Do Mathematicians Agree About Mathematical Beauty

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 27

Review of Philosophy and Psychology

https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-022-00669-3

Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

Rentuya Sa1 · Lara Alcock1 · Matthew Inglis1 · Fenner Stanley Tanswell2

Accepted: 5 December 2022


© The Author(s) 2023

Abstract
Mathematicians often conduct aesthetic judgements to evaluate mathematical
objects such as equations or proofs. But is there a consensus about which mathe-
matical objects are beautiful? We used a comparative judgement technique to meas-
ure aesthetic intuitions among British mathematicians, Chinese mathematicians, and
British mathematics undergraduates, with the aim of assessing whether judgements
of mathematical beauty are influenced by cultural differences or levels of expertise.
We found aesthetic agreement both within and across these demographic groups.
We conclude that judgements of mathematical beauty are not strongly influenced by
cultural difference, levels of expertise, and types of mathematical objects. Our find-
ings contrast with recent studies that found mathematicians often disagree with each
other about mathematical beauty.

Do mathematicians agree about mathematical beauty? Some traditional accounts


assume that they do. Under aesthetic realism, mathematical beauty is conceptual-
ized as existing independently of subjective preferences and social contexts. Realist
accounts hold that beauty is not reducible to ‘reports of experience in the mind of
the observer’ (Simoniti 2017, p.1436). They assume normativity of aesthetic intui-
tion, in the sense that judgements of beauty are either correct or incorrect (Cova and
Pain 2012), and that some level of expertise is necessary to make such judgements.
Mathematicians who endorse realist accounts, such as Hardy and Erdős, therefore
tend to assume aesthetic agreement among mathematicians.
These accounts are, however, open to challenge. Experimental philosophers seek-
ing to empirically investigate assumptions about philosophical intuitions (Knobe
2007) have found widespread aesthetic disagreement within mathematical practice
(Wells 1990; Inglis and Aberdein 2015, 2016, 2020). This suggests an alternative
position of aesthetic non-realism, according to which mathematical beauty is not an

* Rentuya Sa
R.Sa@lboro.ac.uk
1
Department of Mathematics Education, Loughborough University, Schofield Building,
University Road, Loughborough LE11 3TU, UK
2
Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Brussels, Belgium

13
Vol.:(0123456789)
R. Sa et al.

objective property, but where individual aesthetic preferences might differ idiosyn-
cratically, or perhaps be systematically influenced by social contexts.
As a contribution to the field of experimental philosophy, this paper empirically
measures the level of aesthetic consensus among and across British mathematicians,
Chinese mathematicians, and British undergraduate mathematics students. We begin
by examining philosophical accounts of mathematical beauty and methods previ-
ously used to assess aesthetic intuitions. We then introduce comparative judgment as
a means of investigating aesthetics, and describe the stimuli, participants, and proce-
dure we employed. Finally, we discuss our empirical findings in the light of current
understandings of mathematical beauty, and summarise both our substantive contri-
bution to debates about philosophical intuitions and our methodological contribu-
tion to advances in experimental philosophy.

