro-
posed by that particular improver.0 1
The presence of these costs in intellectual property licensing transac-
tions leads to two types of first-order deviations from the efficient behavior
296. See DAVID J. TEECE, THE MULTINATIONAL CORPORATION AND THE RESOURCE COST OF
INTERNATIONAL TECHNOLOGY TRANSFER 43-44 (1976).
297. See FAROK J.CONTRACTOR, INTERNATIONAL TECHNOLOGY LICENSING: COMPENSATION,
COSTS, AND NEGOTIATION 105 (1981).
298. See Richard E. Caves et al., The Imperfect Marketfor Technology Licenses, 45 OXFORD
BULL. ECON. & STATS. 249, 260-62 (1983); cf. Hardy, supra note 264, at 236-39 (discussing the
transaction costs in the computerization of information and arguing for a property entitlement in
cyberspace); Mark A. Lemley, Shrinkwraps in Cyberspace, 35 JURIMErRICs J. 311, 323 (1995)
(suggesting that the growth of the Internet may reduce transaction costs for many types of licenses).
299. See Stanley M. Besen et al., An Economic Analysis of Copyright Collectives, 78 VA. L. REV.
383, 385 (1992); Robert P. Merges, Contractinginto LiabilityRules: Intellectual PropertyRights and
Collective Rights Organizations, 84 CAL. L. REV. 1293, 1296-97 (1996); Merges, supra note 154, at
2669-70.
300. For more detail on such licenses, see Mark A. Lemley, Intellectual PropertyandShrinkwrap
Licenses, 68 S. CAL. L. REV. 1239 (1995).
301. For a detailed discussion of this problem in the multimedia context, see Merges, supra note
299, at 1273-75; Fara Daun, Comment, The Content Shop: Toward an Economic Legal Structurefor
ClearingandLicensing Multimedia Content, 30 LOYOLA L.A. L. REV. 215 (1996).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1055
302. Indeed, Merges declares that "it seems whimsical to assume that all improvers and potential
improvers will be able to bargain with the holders of pioneering patents." Merges, supra note 83, at
374.
303. For example, consider an author who wishes to excerpt from the work of another, but is
unable to track down the successors in interest of a dead author or a defunct publisher.
304. See Merges, supra note 154, at 2657-59 (explaining why uncertainty over the relative value
of original inventions and improvements is likely).
305. Some have suggested that the scope of a patent is "clearly demarcated in the patent itself."
See, e.g. Kenneth W. Dam, The Economic Underpinnings of PatentLaw, 23 J. LEGAL STUD. 247,267
(1994); see also Markman v. Westview Instruments, Inc., 52 F.3d 967, 986 (Fed. Cir. 1995) ("If the
1056 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
First, uncertainty may prevent the parties from recognizing that there are
any gains to be had from trade. In the example above, if neither of us
recognize that you would be better at commercializing the invention than
me, we will not enter into a license agreement. Second, even where the
parties recognize that licensing would be beneficial, uncertainty may cause
them to disagree over the appropriate price in a way that prevents the bar-
gain from taking place. Again using the example above, suppose that
while you would actually be able to commercialize the invention for a $700
profit, because of uncertainty I think your efforts will result in profits of
$900, while you think they will produce profits of only $600. You will be
unwilling to accept my demand that you pay me $700 for the exclusive
right to commercialize the product, even though to me that demand repre-
sents a fair division of what I perceive to be the gains from trade. Rational
Coasean bargaining assumes perfect information, a characteristic strikingly
absent from negotiations involving intellectual property.'
patent's claims are sufficiently unambiguous for the Pro, there should exist no factual ambiguity
... .'), aff'd, 116 S. Ct. 1384 (1996). But that statement is clearly wrong as a factual matter. There
is considerable uncertainty over the scope of most patents, for many reasons: because of drafting
ambiguities, because of the doctrine of equivalents, and because of uncertainty about the validity of the
patent. See supra subpart H(A); cf. Paul N. Higbee Jr., The Jury's Role in Patent Cases: Markman
v. Westview Instruments, Inc., 3 J.INTELL. PROP. L. 407, 422 (1996) (criticizing the Markman court
for reasoning that statutory requirements and administrative supervision removed all ambiguity sur-
rounding the scope of patent claims). All of these uncertainties complicate license negotiations.
306. See Kenneth J. Arrow, The Property Rights Doctrine and Demand Revelation Under
Incomplete Information, in ECONOMICS AND HUMAN WELFARE: ESSAYS IN HONOR OF TIBOR
ScrrovsKy 23, 29-31 (Michael J.Boskin ed., 1979), reprintedin 4 KENNETH J.ARROW, COLLECTED
PAPERS OF KENNETH J.ARROW: THE ECONOMICS OF INFORMATION 216, 222-24 (1984); cf. Steven
N. Wiggins & Gary D. Libecap, Oil Field Unitization:ContractualFailurein the PresenceofImperfect
Information, 75 Am.ECON. REv. 368, 368 (1985) (providing empirical evidencethat divergentvalua-
tions of oil field revenue resulting from "imperfect and asymmetric information" led to the breakdown
of oil field development negotiations in a significant number of cases).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1057
307. I will ignore the cynic's view that the socially efficient number of law review articles might
be zero.
308. See Gordon, supra note 173, at 1630 ("[R]evenues from scholarly articles are arguably
smaller than such [social] benefit would warrant."). For a treatment of the issue in some detail, see
Howard P. Tuckman & Jack Leahey, What Is an Article Worth?, 83 J. POL. ECON. 951 (1975).
309. For examples of actual cases presenting such issues, see DSC Communicationsv. DGI Techs.,
Inc., 81 F.3d 597 (5th Cir. 1996); Sega Enters.Ltd. v. Accolade, Inc., 977 F.2d 1510 (9th Cir. 1992);
and Atari Games Corp. v. Nintendo of America Inc., 975 F.2d 832 (Fed. Cir. 1992). On the general
process of software reverse engineering, see Andrew Johnson-Laird, Reverse Engineering of Software:
Separating Legal Mythology from Actual Technology, 5 SoFrWARE L.J. 331, 342-45 (1992). For a
general discussion of the economic parameters of the problem, see Julie E. Cohen, Reverse Engineering
and the Rise of Electronic Vigilantism:IntellectualProperty Implicationsof "Lock-Out"Programs,68
S. CAL. L. REV. 1091 (1995).
310. See Sega, 977 F.2d at 1518-19.
1058 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
explanation rings hollow, and not merely because competitors might have
noneconomic reasons not to agree.31 In this case, the proposed use
might be socially valuable precisely because it encourages more compe-
tition in a market than would exist without the use, and therefore reduces
the profits of all competitors while benefiting consumers. 3 ' The
enhanced consumer surplus associated with a move from monopoly to
competition by definition cannot be "captured" by the competitor, and so
the competitor cannot possibly offer to pay the original creator the full
social value of the license. Nor can consumers effectively band together
to pay for the reverse engineering, because of collective action
problems. 1 3 This form of licensing market failure is endemic in
transactions where the proposed licensee will compete directly with the
original copyright owner. Such transactions rarely occur. 14
311. On such noneconomic factors, see infra notes 323-26 and accompanying text.
312. See Jerry R. Green& Suzanne Scotchmer, On the Division of Profit in SequentialInnovation,
26 RAND J.ECON. 20, 21-22 (1995) (arguing that the first innovator cannot capture all the profit from
later innovation by a different improver through licensing transactions). Green and Scotchmer view
this as a problem, but in fact it seems central to the limited nature of the intellectual property
enterprise.
