1991-Snyder-Alliances, Balance, and Stability
1991-Snyder-Alliances, Balance, and Stability
1991-Snyder-Alliances, Balance, and Stability
Reviewed Work(s):
The Origins of Alliances. by Stephen M. Walt
The Balance of Power: Stability in International Systems. by Emerson M. S. Niou; Peter C.
Ordeshook; Gregory F. Rose
Glenn H. Snyder
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0020-8183%28199124%2945%3A1%3C121%3AABAS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-H
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/mitpress.html.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic
journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,
and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take
advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
http://www.jstor.org
Thu Aug 23 11:48:58 2007
Alliances, balance, and stability
Glenn H. Snyder
Alliances and alignments are surely among the most central phenomena in
international politics. Yet we have no theory about them that remotely ap-
proaches the richness of our theories about war, crisis, deterrence, and other
manifestations of conflict. What might explain this? Perhaps it is their ubiq-
uity, given their informal as well as their formal manifestations, and con-
sequently the difficulty of isolating them as objects of study. George Liska,
in the opening sentences of his Nations in Alliance, which after nearly three
decades remains the only comprehensive theoretical treatment, put it this
way: "It is impossible to speak of international relations without referring
to alliances; the two often merge in all but name. For the same reason, it
has always been difficult to say much that is peculiar to alliances on the
plane of general analysis."' Thus, would-be alliance theorists, realizing that
they do not really want to write a general theory of international relations,
retreat to something manageable-another analysis of NATO, perhaps.
However, we do have various partial theories, each focusing on a partic-
ular aspect of alliances or approaching them from a distinctive perspective.
For example, the theory of collective goods was in vogue during the 1970s
1. George Liska, Nations in Alliance: The Limits oflnterdependence (Baltimore, Md.: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1962), p. 3. For a comprehensive inventory and discussion of the-
oretical propositions in a more "behavioral" vein, see Ole R. Holsti, P. Terrence Hopmann,
and John D. Sullivan, Unity and Disintegration in International Alliances: Comparative Studies
(New York: Wiley, 1973).
and early 1980s and became quite well developed as an explanation for why
the United States carried a larger share of the arms burden in NATO than
its European allies did. But this theory was rarely extended to other alliances,
particularly pre-bipolar alliances, or to other dimensions of alliance p ~ l i c y . ~
There have been occasional attempts to apply sociological coalition theory,
most interestingly to the U.S.-Soviet-China triangle.3The theory of "struc-
tural balance," which posits a tendency toward a positive product in triadic
relationships (three positives, or two negatives and a positive), has proven
quite fruitful in the analysis of pre-1914 alliance d i p l ~ m a c yN-person
.~ game
theory, apparently the most promising formal approach, has had little ap-
plication until r e ~ e n t l y There
.~ have been some interesting recent formal-
izations from a broadly "rational choice" per~pective.~ But these various
efforts do not cumulate; they remain partial and idiosyncratic.
In this article, I will try to suggest some issues and themes that a com-
prehensive theory of alliances ought to address, while commenting on two
2. The seminal article is Mancur Olson and Richard Zeckhauser's "An Economic Theory of
Alliances," Review of Economics and Statistics 48 (August 1966), pp. 266-79. For typical
examples of the elaborations and critiques that followed, see James Murdock and Todd Sandler,
"A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of NATO," Journal of Conjict Resolution 26 (June
1982), pp. 237-65; and Bruce M. Russett and Harvey Starr, "Alliances and the Price of Pri-
macy," in Bruce M. Russett, ed., What Price Vigilance? The Burdens of National Defense
(New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1970), pp. 91-127. For applications of the theory
to pre-1939 systems, see Wallace Thies, "Alliances and Collective Goods: A Reappraisal,"
Journal of Conjict Resolution 31 (June 19871, pp. 298-332; and Barry Posen, The Sources of
Military Doctrine: France, Britain and Germany Between the Wars (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
University Press, 1984).