1 Agreement and Disagreement about Mathematical Beauty

1.1 Assumed Aesthetic Agreement among Mathematicians

One early realist account of mathematical beauty is the Pythagorean ‘cosmocen-


tric’ belief that beauty is an objective property for humans not to invent but to dis-
cover (Tatarkiewicz 1963). On this account, mathematics governs the unquestion-
able essence of physical reality, which can only be grasped through the beauty and
harmony of numerical and geometrical patterns (Sinclair and Pimm 2006, p.4).
Although this account tends to amalgamate later Pythagorean writers and their mod-
ern interpreters (Berghaus 1992, p.44), it initiated a highly influential understanding
of mathematical beauty. For instance, according to Plato’s Philebus (1993), Socrates
states that mathematical objects such as straight lines or circles are not ‘relatively
beautiful’ like animals or pictures. Instead, their beauty is eternal and absolute,
which means that it does not evolve with changes of social context. This means that
the aesthetic dimension of mathematics exists objectively and is not reducible to
mathematicians’ subjective perceptions and preferences.
Mathematicians who subscribe to such accounts tend to advocate the existence
of fixed aesthetic criteria or a collection of mathematical objects universally agreed
to be beautiful. One well-known such account is G.H. Hardy’s (1940, p.29) list
of six criteria for beauty in a proof. This list includes economy, which is derived
from the classical ideal of beauty as simplicity. This ideal is embodied in differ-
ent forms, including numerical, explanatory, and logical simplicity (McAllister
1996). For Hardy, economy requires that theorems and proofs have simple lines of
argumentation, which facilitate their grasp ‘in a single act of mental apprehension’
(McAllister 2005, p. 19). Identifying economy – and his remaining criteria of sig-
nificance, depth, generality, unexpectedness, and inevitability – demands, according
to Hardy (1940, p.113), ‘a high degree of technical proficiency’ developed through
many years of experience as a mathematician. This implies that non-experts, such as
undergraduate students, may have difficulty making aesthetic judgements.
Another well-known proponent of aesthetic realism is Paul Erdős, who described
‘a transfinite book of theorems’ where ‘the best proofs are written’ (Alexanderson

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

1981, p.254). Erdős frequently referred to beautiful proofs as coming ‘straight out
of The Book’ (Erdős 1983, p.37), and famously claimed that mathematicians do not
necessarily need to believe in the existence of God, but they should believe in the
existence of ‘The Book’ (Aigner and Ziegler 2010, p.v). According to Cherniwchan
et al. (2010), one of Erdős’s great ambitions in life was to find such beautiful proofs.
His students Aigner and Ziegler (2010) published a collection entitled Proofs from
The Book, based on some of Erdős’s own suggestions. According to Aigner and Zie-
gler (2010, p.v), a degree of mathematical proficiency is required to comprehend
‘The Book’, although only at the undergraduate level. This suggests that undergradu-
ate mathematical training would suffice for making at least some aesthetic judgments.
The above accounts make two assumptions regarding mathematical beauty that
are subject to empirical investigation: (i) there should be agreement about aesthet-
ics among mathematicians, and (ii) judgements about aesthetics require a degree of
mathematical proficiency, although it is unclear what level of training is needed. It is
worth noting that the theoretical basis for the former assumption is potentially chal-
lenged by arguments that mathematical beauty is reducible to non-aesthetic properties
that are epistemically centered. Rota (1997, p.175), for instance, agrees that ‘both the
truth of a theorem and its beauty are…equally shared and agreed upon by the com-
munity of mathematicians’, but suggests that this is due to a sense of enlightenment
that is mistakenly referred to as ‘beauty’. Similarly, Todd (2008, pp.71–72) claims
that the ‘normative strength of the putative aesthetic claims’ is due to a relationship
between truth and epistemic warrants, and Dutilh Novaes (2019) argues that Hardy’s
aesthetic criteria are reducible to non-aesthetic properties that facilitate the epistemic
function of explanatoriness. These claims highlight ambiguity between aesthetic and
epistemic dimensions of mathematics, and we address them further later. However,
these authors still assume a degree of agreement between different mathematicians’
aesthetic intuitions, so evidence on (i) pertains to their views too.

1.2 Empirical Evidence on Disagreement about Mathematical Aesthetics

Regardless of their basis, claims about agreement concerning mathematical beauty


are called into question by recent empirical evidence. In one early study, Wells
(1990) asked 68 readers of The Mathematical Intelligencer to use a scale to rate the
beauty of 24 theorems. He reported that renowned theorems such as Euler’s identity,
polyhedron formulas, and the infinity of primes were all rated highly, but other well-
regarded theorems were not. This led him to question whether some of the highly
rated theorems were genuinely perceived to be beautiful, or whether the ratings were
better understood as a product of social influence. Additionally, he detected mixed
aesthetic responses to simplicity, as some theorems were rated low because they
were not proven in a simple and succinct manner, but other theorems with simpler or
easier proofs were also rated low because readers found them too simple and easy.
Agreement, simplicity and social influence have been addressed directly in more
recent studies. On agreement, Inglis and Aberdein (2016) asked 112 mathematicians to
rate the accuracy of twenty adjectives in describing the proof of Sylvester’s theorem from
‘The Book’ (Aigner and Ziegler 2010). They found a low level of aesthetic agreement,