313. Cf. RAFAEL ROB & ARTHUR FISHMAN, THE FREQUENCY AND PRICING OF PRODUCT
INNOVATIONS (University of Pa. Institute for Law and Econ. Discussion Working Paper No. 226,
1995).
314. For example, virtually all software licensing contracts contain provisions purporting to forbid
reverse engineering. See Lemley, supra note 300, at 1239; David A. Rice, Public Goods, Private
Contract, and Public Policy: FederalPreemption of Software License ProhibitionsAgainst Reverse
Engineering, 53 U. PrIr. L. REv. 543 (1992).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1059
you get more than your "fair" share. 15 Such strategies are rational in
the sense that they may produce asymmetric gains skewed in favor of the
party that employs them. However, they may also result in the parties
failing to come to terms at all, particularly if both parties aggressively seek
the lion's share of the gains from trade.316
Robert Cooter has modeled the consequences of strategic behavior for
such negotiations,3 17 and Robert Merges has applied that model in the
patent context. 1 8 Merges treats a hypothetical situation involving two
negotiating parties, one an original inventor whose invention produces
profits of $100, and the second an improver whose improvement will
produce a total of $1000 in profits if used in conjunction with the original
invention.3 19 He suggests that giving absolute control over improvements
to the original inventor encourages that original inventor to seek a larger
share of the gains from trade than the improver, even though the improver
has contributed the majority of the value of the improved invention?' °
This strategic behavior threatens to prevent the parties from concluding a
deal, and indeed Merges notes several examples of what he calls
"bargaining breakdown" in patent history.321 As with the problems of
transaction costs and uncertainty, the effect of strategic behavior is that
parties in some cases will not enter into efficient licensing agreements. 3'
315. See WILLIAM POUNDsTONE, PRISONER'S DILEMMA212-13 (1992) (discussing the advantages
of perceived irrationality in game-theoretic models of "chicken").
316. While one might object that one or both parties should back down if they see that the entire
negotiation is at risk, that is not always the case. Because of information uncertainties it will not
always be evident that a party is playing chicken. Further, where one party is a repeat player in license
negotiations, it may profit that player to develop a reputation for refusing to back down, since that
reputation will in turn influence the behavior of its opponents in subsequent negotiations. See JAMES
W. FRIEDMAN, GAME THEORY WITH APPLICATIONS TO ECONOMICS 136-38 (1986) (arguing that
"tough" responses early in the bargaining process are rewarded later by discouraging other competitors
from entering the market).
317. See Robert Cooter, The Cost of Coase, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 1, 20-21 (1982) [hereinafter
Cooter, Cost of Coase]; Robert Cooter, DecentralizedLawfor a Complex Economy: The Structural
Approach to Adjudicating the New Law Merchant, 144 U. PA. L. REv. 1643, 1675-77 (1996)
[hereinafter Cooter, Law Merchant]; Robert Cooter & Stephen Marks, Bargainingin the Shadow of
the Law: A Testable Model of Strategic Behavior, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 225 (1982).
318. See Merges, supra note 87, at 82-83; Merges, supra note 154, at 2659-60; Merges &
Nelson, supra note 32, at 865-66.
319. See Merges, supra note 87, at 79.
320. See id. at 81.
321. See id. at 84, 84-89 (listing examples involving Marconi Wireless Telegraph Company,
AT&T, RCA, and Bessemer).
322. Indeed, Cooter goes so far as to characterize hard bargaining as a negative externality. See
Cooter, Law Merchant,supra note 317, at 1676.
1060 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
323. If one is willing to take enough noneconomic factors into account in defining rationality, vir-
tually all refusals to license will be rational. For example, licensing your work to someoneyou do not
like may impose a "psychic cost" that would have to be taken into account in determining the market-
clearing license price.
324. The expansion of intellectual property has led to numerous efforts to control references to,
or criticism of, a person, using trademark law and the right of publicity. See, e.g., Waits v. Frito-Lay,
Inc., 978 F.2d 1093, 1096 (9th Cir. 1992); White v. Samsung Elecs. Am., Inc., 971 F.2d 1395 (9th
Cir. 1992); Midler v. Ford Motor Co., 849 F.2d 460 (9th Cir. 1988). For criticism of this trend, see
White v. Samsung Electronics America, Inc., 989 F.2d 1512 (9th Cir. 1993) (Kozinski, J., dissenting
from denial of rehearing en bane).
325. See, e.g., Gordon, supra note 173, at 1632; Robert P. Merges, Are You Making Fun of Me?:
Notes on Market Failureand the Parody Defense in Copyright, 21 AIPLA Q.J. 305 (1993); Richard
A. Posner, When Is Parody Fair Use?, 21 J. LEGAL STUD. 67 (1992); Winslow, supra note 268;
Landy, supra note 36, at 250-51.
326. An example of a refusal to license a parody on any terms is the Campbell v. Acuff-Rose
Music, Inc. case, in which the copyright holder to Roy Orbison's song Pretty Woman refused to grant
a license for a parodic rap version of the song by 2 Live Crew. Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc.,
510 U.S. 569, 572-73 (1994); see also Merges, supra note 325, at 308-09 (noting the irony of subse-
1997] Economics of Improvement 1061
quent arguments by the plaintiff that the song parody "undermines economic incentives"). Gordon
refers to this as an "antidissemination motive" and includes it in her catalogue of potential market
failures. Gordon, supra note 173, at 1632-35; see also Landy, supra note 36, at 250-51 (contending
that refusing to grant permission for the use of copyrighted material in parody cases to avoid criticism
causes market failure).
327. See Cooter, Cost of Coase, supra note 317, at 21; see also Merges, supra note 87, at 81
(discussing the division of the "cooperative surplus"). But see Merges, supra note 299, at 1391-93
(suggesting that unified property rights will encourage the development of licensing organizations, such
as ASCAP, designed to overcome the transaction costs of bargaining). The ASCAP model of market
facilitation is based on statistical estimation of the uses that are made of copyrighted works. This
model works well for market transactions which are frequent, low in individual value, and susceptible
to standardization. Copyright licenses to end users may possess those characteristics, but licenses to
likely improvers do not. It is difficult to imagine how ASCAP or its equivalent could come up with
a statistical model and royalty structure that would capture the complexities of potential improvements
to the satisfaction of all parties involved.
1062 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
328. Such an increase in the surplus will not eliminate the incentive to engage in strategic
behavior, and may even increase it (because more money will be at stake in each transaction). Nor
is it likely to eliminate all noneconomic barriers to trade, though at least some of those barriers should
disappear when a sufficient amount of money is at stake.
329. See Merges, supra note 87, at 80-81.
330. How much the gains from trade increase depends on how important the improvement was
in relation to the original invention. I consider the implications of this fact infra subpart VI(A).
331. In a recent article, Ian Ayres and Eric Talley argue that dividing legal entitlements may
encourage negotiation between the parties owning partial entitlements. See Ian Ayres & Eric Talley,
SolomonicBargaining:Dividinga LegalEntidtlementto FacilitateCoasean Trade, 104 YALE L.J. 1027,
1092-94 (1995) [hereinafter Ayres & Talley, Solomonic Bargaining]. Their argument is not the one
presented in the text-that increasing the gains from trade will increase the incentive to come to terms.
Rather, they suggest that using liability rather than property rules (and thus giving compulsory licenses
to improvers on the payment of a reasonable royalty set by a court) would encourage the parties to
forego strategic behavior in the bargaining process, primarily because it increases uncertainty as to the
outcome of the negotiation. See id. at 1093. For discussion of their model, and of possible counter-
19971 Economics of Improvement 1063
vailing factors, see Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Do LiabilityRules FacilitateBargaining?A Reply
to Ayres and Talley, 105 YALE L.J. 221,227 (1995); Ian Ayres & Eric Talley, DistinguishingBetween
Consensualand NonconsensualAdvantagesof Liability Rules, 105 YALE LJ.235 (1995) [hereinafter
Ayres & Talley, Distinguishing].
