Muslim Schools of Thought
Muslim Schools of Thought
Muslim Schools of Thought
126
3
Agha, “A Viewpoint of the Murjiʾa in the Umayyad Period,” 3.
4
The verse reads: “And [there are] others deferred until the command of God – whether He
will punish them or whether He will forgive them. And God is Knowing and Wise.”
5
Watt, Formative Period of Islamic Thought, 126–27.
6
Blankinship, “The Early Creed,” 44.
a demand to return to the Qurʾan and sunna. From what little can be
reconstructed of the thought of Jahm b. Safwā n, he seems to have empha-
sized an “extreme” Murjiʾite stance whereby˙ faith was conceptualized as
“internalized knowledge in the heart” requiring no actions whatsoever.7
He may well have been among the first Muslims to speak of the principle
of reason (ʿaql) and how it could be used to derive opinions from
propositions.8 By 119/737 the Umayyad armies had worn down the
rebellion to the point where Ibn Surayj entered into an alliance with
a non-Muslim Turkish prince. Jahm was captured and executed in 128/
746, and although pardoned in 127/745, al-Hā rith b. Surayj was killed
˙
and the rebellion finally scattered later in the same year.
Later heresiographical writings would attribute several ideas of
a different sort to Jahm and would accuse him of being associated with
another firqa, the Muʿtazilites. Some even posited the existence of a group
called the Jahmiyya. Hanbalı̄ legal scholars in particular applied these
˙
terms to anyone whom they suspected of harboring Muʿtazilite tenden-
cies, and Ahmad b. Hanbal was said to have written a refutation of their
˙ ˙
thought.9 However, the proto-Muʿtazilite ideas attributed to Jahm may
not have actually been held by him. It is difficult, for example, to imagine
how Jahm upheld the notion of the created Qurʾan long before such an
issue became important (simultaneously, it is easy to see how later
authors might interpolate this issue into the discussion as a way for
them to “refute” it). As for the so-called Jahmiyya, it is noteworthy that
those accused of being a member of the sect were often associated with
other sectarian groups (notably the Muʿtazilites), such that the Jahmiyya
appears to be a wholly made-up and polemical category. It seems that
considerable confusion set in early over who was a Murjiʾite and what that
term meant.
An actual proponent of early Murjiʾism, such as it was in the Umayyad
period and into the early ʿAbbā sid period, was the Kufan legal scholar
Abū Hanı̄ fa, eponym of the Hanafı̄ legal school and the person who
˙ ˙
arranged for the pardon of Ibn Surayj from the Umayyad caliph. In
what is the earliest surviving Muslim creed, the Fiqh al-Akbar I, Abū
Hanı̄ fa upheld what might be considered many of the basic principles of
˙
Murjiʾism. In it, he spoke of a deferral of judgment on ʿUthmā n and ʿAlı̄
(combined with an embrace of the Companions generally), a belief in
predestination, and a statement on God being in the heavens.10 Less
typical of “Murjiʾism” are some of the other statements in the Fiqh al-
Akbar I, such as that guaranteeing damnation to any “Jahmite” who
7
Watt, Formative Period of Islamic Thought, 143–44. 8
Schöck, “Jahm b. Safwā n,” 56.
9
Watt, Formative Period of Islamic Thought, 144. 10 ˙ 103–4.
Wensinck, Muslim Creed,
denies the torment in the grave. That many of these ideas would later
become standard aspects of Sunnism shows just how close Murjiʾism was
to what became later Sunnism (indeed, most Sunni Muslims consider
Abū Hanı̄ fa a model Sunni). Yet Sunni he was not: Abū Hanı̄ fa’s follow-
˙ ˙
ers made Balkh their center, which was known as “Murjiʾabā d”
(Murjiʾa-town) for a time.