13
R. Sa et al.

with 60.4% scoring the proof below the midpoint of the aesthetic scale, and only 31.5%
scoring it above. For a ‘Book proof’ to score so low seems to challenge the existence of
universal agreement about mathematical beauty; it certainly seems that Aigner and Zie-
gler’s aesthetic preferences might not be reflected in the wider community.
On simplicity, Inglis and Aberdein (2015) asked 225 mathematicians to rate the
extent to which 80 adjectives described a proof that they could think of or had recently
read. Using an exploratory factor analysis, they found four main dimensions on which
proofs varied: aesthetics, intricacy, precision, and utility. Neither ‘beautiful’ nor ‘ele-
gant’ correlated strongly with ‘simple’. Thus, even if there is agreement, this might not
be due to traditionally listed criteria.
On social influence, Inglis and Aberdein (2020) replicated their 2016 study, this
time with the manipulation that half of their 203 mathematician participants were
told the proof’s source, Aigner and Ziegler’s (2010) attempt to produce a version of
Erdős’s ‘The Book’. Pure mathematicians who were given the source rated the proof
more highly than those who were not, but applied mathematicians did not show such an
effect. This suggests that mathematicians’ aesthetic judgement might indeed be socially
influenced: Erdős was most active in pure mathematics, so ‘The Book’ is likely better
known among pure than applied mathematicians. This result also relates to the mere-
exposure account of aesthetics, which suggests that an individual’s aesthetic apprecia-
tion is developed through repetitive exposure to the same item (Zajonc 2001). Famous
mathematical objects, such as proofs from Aigner and Ziegler’s ‘The Book’, would
have more exposure within the field, and so mathematicians’ aesthetic appreciation of
such proofs could be socially developed through repetitive exposures. If accounts such
as the mere exposure effect, coupled with social conformity effects of the type studied
by Inglis and Aberdein, can successfully explain mathematicians’ judgement of math-
ematical beauty, then its objective existence would be an unnecessary assumption.
Overall, these empirical results show disagreement between different mathematicians’
intuitions of mathematical beauty. The evidence is not decisive, and there are reasons to
be cautious about the methodological approaches adopted in these studies, as discussed
below. However, it seems reasonable to conclude that investigations into mathematical
beauty should not assume that mathematicians all agree. With this in mind, we examine
judgments of mathematical beauty in relation to simplicity, cultural context, and pro-
ficiency by measuring and comparing the degree of aesthetic agreement among British
mathematicians, Chinese mathematicians, and British mathematics undergraduates.
To further situate this work and to raise issues in methodology, we next elaborate on rele-
vant studies involving the study of cross-cultural and cross-expertise philosophical intuitions.

1.3 Cross‑Cultural Studies of Philosophical Intuitions

Potential cultural influences on perceptions of mathematical beauty have not yet


been philosophically discussed or empirically assessed. Indeed, Larvor (2016, p.8)
argued that there is ‘a dearth of cultural theory’ in the philosophy of mathematical
practice, which is important because mathematical practice – like any other practice
– needs to be ‘culturally embedded, manifested, and valued’, to ‘stabilise and repro-
duce’ its norms and values.

