RIEDEL PopulismDemocraticNonDemocratic 2017
RIEDEL PopulismDemocraticNonDemocratic 2017
RIEDEL PopulismDemocraticNonDemocratic 2017
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Polish Sociological Review
RAFAL RIEDEL
University of Opole
Abstract: The starting point of this paper is the acknowledgement that the DNA of populism is democratic. At the
same time, it may bring undemocratic or even counter-democratic consequences when it questions and contests
liberalism and pluralism. This paper maps the key arguments on the relations between populism and authoritari
anism, and discusses the risk of democratic backsliding as a result of authoritarian populism gaining power. This
topic is critically important and growing urgent with the rising wave of populism across the Western world. Due
to its chameleonic nature, populism (as a "thin-centered" or "empty-hearted" ideology) manifests itself in various
(re)incarnations and intertwines with nationalism, libertarianism, and also radical left-wing ideas or any other
ideology from across the wide political spectrum.
First, the author reconstructs the historicity of populism as well as the most important ways of defining it.
Second, he reflects on the major arguments about the consequences for democracy of populist politics. Finally, in
conclusion, he discusses the threat of authoritarianism that populism brings to liberal democracy and democracy
as such.
Introduction
Populism has become an important political force in Europe and the Americas. Populist
movements appear to be gaining momentum and populist politicians win elections or réf
érendums by stressing the need to return power to the people from the corrupt elites. Such
politicians propose the rejection of liberal institutions and democratic deliberation. They
share an ideological core that consists of authoritarianism in combination with a specific
form of nationalism (or nativism, an ideology that holds that non-native elements—persons,
institutional solutions, norms, or ideas—are fundamentally threatening to the homogenous
"people"1). And as they have been attracting more and more support, populism is dynam
ically and unexpectedly back at the very top of the agenda. This makes the question of
populism of critical importance both for scholarly reflection and in real politics. As it has
become a key feature of the contemporary political landscape, populism has also become
one of the most contentious concepts in the social sciences (Rupnik 2007). Studying pop
ulism can provide important insights into the range of issues challenging contemporary
1 Nativism is by definition illiberal, but not always racist; it can be based on ethnicity, religion, etc. Nativism
includes both racist and non-racist arguments, showing that the exclusion of groups can be made on cultural or
religious grounds as well as ethnicity (Wills 2015).
In the last decades, studies about populist policies and politicians mushroomed bo
quality and quantity (Laclau 1977; Hayward 1996; Mudde 2001; Rosanvallon 2006;
2008; Stavrakakis 2014; Taggart, Kaltwasser 2016). Despite a rich interdisciplinary
course, students of populism still disagree not only about how to explain it, but m
damentally, about what it is. We seem to be witnessing a conceptual cacophony.
isting literature on populism has been plagued by conceptual confusion, deficien
disagreement. Populism remains notoriously difficult to define and the word may
to refer to ideologies, movements, political tactics or experience, styles, frames, an
other things. Few terms have been defined with less precision. Few categories hav
more on intuition rather than solid scholarly conceptualizations. The utility of popul
is precisely in its embrace of a range of diverse and sometimes contradictory politica
liefs.
The most common ways of understanding populism contain its minimum components:
"the good people" that are endangered by "the evil others." Such an alignment runs across
established party lines. This definition of populism correlates with the general everyday
usage of this word whenever—usually for journalistic purposes—we refer to a person, party,
action, or decision that makes claims by appealing to ordinary (non-elite) people. In public
discourse it is often used as a pejorative epithet implying that the accused is corrupt, cynical,
opportunistic, or even undemocratic. The term lacks the necessary precision for scholarly
inquiry and does not allow the features of this flexible method of animating politics to be
grasped.
The etymology of the term goes back to Ancient Rome where the populäres were the
politicians looking for public support. The early uses of the term "populism" were to de
scribe nineteenth-century European (predominantly Russian and French) and American
phenomena. These movements were connected with a desire for a more egalitarian role for
the masses in the context of elitist politics (in Tsarist, Napoleonic, or even early Ameri
can versions). However, the more liberal democracy was established, the more populism
evolved towards more and more regressive positions.
