Curs 1
Curs 1
Curs 1
Order
relations. Functional relations
Sets
Sets
In order to avoid paradoxes, we shall consider that all the elements of the
sets which are considered belong to a certain universal or total set T .
Also, we consider the empty set, which may be defined as
∅ := {x ∈ T |x 6= x} .
Sets
In order to avoid paradoxes, we shall consider that all the elements of the
sets which are considered belong to a certain universal or total set T .
Also, we consider the empty set, which may be defined as
∅ := {x ∈ T |x 6= x} .
Remark
Using the property of the logical operation of implication, according to
which ”False implies anything”, any statement made about the
elements of the empty set is automatically true!
Sets
In order to avoid paradoxes, we shall consider that all the elements of the
sets which are considered belong to a certain universal or total set T .
Also, we consider the empty set, which may be defined as
∅ := {x ∈ T |x 6= x} .
Remark
Using the property of the logical operation of implication, according to
which ”False implies anything”, any statement made about the
elements of the empty set is automatically true!
Definition
Let A and B be two sets. We call the two sets equal, and write A = B,
if for any element x ∈ T of the total set the following equivalence holds
x ∈ A ⇐⇒ x ∈ B .
Definition
Let A and B be two sets. We call the two sets equal, and write A = B,
if for any element x ∈ T of the total set the following equivalence holds
x ∈ A ⇐⇒ x ∈ B .
Proposition
For any sets A, B, and C the following properties hold:
A=A (reflexivity)
A = B ∧ B = C =⇒ A = C (transitivity)
A = B =⇒ B = A (simmetry)
Definition
Let A and B be two sets. We call the two sets equal, and write A = B,
if for any element x ∈ T of the total set the following equivalence holds
x ∈ A ⇐⇒ x ∈ B .
Proposition
For any sets A, B, and C the following properties hold:
A=A (reflexivity)
A = B ∧ B = C =⇒ A = C (transitivity)
A = B =⇒ B = A (simmetry)
Proposition
For any sets A, B, and C the following properties hold:
A⊆A (reflexivity)
A ⊆ B ∧ B ⊆ C =⇒ A ⊆ C (transitivity)
A ⊆ B ∧ B ⊆ A =⇒ A = B (antisimmetry)
Proposition
For any sets A, B, and C the following properties hold:
A⊆A (reflexivity)
A ⊆ B ∧ B ⊆ C =⇒ A ⊆ C (transitivity)
A ⊆ B ∧ B ⊆ A =⇒ A = B (antisimmetry)
CT : Set(T ) −→ Set(T ) ,
CT (A) = {x ∈ T | x 6∈ A} .
CT : Set(T ) −→ Set(T ) ,
CT (A) = {x ∈ T | x 6∈ A} .
Proposition
Let A and B be two arbitrary sets. Then A ⊆ B if and only if
CT (B) ⊆ CT (A)(or B ⊆ A).
Proposition
Let A and B be two arbitrary sets. Then A ⊆ B if and only if
CT (B) ⊆ CT (A)(or B ⊆ A).
by which to any two sets A and B one asocciates a new set A ∩ B, called
their intersection, formed by the common elements of the two sets:
A ∩ B = {x ∈ T |(x ∈ A) ∧ (x ∈ B)} .
Remark
The operation of intersection can be extended from two sets to
arbitrary families of sets. If {Ai }i∈I is a family of stes included in the
total set T , where I is some index set, the intersection of the family is
given by \
Ai = {x ∈ T |(∀i ∈ I )x ∈ Ai } .
i∈I
Remark
The operation of intersection can be extended from two sets to
arbitrary families of sets. If {Ai }i∈I is a family of stes included in the
total set T , where I is some index set, the intersection of the family is
given by \
Ai = {x ∈ T |(∀i ∈ I )x ∈ Ai } .
i∈I
A ∪ B = {x ∈ T |(x ∈ A) ∨ (x ∈ B)} .