It is difficult to think of Murjiʾism as a coherent sect or philosophy in its
early stages. Rather, an apolitical tendency seems to have gathered sup-
porters, often for different reasons, throughout the Umayyad period such
that by the end of the Umayyad period a set of semi-intangible doctrines
appear to animate the rebellion of Ibn Surayj and gain a certain amount of
articulation in the creed of Abū Hanı̄ fa. Yet Murjiʾism as such cannot still
˙
be considered a firqa in the same manner as the Khā rijites and early Shiʿa.
It is, rather, an attitude toward faith and a school of thought in formation,
and with the ʿAbbā sid period this nascent theological trend gained some-
what more definition.
Later Murjiʾa
Later Murjiʾism formed alongside a growing ʿAbbā sid-era interest in
kalā m (ʿilm al-kalā m) (theology, theological discourse/debate). Islamic
theology was broadly focused on questions about the nature of God
(oftentimes by deducing God’s nature from His creation, the natural
world) so that human beings could thereby determine how they should
act in relation to God. The theological speculations of the ʿAbbā sid era
shaped the direction and focus of Islamic sectarian groups of the time in
profound ways. Most weighty in consequence was how the ʿAbbā sid
revolution and the “compromise” established between the ʿAbbā sid
caliphs and the religious scholars addressed many of the most pressing
issues of the late Umayyad period. Gone was the Arab chauvinism of the
Umayyads, replaced by a universalist vision of Islam that demanded
a universal (i.e. “catholic”) legal system grounded in an emergent interest
in hadı̄ th. And for those who more or less accepted the “compromise,” the
˙
issue of God’s justice, with its potential for revolutionary appeal, was
lessened in the face of ʿAbbā sid caliphal order. The relative stability of
the ʿAbbā sid period further reinforced anti-revolutionary tendencies
among the ʿulamā ʾ. Only scattered Khā rijites and militant Shiʿa, mostly
Zaydı̄ s, maintained an interest in violent revolt, while their quietist breth-
ren among the Ibā diyya and Imā miyya remained staunchly pragmatic
˙
and/or apolitical.
In the face of such conditions, the pointed questions of the Umayyad
era over the question of ʿUthmā n and ʿAlı̄ gave way to more general
11
Blankinship, “The Early Creed,” 46.
subsisted along with the act itself, but that such power to act needed to be
created again with each new act. On the issue of seeing God on the Day of
Judgment, al-Najjā r showed his originality: He held that people would see
God, but only with a special eye or unique knowledge that God gave them
on that day.12
Perhaps more important than the Iraqis who were identified as Murjiʾa
were the Murjiʾa of Transoxania, where this theological tendency found
a center around the emerging Hanafı̄ legal school. As the heartland of Ibn
˙
al-Surayj’s rebellion, it is perhaps not surprising that Murjiʾism took root
there. The scholars of Balkh reportedly traveled to Kufa to study with
Abū Hanı̄ fa himself, and during Abū Hanı̄ fa’s lifetime, a student of his,
˙ ˙
ʿUmar b. Maymū n al-Rammā h (d. 171/787–88), became qā dı̄ of Balkh,
˙ ˙
a position he would hold for two decades. Later Central Asian jurists
would codify both Hanafı̄ legal positions and Murjiʾite theological posi-
˙
tions. Abū Mutı̄ ʿ al-Balkhı̄ (al-Hakam b. ʿAbdullā h) (d. 197/812–13)
˙
penned the so-called al-Fiqh al-Absat in which he collected Abū
˙
Hanı̄ fa’s theological positions, including the affirmation that a Muslim
˙
convert in the territory of polytheism who confessed Islam without any
knowledge of the Qurʾan or any of the religious obligations of Islam was
a true believer (muʾmin).13 The same Abū Mutı̄ ʿ also transmitted the
˙
Kitā b al-ʿĀ lim wa’l-Mutaʿā lim (The Book of the Scholar and Learner), an
exposition of Abū Muqā til al-Samarqandı̄ ’s doctrine of irjā ʾ, which Abū
Muqā til attributed to his teacher Abū Hanı̄ fa. These two works formed
˙
the basis of all later Murjiʾite theology of eastern Hanafism, a theology
˙
that itself became part and parcel of an emerging Sunnism.14
With the gradual emergence of Sunnism in the third/ninth to fourth/
tenth centuries, many of the central tenets of “Murjiʾism,” including the
all-important belief that faith was somewhat separated from works, pre-
destination, and the idea of intercession, made their way into the Sunni
consensus (despite initial pushback from luminaries like al-Ashʿarı̄ and
the Hanbalı̄ s). Abū Hanı̄ fa and his legal school became one of the four
˙ ˙
accepted legal schools among Sunnis and the founder himself was grad-
ually shorn of any connections to a movement increasingly deemed
unacceptable. Yet heresiographers such as al-Shahrastā nı̄ continued to
write about the Murjiʾa as if they were a recognized firqa, meaning that
their continued salience offered some sort of rhetorical value to them.15
But why continue to write about a firqa that probably never existed as such
12
Blankinship, “The Early Creed,” 47. 13 Madelung, “The Early Murjiʾa,” 37.