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

Work in this area would also contribute to wider disputes on the degree of cross-
cultural consensus about philosophical intuitions. In early cross-cultural experimental
works, Westerners and East Asians were found to have different patterns of epistemic
and semantic intuitions (Weinberg et al. 2001; Machery et al. 2004), challenging the
normativity of those intuitions and posing a serious problem for the standard philo-
sophical approach of using intuition as evidence (Stich 2001). However, these findings
failed to replicate (e.g. Seyedsayamdost 2015; Kim and Yuan 2015), arguably due to
methodological weaknesses: Knobe (2019, 2021) pointed out that the number of Asian
participants in Weinberg et al.’s study was only 24, and Lam (2010) argued that it was
problematic for Machery et al. to present questions to Asian participants in English
instead of their native languages. Machery et al. (2017) recently addressed these meth-
odological limitations by having a larger sample (N = 521) from four different cultural
backgrounds, and using materials written in native languages. Contrary to the early
experimental results, Machery et al. (2017) identified that people from different cultural
backgrounds exhibit similar patterns of epistemic intuitions. Knobe (2019) cited this
result in support of the hypothesis that philosophical intuitions are robust across cul-
tures. However, this position was criticized by Stich and Machery (2022), who argued
that Knobe had presented an unbalanced summary of the literature: although some
studies failed to replicate earlier findings of cross-cultural differences in intuitions,
many such findings have successfully replicated (Stich and Machery 2022, Table 1).
Similar points have been raised in work directly related to aesthetics, in the
more obvious domain of perceptual beauty (Che et al. 2018). Cross-cultural disa-
greement was initially detected by McElroy (1952) and Lawlor (1955), but agree-
ment was found in a series of later investigations (Eysenck and Iwawaki 1971;
Soueif and Eysenck 1971) and in cross-cultural studies on basic visual features
such as symmetry, proportion, curvature, brightness, and contrast (Che et al.
2018). These contrasting empirical results could be influenced not only by the
choice of stimuli but also by the types of judgements, since these studies varied
in asking participants to judge the stimuli in isolation or in comparison with one
another: McElroy and Lawler asked participants to rank an entire set of artworks
presented simultaneously, whereas Eysenck and his collaborators asked par-
ticipants to make comparative or individual judgements. It is certainly possible
that the apparent degree of aesthetic consensus is influenced by methodological
approach, and we pick up this point below.

1.4 Beauty, Epistemology, and Expertise

As noted above, there are debates about the extent to which aesthetics overlaps with
epistemology. If mathematical beauty requires significant mathematical insight,
then recognizing beauty should be impossible for people without adequate training.
This would be consistent with an early study by Dreyfus and Eisenberg (1986), who
designed a set of problems to evoke elegant solutions and found that undergraduates
struggled to come up with such solutions and were unable to distinguish aesthetically
pleasing solutions from others when prompted. Dreyfus and Eisenberg interpreted

