SPIRO-Culture and Human Nature
SPIRO-Culture and Human Nature
SPIRO-Culture and Human Nature
Melford E. Spiro
Edited by
Benjamin Kilborne and L.L. Langness
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by
any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including
photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in
writing from the publishers.
Notice:
Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for
identification and explanation without intent to infringe.
THE ARTICLES collected in this volume, first brought together and re-
published in 1987 by Benjamin Kilborne and L.L. Langness, explore some
of the relationships that, in my view, obtain among culture, society, and the
human mind. Within this framework this collection addresses a range of
theoretical issues including the limitations of cultural determinism and
cultural relativism, the problem of explanation in the social sciences, and
the importance of a comparative approach for the study of social and
cultural systems.
One of the critical emphases of this collection is the importance not only
of cultural variables, but also of psychological and social variables, for the
understanding of human behavior and human belief systems. Seeing as
most of the articles are based on research conducted in the Micronesian
atoll of Ifaluk, an Israeli kibbutz, and a village in Upper Burma, they hardly
minimize the importance of culture for such understanding. Nevertheless
they argue that social actors possess motivational dispositions and cognitive
orientations—both parochial and universal, and both conscious and
unconscious—that, while derived in part from their cultural heritage, are
also derived from their social experience (most especially early experience
in the family), as well as from the evolutionary status of our species.
Spanning the years between 1961 and 1984, some of the views expressed
in these articles have undergone change, not only in the period subsequent
to that time interval, but also within it. Moreover, even when they have not
changed, in retrospect I wish that these views had been expressed with
greater clarity and felicity. Nevertheless, except for typographical errors, I
have decided (as did Kilborne and Langness) to republish these articles in
their original form.
An implicit theme running throughout this collection is that
contemporary anthropological orthodoxy has replaced an older biological
and psychological reductionism with its own cultural reductionism. That is,
in the case of many contemporary anthropologists, their interpretations and
theories of human behavior, belief systems, emotions, and motivation rest
on a wholesale form of cultural determinism and a radical type of cultural
relativism which leaves little (if any) theoretical space for the concept of a
common human nature. Drawing, however, on my own research in Ifaluk,
Israel, and Burma, as well as on published reports on other societies, the
following articles argue that despite the wide diversity in human cultural
systems, important panhuman characteristics nevertheless are to be found,
for example, in sex-role differentiation, aggression, world view, and the
Oedipus complex, among others.
Although my reasons for rejecting wholesale cultural determinism and
radical cultural relativism are suggested in various of the following
chapters, and explicated in detail elsewhere (Spiro 1992: chs.1–2),
nevertheless because of the ambiguities surrounding “culture,” “cultural
determinism,” and “cultural relativism,” not to mention “human nature,” in
order to preclude misunderstanding it is perhaps useful to indicate at the
outset how I am using these terms here. Let us begin with “culture.”
Although for the past quarter century most anthropologists have tended
to view culture as a symbolic or ideational system—some focusing on the
symbols, some on their meanings—nevertheless they have not consistently
employed the term “culture” to designate either the one or the other. Rather,
they also employ that term, just as it had formerly been employed, to
designate two other things, as well: (a) a social group (“one of the critical
characteristics of Ifaluk culture is the virtual absence of interpersonal
aggression”) and (b) the totality of a group’s customs, beliefs, artifacts, and
technology (“Ifaluk culture is characterized by matrilineal descent,
hereditary chieftanship, a belief in ghosts, horticulture, outrigger canoes,”
etc.).
Since such inconsistency in the use of a single term is not only confusing,
but also (as we shall see below) theoretically misleading, in this volume
“culture” designates an ideational system exclusively, that is, a system of
ideas, values, and norms. More specifically, it designates the subset of
ideas, values, and norms that (a) are encoded in public symbols and other
public signs, (b) are acquired by cultural novices in virtue of their social
transmission, and hence (c) are in varying degrees socially shared. In short,
“culture,” as that term is used here, designates traditional ideas, values, and
norms. Correspondingly, “a culture” designates the traditional ideas, values,
and norms that are found in some particular social group, and consequently
constitute the “cultural heritage” of that group.
Often these elements of their cultural heritage are transmitted to cultural
novices intentionally, and by means of verbal instruction, in which case
they are conveyed in the form of propositions, descriptive (“the Buddha
discovered the Noble Eightfold Path”), prescriptive (“it is wrong to steal”),
and directive (“a successful rice crop requires that the paddy fields be
irrigated”). Often, however, traditional values, ideas, and norms are
acquired by the novices indirectly, as a consequence of their observation of,
and participation in, social relations, religious rituals, and the like. Although
in the latter case these cultural elements are not acquired in the form of
propositions, still that is the form, or so I would claim, in which the novices
typically represent them in their minds.
In either event, from the perspective of cultural novices the ideas, values,
and norms that comprise their cultural heritage are wholly “outside” them.
That is, they are “located” in public symbols and other public signs that
“represent” them, in the behavior of social actors that “express” them, and
in the minds of cultural initiates that hold them. As a consequence,
however, of their enculturation, the erstwhile novices themselves come to
represent these cultural elements in symbols and other signs (both public
and private), and to express them in their own behavior, because now these
elements are also located in their minds. In short, following the novice’s
enculturation, one or another element of the cultural heritage come to be
located not only “outside,” but also “inside,” him or her.
However, for cultural novices to become enculturated—that is, for their
psyches and actions to be importantly influenced by the ideas, values, and
norms that comprise their cultural heritage—it is not sufficient that the
novices acquire these cultural elements, but they must also (as I argue in
chapter 2) internalize them. That is, they must acquire them as cognitively
salient personal beliefs.
In the previous paragraph I used the neutral expression “importantly
influenced” by the cultural heritage, rather than “determined” by it, because
the expression “cultural determinism,” confusingly, has four very different
meanings—culturally constituted, culturally caused, culturally shaped, and
socially caused—which must now be distinguished. (Here, I follow some of
the distinctions made by D’Andrade [1992:13] in his analysis of the
expression “culturally constituted.”)
First, “cultural determinism” is employed in connection with a category
of things which are, as D’Andrade (ibid.) says, created, or brought into
existence, by culture. In contemporary usage this category not only
(properly) includes such symbolic things as nationality, money, baseball,
and unicorns, but it also (improperly) includes such nonsymbolic things as
emotions, gender, the sense of self, and sociality. Let us begin with the
latter.
Although the members of this set are no doubt effected by culture, that
they are, however, created or constructed (whatever that might mean) by
culture is to say the least problematic. Thus, there are substantial grounds
for believing that most emotions (though not their behavioral expression)
are biologically grounded, that many (but not all) gender differences follow
a phylogenetic template, that the sense of self is acquired as a function of
early social interaction, and that human sociality is rooted in our primate (if
not mammalian) needs. In short, to say (as many cultural determinists say)
that the members of this set are “culturally constructed” is perversely to
reject the relevant findings of the neurosciences, ethology, biological
evolution, primate studies, clinical and developmental psychology, and (I
might add) comparative ethnography.
To say, however, that the members of the first set (nationality, money,
baseball, unicorns, and the like) are culturally created or constructed is not
problematic at all. For they, unlike the members of the second set, are as
D’Andrade (ibid.) says, “purely symbolic”; that is, they exist “solely
because [as a function of their cultural heritage] people hold that [these
things] exist and that various actual events count as these things or are
expressions of them.” Since, then, these symbolic entities are constructed
from, and consist of, cultural ideas, rules, norms, and the like, they may be
said to be “culturally determined” in the sense of their being constituted. by
culture.
“Cultural determinism” is employed, in the second place, in connection
with things which, though not themselves cultural, are caused by culture. I
refer here to a class of actions and psychological characteristics (especially
desires and beliefs) of social actors which may be said to be culturally
“caused” in two senses. First, the existence of culture—any culture—is a
necessary condition for the existence of this class of actions, beliefs, and
desires. Second, seeing as the members of this class vary from one social
group to another, the internalization of a particular culture is a sufficient
condition for their existence.
Thus, all cultures prescribe some type of action for greeting one’s
fellows, but whether actors greet each other by shaking each other’s hands,
or instead by placing their own palms together and holding them against
their own forehead, is a consequence of having internalized one particular
culture, rather than another. Again, all cultures contain rules for conflict
resolution, but whether actors desire to resolve their conflicts by litigation,
or instead by conciliation, is also a consequence of having internalized a
particular culture. Similarly, all cultures contain principles for
distinguishing kin from non-kin, but whether actors believe that mothers
(but not fathers) are kin, or instead that fathers (but not mothers) are, or
again that both are, is once again a consequence of having internalized a
particular culture.
Now since the members of this class of actions, beliefs, and desires do
not in themselves consist of culture, it is surely improper to refer to them as
“culturally determined” in the sense of their being constituted by culture.
Since, however, the existence of this class depends on the existence of
culture, and since the particular members of the class vary as a function of
the variability of particular cultures, then both the class and its members
may be said to be “culturally determined” in the sense of being caused by
culture.
“Cultural determinism” is employed, in the third place, in connection
with a class of social actions which, while not caused by culture, are (to use
D’Andrade’s term [op. cit.]) shaped by it. This class consists of actions that
are instigated by biologically or experientially acquired emotions, needs, or
drives. Since, now, it is in the nature of emotions to press for expression, of
needs to press for fulfillment, and of drives to press for satisfaction, it can
be presumed that whatever their culture, or even in the absence of culture,
human actors (like nonhuman actors) would express these emotions, fulfill
these needs, and satisfy these drives in some form of action.
Since, however, in diverse social groups these actions take one form
rather than another, it can also be presumed that often their form is a
function of the values, rules, and norms of each group’s particular culture.
Thus, as a function of the emotional display rules of their respective
cultures, in one social group males express their panhuman emotion of
anger by verbal aggression against its elicitor, whereas in another group
they displace their anger and express it in headhunting. Similarly, as a
function of the gender norms of their respective cultures, in one social
group females satisfy their panhuman maternal drive by bearing many
children, whereas in another group they do so by the intensive nurturance of
a few children. Again, as a function of the achievement values of their
respective cultures, in one social group actors fulfill their panhuman need
for self-esteem by acts of religious piety, whereas in another group they do
so by the accumulation of wealth.
In sum, since all human beings possess biologically and experientially
acquired emotions, needs, and drives which, regardless of culture, press for
expression, fulfillment, and satisfaction respectively, it is entirely
misleading to claim that the actions by which these purposes are achieved
are “culturally determined” in the sense of their being caused by culture.
Seeing, however, that the forms they take are a function of the values and
norms of particular cultures, these actions may properly be said to be
“culturally determined” in the sense of their being shaped by culture.
Finally, “cultural determinism” is employed in connection with a large
class of drives, desires, beliefs, and actions which, although they may be
shared by social actors, are in no sense “culturally” determined, as we may
now see.
From the moment of birth infants, and later children, participate in an
ever expanding circle of social relations, and they undergo an ever
increasing variety of social (and other) experiences, all of which occur
many months and sometimes many years prior to their acquisition of one or
another of the ideas, values, and norms that comprise the cultural heritage
of their group. This is so for at least three rather obvious reasons
First, seeing as they are transmitted in the medium of language, it is
impossible for children to acquire any of these cultural elements prior to
their development of the requisite linguistic competence; until then, they
perforce remain cultural novices. Second, even after they attain the requisite
linguistic competence, many of these cultural elements may nevertheless
not be transmitted to children on the grounds, actual or presumed, that they
have not achieved the requisite maturity, either biological or intellectual.
Third, even after their attaining the requisite biological and intellectual
maturity, others of these cultural elements may not be transmitted to
children on the grounds that they have not yet achieved the culturally
stipulated social age for their acquisition.
Does this interval between birth and the acquisition of culture (which, of
course, varies from one social group to another) entail that the precultural
child is a cognitive, emotional, and motivational tabula rasal Although
implicit in the regnant theory of wholesale cultural determinism (according
to which virtually all nontrivial psychological characteristics of social
actors are either constituted or caused by culture), nevertheless such an
entailment is surely not warranted, as any observer of children (whether
child psychologist or parent) can testify. For apart from their biologically
determined drives and emotions, precultural children also possess any
number of socially determined beliefs and desires, that is, beliefs and
desires acquired from their social (but precultural) experience.
Thus, as a consequence of their socially variable interactions with parents
and other socializers, precultural children may come to believe, for
example, that their social world (to put it more starkly than is actually the
case) is nurturant or punitive or both; that they must compete, or need not
compete, with others in order to receive care and attention; that adults fulfill
or frustrate their needs, or both; that certain of their actions elicit approval
and love, whereas others elicit disapproval and punishment; and so on. All
of these beliefs, and many more, are constructed by the children from their
precultural social experience.
Similarly, as a consequence of their social interactions, and/or the beliefs
to which they give rise, precultural children also acquire any number of
desires: desires, for example, to eat certain things and avoid others; to
perform certain acts, but inhibit others; to achieve certain goals, but eschew
others; to comply with some demands, but violate others; to imitate certain
persons, but refrain from imitating others; to display some feelings, but
suppress others; and so on. All of these desires, and many more, are
socially, but not culturally, acquired.
It is clearly misleading to refer to any of the previously mentioned beliefs
and desires as culturally determined when, in fact, they are not determined
by culture at all. Instead, they are socially determined, in the sense of being
either caused or shaped by children’s social (but precultural) experience. It
might be argued, of course, that insofar as the behavior of parents and
others is governed by cultural norms and values, and insofar as they express
these norms and values in their interaction with their precultural children,
then although the children’s social experience may be the direct and
proximal cause of their beliefs and desires, nevertheless culture is the
indirect and distal cause. Such an argument, however, is valid to only a
limited degree.
Consider, for example, the socialization of aggression. Thus, even on the
assumption, for example, that parents and other socializers respond to the
aggressive action of children with physical punishment as a means to
inculcating cultural values regarding aggression, nevertheless it is unlikely
that from this punitive experience the children internalize such values at all.
For while it is likely that as a consequence of this experience they inhibit
their subsequent aggressive desires, it is also likely that it arouses anger and
fear in the children who, consequently, construct the belief that their
socializers are oppressive, and acquire the desire to aggress against them
(which, from fear, they probably repress).
As a consequence of their social experience, children may acquire a set
of cognitions and motivations which, not so paradoxically, are the very
opposite of the cultural values and norms that their socializers intended to
inculcate. According to personality studies, moreover, these cognitions and
motivations persist, whether consciously or unconsciously, as more or less
durable components of their character structure. Thus, in our example, as
the children become adults they may displace onto other authority figures
their belief that parents and other socializers are oppressive, and they may
express their feelings of anger and hostility to them by similarly displacing
them onto these transference objects. A similar process operates mutatis
mutantis in the case of experientially acquired prosocial cognitions and
motivations.
Let us now summarize this discussion of the terms “culture” and
“cultural determinism.” Formerly, when it was employed globally, “culture”
designated at one and the same time a social group, the customary behavior
patterns of the group, and its traditional ideas, values, and norms. Since this
polysemic usage was too heavy a semantic load for one and the same term
to carry, latterly most anthropologists have come to employ “culture” to
designate the third referent only.
This restricted meaning of the term “culture” entails that the expression
“cultural determinism” should correspondingly be restricted to the shared
behavioral and psychological characteristics of social actors that they
acquire as a consequence of the transmission of the traditional values,
norms, and ideas of their social group. Given this restricted, and logically
consistent, meaning of “cultural determinism,” the persistent
anthropological claim that virtually all of a group’s nontrivial behavioral
and psychological characteristics are culturally determined is clearly
invalid, for a large share of these characteristics are not culturally, but
biologically or socially determined.
Even, however, in this restricted meaning, “cultural determinism” is a
confusing expression because it is used not only in reference to those
psychological and behavioral characteristics that are caused by culture, but
also in reference to those that are shaped by it, as well as to any number of
purely symbolic entities that are constructed by culture, and are therefore
constituted by it.
By viewing all nontrivial characteristics of social actors as determined by
culture, thereby precluding any biological and social determinants, and by
conflating the separate concepts of constitute, cause, and shape, many
anthropologists (and other social scientists) claim that virtually everything
in the human world is culturally determined. I shall return to this concept of
wholesale cultural determinism below, but first it is necessary to examine
the concept of cultural relativism.
Like “cultural determinism,” the expression “cultural relativism” is used
in a number of different, and confusing, ways. Thus, although it is
frequently used to denote the fact that the cultural ideas, values, and norms
of any one group may importantly differ from that of any other group, this
usage confuses cultural relativism with cultural diversity. To say, for
example, that religious ideas, family values, and sexual norms are culturally
diverse is one thing, but to say that they are culturally relative is quite
another, for whereas “cultural diversity” denotes a (well-documented) fact,
“cultural relativism” denotes a (controversial) judgment regarding that fact.
Moreover, even when “cultural relativism” is used in the latter (and only
proper) sense, this expression is still confusing, because in current usage it
denotes not one, but three judgments, which might be termed “descriptive,”
“normative,” and “epistemological,” respectively. Since elsewhere (Spiro
1986, 1992: chapter 1) I have explicated the meanings of these judgments in
some detail, here I shall describe them only briefly.
If, as the Oxford English Dictionary puts it, “relative” means “arising
from, depending on, or determined by relation to something else,” then
descriptive cultural relativism might refer to two very different judgments:
(a) the judgment that the diversity in cultural variables (traditional ideas,
values, and norms) across social groups is a function of the diversity in
noncultural variables (ecology, biology, subsistence economy, and the like);
(b) the judgment that the diversity in social and psychological variables
(social behavior, motivation, cognition, emotions, and the like) across social
groups is a function of the diversity in cultural variables.
Because most contemporary culture theorists, with the exception of
cultural materialists, reject the first judgment (wrongly in my view) on the
grounds that it is materialist or reductionist, it is only the second to which I
shall refer to here as “descriptive” cultural relativism. Accordingly, as a
judgment regarding the fact of cultural diversity, its claim is not that culture
is relative, but that the diverse social and psychological characteristics of
different social groups are culturally relative, in short, that their diversity is
dependent upon, and exists in relation to, the diverse cultures of these
different groups.
Since any judgment, whether explicitly or implictly, is based of course on
some theory, it is now perhaps obvious that descriptive cultural relativism is
based on the theory of cultural determinism (in one or all of the senses
distinguished above). I shall return to this point below after examining the
other two types of cultural relativism.
Normative cultural relativism (like descriptive relativism) also consists of
two judgments regarding cultural diversity which may be stated as follows.
First, because evaluative norms are culturally diverse, and hence any
evaluation of different cultures on a scale of merit or worth is ethnocentric,
the only valid judgment that can be made regarding such variable cultural
systems as religion, science, ethics, kinship, and the like, is that none is
better or worse than any other. They are only different. Second, because any
evaluation of the mental and emotional characteristics of different social
groups is perforce similarly ethnocentric, the only valid judgment that can
be made regarding their logical ability, emotional maturity, and the like, is
that no group is superior or inferior, either intellectually or emotionally, to
any other. They are only different.
Since these claims of normative relativism are critically evaluated in
chapter 2 (though for a more recent, and far-searching critique, see
Edgerton 1992) it would be redundant to repeat my criticisms here. Instead,
I shall proceed directly to the third type of cultural relativism,
epistemological relativism.
A recent arrival, epistemological relativism takes its point of departure
from (what might be termed) the “strong” form of descriptive relativism, a
form which combines a radical view of cultural diversity (the view that the
latter is virtually limitless, so that every culture is unique in the nontrivial
sense of being incommensurate with any other) with wholesale cultural
determinism. From these premises, epistemological relativism draws two
far-reaching epistemological conclusions: (a) panhuman generalizations
regarding culture, human behavior, and the human psyche are likely to be
vacuous, if not false and (b) panhuman theories of culture, human behavior,
and the human psyche are likely to be trivial, if not invalid.
Although these conclusions are logically valid, nevertheless in my view
they are false because, as I have argued elsewhere (Spiro 1992: chapters 1
and 2), their premises (wholesale cultural determinism and radical cultural
diversity) are false. I shall return to this substantive argument below, but
here I wish to make a methodological observation.
Rather than constituting an unbridgable obstacle to the discovery of
nonvacuous generalization and nontrivial theories, as epistemological
relativism claims, cultural and psychological diversity constitute, instead,
an unparalleled opportunity for their discovery. Thus, by the application of
Mill’s canons of similarity and difference to comparative ethnographic data,
anthropology has been able to forge a powerful method for formulating, as
well as testing, generalizations and theories, a method by which some of
them have been confirmed, and others disconfirmed. For an inventory and a
summary discussion of these findings, see Levinson and Malone (1980), as
well as some of the other references cited below.
Based on the foregoing discussion of cultural determinism and cultural
relativism, we may turn, finally, to the second term comprising the title of
this book, “human nature.” Although for many years I had been interested
in the philosophical relevance of the problem of human nature, I had not
developed an interest in its anthropological relevance until 1952, when I
was invited by A.I. Hallowell to present a paper (Spiro 1954) to a
symposium on that question to the annual meeting of the American
Anthropological Association.
Although from its very beginning, American anthropology had a special
interest in the parameters of human nature (Boas 1911), Hallowell’s
decision to organize this symposium was motivated by Robert Redfield’s
response to a paper by Hallowell (1953) on culture and personality, in the
course of which which he, Redfield, had remarked, “In this territory we find
ourselves characterizing human nature as a recognized and subject matter of
our science….” (quoted in Hallowell:1976: 224).
Now if someone, like Redfield, who was hardly known for an interest in
human psychology, had come to recognize the anthropological importance
of the concept of human nature, then—so Hallowell observed in his
introduction to the symposium—the time had come to publically reassess
the anthropological relevance of this concept. And to better promote such a
reassessment, he invited representatives from various subfields of
anthropology—Walter Goldschmidt, G.P. Murdock, S. L. Washburn, and
myself—to participate in the symposium.
Unlike these participants who, like many other members of their
anthropological generation, viewed the concept of human nature—or, as
many of them preferred, “the psychic unity of mankind” (e.g., Kroeber
1948, Wallace 1961)—as indispensable for understanding the mutually
reciprocal relationships among human biology, psychology, society, and
culture, many contemporary anthropologists reject this concept. Their
rejection is based on two arguments.
First, since nature and culture are binary opposites, with the emergence
of culture the latter has virtually become the sole determinant of the human
psyche which, in turn, has come to transcend nature. That being the case,
the concept of a human nature is both “essentialist” and “reduction-ist.”
Second, even though culture is virtually the sole determinant of the human
psyche, nevertheless given the wide diversity in culture, rather than a
common human psyche, there are only culturally parochial and diverse
psyches.
Consider, for example, Geertz’s comment on the psychological
differences that (presumably as a function of their subcultural differences)
distinguish the various categories of actors—scholars, artists, scientists,
professionals, and administrators—comprising the American academic
world. These actors, Geertz (1983:160) writes, “are radically different not
just in their opinions, or even in their passions, but in the very foundations
of their experience.”
If because of their subcultural differences, the actors comprising one
category of only one subgroup of a single society are radically different in
their psychological characteristics from the actors comprising the other
categories of that subgroup, then afortiori the psychological differences
across these subgroups must be even more radical, while the psychological
differences across societies (given the magnitude of their cultural
differences) must be more radical still. Indeed, for the proponents of radical
cultural diversity, the alleged incommensurability of cultures entails a
corresponding incommensurability in the human psyche.
Let us evaluate these two arguments for rejecting the concept of a
panhuman nature, beginning with the first. That nature and culture are
mutually exclusive concepts is a notion that I would have thought had been
laid to rest many years ago, not only by philosophers such as John Dewey
(1929), but also by generations of anthropologists (both cultural and
biological) who have argued that because we are a generalized, plastic, and
instinctless species, culture is our species-specific mode of adaptation. In
short, culture is to a human mode of existence what the biological
specializations of other species are to infrahuman modes of existence.
If culture is an adaptive requirement of our species, then culture and its
psychological (cognitive, motivational, and emotional) products are no less
a part of human nature than the human biological organism and its
psychological products.
But even granting this point, still that would not entail, according to
many contemporary anthropologists, that there is a panhuman nature.
Although culture, as they view it, is virtually the sole determinant of the
human psyche, nevertheless since there is not one culture, but many diverse
cultures, so also there are many diverse human psyches. As Shweder
(1990:2) has put it, the differences among cultures result “less in psychic
unity for humankind than in ethnic divergences in mind, self, and
emotions.”
This, however, is a straw man argument because the concept of psychic
unity never meant, as Shweder presumably takes it to mean, that all human
groups possess identical psychological characteristics, but rather that they
possess a common (and critical) subset of them (Kroeber 1948:00, Wallace
1961). As Hallowell put it,
man is characterized by a unique psychic structure the generic form of which we have only begun
to discern in the common features that underlie the range and variation of personality structure
that have been empirically investigated in recent years. (Hallowell 1955:5, my italics)
And again,
The distinctive psychological structuralization of men, the novel qualitative features that
characterize the psychodynamic of a human level of adjustment, combined with the generic
capabilities of man that are rooted in the phylogenetic status of our species, lie at the very core of
our human nature. (Hallowell 1976:227).
As these passages indicate, for Hallowell (and his colleagues) the concept
of a universal human nature is, in the first instance, an inevitable
consequence of the findings of biological evolution, according to which all
human beings, having evolved from a common primate ancestor, comprise
a single biological species. On the assumption now that our biology is not
totally irrelevant for our psychological functioning, then it can be presumed
that as members of a single species all human beings share a set of
biologically determined psychological characteristics which comprise one,
but only one, component of a common human nature.
Granted that we evolved from an early African primate (and that even
today we share approximately 98 percent of our molecular DNA with
contemporary African chimpanzees and gorillas), still it is not our simian,
but our hominid phylogeny that accounts for the specifically human (as
opposed to the simian) component of human nature. In this regard I would
emphasize, in addition to the frequently mentioned expansion of the
hominid brain (which accounts, in the largest part, for the critically
important cognitive dimension of a uniquely human nature), prolonged
infantile dependency and the suppression of estrus.
I single out these two biological characteristics in particular because,
jointly, they probably account for some of the most important social
characteristics of our species, including the relatively permanent biparental
family, the prolonged and bisexual socialization of children, and intrafamily
incest avoidance. These characteristics of human social systems, in turn, are
critical for the emergence of human nature because, arguably, they are the
most important social determinants of the human psyche (particularly its
emotional and motivational dimensions) which, as some anthropologists
have argued, are no less important than its biological determinants. Once
again Hallowell:
The distinctive psychological organization of the human being, whether described as mind or
personality structure, is just as much a function of his membership in a [homind type] social
group as it is a function of his inherited organic equipment. (Hallowell 1955:5)
References
Arnheim, Rudolf. 1988. Universals in the arts. Journal of Social and
Biological Structures 11:60–65.
Boas, Franz. 1911. The mind of primitive man. New York: Macmillan.
Brown, Donald E. 1991. Human Universals. New York, McGraw-Hill.
D’Andrade, Roy G. 1992. Toward a Theory of Emotion and Culture.
Ms.
Davenport, William H. 1987. The cultural anthropology of sex:
Description (ethnography) and comparison (ethnology). In
Theories of human sexuality, James H. Geer and William T.
O’Donohue, eds., 197–236. New York: Plenum.
Edgerton, Robert B. 1992. Sick societies: Challenging the myth of
primitive harmony. New York: The Free Press.
Geertz, Clifford. 1983. Local knowledge. New York: Basic Books.
Hallowell, A. Irving. 1955. Culture and experience. Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press.
---------. 1976. Contributions to anthropology.. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Hockett, C.F., 1973. Man’s place in nature. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Kluckhohn, Clyde. 1953. Universal categories of culture. In
Anthropology today: An encyclopedic inventory, 507–23. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
______. 1959. Common humanity and diverse cultures. In The human
meaning of the social sciences, Daniel Lemer, ed., 245–284. New
York: Meridian.
Kroeber, A.L. 1948. Anthropology. New York: Harcourt Brace and
Company.
La Barre, Weston. 1954. The human animal. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Levinson, David and Martin J. Malone. 1980. Toward explaining
human culture. New Haven: HRAF Press.
Lloyd, Barbara, and John Gay, eds. 1981. Universals of human
thought: Some african evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Murdock, George Peter. 1945. The common denominator of cultures.