3. See Dina Zinnes, "Coalition Theories and the Balance of Power," in S. Groennings, E. W.
Kelley, and M. Leiserson, eds., The Study of Coalition Behavior (New York: Holt, Rinehart
& Winston, 1970), pp. 351-69; and James C . Hsiung, "Sino-U.S.-Soviet Relations in a Triadic-
Game Perspective," in James C. Hsiung, ed., Beyond China's Independent Foreign Policy
(New York: Praeger, 1985), pp. 107-32.
4. For the original theory, see Fritz Heider, The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations (New
York: Wiley, 1958). See also Howard F. Taylor, Balance in Small Groups (New York: Van
Nostrand Reinhold, 1970). For applications to international relations, see Robert Jervis, "Sys-
tems Theories and Diplomatic History," in Paul Gordon Lauren, ed., Diplomacy (New York:
Free Press, 1979), pp. 212-45; Brian Healey and Arthur Stein, "The Balance of Power in
International History: Theory and Reality," Journal of Conjict Resolution 17 (March 1973),
pp. 33-61; and H. Brooke McDonald and Richard Rosecrance, "Alliance and Structural Balance
in the International System: A Reinterpretation," Journal of Conjict Resolution 29 (March
1985), pp. 57-83.
5. The seminal work applying n-person game theory to political science is William H . Riker's
The Theory of Political Coalitions (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1962), but its
emphasis is on legislative rather than international coalitions. The pioneer in international
applications is R. Harrison Wagner, whose works include "The Theory of Games and the
Problem of International Cooperation," American Political Science Review 77 (June 1983), pp.
330-46; and "The Theory of Games and the Balance of Power," World Politics 38 (July 1986),
pp. 546-76.
6. For recent works in this genre, see Michael F . Altfeld, "The Decision to Ally: A Theory
and Test," Western Political Quarterly 37 (December 1984), pp. 523-44; James D. Morrow,
"On the Theoretical Bases of a Measure of National Risk Attitudes," International Studies
Quarterly 31 (December 1987), pp. 423-38; and Michael D. McGinnis, "A Rational Model of
Regional Rivalry," International Studies Quarterly 34 (March 1990), pp. 111-37.
Alliances 123
recent heroic efforts, one in the traditional mode and the other in the formal
mode.
The first task in any theoretical investigation is to define the object of
analysis. What exactly is an "alliance"? Arnold Wolfers' definition is at-
tractive for its simplicity: an alliance is "a promise of mutual military as-
sistance between two or more sovereign states."' An alliance is a "promise,"
an explicit mutual declaration of future intent. This sets it apart from inten-
tions or expectations of assistance that may arise from sources other than
a promise (more about this presently); it also distinguishes alliance from the
physical act of assisting others, whether or not in fulfillment of a prior
promise. Alliances involve military collaboration. This immediately distin-
guishes them from all nonmilitary associations, ranging from economic car-
tels, such as the Organization of Petroleum Exporting Countries, to political
groups, such as the British Commonwealth. Further, they entail military
cooperation against particular other states, which differentiates them from
universal collective security organizations, such as the League of Nations
and the United Nations. Finally, the restriction to "sovereign states" rules
out government ties with nongovernmental entities, such as revolutionary
groups. The definition leaves open the issue of what form the "assistance"
will take; thus, it embraces not only offensive and defensive alliances but
also agreements not to use force, as in neutrality and nonaggression agree-
ments. A definition of this sort should be followed by a typology that sets
out in greater detail the possible variations on these basic forms and on other
characteristics such as the contingencies that will activate the promise.*
However, our theory must not be limited to formal alliances, thus defined.
What we really want to understand is the broader phenomenon of "align-
ment" of which explicit alliance is merely a subset. Alignment refers to the
expectations held by policymakers concerning the question "Who will de-
fend whom?" or, more broadly, "Who will support whom and who will
resist whom to what extent and in what contingencies?" Expectations of
support or opposition stem from a great variety of sources, most of which
can be crudely grouped into three categories: (1) strength inequalities, (2)
conflicts and common interests among states, and (3) past interaction, in-
cluding the negotiation of formal alliances.