The recent addition of § 104A to the Copyright Act should provide a test of the Ayres-Talley
thesis. As part of its effort to restore copyright ownership to certain works in the public domain,
Congress provided an exception for good faith creators of derivative works. Those who have created
derivative works based on a once-public-domain work in which copyright has been restored can con-
tinue to produce the derivative work, as long as they pay "reasonable compensation" to the owner of
the restored copyright. 17 U.S.C. § 104A(d)(3)(A) (1994). If the parties cannot agree on compen-
sation, either party may go to court to obtain a court order setting compensation. 17 U.S.C.
§ 104A(d)(3)(B) (1994). If Ayres and Talley are correct, this use of liability rules should reduce stra-
tegic behavior among parties negotiating "reasonable compensation."
I discuss objections to the use of liability rules in intellectual property cases in more detail infra
notes 360-62 and accompanying text.
332. Indeed, Michael Heller has suggested that splintering a property entitlement among too many
factions could lead to a "tragedy of the anticommons," in which the parties all hold out and so refuse
to come to agreement. See Michael Heller, Property in Transition 3 (Nov. 12, 1996) (unpublished
manuscript, on file with the Texas Law Review). Heller does note, though, that increasing the cost of
holding out is more likely to bring the parties to agreement. See id. at 49; see also DOUGLAS
LAYCOCK, MODERN AMEImcAN REMEDIES 371 (2d ed. 1994) (suggesting that "bilateral monopoly"
increases transaction costs over multi-party bargaining cases).
333. See supra notes 78-92, 148-68 and accompanying text.
1064 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
just as in copyright law, while radical improvements are the property of the
improver.' (The rule for significant improvements in patent law is
somewhere in between-the parties divide the property entitlement.335)
Not only is the radical improver excused from patent liability to the origi-
nal inventor under the reverse doctrine of equivalents, but she can pre-
sumably patent her improvement, thus excluding the original inventor (and
everyone else) from practicing the improvement without a license.
The copyright approach of assigning a property right in radical
improvements to the original creator will produce an efficient result in
circumstances where the parties can be expected to come to terms-the
copyright owner will presumably license the right to make the valuable
improvement to the radical improver. If licensing is imperfect, however,
patent law's treatment of radical improvers makes much more sense than
copyright's.33 6 If the parties cannot be expected to come to terms in all
cases, a default rule giving all rights in a radical improvement to the origi-
nal intellectual property owner is likely to encourage overinvestment in
initial works and underinvestment in radical improvements. To borrow an
example from Grady and Alexander,
Allowing someone who has invented a crude telephone to control the
entire communications industry creates such a large reward that
inventors would dissipate rents by trying to be the pioneer. In the
perverse equilibrium that would result from a system awarding full
control to the inventor who is first, the costs of developing dreams
that ultimately fail would equal or exceed the benefit to society of
those that succeed.337
334. While Merges refers to this as an exception to property-rule treatment of intellectual property
rights, see Merges, supra note 154, at 2668, that characterization seems inaccurate to me. Radical
improvers can sell their improvement and prevent others from doing so; original inventors have no
power over them. This is as much a property rule as giving original inventors the same power would
be, though of course the party holding the property right is different.
335. See supra notes 80-88 and accompanying text.
336. Mazzoleni and Nelson reach a similar conclusion:
If one assumes that, in general, potential licensees and patent holders have little difficulty
in reaching a license agreement (that is that the transaction costs of patent licensing are
small) then one may take a relatively relaxed view of the costs of granting a large prospect
controlling patent, even when one believes that potential explorers of the prospect are
diverse in terms of what they would do. On the other hand, if one believes that the
transaction costs often are high, and patent holders are prone to litigation, one is less
sanguine about this.
Mazzoleni & Nelson, supra note 283, at 20.
337. Grady & Alexander, supranote 13, at 307-08. While Grady and Alexander offer Bell's tele-
phone patent as an example, perhaps a better example is the crude incandescent light bulb patent issued
to Sawyer and Man. See The Incandescent Lamp Patent, 159 U.S. 465 (1895). If a copyright rule
were to prevail, Sawyer and Man would have had the right to prevent Edison from marketing his
greatly improved light bulb.
1997] Economics of Improvement 1065
338. See Merges, supra note 87, at 101-03 (arguing that ex ante incentives to invent will hardly
be affected by the reverse doctrine of equivalents, since its application in any particularcase is highly
contingent and extremely unlikely).
339. See PAUL A. SAMUELSON, ECONOMICS 470 (11th ed. 1980).
1066 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
349. For more on such markets and the effect of intellectual property, see Mark A. Lemley,
Antitrust and the Internet StandardizationProblem, 28 CONN. L. REV. 1041 (1996). For an example
of how the copyright rule can produce such a result, see infra notes 403-16 and accompanying text.
350. Whether it is economically rational for original inventors to suppress such improvements,
rather than licensing them for a fee, is a matter of considerable debate among economists. For histori-
cal evidence of such suppression, see Mark Clark, Suppressing Innovation: Bell Laboratoriesand
Magnetic Recording, 34 TEcH. & CULTURE 516, 532 (1993), and Richard Dunford, Suppression of
Technology as a Strategy for Controlling Resource Dependence, 32 ADMIN. SCI. Q. 512 (1987).
While it might seem irrational to think that an original inventor would suppress an improvement within
her control if it truly was valuable, several circumstances might induce her to do so. If the improve-
ment requires a new manufacturing technology or a different market approach, there may be substantial
fixed costs associated with switching over production from the old to the new way. The further
removed the improvement is from the original invention, the worse this problem is likely to be. Cf.
Teece, supra note 280, at 288, 288-90 (suggesting that much of the profit from innovation may come
from a firm's ability to capture "complementary assets" that relate uniquely to the particular technology
used). The alternative to switching over production facilities-licensing the improver to compete with
the original inventor, for a fee-is also unlikely to be attractive to the original inventor. Even if the
licensor could extract the full value of the improvement in a licensing transaction, which seems
unlikely, its market control will disappear along with the intellectual property right. Innovationis asso-
ciated with strong first-mover advantages, so the first company to manufacture and sell a product is
likely to maintain its dominant position even after the patent expires. Thus, the improver, rather than
the original inventor, would likely come out the victor in the long run.
351. Other doctrines common to both patent and copyright cases, notably the misuse defenses, may
also be called upon to provide relief in this situation. See Dam, supra note 305, at 260-61; see also
1068 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
C. Conclusions
The copyright rules governing improvements closely track the property
rights model of innovation, under which a strong unified grant of property
rights leads to efficient licensing of the invention and efficient incentives
to produce improvements. Unfortunately, the property rights story is
incomplete. Problems of imperfect information, transaction costs, strategic
behavior, and market power all impose barriers to the hypothetical efficient
license. 52
There is no reason to believe that these problems are uniquely con-
fined to patent rather than copyright licensing. If anything, some of the
problems that prevent efficient licensing are worse in the copyright context
than in the patent context. There are more potential authors and artists
who could improve a particular work than there are engineers who could
improve a particular invention, largely because the degree of specialization
required is less in the artistic world than in engineering. Thus, the prob-
lem of identifying improvers is at least as large for copyrighted works as
it is for patented works. Similarly, the uncertainty associated with the
success of a work of art or literature is probably greater than with
inventions, which at least function (or fail to function) according to defined
principles. While the bargaining costs per transaction are probably less in
absolute terms in copyright licenses than in patent licenses, the underlying
value of the transaction is also less. There is no reason to believe that
transaction costs as a percent of value are any less in the copyright context.