Remark
The operation of union can also be extended to arbitrary families of
sets. If {Ai }i∈I is a family of sets included in the total set T , where I is
an index set, the union of the family is given by
[
Ai = {x ∈ T |(∃i ∈ I )x ∈ Ai } .
i∈I
Remark
The operation of union can also be extended to arbitrary families of
sets. If {Ai }i∈I is a family of sets included in the total set T , where I is
an index set, the union of the family is given by
[
Ai = {x ∈ T |(∃i ∈ I )x ∈ Ai } .
i∈I
−absorbtion: A ∩ (A ∪ B) = A ,
A ∪ (A ∩ B) = A ;
−distributivity: A ∩ (B ∪ C ) = (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ C ) ,
A ∪ (B ∩ C ) = (A ∪ B) ∩ (A ∪ C ) ;
−modularity: A ⊆ C =⇒ (A ∪ B) ∩ C = A ∪ (B ∩ C ) ;
−the laws of the complementary: A ∩ A = ∅ ,
A∪A=T ;
−de Morgan’s laws: (A ∩ B) = A ∪ B ,
(A ∪ B) = A ∩ B .
T S S T
Ai = Ai , Ai = Ai .
i∈I i∈I i∈I i∈I
by which to any two sets A and B one associates a new set, denoted
A \ B(or A − B), called their difference, formed by the elements which
belong to the first set, A, but not also to the second set, B:
A \ B = {x ∈ T |(x ∈ A) ∨ (x 6∈ B)} .
Remark
A \ B = A ∩ CT (B), (∀)A, B ∈ Set(T ).
by which to any two sets A and B one associates a new set, denoted
A \ B(or A − B), called their difference, formed by the elements which
belong to the first set, A, but not also to the second set, B:
A \ B = {x ∈ T |(x ∈ A) ∨ (x 6∈ B)} .
Remark
A \ B = A ∩ CT (B), (∀)A, B ∈ Set(T ).
A \ A = ∅;
(A \ B) \ C = A \ (B ∪ C ) = (A \ C ) \ B ;
A \ (B \ C ) = (A \ B) ∪ (A ∩ C ) ;
A \ (B ∩ C ) = (A \ B) ∪ (A \ C ) ;
A \ (B ∪ C ) = (A \ B) ∩ (A \ C ) ;
(A ∩ B) \ C = (A \ C ) ∩ (B \ C ) ;
(A ∪ B) \ C = (A \ C ) ∪ (B \ C ) .
Remark
Diference is not a commutative operation. Moreover, for any two sets
A and B we have
(A \ B) ∩ (B \ A) = ∅ .
A \ A = ∅;
(A \ B) \ C = A \ (B ∪ C ) = (A \ C ) \ B ;
A \ (B \ C ) = (A \ B) ∪ (A ∩ C ) ;
A \ (B ∩ C ) = (A \ B) ∪ (A \ C ) ;
A \ (B ∪ C ) = (A \ B) ∩ (A \ C ) ;
(A ∩ B) \ C = (A \ C ) ∩ (B \ C ) ;
(A ∪ B) \ C = (A \ C ) ∪ (B \ C ) .
Remark
Diference is not a commutative operation. Moreover, for any two sets
A and B we have
(A \ B) ∩ (B \ A) = ∅ .
by which to any two sets A and B one associates a new set, denoted
A 4 B, called the symmetrice difference of the sets A and B, formed of
those elements which belong to exactly one of the two sets:
A 4 B := {x ∈ T |(x ∈ A ∧ x 6∈ B) ∨ (x 6∈ A ∧ x ∈ B)} .
Remark
From the definition follows immediately that
A 4 B = (A \ B) ∪ (B \ A) = (A ∪ B) \ (A ∩ B) .
by which to any two sets A and B one associates a new set, denoted
A 4 B, called the symmetrice difference of the sets A and B, formed of
those elements which belong to exactly one of the two sets:
A 4 B := {x ∈ T |(x ∈ A ∧ x 6∈ B) ∨ (x 6∈ A ∧ x ∈ B)} .
Remark
From the definition follows immediately that
A 4 B = (A \ B) ∪ (B \ A) = (A ∪ B) \ (A ∩ B) .
Definition
Let n ∈ N∗ be a nonzero natural number such that n ≥ 2, and
A1 , A2 , . . . , An ∈ Set(T ) arbitrary sets. The cartesian product of the sets
A1 , A2 , . . . , An is the set
Definition
Let n ∈ N∗ be a nonzero natural number such that n ≥ 2, and
A1 , A2 , . . . , An ∈ Set(T ) arbitrary sets. The cartesian product of the sets
A1 , A2 , . . . , An is the set
Definition
Let n ∈ N∗ be a nonzero natural number and A1 , A2 , . . . , An n sets.