In The science of man in the world crisis, Ralph Linton, ed., 123—
42. New York: Columbia University Press.
Shweder, Richard A. 1990. Cultural psychology—What is it? In
Cultural psychology: Essays on comparative human development,
James E. Stigler, Richard A. Shweder, and Gilbert Herdt, eds., 1–
46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Spiro, Melford E. 1954. Human nature in its psychological
dimensions. American Anthropologist 56:19–30.
---------. 1986. Cultural relativism and the future of anthropology.
Cultural Anthropology 1:259–86, 1986.
---------. 1992. Anthropological other or Burmese brother: Studies in
cultural analysis. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
Stall, Frits. 1988. Universals: Studies in Indian Logic and Linguistics.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Tiger, Lionel, and Robin Fox. 1971. The Imperial animal. New York:
Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Wallace, Anthony F.C. 1961. Culture and personality. New York:
Random House.
Editors’ Introduction
IN THIS volume are assembled for the first time twelve of the finest
theoretical papers of Melford E. Spiro, one of the most distinguished figures
in anthropology today. Professor Spiro founded the department of
anthropology at the University of California, San Diego, where he is
currently Presidential professor of anthropology. A member of the National
Academy of Sciences, he combines long-standing interest in the
philosophical problems of human existence with extensive anthropological
fieldwork. In short, he is perhaps the most prominent figure in the country
in psychological anthropology and culture and personality, and clearly one
of the outstanding scholars in the areas of social and cultural theory.
This collection of papers, spanning the years between 1961 and 1984,
appropriately demonstrates Spiro’s contributions to the exploration of
human nature and culture. It also addresses the fundamental issues of
cultural relativism, the problem of explanation in the study of culture, and
the anthropological study of religion and belief systems. Grouped according
to theme rather than chronology, these papers have been selected and
arranged so as to give a comprehensive view of Professor Spiro’s
theoretical works.
During the course of his career Spiro has developed a coherent and
systematic body of theory modified by fieldwork, experience, and changes
of mind. This body of theory has over the years provided him with a
framework within which to develop his ideas and pursue various research
projects in the field. Thus Spiro stands out as a scholar of unusual integrity,
at once capable of changing his mind, of modifying his theories in the light
of evidence, and of far-reaching efforts to understand the human condition.
With an eye for well-constructed arguments, he incorporates ideas from a
wide variety of sources.
One of the most fundamental emphases in Spiro’s work has been on the
need to consider both psychological and cultural forces and structures as
part of any explanation of human behavior. In fact, a strong case can be
made for the ineluctable necessity of doing this in the explanation of all
behavior, although some anthropologists and sociologists would either deny
or ignore it. Anthropologists inevitably employ psychological theories and
premises whether or not they admit to doing so. As S. F. Nadel once put it,
they “sneak them in through the back door.” Psychological factors are,
Spiro holds, an explicit and necessary part of any adequate theory of culture
and human action. Indeed, it is difficult to see how a genuine and useful
theory of culture could persist in the absence of an attempt to integrate
within it a theory of the human mind. Spiro stands out as a foremost
American anthropologist who has not wavered in his efforts to address the
problems of human nature, and who has systematically linked theories of
psychological motivation with social structure and belief systems.
The reader will note that Spiro consistently uses elements of
psychoanalytic theory in his explanations and in his own theoretical
constructions. While essentially a proponent of the ethnographic method,
Spiro nonetheless holds that there are deep motivational structures
underlying all human behavior, rational and irrational alike. His emphasis
on psychoanalytic theory, which entails a theory of panhuman nature,
constitutes one of the most fundamental thrusts of this book and, indeed, of
Spiro’s work in general. Thus, although psychoanalytic theory traditionally
has been criticized and often dismissed by anthropologists, who assume that
it is culturally relative and therefore of no use in ethnographic fieldwork
and interpretation, Spiro makes it one of the keystones of his theorizing and
methodology. He argues that psychoanalysis provides the best available
coherent body of theory linking the (panhuman) structure of the family to
concepts of individual motivation, on the one hand, and to concepts of
culture and social organization, on the other. For example, in his Oedipus in
the Trobriands Spiro demonstrates that the conclusions reached by
Malinowski were far too hastily drawn. Spiro’s reanalysis of Malinowski’s
material shows that there is an Oedipal constellation in the Trobriands,
whereas Malinowski’s work, Sex and Repression in Savage Societies, is
commonly assumed to have proven there is not. Thus Spiro contends that
the Oedipal complex can be used to explain Malinowski’s Trobriand data
with distinctly more parsimony and comprehensiveness than Malinowski
employs in his theoretical revision of Freud.
In the first section, on human nature and culture, Spiro’s debt to Freudian
theory stands out clearly. While disagreeing with sociobiologists, he
emphasizes the need for a theory of human nature implying panhuman
psychological characteristics rooted in early childhood experience. Such
psychological characteristics are, Spiro demonstrates, indispensable in
understanding both anthropological questions and anthropological data.
In his interest in theories of human nature, Spiro resembles his friend and
mentor, A. Irving Hallowell. The affinity between the two writers is
palpable also in the second section of this book, where Spiro deals with
motivations for the performance of roles defined as culturally important.
Such sober doggedness in pursuing questions of rather fundamental
significance characterizes both Hallowell and Spiro, and distinguishes these
two writers from more fickle and sometimes also more popular
contemporaries.
Notions of human nature and culture do not stay put in any bed of
Procrustean theory, whether of functionalism, structuralism,
environmentalism, or of the superorganic. Because of this, these notions are
better addressed directly and honestly than indirectly by way of whatever
theories happen to be popular or appealing at the moment. Spiro has built
his career largely on direct and forthright attempts to deal with the questions
of human nature and culture, personality, and cultural values and beliefs,
and he has sought to grasp these questions in all their complexity.
The first section of this book, Culture and Human Nature, includes
papers representing Spiro’s emphasis on a theory of human nature grounded
in individual needs. The opening chapter, as well as those which follow,
speak to the tendency in American anthropology toward both materialism
and economic determinism. Spiro energetically criticizes the radical cultural
relativism and determinism which he sees as characterizing much American
anthropology. He has argued consistently over the past thirty years for the
importance of a theory of human nature rooted in individual human needs,
yet seen in terms of the perceptual configurations and meanings of symbols
and symbol systems in specific societies at particular times.
In “Some Reflections on Cultural Determinism and Relativism…
(chapter 2), for instance, Spiro disputes the claims of cultural relativists by
linking personality to culture as well as by refusing to concede that
personality can ever be reducible to culture. Insisting on the psychological
basis for the persistence of religious beliefs and cultural institutions, he also
challenges the claims of the cultural materialists. Moreover, he strongly
emphasizes both culture and human nature as manifested by the dynamics
of the Oedipus complex and the nature of the human family. For Spiro,
human nature (panhuman psychological characteristics) results from the
interaction of phylogenetically determined biological (inherited)
characteristics, and the functional requirements of any social system. As all
human social systems depend upon the biparental family, it is in such
families that the child’s basic cognitive and motivational orientations are
molded. Therefore, it is on these orientations that all social systems depend.
In this sense, Spiro demonstrates that in fundamental respects the problem
of the locus of culture is a specious one.
“Preculture and Gender” examines concepts of gender identity in kibbutz
members. Whereas in works written earlier Spiro held that gender identity
could be learned, in this chapter he explicitly holds that it cannot be
understood merely in terms of learned roles. Spiro’s change in emphasis is
the direct result of fieldwork and his growing conviction that learning
theory, while valuable, is not enough to account for what he saw in the
kibbutz. A theory of human nature, of the human family, and of the ways in
which families respond to human needs was required.
This theme (of the necessity of developing a theory of human nature and
culture) is further elaborated in chapter 4, “Is the Oedipus Complex
Universal?” In this paper Spiro argues that the Oedipus complex is
structurally invariable (i.e., an expression of invariant features of the human
family on the one hand, and of early stages of emotional cognitive
development on the other). However, he points out, the Oedipus complex is
variable when viewed functionally or culturally. The same material
Malinowski relied upon has been reinterpreted convincingly by Spiro to
demonstrate the presence of an Oedipus complex in the Trobriands as well
as elsewhere.
Beginnings
In an important sense, my intellectual interests have always been more
philosophical than scientific, and just as in the Middle Ages philosophy was
the handmaiden of theology, so for me anthropology has been the
handmaiden of philosophy, a tool for the empirical investigation of some
central issues concerning the nature of man. Although I have worked in four
different societies—the Ojibwa, Ifaluk, an Israeli kibbutz, and Burma—I
have never been interested in ethnographic description, per se; and although
I have published on a variety of institutions—family, kinship, politics,
socialization, and religion—I have had little interest in institutional
analysis, as such. Ultimately—so, at least, I have believed—these
enterprises are useful to the degree that they can illuminate some aspect of
the nature of man. Since, however, anthropology is primarily interested in
society and culture, and since until recently it has been much more
concerned with social and cultural differences than with universals, my
choice of anthropology—rather than, for example, psychology—might
seem rather strange. In the light, however, of the intellectual and political
Zeitgeist of the intellectually formative years of my life, this choice was not
so strange after all.
For liberal intellectuals, like myself, coming to maturity in the late
thirties and early forties, politics was an overriding concern. Existentialists
without knowing it, we had to come to grips with the twin traumata of our
time—the great depression at home, and the rise of Fascism abroad. Having
escaped the seductions of Soviet Communism, while yet deploring the
“poverty amidst plenty” which seemed to be characteristic of capitalism, we
perceived in democratic socialism the only viable alternative to the horrors
of both Fascist and Communist totalitarianism. As Marxists—and, in some
sense, we were all Marxists in those days—we believed that men were the
creatures of their social systems. If American society was characterized (as
we thought) by competitiveness, exploitation, and injustice, these
characteristics were not expressions of human nature, but of a particular
social system. Hence, to abolish these evils it was only necessary to change
the social system that produced them. In a social system, such as
democratic socialism, whose institutions were based on equality and justice,
they would disappear.
If Marxism was the ideological inspiration for these convictions, their
intellectual underpinnings, at least for me, were derived from my
philosophical studies. As a philosophy major, I had been persuaded—to be
sure, I was prepared to be persuaded—by Locke, Hume, Rousseau, and the
philosophers of the Enlightenment that man comes into the world as a
tabula rasa; that anything that is eventually inscribed on the blank slate is
put there by experience; and (though this was not shared by all these
thinkers) that the most important types of experience are those derived from
encounters with social institutions. Hence, the notion of a society in which
men are motivated by cooperation, altruism, and mutual aid was not viewed
as a utopian quest—nor was it viewed as a secular derivative of the
religious visions of Amos or Isaiah, those Hebrew prophets who had earlier
influenced me—but as a logical deduction from the social theories of the
eighteenth century philosophers of Reason. For if, indeed, man has no
“nature,” then his characteristics must be a product of history, as the latter is
distilled by and concretized in the social institutions of his society.
But the capstone—and “proof’!—of the thesis of the malleability of man,
and the omnipotence of social institutions, came from the writings of
Durkheim, for Durkheim (as I viewed him) was not just another speculative
philosopher; he was, rather, an empirical scientist. And if, as he had shown
in The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life, the very forms of thought
(space, time, causality, etc.) are ultimately derived from the structure of
society, what else could be said on the subject? Durkheim, though a
sociologist, had used anthropological data to sustain his arguments. This
convinced me that it was from anthropology that I could best derive future
intellectual nourishment, and when some years later I decided to pursue
graduate studies in the social sciences, I turned to anthropology.
Although I earlier discovered Durkheim was not in good favor in
anthropology—mostly because of Goldenweiser’s critique of his theory of
totemism—the regnant anthropological notions of that time were entirely
consistent with (indeed, they might just as well have been derived from)
Durkheim’s view of society and culture. Still, these notions—cultural
determinism and cultural relativism—provided a different conceptual, as
well as rhetorical, basis for my views concerning the relationship between
man and society. Since cultures vary across space and time, and since
behavior is culturally variable, the inference that man’s nature is similarly
culturally variable seemed irrefutable. The concept of culture not only
seemed to provide the definitive refutation of the notion of a universal
human nature, but it appeared to be a refined tool for understanding group
differences in behavior. Unlike the vague and rather metaphysical concept
of social or historical “forces,” the concept of culture could not only be
broken down into observable units of empirical investigation, but it
generated theories which seemed to account for group differences. (The
culture theories of the time were inadequate to account for cultural
invention, change, or deviance, but I did not perceive this as impugning
their validity.)
Having discovered anthropology, I lost whatever interest I might
otherwise have had in sociology or psychology. Focused on only one
cultural variant—that of Western man—the findings of sociology, so it
seemed to me, could shed little light on Man. Similarly, psychology, with its
concern with subcultural psychological processes (learning, perception,
cognition, and the like) as they could be studied in the laboratory, also
seemed unlikely to shed important light on Man. Its findings were based
either on the study of lower animals who, since they had no culture, seemed
inappropriate models for the study of humans; or, they were based on the
study of Western subjects, and since, as I believed, psychological processes
are culturally shaped, these findings seemed culture-bound. Anthropology,
on the other hand, seemed admirably suited to my interests. If man is the
creature of culture, then the proper study of man, so 1 believed, is the study
of culture; and since culture is variable, then the proper study of Man is the
study of culture in all of its variability. If, moreover, each culture (as Ruth
Benedict had argued in her seductive metaphor) has carved out a different
arc from the total circle of cultural variability, and if (as she also contended)
each primitive culture constitutes a natural experiment in cultural
variability, then it further followed that the proper study of cultural
variability entailed the study of primitive cultures. For me, then,
anthropology was clearly the science of choice. This being so, it is
important to sketch in greater detail the dominant anthropological notions
concerning culture and human nature of that time, notions to which I and
most of my contemporaries became, if we were not already, committed.
Since human behavior is culturally determined, and since cultures vary
enormously, the only valid generalization that can be made about human
nature is that it is enormously malleable (“plastic”). The existence of
cultural universals does not require any qualification of this conclusion
since culture, being “superorganic,” does not reflect (and, hence, cannot be
“reduced” to) noncultural, panhuman, biological or psychological attributes.
Although, so far as biology is concerned, such anatomical attributes as hair
form, eye color, and so on, are biologically determined (subject of course to
cultural selection), biology has little, if any, determination on social
behavior. Since the latter can be explained, without residue, by cultural
determinants, the organism, like the psyche, is conceived as either an
“empty” or a “black box.” Since, according to one “empty box” model,
culture affects behavior by a kind of Newtonian action-at-a-distance, the
box remains perpetually empty. According to a second model, however, the
empty box does not long remain empty for, as a consequence of
“enculturation,” the external culture is somehow incorporated by the social
actors. Nevertheless, since the resultant “inside” (psychological)
determinants of behavior are merely the “outside” (cultural) determinants
that have become “internalized,” and since, therefore, they vary as culture
varies, these psychological determinants can hardly constitute the basis for
a species-specific human nature. The “black box” differs from these two
“empty box” models in that it does not deny the existence of “inside”
variables; it merely denies their influence on social behavior. Since the
latter, so the argument goes, is culturally variable, how can it be explained
by biological or psychological determinants which are constant? Hence,
even if these “inside” variables may be said to constitute or to determine a
species-specific human nature, the latter is irrelevant to the understanding
of man’s social behavior.
Whatever the differences among these three models, it will be noted that
all agree (if only by implication) there can be no conflict between the
individual and culture. If there is nothing inside the individual (the first
model), or if what is inside is either orthogonal to, or represents the
internalization of, culture (the third and second models respectively), then
the individual and culture are in a state of harmony. That is, what the
individual wants to do is identical with what his culture requires him to do.
It should also be noted that although all three models explain behavior by
reference to culture, culture itself is left unexplained. To explain culture by
reference to some set of biological and psychological determinants
(construed as the core, or nucleus, of human nature) is not only inconsistent
with the empty and black box models, but it illustrates the fallacy of
“reductionism.” (For unexplained reasons, reductionism was taken to be a
self-evident fallacy.) Hence, like Aristotle’s First Cause, culture remains an
Unmoved Mover. To be sure, since culture is in large part a symbolic
system, man must everywhere have the capacity to invent, transmit, and
acquire cultural symbols, and to that extent symbolization is to be included
with plasticity as a second attribute of human nature. (Indeed, functionally
or adaptively viewed, symbolization is to human plasticity what instinct is
to animal specificity.) But since symbolization is culturally variable, the
universality of symbolic processes does not imply the universality of
symbolic meanings. Hence, so far as content is concerned, there is no
universal human nature; there are only culturally specific—and therefore
culturally variable—character structures.
Lest the above conceptions be used as a handle for racist arguments, the
concept of cultural relativism—according to which all cultures, and
therefore all culturally variable character structures, are equally valuable—
was enlisted to do battle against racist notions in general, and the notion of
primitive mentality, in particular. It should be noted, however, that cultural
relativism was also used, at least by some anthropologists, to perpetuate a
kind of inverted racism. That is, it was used as a powerful tool of cultural
criticism, with the consequent derogation of Western culture and of the
mentality which it produced. Espousing the philosophy of primitivism—
akin to, but not identical with, Rousseau’s notion of the Noble Savage—the
image of primitive man was used by some few anthropologists as a vehicle
for the pursuit of personal utopian quests, and/or as a fulcrum to express
personal discontent with Western man and Western society. The strategies
adopted took various forms, of which the following are fairly
representative: (1) attempts to abolish private property, or inequality, or
aggression in Western societies have a reasonably realistic chance of
success since such states of affairs may be found in many primitive
societies; (2) compared to at least some primitives, Western man is uniquely
competitive, warlike, intolerant of deviance, sexist, and so on; (3) paranoia
is not necessarily an illness, because paranoid thinking is institutionalized in
certain primitive societies; homosexuality is not deviant because
homosexuals are the cultural cynosures of some primitive societies;
monogamy is not viable because polygamy is the most frequent form of
marriage in primitive societies. Needless to say, the anthropologists of that
period were neither the first, nor—as recent politically motivated
resolutions advocated at meetings of the American Anthropological
Association indicate—the last to use anthropological “findings” as
“scientific” support for personal and political weltanschauungen.
Qualifications
Although many years were to pass before I finally discarded as untenable
many of the ideas described in the previous section, the corrosive process
began when I encountered the theories of A. I. Hallowell, my mentor at
Northwestern University, and (through him) psychoanalytic and learning
theory. From Hallowell’s writings and teachings I came to realize that
culture does not impinge directly on behavior, but is mediated through
personality processes relating to individuals. The contours of these
processes, I came to believe, were best delineated by Freud. It was the work
of Kardiner, however, that persuaded me of the importance of the family
and of socialization in the formation of these processes. From Kardiner, too,
I became convinced of the importance of “projective systems” for the
understanding of those aspects of culture that are not “reality” based. There
remained, however, a missing ingredient. If social actors monitor their own
behavior in accordance with cultural norms and rules, it was necessary to
explain the acquisition of culture in each generation of social actors. Here,
the social learning theorists—and especially Miller and Dollard—provided
the key.
Hence, when I completed graduate work, my theoretical framework
comprised an inchoate synthesis of cultural determinism, and cultural
relativism, neo-Freudian personality theory, and social learning theory. In
this loosely integrated synthesis, culture was viewed as a kind of master
plan for group adaptation; it was transmitted primarily in the family, and in
the early years of life, by traditional methods of socialization and
enculturation; it was acquired as part of the personality by techniques of
social reinforcement; its acquisition (“internalization”), however, often
conflicted with and frustrated other personality “needs”; the conflict was
resolved by the disguised satisfaction of these needs through culturally
mediated symbolic systems (“projective systems”).
It will be noticed that this synthesis, by including explicit attention to
“personality,” represented an important qualification of my earlier thinking.
But this shift from a cultural to a culture-personality framework did not
alter my earlier notions concerning human nature; on the contrary, it
strengthened them. For, although influenced by psychoanalytic thought, the
main thrust of the culture-personality school was precisely the reverse of
psychoanalysis. While the latter postulated invariant stages and processes
(and even invariant symbol formations and symbolic meanings) in the
formation, structure, and functioning of personality, culture-personality
(with some important exceptions) was primarily concerned to demonstrate
their cultural variability. Since, according to this school, personality was
determined by and constituted the internalization of culture, the range of
personality variability across groups could hardly be smaller than the range
of cultural variability. Indeed, since personality characteristics and
personality configurations, respectively, were viewed as isomorphic with
cultural characteristics and cultural patterns, the notion of a pancultural
human nature was viewed as highly unlikely. On the contrary, it was
assumed as almost self-evident that Zunis, Germans, Hawaiians, and Thais
are much more different, not only in culture but also in personality, than
they are similar.
These, then, were the views which I took with me on my first field trip—
to the atoll of Ifaluk in the Central Carolines.
Conclusions
Having described how I gradually and painfully came to discard much of
the received anthropological wisdom, I now wish to explore (what I
consider to have been) the fallacies in traditional anthropological thinking
that led to the adoption of cultural determinism and, hence, to the cultural
relativistic view of human nature.
I have already noted that in the traditional conception, “culture” referred
to all aspects of a group’s environment, except the physical, and to all
aspects of man, except the biological. Given, then, that man constitutes a
single biological species and that, nevertheless, social behavior reveals a
wide range of cross-cultural variability, it seemed to follow that the
organism is an empty or a black box, and that social behavior, therefore, is
determined by culture. Given, too, that personality characteristics were
believed to exist in a one-to-one relationship with behavioral
characteristics, the former being thought to be directly deducible from the
latter, it seemed to follow that personality is also culturally determined. This
meant that no psychological characteristic—no affect, no need, no wish, no
belief—could be part of human personality unless culture put it there.
Given, moreover, that culture is variable, personality (it was further argued)
must similarly be variable; historically specific cultures produce culturally
variable personality characteristics. Given, finally, that depending on their
culture, human beings may acquire any empirical subset of the total
conceivable set of human psychological characteristics, any member of the
latter set (it was concluded) is culturally relative; none is an invariant
characteristic of a universal human nature. Any psychological characteristic
—the feeling of love or hate, the wish for mortality or immortality, the
belief in the talion principle or its reverse—might or might not be found in
any social group as a function of its cultural program.
Skipping over some logical and empirical problems in its global3 and
holistic4 conception of culture, this conceptual structure falters, I believe,
on two related, but separable, theses, both of which are (I believe)
untenable. These are: (1) culture is the exclusive determinant of personality;
and (2) personality consists exclusively of the internalization of culture. Let
us begin with the first.
3. The logical problem raised by the global conception of culture is easily stated. If culture
includes (among other things) behavioral patterns and personality traits, to say that culture
determines behavior and personality is obviously circular. Although this difficulty is easily resolved
—by excluding behavior and personality from the definition of “culture” and thereby rendering the
culture concept less global—yet another problem with respect to personality remains. For if
personality is not part of culture, and, moreover, if personality (as we shall see below) is not
isomorphic with behavior—if, on the contrary, personality is viewed as a system of cognitive,
perceptual, motivational, and affective dispositions “underlying” behavior—it cannot be so blithely
assumed that cultural (and, therefore, behavioral) variability is associated with personality variability.
This latter thesis now becomes an empirical hypothesis, to be tested by direct examination of
personality, rather than an a priori assumption whose proof consists in pointing to the cross-cultural
variability in behavior. In short, if personality is not, merely by definition, a part of culture, and if the
isomorphism of personality and behavior is not accepted as an unchallenged assumption, then the
question of pancultural psychological characteristics remains open.
4. The empirical problem raised by the holistic conception of culture is also easily stated for, given
this conception, it is difficult to know which of the various elements comprising a culture are the
determinants of personality: Art styles? Religious beliefs? Descent systems? Modes of production?
Child rearing? Some of these? All of these? In short, so long as culture is taken as an undifferentiated
whole, a seamless web, the thesis of cultural determination of personality is not very illuminating,
since (even in the now restricted conception of culture) the only things that are excluded as possible
determinants are characteristics of the organism and of the physical environment. Even Margaret
Mead, much of whose work has concentrated on (and has illuminated so much of) the relationship
between child training and personality, has disclaimed any notion that the former is an especially
important cultural determinant; rather, she claims, it is merely a convenient way of entering into the
total configuration of cultural determinants.
Note
Reprinted from The Making of Psychological Anthropology, edited by George D. Spindler
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), pp. 331–60.
References
Ifaluk
1950. A psychotic personality in the South Seas. Psychiatry
13:189–204.
1951. Some Ifaluk myths and folk tales. Journal of American
Folklore 64:280–303.
1952. Ghosts, Ifaluk and teleological functionalism. American
Anthropologist 54: 497–503.
1953. An atoll culture, with E. G. Burrows. New Haven: Human
Relations Area Files.
1953. Ghosts: An anthropological inquiry into learning and
perception. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 48:376–
82.
1959. Cultural heritage, personal tensions, and mental illness in a
South Sea culture. In Culture and mental health, ed. M. K. Opler.
New York: Macmillan.
1961. Sorcery, evil spirits, and functional analysis. American
Anthropologist 63:820–24.
Kibbutz
1954. Is the family universal? American Anthropologist 56:839–
46.
1955. Education in a communal village in Israel. American
Journal of Orthopsychiatry 25:283–92.
1956. Kibbutz: Venture in Utopia. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press. (New augmented edition, 1971, with a new chapter.)
1957. The Sabras and Zionism: A study in personality and
ideology. Social Problems 5:100–110.
1958. Children of the kibbutz. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press. (New augmented edition, 1975, with a new chapter.)
Burma
1965. Religious systems as culturally constituted defense
mechanisms. In Context and meaning in cultural anthropology,
ed. Melford Spiro. Glen-coe: Free Press.
1966. Buddhism and economic saving in Burma. American
Anthropologist 68: 1163–73.
1967. Burmese supernaturalism: A study in the explanation and
resolution of suffering. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
1968. Religion, personality, and behavior in Burma. American
Anthropologist 70:359–63.
1968. Politics and factionalism in Upper Burma. In Local level
politics, ed. Marc Swartz. Chicago: Aldine.
1969. Religious symbols and social behavior. Proceedings of the
American Philosophical Society 113:341–50.
1969. The psychological functions of witchcraft: The Burmese
case. In Mental health in Asia and the Pacific, ed. Caudill and
Lin. Honolulu: East-West Center Press.
1971. Buddhism and society: A great tradition and its Burmese
vicissitudes. New York: Harper and Row.
1972. Violence in Burmese history: A psychocultural
interpretation. In Collective violence, ed. Short and Wolfgang.
Chicago: Aldine.
1973. Social change and functional analysis: A study in Burmese
psycho-cultural history. Ethos 1:263–97.
1974. The Oedipus complex in Burma. Journal of Nervous and
Mental Disease 157:389–95.
1975. Some psychodynamic determinants of household
composition in village Burma. Contributions to Asian Studies
8:126–38.
1977. Kinship and marriage in Burma: A cultural and
psychodynamic analysis. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
1979. Symbolism and functionalism in the anthropological study
of religion. Proceedings of the Study Conference of the
International Association for the History of Religion. In Science
of religious studies in methodology, ed. Lauri Honko. The Hague:
Mouton.
2
Some Reflections on Cultural
Determinism and Relativism with
Special Reference to Emotion and
Reason
A Conception of Culture
AS I SEE IT, “culture” designates a cognitive system, that is, a set of
“propositions,” both descriptive (e.g., “the planet earth sits on the back of a
turtle”) and normative (e.g., “it is wrong to kill”), about nature, man, and
society that are embedded in interlocking higher-order networks and
configurations. Cultural and noncultural propositions differ in two
important dimensions. First, cultural propositions are traditional, that is,
they are developed in the historical experience of social groups, and as a
social heritage, they are acquired by social actors through various processes
of social transmission (enculturation) rather than constructed by them from
their private experience. Second, cultural propositions are encoded in
collective, rather than private, signs (indices and icons, to employ Peirce’s
distinctions, as well as symbols). Hence, they exist and (in the first
instance) are discoverable by anthropologists in the collective
representations of social groups without their having to probe for them in
the private representations of social actors (though, as I shall soon argue,
many of them are also found there, albeit in a different form). This is not to
say that cultural statements, rules, values, norms, and the like are always
stated in propositional form, for clearly they are not, but that they are
susceptible of statement in that form.
This restricted conception of culture has important implications for what
“culture” does not designate. First, although by this conception, culture is
obviously an important—though only one—determinant of behavior,
culture as such does not consist of behavior. Moreover, although culture—
to broaden this implication—includes propositions referring to social
structure, social organization, social behavior, and the like, culture as such
does not consist of them. It might be added that because the latter have
noncultural (situational, ecological, economic, political, biological,
emotional, etc.) as well as cultural (ideational) determinants, the cultural
propositions comprising the emic models of social structure, social
organization, and the like cannot in themselves provide a reliable basis for
predicting their content or their shape. For the same reason, cultural models
cannot be reliably deduced from the observation of social behavior alone.