Indeed, for at least one important class of copyrighted works (multimedia
works), the transaction costs of the required licensing threaten to stifle an
entire industry.3 53 Finally, copyright owners are more likely than patent
Cohen, supra note 309, at 1181-98 (suggesting that such holdups can be cured by applications of the
misuse doctrines). However, applying antitrust and related doctrines to achieve structural relief in stan-
dardized markets may be futile, as I have suggested elsewhere. See Lemley, supra note 349, at 1073.
352. I am sensitive to Wendy Gordon's concern that "occasional cases of market failure should
not immediately trigger judicial exceptions," given the high administrative cost of case-by-case
decisionmaking. Gordon, supra note 258, at 474. Nonetheless, two factors lead me to believe that
varying property rights in accordance with the patent model is the more appropriate solution. First,
that variance operates by dividing cases into classes, rather than treating each one individually, a fact
which should reduce the administrative costs of decisionmaking. Second, I do not believe the circum-
stances detailed in this Part can be dismissed as "occasional" instances of market failure.
353. See generally Robert D. Sprague, Multimedia: The Convergence of New Technologies and
TraditionalCopyrightIssues, 71 DENV. U. L. REV. 635, 659-69 (1994) (examining the effects of cur-
rent copyright law when applied to multimedia); Daun, supra note 301, at 217, 217-18 ("When the
product's content consists of hundreds or even thousands of separate items of intellectual property, the
tasks and costs associated with negotiating and administering individual licenses can be overwhelming
and even paralyzing."); Heather J. Meeker, Note, Multimedia and Copyright, 20 RUTGEes COMP. &
TECH. L.J. 375, 397-400 (1994) (arguing that the difficulty in persuading copyright holders to license
their intellectual property is a contributing factor to the slow growth of the multimedia industry).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1069
354. See generally Margaret Jane Radin, PropertyandPersonhood,34 STAN. L. REv. 957(1982)
(suggesting that the personal economievalue of some forms of property predominates over its economic
value); see also Neil Netanel, Copyright Alienability Restrictions and the Enhancement of Author
Autonomy: A Normative Evaluation, 24 RUTGERS L.J. 347, 422-23 (1993) (applying Radin's theory in
the copyright context).
355. See Hardy, supra note 264, at 239 ("The 'absolute' amount of transaction costs, however,
does not provide a complete picture. We really care about 'high' or 'low' costs relative to the value
of the contract undertaken. That is, the important figure is the ratio of the transaction costs to the value
of the rights being sought."). In the context I am discussing, I would amend Professor Hardy's analy-
sis only slightly, to suggest that the relevant question for our purposes is the ratio of the transaction
costs to the potential value added by the licensing transaction.
356. See, e.g., Ayres & Talley, Solomonic Bargaining, supra note 331, at 1032-33, 1029-30
(asserting that "liability rules possess an 'information-forcing' quality" that "may induce more
contracting and more efficient contracting"); Netanel, supra note 12, at 334-35 & nn.247-48
(discussing Ayres and Talley's Solomonic Bargaining). It is interesting that the GATT Agreement on
Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPs) contemplates a compulsory license in
the situation of significant or radical improvement. Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual
Property Rights, Apr. 15, 1994, art. 3(L)(i).
1070 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
circumstances a divided property 357 entitlement such as the one patent law
offers should have similar effects.
The reverse doctrine of equivalents serves as an efficient default rule.
It reflects a recognition that real-world economic problems will prevent
efficient licensing from taking place in some instances. Where efficient
licensing does not occur, the reverse doctrine of equivalents ensures that
it is the radical improver, rather than the (relatively more modest) original
inventor, who retains a property right in the improvement. The reverse
doctrine of equivalents also serves to counteract some of the holdup prob-
lems introduced-by intellectual property rights which happen to confer
market power. It does this by allowing a radical improver to use an origi-
nal inventor's idea in certain circumstances in which the original inventor
could otherwise have held the radical improvement hostage.
The basic structure of the patent model is therefore quite simple. The
treatment of improvements is a function of the value and significance of the
improvement in relation to the original invention. Improvements which are
minor in relation to the original invention are likely to be found to infringe,
either literally or under the "insubstantial differences" test for doctrine of
equivalents infringement."' More significant improvements within the
range of the original claims still infringe the original patent, but in such
cases the improver is entitled to a patent of his own. This not only encour-
ages the development of significant improvements, but gives improvers bar-
gaining leverage in licensing negotiations in direct proportion to the relative
value of their improvements. Finally, truly radical improvements are ex-
empted from liability to the original patent owner, regardless of whether
they fall within the literal scope of the original claims, in order to encour-
age such improvements and to ensure that they reach the market.359
357. See Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 331, at 222 n.5. Ayres and Talley acknowledge that
divided ownership of property entitlements may sometimes serve the same preference-revealingfunction
as liability rules. Ayres& Talley, SolomonicBargaining,supra note 331, at 1072-82,1116-17. They
identify several types of property division, including probabilistic assignment of property rights and
division into scope of possible uses. See id. Arguably, blocking patents involve both division of
property rights into different possible uses (since the original inventor retains the old use, and the
improver owns the right to the new use) and probabilistic assignment of property rights (since the exis-
tence of blocking patents will depend on an administrative and/or judicial assessment that both inven-
tions warrant patent protection, and that the patents block). While Ayres and Talley argue that a com-
pulsory license should replace the divided property entitlement of blocking patents, see id. at 1092-94,
they appear to concede that a divided property entitlement is preferable to an undivided one for their
purposes.
358. See Hilton Davis Chem. Co. v. Wamer-JenkinsonCo., 62 F.3d 1512, 1517 (Fed. Cir. 1995)
(en bane), rev'd on other grounds, 117 S. Ct. 1040 (1997). Judge Newman suggests that making
minor improvers liable for infringement under the doctrine of equivalents will not only serve the
function of encouraging original inventors, but may also encourage better improvements, since
improvers will be forced into "leapfrogging" rather than incremental advances over the prior art. See
id. at 1532-33 (Newman, J., concurring).
359. This model is in line with the conclusions Merges and Nelson draw regarding patent law.
See Merges & Nelson, supra note 32, at 909 ("Once a court completes its assessment of the
1997] Economics of Improvement 1071
significance of the patented device, it should consider in addition the importance of the advance
represented in the accused device." (emphasis in original)).
360. See Fisher, supra note 190, at 1725-26; Merges, supra note 325, at 307-12.
361. See Gordon, supra note 268, at 868-69. While high transaction costs have been offered as
a justification for the imposition of liability rules (such as compulsory licensing in the intellectual
property context), Merges has persuasively argued that liability rules may not be justified in intellectual
property cases to the extent that private organizations will efficiently contract into liability rules
themselves. See Merges, supra note 299, at 1391-92; Merges, supra note 254, at 2662.
362. See Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 254, at 762 (arguing that property rules are superior to
liability rules when the initial possessors of a thing place greater idiosyncratic value on it than those
who take it from them and when courts have difficulty in valuing the thing). For the reasons discussed
in the last section, both of these circumstances are likely in the case of intellectual property. Of course,
deciding that a property entitlement is appropriate does not answer the question of who should receive
that property entitlement. See supra note 334.
363. C. Merges, supra note 299, at 1306-07 (preferring undivided property entitlements to
liability rules in part because of their lower administrative cost).