14
Madelung, “The Early Murjiʾa,” 38–39.
15
al-Shahrastā nı̄ , al-Milal wa’l-Nihal, 139ff.
˙
in the first place, and with whom the main proponents (Abū Hanı̄ fa and
˙
his followers) could no longer be directly associated?
In part, this compulsion to reify the Murjiʾa can be explained by the
heresiographical need to create seventy-two sects. Heresiographers con-
tinued to use a distinctive firqa called the “Murjiʾa” with its various
subsects to round out their taxonomies. After all, earlier luminaries
such as al-Ashʿarı̄ and Ahmad b. Hanbal had written of Murjiʾites as if
˙ ˙
they were a coherent group, and so they may well have been. It was left to
the heresiographers, then, to muster enough individuals to satisfy the
requirement for a group called the Murjiʾites. That heresiographers and
others went about imagining the Murjiʾites in different and even contra-
dictory ways is evident from the lists of persons who supposedly made up
the sect. The early Shiʿi heresiographer al-Nawbakhtı̄ , for example,
claims that the Murjiʾa consisted of four groups: the Jahmiyya, who
followed Jahm b. Safwā n; the Ghaylā niyya, who followed Ghaylā n
˙
b. Marwā n al-Dimashqı̄ ; the Mā siriyya, who followed ʿAmr b. Qays al-
˙
Mā sir (a group which included Abū Hanı̄ fa and his followers); and the
˙ ˙
Batriyya or the Ahl al-Hadı̄ th, including Sufyā n al-Thawrı̄ , Shā rik
˙
b. ʿAbdullā h, Ibn Abı̄ Layla, al-Shā fiʿı̄ , Mā lik b. Anas, and many
others.16 Analyzing al-Nawbakhtı̄ ’s list, it becomes apparent that “real”
Murjiʾa are hard to find. Jahm b. Safwā n was associated with al-Hā rith
˙ ˙
b. Surayj, an early Murjiʾite of sorts, and Ghaylā n al-Dimashqı̄ was said to
have held to irjā ʾ, but also to have believed in qadar (and therefore
associated with a different group known as the Qadariyya).17 ʿAmr
b. Qays is obscure, and it is into this group that al-Nawbakhtı̄ slips Abū
Hanı̄ fa and his followers. The Batriyya were a Zaydı̄ Shiʿa group that
˙
eventually merged with Sunnism in Kufa, while the rest of those included
in al-Nawbakhtı̄ ’s list of Murjiʾites comprise prominent early proponents
of hadı̄ th as well as the eponymous founders of three of the four Sunni
˙
legal schools (Abū Hanı̄ fa, al-Shā fiʿı̄ , Mā lik). What comes through is that
˙
the Murjiʾites are either obscure religious figures, persons with dubious
Murjiʾite credentials, or persons who later became strongly associated
with Sunnism.