13
R. Sa et al.

this as indicating that people need mathematical training beyond undergraduate level
in order to appreciate mathematical beauty. Of course, it could be that Dreyfus and
Eisenberg’s own criteria for elegance or beauty are not widely shared, or that under-
graduates can appreciate beauty only in relatively simple mathematical contexts.
It could also be that mathematicians, who do have the potential to make aesthetic
judgements based on epistemology, do so only partly on that basis. Starikova (2017)
argues in this direction, distinguishing intellectual and perceptual aspects of math-
ematical beauty. She suggests that intellectual beauty is the aesthetic response to
abstract properties of a mathematical object, such as structure or degree of gener-
ality; sufficient proficiency is required to detect and appreciate these. Appreciating
perceptual beauty, on the other hand, does not necessarily require mathematical
understanding. Similarly, Montano (2014) and Pearcy (2020) distinguish the per-
formative appreciation response, which is a reaction of active intellectual engage-
ment, from the basic appreciation response, a passive and automatic reaction. Pearcy
(2020, p.59–60) illustrates this with the example of the physicist Richard Feynman
and his artist friend who could both see a flower as beautiful, but for different rea-
sons: Feynman has a basic appreciation response in visual aesthetics, but a perform-
ative appreciation response in scientific aesthetics, his artist friend vice versa.
These theoretical suggestions are consistent with empirical evidence. Zeki et al.
(2014), for instance, asked 15 mathematicians (postgraduate students and postdoc-
toral researchers) to study 60 equations, rating each for beauty from -5 to 5. After
about 2 to 3 weeks, the mathematicians were asked to re-rate the equations as ugly,
neutral, or beautiful while their brain activity was fMRI-scanned. A few days after
scanning, they were asked to rate their understanding of each equation from 0 to 3.
Zeki et al. found a significant positive correlation between understanding and scan-
time beauty rating, and a significant difference in brain activity in a region associ-
ated with appreciating beauty when participants were viewing equations they rated
as beautiful as opposed to ugly or neutral. The latter was driven by beauty ratings
after accounting for understanding, so there is room for aesthetic judgements to be
based partly on understanding and partly on visual appearance. Consistently with
this interpretation, Zeki et al. also found that 12 non-expert participants (educated
in mathematics only to the age of 16) indicated that they had no understanding for
the vast majority of the equations, but some did give positive beauty ratings for a
minority.
For our purposes, this provides evidence of an imperfect overlap between aes-
thetics and epistemology for experts, but no indication how this develops prior to
expertise or of whether or not there is aesthetic agreement. In fact, although Zeki
et al. found a highly significant positive correlation between pre-scan and scan-time
beauty ratings, the correlation coefficient of r = .612 is some way from perfect, and
some large shifts in ratings were seen between the two times. If mathematicians do
not always agree with themselves, perhaps it is unreasonable to expect them to agree
with one another. The aesthetic judgement of experts and non-experts has been fur-
ther studied by Johnson and Steinerberger (2019) who asked two groups of experts
(mathematicians and mathematics undergraduates) and a group of non-experts to
rate the similarity of mathematical arguments to artworks (paintings and classical

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

music). Perhaps surprisingly, they found that participants could associate each math-
ematical argument to an artwork, with agreement at above chance levels, suggesting
some degree of shared consensus about this kind of aesthetic correspondence.
Using different methods, Hayn-Leichsenring et al. (2021) studied both
undergraduate students and aesthetic agreement. They asked twenty mathematics
undergraduates and twenty undergraduates without university-level mathematical
training to distribute 64 equations into 9 piles ranging from “extremely unaesthetic”
to “extremely aesthetic” with predetermined numbers in each pile to form a normally
distributed pattern. After participants completed their judgements, they were asked
to state which equations they were familiar with, and to indicate the criteria behind
their judgements from options including “meaning”. In line with the works of Zeki
et al. and Johnson and Steinerberger, Hayn-Leichsenring et al. found a positive
relationship between understanding and perceived beauty: in both groups, ratings
were significantly higher for familiar equations. This was more pronounced for the
mathematics undergraduates, who were familiar with more equations and who more
often stated that their aesthetic judgement relied on meaning. This seems to imply that
greater understanding would result in greater aesthetic appreciation in mathematics.
However, an alternative account would be that understanding is merely an essential
pre-condition in making any forms of judgements on equations or proofs. More
investigations are needed to examine how intuitions about mathematical aesthetics are
related to familiarity and understanding.
Hayn-Leichsenring et al. also looked explicitly at simplicity, finding a significant
negative relationship between the number of elements (numbers, letters and
mathematical signs) in an equation and its aesthetic rating for the mathematics
undergraduates but not the other group. They also found that compared to
undergraduates without mathematical training, mathematics undergraduates shared a
higher level of aesthetic agreement.
These results suggest that undergraduates with university-level mathematical
training have attained sufficient proficiency to share a performative appreciation
response to mathematical beauty. And this returns us to questions about methodology.
In some of these empirical studies, it seems that mathematicians do not agree about
beauty as much as traditional philosophical accounts suppose. In others, it seems
that agreement is present even among comparatively inexperienced undergraduates.
We suggest that method might be one reason for this. Notably, in Johnson and
Steinerberger’s study, participants’ aesthetic judgement was conducted through
comparing and contrasting mathematical arguments with artworks. Similarly,
in Hayn-Leichsenring et al.’s study, participants also compared and contrasted
equations for fine-grained aesthetic classification. In both studies, participants’
aesthetic judgements were relative rather than absolute. We believe it is plausible that
mathematicians might have different absolute standards for beauty and thus appear
to disagree when asked for absolute judgements, but might nevertheless agree about
which objects are more or less beautiful. If this is the case, then such agreement is
best sought with methods involving relative judgements. We used one such method,
as described below.