1072 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
A. Patent Law
While the model presented in Part V is derived from patent law
doctrine, and therefore is consistent with that doctrine, it does have
implications for one controversial aspect of patent law: the treatment of
pioneer inventions. A pioneer invention is "a wholly novel device, or one
of such novelty and importance as to mark a distinct step in the progress
of the art, as distinguished from a mere improvement or perfection of what
had gone before."365 Other courts have used various terms in an attempt
to distinguish pioneering from normal inventions. 3" However defined,
the basic idea is that pioneer inventions are somehow more fundamental
than the average patentable invention. They open up a new industry, or
at least a new avenue of approach.367 Under long-standing judicial
doctrine, pioneer patents receive a broader range of protection under the
doctrine of equivalents than other patented inventions." 8 Further, the
range of equivalents is calibrated even more finely than that, with
the effective scope of a patent depending on the significance of the
patented invention."6 While some commentators have defended the
364. See supra notes 331-32 and accompanying text (discussing the Ayres-Talley model).
365. Westinghousev. Boyden Power Brake Co., 170 U.S. 537, 561-62 (1898).
366. See, e.g., Sun Studs, Inc. v. ATA Equip. Leasing, Inc., 872 F.2d 978, 987 (Fed. Cir. 1989)
(using the term "broad breakthrough'); Universal Gym Equip., Inc. v. ERWA Exercise Equip. Ltd.,
827 F.2d 1542, 1548 (Fed. Cir. 1987) (using the term "major advance'); see also John R. Thomas,
The Question Concerning PatentLaw and PioneerInventions, 10 HIGH TECH. L.J. 35, 48 (1995)
(collecting cases describing pioneer patents in various ways).
367. It is important to distinguish pioneer inventions, as that term is used in patent law, from the
"original inventions" at issue in this Article. My model assumes a "first" invention and subsequent
improvements on that invention purely for the sake of simplicity. In practice, the "original' invention
in the model is likely itself to be an improvement on what came before it, and it may or may not be
a pioneering invention.
368. See Graver Tank & Mfg. Co. v. Linde Air Prods. Co., 339 U.S. 605, 608 (1950).
369. Thus, inventions that are important but not pioneering are entitled to fairly broad scope,
though less than pioneering patents. See Hughes Aircraft Co. v. United States, 717 F.2d 1351, 1354
1997] Economics of Improvement 1073
doctrine3 " and even suggested ways to extend it,37 others have
attacked some of its implications. 3" The Federal Circuit cast doubt on
the status of the doctrine in its 1995 en bane decision in Hilton Davis,
which reformulated the doctrine of equivalents in a way that did not
include the pioneer status of the invention."
The pioneer invention doctrine is entirely consistent with the model of
improvements derived in Part V. That model identifies the relative impor-
tance of the original invention and the improvement as the critical factor
in determining how the improvement will be treated once it is determined
to be infringing?7" This approach implicitly accounts for pioneering
inventions in one respect: the significance of the original invention will
help determine how important an improvement must be to qualify as
"significant" or "radical." An improvement worth $500 may be radical if
it is made to an original invention worth only $100, but not if made to
an original invention worth $2000. The fundamental insight of the
pioneer invention doctrine is the same as that of the improvements
model-efficiency is best served by some sort of calibration, however
rough, between the importance of the invention and the scope of the patent.
B. Copyright Law
Copyright law would need to change in two ways to accommodate the
model. First, the current copyright rules regarding the ownership of
derivative works are inconsistent with the model's treatment of significant
improvements. Second, as currently interpreted, copyright's fair use
doctrine does not provide effective protection for radical improvers in all
cases. In this subpart, I suggest how copyright law could be modified to
(Fed. Cir. 1983). Inventions that are narrow advances within a highly developed art receive a very
limited range of equivalents. See Thomas & Betts Corp. v. Litton Sys., Inc., 720 F.2d 1572, 1580
(Fed. Cir. 1983).
370. See, e.g., Esther Steinhauser, Note, Using the Doctrine of Equivalents to Provide Broad
ProtectionforPioneerPatents:Limited ProtectionforImprovementPatents, 12 PACE L. REV. 491,494
(1992) (advocating a "return to the original raison d'etre for the doctrine of equivalents by providing
broad protection for pioneer patents").
371. See, e.g., A. Samuel Oddi, Beyond Obviousness: Invention Protection in the Twenty-First
Century, 38 AM. U. L. REv. 1097, 1128-37 (1989) (proposing a new "revolutionary patent" for pio-
neer inventions that would have broader scope and extended duration); Harold C. Wegner, Equitable
Equivalents: Weighing the Equities to Determine Patent Inftingement in Biotechnology and Other
Emerging Technologies, 18 RUTGERS COMP. & TECH. L.J. 1, 46 (1992) (recommending that pioneer
status be relevant in deciding whether to apply the doctrine of equivalents at all).
372. See, e.g., Thomas, supra note 366, at 95 (suggesting that pioneer status should depend on
the social implications of a new invention, rather than merely its technological significance).
373. Hilton Davis Chem. Co. v. Wamer-JenkinsonCo., 62 F.3d 1512, 1519-20 (Fed. Cir. 1995)
(en banc) (listing other relevant factors, including "known interchangeability of the accused and claimed
elements," copying, "designing around," and independent development), rev'd on other grounds, 117
S. Ct. 1040 (1997).
374. By contrast, the pioneer invention doctrine works towards the same goal as the model in a
different way, by basing the infringement determination itself in part on the significance of the patent.
1074 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
fit the improvements model, and offer some examples of how such modifi-
cations would affect actual copyright cases.
375. See supra notes 152-62 and accompanying text (discussing copyright's treatment of derivative
works).
376. 17 U.S.C. § 106(2) (1994).
377. Section 103(a) provides that "Ithe subject matter of copyright as specified by section 102
includes compilations and derivative works, but protection for a work employing preexisting material
in which copyright subsists does not extend to any part of the work in which such material has been
used unlawfully." 17 U.S.C. § 103(a) (1994). Based on the languageof this section, it is possible for
infringing improvers to copyright their derivative works so long as the infringing material is separable
from the original expression. Thus, an infringing song on a CD of otherwise original songs will pre-
sumably not bar copyright in the original songs. But when the original and derivative contributions
are intertwined, as is the case in many derivative works (such as movies based on books, translations,
and computer programs), the improver loses any claim to his original contributions to the derivative
work.
378. Goldstein has taken a similar position. He writes:
The [derivative works] rule is, however, hard to justify when applied to derivative works
such as the motion picture in Sheldon v. MGM in which the underlying work represents
only a small part of the value of the derivative work but, because it underlies the whole,
will defeat copyright protection for the entire derivative work.
Goldstein, supra note 37, at 244; see also Gordon, supra note 268, at 865-66 (criticizing the broad
control copyright owners have over derivative works); Gordon, supranote 162, at 10 19-20 (advocating
a patent-like model of improvements for copyright); Nadan, supra note 146, at 1660-72 (offering an
alternative proposal to recognize component works as noninfringing and separately copyrightable).
379. Courts have required that substantial original material be contributed by an improver in order
to make the derivative work separately copyrightablerand therefore eligible for the proposed blocking
copyrights rule. See, e.g., Gracen v. Bradford Exch., 698 F.2d 300, 305 (7th Cir. 1983); Durham
Indus., Inc. v. Tomy Corp., 630 F.2d 905, 910 (2d Cir. 1980); L. Batlin & Son, Inc. v. Snyder, 536
F.2d 486, 489-92 (2d Cir. 1976); cf. Landes & Posner, supra note 255, at 356 (justifying this require-
ment on the grounds that it would otherwise be difficult to distinguish original from derivative works).