Comparing this list with that given in al-Shahrastā nı̄ (also a Shiʿi here-
siographer, but an Ismā ʿı̄ lı̄ who extensively used Ashʿarı̄ sources) is
instructive in how the playing field of Murjiʾism can shift depending on
the needs of the heresiographer in question. Al-Shahrastā nı̄ ’s list of
Murjiʾites also breaks the group into four: the Khā rijite-Murjiʾa, for
whom he provides no examples; the Qadarı̄ -Murjiʾa, who include the
16
al-Nawbakhtı̄ , Kitā b Firaq al-Shı̄ ʿa, 6–7.
17
Watt, Formative Period of Islamic Thought, 86.
18
al-Shahrastā nı̄ , al-Milal wa’l-Nihal, 139–46.
19 ˙ al, 141.
al-Shahrastā nı̄ , al-Milal wa’l-Nih
20
Watt, Formative Period of Islamic˙ Thought, 142.
The Qadariyya
As with the Murjiʾa, the origins of the Muʿtazila, one of the great intellec-
tual movements of medieval Islamdom, remain difficult to discern with
any certainty. From the perspective of intellectual history, Muʿtazilite
notions of free will appear to have their antecedents in an Umayyad-era
group known as the Qadariyya. The Qadariyya derived their name from
their promotion of the concept of qadar, which is usually rendered as “free
will,” but can also take the sense of “measure” insofar as God is held to
have measured out a modicum of latitude for human beings to choose
good or evil. This belief in human free will ran counter to the predomin-
ant notion of predestination, but its aim in the early period seemed to
emphasize that human beings were responsible for their sins. That is to
say, human beings could be considered accountable for their actions only
if they were free to choose their actions. It is difficult to argue that human
beings should be rewarded or punished if the source of their actions is, in
fact, God Himself.
Considering the widespread perception of the Umayyads as suspect or
corrupt, preaching human free will and the consequent doctrine of
human responsibility for action could be taken as a political act. Al-
Hasan al-Basrı̄ , a popular Basran preacher and pietist, for example, was
˙ ˙
said to have caught the attention of the Umayyad caliph ʿAbd al-Malik,
for preaching something akin to qadar, and thereby suggesting that
human beings (including caliphs and governors) were to be held
accountable for their actions. A letter attributed to him, allegedly in
response to the caliph’s request for clarification, emphasizes that evil
acts come from human beings, who have a modicum of free will. Later
Muʿtazilites considered al-Hasan al-Basrı̄ a Qadarite, though some
˙ ˙
contemporary scholars have been skeptical about the extent of his pur-
ported Qadarism as well as the authenticity of his letter.21 Given the
popularity of al-Hasan al-Basrı̄ , his stance certainly represented
˙ one that did
a political act, albeit ˙ not involve rebellion, unlike some
other Qadarite movements.
The alleged “founder” of the Qadarı̄ movement was Maʿbad b. ʿAbdullā h
al-Juhanı̄ , a Basran hadı̄ th scholar (muhaddith) and a respected member of
˙ ˙
the Umayyad elite. He was executed in 80/699, either by the caliph ʿAbd al-
Malik or his deputy, al-Hajjā j b. Yū suf. While many sources claim that it was
˙
21
Judd, “Ghaylan al-Dimashqi,” 180n4.
his Qadarı̄ beliefs that led to his execution, a report suggests that he partici-
pated in the failed revolt of Ibn al-Ashʿath.22 One of the bitter enemies of the
Qadariyya, ʿAbd al-Rahmā n al-Awzā ʿı̄ , claimed that al-Juhanı̄ learned
˙
Qadarism from the Christians, a polemical move that likely served to isolate
al-Juhanı̄ from the mainstream, as well as de-emphasizing the importance of
al-Hasan al-Basrı̄ by making al-Juhanı̄ the “first” Qadarite.23 Such claims
˙ ˙
can thus be treated with some skepticism.
Al-Juhanı̄ ’s most important associate, and possibly his pupil, Ghaylā n
al-Dimashqı̄ , was another who became associated with the Qadariyya.
However, he is also identified in heresiographical sources as a Murjiʾite.