One of the first analytical works on populism appeared in 1929 in The American Eco
nomic Review, where John D. Black published an article on "The McNary-Haugen Move
ment." He discussed the political and economic aspects of the relations between the agri
cultural sector and commerce and industry. This field of analysis correlates very well with
the populist ideology of the agrarian revolt in the USA in the 1890s and the accompanying
concept of two nations: the nation of the producers (the exploited) and the nation of the
well-to-do elites (Black 1929). This distinction gave birth to the political cleavage present
in populist politics: that is, the confrontational relation between the authentic people and
the parasitical elite.
Populism cannot be fully understood outside of the historical continuum. The current
form of populism is an outcome of a specific historical process. It emerged as a form of
authoritarian democracy, which could accommodate the sentiment for a totalitarian version
of politics with the post-war hegemony of democratic representation. Framing populism
historically helps us understand why its return to Europe actualizes this continent's past
xenophobic and anti-democratic characteristics. Modern populists are surprisingly open to
its pre-democratic foundations. At best they are ambivalent about democracy; at worst they
want to destroy it (Finchelstein 2014).
In the general understanding, populism is a set of ideas or an argumentation that is
catchy and attractive based on emotional and irrational grounds, the longing for simple so
lutions to complicated problems, and a direct connection to the will of the majority. It very
often manifests itself in a simplistic, equalizing democracy where the will of the majority
is unlimited (the "tyranny of the majority" thesis). Populists claim that the majority is—
by democratic logic—"right" and must be respected. Such idealization and romanticizing
leads to political claims that the only source of moral truth is "the people." However, such
claims ignore the fact that when populism appears—usually in rapidly modernizing soci
2 It is "thin" due to the fact that its particular ideas are of limited scope, complexity, and ambition; it is not
a complete ideology in contrast to full ideologies such as nationalism, socialism or liberalism. Michael Freeden
explains that a thin-centered ideology arbitrarily serves itself from wider ideational contexts; it flexibly removes
or replaces some concepts. It lacks internal integrity and coherence (Freeden 1998).
elites against the backdrop of popular sovereignty. Such a conceptualization has become the
dominant position in the literature. It considers society to be ultimately divided into two
homogenous and antagonistic groups: "the pure people" and "the corrupt elite" (Mudde
2004: 543) and politics is supposed to be an expression of the general will of "the pure
people." This places populism in opposition to elitism and pluralism. In populist politics
there are less spaces left for minorities and they are often presented as traitors to the real
will of the nation or even as marionettes of foreign powers. The idea of the general will of
the people resembles Jean-Jacques Rousseau's thoughts on a specific form of democracy
which has at its core a conviction or assumption about the existence of a homogeneous
demos—a mythical and equally Utopian nation. In the populist understanding, democracy
means the power of the people and only the power of the people, without any other nu
ances.
ism increases with the worsening of the economy and declines when the economy i
(Kubik 2012; Mahoney 2001).
Populism is not just anti-elitist, it is anti-pluralist—and herein lies its profoun
democratic character (Mueller 2015). Populist actors promise protection against t
curities of pluralism. The "united people" rhetoric offers some kind of harmony
est. It goes hand in hand with the overestimation, idealization, and romanticizing
own nation and is accompanied with stereotyping and stigmatizing "enemies of
tion"—other nations, international organizations, capitalists, or minorities. Populi
cians exploit persistent patterns of prejudice. The regular problems of everyday l
supposedly related to the presence of foreigners or minorities or other forms of
This results in questioning universal norms and amplifying authoritarian tendencie
cost of democratic pluralism. The authoritarian personality studies of Fromm, Ador
their followers teach us that nationalism strongly correlates with ethnocentrism,
bia, racism, anti-Semitism, militarism, and authoritarianism. This can be explained
populist assumption about the homogeneous people, the heartland. Intolerant, anti-
visions of democracy reveal the authoritarian syndrome of populism. Xenophobia a
Semitism have reappeared, resembling ghosts from the past. The nationalist-author
orientation is becoming dominant over cosmopolitan liberalism (Weiss 2003). Popul
a biting critique of the limitations of democracy; it rejects all barriers on the expre
the majoritarian will, most notably the independence of key institutions (the guar
democracy).