Degrees of strength inequality form the basis for the familiar distinction
between bipolar and multipolar system structures. Each of these ideal types
logically generates different sorts of alignment expectations. In a bipolar
system, characterized by extreme inequality, the superpowers have clear
strategic interests in resisting each other's expansion. Consequently, the
Traditional theory
Stephen Walt's The Origins of Alliances does not completely fill the alliance
theory void, but it makes an impressive start. As the title suggests, his study
is principally about alliance formation rather than the politics of alliances
after they form. Walt asks two central questions: Why do states ally? And
how do states choose their friends? He then advances five hypotheses:
(1) states ally against states that threaten them-that is, they "balance";
(2) states ally with states that threaten them-that is, they "bandwagon";
(3) states choose allies of similar ideology; (4) foreign aid attracts allies;
and (5) political penetration facilitates alliance. In testing the hypotheses
against the history of alliances in the Middle East between 1955 and 1979,
Walt finds strong support for the balancing hypothesis, little for bandwa-
goning, modest support for ideological attraction, and little for aid and pen-
etration as causes of alliance.
Walt proposes to replace the traditional theory of "balance of power"
with a more comprehensive "balance of threat." Balance-of-power theory,
10. Liska, Nations in Alliance, p. 12.
126 International Organization
he argues, is too one-dimensional and thus distorting in its claim that states
ally in order to balance off the power of others. Actually, "states ally to
balance against threats rather than against power alone."" The level of threat
facing a state is a function not only of the distribution of power but also of
the geographic proximity, offensive capabilities, and, in particular, the per-
ceived intentions of others.
I wondered, on first reading, just how new this reformulation was. Was
it a "major revision," as the dust jacket announces, or was it only a "re-
finement," as the text describes it? The first three factors simply appear to
be components of "power" or "capability"; had we not recognized them
all along, at least implicitly? As for the fourth factor, intentions, had we not
always understood that balancing coalitions formed only (or usually) against
states that were apparently aggressive as well as powerful? A quick check
of several titles in the balance-of-power literature produced mixed results. l 2
Some authors describe the balancing process (when it is conceived as a
process rather than a static equilibrium) as something that is triggered by
the existence of "imperialist" or "revisionist" states. But others do imply
that the mere possession of great power will be enough to stimulate coun-
tervailing alliances. Hardly ever are powerful capabilities and expansionist
intentions explicitly separated as independent sources of threat. Nor, typi-
cally, are geographic factors introduced as either positive or negative mod-
ifiers of capabilities. Thus, in disaggregating these variables and then rein-
tegrating them in the concept of "threat," Walt has made a useful theoretical
clarification, one that brings balance-of-power theory more into line both
with common sense and with the historical record.
Walt has not quite buttoned up his revision, however. If what is balanced
is "threat," rather than "power," of what does the balancing consist? At
several points, he says that the more "dangerous" the threat (and he clearly
has in mind the "intentions" component of the threat), the more power will
be mobilized against it. Thus, the coalitions that formed against Germany
in World Wars I and I1 were far larger than necessary for "balance of power,"
and a large number of powerful states have coordinated their policies against
Libya, despite that state's modest capabilities. Threatening intentions are
therefore balanced by mobilizing extra power.I3 But this seems to ignore the
intentions factor on the defensive side. If threats are comprised of two broad
components-capabilities and intentions-might not the defensive reaction
16. For a discussion of these trade-offs, see Morrow, "On the Theoretical Bases of a Measure
of National Risk Attitudes."
17. Walt has subsequently relaxed the dichotomy. Balancing and bandwagoning are ideal
types which actual behavior only approximates: "balancing against a potential threat does not
require unremitting hostility to it." States should "maximize security by aligning dith one side
while maintaining cordial relations with the other." See Walt, "Testing Theories of Alliance
Formation," p. 315.