Definition
Let n ∈ N∗ be a nonzero natural number and A1 , A2 , . . . , An n sets. An
n−ary relation between the elements of the sets A1 , A2 , . . . , An (in this
order) is an ordered system R = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G ) formed by the n
sets and a subset G of the cartesian product A1 × A2 × . . . × An , called
the graph of the relation. The product A1 × A2 × . . . × An is called the
domain of the relation R.
Definition
Let n ∈ N∗ be a nonzero natural number and A1 , A2 , . . . , An n sets. An
n−ary relation between the elements of the sets A1 , A2 , . . . , An (in this
order) is an ordered system R = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G ) formed by the n
sets and a subset G of the cartesian product A1 × A2 × . . . × An , called
the graph of the relation. The product A1 × A2 × . . . × An is called the
domain of the relation R. If (a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ∈ G , we write
R(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) and say that a1 , a2 , . . . , an are related by the relation
R, or that a1 , a2 , . . . , an satisfy the relation R.
Definition
Let n ∈ N∗ be a nonzero natural number and A1 , A2 , . . . , An n sets. An
n−ary relation between the elements of the sets A1 , A2 , . . . , An (in this
order) is an ordered system R = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G ) formed by the n
sets and a subset G of the cartesian product A1 × A2 × . . . × An , called
the graph of the relation. The product A1 × A2 × . . . × An is called the
domain of the relation R. If (a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ∈ G , we write
R(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) and say that a1 , a2 , . . . , an are related by the relation
R, or that a1 , a2 , . . . , an satisfy the relation R. If
A1 = A2 = · · · = An = A, we call R a (homogenous) n−ary relation on
the set A.
Definition
Let n ∈ N∗ be a nonzero natural number and A1 , A2 , . . . , An n sets. An
n−ary relation between the elements of the sets A1 , A2 , . . . , An (in this
order) is an ordered system R = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G ) formed by the n
sets and a subset G of the cartesian product A1 × A2 × . . . × An , called
the graph of the relation. The product A1 × A2 × . . . × An is called the
domain of the relation R. If (a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ∈ G , we write
R(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) and say that a1 , a2 , . . . , an are related by the relation
R, or that a1 , a2 , . . . , an satisfy the relation R. If
A1 = A2 = · · · = An = A, we call R a (homogenous) n−ary relation on
the set A.
R = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , A1 × A2 × . . . × An \ G ) .
R = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , A1 × A2 × . . . × An \ G ) .
Remark
For (a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ∈ A1 × A2 × . . . × An we have
R(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ⇐⇒ R(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) .
R = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , A1 × A2 × . . . × An \ G ) .
Remark
For (a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ∈ A1 × A2 × . . . × An we have
R(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ⇐⇒ R(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) .
R1 ∩ R2 = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G1 ∩ G2 ) .
R1 ∪ R2 = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G1 ∪ G2 ) .
R1 ∩ R2 = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G1 ∩ G2 ) .
R1 ∪ R2 = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G1 ∪ G2 ) .
Remark
For (a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ∈ A1 × A2 × . . . × An we have
R1 ∩ R2 = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G1 ∩ G2 ) .
R1 ∪ R2 = (A1 , A2 , . . . , An , G1 ∪ G2 ) .
Remark
For (a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) ∈ A1 × A2 × . . . × An we have
Definition
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is called a binary relation between the
elements of the sets A and B.
Generaly, in the case of a binary relation we write aRb in stead of
R(a, b).
Definition
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is called a binary relation between the
elements of the sets A and B.
Generaly, in the case of a binary relation we write aRb in stead of
R(a, b). In case of a binary relation R = (A, B, G ), the set A is called
the domain of the relation R, denoted dom(R), respectively B is called
the codomain of the relation, denoted codom(R).
Definition
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is called a binary relation between the
elements of the sets A and B.
Generaly, in the case of a binary relation we write aRb in stead of
R(a, b). In case of a binary relation R = (A, B, G ), the set A is called
the domain of the relation R, denoted dom(R), respectively B is called
the codomain of the relation, denoted codom(R).
Definition
Let R = (A, B, G ) and S = (B, C , H) be two binary relations, with the
property that codom(R) = dom(S). The composite of the two relations
is the relation
R · S = (A, C , G · H) , where
G · H = {(a, c) ∈ A × C |(∃)b ∈ B : (a, b) ∈ G ∧ (b, c) ∈ H} .