Second, although by this conception “culture” designates a cognitive
system, it is not the only—though it is clearly the most important—source
of the cognitions and schemata held by social actors. The other source, of
course, consists of their own experience. Thus, on the basis of their social
experience, a group of actors may come to construct a conception of their
social universe as hostile and threatening even though such a conception is
not transmitted to them by intentional enculturative processes and may even
be inconsistent with cultural propositions that convey the very opposite
message. Although conceptions of this type—beliefs or cognitive
orientations constructed by social actors as an unintended consequence of
social experience—have important effects on the social behavior, social
structure, and world view of social groups, they are not, by our definition,
“cultural.” Usually, but not always, unconscious, they are not encoded in
collective signs, and they are (therefore) not transmitted by means of
intentional enculturative processes. (They are discovered by the
anthropologist as an inference from clinically oriented interviews, dreams,
projective tests, and culturally constituted projective systems such as myths,
folklore, and the like.)
Third, although many cultural propositions have emotional antecedents,
and although others have emotional consequences—they arouse emotional
responses in social actors—and although some even prescribe the proper
conditions for the expression of emotions, culture as such—a cognitive
system encoded in collective representations—does not consist of emotions.
The exclusion of emotion from this conception of culture is not based on
the view—which, it might be thought, I hold either from ignorance or
foolishness—that emotions occur without thought or thought without
emotions. Even if I held such a misguided view (which I do not), it would
hardly be germane to the present issue because—although I have defined
“culture” as a cognitive system—culture does not consist of thought
(thinking) any more than it consists of emotion (feeling). As thinking and
feeling are properties of persons, and as culture—neither by this definition
nor by any other that I am aware of—does not consist of persons—though
society does—it is hard to see how either could be part of culture.
Although not a part of culture, thinking and feeling are often determined
by culture. That is, we most often think by means of the concepts
comprising cultural propositions, and our emotions are often aroused by
them; in short, many of our thoughts and emotions are (what might be
termed) “culturally constituted.” But just because thoughts and emotions
are culturally constituted, it is logically impermissible to conclude that
culture, as such, consists of emotion or thought any more than it can be
concluded that culture consists of behavior or social structure, although they
too are culturally constituted (cultural propositions serve to motivate
behavior and to provide a model for special structure). The conflation of
culture and culturally constituted phenomena is based on a confusion of
logical types, of cause with effect, structure with function, producer with
product. (It is that very confusion that invalidates my earlier attempt ([Spiro
1950] to understand the relationship between mind and culture by arguing
—as I now see it—fallaciously that “culture” and “personality” are
synonymous.)
If, then, the exclusion of emotion from this conception of culture is not
based on the misguided view that feeling is isolated from thinking, neither
is it based on the view that while emotions (because they are “located” in
the mind) are private events, thoughts (because culture is “located” in
collective representations) are public. In fact, I reject that view, not because
I believe that emotions are public—although their expression is—but
because I believe that thoughts are also private. Hence, as culture is a public
system, thoughts no less than emotions are, by definition, excluded from
“culture.”
Culture is public because it consists of propositions that are encoded in
collective representations, or public signs, usually, but not always, symbols.
It is precisely for that reason that anyone—and not only a native—can learn
the culture of any social group. Since, then, the “meanings” of those signs
consist of the concepts they designate and represent, cultural propositions
are public because—as Saussure (1966) has shown—their meanings are
“located,” as it were, in the signs themselves: the signs, to employ his
terms, function simultaneously as both signified (concept) and signifier
(sign vehicle). When, however, cultural propositions are learned by social
actors, they become personal thoughts that, like emotions, are private; they
are now “located” in the mind.
However, because these private thoughts are derived from, though they
may be less than isomorphic with, cultural propositions, they are (to employ
a term introduced earlier) culturally constituted. Nevertheless, inasmuch as
they are “located” in the (private) mental representations of social actors,
rather than in the (public) collective representations of their group, to
conclude that culture consists of these culturally constituted thoughts is to
commit the logical fallacies mentioned earlier.
Finally, this conception of culture does not imply that the meanings of the
symbols and other signs—both “discursive” and “presentational”—in which
cultural propositions are represented are only conscious, nor (in the latter
case) only denotative. This conception of culture recognizes that cultural
symbols have unconscious and connotative meanings, as well—the
meanings that are expressed in metaphor, metonymy, and other tropes.
Moreover, as it is in these meanings that most of the emotional action of
symbols is found, it is in respect to them that the interaction between
culture and emotion is most pronounced. As these meanings, however, do
not constitute the (conventional) meanings of symbols but are rather the
meanings that social actors, consciously or unconsciously, intend for them
to have, they are “located” not in the symbols themselves but in the minds
of social actors. Hence, if we distinguish between the meanings of cultural
symbols and the meanings that they have for social actors, the range of
meanings that a culture has for social actors is much broader than the range
of meanings of (conventional) cultural symbols.
Because of this difference in range, although anyone, not only the
natives, can learn a culture, the meanings that it has for the natives may be
very different from those that it has for non-natives. In learning a foreign
culture a non-native may acquire as firm a grasp of the meanings of the
culture as a native, but not having been socialized in the group, he or she
has not had those social experiences that, alone, serve to invest the culture
with those surplus meanings, that it has for the native.
That is why, too, we must distinguish between learning a culture and
becoming enculturated. To learn a culture is to acquire its propositions; to
become enculturated is, in addition, to “internalize” them as personal
beliefs, that is, as propositions that are thought to be true, proper, or right.
This is especially the case for those propositions that Shweder (1984) calls
“cultural frames,” propositions that can be neither proved nor disproved.
Thus, for example, a non-Buddhist scholar of Buddhism may have studied
its textual doctrines and may know their meanings in much greater detail
than a Buddhist. Nevertheless, the scholar is rarely converted to Buddhism
—its textual doctrines do not become personal beliefs—because, not having
been socialized in a Buddhist society, its textual doctrines do not have for
him the connotative meanings, nor do they arouse in him the emotional
responses, that alone serve to transform cultural frames into culturally
constituted beliefs. I shall return to this thesis later.
That is also why, even for the natives themselves, many cultural frames
are, or become, what might be called “cultural cliches”—propositions to
which actors may give nominal assent but which are not “internalized” by
them as personal beliefs. Although this may occur for many reasons, the
most important, in my view, is that these particular propositions do not
have, or have lost, emotional importance for them.
Finally, that is why the anthropologist who is interested in the meanings
that a culture has for the social actors must investigate the personality of the
actors with the same diligence that he investigates their cultural symbol
systems. For, in addition to the fact that, as D’Andrade has observed (1984),
there is considerable slippage in the transformation of cultural propositions
into (culturally constituted) beliefs, the surplus meanings of cultural
symbols are “located” in the minds of the actors.
Concluding Remarks
I should like to conclude with some personal observations. Thus far I have
examined particularistic cultural determinism and normative cultural
relativism in theoretical terms alone. But theories also have consequences,
and these theories have some (largely unintended) consequences, which—
given my values—I consider unfortunate. Because values, whether
personally constructed or culturally constituted, may be frames, it would be
a conceit to claim that the values on which this judgment is based are
grounded in logic or evidence or that they are free of emotional
determinants. Because the contrary is very likely the case, I refer to these
remarks as “personal observations.”
Shweder, entirely correctly in my view, places (normative) cultural
relativism in the “romantic’’ movement, a movement that tends to place a
high value on the nonrational. Hence, (normative) cultural relativism not
only defends the “coequality of fundamentally different ‘frames’ of
understanding” but, consistent with its intellectual heritage, also celebrates
them precisely because they are nonrational. Shweder puts this view
forthrightly: “Don’t knock the mystical, the transcendental, or the
arbitrary,” he exhorts us even though the “arbitrary” in his discussion
ranges, on the one hand, from differences between one kin type
classification and another to the difference between taking heads and
feeding starving Armenians, on the other.
Now, by this time it should be abundantly clear that I fully agree with
Shweder’s twin contentions that “there’s something more to thinking than
reason and evidence” and that reason is in short supply. But it is precisely
because reason is in short supply, and because (in my view) its alternatives
are not only the nonrational and the logically fallacious irrational but also
the emotionally driven irrational, that I believe that it is reason and those
aspects of culture that are based on it that should be celebrated. To be
concrete, it is not only because the emotionally driven irrational leads to
witchcraft accusations, food taboos, and head hunting, but because it also
leads to the destruction of scholarly papers and scientific laboratories—and
I am referring not only to the Arabian armies that sacked Alexandria in 640
but also to the university students who sacked Columbia, Cornell, and
Wisconsin in the 1960s—that I am dubious about celebrating the mystical,
the transcendental, and the arbitrary. In short, it is because reason is in short
supply that I prefer—as Freud once put it in expressing the goal of
psychoanalytic therapy—“where id was, there ego shall be.”
By the same token, it is because the emotionally driven irrational has no
limits or—to be more cautious—because its limiting case is Auschwitz, that
I believe that there are standards “worthy of universal respect” by which
cultural frames can be evaluated. That is the case, of course, only if it can
be agreed that those standards—to advert to Freud’s metaphors for the
different parts of the mind—are the standards not of the “id” but of the self-
reflective “ego.” Assuming agreement on that, then, inasmuch as the
preference for headhunting over the feeding of starving Armenians is based
on the standards of the former, while the contrary preference is based on
those of the latter, the latter preference can then be judged to be superior to
the former.
To be sure, not all social actors have self-reflective egos. But on the
assumption that self-reflection is a characteristic at least of philosophers
and saints, and that all societies, including—as Radin has observed—
primitive societies, have their philosophers (and probable saints too), the
preference for feeding starving Armenians over the taking of heads is based
on a standard that, I would argue, is universal in that it is found in at least
the reflective members of all societies.
If, however, it turned out that in some headhunting societies—the
Ilongot, for example—even the philosophers judged headhunting to be
preferable to feeding, say, the starving Ifugao, I would then argue that the
contrary judgment of the Buddha and Christ, of Isaiah and Laotzu, of
Socrates and Gandhi is worthy of greater respect. For, I would contend, the
Ilongot philosophers are unable because of emotional constraints to apply
the standards of their self-reflective ego to this question.
Given my values, particularistic cultural determinism and normative
cultural relativism have a second consequence that I consider to be
unfortunate. As these theories have come increasingly to dominate
anthropological thought, the vision of anthropology as the “study of man”
has been gradually eroded and replaced by the vision of anthropology as the
“study of men.”
The latter vision, which represents a departure from an attempt to
discover cross-cultural regularities and to formulate theories that might
explain them, challenges the status of anthropology as a “science” (as I
characterized that term earlier) because it views each culture (so far at least
as its cultural frames are concerned) as a kind of Leibnitzian cultural
monad. The diversity of cultures, from the perspective of this new vision,
represents a very Babel of voices, each expressing a set of arbitrary ideas
encoded in a set of arbitrary symbols. The noncommensurability of cultural
frames renders them incomprehensible to each other and recalcitrant to
scientific explanation, and their power—like that of God’s voice at Creation
—is sufficient to construct reality itself.
The result of this vision is well known. Although anthropology has made
much progress in the meticulous recording and reporting of the ideas and
institutions of particular cultures, it has made little progress in relating its
findings to the development of a theory of culture. The latter enterprise, we
are now increasingly told, is precluded in principle by the proclaimed
incommensurability of cultures. Thus, we can’t have a cross-cultural theory
of incest taboos, for example, because “incest” has different meanings in
different cultures; we can’t have a cross-cultural theory of religion, because
“religion” means very different things in different cultures and so on.
That view, in my opinion, is unfortunate, and has the potentiality for
becoming even more unfortunate. For as the premises of this new vision
gain currency, it might then be contended—as indeed some have already
contended—that one or more of the following conclusions may be derived
from those premises. (1) Anthropologists cannot adequately describe, let
alone explain, any culture different from their own. (2) For any culture to be
adequately described and understood, it must be investigated by an
anthropologist who himself has been enculturated in it. (3) For the latter to
adequately convey the ideas and institutions of that culture, they must be
reported in the native language, for there is no adequate way of rendering
the conceptual system of one culture by the concepts of another—not even
those of (anthropological) science, which is just another culture-bound
(Western) conceptual system. All science is ethnoscience.
Such a scenario may be the reductio ad absurdum of the new vision of
culture rather than its logical entailment. Nevertheless, we have seen it
enacted (sometimes with the encouragement of anthropologists) in another
form in some American universities. Thus, there are some few programs in
ethnic and women’s studies that claim that only ethnics are qualified to
teach the former and women the latter. Given the new vision of culture, why
should the same logic not apply to the teaching of Confucian philosophy,
the Old Testament, or the French Revolution?
However, even if the former scenario is only the reductio of the new
vision of culture, insofar as it is a potential consequence of that vision, I
would hope that the present ascendancy of particularistic cultural
determinism and normative cultural relativism might be subjected to
continuous and searching scrutiny.
Notes
Reprinted from Culture Theory: Essays on Mind, Self, and Emotion, edited by Richard A. Shweder
and Robert A. LeVine (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 323–46. © 1984 by
Cambridge University Press. Reprinted by permission of the publisher.
Although we continue to disagree on some key issues, this chapter has importantly benefited from
the suggestions and comments of Roy D’Andrade, Richard Shweder, Marc Swartz, and Donald
Tuzin.
References
A Precultural Interpretation
ANY ATTEMPT to assess the possible determinants of the counter-
revolutionary changes that have occurred in the kibbutz movement in such
institutions as marriage, the family, and sex-role differentiation is beset with
formidable difficulties. The problem is too complex, the data are too
limited, and our methods of investigation were too primitive to permit an
unequivocal interpretation. The weight of the evidence nevertheless
suggests that although several possible cultural determinants may have
contributed to these changes, on balance they do not appear to have been
decisive. Evidence from sabra childhood behavior suggests, instead, that
these counterrevolutionary changes were more probably brought about not
primarily as a response to external cultural conditions nor by culturally
acquired motives, but by precultural motivational dispositions.
Since, however, it is a basic axiom of the social sciences that human
behavior and motives are primarily, if not exclusively, culturally
programmed, I wish to observe, lest this conclusion be rejected on
axiomatic grounds, that the counterrevolutionary changes in the above
domains were not the only (nor even the most dramatic) changes brought
about by the sabras. A perhaps even more dramatic change occurred in the
sexual domain. Hence I would like to examine briefly this latter change
which constitutes a rather unequivocal exception to our social science
axiom.
According to the ideology of the kibbutz pioneers, attitudes and
orientations to sexual behavior and sexual anatomy are cultural artifacts.
Hence, so they believed, if children were raised in a sexually permissive
and enlightened environment, in which boys and girls, living together, were
acquainted with each other’s bodies and were taught to view nudity as
natural, so that notions of shame were not attached to the exposure of sex
organs—in such an environment, differences in sexual anatomy would
assume little more importance than any other kind of anatomical
differences. This belief was important for the pioneers not only because of
their commitment to healthy sexual attitudes, but also because of their
conviction that sexual equality (in its “identity” meaning) required an
attitude of indifference to sexual di-morphism. If, as they believed, the only
“natural” difference between the sexes consists in differences in sexual
anatomy, if children were raised to view this difference as inconsequential,
the road to sexual equality (as they conceived it) would then have been
paved.
Acting upon their beliefs, the pioneers established an entirely
“enlightened” sexual regime in the children’s houses. Boys and girls used
the same toilets, dressed and undressed in each other’s presence, walked
about their dormitory rooms (if they chose) in the nude, showered together
in one shower room, and so on. This system worked (and works) as the
pioneers expected until the first intimations of puberty in the girls—in
general, girls enter puberty a year or two before the boys—at which time
the very girls who had been raised in a sex-blind environment developed
intense feelings of shame at being seen in the nude by the boys. Sometime
before our 1951 study, the girls in Kiryat Yedidim, for example, initiated an
active rebellion against the mixed showers: they began to shower separately
from the boys, refusing to admit them into the shower room at the same
time. Consistent with this attitude, some of the girls would return early to
their children’s house at night to undress and be in their pajamas before the
boys arrived.
Despite the girls’ active opposition, the educational authorities refused to
change the system of mixed showers. Moreover, when high schools were
built in the kibbutzim, mixed showers and bedrooms were instituted in the
high school dormitories as well. By 1951, however, the mixed showers in
most kibbutz high schools had been unofficially abandoned. As one teacher
in Kiryat Yedidim put it, the mixed showers had become “a form of torture”
for the girls, their shame at exposing their nude bodies in front of the boys
being intensified by the latter’s teasing. Hence, though the high school
authorities did not officially sanction it, arrangements were made for boys
and girls to shower at different times. In a survey I conducted in Kiryat
Yedidim in 1951, only three students in the entire student body favored a
return to the mixed showers. Today, the sexes not only shower separately,
but in almost all kibbutz high schools there are now separate shower rooms
for boys and girls.
The same process has taken place with respect to the dormitory rooms. I
have already noted that even in the grade school the older girls felt
considerable discomfort about undressing in the presence of the boys. Their
discomfort was exacerbated in the high school. In 1951, for example,
although boys and girls in the high school in Kiryat Yedidim shared the
same rooms (usually three boys and three girls to a room), they were careful
to undress in the dark with their backs to each other. Moreover, so that their
bodies would not be exposed, the girls wore pajamas (regardless of the
heat) even though they slept under sheets. Despite these precautions,
succeeding generations of students have been persistently unhappy with
these living arrangements until, seven years ago (and after many
generations of female protest), the high school authorities capitulated to the
girls’ demands, and instituted unisexual bedrooms. Similar changes have
been introduced in most other kibbutzim as well.
In sum, the original kibbutz belief, that in the proper learning
environment children would be sex-blind, was proven to be false even in
the sexually enlightened conditions in which these children were raised.
Even if it were the case that the only natural difference between males and
females is one of sexual anatomy, this one difference apparently is not as
trivial as had been assumed. In this instance, at least, it had important social
and psychological consequences which could hardly have been culturally
determined, for these children (as we have seen) developed a sense of
sexual shame not as a result of, but in opposition to, the cultural values of
their learning environment.1 Apparently, nudity on an impersonal and
anonymous bathing beach is one thing; but in an intimate and potentially
sexually charged small group, it is quite another. When, then, the social
institutions that embodied these cultural values became too painful for the
children, they pressed for their abolition in violation of the attitudes in
which they had been imbued and over the opposition of the adults.2
1. In 1951, under the influence of kibbutz ideology, the high school personnel attributed the sabras’
reactions to the influence of students from the city who had imbued them with feelings of sexual
shame. Being a cultural determinist at that time, I too found this to be a persuasive explanation
although, in retrospect, its flaws are obvious. First, these shameful feelings were almost always
aroused during (or shortly before) pubescence when most girls, still in the grammar school, were not
yet exposed to city students. Second, even for those whose puberty was delayed till high school, the
assumption that the cultural values of a tiny minority of outside students could prevail over those of
the majority, especially when the latter were natives (supported by the entire weight of their native
and much more prestigeful environment) makes little sense. Moreover, if the absence of sexual
shame is natural and its acquisition cultural, this explanation makes even less sense, for one would
then have expected the cultural to give way to the natural. If the kibbutz students were indeed
influenced by the city students, it is more reasonable to believe that they were ready to be influenced
because this influence was syntonic with their natural dispositions.
2. It is pertinent to observe here that these children, whose behavior refuted the assumption that the
shame aroused by sexual dimorphism is cultural, are the same children who, upon becoming adults,
reversed the attempts of the pioneers to minimize the importance of dimorphism by eschewing
feminine clothing, jewelry, and cosmetics. Today, as we have seen, female sabras attempt to enhance
their feminine appearance by these cultural means, and male sabras obviously approve of these
attempts.
Single cases prove little; they are primarily useful insofar as they
challenge received opinion. The kibbutz case does not prove the existence
of precultural sex differences. Rather, it challenges the current intellectual
and political pieties which deny the existence of such differences (just as
they deny the existence of other group differences) on the grounds that to be
different is ipso facto to be unequal. That individuals and groups must be
identical in order to be equal is surely one of the more pernicious dogmas of
our time, and the fact that, ironically enough, it has become a liberal dogma
does not make it any the less so. Until or unless the kibbutz data are
interpreted differently, the kibbutz case constitutes a challenge to this
dogma so far as sex differences are concerned. Of course, the strength of
this challenge cannot be determined without much more extensive research
—especially longitudinal research—in a variety of cultural settings. Until
then, prudence suggests that scientific formulations and public policies
related to sex differences proceed with caution.
Note
Reprinted from Melford E. Spiro, Gender and Culture (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press,
1979), pp. 97–110. © 1979 by Melford E. Spiro.
References
Note
Reprinted from Melford E. Spiro, Oedipus in the Trobriands (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1982), pp. 144–80.
References
Introduction
WHEN ANTHROPOLOGY was primarily interested in culture history, the
question of how societies get their members to behave in conformity with
cultural norms was of small concern. But when anthropology became
interested in the problem of how societies operate, this question became—
and has remained—salient, not only for culture-and-personality theorists but
for other anthropologists as well. “Our great problem as anthropologists,”
says Firth, is “… to translate the acts of individuals into the regularities of
social process” (1954: 11).
Since social systems are attributes of society and personality systems are
attributes of individuals, it was formerly assumed, both by anthropologists
and by psychologists, that there was little relationship between “the acts of
individuals” and the “regularities of social process.” Before the development
of culture-and-personality studies, this assumption seemed reasonable. First,
although there is but one social system for a society, there are as many
personalities as there are members of society. Secondly, since social systems
are normative, their constituent activities are prescribed; but since
personality systems are conative, their activities are motivated. Finally,
social systems serve social functions, while personalities serve individual
functions. In short, although the functions of social systems are served by the
activities of individuals, these activities were not seen as serving personal
functions. Hence, older theories of cultural conformity1 and social control
ignored personality as an irrelevant variable.
1. The concept, “cultural conformity,” is here taken to mean, behavior which is in conformity with
cultural norms. Hence, “cultural conformity,” as used in this chapter, is to be distinguished from
“social conformity,” which refers to behavior which is in conformity with the behavior of others. In a
fully integrated and relatively unchanging society it would be difficult to distinguish between these
two types of conformity: the behavior of others would be more or less identical with the requirements
of the cultural heritage. In a somewhat less integrated and rapidly changing society (such as our own)
the distinction between these two types of conformity is clearer; Riesman’s (1950) other-directed
individuals, for example, represent social conformity rather than (or more than) cultural conformity. In
either case, though it might be difficult to distinguish between these types of conformity in overt
behavioral terms, it is not at all difficult to distinguish between them in motivational terms. Social
conformity is motivated by the desire to conform to the behavior of others; cultural conformity, by the
desire to conform to cultural norms. Cultural conformity, as we shall attempt to show, is a requisite for
the functioning of human social systems, whereas social conformity is not.
Classical cultural determinism, for example, attributed efficient causation
to the cultural heritage—people perform this or that activity of the social
system “because it’s part of their culture.” Although this theory represents an
advance over still older biologistic theories, it begs the very question which
is to be answered. As Nadel has put it: “… little is gained [in the study of
social control] by adducing the force of custom and tradition, that is, the
sheer inertia of habitual behavior and inherited practice” (1953:266). The
mere existence of a cultural heritage does not imply that it will be inherited;
or, if inherited, that behavior will be in conformity with its requirements.
The notion that cultural behavior is inherited automatically from the cultural
heritage is probably based on a confusion ultimately derived from Tylor’s
omnibus definition of culture (1874:1). For it would seem that the model
upon which the inheritance of cultural behavior is based is the inheritance of,
for example, tools, paintings, and houses—all of which are, of course,
inherited automatically, without either effort or motivation. Culture behavior,
too, is transmitted from a previous generation; but it is inherited by learning,
and not merely by being handed down.
Another answer to the problem of cultural conformity is provided by the
social sanctions theory. According to this theory, compliance with cultural
norms is achieved through positive and negative sanctions—rewards and
punishments—which function as techniques of social control. Although the
use of sanctions is probably universal, the thesis that cultural conformity is
achieved primarily or exclusively through the use of social sanctions rests, at
least implicitly, on two demonstrably false assumptions. These are the
Rousseauist assumption that culture is necessarily frustrating, and the super-
organistic assumption that cultural norms “exist” in the cultural heritage, but
are not internalized by the members of society.
Agreeing with the first, but disagreeing with the second of the above two
assumptions, a third theory of cultural conformity views compliance with
cultural norms as a function, primarily, of their internalization within
personality. Although cultural norms are, indeed, internalized, and although
conscience does play an important part in achieving cultural conformity, this
theory too is but a partial theory for, as we shall attempt to show, social
control is frequently achieved without the necessity for norm internalization.
Culture-and-personality studies suggest that though there is a large
measure of truth in these theories, cultural conformity is most frequently
achieved because social systems satisfy personality needs. This chapter,
then, will attempt to show that there is an intimate relationship between
social systems and personality: social systems operate by means of
personality, and personality functions by means of social systems. Many of
the social functions of social systems can be served only when this intimate
relationship obtains.
6. For a preliminary typology of functionalism, see Spiro 1953. For a detailed analysis of
functionalism as “functional consequence,” see Merton 1949. For illuminating discussions of
functionalism, based on Merton’s analysis, see Nagel 1957: chap. 10, and Hempel 1959. For a general
review of recent functionalist theory and research, see Firth 1955.
But if cultural goals are cathected as personal goals only when social
functions are internalized as personal drives, the number of roles whose
performance can serve personal functions would be small indeed. Indeed, it
is precisely because the social functions of roles only rarely become personal
drives that some theorists have stressed the importance of social sanctions as
a means, par excellence, of assuring cultural conformity. And surely the
argument is plausible. For if a role has a social function, and if the serving of
its function is not a personality need, how can its performance be motivated
by the expectation of satisfying a personality need?
This argument, however plausible, neglects to consider still another
possibility. Stipulated goals may be cathected, and therefore social roles
performed, although social functions are not internalized; and social
functions may be served, although they are unintended. As Kroeber,
generalizing from his analysis of religious change among the Kota, has put
it: “!n manipulating their culture for their personal ends, the participants
often produce a cultural effect that may be enduring, as well as attaining
their individual goal or tension reliefs” (1948:507).
This can happen in two ways: when personal and social functions are
members of the same functional class, and when they are members of
different functional classes. Both of these ways, beginning with the first, can
be illustrated by returning to the soldier role and the motives for its
performance. Since individuals exist qua members of society as well as qua
individuals, their welfare is frequently dependent upon the welfare of
society. Thus, though an individual may not internalize the adaptive (social)
function of the soldier role as a personal drive, he may nonetheless, if he
believes that his personal survival depends on the survival of his society,
cathect its goal of national defense; and he may then be motivated to
perform the role in order to satisfy this personality need. But since the social
(adaptive) function of the soldier role consists in the summation of its
personal (adaptive) functions for individuals, the performance of the role not
only serves a personal function, but it serves its social function as well—
albeit unintentionally.
There is still another way in which culturally stipulated goals can become
personality needs. Not everyone who becomes a professional soldier, for
example, is motivated to achieve or to perform this role in order to defend
either himself or his society from enemy attack. Since the promotion of
national defense is, at least in our society, one means for the attainment of
prestige and power, this culturally stipulated goal may become the cathected
goal for the reduction of these drives. The performance of the soldier’s role
may then be motivated by the expectation of satisfying power and prestige
needs. Nevertheless though the personal functions (integrative and adjustive)
and social function (adaptive) of the role are members of different functional
classes, and though its performance is intended to serve personal functions,
its social function—although unintended—is served as well.
Diagrammatically, these last two cases can be represented thus:
To sum up, any act may be viewed from at least two perspectives: motive
and function. The motive of an act is the consequence, either for the actor or
for society, which is intended by its performance; its function is the actual
consequence of its performance, either for the actor or for society. Functions
may be positive or negative; that is, the consequence of an act may
contribute to the welfare of the actor or of society or it may detract from
their welfare. (We are here concerned with positive functions only, and the
generic term, “function,” refers to positive function exclusively.) Finally acts
have intended and unintended functions. That is, the consequence of an act
may be the consequence which was intended by its performance, or it may
be one which was not intended by its performance. Since social roles have
social functions, and since acts are performed only if they have personal
functions, it has often been assumed that there is little intrinsic relationship
between personality needs and the performance of roles except in those few
instances in which an act is intended to serve both personal and social
functions. A soldier, for example, might be motivated to play his role
because he intended to serve both himself and his country.