13
R. Sa et al.

2 Methodology: Comparative Judgement

We used a comparative judgement (CJ) approach to measure aesthetic judgments about


mathematical beauty. Under CJ, participants do not use absolute rating scales, but instead
each make multiple pairwise judgements about which of two objects rates more highly in
relation to a given quality. The judgements are then used collectively to construct a scaled
rank order in which each object is assigned a score (Bisson et al. 2016). This approach is
based on the psychological principle that people tend to be better at making relative judg-
ments than at judging one object against a predetermined criterion (Thurstone 1994). This
principle is derived from substantial investigation on human judgement of sensory factors
such as temperature and audio frequency (Laming 2003; Pollack 1952; Thurstone 1928).
Using CJ has two advantages that are specific in our context, First, it does not
require pre-determined criteria for the concept to be measured. Instead, the scores are
directly derived from participants’ pairwise judgements. This characteristic enables an
open-ended approach to measuring concepts that are ambiguous and fuzzy (Bisson
et al. 2016, p. 143), as demonstrated by successful use of CJ in measuring students’
conceptual understanding (Bisson et al. 2016; Jones et al. 2019), proof comprehen-
sion (Davies et al. 2020), and the notion of explanatoriness of proofs (Mejía Ramos
et al. 2021). Here, mathematical beauty is conceptualized as an ambiguous concept
under dispute among philosophers, and CJ has the advantage of not presupposing any
philosophical accounts. Second, CJ directly measures mathematicians’ aesthetic con-
ceptions without using absolute scales. It therefore circumvents subjective perceptions
of such scales, which could potentially obscure agreement (Heine et al. 2002).
Using CJ, we conducted two studies, in both of which participants were asked
to consider pairs of mathematical objects and to judge which is more beautiful. In
Study 1, the objects were equations, and participants were from three demographic
groups: British mathematicians, Chinese mathematicians, and British mathematics
undergraduates. This allowed us to investigate cross-cultural and cross-expertise
(dis)agreement about mathematical beauty. The equations were accompanied by
brief descriptions, and we also considered factors that might potentially affect aes-
thetic judgements: number of characters in the equations as a measure of simplicity,
number of words in the description, and number of mathematicians’ names men-
tioned in the description as a measure of social influence. In Study 2, the objects
were proofs and participants were British mathematicians. This allowed us to inves-
tigate whether aesthetic agreement is contingent upon different types of stimuli.

3 Study 1: Measuring Mathematicians’ and Undergraduates’


Aesthetic Judgements

3.1 Stimuli

The stimuli for this study were chosen from Zeki et al. (2014)’s list of 60 equations; 20
out of the 60 equations were used (selected by taking every third one), along with the
brief descriptions written by Zeki et al. For the Chinese participants, the descriptions were

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

translated into simplified Chinese. The selected equations and their descriptions were for-
matted and uploaded to the online CJ platform No More Marking (https://​www.​nomor​
emark​ing.​com). The 20 equations appear in Table 1 in the Results section (along with
their CJ scores, to be explained below); their descriptions appear in Table 3 the Appendix.
To assess factors that might predict judgements of mathematical beauty, we counted
the number of characters in each equation, the number of words in its description, and
the number of mathematicians’ names mentioned in the description. For the equations,
we counted individual characters ignoring any commas, so that dx dt
and (𝛼 − 𝛽y) have 5
and 6 characters respectively. For the descriptions, we counted words ignoring punc-
tuation and brackets; any mathematical element that appeared within the description
was counted as one word. For the counts for each equation, see again Table 3.