Among the beliefs attributed to him in these sources are his deferring the
judgment of sinners to God, and holding that faith was a secondary
knowledge of God (both beliefs associated with the Murjiʾa), as well as
the idea that sin came from human action, while good deeds came from
God (notions associated with Qadarism). Ghaylā n was, like his teacher,
an Umayyad bureaucrat, one who reportedly gained the confidence of the
Umayyad caliph ʿUmar b. ʿAbd al-ʿAzı̄ z for a time (Ghaylā n was one of
his secretaries and also ran the Damascus mint) before the caliph report-
edly dissociated himself from him (ʿUmar b. ʿAbd al-ʿAzı̄ z reportedly
penned a long treatise attacking the notion of qadar). Ghaylā n also served
in the Umayyad army, but reportedly ran afoul of his superiors. Ghaylā n
was later executed in Damascus, purportedly for his Qadarite beliefs.24
Another early pietist, Abū ʿAbdullā h Makhū l b. Abı̄ Muslim, reflected
the extent to which frontier soldiers shaped the expectations of the early
Qadariyya. Makhū l was an Iranian captive who had been stationed on the
frontier, and whose religious zeal and knowledge made him into
a respected legal expert among his fellow soldiers. This frontier zeal,
combined with grievances from the southern Arab soldiers at their treat-
ment in Syria, fueled the Syrian Qadariyya and may have led them into
supporting a putsch that brought the Umayyad caliph Yazı̄ d b. al-Walı̄ d
(Yazı̄ d III) to power.
After the execution of Ghaylā n, many of the Qadariyya became openly
political, finding a champion in the caliph Yazı̄ d b. al-Walı̄ d (d. 126/
744).25 Yazı̄ d b. al-Walı̄ d used Qadarism as a means to challenge his
cousin, the caliph al-Walı̄ d b. Yazı̄ d (Walı̄ d II, d. 126/744), who advo-
cated an intense belief in of predestination. Both Murjiʾites and Qadarites
were said to have supported Yazı̄ d b. al-Walı̄ d, to have constituted his
inner circle, and to have used the doctrine of qadar as a means to justify
22
Judd, “Muslim Persecution of Heretics,” 5.
23
Judd, “Muslim Persecution of Heretics,” 5.
24
Judd, “Ghaylan al-Dimashqi,” 163; Judd, “Muslim Persecution of Heretics,” 10.
25
Judd, “The Early Qadariyya,” 51.
The Muʿtazila
Like many of the firaq examined in this book, the origins of the religious
movement known as the Muʿtazila, which would go on to become one of
the most important medieval theological schools in Islamdom, remain
obscure, and the sources available for the study of early Muʿtazilism
present serious problems. Consequently, there is considerable variety in
how to approach the beginnings of this group. Of the later development of
Muʿtazilism there is more material, and thus, more consensus on the
fundaments of what animated them as well as what caused them to
decline among Sunnis (while remaining a prominent feature of certain
Shiʿite theological inquiry). Muʿtazilism could be said to have three
phases: an origin, early, and scholastic phase. Of these three, the origin
period is the most difficult to reconstruct.
Muslim sources often tell a story of how the Muʿtazila began in Basra
with Wā sil b. ʿAtā ʾ and ʿAmr b. ʿUbayd, both pupils of al-Hasan al-
˙ ˙ ˙
Basrı̄ .26 One of the more popular stories concerning their origins speaks
˙
of Wā sil’s “withdrawal” (iʿtizā l) from the study circle of his teacher over
˙
the question of the sinner. Wā sil was said to have interrupted al-Hasan
˙ ˙
when he was speaking about the state of the sinner, declaring that there
was an “intermediate position” between considering the sinner either
a believer or nonbeliever. Having made this declaration, Wā sil was said
˙
to have “withdrawn” to a different corner of the mosque, signaling his
formal break with his teacher.