Populism seeks to build a political system devoid of the rule of law and therefore i
nicious phenomenon. It is itself chauvinistic and fundamentalist, and aims at dism
checks and balances (as being the work of non-representative, unelected bodies). Po
do not respect the fragile equilibrium between non-majoritarian institutions and th
of the people. If necessary they will question the constitutional order (explicitly or
itly), and challenge international treaties and obligations by various forms of mobi
or pseudo-representation (e.g., a plebiscite) (Kaltwasser 2014). Populist actors mak
itics more polarizing. By perceiving representative politics as corrupt and divorced
ordinary people, they spread the vision of an exclusivist nation (Jasiewicz 2008).
democratic authoritarianism may be to a large extent explained on the basis of th
insecurity developing as a result of the democratic rules of institutionalized confl
struggle of interest groups, and power shifts (Keane 1994; Weiss 2003). The tran
tion from non-democracy to democracy is a particularly fragile period in which t
thusiasm for democracy-building may rapidly evaporate in the face of social and ec
unrest. Populist, nationalistic, and authoritarian attitudes can be interpreted as an emo
reaction to the "shock of modernization."
Populism grows very fast on the fertile ground of political discontent. At the sam
populists, once strong, fuel such discontent (Rooduijn, van der Brug, de Lange 201
ulism is thus both the source and the consequence of political discontent. This mec
creates a vicious circle. The rise in populism may be explained by the reaction to th
ous apolitical or non-ideological politics. Technocratic, expertise-driven decision-
deliberation, and a consensual political culture—all these have been associated with
quality of democracy. Any country emerging from a non-democratic regime un
Conclusion
cratic process. For populists, though, the political sphere is not an open space
test of conflicting ideas and interests, which seems to be the core of the de
sion.
There is also the hopeful idea that populism has self-limiting features. Acc
populism is extremely effective when it comes to protest politics or to mobiliz
some entity or idea (the elites, an enemy, contested values, etc.), whereas it u
down when its leaders gain office (Taggart 2004). However, such a claim is d
relation to authoritarian populism. As is observable in many locations aroun
cratic world, once in office populists consolidate their position by further que
norms and institutions of liberal democracy. It is considerably more difficult
an anti-elitist narrative when the populist politician becomes part (or core) o
lishment. Nevertheless, populists manage to focus the public attention on discr
existing order (leaders, the party system, values, etc.) while not promoting an
one (Riedel 2010). Populism does not offer clear ideas about popular sovereign
macy, or leadership. It is in essence a protest ideology focused on questionin
testing and lacks constructive and stable ideas. It feeds on the deficits of dem
tice (rather than ideas). It is received wisdom that representative democracy
is in crisis. This is obvious in the rise in abstentionism, the drop in party iden
the increase in the number of floating voters, and the growing lack of trust
ical elite and politics as such (Chariot 1996). Lack of interest and participatio
can develop respectively into apathy or increasing extremism, do not seem t
plementary. Some of the phenomena that are now regarded as threats to demo
once perceived as necessary to the preservation of democratic stability. Usin
ple of the Weimer Republic, it can be argued that a high level of political pa
may overload the democratic system with highly politicized and polarizing con
(Andeweg 1996: 145).
Already half a century ago Hans-Dieter Klingeman (1967) claimed that we s
treat populism as a sickness of democracy but as a regular pathology of the W
of democracy. Such a statement obviously stems from the acknowledgement th
is both a democratic norm and at the same time it may be a syndrome of demo
function. There is no question but that populism challenges democracy while a
time being its constitutive element. Or the other way around: it could be said
racy is a system that is naturally exposed to the threat of populism. Therefore,
unavoidable (Crick 2005) in the democratic process. For a long time, populism
part of the political mainstream. Politicians can no longer afford not to use popul
Moreover, it is the citizens who have been accepting a more and more populist
In the end, political scientists have become more tolerant towards populism in
ical analyses. Consequently, the mainstreaming of populism is observable in
well as academic discourse. It coexists (and correlates) with the crisis of liber
in both domains. Its anti-elitist and anti-pluralist character is hardly imaginab
rective for democracy, especially in its liberal version. Consequently, populism
seen as a two-edged sword—it may be refreshing for democracy in some circum
in other contexts it may be undemocratic in essence. When populism adopts au
traits, it easily leads to counter-democratic outcomes.