Definition
Let R = (A, B, G ) and S = (B, C , H) be two binary relations, with the
property that codom(R) = dom(S). The composite of the two relations
is the relation
R · S = (A, C , G · H) , where
G · H = {(a, c) ∈ A × C |(∃)b ∈ B : (a, b) ∈ G ∧ (b, c) ∈ H} .
bR−1 a ⇐⇒ aRb ;
a(R · S)c ⇐⇒ (∃)b ∈ B : aRb ∧ bSc .
R ⊆ R0 ⇐⇒ R−1 ⊆ R0−1 ;
(R ∩ R0 )−1 = R−1 ∩ R0−1 ;
(R ∪ R0 )−1 = R−1 ∪ R0−1 ;
xR := {y ∈ B| xRy }
xR := {y ∈ B| xRy }
xR := {y ∈ B| xRy }
Proposition
Let R = (A, B, G ) be a binary relation, X ⊆ A and Y ⊆ B. Then
Proposition
Let R = (A, B, G ) be a binary relation, X ⊆ A and Y ⊆ B. Then
Definition
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is called a functional relation if R−1 · R ⊆ idB .
Remark
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is a functional relation if and only if for any
a ∈ A there is at most one element b ∈ B such that aRb.
Definition
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is called a functional relation if R−1 · R ⊆ idB .
Remark
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is a functional relation if and only if for any
a ∈ A there is at most one element b ∈ B such that aRb.
Remark
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is a function if and only if for any a ∈ A there
is exactly one element b ∈ B such that aRb.
Remark
A relation R = (A, B, G ) is a function if and only if for any a ∈ A there
is exactly one element b ∈ B such that aRb.
Definition
Let R = (A, B, G ) be a function and X ⊆ A. The section X R is then
the set
X R = {aR | a ∈ X }
and is called the image of the set X with respect to the function R. In
particular, AR is called the image of the function R and is denoted
Im(R).
Definition
Let R = (A, B, G ) be a function and X ⊆ A. The section X R is then
the set
X R = {aR | a ∈ X }
and is called the image of the set X with respect to the function R. In
particular, AR is called the image of the function R and is denoted
Im(R).
Definition
A function f : A −→ B is called injective if for any y ∈ B the equation
x f = y has at most one solution x ∈ A.
Definition
A function f : A −→ B is called injective if for any y ∈ B the equation
x f = y has at most one solution x ∈ A.
Definition
A function f : A −→ B is called bijective if for any y ∈ B the equation
x f = y has exactly one solution x ∈ A.
Definition
A function f : A −→ B is called injective if for any y ∈ B the equation
x f = y has at most one solution x ∈ A.
Definition
A function f : A −→ B is called bijective if for any y ∈ B the equation
x f = y has exactly one solution x ∈ A.
Proposition
A function f : A −→ B is invertible if and only if it is bijective.
Proposition
A function f : A −→ B is invertible if and only if it is bijective.
Remark
1) Since for any set A, the function idA : A −→ A is bijective, we find
that A ∼ A for any set A.
Remark
1) Since for any set A, the function idA : A −→ A is bijective, we find
that A ∼ A for any set A.
2) If A, B, and C are sets such that A ∼ B and B ∼ C , then there are
bijective functions f : A −→ B and g : B −→ C . Their composite
f · g : A −→ C is then also bijective, hence A ∼ C .
Remark
1) Since for any set A, the function idA : A −→ A is bijective, we find
that A ∼ A for any set A.
2) If A, B, and C are sets such that A ∼ B and B ∼ C , then there are
bijective functions f : A −→ B and g : B −→ C . Their composite
f · g : A −→ C is then also bijective, hence A ∼ C .
3) If A and B are sets such that A ∼ B, then there is a bijection
f : A −→ B. Its inverse f −1 : B −→ A is then aslo bijective, so that
B ∼ A.
Remark
1) Since for any set A, the function idA : A −→ A is bijective, we find
that A ∼ A for any set A.
2) If A, B, and C are sets such that A ∼ B and B ∼ C , then there are
bijective functions f : A −→ B and g : B −→ C . Their composite
f · g : A −→ C is then also bijective, hence A ∼ C .
3) If A and B are sets such that A ∼ B, then there is a bijection
f : A −→ B. Its inverse f −1 : B −→ A is then aslo bijective, so that
B ∼ A.
Remark
A ∼ B ⇐⇒ |A| = |B| .
Remark
A ∼ B ⇐⇒ |A| = |B| .
Remark
1) |A| = |B| =⇒ |A| ≤ |B|.
Remark
1) |A| = |B| =⇒ |A| ≤ |B|.
2) |A| ≤ |A|, for any set A.