Whatever the entertainment value of this story, it is unlikely to be
a strict historical account of the origins of the Muʿtazila. The narrative
is a bit too neat and seems tailor-made to account for the name of the
group. Modern scholars, however, offer little consensus on the possible
historical origins of the group. Some of the first scholars of the Muʿtazila
offered semantic analysis of the term, arguing that it indicated how the
26
Bennett, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (II),” 144; El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement
(I),” 134–35.
early Muʿtazila were pious ascetics, who withdrew from the wider society,
or from the political wrangling of the early period, or, alternately, from
specific persons such as ʿAlı̄ .27 More recent scholarship has tended to
focus less on the semantic roots of the word and more on the persons said
to be associated with the group. It examines, for example, how Wā sil
˙
b. ʿAtā ʾ appeared to have connections to Muhammad b. al-Hanafiyya and
˙ ˙ 28 ˙
along with him adopted a generally pro-ʿAlı̄ d stance. He reportedly held
that the imamates of Abū Bakr, ʿUmar, and ʿUthmā n were valid though
they were not the most excellent (afdal) candidates. Rather, ʿAlı̄ was the
˙
most excellent candidate in his estimation. Overall, these stances indi-
cated a position of political neutrality, yet still one that favored the
ʿAlı̄ ds. Moreover, Wā sil was said to have given sermons to the
˙
Umayyad governor and to have sent his followers out from Basra as
missionaries (much like the Ibā dı̄ s of Basra were doing), spreading his
˙
views through kalā m, surviving through commercial activity, and pro-
viding a pious example of asceticism. His embrace of the concept of free
will (qadar) probably earned him, as an outsider (who reportedly could
not pronounce the letter “r”), a place in the city that teemed with
Qadarites. On his death, many of Wā sil’s students were said to have
gone to North Africa.29
Equally important to the early Muʿtazila was the figure of ʿAmr
b. ʿUbayd (d. 144/761), a traditionalist who was strongly associated
with the concept of free will.30 Also a student of al-Hasan al-Basrı̄ , his
˙ ˙
asceticism even earned him the grudging admiration of his opponents.
Contrary to Wā sil, Ibn ʿUbayd upheld the leadership of “most worthy”
and was reportedly sympathetic to ʿUthmā n. He was not interested in
kalā m, and he seems more known for his piety and asceticism as well as his
consequent mistrust of the political elites of his age. His stature surely
helped the Muʿtazila spread in Basra. After the ʿAbbā sid revolution, ʿAmr
spoke often and fearlessly at the court of the ʿAbbā sid caliph al-Mansū r,
˙
who respected him and praised him in a eulogy after his death.31 It is
possible that his appearance in al-Mansū r’s court was aimed at securing
˙
the same kind of political neutrality that ʿAmr had encouraged during the
ʿAbbā sid revolution. Some of his students, however, apparently partici-
pated in the revolt of the Zaydı̄ rebel al-Nafs al-Zakiyya after ʿAmr’s
death, eschewing the political neutrality of their teacher.
27
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 132–33.
28
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 135.
29
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 135–36.
30
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 135.
31
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 136–37.
32
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 136; Van Ess, Theology and Society, 2:348.
33
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 137.
34
El-Omari, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (I),” 137.
35
Bennett, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (II),” 144–45.
36
Turner, Inquisition in Early Islam, 150.
37
Bennett, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (II),” 146.
38
Haider, Shı̄ ʿı̄ Islam, 18. 39 Blankinship, “The Early Creed,” 50.
40
Bennett, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (II),” 153; Blankinship, “The Early Creed,” 48.
participated in the way that God Himself was uncreated, was likewise
uncreated. The implications of this stance, that the Qurʾan was uncre-
ated, implied that God’s commands must simply be followed without
question, and that the seeming anthropomorphisms of certain qurʾanic
verses – for example, verses that spoke of God’s “throne” or of the “face of
God” – referred to an actual Throne and Face.
The Muʿtazilites, on the other hand, held that God’s speech, once
uttered, came into the world and participated in the existence of the
world. It existed in time and space, and thus the speech of the Qurʾan
was created, just as the things of the world were also created things. The
Qurʾan, then, could be apprehended by human beings through their
reason, even though this understanding would itself be time bound and
flawed. What seems to lie behind this concern with the Qurʾan as created
speech was a desire to keep the questions of religion relevant to their time.