But see Goldstein, supra note 37, at 243 (criticizing the heightened originality standard for derivative
work copyrights).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1075
380. See Netanel, supra note 12, at 318 n. 155 (suggesting that "by making unauthorized derivative
works an infringement and subjecting infringing derivative authors to property rule damages and
injunction, the Copyright Act so substantially impairs such derivative authors' incentive to create such
new works that depriving them of their own copyright, while probably overkill, has little additional
incentive-impairing effect").
381. See Reichman, supra note 204, at 815 (suggesting that broad derivative rights protection
allows original developers of computer programs to capture functional attributes of those programs).
382. See supra notes 152-56 and accompanying text.
383. See Harper Bros. v. Klaw, 232 F. 609, 610 (S.D.N.Y. 1916) (finding that a dramatic work
produced by a licensee based on a novel "follows the novel very closely, and it would (I think) be quite
impossible to make another play that really told the story of Ben Hur without presenting substantially
the same sequence of ideas as is presented by the copyrighted version"); cf. Cohen, supra note 44
(distinguishing similarity probative of copying and similarity constituting unlawful appropriation). Of
course, if it truly is impossible to make another movie version of the book without using material from
the first adaptation, the doctrine of merger might come into play to justify the use by the book owner
of expression from the movie. See Morrissey v. Procter & Gamble Co., 379 F.2d 675, 678-79 (Ist
Cir. 1967) (maintaining that the merger doctrine prevents copyright protection when granting a copy-
right would exhaust all future use of the substance of the forms). Because of the merger doctrine, it
should be difficult for opportunistic "improvers" to interfere with a company's existing plans to create
derivative works (for example, by being first to market a line of stuffed animals based on a new Disney
film).
384. 232 F. 609 (S.D.N.Y. 1916). Because there is no blocking copyrights rule in current law,
this case is not a perfect example. The dual injunctions in the case were the function of a prior license
agreement between the parties. See id. at 610.
1076 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
the copyright in the 1899 novel Ben Hur. Wallace had licensed to Harper
Brothers the rights to produce a dramatic version of the novel for the
purposes of stage production.3" After the development of motion
pictures, both sides to the license claimed that they owned the exclusive
rights to produce a screenplay version of Ben Hur. The court found that
Harper had not been granted the right to produce a screenplay, but that
Wallace could not do so without infringing on the rights that had been
licensed to Harper.386 Noting that "it does not always follow that,
because one owns a certain thing, he may use it to the detriment of
another," the court enjoined both parties from producing a screenplay
without the agreement of the other.3" This dual injunction-and the
obvious incentive it provides for the parties to come to terms-are the
essential features of the blocking patents regime.
A blocking copyrights rule may also relieve pressure on improvers in
a second way: by reducing the incentives for opportunistic copyright suits
by plaintiffs claiming, for example, that a successful movie is based on
their book or screenplay. Under current law, plaintiffs may be enticed to
sue by the knowledge that if they are successful in asserting that the movie
is a derivative work, they will effectively own the movie. Examples of
suits in this category include Litchfield v. Spielberg,85 where the plain-
tiffs claimed that the movie E.T. was based on her screenplay Lokey from
Maldomar; Sheldon v. Metro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp.,389 where the
plaintiffs successfully alleged that the movie Letty Lynton was based upon
their play; and Abend v. MCA,390 where the plaintiffs sought to terminate
defendant's right to distribute the movie Rear Window, which was based
on a license from their book.
Some suits of this sort undoubtedly have merit-indeed, some have
been successful-but others are brought primarily in the hope that the
plaintiff will capture the value contributed by the defendants, even though
the value of the improvement vastly exceeds the value contributed by the
original work. 39 1 A blocking copyrights rule will not eliminate such
suits, whether baseless or not-plaintiffs may still hope to get money out
of a defendant through the threat of an injunction, or by an apportionment
of the profits that the court decides is attributable to the original work.3'
385. Id.
386. Id.
387. Id. at 613.
388. 736 F.2d 1352 (9th Cir. 1984).
389. 309 U.S. 390 (1940).
390. 863 F.2d 1465 (9th Cir. 1988), aff'd sub nom. Stewart v. Abend, 495 U.S. 207 (1990).
391. By citing these cases as examples, I do not intend to suggest :hat any of these plaintiffs acted
in bad faith, nor to pass on the merits of their claims. I merely identify them as representative of the
sort of lawsuit that is likely under the current rule.
392. For example, in Sheldon, the plaintiffs were entitled to enjoin the defendants from marketing
their film, even though the court found that 80% of the value of the film was contributed by the defen-
1997] Economics of Improvement 1077
But it should reduce the incentive to bring such suits; plaintiffs cannot hope
to capture the value of the defendant's work directly, because the defendant
would own the copyright in her contributions.
dants themselves. Sheldon, 309 U.S. at 408-09 (upholding apportionment of profits); Sheldon v.
Metro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp., 81 F.2d 49, 56 (2d Cir. 1936). But see Abend, 863 F.2d at 1479
(refusing to enjoin distribution of Rear Window despite finding a valid copyright termination);
Goldstein, supra note 37, at 238 (criticizing the injunction granted to the plaintiffs in Sheldon).
393. See supra notes 163-96 and accompanying text.
394. Indeed, fair use itself is sometimes justified merely as a mechanism for implying agreement
where the parties would have agreed but for transaction costs. See Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v.
Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 563 (1985); Gordon, supra note 173, at 1629-30 & n.162. The implied
agreement theory cannot explain fair use doctrine, however. It is hard to imagine a plaintiff bringing
a lawsuit (much less going all the way to the Supreme Court) over a use small enough that she would
have been willing to license it but for transaction costs. The absurd implication of this theory is that
in any case important enough to be litigated, fair use should never apply! See 3 NIMMER & NIMMER,
supra note 9, § 13.05, at 13:153 (asserting that the theory of implied consent is "fictional"); Thau,
supra note 192, at 195-96 ("[W]here the costs of copyright enforcement exceed the plaintiff's potential
gain from bringing suit, there is no need for a special doctrine in copyright law to say that the
defendant's use is allowed.").
395. Some commentators fear that the transformative use doctrine will end up restricting fair use.
See, e.g., Nicole B. Casarez, Deconstructing the Fair Use Doctrine: The Cost of Personal and
Workplace Copying After American Geophysical Union v. Texaco, Inc., 6 FoRDHAM INTELL. PROP.
MEDIA & ENT. L.J. 641, 680-81 (1996); Gordon, supra note 173, at 1601; Lape, supra note 190, at
712-13. This fear is unwarranted. See Campbell v. Acuff-RoseMusic, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 580 (1994)
(indicating that transformative use operates in addition to other factors favoring fair use, rather than
as a replacement for them); cf. Casarez, supra at 682-83 (suggesting that transformative use and public
benefit analyses can coexist). Further, in some cases other statutory provisions (such as 17 U.S.C.
§ 117 (1994)) may protect certain adaptations or copies from infringement liability. Samuelson, for
example, argues that even minor changes should be permitted in computer software where necessary
to correct errors. See Samuelson, supra note 192, at 205 & n.130.
1078 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
396. An alternative proposal that would accomplish some of the same goals as protecting radical
improvers directly is to grant fair use where the court has determined that one of the market failures
identified in Part V is likely to prevent effective licensing. See Dratler, supra note 190, at 296-97
(proposing to treat market effect under the first statutory factor, by determining whether "market
failure" will prevent the efficient licensing of productive works); Elkin-Koren, supra note 159, at 293
(arguing that fair use should apply where licensing fails, but successful licensing should not always
preclude a finding of fair use). Dratler's approach would solve the problem of licensing failure, at least
if courts can be counted on to identify and respond to such failures accurately. It would not solve the
market power holdup problem, however.