Table 1  The ranking and the β score for each equation, separately for each demographic group
Equation British Mathematicians British Undergraduates Chinese Mathematicians
Ranking Score Ranking Score Ranking Score

1 + ei𝜋 = 0 1 2.391 1 1.347 1 2.032


∫ 𝜕M 𝜔 = ∫ M d𝜔 2 1.147 8 0.336 4 0.689
𝜋2

∑ 1 3 1.110 6 0.513 2 1.212
6
= n2
n=1

a2 + b2 = c2 4 0.764 3 0.889 3 0.833


d x
e = ex 5 0.665 4 0.784 16 –0.598
dx
a + bn =
n cn , n > 2 6 0.602 2 0.973 5 0.645
Δ𝜑 = 0 7 0.523 10 0.187 10 –0.045
e = lim (1 + 1n )
n
8 0.393 7 0.411 7 0.362
n→∞
∫ M KdA + ∫ 𝜕M kg ds = 2𝜋𝜒(M) 9 0.083 18 –1.012 12 –0.169
‖x + y‖ ≤ ‖x‖ + ‖y‖ 10 –0.046 5 0.755 6 0.366
A = ∫ 𝜎(A) 𝜆dE𝜆 11 –0.196 13 –0.256 15 –0.489
32 + ­42 = ­52 12 –0.346 9 0.303 9 0.108
∞ �
∏ ∞
� ∑ 13 –0.461 15 –0.445 14 –0.277
1 + xk = p(x)xn
k=0 n=0

f (x) = ∫

− y)f (y)dy
−∞
𝛿(x 14 –0.482 11 0.074 11 –0.143
∑∞
15 –0.607 14 –0.355 8 0.287
1 = (𝜁 (n) − 1)
n=2

16 –0.713 16 –0.741 18 –0.828


n
𝜋2
Vn (r) = Γ( n2 +1)
rn

1

∑ 𝜇(n) 17 –0.930 20 –1.624 13 –0.212
𝜁 (s)
= ns
, s𝜖ℂ, Re(s) >1
n=1
dx
d
= x(𝛼 − 𝛽y), dy
dt
= −y(𝛾 − 𝛿x) 18 –1.048 12 –0.033 19 –0.964
T = de + 𝜔 ∧ e,R = d𝜔 + 𝜔 ∧ 𝜔 19 –1.387 17 –0.765 17 –0.729
R𝛼𝛽[𝛾𝛿;𝜆] = 0 20 –1.461 19 –1.341 20 –2.081

13
R. Sa et al.

3.2 Participants and Procedure

British mathematicians and British undergraduates were recruited via an invitation


email sent to two UK mathematics departments’ mailing lists. Chinese mathemati-
cians were recruited by the same translated invitation email which was sent to the
mailing addresses of various mathematics departments in China. The email contained
a brief introduction about the research, specific information on what was involved in
this study, and a web link to enter the study. Participants who entered the study were
assured that it was ethically approved by Loughborough University and that none of
their personal data would be collected. Mathematician participants were, however,
asked to select their AMS subject classification, their career stage and their number of
years working as a mathematician. British undergraduate participants were asked to
state their current subject year of study. All then read these instructions:
“We are interested in understanding what mathematicians (undergraduates)
mean when they say that certain mathematical objects are “beautiful”. To
this end, we are going to ask you about the beauty of various mathematical
equations. You will be shown pairs of different equations. Every time you
see a pair, we will ask you to choose which equation you think is the most
beautiful. Once you have started the judging session…Simply look at the
two equations and choose which one you think is more beautiful by clicking
either ‘Left’ or ‘Right’. If you are unsure, just go with your instinct.”
Each participant was asked to complete 20 judgements of randomly generated
paired equations, with no time limit. In total, 24 British mathematicians com-
pleted 480 judgements, 24 Chinese mathematicians completed 480 completed
judgements, and 81 British undergraduates completed 1620 judgements.