If human beings could apprehend the Qurʾan through their reason, then it
offered an endless source of contemplation, inspiration, and guidance.
Seeming anthropomorphisms in the Qurʾan were not to be taken literally,
but as metaphors: God’s throne and face were indicators of His majestic
station.
In these questions of the nature of qurʾanic speech, it is hard to miss the
reflections of the Christological debates of early centuries. The status of
Christ (as the “word” of God made flesh) as fully human or fully divine, or
both, was something that exercised the early Christian community, for-
cing it to articulate stances that created orthodoxies and heresies. Islamic
theology owes a debt to Christian theology, and this is one of the legacies
of the translation movement.
Beyond the “five principles,” other questions occupied the early
Muʿtazilites. They were atomists, meaning that they conceived of the
world as being made up of discrete particles, atoms (ajzā ʾ, though some-
times jawā hir), as well as the force which inhered and animated these
particles, known as the “accident” (ʿarad). A great variety of Muʿtazilite
˙
positions on atomism existed, but overall these positions pointed to
a concern with the physical makeup of the universe, with causality, and
with the work of God in creating and commanding the elements.41 This
concern allowed the Muʿtazilites to show how human beings became
responsible for their actions. Human action created chains of causes
such that they caused, for example, the pain that they chose to inflict in
others, not God (who, according to some, merely created the “capacity”
to cause pain in others). Here the freewill legacy of the early Qadariyya
found a new home.
41
Bennett, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (II),” 147–50.
The turn of the fourth/tenth century initiated the final and “scholastic
phase” of the Muʿtazilite movement, one in which the individualistic and
scattered concerns of the early period gave way to coherent doctrinal
systems articulated by two distinct Muʿtazilite schools. The first, the
Basran school, was led by Abū ʿAlı̄ al-Jubbā ʾı̄ (d. 303/915–16), while
the second, the school of Baghdad, was headed by Abū al-Qā sim al-
Balkhı̄ (d. 313/931).42 Abū ʿAlı̄ al-Jubbā ʾı̄ took up the work of Abū al-
Hudhayl, refining and sometimes refuting elements of it to create
a comprehensive philosophical system. His son, Abū Hā shim al-Jubbā ʾı̄ ,
claimed leadership of the Basran Muʿtazila after his father’s death,
though several opponents of Abū Hā shim’s leadership emerged and
later coalesced as the Ikhshı̄ diyya. Abū Hā shim’s group became known
as the Bashamiyya. Until recently, texts from the Basran Muʿtazilites
existed only in quotations from later works.43
Abū al-Qā sim al-Kaʿbı̄ al-Balkhı̄ , the leader of the Baghdad school of
Muʿtazilism in the early to mid-300s/900s, heavily influenced not only
later Muʿtazilites, but also Sunnism, specifically Hanafism in Central
˙
Asia, and especially al-Mā turı̄ dı̄ , who considered al-Kaʿbı̄ his foil. He
also influenced Shiʿite thinkers such as al-Mufı̄ d. The thought of al-Kaʿbı̄
must be reconstructed, largely from the work of his student (and later
pupil of ʿAbd al-Jabbā r), Abū Rashı̄ d al-Nı̄ sā bū rı̄ .
The succeeding luminary of the Baghdadi Muʿtazila, ʿAbd al-Jabbā r al-
Hamdā nı̄ , became their leader in 369/980. He had joined the Bashamiyya
movement as a young man, having been a pupil of Abū ʿAbdullā h al-
Basrı̄ . Under the Bū yids, ʿAbd al-Jabbā r was appointed chief judge (he
˙
was Shā fiʿı̄ in his legal orientation) of their territories and their capital,
Rayy. His position enabled him to attract several students, including
Zaydı̄ and Imā mı̄ Shiʿites. These turned Rayy into an intellectual center
of the Muʿtazilite movement.44 Of ʿAbd al-Jabbā r’s numerous works, al-
Mughnı̄ fı̄ Abwā b al-Tawhı̄ d wa’l-ʿAdl (The Enricher of the Gates of God’s
˙
Oneness and Justice) remains one of the most important sources for later
Muʿtazilite doctrine. ʿAbd al-Jabbā r’s students and successors, Abū
Rashı̄ d al-Nı̄ sā bū rı̄ , Abū Muhammad al-Muttawayh, and Abū Jaʿfar
˙
Muhammad b. ʿAlı̄ b. Mazdak, were likewise important figures.