Still others suggest that the fair use inquiry should be used to promote licensing by requiring fair
use claimants to offer a reasonable royalty to the copyright owner before using the work. See, e.g.,
Melanie A. Clemons, Author v. Parodist:Striking a Compromise, 46 OHio ST. L.J. 3, 17-19 (1985);
Landy, supra note 36, at 251; Winslow, supra note 268, at 805-06; cf. Merges, supra note 325, at 309-
10 (suggesting that a copyright owner's failure to accept an offered royalty should weigh in favor of
finding fair use). Introducing such evidence is intended to promote licensing and alleviate the perceived
unfairness of the "all-or-nothing" fair use inquiry. However, such a scheme would introduce a host
of problematic issues into the legal process: What happens when the author cannot be found? When
secrecy is an issue? How much money is "reasonable"? Further, given that many refusals to license
in the parody context are noneconomic, it is not clear that such an offer would actually lead to much
additional licensing.
397. See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (1994).
398. See supra notes 173-80 and accompanying text.
399. This is in accord with the rule in Germany, where under the doctrine of "free use" a use may
be assumed to be free if "the individuality of the used work is thrust into the background and pales
beside the individuality of the newly created work." See Jan-Hendrik Brinink, Computer Software
Users' Rights in Germany and in the United States: A Comparison 8-9 & n.21 (1996) (unpublished
manuscript, on file with the Texas Law Review) (citing Helmut Haberstumpf, Der urheberrechtliche
Schutz von Computerprogrammen,in RECHTSSCHUTZUNDVERWERTUNGVON COMPUTEtPROGRAMMEN
139-46 (2. Auflage 1993)).
1997] Economics of Improvement 1079
400. See Winslow, supra note 268, at 811-12 (arguing that trivial changes should not trigger a fair
use defense).
401. See American Geophysical Union v. Texaco Inc., 60 F.3d 913, 932-36 (2d Cir. 1994)
(Jacobs, J., dissenting) (arguing that photocopying an article for use in scientific research is
transformative).
402. Whether there ws market harm in the American Geophysical Union case is another matter
entirely. See id. at 937 (Jacobs, J., dissenting) (pointing out that the majority's theory of market harm
is circular because any harm is predicated on a finding of no fair use).
403. 49 F.3d 807 (1st Cir. 1995) ("Borland V'), aff'd by an equally divided court, 116 S. Ct. 804
(1996). The litigation between Lotus and Borland arrived before the First Circuit as the culmination
of extended litigation. No fewer than four reported opinions dealt with various aspects of the case in
the district court. See Lotus Dev. Corp. v. Borland Int'l, Inc., 788 F. Supp. 78 (D. Mass. 1992)
("Borland 1"); Lotus Dev. Corp. v. Borland Int'l, Inc., 799 F. Supp. 203 (D. Mass. 1992) ("Borland
1"); Lotus Dev. Corp. v. Borland Int'l, Inc., 831 F. Supp. 202 (D. Mass. 1993) ("Borland 1IP');
Lotus Dev. Corp. v. Borland Int'l, Inc., 831 F. Supp. 223 (D. Mass. 1993) ("Borland IV').
404. For varying accounts of the facts of the case, see Borland V, 49 F.3d at 809-12; id. at 821
(Boudin, J., concurring); and Borland IV, 831 F. Supp. at 226-29.
405. BorlandIlI, 831 F. Supp. at 217-21.
406. BorlandIV, 831 F. Supp. at 231-33.
407. 740 F. Supp. 37 (D. Mass. 1990).
1080 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
cases, Judge Keeton reasoned that the menu command hierarchy was
copyrightable since it was detailed enough to include original expression,
and was not completely dictated by functional considerations." 5 On
appeal, the First Circuit reversed. It held that Lotus's menu command
hierarchy was entirely uncopyrightable as a "method of operation" of the
program itself.'
Neither approach is particularly satisfactory.41 Judge Keeton's
approach gives Lotus the power not only to control inherently functional
aspects of its program under copyright, but also to lock up the industry
with an inefficient program. Because the Lotus program represented an
industry standard at the time Borland wrote its competing program (though
not by the time of the First Circuit's decision), Borland would have been
at a significant competitive disadvantage if it could not copy enough of
Lotus's program to allow users to continue to use their stored files. At the
same time, the First Circuit's reasoning is problematic. Nof only is it in
tension with decisions from other courts construing the "method of
operation" exception narrowly (or ignoring it altogether),411 but it treats
Borland and Paperback Software identically, even though one has invested
a great deal in advancing the art of spreadsheet programming and the other
has not.412 Judge Boudin's concurrence expressed his dissatisfaction with
the majority's rationale, but failed to articulate a coherent alternative
ground for decision.4 3
This case seems a good candidate for applying a radical improver
doctrine in copyright. While it is possible to argue that Lotus's menu
command hierarchy should not be copyrightable, there are problems
408. Id. at 68; Borland I, 799 F. Supp. at 217-19; BorlandIf, 831 F. Supp. at 214-15.
409. Borland V, 49 F.3d at 815.
410. See David R. Owen, Note, Interfaces and Interoperabilityin Lotus v. Borland: A Market-
OrientedApproach to the FairUse Doctrine, 64 FoRDHAM L. REv. 2381,2403-10 (1996) (criticizing
both opinions).
411. See, e.g., Engineering Dynamics, Inc. v. Structural Software, Inc., 26 F.3d 1335, 1348 (5th
Cir. 1994); Autoskill, Inc. v. National Educ. Support Sys., Inc., 994 F.2d 1476, 1495 n.23 (10th Cir.
1993); Brown Bag Software v. Symantec Corp., 960 F.2d 1465, 1477 (9th Cir. 1992).
412. See Cohen, supra note 309, at 1148-52; Lemley, supra note 224, at 31-32 (both identifying
this problem).
413. Borland V, 49 F.3d at 821-22 (Boudin, J., concurring); see also Lunney, supra note 37, at
2418 (characterizing the Lotus case as a choice between underprotecting and overprotecting Lotus's
spreadsheet).
414. See Dennis S. Karjala & Peter S. Menell, Brief Amicus Curiae: Applying Fundamental
CopyrightPrinciplesto Lotus Development Corp. v. Borland International, Inc., 10 HIGH TECH. LJ.
177 (1995) (supportingthe First Circuit's rationale); Lemley, supra note 224, at 21-22 (suggesting that
the First Circuit could have reached the conclusion that it did under the rationale of Computer
Associates Internationalv. Altai, Inc., 982 F.2d 693 (2d Cir. 1992)); Pamela Samuelson et al., Brief
Amicus Curiae of CopyrightLaw Professorsin Support of Respondent in Lotus Development Corp. v.
Borland International, Inc., 3 J. INTELt. PRoP. L. 103 (1996) (offering several alternative rationales
for a decision in Borland's favor).