But if acts can have unintended as well as intended consequences, it is
possible for personal and social functions to be served in the performance of
the same acts or roles. And this can happen in two ways: when their personal
functions are intended and their social functions are unintended, and when
their personal functions are unintended and their social functions intended.
In either event since the performance of the roles serves personal as well as
social functions, their performance is motivated—without the operation of
social sanctions—because they satisfy personality needs. Since these needs
consist in the personal cathexes of culturally stipulated goals, the
performance of social roles is effected by, what may be termed, “intrinsic
cultural motivation.” Alternatively, the cultural conformity which results
from this type of motivation is achieved by “intrinsic social control,” for the
control function is, as it were, built into the very fabric of the role. By
satisfying personality needs, its performance is assured, and its social
functions performed, without the necessity for sanctions extrinsic to the role
or for agents external to the actor.
Thus far it has been contended that personality plays an important part in the
operation of social systems because, by motivating the performance of social
roles, it enables the social system to serve its social functions. The
discussion, however, has dealt with the manifest functions of roles
exclusively, that is, with those social functions which, whether intended or
unintended by the members of society, are recognized by them. But social
systems, have latent functions as well, and sometimes their latent functions
are more important for society than their manifest functions. It is here,
moreover, that personality is uniquely important for the functioning of
society.
If manifest functions are those consequences of role performance which
are recognized by the members of society, latent functions are those
consequences which—whether intended or unintended—are not recognized
by them.7 That the paradox of an intended but unrecognized function is
apparent rather than real, becomes clear when one considers that motives
may be unconscious, as well as conscious. In short, manifest (recognized)
functions are served by the performance of roles when at least one of the
motives for their performance is conscious; latent (unrecognized) functions
are served when at least one of the motives for their performance is
unconscious. Hence, before analyzing latent functions, it is necssary to
examine the concept of unconscious motive.
7. Merton (1949), whose now-classic analysis of functionalism remains the incisive treatment of
this subject, and who first introduced the terms “manifest” and “latent” into functional analysis,
ignored a potentially powerful mode of analysis by merging “intention” and “recognition.” As he
defines them, manifest functions are those which are both intended and recognized, while latent
functions are those which are neither intended nor recognized. Since manifest functions—as we have
seen—may be unintended, and since latent functions—as we shall see—may be intended, intention
and recognition may vary independently.
If the motive for behavior consists in an intention to satisfy a need by
performing a particular act (and if a need consists in a drive and a goal), a
motive may be unconscious, i.e., unrecognized, in any one or all of these
three dimensions. Thus a drive, its goal, and the desired means for the
attainment of the goal may all be unconscious. With the exception of
neurotic, i.e., idiosyncratic, repression, if any or all of these dimensions of a
motive are unconscious in a typical member of a society, the motive has
generally been rendered unconscious because of a cultural prohibition or
because of its systematic frustration. In the latter case, since need-frustration
as well as the memory of need-frustration are painful, repression of the
frustrating experience as well as of the need is one possible defense against
pain. We shall confine the discussion to the former basis for repression.
Thus, for example, the cultural heritage may prohibit any reduction of the
sex drive, as in sacerdotal celibacy; or it may prohibit a desired goal for its
reduction, such as intercourse with kinsmen who fall within the boundaries
of the incest taboo; or it may prohibit a desired means for the attainment of
the goal, such as some “perverted” technique of sexual relations. In short the
cultural heritage not only provides means of need-satisfaction for an animal
without instinctive means for drive-reduction, but—by prescribing these
means—it prohibits other means which this relatively plastic and
imaginative animal may come to prefer. Moreover it may completely
prohibit any conceivable (manifest) expression or reduction of certain drives.
But motives do not disappear simply because they are prohibited. Even if
the cultural prohibition is internalized as a personal norm, the culturally
prohibited canalization may continue to persist as a personally preferred
canalization, and the culturally prohibited drive may continue to seek
expression. The resultant incompatibility between internalized norm and
personal desire leads to inner conflict which must be “handled” in some way.
If these personally preferred, but culturally prohibited, canalizations are
stronger than the internalized cultural prohibition, they may be expressed
directly. If, then, the resultant behavior is categorically prohibited, it is
deemed criminal or psychologically aberrant (depending on the culture) by
the members of society. Alternatively, if the behavior is culturally aberrant,
but not clearly prohibited, it may be viewed as a cultural innovation—that is,
as a new, but culturally acceptable, behavior pattern.
On the other hand, should the internalized cultural prohibition be stronger
than the personal desire, the inner conflict may be resolved by repressing the
desire. The prohibited motive, in short, becomes unconscious. But
unconscious as well as conscious motives seek expression and satisfaction.
They may be expressed (and satisfied) in neurosis and psychosis; in private
fantasy (day-dreams and night dreams); in symbolic, but culturally creative,
ways (artistic and scientific work); or, and more germane to this chapter, in
the performance of culturally prescribed roles. Since unconscious motives
cannot be satisfied directly—if they could they would not be unconscious—
they may thus seek indirect satisfaction in the performance of culturally
sanctioned behavior. In short, in addition to its conscious motivation,
culturally sanctioned behavior, including role behavior, may be
unconsciously motivated as well. Since, in the latter case, the performance of
a role is motivated by an unconscious as well as by a conscious intention of
satisfying a need, the role may have unrecognized though intended personal
functions; and these, in turn, may produce unrecognized and unintended
social functions. This thesis may be illustrated by examples from two
societies: warfare among the Sioux Indians of the American Plains, and
religion among the Ifaluk of Micronesia.
Diagrammatically, the relationship between the motives for the
performance of the Sioux warrior role and its various personal and social
functions can be represented thus:
Sioux warfare was motivated by two conscious needs: prestige and
protection from enemies. In satisfying these needs for prestige and
protection, warfare served manifest personal (integrative) and social
(adaptive) functions. It may be assumed, it served an unintended
(integrative), but manifest social function, as well—the promotion of social
solidarity by the creation of esprit de corps among the warriors.
But the “choice” of warfare as a preeminent institutionalized means of
obtaining prestige leads us to suspect that the conscious motives for the
performance of the warrior role, though genuine, were not its only motives.
Warfare is an aggressive activity, why did the Sioux act aggressively when
the objective threat from the enemy was slight? Sioux war parties, it will be
recalled, attacked rather than defended; they preferred to attack when their
“enemies” were least prepared, that is, when they constituted no threat;
young bucks had to be restrained from going on the warpath, rather than
having to be encouraged to do so. And why did they seek prestige through
aggression when, as the cross-cultural record reveals, there are many
nonaggressive roles through which prestige can be obtained? Sioux warfare
apparently was motivated not only by the conscious needs of prestige and
protection, but by yet another, unconscious, motive—hostility against their
fellows.
As is the case in most societies, Sioux socialization, as well as the
conditions of adult Sioux social life, created in each new generation a motive
for aggression against their fellows (Erikson 1939, 1945). Like most
societies, moreover, the cultural heritage of the Sioux prohibited physical
aggression against the in-group. However, only one of the three dimensions
of this motive was prohibited. Neither the drive itself (hostility) nor the
means of its reduction (physical aggression), but only its object (the in-
group), was prohibited. It was assumed, then, that the specific dimension of
physical aggression against fellows was repressed, i.e., rendered
unconscious. But by displacing hostility from the in- to the out-groups, this
motive could now be expressed. This motive, one may suggest, sought
satisfaction in, and was therefore important in the motivation of, Sioux
warfare. In addition to their motives of prestige and protection, Sioux war
parties were also motivated by aggression. In satisfying this motive, the
warrior role served a latent personal function (integration), as well as its
manifest personal and social functions.
When the performance of roles is motivated by unconscious needs, it
serves unintended and unrecognized social functions as well as intended but
unrecognized personal functions. What possible unintended and
unrecognized function for society was served by the Sioux institution of
warfare? By displacing hostility, and its subsequent aggression, in warfare
against the outgroup, the warrior role protected Sioux society from the
aggression of its own members (adaptive function). Had the original hostility
not been displaced and subsequently gratified in socially sanctioned
aggression, it might have sought un-disguised and, therefore, socially
disruptive expression. It might have sought expression in other ways as well.
Indeed, Erikson interprets the sun dance, and its painful consequences for its
participants—staring into the sun and tearing of skewers from their flesh—as
the turning of aggression inward. It might be suggested, then, that in the
absence of war, even more aggression would have been turned against the
self. Hence, the performance of the warrior role served a latent, unintended
personal function, as well as its latent unintended social function.
But to return to the social functions of Sioux warfare: by deflecting
hostility from in- to out-group, the preponderance of positive over negative
sentiments concerning the members of the group was increased, thereby
promoting in-group solidarity (integrative function). Neither of these
unintended and unrecognized social functions would have been served had
the performance of the warrior role been motivated exclusively by the
motives of prestige and protection. Moreover, those anthropologists who are
unaware of, or uninterested in, the latent personal functions of roles—
because unaware of, or uninterested in, unconscious motives—would remain
ignorant of the important latent social functions which are served by this
role, and of the general functional significance of Sioux warfare within the
total social system.
The second example of the relationship between unconscious motives and
social functions not only illustrates the importance of unconscious
motivation in the functioning of social systems, but it also illustrates how a
society and its social system may be affected by the intrinsic motivation of
another cultural system—religion. Most public religious rituals in the
Micronesian atoll of Ifaluk are either therapeutic or prophylactic in nature;
they are designed to maintain or restore health by exorcising malevolent
ghosts (who cause illness by possessing their victims), or by preventing
these ghosts from executing their intentions in the first place. It is not within
the province of social science to decide whether one of the manifest,
intended, functions of these rituals—defeat of the ghosts—is served; the
Ifaluk, of course, believe that it is. But these rituals serve other manifest
functions to which the behavioral scientist can testify. By their performance
the twin fears of illness and of attack by ghosts are reduced (manifest
intended personal function), and by assembling and acting in concert for the
achievement of a common end, good fellowship is strengthened (manifest
unintended social function).
But the performance of these rituals requires another motive in addition to
its therapeutic motive. These are aggressive rituals in which malevolent
ghosts are attacked and, it is hoped, routed. It requires little insight to infer
that hostility, as well as fear, motivates the performance. Indeed, the Ifaluk
are quite consciously hostile toward the ghosts. But though consciously
hostile to ghosts, the Ifaluk, like all people, have occasion to be hostile to
their fellows, particularly to their close kinsmen. By displacing hostility
from fellows to ghosts, their hostility is acceptable, and their subsequent
aggressive motive can be gratified in a socially sanctioned manner in the
performance of these rituals (Spiro 1953a). A latent personal function
(integrative) of these rituals, then, consists in the opportunity which their
performance affords for the satisfaction of this aggressive need.
As in the Sioux example, however, the performance of these rituals also
serves a latent (unintended) social function, one which is vital for this
society. The Ifaluk social system, based on the strongly held values of
sharing, mutual aid, and kindliness, is highly cooperative. If the Ifaluk were
unable to express aggression symbolically in ritual, it is not improbable that
their hostility would eventually seek direct expression. If this were to
happen, the probability of physical survival on an atoll, six-tenths of a mile
square, would be effectively reduced. By serving to deflect aggression onto
malevolent ghosts, the performance of these rituals effectively increases the
chances for survival. Moreover, as in the case of the Sioux, the belief in
malevolent ghosts, which permits the displacement of hostility from the in-
group to the wicked out-group, assures the persistence of the warm
sentiments which the Ifaluk harbor towards each other. Hence the
psychological basis for their cooperative social system—probably the only
kind of system which is viable in this demographic-ecological balance—is
preserved. In short, by serving its latent personal function, this ritual is also
able to serve the latent social functions of promoting the group’s survival
and of preserving the viability of its social system (Spiro 1952).
Diagrammatically, the relationship between the motives for the
performance of Ifaluk rituals, which attack and exorcise malevolent ghosts,
and their personal and social functions can be represented in the following
way:
This discussion of unconscious motives, and of the latent social functions
served by social roles (and other types of cultural behavior) whose
performance is motivated by them, has been somewhat extended because,
with the exception of culture-and-personality research, they are ignored in
most analyses of social systems. Unconscious motives are frequently
dismissed by social scientists as irrelevant to an understanding of society.
“Oh,” it is often said, “these unconscious motives may be important for
personality, but we re interested in the study of society.” This analysis has
attempted to demonstrate that anyone interested in society should also be
interested in unconscious motives. They are as important for the student of
society as for the student of personality, not only because they motivate the
performance of social roles but because the latent social functions which
they enable these roles to serve are often more important than those which
are served under conscious motivation. It should be emphasized, however,
that unconscious motives, however important, are not the only motives of
behavior, that conscious motives are not merely rationalizations. Though this
may sometimes be the case, the assumption that only unconscious motives
are genuine is as fallacious as the contrary assumption. If the conscious
motives of Sioux warfare and Ifaluk ritual are not sufficient explanations for
their performance, neither are the unconscious motives: both are necessary,
both are genuine, neither is sufficient. To assume that only unconscious
motives are genuine is to perpetuate that vulgar interpretation of
psychoanalytic theory in which schoolteaching, for example, is “nothing
but” the sublimation of an unconscious sexual motive, or surgery is “nothing
but” the displacement of unconscious aggression.
Theories of social systems that ignore unconscious motives are not only
truncated, but when social analyses which are based on such theories are
applied by administrators, they often lead to unfortunate results. If we were
to assume, for example, that Sioux warfare or Ifaluk religious rituals are
means merely for obtaining prestige or reducing anxiety concerning illness
respectively, and that by achieving these ends they also promote social
solidarity—the typical social anthropological functionalist analysis—then it
is a fair administrative conclusion that these “savage” and “superstitious”
practices can be abolished without harm to society as long as the “civilized”
practices with which they are replaced are their functional equivalents, as
long, that is, as the new practices are also means for obtaining prestige, for
reducing anxiety concerning illness, and for promoting social solidarity. But
despite these good intentions, the new practices are not the functional
equivalents of the old if they do not serve, as well, the latent personal
function of displacing unconscious hostility. Unless this function is
achieved, substitutes cannot serve the latent social function of deflecting
aggression from the in-group. Hence, this unconscious motive may seek
expression in numerous dysfunctional ways—dysfunctional both for
individuals and society. It may be expressed directly, leading to crime, or
indirectly, leading to drunkenness, etc.; it may be inverted, leading to anxiety
and depression (“race suicide”), and so forth. By ignoring the importance of
unconscious motivation in social behavior, the attempt of well-intentioned
administrators (acting upon the findings of psychologically uninformed
researchers) to substitute “unobjectionable” for “objectionable” native
practices has often been a history of grave disappointments to the
administrator and sordid results for the natives.
It should be strongly emphasized that although personality needs are
satisfied in and therefore motivate the performance of social roles, a person’s
personality cannot necessarily be inferred from a knowledge of the roles he
performs. In the first place, although this chapter is concerned with the
relationship between personality and the social system, it is obvious that
only part of the personality is relevant to and is expressed through the social
system. The relationship between personality and other cultural systems
(religion, art, science, etc.), as well as those private aspects of personality
that are not caught up in the sociocultural net (Murphy 1958: part 3), are
deliberately ignored. In short, a description of a person’s various social roles
would not lead to an exhaustive description of his personality.
More important, however, for our purposes, a knowledge of a person’s
social roles would not even lead to an accurate prediction of those aspects of
his personality that are caught up in their performance. For, as this section
has attempted to show, since different goals may be cathected by the same
drive and since different roles may be instrumental for the attainment of the
same goal, “a high degree of role differentiation,” as Kaplan has put it, does
not necessarily require “a similar degree of differentiation at the personality
level” (1957: 100). At the same time, since the same goal may be cathected
by different drives, and since the same role may be instrumental for the
attainment of different goals, a high degree of personality differentiation
does not necessarily require a similar degree of differentiation at the social
system level. Thus, (1) different drives may be canalized by the same goal,
which is attained by the performance of the same role; (2) the same drive
may be canalized by different goals, which are attained by the performance
of different roles; and (3) different drives may be canalized by the same goal
which is attained by the performance of different roles. These alternatives
are shown in the following diagrams.
But if this is true within a society, it is equally true across societies. Since
there are fewer drives in man than there are goals in all his societies, and
since there are fewer goals in all human societies than there are roles in their
social systems, it is reasonable to expect fewer modal personality systems
than social systems. On the other hand, since drives, goals, and roles may
vary independently of each other, it is possible for different modal
personality systems to be associated with similar social systems, and for
similar modal personality systems to be associated with different social
systems.
If this is so the student of social systems, who is interested in their
motivational well-springs, must at the same time be a student of personality;
and statements about the relationships between personality and social
systems must be based on personality investigations, and not inferred from a
description of social systems (Inkeles and Levinson 1954). Personality
investigation may entail the use of psychological instruments, such as
projective tests (Hallowell 1955), the analysis of dreams (Eggan 1952), the
collection of life histories (Kluckhohn 1945), and depth interviewing. It may
also be based, however, on the observation of behavior when viewed from
the perspective of, and interpreted in terms of, psychodynamic personality
theory. For if the same set of activities can serve both personal and social
functions, the same set of activities may be viewed from a personality
perspective (as a means for serving personal functions) or from a social
system perspective (as a means for serving social functions). If one’s focus is
on society and on those adaptive, adjustive, and integrative prerequisites of a
viable social life, a given set of activities is analyzed as a role within the
social system. If, on the other hand, one’s focus is on an individual and on
the adaptive, adjustive, and integrative prerequisites of a viable individual
life, the same set of activities is analyzed as a means for satisfying the needs
of the personality system. This last technique uses a powerful, but rare
instrument—a sensitive observer.
Conclusions
In the past, when the behavioral sciences were still reacting against
instinctivist theories of social behavior, the relationship between social
system and personality was viewed as primarily asymmetrical. Personality
was viewed as a relatively passive agent—affected by, but not affecting, the
social system. Faris (1937: ch. 3), for example, refers to personality as the
“subjective aspect of culture.” Recent work in culture-and-personality,
however, has tended to conceive of the social system—personality
relationship as more nearly symmetrical. These studies have suggested that
although personality is, indeed, affected by the social system, the social
system, in turn, is affected by personality.
This changing conception of the relationship between personality and
social system has had its influence on the study and analysis of social
systems by culture-and-personality theorists. Instead of merely asking how
the social system influences the development and structuring of personality,
we are now equally interested in how personality affects the functioning of
social systems. And, in general, it seems to be agreed that there is feedback
between social system and personality such that the social system creates
those personality needs which, in turn, are satisfied by and motivate the
operation of the social system (Kardiner 1939). Since society has but one
social system, while the component members of society have different
personalities, this feedback is effected because the component roles of the
social system can satisfy different needs, and its socialization system
produces common needs, or a modal personality (DuBois 1944).
This chapter has been exclusively concerned with the impact of
personality on the social system, and specifically on the importance of
personality for the motivation of role performance. Since the social system
can serve its functions for society only if its component roles are performed,
every society is confronted with the problem of social control—the problem
of getting people to behave in conformity with cultural norms. By supplying
the psychological basis for cultural motivation, personality is a vital
instrument in society’s attempt to achieve social control. It serves as such an
instrument in three ways.
In the first place, although society provides sanctions as a means for
achieving social control, these sanctions are effective only if the members of
society have drives which can be reduced by the attainment of these goals. If
this is the case these sanctions are cathected, and thereby become personality
needs which motivate role performance. Second, if the cultural norms, which
prescribe the performance of the role, are internalized by the members of
society, nonconformity induces anxiety. Since this anxiety can be reduced by
the performance of the role, conformity with these norms becomes a need
which motivates role performance. Finally, the prescribed goals which are
attained by role performance are, themselves, cathected and, hence, serve as
per sonality needs to motivate the performance of roles.
These three types of control have been termed, extrinsic, internalized, and
intrinsic, respectively. We may summarize their differences and similarities,
as follows: (a) In extrinsic control which is based on positive social
sanctions, and (b) in intrinsic control which is based on manifest personal
functions, the performance of roles is motivated by the desire to obtain a
rewarding goal—either the cathected social sanction or the cathected goal of
the role, (c) In extrinsic control which is based on negative social sanctions,
(d) in internalized control, and (e) in intrinsic control which is based on
latent personal functions, the performance of roles is motivated by the desire
to avoid pain—in the forms of physical or social punishment, moral anxiety,
or unrelieved needs, respectively.
Note
Reprinted with permission of Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc., from Studying Personality Cross-
Culturally, edited by Bert Kaplan, pp. 93–127. © 1961 by Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc.
References
Burmese Monasticism 1
1. Materials in this section are based on field work carried out during 1961–62; I am grateful to the
National Science Foundation for a fellowship which made the research possible.
Note
Reprinted with permission of The Free Press, a division of Macmillan, Inc., from Context and
Meaning in Cultural Anthropology, edited by Melford E. Spiro, pp. 100–113. © 1965 by The Free
Press.
References
Let me summarize my argument thus far. My main point has been that
the belief in the reality of the mythicoreligious world, a belief in which
culturally-constituted fantasy is invested with the appearance of reality, may
be explained to a large extent as a function of the primary process mode of
cognition. The cultural conceptions of the superhuman beings who inhabit
that world are conveyed, of course, by the external cultural symbols by
which they are represented—words, icons (sculpture and painting), and
ritual—and from these collective representations the believer forms his
mental representations of them. That these beings are believed to exist
independently of the collective, as well as the mental, representations which
signify them is best explained by the correspondence that exists between
these representations and the mental representations that the young child
previously forms of those actual powerful beings whose reality he has
personally experienced—his parenting figures. These representations are
based on the primary process mode of cognition because, in the absence of
language, the representational medium consists of images; in the absence of
object constancy, these images are formed by the process of splitting; and in
the absence of reality testing, they are reified and externalized. It is the
merging of the believer’s mental representations of the parents of early
childhood with his or her mental representations of the superhuman beings
comprising the mythicoreligious world that constitutes the cognitive basis
for the belief that the mythicoreligious world exists independently of the
collective representations by which it is both represented and signified.
By this explanation for the belief in the reality of the mythicoreligious
world, religious symbols have both ‘surface’ and ‘deep’ meanings, and no
interpretation of any particular religion is complete unless its symbols are
interpreted at both levels.2 For this reason, the interpretation of religion
(and other cultural systems) is similar to the interpretation of a dream in that
the knowledge of its manifest content alone can be highly misleading
without knowledge of its latent content.
2. The current interest in cultural hermeneutics persistently distinguishes between interpretation
and explanation, interpretation being viewed as a humanistic endeavor, concerned with intentions’
purposes, goals, and the like, while explanation is viewed as a scientific or positivistic endeavor,
concerned with the search for causal and functional ‘laws.’ In my view, this is a false dichotomy. If
the former endeavor is concerned with producing valid, rather than just any kind of interpretations, it
must be no less concerned with ‘laws,’ than the former, because, of course, the cogency, if not
validity of the idiographic interpretation is dependent on the nomothetic theory from which it is
implicitly or explicitly deduced.
According, then, to this explanation, the external and public symbols of
religion—its collective representations—represent and signify at their
‘surface’ level the superhuman beings whose existence is affirmed by the
various culturally parochial, religious traditions—Jahweh, Allah, Siva, the
Madonna, Durga, and the like. These are their conscious and culturally
variable meanings. At their ‘deep’ level, however, these symbols represent
and signify the projections of the mental representations of the parents of
early childhood. These are their unconscious, and culturally universal
meanings. (Such an interpretation of the collective representations of
religion might be contrasted with that of Durkheim who, it will be recalled,
viewed them—in their ‘deep’ meanings—as signifying society.)
In sum, I have argued thus far that underlying the cross-cultural diversity
in the surface meanings of culturally parochial religious symbols, there are
universal deep processes and meanings. If this is so, these cultural symbols
effect three important psychological transmutations in the religious actors:
transmutation of infantile into adult conceptions, of individual into public
meanings, and of unconscious into conscious concerns. The satisfaction of
these adult, public, and conscious concerns—especially those related to the
explanation and conquest of suffering—constitutes, so I have argued, the
most important manifest function of religion, providing a powerful
motivational basis for the belief in the reality of the mythicoreligious world.
However, if religious symbols also have deep meanings, then religion not
only has manifest functions related to the surface meanings of these
symbols, but it must also have latent functions related to their deep
meanings. Hence in this, the concluding section of this paper, I wish to
argue that religion attends not only to the conscious and public concerns of
the actor’s adult-like experience, but also to the unconscious and private
concerns of his child-like experience. For if religious symbols are
associated with unconscious infantile mental representations, it can only be
because in addition to their conscious, adult concerns, social actors retain
unconscious, infantile concerns, and it is their satisfaction that constitutes
the latent function of religion. The intention of satisfying these concerns
constitutes yet another—an unconscious—motivational basis for the belief
in the reality of the mythicoreligious world.
Since dreams constitute the most important private symbol system for the
gratification, in fantasy, of infantile needs, I shall turn once again to the
dream to help us understand the motivational aspects of unconscious
symbolic processing. Since in this context, however, we are interested not
in the hallucinatory, or ontological dimension of primary process cognition,
but in its “logical” dimension, we shall seek assistance from poetry as well.
(The argument of this section of the paper is similar to, but also differs to
some extent from one I have previously developed elsewhere. See Spiro
1977:xix-xxx.)
Should a poet wish to represent a conception of a friend—his bravery for
example—he may convey this conception in a simple prose sentence, “John
is brave”; in a figure of speech, such as the simile, “John is like a bull”; or
in a trope, such as the metaphor, “John is a bull.” In the metaphor, the
intended meaning of the verbal symbol, “bull,” is figurative rather than
literal, for it is intended to represent the poet’s conception of John, rather
than to signify the brave bull in Madrid’s corrida. Unlike the poet, the
dreamer has fewer degrees of freedom to express his thoughts because a
representational medium consisting of images cannot directly represent
qualities, such as bravery, which in language are represented by adjectives,
adverbs, and similar parts of speech. In such a medium, which only contains
the structural equivalents of nouns and verbs, the thought, “John is brave,”
cannot be represented in a form analogous to a simple sentence, let alone a
simile. Rather, given the constraints of his medium, the dreamer, just like
the painter or sculptor, can only represent such a thought in a form
analogous to a trope. Hence, to represent the thought that John is brave, he
may dream of a bull. Like the verbal trope of the poet, the visual trope of
the dreamer can be misleading to one who does not understand the code.
Thus, though the consciously intended meaning of the bull is figurative,
rather than literal, inasmuch as an image of a bull is conventionally taken to
be a representation of a certain species of bovine, it is a conventionally
inappropriate sign for a human being.
To put it in Peirce’s classification of signs, since the image of the bull is
intended as a symbol for John, its meaning will be misunderstood if it is
taken as an icon for a bull. And this potential confusion is precisely one of
the difficulties that is posed by the interpretation of dreams, as well as one
of the reasons for their seemingly bizarre qualities. For although in the
sleeping code by which he constructs his dream, the dreamer consciously
intends the bull to be a symbolic representation of John, in his waking code
by which he interprets the dream, it is taken by him to be an iconic
representation of a bovine. In short, in the dream-as-recalled, the image of
the bull is taken literally, though in the dream-as-dreamt it was intended
figuratively.
The poet, of course, does not have an analogous problem—though his
reader may—because he uses the same code in reading his poem that he had
used when composing it. On both occasions, the conventionally
inappropriate verbal symbol, “bull,” is consciously understood by him to be
a metaphor, a form which he chose in the first place in order to convey his
conception of John more effectively, forcefully, or artistically than might
have been achieved by a simple prose sentence. In short, both in the case of
the poem and of the dream-as-dreamt, the figurative meaning of the sign—
the word in the former, the image in the latter—is its consciously intended,
and only, meaning.