Alliances 129
and when they will conciliate them. Those instances of conciliation, espe-
cially of major "appeasement," that have motivations similar to those of
the bandwagoning alliance ought logically to be labeled bandwagoning. But
this excludes the lesser forms and degrees of conciliation that are not sim-
ilarly motivated and that may play a role in the formation of alliances gen-
erally-for example, as preludes to alliance, bargaining ploys, means of
keeping options open, and hedges against excessive dependence on an ally.
Given Walt's "neorealist" orientation, it is odd that the variable of system
structure plays little role in his analysis. He apparently believes that his
generalizations are equally applicable to multipolar and bipolar systems,
although he seems to have the post-1945 bipolar system chiefly in mind.21
Greater sensitivity to structural differences would have enriched his theory.
For example, bandwagoning is logically more likely in a multipolar system
than in a bipolar one. Balancing is inhibited in a multipolar system because
of collective goods anxieties ("if I try to balance against this aggressor, will
others do the same?") and hopes ("somebody else will do the job"). Bal-
ancing may also be hindered by ambiguity about which state poses the
greatest threat. Bandwagoning is encouraged by the thought that there are
other targets toward which an aggressor's energies may be diverted and
there are other potential allies that a state may call upon for help in the event
that its aggressor-ally turns against it. In a bipolar system, bandwagoning is
less likely not only because of the virtual certainty that the superpower
protector will continue to balance off the superpower threat but also because
the threat itself is so unambiguous. Small states are less tempted to band-
wagon with the threat, since they need not fear being deserted if they balance
and since bandwagoning so clearly risks subservience.
Walt could have made use of such reasoning to explain why U.S. poli-
cymakers are excessively concerned about the reliability of U.S. allies: they
simply fail to appreciate the structural constraints on bandwagoning in a
bipolar system. In the new multipolar world toward which we are presently
drifting, such concerns may become more appropriate.
Nevertheless, Walt deserves credit for having initiated theorizing about a
phenomenon hitherto almost ignored. Further development would seek to
understand bandwagoning as a systemic process and to determine how it
relates to other such processes. Bandwagoning apparently is the alliance
equivalent of the domino theory in adversary relations.22 As Robert Jervis
has noted, both are theories of positive feedback or instability; a departure
21. Walt does recognize that the Middle East is a "multipolar, regional subsystem embedded
within a bipolar global system" and that this structural condition gives certain distinctive
characteristics to alliance formation in the area-notably a preference for superpower support
over alignment with regional actors. See Walt, The Origins of Alliances, p. 266.
22. Compare Deborah Welch Larson, "Bandwagon Images in American Foreign Policy:
Myth or Reality?" and Robert Jervis, "Domino Beliefs and Strategic Behavior," both in Robert
Jervis and Jack Snyder, eds., Dominoes and Bandwagons: Strategic Beliefs and Superpower
Competition in the Eurasian Rimland (New York: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
Alliances 131
influence with aid to Arab states. He notes that the United States has been
somewhat more.successfu1 with Israel.
Formal theory
Until recently, one of the most conspicuous gaps in alliance theorizing has
been the lack of formalization and, in particular, the absence of any sustained
attempt to apply n-person game theory. The explanation, I think, lies not
so much in the mathematical complexity of the theory, as is often supposed,
as in the difficulty of operationalizing the theory in international relations
terms. At first glance, this theory, with its components of coalition formation,
winning and losing coalitions, defections, bargaining, indeterminacy of part-
ners, and so forth, seems ready-made as a model for alliances, but the
appearance is deceptive. There is a considerable gap between the realities
of international life and the entities, assumptions, and workings of the theory;
a prerequisite to fruitful application is to close or at least narrow this gap.
Among the key concepts in n-person theory are those of "weights," "win-
ning," "coalition," and "payoff." "Weights" translate fairly straightfor-
wardly as "military power and potential." The other notions are more prob-
lematic. In the theory, a coalition wins when its aggregate weight is greater
than that of its complement-that is, greater than the aggregate weight of
all players outside the coalition. But international alliances begin to produce
value when they are far short of controlling over half of the power resources
in the system-presumably when they outweigh their most likely opponents,
and sometimes even short of that.