Remark
1) |A| = |B| =⇒ |A| ≤ |B|.
2) |A| ≤ |A|, for any set A.
3) If A, B, and C are sets such that |A| ≤ |B| and |B| ≤ |C |, then there
are injective functions f : A −→ B and g : B −→ C . Their composite
f · g : A −→ C is then also injective, hence |A| ≤ |C |.
Remark
1) |A| = |B| =⇒ |A| ≤ |B|.
2) |A| ≤ |A|, for any set A.
3) If A, B, and C are sets such that |A| ≤ |B| and |B| ≤ |C |, then there
are injective functions f : A −→ B and g : B −→ C . Their composite
f · g : A −→ C is then also injective, hence |A| ≤ |C |.
Proposition
(Cantor-Bernstein’s theorem) Let A and B be two sets such that
|A| ≤ |B| and |B| ≤ |A|. Then |A| = |B|.
Proposition
(Cantor-Bernstein’s theorem) Let A and B be two sets such that
|A| ≤ |B| and |B| ≤ |A|. Then |A| = |B|.
Definition
A set is called finite if it is not infinite.
Definition
A set is called finite if it is not infinite.
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
def
- transitive ⇐⇒ R · R ⊆ R;
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
def
- transitive ⇐⇒ R · R ⊆ R;
def
- symmetric ⇐⇒ R ⊆ R−1 ;
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
def
- transitive ⇐⇒ R · R ⊆ R;
def
- symmetric ⇐⇒ R ⊆ R−1 ;
def
- antisymmetric ⇐⇒ R ∩ R−1 ⊆ idA ;
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
def
- transitive ⇐⇒ R · R ⊆ R;
def
- symmetric ⇐⇒ R ⊆ R−1 ;
def
- antisymmetric ⇐⇒ R ∩ R−1 ⊆ idA ;
def
- a preorder relation ⇐⇒ R is reflexive and transitive;
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
def
- transitive ⇐⇒ R · R ⊆ R;
def
- symmetric ⇐⇒ R ⊆ R−1 ;
def
- antisymmetric ⇐⇒ R ∩ R−1 ⊆ idA ;
def
- a preorder relation ⇐⇒ R is reflexive and transitive;
def
- an equivalence relation ⇐⇒ R is a symmetric preorder relation;
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
def
- transitive ⇐⇒ R · R ⊆ R;
def
- symmetric ⇐⇒ R ⊆ R−1 ;
def
- antisymmetric ⇐⇒ R ∩ R−1 ⊆ idA ;
def
- a preorder relation ⇐⇒ R is reflexive and transitive;
def
- an equivalence relation ⇐⇒ R is a symmetric preorder relation;
def
- an order relation ⇐⇒ R is a symmetric preorder relation.
Definition
Let R = (A, A, G ) be a homogenous binary relation on a set A. We call
the relation R
def
- reflexive ⇐⇒ idA ⊆ R;
def
- transitive ⇐⇒ R · R ⊆ R;
def
- symmetric ⇐⇒ R ⊆ R−1 ;
def
- antisymmetric ⇐⇒ R ∩ R−1 ⊆ idA ;
def
- a preorder relation ⇐⇒ R is reflexive and transitive;
def
- an equivalence relation ⇐⇒ R is a symmetric preorder relation;
def
- an order relation ⇐⇒ R is a symmetric preorder relation.
Notation
If A is a nonempty set, we denote by Eq(A) the set of equivalence
relations defined on the set A, respectively by Ord(A) the set of order
relations defined on A.
Notation
If A is a nonempty set, we denote by Eq(A) the set of equivalence
relations defined on the set A, respectively by Ord(A) the set of order
relations defined on A.
[a]ρ := {b ∈ A| aρb}
[a]ρ := {b ∈ A| aρb}
Proposition
If ρ = (A, A, G ) is an equivalence relation on the nonempty set A, then
1) a ∈ [a]ρ , (∀)a ∈ A ;
2) b ∈ [a]ρ ⇐⇒ a ∈ [b]ρ ⇐⇒ [a]ρ = [b]ρ ;
3) [a]
Sρ =6 [b]ρ =⇒ [a]ρ ∩ [b]ρ = ∅ ;
4) [a]ρ = A .
a∈A
[a]ρ := {b ∈ A| aρb}
Proposition
If ρ = (A, A, G ) is an equivalence relation on the nonempty set A, then
1) a ∈ [a]ρ , (∀)a ∈ A ;
2) b ∈ [a]ρ ⇐⇒ a ∈ [b]ρ ⇐⇒ [a]ρ = [b]ρ ;
3) [a]
Sρ =6 [b]ρ =⇒ [a]ρ ∩ [b]ρ = ∅ ;
4) [a]ρ = A .
a∈A
1) M 6= ∅, (∀)M ∈ Π ;
∩ M, (∀)L, M ∈ Π, L 6= M ;
2) LS
3) M = A.