In addition, however, to the representational constraints of his medium,
the dreamer may set forth his thoughts in conventionally inappropriate
images for yet another reason: the wish to disguise them. All of us have
thoughts that are repugnant to our moral values, and since such thoughts are
painful—they arouse moral anxiety—we often repress them, i.e., eliminate
them from conscious awareness. Let us suppose, then, that in his waking
state a dreamer has a repressed thought concerning his friend, John—the
thought, for example, that he would like him to die. Let us further suppose
that this thought continues in his sleep. If the dreamer were to distort this
thought, by substituting a bull for John as the object of his wish, then he
might, with moral impunity, gratify this disguised wish in a dream in which
he kills a bull. In such a dream, the image of the bull has two meanings
simultaneously—one literal, the other figurative. Its literal meaning (bull) is
consciously intended, while its figurative meaning (John) is unconsciously
intended. Since in this dream, unlike the first, the image is an unconscious
symbol for John—consciously, of course, it is taken as an icon of a bull—
the substitution of a bull for John is an example not of a trope, but of a
defense mechanism; that is, it is a cognitive maneuver in which a forbidden
wish undergoes unconscious symbolic distortion in the service of a
disguise.
Let me now summarize very briefly the formal characteristics of defense
mechanisms, in contrast to tropes, in somewhat more technical terms: (a) In
a defense mechanism the symbolic distortion of the wish is overdetermined,
that is, it is based on multiple and simultaneous motives, including the
motives to gratify and—since it is forbidden—to disguise a wish; (b)
Disguise and gratification alike are achieved by displacement,, an
unconscious process in which a conventionally inappropriate sign is
substituted for an appropriate one. (Displacement is based on the same
criteria—similarity or contiguity between the original and substituted
objects signified by the two signs—that are employed in the symbolic
substitutions found in metaphor, metonymy, synecdoche, and other tropes.);
(c) Hence, the substitute sign is characterized by condensation, i.e., it has
two or more simultaneously intended meanings, at least one of which is
unconscious; (d) The conscious, or manifest meaning of the sign is its literal
meaning; its unconscious, or latent meaning is its figurative meaning.
Let us now apply this analysis of the defensive use of the private symbols
comprising the dream to the cultural symbols comprising religion. As a
cultural system, religion attends in the first instance, as I have stressed more
than once, to the public and conscious concerns of the believers’ adult
experience, especially their concern with suffering in both its intellectual
and existential dimensions. That is, it attends to the needs to both explain
and overcome suffering. To achieve the latter end, the religious actor
engages in ritual transactions with the superhuman beings comprising the
mythicoreligious world. Some of these beings, kindly and benevolent, he
turns to for assistance and aid in his attempt to cope with suffering. Others
of them, aggressive and malevolent, are often viewed as the cause of
suffering, and these he attempts to drive out or drive off. The former type
arouse his wishes for and emotions of dependency and succorance; the
latter type arouse his aggression, fear, and hatred.
Although such postures of dependency and aggression—whether
expressed in the form of wishes, emotions, or actions—are culturally
appropriate for adults in the religious contexts in which they are aroused
and displayed, they are usually considered inappropriate for them in other
contexts. There is one context, in particular, in which they are especially
inappropriate; that context, of course, is the family. As the child’s most
significant others, his parents are at once his most important frustrating
figures (consequently, the targets of his most intense aggressive feelings
and wishes) and his most important nurturant figures (consequently the
objects of his most intense dependency feelings and wishes). Parents are
also, however, the very persons concerning whom, following an initial,
culturally variable period of indulgence, the cultural prohibitions against
dependency and aggression are most severe. The reasons are obvious.
Social survival requires that children eventually outgrow their dependency
on their family of origin, and that, having achieved independent status, they
establish their own families and become objects for the dependency of their
own children. Similarly, since aggression within the family is entirely
disruptive of its integration, if not survival—hence inimical to its vital
individual and social functions—it too must be prohibited.
This being so, every social actor and every society is confronted with an
acute existential dilemma. Although his parents are the objects of the
child’s most intense dependency and aggressive needs and wishes, they are
also the persons concerning whom their gratification is eventually most
strongly frustrated. For although as children grow older and become adults,
they learn to comply with the cultural norms prohibiting the overt display of
aggression toward and dependency upon parents, this does not mean that
these infantile needs are extinguished. That the contrary is the case is
indicated not only by an abundance of clinical evidence, but also by
commonplace observations of everyday life which indicate that these
emotions and wishes are capable of arousal—and not only in a displaced
form—in certain contexts, at least, and under certain provocations.
In sum, then, I am arguing that the intense dependency and aggressive
wishes of children concerning parents, though seemingly extinguished,
continue to exist in a repressed state in adults. Like all repressed wishes,
these too seek gratification, and like them they are typically gratified—if
they are gratified at all—in symbolic disguise. In addition to dreams,
repressed wishes may be represented and (partially) gratified in the many
privately constructed symbolic forms (including symptoms) which have
been described and classified by psychiatrists. Typically, however, such
wishes, particularly if they are widely shared, are represented and gratified
in culturally-constituted rather than privately-constructed symbolic forms.
Although many cultural systems—from games through politics—can be
and have been used for this purpose, I would argue that religion is the
system, par excellence, which is used for the disguised representation and
gratification of the repressed wishes with which we are concerned here—
dependency and aggressive wishes with regard to the parents of childhood.
This is certainly the case in traditional societies, and if newspaper reports
and television broadcasts can be taken as evidence, it is also the case, to a
larger extent than we usually credit, in certain strata of modern society as
well.
That religion should be a focal system for the gratification of these
wishes is hardly surprising if the explanation which I have offered for the
meaning of its symbols is valid. For if the cultural symbols which represent
the superhuman beings of the mythicoreligious world signify, in their ‘deep’
meaning, the reified and externalized mental representations of the parents
of childhood, what better way to express and gratify unconscious rage
toward and dependency longings for these parents than through the vehicle
of religious beliefs and rituals?
My thesis, then, is that when religious actors invoke the assistance of
benevolent superhuman beings, or exorcise malevolent superhuman beings,
they are not only consciously gratifying dependency and aggressive needs
in regard to beings who are their culturally appropriate objects and targets,
but they are also doing more than that. For if the actors’ mental
representations of these benevolent and malevolent superhuman beings are
merged with the reified and projected representations of their kindly and
hateful parents of childhood, then, they are simultaneously, but
unconsciously, gratifying their dependency and aggressive needs in regard
to their childhood parents, their culturally inappropriate objects and targets.
That religion-in-use serves this (latent) function explains at least one of the
unconscious motivational bases for the belief in the reality of the
mythicoreligious world. I might add that if this argument is valid, religion
also serves an equally important latent function for society. For if religion-
in-use is a means for the symbolic gratification of these powerful infantile
needs, society is thereby spared the highly disruptive consequences of their
direct gratification. But that is a topic for another paper.
We may now summarize the implications of this paper, with respect to
both its specifically religious argument and its more general cultural-
symbolic argument. The former argument has been concerned with only
one problem related to the explanation of religious systems, the problem of
why religious actors believe in the reality of the mythicoreligious world.
Whether or not the particular solution offered here is correct is less
important, however, than its underlying thesis that a comprehensive
explanation for such a belief must attend to at least three dimensions of the
problem: (a) the private, as well as public meanings of religious symbols;
(b) their ‘deep,’ or socially acquired meanings, as well as their ‘surface,’ or
culturally transmitted meanings; and (c) the latent, as well as the manifest
functions of the actor’s belief that these symbols signify a real, and not
merely a representational world. An explanation that ignores any of these
dimensions is, I have tried to show, incomplete.
To arrive at such a comprehensive explanation, I further attempted to
show, we must be as much concerned with the properties and processes of
the human mind as with the properties of cultural symbols and the doctrines
which they represent. Although Durkheim’s insistence that collective
representations constitute the focus of anthropological investigation marked
a giant leap forward in the study of sociocultural systems, he made a serious
error in ruling out the study of mental representations as irrelevant to their
study. For, as this paper has attempted to show, any cultural system is a vital
force in society so long as there is a correspondence between the symbols in
which cultural doctrines are represented and their representation as beliefs
in the minds of social actors. When such a correspondence does not obtain,
a cultural system may yet survive, but it survives as a fossil—as a set of
cliches—rather than as a living force. If this is so, then the study of mental
representations is no less important than that of collective representations
for the anthropological enterprise.
My argument, however, makes an even more radical claim, namely, that
in attending to the human mind it is as important to understand its
unconscious, as well as its conscious processes. Although a knowledge of
conscious cognitions and motives can help us to understand the ‘surface’
meanings and manifest functions of cultural symbols, knowledge of
unconscious cognitions and motives is required to understand their ‘deep’
meanings and latent functions. Lest I be misunderstood, I have not argued,
as an older generation of psychoanalytic theorists was sometimes prone to
do, that the latter meanings and functions are more important for the
understanding of symbols (whether cultural or noncultural) than the former.
I have argued, however, that they are no less important.
Notes
Reprinted from On Symbols in Anthropology: Essays in Honor of Harry Hoijer, edited by Jacques
Maquet (Malibu: Udena Publications, 1982), pp. 45–72. © 1982 by Melford E. Spiro.
I am indebted to Jacques Maquet and Walter Goldschmidt for inviting me to participate in the
second series of lectures in honor of Harry Hoijer, and to Roy G. D’Andrade, Fitz John Poole,
Theodore Schwartz, Marc J. Swartz, and Donald F. Tuzin for their valuable criticisms of an earlier
draft of this paper. I wish to acknowledge my gratitude to the National Institute of Mental Health for
its support of a research project on the comparative study of culturally-constituted defense
mechanisms, some of whose findings are incorporated in this paper.
References
Introduction 1
1. Work on this paper is part of a cross-cultural study of religion supported by research grant M-
2255 from the National Institutes of Health, U.S. Public Health Service.
Needs
As a concept in the social sciences, ‘need’ has been borrowed from two
sources: biology and psychology. Its ambiguity as a social science concept
stems from a confusion in its two possible meanings. In biology ‘need’
refers to what might be termed a ‘want’, i.e. to some requirement which
must be satisfied if an organism is to survive. In psychology, on the other
hand, it refers to what might be termed a ‘desire’, i.e. a wish to satisfy some
felt drive by the attainment of some goal. These two meanings may, of
course, overlap. Thus water satisfies an organic want and it may also be the
object of desire. Just as frequently, however, they do not overlap. The
circulation of the blood is a want, but—for most animals, at any rate—it is
not the object of desire. In sociological and, especially, in functionalist
discourse, much confusion has resulted from not distinguishing these two
meanings of ‘need’ when it is applied to society. In this paper I shall, when
clarity does not suffer, use the generic ‘need’ to refer both to sociological
wants and to psychological desires. Otherwise, I shall use ‘sociological
want to refer to any functional requirement of society; and I shall use
‘desire’ in its motivational sense. I hasten to add that desires are not
necessarily ‘selfish’, oriented to the welfare of the self. The goal, by whose
attainment a drive is satisfied, may be—and, obviously, it often is—the
welfare of an entire group, or of one or more of its constituent members.
We may now return to our question. If the practice of religion is
instigated by the expectation of satisfying needs, by which set of needs—
desires or wants—is its practice to be explained? It should be perfectly
obvious that although behavior can satisfy both wants and desires, it is
motivated by desires, not by wants. Wants in themselves have no causal
properties. The absorption of moisture, for example, is a functional
requirement of plants; but this requirement cannot cause the rains to fall.
Human behavior, to be sure, is different from the growth of plants. A social
group may recognize the existence of some, at least, of its functional
requirements, and these recognized wants may constitute a set of stimulus
conditions which evoke responses for their satisfaction. Notice, however,
that it is not the functional requirement—even when it is recognized—
which evokes the response, but rather the wish to satisfy it. A functional
requirement of society becomes a stimulus for a response, i.e. it acquires
motivational value if, and only if (a) it is recognized, and (b) its satisfaction
becomes an object of desire. If the functional requirement of social
solidarity, for example, is not recognized, or, if recognized, it is not an
object of desire, or, although both recognized and desired, it is not the
desire whose intended satisfaction motivates the practice of the variable to
be explained, it cannot be used to explain behavior, even though need-
satisfaction may be one of its consequences. If social solidarity is a
consequence—an unintended consequence—of the practice of religion,
social solidarity is properly explained by reference to the religious behavior
by which it is achieved; but religion, surely, is improperly explained by
reference to social solidarity. An unintended consequence of behavior—
however important it may be—can hardly be its cause. If religious behavior
is to be explained by reference to those functions which it serves—and,
indeed, it must be—the functions must be those that are intended, not those
that are unintended (and probably unrecognized). We must, therefore,
remind ourselves of some elementary distinctions among functions.
Functions
I should like, first, to distinguish between ‘psychological’ and ‘sociological’
functions. The psychological functions of behavior consist in the
satisfaction of desires,5 its sociological functions consist in the satisfaction
of functional requirements.
5. That a function ‘psychological’ does not mean that the object of desire is psychological. The
object of desire may be political, meteorological, economic, nutritional, sexual—and all other goals
known to man. These goals are cathected because they satisfy some drive, acquired or innate. The
attainment of the goal reduces the drive or, alternatively, satisfies the desire. The satisfaction of the
desire—or, more realistically, the set of desires—whose intended (conscious or unconscious)
satisfaction instigates behavior is its ‘psychological’ function.
Second, I should like to distinguish between ‘manifest’ and ‘latent’
functions. In his now-classic analysis of functional explanation, Merton
(1957) distinguished between intended and recognized functions—which he
termed ‘manifest’—and unintended and unrecognized functions—which he
termed ‘latent’. Merton’s dichotomous classification can be shown to yield
a four-class functional typology. In addition to intended-recognized and
unintended-unrecognized functions, we can also distinguish intended-
unrecognized and unintended-recognized functions (Spiro 1961a). The
latter is a simple concept to grasp; social solidarity may be a recognized
function of religious ritual, for example, although the intention of satisfying
this functional requirement may not motivate its performance. An intended-
unrecognized function, however, seems paradoxical. Assuming that
intentions may be conscious as well as unconscious, this paradox is more
apparent than real; if a behavior pattern is unconsciously motivated—or,
more realistically, if its motivational set includes both conscious and
unconscious intentions—one of its functions, although intended, is
unrecognized.
The final distinction I should like to make is between real and apparent
functions. ‘Real functions’ are those which, in principle at least, can be
discovered by the anthropologist, whether or not they are recognized by the
actors. ‘Apparent functions’ are those which the actors attribute to the
sociocultural variable in question, but which cannot be confirmed by
scientific investigation.
With these distinctions in mind, we may now attempt to answer the
question with which we began this section. If institutional behavior in
general is motivated by the expectation of satisfying desires, to what extent
can religious behavior, specifically, be explained within this framework?
That is, what desires are satisfied by religion? Since this question remains
one of the unfinished tasks of empirical research, I can only make some
tentative suggestions. As I interpret the record, I would suggest that there
are at least three sets of desires which are satisfied by religion and which—
for lack of better terms—I shall call cognitive, substantive, and expressive.
The corresponding functions of religion can be called adjustive, adaptive,
and integrative.
Cognitive
I believe that it can be shown that everywhere man has a desire to know, to
understand, to find meaning;6 and I would suggest—although this is a
terribly old-fashioned nineteenth-century idea—that religious beliefs are
held, and are of ‘concern’, to religious actors because, in the absence of
competitive explanations, they satisfy this desire. Religious belief systems
provide the members of society with meaning and explanation for otherwise
meaningless and inexplicable phenomena.
6. The most striking evidence, on the simplest perceptual level, of this ‘need’ for meaning is
provided by the cross-cultural use of the Rorschach test. As Hallowell has observed (1956:476–88),
the most dramatic finding of cross-cultural Rorschach investigations is that at every level of
technological and cultural development in which this test has been administered, subjects have
attempted to offer ‘meaningful’ responses to what are, objectively, ‘meaningless’ ink-blots. The
insistence, even on the part of ‘primitive’ peoples, on finding meaning in what is for them an exotic
task—something concerning which many anthropologists had been skeptical—is certainly consistent
with the assumption concerning a universal need for meaning.
‘Meaning’, of course, is often used in two senses. It may be used in an
exclusively cognitive sense, as when one asks for the meaning of a natural
phenomenon, of a historical event, of a sociological fact. In this sense, it has
the connotation of ‘explanation’, as that word is typically used. But
‘meaning’ is also used in a semantic-affective sense, as when one asks for
the meaning of unequal life-fates, frustration, or death. The phenomena for
which religion provides meaning, in this second sense of ‘meaning’, have
been classified by Weber under the general rubric of ‘suffering’ (Gerth &
Mills 1946: ch. 11). The main function of the higher religions, he argues, is
to provide meaning for suffering (and some means to escape from or to
transcend it).
Although the range of phenomena for which religious beliefs provide
meaning in the first, explanatory, sense of meaning’, occupies a broad
spectrum, some structuralists hold to the peculiar notion that man’s
curiosity is so limited that religious explanations, regardless of their
ostensible meaning, are concerned almost exclusively with phenomena of
social structure. Again I should like to use an example from Leach—
although the example concerns magical rather than religious belief—
because, with his usual verve, he adopts what I would think to be an
extreme position.
In his highly critical evaluation of Frazer, Leach (1961) tells us that
Frazer (and Roth, too) is naïve in interpreting Australian explanations for
conception as in fact referring to conception—and, therefore, as reflecting
ignorance of physiological paternity. According to the ‘modern
interpretation’, their notions of conception are to be seen, not as biological,
but as sociological, statements. Let us examine the ethnographic facts, as
Leach (p. 376) quotes them from Roth. Among the Tully River Blacks,
A woman begets children because (a) she has been sitting over the fire on
which she has roasted a particular species of black bream, which must have
been given to her by the prospective father, (b) she has purposely gone a -
hunting and caught a certain kind of bull-frog, (c) some man may have told
her to be in an interesting condition, or (d) she may dream of having the
child put inside her.
Both Frazer and Roth agree—and, I may add, I agree with them—that
these statements are addressed to the problem to which they appear to be
addressed—the problem of conception; and they agree that from these
statements it may validly be deduced that the aborigines are ignorant of
physiological paternity, believing rather that conception is the result of four
kinds of ‘magical’ causation. Leach will have none of this. For him (ibid.) it
is not
a legitimate inference to assert that these Australian aborigines were ignorant of the connection
between copulation and pregnancy. The modern interpretation of the rituals described would be
that in this society the relationship between the woman’s child and the clansmen of the woman’s
husband stems from public recognition of the bonds of marriage, rather than from the fact of
cohabitation, which is a very normal state of affairs.
Substantive
The most obvious basis for religious behavior is the one which any
religious actor tells us about when we ask him—and, unlike some
anthropologists, I believe him. He believes in superhuman beings and he
performs religious ritual in order that he may satisfy what I am calling
substantive desires: desires for rain, nirvana, crops, heaven, victory in war,
recovery from illness, and countless others. Everywhere man’s mammalian
desires (those which can be satisfied by naturalistic goals) must be satisfied,
and in the absence of competing technologies which confer reasonable
confidence, religious techniques are believed to satisfy these desires.
Almost everywhere, moreover, the human awareness of the cessation of
existence and/or of the unsatisfactory character of existence, produces
anxiety concerning the persistence of existence (in some cases, it is desired;
in others, it is not desired), and in the absence of competing goals for the
reduction of anxiety, belief that one is successfully pursuing these religious
goals (heaven-like or nirvana-like states) serves to reduce this anxiety.
Most, if not all, of these substantive desires, then, can be classified as
attempts to overcome or transcend suffering. The religious actor wishes to
overcome specific suffering—economic, political, physical, and the like;
and he wishes to transcend more general suffering induced by some
conception of life and the world as being evil, frustrating, sinful, and so on.
Religion, as Weber (1930) points out, not only provides an explanation for,
but it also promises redemption from, suffering. Religious techniques—
performance of ritual, compliance with morality, faith, meditation, etc.—are
the means by which this promise is felt to be fulfilled.
For the religious actor, if we can believe him, the expectation of realizing
this promise is the most important motivational basis for religous behavior;
the realization of this promise is its function. For him, it is an intended and
recognized function. Believing in its reality, he clings tenaciously to his
religious beliefs and practices—however irrational they may seem, and
however dysfunctional with respect to other ends their consequences may
be. From the anthropologist’s point of view—and this is what presents such
a knotty problem to many classical functionalists—these functions are
apparent; they are not real. Ritual cannot effect rainfall, prayer cannot cure
organic diseases, nirvana is a figment of the imagination, etc. It is this
seeming irrationality of religion and, therefore, the apparent—rather than
real—nature of its intended functions, that has given rise, I believe, to
misplaced emphases on the importance of its sociological functions. Thus,
despite Merton’s incisive analysis of functional theory, it is highly
questionable if the persistence of Hopi rain ceremonies is to be explained
by the social integration to which he (Merton) thinks their performance is
conducive (their real, but latent, functions), rather than by the
meteorological events to which Hopi think they are conducive (their
manifest, but apparent, functions).
The Hopi belief in the efficacy of their rainmaking ritual is not irrational
—although it is certainly false—because the conclusion, rain ceremonies
cause the rains to fall, follows validly from a world-view whose major
premise states that gods exist, and whose minor premise states that the
behavior of the gods can be influenced by rituals. That the premises are
false does not render them irrational—until or unless they are discontinued
by evidence. But all available ‘evidence’ confirms their validity: whenever
the ceremonies are performed it does, indeed, rain. Hence, given their
‘behavioral environment’ (Hallowell 1955:75–110), Hopi beliefs are not
irrational; and given their ecological environment, the apparent function of
these ceremonies is surely a sufficient explanation for their persistence. (For
further argument, see Spiro 1964).
If it is not sufficient, however, no appeal to unintended sociological
functions will provide us with a better explanation—indeed, as we have
already seen, it can provide us with no explanation at all. For how can the
function of social solidarity explain the practice of these—or of any other—
rituals? Notice that the objection to such an explanation is not that social
solidarity may not be an object of desire—there is no reason why it cannot;
and it is not that social solidarity is not achieved by the practice of these
rituals—it often is. The objection, rather, is that the achievement of this end
is not the desire which the practice of these rituals is intended to satisfy.
Surely, not even the proponents of this type of explanation would suggest
that Hopi rain ceremonies, sacrifices to Kali, exorcism of demons,
celebration of the Mass, and the like are practiced with the conscious
intention of achieving social solidarity. Is it suggested, then, that this is their
unconscious intention? I would doubt that anyone would make this
suggestion, for this suggests that if the efficacy of these rituals for the
attainment of their designated ends were to be disbelieved, they would
nevertheless be performed so that their solidarious functions might be
served. This argument surely cannot be sustained. I can only conclude, then,
that the persistence of these rituals is explicable by reference to what, for
anthropologists, are their apparent, rather than their real, functions.7
7. One might, of course, wish to defend the weaker thesis, viz. that if these practices were
sociologically dysfunctional, they would eventually disappear. Even this thesis is somewhat doubtful,
however, when applied to multi-religious societies in which the practice of religion, however
solidarious it may be for each religious group, has important dysfunctional consequences for the total
social system. Still these religions persist, and with undiminished vigor, despite—one is tempted to
say, because of—these consequences.
Even if it were to be conceded that institutions must have real, rather than
apparent, functions, anthropologists must surely be aware of those real
functions of ritual which are recognized by religious actors and which may,
therefore, reenforce their practice. For although religious ritual may not, in
fact, be efficacious for the elimination of poverty, the restoration of health,
the bringing of rain, and the like, the belief that it does achieve these ends
serves the important psychological (real) function of reducing hopelessness
—and its attendant anxiety—concerning their otherwise impossible
attainment.
Expressive
In sum, from the fact that religion is a sufficient condition for the
satisfaction of a requirement, it is invalidly deduced that it is a necessary
condition. And, if it is not a necessary condition, its existence cannot be
explained by arguing that without it society could not survive.
Although it is society, rather than religion, which is explained by the
sociological consequences of religion, social anthropology—as the
comparative study of social and cultural systems—is most certainly
concerned with these functions; and psychological variables are not only
necessary for the explanation of religion, but without them certain of its
sociological functions would go unrecognized. (The classic example, of
course, is Weber’s [1930] analysis of the rise of capitalism, but it deals with
the change in, rather than the persistence of, a social system.) Thus, the
adjustive (real) function of religion, by satisfying the need for explanation,
provides a society with a common ‘behavioral environment’ which, as
Hallowell (1955) observes, satisfies a set of minimal requirements for the
existence of any society: the requirement for a common object orientation,
spatiotemporal orientation, motivational orientation, and normative
orientation. It would be difficult to conceive of the possibility of social
integration without a minimum level of such shared orientations.
The adaptive (apparent) function of religion, in satisfying the desire for
the attainment of goals, provides—as Marxism has stressed—a most
important basis for social stability. Disbelief in the efficacy of superhuman
means for the achievement of this-worldly goals could certainly become a
potential basis for social discontent and socioeconomic change. At the same
time, the (real) function of religion in reducing anxiety concerning the
attainment of goals—especially those for whose attainment available
technological skills are ineffective—and, thus, in providing a minimum
level of psychological security, serves to release energy for coping with the
reality problems of society.
Finally, the inteerative (real) function of religion, in allowing the
disguised expression of repressed motives, serves a number of sociological
functions. By providing a culturally approved means for the resolution of
inner conflict (between personal desires and cultural norms), religion (a)
reduces the probability of psychotic distortion of desires, thereby providing
a society with psychologically healthy members,11 (b) protects society from
the socially disruptive consequences of direct gratification of these
forbidden desires, (c) promotes social integration by providing a common
goal (superhuman beings) and a common means (ritual) by which the
desires may be gratified.
11. Nadel, recognizing the ‘defensive’ function of religion, writes that in providing rituals by
which forbidden impulses may be expressed, religion “… anticipates as well as canalizes the working
of psychological mechanisms, which might otherwise operate in random fashion or beyond the
control of society, in the ‘private worlds’ of neurosis and psychopathic fantasies” (1954:275).
Conclusion
It would appear from the foregoing discussion that an adequate explanation
for the persistence of religion requires both psychological and sociological
variables. If the cognitive bases for religious belief have their roots in
childhood experience, their explanation must be found in social structural
and, more specifically, family structure variables. Here religion is the
dependent variable, and family structure is the independent sociological
variable which effects religious belief by means of such intervening
psychological variables as fantasies, projections, perceptions, and the like.
If religion persists because of its gratification of desires, explanations for
the bases of religious behavior must be found in psychological and,
specifically, motivational variables. Here, again, religion is the dependent,
and motivation is the independent, variable. Since, however, motivation
consists in the intention of gratifying desires, and since desires are rooted
either in organic or in acquired drives, the motivational roots of religious
behavior can, ultimately, be found in those biological and social structural
variables, respectively, by which they are produced and/or canalized. Again,
it is the family which emerges as the crucial sociological variable. Religion,
then, is to be explained in terms of society and personality.
Many studies of religion, however, are concerned not with the
explanation of religion, but with the role of religion in the explanation of
society. Here, the explanatory task is to discover the contributions which
religion, taken as the independent variable, makes to societal integration, by
its satisfaction of sociological wants. This is an important task, central to
the main concern of anthropology, as the science of social systems. We
seriously err, however, in mistaking an explanation of society for an
explanation of religion which, in effect, means confusing the sociological
functions of religion with the bases for its performance.
In this paper, I have been concerned almost exclusively with the latter
aspect of religion. I have not, except incidentally, dealt with its sociological
functions or, what is perhaps more important, with how these are to be
measured. I have not dealt, moreover, with the problem of religious origins
because—despite the fact that numerous speculations have been proposed
(and I have my own, as well)—these are not testable. Nor have I dealt with
the problem of the cross-cultural variability in religion, except to suggest
some motivational bases for the persistence of different types of belief and
ritual. But the crucial problems—to which Max Weber has most
importantly contributed—I have not even touched upon. If, for example,
religion is centrally concerned with the problem of ‘suffering’, why is it that
explanations for suffering run such a wide gamut: violation of ethical
norms, sin of ancestors, misconduct in a previous incarnation, etc.? Or, if
religion promises redemption from suffering, how are the different types of
redemption to be explained? And, moreover, what is the explanation for the
different means by which the redemptive promise is to be achieved? These
are but a few of the central problems in the study of religion with which this
chapter, with its limited focus, has not been concerned.
Acknowledgments
Thanks are due to the author, the editor, and the American Academy of Arts
and Sciences for permission to quote the passage from “Golden Bough or
Gilded Twig?” by E. R. Leach, in Daedalus, 1961.
Note
Reprinted from Anthropological Approaches to the Study of Religion, edited by Michael Banton
(London: Tavistock Publications, 1966), pp. 85–126.
References
Introduction
IN HIS CLASSIC report, W. E. Roth (1903:22) described the conception beliefs
of the Tully River Blacks. None assigns a procreative role to the father.