In the theory, "winning" occurs at some discrete point in time, when the
winners receive their payoffs, which are generally equivalent to the losses
of the losers-that is, the game is zero-sum. But in international relations,
there is no such clear decision point, nor is the game zero-sum. If payoffs
are conceived as security, they are experienced in a continuous stream over
time, a stream that expands and contracts with changes in the environment
or in relations within the alliance. And security gained by an alliance is not
necessarily equivalent to security lost by its opponents.
Even the notion of "coalition" does not have a clear-cut empirical ana-
logue. In cooperative game theory, whether or not a coalition exists is un-
ambiguous: either an agreement has been made or it has not; and if it has
been made, it will be fulfilled. In international life, however, the existence
of a coalition does not depend on formal agreement. Mutual expectations
of military support may follow from a variety of behaviors short of formal
alliance or merely from a coincidence of interests. And it is always uncertain
whether these expectations will be fulfilled, however they are generated.
Thus, the existence of a coalition is a probabilistic matter, or, in other words,
the value of an alliance must be discounted by a "loyalty coefficient."
Alliances 133
26. It is not clear why peaceful transfers are preferred over war gains, since wars are assumed
to be costless. Zero war costs are assumed in order to simplify the model; the assumption does
not affect the theoretical results. See Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose, The Balance of Power, p.
52.
Alliances 135
or more members of the latter, with the goal of counterchallenging the re-
maining members. The turncoats will, of course, have to be offered more
than they expected in their first coalition to induce them to switch sides.
But then the remaining members of the first coalition can similarly induce
members of the second to switch, the second coalition can respond in kind,
and so on. No state can be offered more than half of the resources in the
system, since that would confer preponderance. The cycle ends when mem-
bers of a losing coalition, in order to avoid elimination, offer to transfer
enough resources to the largest of the winners to make it near-preponderant.
The offer will be accepted (again, "freezing" the system) because the ad-
vantaged state would rather make its gains peacefully than via war. Thus,
the two types of viable counter are not really independent; ultimately, system
stability depends on the feasibility of large voluntary resource transfers.27
Stated in game theory terms, system stability obtains when all actors are
"essential," meaning that each is an indispensable member of some "min-
imum winning coalition." In that case, each member either is able to mobilize
a viable countercoalition when threatened or is able, by itself or jointly with
others, to transfer sufficient resources to the threatener to give the latter
half of the total resources in the system.
The notion that a threatened state, in order to preserve its sovereignty,
would voluntarily transfer enough resources to its threatener to place the
latter on the brink of preponderance is the linchpin of the theory; therefore,
it must pass particularly severe muster. The issue is not so much whether
the transfer is physically feasible but whether a state would ever find it
desirable or necessary to make it. Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose point out that
such transfers are made all the time, but their examples-the granting of
spheres of influence, the payment of indemnities and reparations, the grant-
ing of trade concessions, and the transfer of territory as the consequence of
wars-fall well short of the scale implied by their theory, which is the
voluntary transfer of anything short of the entire territory of the homeland.
Of course, states sometimes do surrender large amounts of territory in the
face of overwhelming power, but generally they do so with the intention of
avoiding futile war costs, not with the intention of giving the aggressor half
of the total resources in the system and thereby obtaining the support of
others for the defense of some remnant of their territory. Moreover, a single
victim state, even if it were "essential," might not have enough territory to
27. One is tempted to suggest a parallel between the two types of viable counter and Walt's
choice between balancing and bandwagoning. The second type of counter, the countercoalition,
is crudely analogous to balancing. The ceding of resources has the flavor of the defensive form
of bandwagoning or simply of appeasement. However, there seem to be no examples in history
of an aggressor being appeased to the extent of giving it half of the power in the system. And
the motive for appeasement, in its conventional sense, is to moderate an aggressor's intentions,
not to increase its capabilities.