References
Auer, S. 2010. 'New Europe': Between Cosmopolitan Dreams and Nationalist Nightmares, JCMS 48 (5): 1163—
1184.
B1 ack, D. J. 1928. The McNary-Haugen Movement, The American Economic Review XVIII (3): 405-427.
Canovan, M. 2005. The People. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bourdieu, P. 1991. Language and Symbolic Power. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Chariot, J. 1996. From Representative to Responsive Governmen, in: J. Hay ward (ed.), Elitism, Populism, and
European Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 88-100.
Crick, B. 2005. Populism, Politics and Democracy, Democratization 12 (5).
Finchelstein, F. 2014. Returning Populism to History, Constelations 21 (4): 465-482.
Freeden, M. 1998. Is Nationalism a Distinct Ideology?, Political Studies 46 (4): 748-765.
Good wyn, L. 1978. The Populist Moment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hay ward, J. 1996. The Populist Challenge to Elitist Democracy in Europe, in: J. Hay ward (ed.), Elitism, Pop
ulism , and European Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 10-32.
H echt er, M. 2000. Containing Nationalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jansen, S. R. 2011. Populist Mobilisation: A New Theoretical Approach to Populism, Sociological The
ory 29 (2): 75-96.
J a s i e w i c z, K. 2008. The New Populism in Poland. The Usual Suspects?, Problems of Post-Communism 55 (3):
7-25.
Keane, J. 1994. Nations, Nationalism and Citizens in Europe, International Social Science Journal 4:169-184.
Kaltwasser, R. C. 2014. The Responses of Populism to Dahl's Democratic Dilemmas, Political Studies 62:
470-487.
Lac lau, E. 1977. Politics and Ideology in Marxist Theory. London: Verso.
Mahoney, J. 2001. The Legacies of Liberalism: Path Dependence and Political Regimes in Central America.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Mierina, I., Koroleva, I. 2015. Supporters for Far Right Ideology and Anti-migrant Attitudes Among Youth
in Europe: A Comparative Analysis, The Sociological Review 63 (2): 183-205.
Moffit, B., Tormey, S. 2014. Rethinking Populism: Politics, Médiatisation and Political Style, Political Stud
ies 62'. 381-397.
M u d d e, C. 2001. In the Name of the Peasantry, the Proletariat and the People: Populism in Eastern Europe, East
European Politics and Societies, March: 33-53.
M u d d e, C. 2004. The Populist Zeitgeist, Government and Opposition 39 (4): 542-543.
Mudde, C., Kaltwasser, C. (eds.). 2012. Populism in Europe and the Americas, Threat or Corrective for
Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
M u e 11 e r, J.-W. 2015. Parsing Populism. Who Is and Who Is not a Populist These Days?, Juncture 22 (2): 80-89.
Nicholson, P. S. 2012. Who's the Party of the People? Economic Populism and the U.S. Public's Beliefs About
Political Parties, Political Behaviour 34: 369-389.
Pelinka, A. 2010. Populizm w Europie — w poszukiwaniu znaczenia mglistego pojçcia, in: J.-M. De Waele,
A. Paczesniak (eds.), Populizm w Europie. Defekt czy przejaw dmokracji? Warszawa: Oficyna Naukowa,
p. 17-34.
R i e d e 1, R. 2010. Populizm jako wyzwanie dla wspôtczesnego rozumienia demokracji (w wariancie przedstawi
cielskim), in: J.-M. De Waele, A. Paczeéniak (eds.), Populizm w Europie. Defekt czy przejaw demokracji?
Warszawa: Oficyna Naukowa, p. 145-158.
Rooduijn, M. van der Burg, W., de Lange, S. 2016. Express info or fuelling discontent? The relationship
between populist voting and political discontent. Electoral Studies 43: 32-40.
Rosanvallon, P. 2006. Democracy Past and Future. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rupnik, J. 2007. From Democracy Fatigue to Populist Backslash, Journal of Democracy 18 (4): 17-25.
E-mail: riedelr@icloud.com