Although sexual connection as a cause of conception is not recognized among the Tully River
blacks so far as they are themselves concerned, it is admitted as true for all animals:—indeed this
idea confirms them in their belief of superiority over the brute creation. A woman begets children
because (a) she has been sitting over the fire on which she has roasted a particular species of
black bream, which must have been given to her by the prospective father, (b) she has purposely
gone a-hunting and caught a certain kind of bullfrog, (c) some man may have told her to be in an
interesting condition, or (d) she may dream of having a child put inside her.
By whichever of the above methods the child is conceived, whenever it eventually appears, the
recognized husband accepts it as his own without demur. (My emphasis.)
1. Since my entire contribution to the present controversy is confined to this brief statement, it
is rather intriguing to know by what modes of inference Dr. Leach was able to conclude in his
most recent contribution that (to take some examples at random):
Professor Spiro believes that explanation consists of postulating causes and ultimate origins
for the facts under observation (Leach 1967:39).
He is positively eager to believe that the aborigines were ignorant and he accepts their
assertion as a fact without investigating the evidence at all (1967:41, original emphasis).
He displays an extreme reluctance to believe that the products of aboriginal thought can be
structured in a logical way (1967:41, my emphasis).
Professor Spiro (and all the neo-Tyloreans who think like him) desperately wants to believe
… that dogma and ritual must somehow correspond to the inner psychological attitudes of the
actors concerned (1967:40, my emphasis).
Although Leach’s attribution of a racist ideology to his opponents is, like all
ad hominem arguments, irrelevant to the substantive issues of this
controversy, it must nevertheless be examined because it looms so large in
his lecture: it is, he claims, the “crux” of the controversy (1967:45). Leach’s
argument is simply stated. That Australians are ignorant of physiological
paternity is not a scientific finding, but a personal prejudice based on the
conviction that primitive peoples are intellectually inferior and incapable of
logical thought.
To say that a native is ignorant [notice the escalation of the specific, “ignorant of physiological
paternity,” to the generic, “ignorant”] amounts to saying that he is childish, stupid, superstitious.
Ignorance is the opposite of rationality; it is the quality which distinguishes the savage from the
anthropologist (1967:41, original emphasis).
I think it is rather inconsistent to get excited about the faulty knowledge of the Trobrianders when
it comes to processes of sexual fertilisation, wnile we are perfectly satisfied that they possess no
real knowledge as to processes of nutrition, or metabolism, the causes of disease and health, or
any other subject of natural history … (Malinowski 1932:ii).
Although space forbids the citation of similar statements by, for example,
Roth (1903:23), Malinowski (1932:ii sqq), Kaberry (1939: ch. 2), Spiro
(1964:109–10), etc., the conclusion is inescapable. It is not true that those
anthropologists who believe that the aborigines are ignorant of
physiological paternity either view their ignorance as childish, or view them
as intellectually inferior.
2. The Argument from the Australian Evidence
Since those who hold that the Australians are ignorant of physiological
paternity base their conclusion, according to Leach, on prejudice, an
objective examination of the ethnographical data, so he argues, supports his
thesis that the Australians are not ignorant of physiological paternity. I
submit that, with one exception, none of the data which Leach cites support
this conclusion.
Leach’s first argument is that there is a “classically established reason”
for supposing that the Tully River Blacks were not ignorant: “They freely
admitted to Roth that the cause of pregnancy in animals other than man is
copulation” (Leach 1967:40). Since that is the entire argument and the full
quotation, it is rather difficult to divine precisely what the force of this
argument might be:9 that we can best know about a people’s beliefs about
themselves from their beliefs about animals? But then Dr. Leach would
have to concede that the Trobrianders and the Arunta, for example, are
indeed ignorant of physiological paternity because they, like many other
groups, deny any procreative basis for animal pregnancy. (For the
Trobriands, cf. Malinowski 1932:162; Austin 1934:112; for the Arunta, cf.
Spencer & Gillen 1899:84, v. 2.) Moreover, people everywhere make
distinctions between themselves and animals, sometimes invidious to
themselves, sometimes invidious to the animals. In the Tully River case the
latter is the case, as Roth tells us: “This idea confirms them in their belief of
superiority over the brute creation.”
9. In order to forestall Leach’s penchant for impugning the scholarly knowledge of his opponents, I
would only comment that know the arguments of Roheim, Warner, and Thomson on the subject. It is
Leach’s that I am unaware of.
Leach’s second argument is that the data of the more recent
ethnographers, working in other parts of Australia, show that Australian
conception beliefs are cultural dogmas, “a kind of religious fiction”; hence
the “formally expressed ignorance” reflected in the dogmas does not
correspond to the attitudes of the social actors (Leach 1967:40). Ignoring
the debatable methods by which data from other parts of Australia are used
to refute the Tully River data, or (even conceding that) by which data
collected thirty to fifty years after the original report are used (considering
the variety of ensuing acculturative forces) to interpret its meaning, my
reading of these data is rather different from his.
Of the six ethnographies which Leach says support his position Warner’s
alone (1937) can be claimed; the others are either unclear, or else they
refute it. Thus, Stanner (1933) argues that the “confused version” of
physiological paternity, which is found side by side with a “mystical
theory” among the Daly River tribes, is a result of acculturation. Meggitt,
although certainly stressing that the contemporary Walbiri (especially the
females) emphasise both spiritual and physical causes of pregnancy, is
cautious, in view of Spencer and Gillen’s data, about drawing conclusions
conerning the beliefs of former generations from contemporary data.
“Although it is clear,” he writes, “that people in the past recognized the fact
of physiological maternity, we cannot be sure to what extent they were
aware of physiological paternity” (Meggitt 1962:272). Roheim, although
arguing that the Australians are indeed aware of physiological paternity, yet
admits that following initiation, the knowledge is repressed, i.e., it is
rendered unconscious (Roheim 1932:97); on a conscious level, adults are
ignorant.
Thus far, then, Leach’s contention that his position is supported by recent
ethnographers, is rather misleading. When, however, he includes Sharp and
Thomson (1933) among those whose data allegedly support him, his
contention is not only misleading, it is untrue. Lauriston Sharp (in letters
written from the field to Ashley Montagu) states repeatedly that the Yir-
Yiront are literally ignorant of physiological paternity. Moreover, after three
years of fieldwork he expresses astonishment that their ignorance “…
should by some be considered as an indication that they must be moronic”
(Sharp, in Ashley Montagu 1937:162–65). As for Thomson, although he
reports that the Koko Ya’o believe in the procreative function of semen,
their procreative knowledge remains as “magical” as—and, from Leach’s
view, even more “irrational” than—that of the other Australian tribes. For,
while affirming physiological paternity, they strongly deny physiological
maternity: “Informants … treated contemptuously any suggestion that the
mother has any part in conception” (Thomson 1933:506).10
10. Leach concedes that the data of at least one “modern” ethnographer—Phyllis Kaberry—do not
support his thesis; but he attributes this fact to her faulty interpretation. When properly interpreted, he
argues, her data support him. Thus, he claims, Kaberry’s finding concerning the belief in a spirit-
child theory of conception means that the entry of a spirit-child into a woman is a sign of pregnancy,
not its cause. Commenting on Kaberry’s report, he writes (1967:47). “In other words, a woman
recognizes that she is pregnant when she experiences ‘morning sickness’—which is true also of
European women” (my emphasis). Now, in addition to his misreading of European ethnoscience—
European women recognize pregnancy by the stopping of their menses, an event which occurs before
morning sickness—Leach has misread Kaberry as well. For, in the passage quoted by Leach, Kaberry
writes: “Conception occurs when one of these [spirit children] enters a woman. Its presence in the
food given her by her husband makes her vomit …” (Leach 1967:47, my emphasis). I submit that
“conception occurs” does not mean “… a woman recognises that she is pregnant… Exegesis aside,
however, although Kaberry herself interprets this belief as referring to the cause of conception, not its
recognition, Leach’s only rebuttal is to state that it is not so.
Again, to Kaberry’s comment that, “Questioned on the function of intercourse natives admitted
that it prepared the way for the entry of the spirit child” (Leach 1967:47). Leach is “very puzzled as
to how anyone [i.e. Kaberry] could interpret such data as indicating ‘ignorance of physiological
paternity.’” But I am puzzled by Leach’s puzzlement. It is one thing to say that sexual intercourse
opens the vagina so that the spirit child can enter the woman—a frequently recorded belief in
Australia; it is quite another to say that it impregnates the woman, especially when the conception
belief states explicitly that only the spirit-child does that. The issue, in short, is whether intercourse is
believed to be the cause of pregnancy, and this the natives deny. As Ashley Montagu (1937:200),
summarizing all of the data on this question, remarks: [When the anthropologist] inquires whether
intercourse has any connection with pregnancy or childbirth he is in most cases informed that
intercourse serves to prepare the woman for the entry of a spirit child into her, but that this
preparation is not in itself the cause of pregnancy or of the entry of the child into the woman … In
other words, intercourse prepares the way for that factor to become operative which is the cause of
pregnancy [spirit child entry], but intercourse is not either alone or in conjunction with other factors
the cause of pregnancy.
Leach’s last argument in support of his thesis that the Tully River Blacks
believe in physiological paternity is that the alleged ignorance of
physiological paternity in the Trobriands is seriously to be questioned.
Thus, Leach claims that 1) by 1932 Malinowski had seriously qualified his
original position; 2) Powell and Austin, independently, had recorded
observations “strikingly similar” to those of Meggitt on the Walbiri; 3)
Fortune showed that Trobriand “ignorance” reflected religious dogma,
rather than the state of their knowledge. Ignoring again the methodological
problem, the fact is that all of these claims (with the exception of the one
concerning Powell) are demonstrably false.
In summary, then, the Australian data cited by Leach are, for the most
part, the reverse of what he purports them to be. 1) That Tully River Blacks
admit that sexual intercourse is the cause of animal pregnancy is true, but
its implication for the issue at hand is unclear. 2) Contrary to Leach’s
argument, the modern ethnographies cited by him refute his claims that as
cultural “dogmas” Australian conception beliefs are not taken seriously. 3)
Contrary to Leach’s argument, Malinowski’s data on the Trobriand remain
unchanged by either what he, or any of the other scholars cited by Leach
(with the possible exception of Powell) have written.
Referring to the numerous European folk tales which recount the magical
conception of gods and heroes, Leach (1967:40) observes that “some of
these stories resemble very closely indeed the account given to Roth by the
Tully River Blacks of how ordinary human births occur” (original
emphasis). He then asks, rhetorically:
But if the existence of European tales about ladies who became pregnant after eating magical fish
is not now held to imply that Europeans are, or were, ignorant of the facts of physiological
paternity, why should such stories have this implication in the case of the Tully River Blacks?
But Leach’s analogical argument does not stop there. If, as he argues, the
dogma of the Virgin Birth is not held to imply ignorance of physiological
paternity it is because, being a dogma, its biological message is not taken
very seriously; rather it serves to “reinforce the dogma that the Virgin’s
child is the son of God” (1967:32). Now ignoring the logical difficulty
posed by this argument—since the “dogma” that the Virgin’s child is the
son of God is one and the same dogma, it is difficult to understand how a
dogma can reinforce itself—of course (as I would prefer to put it) the
theological function of the Virgin Birth is to legitimize the Christian claim
that Jesus is the son of God. It is not clear, however, why this implies that
the dogma of the Virgin Birth does not have a biological message, or—
since it explicitly states that Jesus was not begotten of Joseph—that this
message is not taken seriously. Indeed, how else, except by denying to
Joseph a procreative role in the conception of Jesus, can the dogma then
assign that role to the third person of the Trinity? And how else can Jesus
be divine unless He is God’s—not Joseph’s—only begotten Son? In short,
were it not for its biological message—Jesus did not have a human genitor
—and were this message not taken seriously, the theological function of the
dogma of the Virgin Birth could not be served.
Having examined Leach’s arguments on behalf of his first thesis, viz.,
that from Australian conception beliefs it may not be inferred that the
natives are ignorant of physiological paternity, we may now turn to his
arguments on behalf of his second thesis, viz., that these beliefs are not
about conception but about patrilateral filiation.
Leach’s real concern, however, is not with the Australian evidence, but with
the Christian analogy, the Virgin Birth. The basic message of the Virgin
Birth—and so, too, the basic message of Australian conception beliefs—is,
according to Dr. Leach, neither biological nor theological, but sociological.
Moreover, it is identical with his interpretation of the Australian conception
beliefs. Thus, from the fact that although the dogma of the Virgin Birth
asserts that God is His father, two of the synoptic Gospels (Matthew and
Luke) provide Jesus with a pedigree which places him “in the direct line of
patrilineal descent from David through Joseph” (Leach 1967:42, original
emphasis), Leach concludes:
In other words the kind of interpretation which I put on Roth’s evidence … has been orthodox
among Christians for about 1600 years. The myth, like the rite, does not distinguish knowledge
from ignorance. It establishes categories and affirms relationships.
That a son should wish to reject knowledge of the fact that his father is
his genitor is not, of course, a strange notion in the annals of child
development. One explanation for this frequently found wish is based on
the assumption—derived from psychoanalytic theory, and supported by a
great deal of empirical evidence—that fathers are both loved and hated, and
that the latter emotion derives from one or both of the following conditions:
resentment over their punitive authority, and/or jealous rivalry for the love
(sexual and/or affectionate) of the mother. But hatred of the father leads to a
typical Oedipal conflict. On the one hand, the child, motivated by
resentment or by rivalry, wishes to harm, to be rid of, the father. On the
other hand, whether from a talion fear (“I want to harm him, therefore he
wants to harm me”) or from guilt (“Since he loves me and/or since I love
him, how can I wish to harm him?”) this wish is extremely painful. In the
absence of institutional or cultural assistance in dealing with this conflict,
the child must cope with it by his own internal resources, of which I shall
mention only two. He can repress his hatred, which is the typical (and
normal) technique found in Western society, or he can express it
symbolically by denying in fantasy that his father is his genitor. (The latter
is often accomplished, both in private fantasy as well as in hero myths, by
the substitution of grandiose fathers—gods, kings, and so on—for the real
father.) Sometimes, it should be added, rather than denying that his father is
genitor, the child denies that he had any genitor: his conception was not
caused by procreation. (For a discussion of the mechanism of denial, cf.
Freud 1946: chaps. 5–7.) Both of these defense-mechanisms resolve the
conscious conflict, but in different ways—the former by rendering the
child’s hatred unconscious, the latter by expressing it by means of a
symbolic short-circuit.
Not all conflicts, however, find resolution by the unaided, intrapsy-chic,
efforts of the individual. Many conflicts, expecially those which are shared
by social actors, are resolved by means of social institutions and cultural
beliefs. Indeed, just as culture has cognitive-explanatory functions, so it has
(among others) affective-integrative functions. My second, alternative,
interpretation of the Australian conception theory views it as having such a
function. This interpretation holds that the spirit-child theory, whatever the
basis for its origin might have been, now serves (this at least would be one
of its functions) to resolve the natives’ Oedipal conflict by providing them
with the cognitive (cultural) basis for denial. By believing in the traditional
conception theory, each Australian is implicitly, but necessarily, denying
that his father is his genitor. For since, according to this cultural theory, all
conceptions are caused by a nonprocreative method, then he too was
conceived without parental intercourse. Hence, his father is not his genitor,
although he is his mother’s husband.
This conception belief not only enables the Australian to deny that his
father is his genitor; it enables him to do so by means of a wish-fulfilling
fantasy. For since, according to this belief, conception is caused by the entry
of a spirit-child into a woman’s womb, he too was a spirit-child, and he too
was conceived by entering the womb of his mother. Hence, since he not
only came out of, but also went into, his mother’s womb, it was his entry,
not his father’s, that caused her to become pregnant. By believing in this
cultural theory, then, the boy takes his father’s place, for, according to this
theory, the son is literally the father of the man—and of the child; he is his
own genitor. By believing in this conception theory, then, the boy both
denies the painful fact that his conception was caused by the sexual
intercourse of his parents, and he fulfills his wish that he take his father’s
place.
If, then, according to the first of these functional interpretations, belief in
the conception theory is motivated by curiosity concerning the cause of
conception, it is motivated according to this second interpretation, by the
child’s pain-induced hatred of his father; and if, according to the first
interpretation, the function of belief is cognitive—it satisfies an intellectual
need—according to the second, its function is ego-integrative—it resolves
emotional conflict. For both interpretations, however, this conception belief
has the same microsociological implication, viz., it implies that father is
pater (either because, according to the first interpretation, genitorship is
unknown; or because, according to the second, it is denied); and for both,
therefore, it has the same macrosociological implication, viz., the basis for
patrilateral filiation is sociological. (For the first explanation these
implications are the unintended—but recognized—functions of ignorance
of physiological paternity; for the second they are the unintended—but
recognized—functions of denial of physiological paternity.)
According to the second interpretation, finally, belief in the conception
theory has an (unintended) interpersonal adaptive function whose
importance exceeds these (adaptively neutral) sociological functions: it
promotes a high degree of amity between father and son. Whether the
culturally assigned basis for the father-son relationship is the father’s
paterhood or his genitorship, the emotional quality of this relationship
depends on (among other things) how the son copes with his hostility to his
father. If the hostility-induced conflict is not resolved, father is, at best, the
affectively neutral mother’s husband, at worst the hated Oedipal figure. It
can be resolved, as we do, intrapsychically, by the repression of the hatred;
or it can be resolved—as suggested by this second interpretation of the
spirit-child belief—culturally, by institutionalized denial. Both techniques
of conflict resolution have their respective advantages and disadvantages.
The second technique can serve to transmute a hated genitor, not merely
into a mother’s husband—a sociological pater—but, if we can believe
Malinowski, into a warm and nurturant father—a psychological pater.
Here, then, is a second functional interpretation of the Australian
conception belief which, like the first, is faithful to the manifest meaning of
the belief, whose internal structure creates no logical difficulties; and whose
sociological and psychological consequences pose no conceptual problems.
Which of these interpretations—if either—is true, cannot be decided from
the available data. Both are consistent with the reported data that the natives
are—or, at least, were—ignorant of physiological paternity, but they
interpret these data differently: and from the data, alone, it cannot be known
whether ignorance is—or, at least, was—based on absence of knowledge or
on denial. Theoretically, there is little to choose between them. The first
explanation is by far the more parsimonious; the second copes with the
ethnographical problem raised by procreative ignorance.
Both explanations, finally, are derived from the same model of culture, a
model whose assumptions are, if I understand him correctly, precisely the
reverse of Leach’s. In this model, to mention only those of its assumptions
that are relevant to this controversy, culture serves a number of functions—
not only sociological, but psychological (cognitive and emotional) as well;
cultural theories attend not only to the functional requirements of society,
but also to the functional requirements of social actors—hence, their
messages may relate to nature and human nature, as well as to social
structure; belief in these theories is motivated (by cognitive and/or
emotional needs)—hence their functions and meaning, alike, are often
inexplicable without an awareness of the possible motivational bases for
beliefs; finally, culture is man’s most important means of adapting to the
condition of being human—hence, since psychological tension (including
cognitive curiosity and emotional conflict) is a persistent feature of that
condition, cultural beliefs represent, among other things, the attempts of
social groups to cope with these tensions.18
18. After receiving proofs, my attention was called to still a third possible basis for ignorance of
physiological paternity (at least among the Trobrianders) in a suggestion made by Dorothy Lee. In
her ingenious reconstruction of Trobriand thought (Lee 1940), she suggests that Trobriand conceptual
categories do not allow for the perception of teleology, in any strict sense of that term; that the
cultural emphasis is on the “essential, rather than the accidental or relational” (361); that, given this
conceptual set, events are viewed as “self-contained and essentially unrelated” (360); and that serial
events are perceived to exhibit “simple sequence” rather than causal relationship. If this be so, then—
as Lee herself observes (358)—Trobriand ignorance of physiological paternity might be a function of
their (culturally based) nonteleological, cognitive set.
If her reconstruction is sound, this epistemological hypothesis—that Trobriand cognition is
concerned with things (objects, events, essences) rather than with relationships among things—is
consistent with either of the two hypotheses advanced in the text to account for ignorance of
physiological paternity. The cultural hypothesis becomes, then, a theorem which is deducible from
the epistemological axiom; and the psychological hypothesis becomes a subset of a more
comprehensive theory which would attempt to discover the psychodynamic function of a cultural
epistemology that emphasizes things over relationships.
Note
Reprinted from Man: The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, vol. 3, no. 2 (June
1968):224–61. This article was written while I was a Research Fellow in the Social Science Research
Institute, University of Hawaii. It has importantly benefited from the criticisms of Robert I. Levy and
David M. Schneider.
References
There has been a strong tendency in structural and symbolic anthropology to assume that sex and
aggression are of no concern to cultural symbol systems. Even when cultural beliefs, myths, or
rituals are explicitly and preponderantly sexual or aggressive in content, they are typically
interpreted as metaphors for social structural themes. This thesis is illustrated with respect to
aggression by an analysis of Lévi-Strauss, interpretation of a Bororo myth, after which the
assumptions that structural theory makes concerning the place of aggression in cultural symbol
systems are contrasted with the opposing assumptions of psychoanalytic theory
[STRUCTURALISM, PSYCHOANALYSIS, CULTURAL SYMBOL SYSTEMS, MYTH].
Take, for example, the son’s rape of his mother. In the first step in code
switching, that episode is classified by Lévi-Strauss as “incest,” i.e., its
sexual dimension remains but its violence dimension disappears. In the
second step the sexual dimension also disappears, for “incest” becomes a
metaphor—voila!—for the boy’s dependent attachment to his mother. Thus,
since the palms collected by the women in the myth are of the type used for
penis sheaths, that signifies that the son had reached the age of initiation,
when boys are expected to transfer from their mother’s hut to the men’s
house. In such a sociocultural context, the mother-son “incest” (the code
word for the boy’s rape of his mother) signifies the son’s objection to the
“loosening of the maternal bonds” and his “return to the mother’s bosom at
a time when other sons are about to be weaned for good” (1969:56).
As if to emphasize that this translation is not a structuralist spoof, Lévi-
Strauss clinches his argument with the following piece de resistance. Since
the adult hero of a cognate myth, the putative homologue of the boy in the
present myth, is nicknamed “Secluded,” and since, by structuralist
assumptions, the boy can be assumed to have had the same nickname, and
since a secluded boy in the sociocultural context alluded to above is one
who “refuses to be separated from female society,” it follows that the son is
“the sort of boy who, as we say, ‘clings to his mother’s apron strings’”
(1969:57).
And what about the behavior of the boy’s parents? By a similar technique
of code switching, the violent acts in which the mother and father are
respectively involved with their son signify the polar differences in their
“attitudes” toward him. Thus, having classified the son’s rape of his mother
as incest, the mothers “incestuous” relationship with the son is taken to be
indexical of her “close” attitude to the son, while the father’s “murderous”
relationship is indexical of his “remote” attitude to him (1969:138–39).
Thus it is that, by the alchemy of code switching, aggression is simply
abolished as a mythic category: the son’s sexual assault on his mother is
transmuted into his dependency upon her, while the mother’s victimization
by the son’s assault as well as the father’s assaults upon the son are
transmuted into positions on a scale of psychological distance from the son.
Lest I be misunderstood, I hasten to emphasize that I am not un-mindful
of the fact that Lévi-Strauss is not so much interested in the content of
myths, per se, as in their logical structure—“the system of interrelationships
to which we reduce them” (1969:12)—and that, since that aim is achieved
by the structural comparisons of a large corpus of myths, it must be pursued
by means of a code whose concepts are sufficiently abstract to subsume the
concrete concepts of the codes employed by the myths themselves. Since,
however, his code consists not of the formal and content-free symbols of
mathematics and symbolic logic, but of concepts only slightly more abstract
than those of the myths he analyzes, the fact that Lévi-Strauss chooses
concepts that systematically eliminate every theme of violence from these
myths indicates that this consequence is principled rather than fortuitous.
An excellent case in point is the conversion of rape (“incest”) and murder in
the Bororo myth into the attitudes “close” and “remote.”
The attitudes “close” and “remote” are attributed to the parents in the
Bororo myth in order to show that “family attitudes” is one variable in a set
of variables by which this myth can be inferred to be the inversion (and
hence the transform) of the Ge myth. In the latter myth, a young boy who is
left by his brother-in-law to die in the wilderness is rescued by a jaguar,
who then brings him to his own home (thereby becoming his “adopted
father”). The jaguar’s wife (therefore, the boy’s “adopted mother”) dislikes
the boy and tries to kill him, but, encouraged by the jaguar, the boy kills her
instead. As Lévi-Strauss sees it, the parental attitudes exhibited in the
Bororo myth are an inversion of those exhibited in the Ge myth: in the
former the mother is “close” and the father “remote,” whereas in the latter
the father is “close” and the mother “remote.” The dimension close/remote
is a perfectly good dimension for describing attitudes, but there are at least
three reasons for rejecting the assumption that this is the dimension along
which the opposite-sex parents in these myths sustain the logical relation of
binary opposition within each myth and that of identity across the myths.
(a)That the attitudes of the (adopted) Ge parents toward their son exhibit
a relation of binary opposition is self-evident: the father saves the
boy’s life, while the mother attempts to kill him. Nevertheless, even on
the dubious assumption that “close” is an appropriate term to
characterize the attitude expressed in a father’s rescue of a son’s life, to
characterize as “remote” the attitude expressed in a mother’s attempt to
kill her son is surely to distort the meaning of the text beyond
recognition. These designations not only distort the meaning of the text
but are not necessary in order to show that binary opposition in the
parents’ attitudes. Thus, for example, the dimension life-giving/life-
destroying (or some such terms) is not only faithful to the text but
denotes much more effectively the relation of opposition that
characterizes the attitudes of the Ge father and mother to their son.
(b)The dimension close/remote is even less applicable to the Bororo
parents than to the Ge parents. If “remote” which converts lethal
intentions into indifference, is an inappropriate designation for the
murderous father, “close” is entirely misplaced when applied to the
mother. For, whether we remain faithful to the text (and describe the
mother as the victim of her son’s rapacious assault) or distort the text
(and describe her as the object of the son’s “incest”), how can the
attitude “close” or any other attitude be applied either to an involuntary
victim (rape) or a passive object (incest)? If, nevertheless, the
close/remote dimension is still held to be applicable to the mother, I
would have thought that “remote” would be the more appropriate term
because, presumably, one is raped only after resisting (= “remote”)
seduction. But if the mother is “remote,” the Bororo parents cannot be
contrasted along the close/remote dimension unless we are prepared to
designate the father as “close.” Rejecting such sophistry, a relation of
binary opposition can be validly attributed to the Bororo parents only
by comparing them (as I suggested in the case of the Ge parents) along
some dimension that is faithful to the violent themes of the myth itself.
That can be done in one of two ways. Restricting the comparison to the
episodes described in the myth, we can draw a contrast between the
mother, as the victim of violent (sexual) assaults by her son, and the
father, as the agent of violent assaults on his son. Or, going beyond the
episodes described in the myth, we can contrast the parents along the
same dimensions employed in characterizing the Ge parents: the
mother (having borne the son) is life-giving and the father (being
murderous) is life-destroying. From a structuralist point of view, and
consistent with Lévi-Strauss’ aim of showing that the Bororo myth is a
transformation of the Ge, that has the additional advantage of
demonstrating that the attitudes of the parents in the Bororo myth are
an inversion of those exhibited by the parents in the Ge myth.
(c)Contrary to Lévi-Strauss, a comparative analysis of the two myths
does not permit the conclusion that the Bororo mother and Ge father
sustain the logical relation of identity on the close/remote dimension.
For, even granting the dubious classification of incestuous rape as
“incest,” by what logical criterion is the attitude “close” attributed both
to a passive object of incest (the Bororo mother) and an active agent of
nurturance (the Ge father)? If, moreover, the classification of
incestuous rape as “incest” is invalid (as I deem it to be), the
attribution of an identity relation to the Bororo mother and Ge father
would seem to be fallacious. How can the same attitude (“close”) be
attributed to two parents of which one is the victim of a son’s
rapacious assault and the other a protector of the son against assault?