136 International Organization
28. For example, France's capitulation in 1940 did not give Germany near-preponderance,
nor would have the capitulation of all of Western Europe; concessions by the Uhited States,
the Soviet Union, or both would have been required to preserve remnants of territory and
sovereignty for the Western European countries.
Alliances 137
could always hope that it would preserve more of its territory in allowing
others to defend it than in ceding whatever was required to preserve its
sovereignty. These others might prefer to restrict the aggressor to something
less than half of the total resources of the system; they could not assume,
as these authors do, that all states will grow at the same rate, and they might
prefer to avoid the eternal vigilance and constraint on their own policy that
would be entailed in permitting one state to be near-preponderant. This
scenario could be formally stated in a manner consistent with bargaining-
set logic, although it would require the addition of certain quite plausible
assumptions: that alliance bargains are not necessarily kept, that bargaining
continues during war, and that members of an attacking coalition are unequal
in strength or do not conquer resources at the same rate. Thus, realism
would be improved at some cost to parsimony-a desirable exchange in this
case.
Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose provide an empirical test of their model, using
great power alliance formation between 1871 and 1914 to "discern histori-
cally the forces it describes and the extent to which those forces appear to
operate despite the frictions characterizing reality."29 Their central hypoth-
esis is that states will form coalitions which are only large enough to win
and which maximize the ratio of the alliance's gain to its resources. An index
of resources for the six states involved is constructed from standard com-
ponents: production of coal, iron ore, pig iron, and steel; military-age male
population; mobilization efficiency; and force projection. The gain to any
winning coalition is operationalized as the amount of resources that a losing
coalition would have to transfer to the largest member of the winning co-
alition to give that member exactly half of the resources in the system. That
amount, then, is divided among the members of the alliance according to
their proportional resource contributions. This operationalization is, of course,
true to the initial statement of the theory and is therefore subject to the
anomalies mentioned earlier; it strains credibility to think of it as a plausible
measure of the value of alliances.
The "process" part of the theory-its description of alliance bargaining
and the preservation of stability-hardly shows up in the historical assess-
ment. The notion of "ceding," which is central to the model, is virtually
absent from the history. The only concrete reference is to the possibility of
Germany ceding Alsace-Lorraine to France in the 1880s to block a
Franco-Russian alliance, a concession which, the authors comment, "al-
most certainly would have led to the demise of the nascent German state."30
Although threats and counterthreats of alliance occasionally appear in the
history, they are not translated formally into bargaining-set dynamics.
Regarding outcomes, the results of the empirical assessment are hard to
appraise because there is no summary statement of correct and incorrect
29. Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose, The Balance of Power, p. 223.
30. Ibid., p. 262.
138 International Organization
predictions. Some of the alliances that actually formed were consistent with
theoretical expectations; others were not. In the latter cases, the authors
resort to a variety of selective ad hoc explanations, most of which appeal
to variables clearly present in reality but omitted from the model. Thus,
Germany's decision to join a "losing" alliance with Austria in 1879 rather
than a winning one with Britain is explained by Britain's lack of interest in
alliance with Germany at the time and by Anglo-German economic com-
petition. Germany's failure to choose the higher-paying Russian alliance over
alliance with Austria is explained by Germany's "mistrust" of Russia and
by its desire to keep Britain, Russia's enemy, unaligned. Certain other well-
known factors, such as Bismarck's belief that he could count on Britain in
any case because of its common interests with Austria and that he could
control Austria but not Russia, are not mentioned.
Most of these improvisations make reference to interests of or conflicts
between certain parties-obvious determinants of alliance behavior which
are practically ignored in the model. Interests appear in the operationalized
model only peripherally and crudely, as when certain alliance possibilities
such as Germany-France or Austria-Russia are labeled "infeasible" owing
to severe conflicts. Common interests and less-than-severe conflicts of in-
terest simply do not appear in the model; alliances are valued according to
their "winning" potential, regardless of commonalities or conflicts among
the allies or between them and their opponents. Thus, in being faithful to
the "power side" of realist theory, the authors' model slights the equally
central "interest side" and winds up being a caricature of realism rather
than a model of it.