19971 Economics of Improvement 1081
with that argument. What does seem clear is that Borland has taken only
a portion of the Lotus program, and at least part of that taking is critical
to Borland's ability to bring its own radically improved spreadsheet
program to market. As with the series of reverse engineering cases in the
computer industry, 415 the market impact on the original copyright owner
is not really the result of the copying, but rather of the improvements that
the copier has made. The fact that the improver has chosen to compete
directly with the original copyright owner should not render it liable for
copying where the improvements are sufficiently radical that the improver's
product is for all intents and purposes a new one. This is particularly true
where, as in Lotus, enforcing the copyright would permit the copyright
owner to engage in holdup tactics.416
The same rationale may also explain the application of fair use in the
context of parody, biography, literary criticism, and even certain fictional
works in the same genre. Like the Borlandcase or the reverse engineering
cases, these types of uses require the improver to start with some part of
the original program,417 but in many cases the improved product is suffi-
ciently different from the original that it stands or falls on its own merits
rather than the merits of the work it copied. As an example, consider Tom
Stoppard's play Rosencrantz and Guildenstern Are Dead.415 The entire
play focuses on two minor characters from Shakespeare's Hamlet, telling
their story (and in the process, telling portions of Hamlet from a different
perspective). Hamlet is of course in the public domain, at least for the
time being.419 But if it were not, or if the play were instead based on
Margaret Mitchell's Gone with the Wind,' one can imagine the author
of the underlying work wishing to capture the value of Stoppard's work as
well, on the theory that it is after all derivative of his masterpiece. Such
a copyright claim should fail, not because there is no copying (there is),
415. See, e.g., Batemanv. Mnemonics, Inc., 79 F.3d 1532, 1539 (11th Cir. 1996); Sega Enters.,
Ltd. v. Accolade, Inc., 977 F.2d 1510, 1522-23 (9th Cir. 1992); Atari Games Corp. v. Nintendo of
Am. Inc., 975 F.2d 832, 843 (Fed. Cir. 1992).
416. See Fisher, supra note 190, at 1728 (suggesting that courts should be more willing to find
fair use where the alternative is anticompetitive control of the market).
417. For example, biographers may need to quote from the papers of their subjects in order to
prove a point in their book. See Leval, supra note 11, at 1113-14 (discussing New Era Publications
International,ApS v. Henry Holt & Co., 873 F.2d 576 (2d Cir. 1989)).
418. STOPPARD, supra note 228.
419. Recent efforts to "resurrect" copyright in public domain works, see 17 U.S.C. § 104A
(1994), combined with the ever-lengthening term of copyright protection, see S. 483, 104th Cong.
(1996), and the growth of non-copyright means of protecting literary works, see ProCD, Inc. v.
Zeidenberg, 86 F.3d 1447, 1454 (7th Cir. 1996) (allowing parties to protect uncopyrightable works
by contract); H.R. 3531, 104th Cong. (1996) (proposing sui generis protection for databases, and
defining databases to include any collection of information), suggest that we cannot guarantee that it
will stay there.
420. MARGARET MITCHELL, GONE WITH THE WIND (1936).
1082 Texas Law Review [Vol. 75:989
but because the principal value of Stoppard's play lies not in what he has
taken, but in what he has added. A similar argument might be made
regarding Woods v. Universal City Studios, Inc., where the owner of a
copyrighted chair shown in a film gave the copyright owner the power to
obtain an injunction against the showing of the film.42
The radical improver doctrine should also justify fair use protection
of independent works that merely interoperate with a copyrighted
work,4' though it seems likely that the fair use doctrine as currently
interpreted would already protect such works. 4' In many of the software
and video game compatibility cases, for example, the plaintiff seeks to
prevent the defendant from copying the small portion of its game cartridge
object code which serves as a "key," allowing the game cartridge to
operate on the plaintiff's game system.' Where all that is copied in the
final product is the "key" code, the defendant's final product seems likely
to qualify as a "radical improvement. " ' The value of the defendant's
independently created computer game comes from their own software, not
from the functional key code that they copied from the plaintiffs.'
Finally, one might also argue that intermediate copying ought to
be excused to the extent that it is a necessary step towards the creation
of an improvement which will itself be relieved from liability under the
doctrine I have proposed. The creation of intermediate or laboratory
copies is unquestionably infringement under section 106.427 However,
recent courts have been relatively lenient towards such intermediate
copying under the fair use doctrine, reasoning that a defendant should not
be foreclosed from undertaking lawful analysis or competition by the fact
that a copy will necessarily be made in the course of preparations for that
lawful activity.' It should be relatively straightforward to apply the
421. Woods v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 920 F. Supp. 62, 65 (S.D.N.Y. 1996).
422. See Nadan, supra note 146, at 1653.
423. See supra note 147 and accompanying text.
424. See, e.g., Sega Enters. Ltd. v. Accolade, Inc., 977 F.2d 1510 (9th Cir. 1992); Atari Games
Corp. v. Nintendo of Am. Inc., 975 F.2d 832 (Fed. Cir. 1992).
425, Intermediate copying to obtain the key code is a different issue. It was this issue that was
actually treated by the courts in Sega and Atari. See Cohen, supra note 309, at 1091.
426. While copying the key code does add value to the defendant's program, the value comes not
from the plaintiff's copyrighted work, but from compatibility with the plaintiff's game system, which
the defendanthas not copied. See DSC Communications Corp. v. DGI Techs., Inc., 81 F.3d 597, 600
(5th Cir. 1996) (noting that the plaintiff's attempt to block defendant from copying operating systems
to test its processor compatibility could constitute a misuse of copyrighted software to stifle competition
with plaintiff's unpatented processors).
427. See Sega, 977 F.2d at 1519.
428. See, e.g., id. at 1527-28; Vault Corp. v. Quaid Software Ltd., 847 F.2d 255, 261 (5th Cir.
1988); Batemanv. Mnemonics, Inc., 79 F.3d 1532, 1547 (11th Cir. 1995); see also Cohen, supra note
309, at 1134 (approving of the Sega decision and opining that "where copying is necessary to gain
access to and understanding of the ideas and principles embodied in a work, copying solely to gain
understanding should be deemed fair use").
1997] Economics of Improvement 1083
VII. Conclusion
Intellectual property law represents a "delicate balance" between the
rights of intellectual property owners and the rights of users, among them
the next generation of owners.43 That balance does not reflect merely
a legislative compromise between interest groups. 2 Rather, it can be
429. See supra notes 96-106 and accompanying text (noting the small number of cases in which
the reverse doctrine of equivalents has been applied).
430. See 1 GOLDSTEIN, supra note 120, § 1.6, at 1:18.
431. See Fogerty v. Fantasy, Inc., 510 U.S. 517, 526-27 (1994); Stewart v. Abend, 495 U.S. 207,
228 (1990).
432. See, e.g., Julie E. Cohen, A Right to Read Anonymously: A Closer Look at "Copyright
Management in Cyberspace, 28 CONN. L. REv. 981, 994-1002 (1996) (discussing the inadequacies
of the private ordering model in intellectual property). Indeed, interest group theory suggests a rather
1084 Texas Law Review
justified in economic terms by the need to ensure not only the creation of
entirely new works of intellectual property, but also the creation of
improvements to existing works. Patent law has a number of doctrines
which balance the rights of original inventors with those of improvers,
including the blocking patents rule and the reverse doctrine of equivalents.
Surprisingly, copyright has no such doctrines, relying instead on a rule that
gives original creators property rights over improvements made by others
in most circumstances.
The copyright rule cannot be explained on efficiency grounds, for the
patent approach is more efficient than the copyright approach. This is true
largely because copyright law assumes that strong, unified property rights
will lead to efficient licensing, while patent doctrine .accommodates the
imperfections that exist in the market for licensing improvers. Nor can the
copyright rule be explained by other substantive differences between the
two laws. I recommend some changes to copyright law which are fairly
easily accomplished, and which would bring copyright law in line with a
more realistic model of intellectual property licensing.
more robust imbalance, since intellectual property owners have far more political power and organizing
ability than users. See generally Jessica Litman, CopyrightLegislation and Technological Change, 68
OR. L. REv. 275 (1989).