On either account, when they are compared with respect to the
close/remote dimension, it must be concluded that, rather than
sustaining a relation of identity, the relation of the Bororo mother and
Ge father is one of binary opposition. If they are to be attributed
instead with a relation of identity—and if, therefore, the parents of the
Bororo myth are to be seen as an inversion of those in the Ge myth—
that can only be accomplished by concepts that are faithful to the
violent themes found in these myths. Thus, for example, use of the
dimension violent/nonviolent (restricting the comparisons to the
episodes described in the myths themselves) or the dimension life-
giving/life-destroying (going beyond the episodes described in the
myths) makes it apparent that the opposite-sex parents sustain a
relation of binary opposition within the myths and one of identity
across the myths: hence, the relation of the parents in the Bororo myth
is an inversion of that of the parents of the Ge myth.
By this time the reader may be wondering why I stated at the outset that I
had changed my topic from hermeneutics to the relationship between nature
and culture when, thus far, this chapter has been devoted entirely to the
interpretation of cultural symbol systems. The paradox is more apparent
than real, however. It should be evident by now that the two codes
examined (one that systematically and totally denies that sex and aggression
in ritual and myth really signify sex and aggression and one that allows that
they may indeed signify sex and aggression) may seem to differ in
hermeneutic assumptions about the role of metaphor in cultural symbol
systems, but actually differ in psychological assumptions about the
importance of sex and aggression in human nature following the transition
to culture.
What might be the assumptions of a code that interprets the Bororo myth
(which on its surface explaines why it is that a boy became a vicious
parricide) to be an origin myth, whether of cooking or of rain, a code by
which a boy’s rape of his mother signifies his dependent attachment to her,
the mother’s being the victim of his rape signifies her close attitude to him,
and the father’s attempts to murder his son signify his (the father s) remote
attitude to him? Such a code, I would suggest, can be based only on an
assumption that, in a state of culture, aggressive motives of this type are
either transcended or markedly muted so that they cannot possibly be the
real concern of myths.5 Hence it is that, if aggression seems to be the
dominant theme of the Bororo myth, its aggressive episodes must be
interpreted to mean something other than (if not the very opposite of) what
they seem to mean.
5. The same assumption underlies Douglas’ (though not necessarily Leach’s) elimination of sex as
a concern of cultural belief systems.
In making this suggestion, I am aware, of course, that Lévi-Strauss
contends (1969:12) that his interpretations of myths refer to their
“unconscious formulations.” That contention, however, does not affect the
validity of my suggestion, because, for Lévi-Strauss, the “unconscious”
meaning of a myth or a mythic episode is not its trivial meaning, but its
most fundamental meaning. Hence, when he interprets a myth of Oedipal
violence as (unconsciously) signifying the origin of cooking fire, he is not
making the trivial claim that the latter element is also to be found in the
myth; rather, he is making the important claim that this myth, which seems
to be about violence, is really about something else. Consider, then, that in
Lévi-Strauss’ code, aggression is systematically and gratuitously precluded
as the (unconscious) meaning of any of the violent episodes in these myths.
Consider, too, that alternative codes (such as those suggested above), whose
(unconscious) interpretations are faithful to the violent content of the myths,
achieve the aims of structural analysis without the dubious logic and textual
distortions often required by Lévi-Strauss’ interpretations. Consider, also,
that for Lévi-Strauss, their unconscious meanings are the fundamental
meanings of myths. Considering all of this, it seems reasonable to conclude
that Lévi-Strauss’ elimination of violence as a mythic category, although
applying to the unconscious meaning of myths, is based on the assumption
that violent motives of the type exhibited in the Bororo and Ge myths
cannot be their real concern.
That conclusion is supported by his contention (1969:164)—although he
attributes the notion to native thought—that cooking marks the transition
from nature to culture and that the Bororo myth therefore explains the
origin not merely of cooking but also (and by that very same fact) of
culture. That is not only, he argues, because of the analogy raw:cooked:
:nature:culture but also because in the Ge myths both useful and ornamental
objects are manufactured from the inedible parts of the cooked plants and
animals. That he, therefore, interprets all of the aggressive episodes in the
Bororo myth metaphorically suggests that this exegetical maneuver is a
solution to a painful dilemma. It is as if he were saying that, if this myth is
really concerned with filial rape, parracide, and filicide, the origin of
cooking cannot represent the transition to culture, because aggressive
motives of this kind, although found perhaps in a state of nature, cannot
possibly persist in a state of culture; but, on the other hand, if this myth
does not explain the origin of cooking, and if cooking does not represent the
transition to culture, the entire argument of the book would collapse. It is
this dilemma that is resolved by a code that interprets all aggression in the
myth as a metaphor.
It will come as no surprise—turning finally to the psychoanalytic
dimension of this paper—that the assumptions of Freud concerning the
relationship between aggression and culture are the polar opposite of those
of Lévi-Strauss. In Freud’s view, aggressive motives are as strong in a state
of culture as in a state of nature. Given that assumption, the themes of
parricide, filicide, and the like, although really signifying parricide and
filicide, would not in themselves disqualify the Bororo myth from being
interpreted by Freud as a myth of the origin of culture. Nevertheless, even
granting that this myth explains the origin of cooking fire, Freud would
never agree that it depicts the origin of culture, as can easily be seen from
even a cursory glance at Freud’s own origin myth. That myth (Freud
1971a), although remarkably similar to the Bororo myth (both are
concerned with violent conflicts between father and son over the sexual
possession of the wife-mother), is its structural inversion. In Freud’s myth
(which, however, he took to be history), the sons desire the father’s wives,
and since he will not share them, the sons kill the father in order to take
possession of them. Following their patricide, however, the sons experience
feelings of remorse that lead them to atone for their deed by renouncing
their claims on the women and to institute prohibitions against further
parricide, fratricide, and incest.
For Freud, then, it is not the acquisition of cooking fire, nor even the
manufacture of useful and ornamental objects attendant upon the cooking of
food, that marks the transition from nature to culture, but the institution of
norms for the control and regulation of aggression (first, within the sibling-
group and subsequently to increasingly larger groups). For Freud,
moreover, the transition to culture does not mean the transcendence of
nature. Hence, although aggressive behavior, regulated as it is by cultural
norms, may be inhibited in a state of culture, aggressive motives are not
extinguished. Indeed, it is precisely because these motives (including
parricide and filicide) persist in and are even exacerbated by culture (Freud
1971b) that the existence of norms for their regulation is a necessary
condition for the existence of culture. Necessary, although not sufficient.
For, as Freud views it, it is the internalization of these norms (as a result of
the infant’s prolonged attachments to nurturant parenting figures) that
produces the moral anxiety and guilt that, by inhibiting expression of
aggressive motives, preclude the return to a state of nature.6
6. That Freud is the (unacknowledged) spiritual descendant of Hobbes, just as Lévi-Strauss is the
(acknowledged) spiritual descendant of Rousseau, would seem to be obvious. Freud differs from
Hobbes in that the latter believed that the physical authority of the state is necessary to assure
compliance with the cultural prohibition on aggression, while Freud believed that the key to the
problem is the moral authority of the parents, internalized as the superego and reflected in moral
anxiety and guilt.
We can now see why Freud would never characterize the Bororo myth as
marking the transition from nature to culture—not because the son desired
his mother, or the father wished to kill his son, or the son wished to kill his
father, nor even because they acted upon their wishes, but because they
experienced neither moral anxiety about their desires nor guilt about their
deeds.7 Since absence of anxiety and guilt implies an absence of cultural
norms prohibiting aggressive behavior, in Freud’s view this myth could not
possibly represent a transition from nature to culture, even if it were granted
that it represents the origin of cooking.
7. Indeed, rather than experiencing guilt and, thereby, atoning for killing his father by renouncing
his claims on his mother and stepmothers, the son continues to take his “revenge” on them.
For Freud this myth would, however, represent something else. Holding
that the transition to culture, although marking the control of aggressive
behavior, does not mark the disappearance of aggressive affects and
motives. Freud assumed that aggression is a matter of important concern to
social actors in a state of culture. And since, so he further assumed, their
important concerns are inevitably represented in their fantasies—the
privately constituted fantasy of dreams and the culturally constituted
fantasy of myth and religion—it follows that the manifestly aggressive
themes in the Bororo myth, like the manifestly sexual themes in the rituals
and beliefs analyzed by Leach and Douglas, are just that: aggressive and
sexual themes. In short, for Freud, the myths, rituals, and beliefs discussed
in this paper are concerned with those very sexual and aggressive wishes
and fears that these anthropologists and their many followers, denying that
they are of concern to cultural symbol systems, interpret out of existence. It
is rather startling that this simpleminded view (which, of course, is hardly
original with Freud or restricted to Freudians) must be reiterated to an
anthropological audience in 1977.
Notes
Reprinted from American Anthropologist vol, 81, no. 1 (Mar. 1979):5–13, by permission of the
American Anthropological Association. Not for further reproduction.
This paper was prepared for, and a shorter version was read at, the 1977 annual meetings of the
American Anthropological Association, as a part of a symposium entitled “Psychological
Anthropology: a Perennial Frontier?” organized by Professor Theodore Schwartz. The preparation of
this paper was assisted by a grant from the National Institute of Mental Health.
References
Douglas, Mary. 1966. Purity and danger. New York: Praeger.
Freud, Sigmund. 1971a. Totem and taboo. In The standard edition of
the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, vol. 13.
London: Hogarth Press.
_____1971b. Civilization and its discontents. In The standard edition
of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freudy vol. 21.
London: Hogarth Press.
Leach, Edmund. 1967. Virgin birth. Proceedings of the Royal
Anthropological I nstitute for 1966:39–49.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. 1969. The raw and the cooked. New York:
Harper and Row.
Spiro, Melford E. 1968a. Review of purity and danger. American
Anthropologist 70:391–93.
_____1968b. Virgin birth, parthenogenesis, and physiological
paternity. Man 3:224–61.
11
Some Reflections on Family and
Religion in East Asia
Introduction
THE FAMILY and religion were among the core interests of anthropological
inquiry from its very inception, and they have remained among its most
perduring subjects of investigation. There are, I believe, at least two reasons
why this should have been so.
In the first place, although like the family and religion other sociocultural
systems are also universal, none is as easily recognizable across all the etic
types which are employed by anthropologists to classify the wide array of
sociocultural systems as are family and religious systems. In the case of
economic and political systems, for example, those which fall at the polar
extremes of any of the recognized typologies by which they are classified
are often identifiable as members of the same series only because of their
similarities to the intermediate types comprising the typologies. We need
only remind ourselves of the differences between nomadic-gathering
economies and industrial-bureaucratic economies, or between small,
acephalous band organizations and large-scale centralized empires in order
to grasp this rather simple point. For both comparisons it is difficult to
identify an invariant sociocultural core that cuts across all the types
comprising a formal typology, or that persists from the earliest
manifestation of an evolutionary typology to the most recent of its
manifestations.
The contrary, however, is the case in regard to the family or religion, or
so it would seem, if I am correct in claiming that the nuclear family is the
invariant core of every family system, and that the worship of superhuman
beings comprises the invariant core of every religious system. Indeed, the
founders of nineteenth century evolutionary thought in Europe were as
perplexed by the similarities between their own (Victorian) family and
religious systems and those of the non-European societies that they studied
as they were intrigued by (and sometimes contemptuous of) the differences.
The second reason, I believe, for the perduring anthropological interest in
the family and religion is that these two systems are related to one another
in a systematic relationship which holds for no two other sociocultural
systems. At first blush, this statement seems paradoxical because while the
human family marks man’s affinity with the rest of the animal kingdom—
especially the class of mammals—religion marks his uniqueness. That is,
the family (whether uniparental or biparental) is a generic mammalian
institution, and since man evolved from a mammalian (more particularly a
primate) species, it is hard to escape the assumption that the human family
is phylogenetically rooted in the family system of our prehominid ancestors.
Since religion, however, is found (as far as we can tell) in our species
alone, if religious systems are also universal it is because (as Robertson
Smith and Freud pointed out a long time ago) they are rooted in, and may
be viewed as metaphorical expressions of family (including kinship)
relations. If that is so, then religion and the family (in contrast, say, to
religion and economics or religion and politics) sustain a special
relationship with each other, the existence of religion being in large part a
function of the existence of the family.
To say that religious systems may be viewed as a metaphorical
expression of family relations is to say that while the existence of the family
may be explicable in terms of biological characteristics and needs which we
share with other mammals, religion is explicable only in terms of the
uniquely human capacity for symbolization, for it is in the symbolic process
that the privately-constituted world of fantasy, the wellspring of religious
belief, is transformed into the culturally-constituted world of religion. That
is so because the symbol creates Being (spirits and gods) out of non-Being,
and it invests words and gestures with the instrumental power that is
imputed to religious ritual. In short, religious symbols often represent the
transformation and elaboration, at the cultural level, of fantasies and
cognitions that are found at the psychological level, which in turn, are
produced by family relations at the social level.
Although there is nothing new in this, its implications for the universal
dimensions of the family and religion have not always been spelled out by
anthropologists who, in their special concern with variation, have more
often concentrated on the cross-cultural differences in family and religious
systems than in their regularities. Although there can be no denying the
importance of these differences, their regularities are equally important, and
it is the recognition of the cross-cultural regularities in the family, viewed as
a system of social relationships, that enables us to understand its connection
with religion, viewed as a system of symbolic relationships.
The panhuman roots of the regularities in human family systems are not
hard to discover, for however much these systems must adapt to and are
conditioned by variations in ecology, economy, demography, the polity, and
the like, every family (and kinship) system is a response to certain
irreducible biological characteristics of human existence, among which I
would stress the following.
Although ancestors are most often viewed as benign, it is also the case that
sometimes they may be punitive. Fortes claimed that in East Asia, as well
as West Africa, “the feature that stands out most conspicuously in all
varieties of ancestor worship … is their punitive character” (Fortes
1977:145). Thus, in Korea, the dead (including ancestors and ghosts) are
dangerous, so Kendall (1984) remarks, “simply because they are dead …
and their touch brings illness or affliction.” This is especially true in the
case of ancestors who died with “unfulfilled desires.” Restless ancestors, as
well as ghosts and angry household gods, cause not only illness, but
financial loss and domestic strife, as well. Similarly, Lee observes that if the
ritual service for an ancestor is not performed, the ancestor spirit becomes a
wandering ghost; and although, he further observes, ghosts have no power
to punish their descendents directly, this implies, I would assume, that they
do have power to punish them indirectly.
In his treatment of ancestor worship in China (Taiwan) Suenari (1984)
does not deal with the punitive dimension of ancestors, but it is implicit in
his emphasis on (what he calls) the “economic reciprocity” characteristic of
family relationships, including that with ancestors. Like their relationship
with the gods, the Chinese relationship with their ancestors is “contractual,”
which implies that the latter’s punitive or nonpunitive action is contingent
upon the offering or withholding of gifts by their descendents. This
implication is explicit in the work of Emily Ahern on ancestor worship in
Taiwan. According to Ahern’s findings ancestors are not infrequently
blamed for such serious misfortunes as insanity, serious infirmity and death
(Ahern 1973: chap. 12).
The situation in Japan is no different. Thus, Morioka (1984) observes that
for the lower class, at least, the function of ancestor worship is to “avert
disaster” which would be caused by ancestors if their worship were
neglected. Carmen Blacker makes the same point without restricting it,
however, to the lower class. Thus, if “the ancestral dead are not correctly
treated by their descendants, if the offerings or the obsequies necessary to
their nourishment are neglected, then with frightening suddenness their
nature will change. The kindly old grandfather, the sympathetic father, the
loving mother will turn in an instant into a vicious and capricious tyrant,
punishing the neglectful family with curses.” (Blacker 1975:47–48).
In order to understand these findings, it is important to consider other
data. First, approximately 50 percent of Japanese families, according to
Morioka, continue to practice ancestor worship even when the te system has
collapsed. Second, in Korea, according to Lee, the ancestor tablet is kept in
the ancestral shrine only until the fourth ascending generation, following
which it is buried in the grave, which implies that the ancestor remains
individuated only for a relatively short time, after which he is assimilated to
the generic class of “ancestor.”
Now although in ancestor worship, rites are performed for all one’s
ancestors, these findings suggest that the cognitively salient ancestors are
not the genealogically remote ancestors, but rather the genealogically close
and immediately dead ancestors—i.e., the parents and grandparents. The
remote ancestors, of course, are important both jurally (to establish claims
on property, to enhance the prestige of a clan line or to legitimize its rights)
and politically (to inculcate respect for authority, beginning with the family
and ending with the centralized state). But for the average individual, I
would suggest, these corporate functions are second in importance to their
“religious” functions. In the latter regard, an ancestor (like anyone else) is
cognitively salient for a religious actor only to the degree that he has a clear
and vivid mental representation of him, and the ancestors concerning whom
he has the clearest and most vivid mental representations are his deceased
parents and grandparents—those whom he himself has personally
encountered. Hence, even though in ancestor worship the actor in principle
attends to all of his ancestors, it is his immediate ancestors, especially his
parents, who, so I would suggest, he has most in mind, or whose mental
representation forms the template for his conception of the other ancestors.
Fortes (1961:187) put it most succinctly in his remark that “ancestor
worship is primarily the religious cult of deceased parents.”
These claims are supported by Morioka’s finding that (a) although
traditionally a Japanese “ancestor” is the ancestor of the te, with the
collapse of the ie in urban families, “ancestor” has increasingly come to
designate the “deceased bilateral kindred” (which most importantly means,
I would suggest, the ascendance of the mother to the status of a cognitively
salient ancestor), and that, (b) the “private” meanings of ancestor worship
have superseded its “public” meanings. Consistent with my previous
hypothesis, however, I would suggest that these private meanings were
always foremost in the worshipper’s mind (although the public meanings
were, no doubt, the important formal meanings), and that the collapse of the
ie merely permits their centrality to be acknowledged.
Even more important, however, is Morioka’s finding that although many
urban families do not own a butsudan, the rate of ownership dramatically
increases with the death of a parent, and that even in extended family
households (in which, presumably, the ie is still somewhat important) it
increases significantly in households with widows. These two findings
suggest once again that the cognitively and emotionally salient ancestors
are the immediate dead. Moreover, taking Morioka’s findings concerning
widows into account, the ancestors need not even be lineal ancestors so
long as they had been household members with whom the actor had
sustained important social relationships.
If this is so, then inasmuch as ancestors are not only revered—an
extension of filial piety—but also feared, I would suggest that both attitudes
are a function of the mental representations that, as children, the actors had
formed of their immediately deceased ancestors, most especially, but not
exclusively, the father. The latter attitude, which is the one we are
concerned with here, might be explained in the first instance by Fortes’
hypothesis that it is the “authority component” of the father that is elevated
to ancestorship. If, then, in addition to his positive feelings for him, the
child also develops negative feelings toward the father, one would expect—
given the over-arching value of filial piety—that he would probably repress
these feelings, or at least not exhibit them in overt behavior. That upon his
death the father—now an ancestor—is viewed as a potentially dangerous
figure, capable of inflicting harm on his descendants, is then susceptible of
two complementary interpretations.
First, the repressed hostility which was felt for the father when he was
alive can now find an outlet in the culturally-constituted belief that
ancestors are potentially dangerous. Specifically, that belief allows the child
to project his erstwhile hostility toward the living father onto the dead
ancestor, thereby transforming him from an ordinarily oppressive authority
figure into a potentially dangerous one. The second interpretation is more
complex. Clinical evidence indicates that hostility toward some person may
generate death wishes (if only as an unconscious fantasy) toward him;
should that person die, the actor, given that the “omnipotence of thoughts”
is one of the characteristics of unconscious mentation, may unconsciously
experience his death as resulting from his death wishes toward him. Given,
then, that the principle of lex talionis informs not only many legal systems,
but unconscious mentation as well, the belief that the deceased father is
potentially dangerous might be explained by the unconscious conviction of
the child that the former might harm him in retaliation for the ‘harm’ that he
(the child) had inflicted on the father.
Since the most notable feature of the mother-son relationship in East Asia is
the mother’s nurturance and the son’s dependence, we would expect that
dimension of the mother-son relationship to be reflected in East Asian
religion. The extraordinary nurturant-dependent nature of the mother-son
relationship in East Asia, at least in Japan, is stressed in the reports by
Tanaka and Sofue. A “good mother,” Tanaka observes, “is believed to care
for and worry about her son eternally.” Hence, the son’s dependency (amae)
on the mother persists not only over her lifetime, but even after her death
when, as an ancestress, she is still “supposed to be watching over him.” As
a measure of what he characterizes as the son’s “very strong dependency
need” in regard to the mother, Sofue points to the fact that it is the favorite
theme of Japanese popular culture. For him, therefore, this need comprises
a “mother-complex.” Whatever that expression may denote, it certainly
connotes the formation by the son of a mental representation of the mother
as extraordinarily loving and nurturant, one who can be expected to do
anything in her power in the service of his welfare.
Such a maternal representation is too good to give up. Hence, it is little
wonder that when the mother becomes an ancestor the son continues to
expect that he can rely on her assistance. It is little wonder, too—though I
would not have predicted it—that with the introduction of Buddhism to
China, and thence to Japan, the infinitely compassionate Hindu god,
Avalokitesvara, was transformed into the goddess, Kuanyin (China) or
Kannon (Japan). That the amae relationship with the mother is transferred
to Kannon—probably the most popular deity (actually Bodhisattva) in
Japan—and that the benevolent dimension of the maternal representation is
reflected in the collective representation of Kannon (just as the authority
dimension of the paternal representation is reflected in the collective
representation of the male ancestors) can be seen in the following statement
of Teruko Furuya. (The translation is by Yohko Tsuji.)
Kannon’s concern is not directed toward heaven or a utopia, but toward this world (in which
many people still suffer). Kannon is benevolent and omnipotent. She never punishes us, nor gets
angry with us. On the contrary, consistently and promptly she answers our selfish prayers, such as
a desire to have an attractive child, a desire to pass an entrance examination for a prestigious
school, a desire to get promoted at work, and so on. She is just like an amai mother who always
listens to the desires of an indulged child.
Like the mother, Kannon is not only infinitely compassionate, but she has
another quality that the mother does not have: she is also all-powerful, as
the following quotation from Blacker (1975:94) indicates.
A man only has to think of the Bodhisattva Kannon to be saved from every conceivable calamity.
A man hurled into a fiery pit has but to think of the Kannon for the fire to be quenched. A man
floundering in an ocean of sea monsters has but to think of Kannon and he will neither sink nor
drown. A man bombarded with thunderbolts has but to think of Kannon and not a hair of his head
will be hurt. A man beset by goblins, demons, ghosts, giants, wild beasts or fearful fiery serpents
has but to think of Kannon for these creatures to vanish.
Power of this magnitude, of course, is never found in any human being but
it is found in the mental representations that a young child forms of his
parents. In the child’s eyes the parent, who literally has the power of life or
death over him, is indeed omnipotent. Hence, when the omnipotence of the
maternal representation of the Japnese child is conjoined with its
benevolence, the result—I would suggest—is a maternal representation that
is projected in the adult’s collective representation of Kannon.
But the relationship between the religious devotee and Kannon is not the
only manifestation of the child’s amae relationship with the mother on the
religious plane. It is also manifested, as Tsuji (1980) has suggested, both in
the relationship between client and shaman (miko)—and here, I would
include Korea as well as Japan—and in that between the members and
founders (kyoso) of the new religions.
In Japan and Korea, though not in China, shamans are almost exclusively
female, and the rare male shaman performs his role as a trasvestite. In
Korea, according to Kendall, the shaman (mansin) is used to help the
household overcome the afflictions—illness, financial loss, domestic strife
—that are brought about by restless ancestors, ghosts, and angry household
gods, as well as to help young women overcome infertility. According to
Blacker, similar functions are served by the Japanese miko as well as by her
modern counterpart, the kyoso, most of whom are also female. So far as the
latter are concerned, Davis observes that the “great majority” of those who
join a new religion hope “to receive some practical benefit—cure of
disease, solution to some personal problem, support for some psychological
difficulty, etc—from their affiliation” (Tsuji 1980:ms). In short, in both
cases when faced with adversity, the adult reestablishes a dependency
relationship with a female religious specialists that as a child he had
experienced with his mother.
I might add that just as the devotees’ relationship with these female
religious specialists is best understood by reference to the family—as a
recapitulation of their early experience with the mother—the recruitment of
these women to their religious vocations is also best understood by
reference to the family—to their experience as wives in a sexually
frustrating marital relationship. This, in Korea, Kendall tells us, shamans
are usually recruited to their calling in middle age, after suffering a “run of
ill luck” as a result of possession by some god who claims them. In Japan,
Sasaki (1984) writes, there are two ways of becoming a shaman: “One is by
divine calling and the other by self-searching for shamanship.” In the
former case, the woman suffers from some mental and physical
abnormality, including visual and auditory hallucinations, trance, decrease
in appetite, severe palpitations of the heart, sleeplessness and loss of
weight. If her condition is not improved by resort to modern medical
specialists, she will visit a shaman to discover the cause of her affliction.
Should it be diagnosed as resulting from spirit possession, the most
important means for overcoming her afflictions is for her to become a
shaman herself, and to serve the spirit or god who has possessed her. (In
Okinawa, this often means agreeing to marry him.) After agreeing to
become a shaman, her “abnormality” gradually disappears.
These women, according to Blacker, exhibit in their personal histories a
“curiously uniform pattern,”
Nearly all of them in their early life betray symptoms of what could be called ‘arctic hysteria.’
They are sickly, neurotic, hysterical, odd, until a moment comes when exacerbated by suffering,
these symptoms rise to a climactic interior experience of a mystical kind. A deity, by means of a
dream or a possession, seizes them and claims them for his service. Thenceforward they are
changed characters. Their former oddity and sickliness give way to a remarkable strength and
magnetism of personality, which is conferred on them, together with various supernormal powers,
by the deity who has possessed them (Blacker 1975:129)
1. That the pursuit of the religious life requires the rejection of family ties is, of course, not
restricted to the salvation religions of Asia. Early Christianity (as the attitude of Jesus, both to his
ties with his own family, as well as to family ties in general reveal) required an equally powerful
rejection (cf. Mark 3:31ff, Luke 9:59ff, Luke 14:26).
In both cases, Buddhist and Taoist alike, the attitude of the perfect “goer-
forth” is best described in the famous injunction of the Sutta Nipata.
“Having left son and wife, father and mother, wealth, and corn, and
relatives, the different objects of desire, let one wander alone like a
rhinoceros” (Sutta-Ntpata, verse 26 of the Khaggavisana Sutta). But, of
course, for the typical Buddhist monk, “leaving home” does not entail
wandering alone like a rhinoceros; instead, everywhere he enters a
community of like-minded “goers-forth,” a monastery.
Unless, as Lancaster perceptively observes, we recognize the “appeal of
the monastery life, it is difficult to account for the fact [that despite the
monks’ violation of the sacred duty of filial piety] Buddhist monastic
organizations thrived and became one of the most important features of the
religious, economic and social life of China, Korea and Japan.” In his
discussion of monastic recruitment, Lancaster is entirely correct in stressing
the appeal of the “pull” factors, as migration theorists call them, that attract
young men to the monastery—special dress, ritual, mystical practices, and
the like; but for the purposes of this paper, I should like to stress the “push”
factors that motivate them to “leave home.”
In attempting to understand these “push” factors it is important to stress
that when the young man “goes forth,” he does more than leave home—that
is much too passive a term to characterize this process, especially in the
societies of East Asia in which filial piety is an overriding value. Rather, he
abandons home, i.e. he actively severs his ties with his parents and siblings,
and he refrains from forming normally expectable ties with a wife and
children. It is the wish to sever the former ties and to refrain from forming
the latter which constitutes, I am suggesting, the “push” factor in his
“leaving home.” This suggestion is supported by the fact that (as has
already been noted) “going forth” does not mean wandering alone like a
rhinoceros, but rather substituting a voluntary community, based on
religiomystical ties, for an involuntary one, based on biological-kinship ties.
When it is considered, moreover, that the voluntary community, the
monastery, has many of the characteristics of the family—indeed, in China,
as Lancaster observes, the monastery became an actual family surrogate,
even including fictive father-son relationships, fictive lineage formations,
and fictive ancestral tablets—it becomes all the more obvious that it is not
living in a family-like structure as such that the “goer-forth” rejects in
“leaving home,” but rather living in his own biological family.