˙
Another significant representative of Bashamı̄ Muʿtazilism was Abū
Saʿd al-Muhassin b. Muhammad b. Karrā ma al-Bayhaqı̄ , a Hanafı̄
˙ ˙ ˙
judge who followed Muʿtazilite theology and wrote an important
42
Schmidtke, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (III),” 159.
43
Schmidtke, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (III),” 162. For newly published Basran
Muʿtazilite works, see Adang et al., Basran Muʿtazilite Theology.
44
Schmidtke, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (III),” 166.
encyclopedia, the Sharh ʿUyū n al-Masā ʾil (Elucidation of the Sources of the
˙
Questions). Later in life he became a Zaydı̄ Shiʿite.45
Abū al-Husayn al-Basrı̄ (d. 436/1044) led a rival school of Baghdadi
˙ ˙
Muʿtazilism after he challenged his teacher, ʿAbd al-Jabbā r, on certain
points of Bashā mı̄ doctrine. Raised a Hanafı̄ and a Muʿtazilite, Abū al-
˙
Husayn also pursued both medicine and Aristotelian philosophy in
˙
Baghdad. He challenged several standard Muʿtazilite views, such as that
on the nature of God’s existence, earning him condemnation, and even
some accusations of unbelief (kufr), from some of his fellow
Muʿtazilites.46 One of his important works was the Kitā b Tasaffuh al-
Adilla (Examining the Evidence). His most popular work was al-Muʿtamad˙ ˙
fı̄ Usū l al-Fiqh (The Convention on the Sources of Jurisprudence), a work on
˙
legal theory. Despite his disagreements with the main group of
Bashamiyya, his thought had a great impact on his contemporaries and
successors. He taught a large circle of students and had several succes-
sors, such as Ibn al-Walı̄ d, Abū al-ʿĀ sim al-Wā hid b. ʿAlı̄ b. Barhan al-
˙ ˙
ʿUkhbar al-Asadı̄ , and al-Qā dı̄ ʿAbdullā h al-Saymarı̄ , who led the prayers
˙
over Abū al-Husayn on his death. His thought also left an impression on
later Ashʿarite˙ thinkers, such that the Ashʿarı̄ scholar al-Juwaynı̄ relied on
Abū al-Husayn’s notion of contingency when he formulated his proof for
˙
the existence of God. He was even quoted by the staunch Sunni Ibn
Taymiyya.47
Abū al-Husayn’s group of Muʿtazilites, however, represented the last
˙
effective generation of Muʿtazilite theologians, who increasingly found
their theology challenged and eclipsed by that offered by Abū al-Hasan al-
˙
Ashʿarı̄ and his followers. Muʿtazilite modes of thinking and reasoning, as
well as many of its core doctrines, would live on among Zaydı̄ and other
Shiʿite thinkers, but by the sixth/twelfth century it was waning in the
heartlands of Islamdom. The Mongol invasions wiped away the last traces
of it, with the exception of those Shiʿites who had adopted Muʿtazilı̄ ideas
of rationalism and justice and applied them to their own theological
speculations.
The narratives of Murjiʾism and the Muʿtazilites shift the focal point of
Islamic sectarianism away from the revolutionary fervor of the Umayyad
era to the relative stability of the ʿAbbā sid period. In that era of relative
prosperity, these two ʿAbbā sid-era schools of thought matured into highly
specialized intellectual schools, developing philosophies/theologies that
45
Schmidtke, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (III),” 167–69.
46
Schmidtke, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (III),” 170.
47
Schmidtke, “The Muʿtazilite Movement (III),” 174.