M∈Π
1) M 6= ∅, (∀)M ∈ Π ;
∩ M, (∀)L, M ∈ Π, L 6= M ;
2) LS
3) M = A.
M∈Π
Proposition
Let A be a nonempty set, andSΠ ∈ Part(A) a partition of the set A. The
binary relation ρΠ := (A, A, M × M) is then an equivalence relation on
M∈Π
the set A.
Proposition
Let A be a nonempty set, andSΠ ∈ Part(A) a partition of the set A. The
binary relation ρΠ := (A, A, M × M) is then an equivalence relation on
M∈Π
the set A.
Proposition
Let A be a nonempty set. The applications
Proposition
Let A be a nonempty set, andSΠ ∈ Part(A) a partition of the set A. The
binary relation ρΠ := (A, A, M × M) is then an equivalence relation on
M∈Π
the set A.
Proposition
Let A be a nonempty set. The applications
is called the canonical projection of the set A onto the factor set A/ρ.
Remark
aρb ⇐⇒ [a]ρ = [b]ρ ⇐⇒ aπρ = b πρ .
is called the canonical projection of the set A onto the factor set A/ρ.
Remark
aρb ⇐⇒ [a]ρ = [b]ρ ⇐⇒ aπρ = b πρ .
Definition
The relation ρf defined in the previous proposition is called the relation
induced by ρ on A through the function f , or the preimage of the relation
ρ through f .
Definition
The relation ρf defined in the previous proposition is called the relation
induced by ρ on A through the function f , or the preimage of the relation
ρ through f .
Remark
1) (∀)a, a0 ∈ A, a ker (f )a0 ⇐⇒ af = a0f ;
Remark
1) (∀)a, a0 ∈ A, a ker (f )a0 ⇐⇒ af = a0f ;
2) ker (f ) = f · f −1 .
Remark
1) (∀)a, a0 ∈ A, a ker (f )a0 ⇐⇒ af = a0f ;
2) ker (f ) = f · f −1 .
Definition
The relation ρR defined in the previous proposition is called the
association relation with respect to R.
Definition
The relation ρR defined in the previous proposition is called the
association relation with respect to R.
Definition
Let A be a set and R = (A, A, G ) an order relation on A. The pair
(A, R) is called an ordered set.
Remark
Let A be a set and R = (A, A, G ) an order relation on A. The inverse
R−1 of the relation R is then also an order relation.
Definition
Let A be a set and R = (A, A, G ) an order relation on A. The pair
(A, R) is called an ordered set.
Remark
Let A be a set and R = (A, A, G ) an order relation on A. The inverse
R−1 of the relation R is then also an order relation.
Notation
Generally we shall denote by ≤ an order relation on a set, respectively
by ≥ the inverse ≤−1 of the relation ≤.
Definition
Let A be a set and R = (A, A, G ) an order relation on A. The pair
(A, R) is called an ordered set.
Remark
Let A be a set and R = (A, A, G ) an order relation on A. The inverse
R−1 of the relation R is then also an order relation.
Notation
Generally we shall denote by ≤ an order relation on a set, respectively
by ≥ the inverse ≤−1 of the relation ≤.
Definition
An ordered set (A, ≤) is called well ordered if any nonempty subset of A
has a least element.
Definition
An ordered set (A, ≤) is called well ordered if any nonempty subset of A
has a least element.
Remark
Any well ordered set is totally ordered.
Definition
An ordered set (A, ≤) is called well ordered if any nonempty subset of A
has a least element.
Remark
Any well ordered set is totally ordered.
Proposition
(Zorn’s lemma - ”strong variation”) Let (A, ≤) be a nonempty
inductively ordered set and a ∈ A an element of A. Then there is a
maximal element ma ∈ A such that a ≤ ma .
Proposition
(Zorn’s lemma - ”strong variation”) Let (A, ≤) be a nonempty
inductively ordered set and a ∈ A an element of A. Then there is a
maximal element ma ∈ A such that a ≤ ma .