And make no mistake about it. “Leaving home” is a rejection of the latter
family, despite the monks’ attempts to rationalize it, and thereby cope with
the guilt induced by this act of filial impiety, by claiming that by
transferring merit to deceased parents and thereby promoting their
otherwordly welfare, the monastic vocation is in fact an expression of filial
piety. This is tellingly demonstrated, for example, in Lancaster’s data which
show that 70 percent of the Korean monks he interviewed entered the
monastery against the wishes of their parents, that they persist in their
decision despite the fact that for as many as ten years their parents begged
them to return home, that the resentment of their siblings for having to
assume the entire burden for caring for their aged parents is well-known to
them, and that their lingering guilt for having abandoned the parents is
evidenced by their resistance to discuss this matter in their interviews.
The recognition that monastic recruitment violates the norm of filial piety
—and the attendant psychological consequences of guilt, remorse, and
rationalization attendant upon this violation—is clearly evident as well in
the autobiographies of the five Korean nuns that Koh summarizes in her
paper. To be sure, the “pull” factors in the nuns’ motivation to enter the
monastery—the traumata attendant upon such experiences as the death of a
lover, marriage failure, frustrated child-lessness, the remarriage of a father,
the death of a mother, etc.—were even stronger, it is safe to say, than the
“push” factors. Nevertheless, their recognition of their violation of the duty
of filial piety, more especially since they had been importantly influenced
by the Confucian ethic, is equally evident. Thus, one nun characterized her
decision as “this unfilial act,” but then immediately rationalized the
decision by saying that as a Buddhist nun she could more effectively fulfill
her filial duties. Another nun, though her father was a Christian minister,
made the same claim. Their rejection of the family, their guilt, and their
rationalizations are all evidenced in the fact that, as Koh observes, they all
experienced “sorrow” about leaving home without their families’
permission, and yet they nevertheless carried out their decision over the
strong opposition of their families, and in the full realization that the latter
would suffer “tremendous social stigma.” Now, it may also be true, as Koh
claims, that their decision, given their “sentimental and deep attachment” to
their family members, is a measure of their self-reliance, but it is also a
measure (I would argue) of their willingness, if not wish, to reject their
families.
Since, however, the nuns’ decisions to enter the monastery were
traumatically motivated, I shall return to the monks in order to address the
problem that is by now rather obvious: what “push” factors could possibly
account for the fact that a young man, reared in a culture which places such
strong emphasis on filial piety, is nevertheless motivated to violate his filial
duties in such an extreme fashion?
The answer—or at least one of the answers—is to be found, I would
suggest, in the wish to escape the tensions that, as discussed at the
beginning of this chapter, are endemic in East Asia (but not only East Asia)
in the relationship between the boy and the other members of his family.
These tensions include the fear and resentment engendered by the father,
the incestuous and dependency anxiety aroused by the mother, and the
rivalry induced by male siblings in his family of origin. They also include
the Oedipally-induced fears concerning the formation of a sexual
relationship with a woman other than the mother, as well as the anxiety
about giving up his dependency orientation, both of which are aroused in
anticipation of establishing a family of procreation. All of these tensions, I
would submit, are experienced in some sense by most young men in East
Asia. (For a Southeast Asia parallel example, cf. Spiro 1977.)
In most cases these tensions are of a magnitude that can be handled and
overcome. In some few cases, however, they are too powerful to sustain in
continuous and ongoing relationships with members of the family—
especially since most of these tensions continue to be experienced
interminably because of the stem and extended family households of East
Asian societies. For such men the monastery is a marvelously contrived
institution which, inasmuch as it is religiously sanctioned, permits them to
avoid family relationships while at the same time providing cultural
legitimacy for their violating the duty of filial piety by interpreting the
seeming violation as motivated by a higher duty. Indeed, I would suggest
that the resort to such an extreme solution, in spite of the sacred duty of
filial piety, is convincing demonstration of how painfully those family
tensions are experienced by them.
But we don’t have to turn to those few who seek a solution in
monasticism to assess their strength even for the majority that are able to
cope with them. Thus, it is not accidental, I believe, that when they have the
chance, even those who continue to recognize the duty of filial piety seize
the opportunity to leave their homes, not for the monastery, but for the city.
And once there, rather than forming stem or extended family households,
most of them establish nuclear family households, as Tanaka and Lee have
shown for Japan and Korea respectively. It is for that reason that I disagree
with Lee’s interpretation of the “modernization of the Korean family and
religion as an extension of traditional familism.” The traditional sentiment
may still remain—after all we are still witnessing the first generation of this
phenomenon—but the difference between the persistence of the sentiment
of familism and its expression in the formation of a stem household is a
difference that, as William James puts it, makes a difference.
I wish now to conclude this chapter with the mother-son relationship, the
theme with which it began. I want to suggest that of all the tensions that
motivate home-leaving, whether it be for a celibate life in the monastery or
a married life in the city, the most important is the tension the son
experiences in his relationship with the mother. Let us consider the choice
of the monastery—because we can learn most from the more extreme case.
Since the monastery can be viewed, as we have already seen, as a kind of
nonbiological family, it is not inaccurate to say about Buddhist monasticism
everywhere—as Lancaster says about Buddhist monasticism in China—that
the monk can “join the new group [the monastery] and break the binds of
the family system and yet find within Buddhism a re-creation of the
family.” That is not, as I said, inaccurate, but it is not entirely accurate
either, because although the monk can re-create in the monastery a
relationship with a “father,” “sons,” and (male) “siblings,” there is one
relationship that he cannot re-create, that with a “mother”! And it is that
pivotal relationship of the East Asian son, I would suggest, that the monk
especially wishes to avoid by joining the monastery. For despite its highly
pleasurable aspects, the young boy’s relationship with the mother, as I have
already stressed, has two potentially frightening dimensions, as well: a
sexual dimension, on the one hand, and a symbiotic one (Mahler et al.
1975) on the other.
Thus, if the highly attentive mother is “seductive” in her relationship
with the son, the intensity of the libidinal dimension in their relationship
can become frightening for him because of its incestuous implications.
Similarly, if, rather than being seductive, the mother is overprotective
toward him, the exaggeration of his dependency on her can become
frightening for the son because it signifies a regressive pull to the symbiotic
state of early infancy in which the psychic differentiation between self and
mother has not yet been achieved. If either alone can be frightening, the
combination can be terrifying. In becoming a monk, then, the son not only
escapes these frightening dimensions of his relationship with the mother,
but he also—because of the monastic rule of celibacy—avoids their re-
creation in a relationship with a wife. (For a more detailed analysis of these
and other motives for monastic recruitment in Southeast Asia, see Spiro
1982b). I am suggesting, then, that the monastery is attractive to those few
men for whom the relationships with mother and wife are too threatening to
sustain because it allows them to escape the former and avoid the latter.
Note
Reprinted from Religion and Family in East Asia, edited by George DeVos and Takao Sofue. Senri
Ethnological Studies, no. 11. Presented at the Fifth International Symposium, National Museum of
Ethnology, Sept. 1981. (Osaka: National Museum of Ethnology, 1984), pp. 35–54. © 1987 The
Regents of the University of California.
References
Ahem, Emily. 1973. The cult of the dead in a Chinese village.
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
Blacker, Carmen. 1975. The Catalpa bow. London: George Allen and
Unwin.
Dutt, Sukumar. 1962. Buddhist monks and monasteries of India.
London: George Allen and Unwin.
Fortes, Meyer. 1961. Pietas in ancestor worship. Journal of the Royal
An-thropological Institute 91:166–91.
_____ 1977. Custom and conscience in anthropological perspective.
International Review of Psychoanalysis 4:127–54.
Freud, Sigmund. 1968. On the universal tendency to debasement in the
sphere of love. In The standard edition of the complete
psychological works of Sigmund Freud, vol. 11 [1912]. London:
The Hogarth Press.
Hsu, Francis L. K. 1971. Under the ancestor’s shadow. Stanford,
Calif.: Stanford University Press.
Jordan, David K. 1972. Gods, ghosts and ancestors: Folk religion in a
Taiwanese village, Berkeley: University of California Press.
Kendall, Laurel. 1984. Korean shamanism: Women’s rites and a
Chinese comparison. In Religion and the family in East Asia, ed.
George DeVos and Takao Softie. Osaka: National Museum of
Ethnology.
Koh, Hesung Chun. 1984. Religion and socialization of women in
Korea. Ibid.
Lancaster, Lewis. 1984. Buddhism and family in East Asia. Ibid.
Lee, Kwang Kyu. 1984. Family and religion in traditional and
contemporary Korea. Ibid.
Mahler, Margaret S., Fred Pine, and Anni Bergman. 1975. The
psychological birth of the human infant. New York: Basic Books.
Morioka, Kiyomi. 1984. Ancestor worship in contemporary Japan:
Continuity and change. In Religion and the family, ed. DeVos and
Sofue.
Ozaki, Masaharu. 1984. The Taoist priesthood: From Tsai-chia to
Ch’u-chia. Ibid.
Roy, Manisha. 1975. The Oedipus complex and the Bengali family in
India (a study of father-daughter relations in Bengal). In
Psychological anthropology, ed. Thomas E. Williams. The Hague:
Mouton.
Sasaki, Kokan. Spirit possession as an indigenous religion in Japan
and Okinawa. In Religion and the family, ed. DeVos and Sofue.
Sofue, Takao. 1984. Family and interpersonal relationships in early
Japan. Ibid.
Spiro, Melford E. 1977. Kinship and marriage in Burma. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
-------- 1978. Burmese supematuralism. 2d exp. ed. Philadelphia:
I.S.H.I.
_____ 1982a. Oedipus in the Trobriands. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
_____ 1982b. Buddhism and society: A great tradition and its Burmese
vicissitudes. 2d exp. ed. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Suenari, Michio. 1984. The “religious family” among the Chinese of
central Taiwan. In Religion and the family, ed. DeVos and Sofue.
Tanaka, Masako. 1984. Maternal authority in the Japanese family. Ibid.
Tsuji, Yohko. 1980. Females in Japanese religion. Unpublished ms.
Tu, Wei-Ming. 1984. On neo-Confucianism and human relatedness. In
Religion and the family, ed. DeVos and Sofue.
Yang, C. K. 1969. Chinese communist society: The family and the
village. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Pali Texts (translations)
1957. The Jataka, ed. E. B. Cowell. London: Luzac and Co.
1881. Sutta-Nipata, transi. V. Fausboll. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
12
Symbolism and Functionalism in the
Anthropological Study of Religion
Introduction
FOR THE HISTORIAN and sociologist of science, the history of social science
provides many fascinating problems for inquiry, not the least of which is the
propensity of its practitioners to reject old approaches as false whenever a
new approach acquires saliency. Even Marxist and Hegelian social
scientists for whom antitheses must necessarily eventuate in some kind of
synthesis, nevertheless view the different approaches to sociocultural
inquiry as constituting binary opposites, one of which (their own) is
believed (with all the fervor of a Manichean) to represent the forces of light,
the other the forces of darkness. A relevant case is the rejection of
functionalism by the practitioners of the new symbolist approach to
religious anthropology, much as the functionalists had rejected the
evolutionary approach of the generation before them. The current symbolic
approach, it might be added, is part of the contemporary Zeitgeist;
everywhere, in politics and kinship, as well as in religion and myth,
functionalism is out, symbolism is in, motivation is out, cognition is in,
social processes are out, mental processes are in.
Roughly speaking, we can distinguish at least three different
anthropological approaches to the study of cultural symbols and symbol
systems; (a) phenomenological analysis of the philosophical meanings of
the symbols, (b) structural analysis of the logical relationships among the
symbols and (c) formal semantic analysis of their classificatory schemata.
Although these three approaches are obviously quite different from each
other, they have in common an exclusive attention to symbols and symbol
systems as such, and an avoidance of attention to the relationship between
cultural symbols and social experience. The latter is viewed (at best) as
theoretically uninteresting, and (at worst) as an intellectual sin against the
Cartesian theory of the mind held by many of them.
The previous generation of functionalists were equally dogmatic in the
opposite direction. For many of them, at least, the cognitive meaning of
cultural symbol systems was more or less ignored in favor of their
relationship either to the psychobiological needs of the social actors or to
the functional requirements of their social system. With some few
exceptions the cognitive meaning of the symbols, as such, was of little
interest.
Despite the polemical opposition between symbolic and functionalist
approaches, there is no intrinsic opposition between them. On the contrary,
I would say (to paraphrase Kant) that functionalism without symbolism is
blind, and symbolism without functionalism is lame. For, surely, the social
functions of symbol systems largely depend on their cognitive meaning, and
the meanings which symbol systems have for social actors derive from and
are related to their social context. This, at least, is the thesis I wish to
explore in this chapter, not, however, by a logical analysis of the postulates
and theorems of these respective theoretical approaches, but by a concrete
comparison of a subset of the set of symbol systems of traditional Judaism
and Theravāda Buddhism, namely, their soteriological symbols. My choice
of these two religions stems primarily from the fact that I happen to have
conducted research in two communities—an Israeli kibbutz and a Burmese
village—whose cultures are informed by these two religious traditions.
Theravāda Buddhism comprises the most important idea system (religious
or secular) in Burma; and although the kibbutz (a collective agricultural
settlement) which I studied is atheist, its founders—those who created its
institutions and established its ethos—were reared in, and internalized most
of the basic concepts and values of, orthodox Judaism.
What I hope to do, then, is to compare some basic, or core, symbols of
these religions with respect to their philosophical meaning—I shall forgo a
structural and logical analysis of the symbols—and I shall then attempt to
relate them to the cultural orientations and motivational dispositions found
in Yeigyi, a village in Upper Burma, and Kiryat Yedidim, a kibbutz in
central Israel.
The Soteriological Symbolism of Judaism and
Buddhism
Introduction
Jahweh—Buddha
Torah-Dhamma
Israel—Sahgha
Chercher la Femme
Buddhism and Judaism not only share a common trinity of formal
soteriological symbols—a sacred person, a sacred law, and a sacred group
—but these symbols share a common attribute—none of them is feminine.
To be sure, it can be argued—and empirical support can be adduced for
such an argument—that feminist elements have been bootlegged into both
Buddhism and Judaism in the unconscious meanings of some of their other
symbols. Nevertheless, at the level of their formal and conscious meanings,
their symbols, including those that have been examined in this chapter, are
primarily (Judaism) if not exclusively (Buddhism) masculine. I say
“primarily” in the case of Judaism because Israel may be viewed as a
combined male and female symbol since its empirical referent, the people
of Israel, includes both males and females. Even this statement, however,
must be qualified by the observation that the female component in the
symbol, Israel, is only physically, but not ritually or jurally, relevant. God’s
covenant with Israel, which is the jural basis for its status as a sacred
people, is renewed in, and symbolized by, the circumcision ritual, which is
performed for males alone. That, nevertheless, physical membership in the
group is determined by the mother—by Talmudic law, the child of a Jewish
father and a non-Jewish mother is not a Jew—is one of those paradoxes
which might be variously resolved by structuralist, psychoanalytic, and
other theories which delight in paradox. Ritually, too, Israel is essentially a
masculine symbol in that, traditionally, Jewish congregational worship
requires a quorum of ten adult males. Although females, like minors, may
participate in the worship, they may not be counted in the quorum.
Buddhism is even more exclusively masculine in its symbolism than
Judaism. Not only is the historical Buddha, Gautama, a male, but all
previous Buddhas have also been, and all future Buddhas will also be,
males. Buddhahood can be attained only in a masculine form. The Sańgha,
too, is an exclusively male institution. In Judaism the physical Israel, at
least, includes both sexes, even though jurally and ritually females are
peripheral members. This is not the case even with respect to the physical
Sańgha. To be sure, in early Buddhism, females were permitted to become
monks—over the objection, it should be noted, of the Buddha—but after a
few short years they were, and they have continued to be, excluded from the
order. A woman’s aspiration to the monkhood must be deferred until her
future rebirth as a male.
To summarize, then, Judaism and Buddhism alike are characterized by a
pervasive and systematic exclusion of females and feminine symbols from
soteriological, devotional, and liturgical significance. On this dimension
Buddhism and Judaism may not only be classified together, but (among the
great religions) they are members of a class which includes Islam,
Confucianism and Protestantism, and which excludes Hinduism and
Catholicism. Like Buddhism and Judaism, the latter two religions are also
characterized by a soteriological trinity, but, unlike the former, they include
an important feminine component. Now, of course, just as Lévi-Strauss and
the structuralists can always find binary oppositions, so too I can be charged
with always finding trinities. In each of these cases, however, the trinity was
not discovered by fancy intellectual methods; rather trinities are enunciated
by the social actors themselves, and the problem consists in deciding which,
among alternative trinities, is most germane to the present discussion. Thus,
for example, both Hinduism and Catholicism exhibit one type of trinity
which is isomorphic with that of Judaism and Buddhism: a sacred being
(Brahma and God), a sacred law (Dharma and the teachings of the Church),
and a sacred group (Varna and the Church). Unanalyzed, these trinities are
as exclusively masculine as their Judaic and Buddhist counterparts. But the
Hindu “Brahma” and the Catholic “God,” it will be recalled, are generic
terms, best glossed as “divinity” or “godhead,” each of which, depending
on the interpretation, comprises three component deities or aspects of the
godhead.
These divine trinities are, of course, well known. The Hindu trinity
consists of Vishnu, Shiva, and one of the forms taken by the feminine
principle—Sakte—variously conceived as Parvati, Kali, or Durga. The
Catholic trinity consists of God, Christ, and the Virgin Mary. In Catholic
theology, to be sure, the Trinity refers to the triune God—Father, Son, and
Holy Spirit. To the anthropologist, however, who follows the lead of the
religious actor and his devotional concerns, the third member is not the
Holy Spirit, but the Holy Virgin.
Now the difference between the presence or absence of a feminine
symbol within the set of sacred symbols of a religion is not, I need
emphasize, a trivial difference; and it certainly involves much more than a
cognitive preference or lack of preference for binary oppositions (the
opposition, in this case, of male and female). For, although I have thus far
used the abstract concept, “feminine,” in referring to the Virgin and Parvati,
neither, as is well known, represents a generically conceived, abstract,
female principle. Rather, both represent a specific type of female, and that
type is not wife, or sister, or daughter, or aunt, but Mother. Both are
expressly referred to as Mother. The difference, then, between the absence
of a sacred female symbol in Judaism and Buddhism (as well as in Islam,
Protestantism and Confucianism), on the one hand, and its presence in
Catholicism and Hinduism, on the other, is the difference between the
presence or absence of a Mother Goddess. And this difference, in turn, is
related, on the one hand, to the general importance of familial symbols
within the sacred symbol system, and to the role of women in the secular
domain, on the other.
Of the four religions we are considering here, Buddhism has most
systematically expunged all familial symbols from its sacred symbol
system. It not only excludes all mother symbols, but it also excludes all
father symbols. The Buddha is a male, but he is never designated as father.
Judaism, too, excludes all mother symbols—though the prophets had to
fight a long battle before the various Astartes were expunged from the
religious life of the ancient Hebrews—but the Jewish God is an expressly
conceived father symbol, as is the God of Islam and Protestantism.
Hinduism, on the other hand, includes both father and mother symbols.
With respect to the latter it might also be observed that the mother symbol
is not restricted to the Goddess, for we can hardly ignore the symbolism of
Mother India or of the sacred cow. It should also be added that in the form
of baby Krishna, Hinduism, like Catholicism, includes the sacred child
symbol—and why is the child a son rather than a daughter?—although
father, mother, and son are not integrated to form one sacred family. Family
symbolism, of course, is most pervasive in Catholicism. Not only does the
earthly family find its isomorphic representation in the Divine Family of
Father, Mother, and Son, but the priest is “father,” the nun is “sister,” and
the Church (as well as the nun) is a “bride” (the Bride of Christ), and so on.
Now to pursue all the ramifications of the conceptual, not to mention the
soteriological, differences in the sacred symbols of these religions would
require a monograph. Here, I am interested only in the presence or absence
of the Mother symbol. Since all human beings have mothers, why is this
symbol such a salient feature in some religions, absent in others, and almost
phobically avoided in still others? It is in their different answers to this type
of question that contemporary symbolic approaches differ from
functionalist approaches to the study of religion. The various symbolic
approaches would attempt to answer this question by reference to the
semantics, or syntax, or grammar of the symbol systems themselves, while
the various functionalist approaches would look outside of the symbol
systems for an explanation. A functionalist cannot ignore the obvious
correlations, for example, between the following array of variables in India
and China, respectively. The worship of mother goddesses in India is
associated with an almost obsessive concern with the mother, the sacredness
of the cow, the dietary importance of milk and milk products, the
voluptuousness of sacred female iconography, and the heavy-breasted
woman. The lesser importance of mother goddesses in China, on the other
hand, is associated with the relative unimportance of the mother, the lack of
concern with the cow, the rejection of milk and milk products, the absence
of female iconography, and the flat-chested woman. Given what we know
today about population genetics and the influence of cultural factors on
biological selection, the possibility of a systematic relationship among these
social, cultural and biological variables is not as farfetched as it might
seem.
But these correlations do not provide an explanation for the difference
between the presence or absence of mother symbols in different religions.
Rather, they provide a broader context or frame in which such symbols are
to be viewed, and their systematic covariation with a wide array of variables
suggests to a functionalist that differences in symbols and symbol systems
are best explained by differences in the social systems in which they are
embedded and from which, ex hypothec, they arise and derive their
meaning. He would point, for example, to differences in cultural attitudes to
sex, in the social status of women, in the roles of women as wives and
mothers, and, if he is psychoanalytically oriented, to differences in the
parent-child relationship and, especially, to the variable vicissitudes of the
Oedipus complex.
On the basis of my own work in Buddhist Burma, I would suggest that
the presence or absence of the mother goddess is systematically related to
two feminine roles, those of mother and of wife, and to the differences in a
single dimension of each of these roles, viz., the nurturance dimension of
the mother role and the dominance dimension of the wife role. Although
preliminary research (to be published separately) supports this hypothesis,
for our present purposes the specific empirical findings are less important
than the assumption underlying its construction, viz., religious symbols—
and cultural symbols in general—though created by the human mind, do not
arise from a mental tabula rasa. Although they are elaborated by
philosophical thought, and infused with theological and metaphysical
meaning, these symbols are ultimately the products of individual fantasies
which are produced by (and therefore vary with) different types of social
experience. Like private symbols they serve to express certain aspirations
and needs which arise from such experience, to resolve the conflicts that are
induced by the experience, and to integrate them in a manner which renders
them existentially meaningful. For religious actors, religious symbols are
created not only to think by, but also—and much more important—to live
by.
The Relationship Between the Presence or Absence of Mother Goddesses and Certain Female Roles
mother wife
India + -
Catholicism (Italy) + -
Ceylon + -
Burma + +
Israel + +
Islam (Arab) - -
China - -
Calvinism (Reformation) - -
Key:mother: + = high nurturance
- = low nurturance
wife: + = high dominance
- = low dominance
Note
Reprinted from Science of Religious Studies in Methodology, edited by Lauri Honko. Proceedings
of the Study Conference of the International Association for the History of Religion, Turku, Finland,
Aug. 27–31, 1973. (The Hague: Mouton, 1979), pp. 322–39.
Index
East Asia: family and religion in, 262–85; family tensions in, 268–71, 271–83
Eggan, D., 134
Ego, 27
Egypt, marriage in, 83–84
Elwin, Verrier, 93
Emotion, in culture, 32–58
“Empty box,” 6–7, 23
Enculturation: as humanization, 45; learning a culture vs., 35–36
Erikson, Erik H., 65, 97, 122, 129
Essenes, 290
Evans-Pritchard, E. E., 191
Existentialism, 4
Explanation(s), 177n; causal, 199–200, 216–19; functional, 200–201, 216–19; in social anthropology,
199–201
Expressive desires, in religion, 209, 213–15
Family: Buddhist monasticism and, 278–83; in East Asia, 262–85; kibbutz as, 66–67; monasticism
and, 278–83; religion and, 262–85
Family systems: biological characteristics of, 265–66; cross-cultural regularities in, 265–68
Family tensions in East Asia, 268–71, 271–83
Fantasy as reality, 168–71
Faris, E., 140
Father: ancestor worship and, 272–75; God as, 176; religious beliefs and, 202–5
Father-son relationship, 73–103, 252–60; ancestor worship and, 274–75; in East Asian families, 269
Feuer, Lewis S., 97
Firth, Raymond, 109, 123n, 216
Fortes, Meyer, 203, 272, 274
Fortune, Reo F., 232, 233
Fox, Robin, 75, 76, 85, 93
Frazier, J. G., 76, 100–102, 210
Freud, Anna, 245
Freud, Sigmund, 8, 27–29, 65, 66, 72, 87, 135, 202–4, 239n, 259–61, 263, 270
Fromm, E., 120–21, 239n
Frustrations, 12, 13, 24
Functional analysis, 107–84; personality and, 109–44; social systems and, 109–44
Functional explanations, 200–201, 216–19
Functionalism, 107–84; religion and, 286–301; typology of, 123n
Furuya, Teruko, 275–76
Gathome-Hardy, Jonathan, 93
Ge, 253–59
Gender, 59–71
Genotypes, in culture, 26–27
Gerth, H. H., 196, 209
Gillen, F. J., 230
Girls, parenting need of, 63–71
God as genitor, 235, 238
Goddesses, 299–301; mothers and, 275–78
Goldenweiser, Alexander, 5
Goldschmidt, Walter, 161n
Goody, J., 195
Gough, E. Kathleen, 88, 97
Guilt cultures, 136–39
Hallowell, A. Irving, 8, 10, 112, 116, 134, 135, 145, 146, 150, 209n, 212, 218, 228
Harlow, H., 118
Hamack, A. von, 239n
Headhunting, Ilongot, 43–45
Hempel, C. G., 123n, 187
Henry, J., 120
Herdt, Gilbert H., 93n, 94–96
Hiatt, L. R., 93
Hinduism, 18, 194, 195, 298
Hine, R., 115
Hobbes, Thomas, 260n
Hoijer, Harry, 161n
Honko, Lauri, 286n
Hopi, 212, 213
Hopkins, Keith, 83
Horton, R., 195, 204
Hostility, 11–17, 23; father-son, 73–103
Hsu, Francis L. K., 271
Huang, Chich-Shan, 76
Humanization, enculturation as, 45
Human nature: culture and, 3–31, 250–61
Hunt, Robert C., 91
Husband-wife relationship in East Asian families, 269–71
Magic, 50–54
Mahayana Buddhism, 193, 195, 288
Mahler, Margaret, et al., 270, 283
Malinowski, Bronislaw, 72–103, 112, 225–46
Maquet, Jacques, 161n
Marian cult, 97
Marxism, 4
Matrifocal households, 88
Mead, Margaret, 22n, 112, 137
Meaning: of cultural doctrines, 163–64; meanings of, 209
Meggitt, M. J., 230
Mental representations, in religious symbol systems, 161
Merton, Robert K., 114, 123n, 126n, 135, 208, 212, 218
Mexico, 9; Marian cult in, 97
Miller, Neal A., 8, 117n
Mills, C. Wright, 196, 209
Mind, 183; defined, 161–62; religious symbols and, 167–69; theory of, 287
Monasticism, 291–92; Buddhist, 278–83; Burmese, 151–58; family and, 278–83; psychosis and,
155–59
Money, John, 76
Montagu, M. F. Ashley, 111, 226–27, 228, 231, 232
Moral anxiety, 136–39
Morioka, Kiyomi, 273, 274
Mother(s), in East Asian religion, 275–78
Mother-son relationship, 73–103, 253–61; in East Asia, 266, 282–83
Moulton, Ruth, 70
Murdock, George Peter, 48
Murphy, Gardner, 117, 121, 122, 133
Tallensi, 203
Talmon, Yonina, 78
Tanaka, Masako, 91, 269–70, 275, 282
Tertullian, 17, 235
Thailand, Burmese in, 18
Theravada Buddhism, 151–58, 190–95, 287–301
Theresa, St., 148
Thompson, W., 115
Thomson, D. F., 229n, 230, 231
Tiger, Lionel, 64
Tinbergen, N., 115
Tolman, E. C., 117n
Torah—Dhamma, 288, 290–91
Totemic symbols, 294
Trinities, 298–99
Trivers, Robert L., 64n
Trobrianders, 230–33, 244n, 247n
Trobriand Islands, 72–103
Truth, of religious beliefs, 201–5
Tsuji, Yohko, 275–76
Tu, Wei Ming, 271
Tully River Blacks, paternity theory, 210, 223, 229, 230, 233, 236
Turner, V. W., 205n
Tuzin, Donald F., 32, 93n, 96, 161n
Tylor, E. B., 110