Conceiving alliance values in terms of resources does capture the dis-
tinctive element of international politics mentioned earlier: that gains and
losses are counted more in terms of strategic values or relative power than
in terms of intrinsic values. It also provides a precise measure of value that
is commensurate and transferable across states. And, of course, strategic
values are at the center of the realist paradigm that the authors are attempting
to model. These are important strengths of their method. But these advan-
tages are gained at a considerable cost in verisimilitude. First, calculating
alliance payoffs strictly as potential resource gains at others' expense im-
plicitly casts alliances as offensive. Defensive alliances presumably are val-
ued chiefly for the "security" they provide for values presently held, not
for their capacity to acquire more, although a superiority in resources would
be conducive to security. The authors admit that their criterion of value
"may be irrelevant" to defensive alliance^,^' but they then proceed to test
their theory against a historical period in which most alliances were defensive
or primarily so. Consequently, the values they attribute to alliances between
1871 and 1914 can hardly be taken seriously.
Computing the security value of defensive alliances would require a fairly
imization, rather than security, and their conclusion that bipolar systems
are less stable than multipolar systems make their approach more an example
of old-style realism than of "neorealism."
Comparison of the two books under review is difficult because of their
different methodologies and purposes, but some interesting contrasts do
emerge. One obvious difference is that for Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose,
alliances are offensive and driven by greed; for Walt, they are chiefly de-
fensive and are driven by fear. The coauthors seem, again, to have been too
much influenced by the logic and dynamics of their model and not enough
by the world they are modeling. Walt's stance is the more realistic one. Walt
takes full account of conflicts and commonalities of interest, notably in
adding the factor of "intentions" to the "threat" against which states bal-
ance. Niou and his colleagues consider only "capabilities" ("resources")
in their model and introduce interests only verbally and partially. Both books,
to their credit, pay particular attention to geographical factors, but they
reach dismayingly different conclusions about them. For Walt, geographical
proximity is a source of threat. For Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose, proximity
is stabilizing, while distance is destabilizing: since resources have to be
discounted for distance, fewer resources have to be transferred to a nearby
aggressor than to a distant one to "buy stability." In their interesting chapter
on geography, the three have formalized the notion of "balancer" and the
special positions of "central" and "peripheral" powers. They have also
formalized the idea of preventive war. Thus, for these authors, alliances are
only one of several phenomena associated with the balance of power, while,
for Walt, alliances are the focus of analysis, and the balance of power is a
subsidiary theme. Niou and his colleagues are more systemic than Walt;
they approach alliances as a process central to systemic stability, whereas
Walt sees them principally as an instrument of statecraft.
So different in style, these books make different sorts of contributions.
Walt's work demonstrates that there is still room for theoretical progress in
the traditional realist mode. The contribution of Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose
is less in theoretical substance than in method.32It is the first comprehensive
formalization of realist balance-of-power theory, a valuable ground-breaking
effort despite its substantive flaws.
Where do these two books leave the theory of alliances and the balance of
power? What remains to be done? Neither book is or claims to be a general
theory of alliances. Much is omitted from both that would have to be included
32. On the whole, the authors' mathematics are accessible to the novice.
Alliances 141
33. 1 attempt such an exercise in "Alliance Theory: A Neorealist First Cut," Journal of
International Affairs 44 (Spring-Summer 1990), pp. 103-25. I have drawn on this article for
several other ideas in the present review essay; see pp. 103-5 and 108-9. The progressive
relaxation of assumptions is also part of the method of Niou and his colleagues. For instance,
they relax their initial assumption of equal rates of growth to develop their model of preventive
war.
142 International Organization
34. For a discussion of these risks, see Glenn H. Snyder, "The Security Dilemma in Alliance
Politics," World Politics 36 (July 1984), pp. 461-96. Apparently, the concepts of entrapment
and abandonment were initially proposed by Michael Mandelbaum in The Nuclear Revolution:
International Politics Before and After Hiroshima (New York: Cambridge University Press,
1981), pp. 151-52.