3.3 Results

3.3.1 Is There Aesthetic Agreement Among British Mathematicians, Chinese


Mathematicians, and British Undergraduates?

For each demographic group, we used the Bradley-Terry Model, which assigns each
equation i a parameter 𝛽i to estimate its beauty. It does this via a process based on using
the judgements to iteratively update the probability that equation i is judged to be more
beautiful than equation j (Bradley and Terry 1952). To check that this yielded meaning-
ful scores, we then calculated inter-rater reliability (IRR) for each demographic group.
We randomly split each group into subgroups of 12, splitting the mathematician groups
evenly and randomly selecting two groups of 12 from among the undergraduates. We
then calculated new estimates of each equation’s aesthetic quality from each subgroup’s
judgements. This process was repeated 1000 times to calculate the average Pearson cor-
relation coefficient between the scores for the two subgroups.
The IRR of the British mathematicians’ judgements was r = 0.721, the IRR of
the British undergraduates’ judgements was r = 0.701, and the IRR of the Chinese
mathematicians’ judgements was r = .722. These results indicate relatively consistent

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

aesthetic agreement within each demographic group: the CJ approach does detect
agreement based on relative judgements for all three groups. We thus treat the equa-
tion scores for the complete groups as reliable, and these scores are shown in Table 1,
ordered from most to least beautiful by the British mathematicians’ rankings.

3.3.2 Is There Cross‑Cultural Agreement?

A first indication of agreement not just within but across the demographic groups
is visible in the rankings and scores in Table 1. Both the British and the Chinese
mathematicians judged Euler’s identity the most beautiful equation and the Sec-
ond Bianchi Identity the least beautiful. Moreover, although the rankings do not
match perfectly, equations judged more beautiful by one group were generally

3
r=0.846
Chinese Mathematicians' Perceived Aesthetics

1
2

11

1 6
20 12

9 4
17
10
0 3 5 2
19
13
18
8
14
15
7
1

2 16

3
2 1 0 1 2 3
British Mathematicians' Perceived Aesthetics
Fig. 1  The correlation between CJ scores derived from British mathematicians’ and Chinese mathemati-
cians’ aesthetic judgements. Error bars show ±1 standard error

13
R. Sa et al.

judged more beautiful by the other. This is reflected in a statistical analysis: there
is a significant and strong positive correlation between the two sets of scores
r = .846, 95% CI[.645, .937]; see Fig. 1. At least for equations, it seems, relative
mathematical beauty is judged fairly consistently across these two cultures.

3.3.3 Is There Cross‑Expertise Agreement?

A first indication of agreement across expertise levels is also visible in Table 1. The Brit-
ish undergraduates, like both groups of mathematicians, judged Euler’s identity the most
beautiful equation. They also, like the Chinese mathematicians, broadly agreed with
the British mathematicians: again we found a significant and strong positive correlation
between the two sets of scores r = .781, 95% CI[.518, .909]; see Fig. 2. Again, at least

2
r=0.781
British Undergraduates' Perceived Aesthetics

1 20
6
9 8

11
4
10 12
19
5
0 7

18
17
13

14 15

2
1
16

2
2 1 0 1 2 3
British Mathematicians' Perceived Aesthetics
Fig. 2  The correlation between CJ scores derived from British mathematicians’ and British undergradu-
ates’ aesthetic judgments. Error bars show ±1 standard error

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

Table 2  Unstandardized Predictor British mathema- British under- Chinese mathema-


regression coefficients (Bs) ticians B graduates B ticians B
predicting perceived aesthetics
for British mathematicians, Number of Characters –0.0890** –0.0676* –0.0548
British undergraduates, and Number of Names 0.1754 -0.1367 0.1698
Chinese mathematicians Number of Words 0.0135 0.0164 0.0188
R2 0.3730 0.4450 0.2120

*p < .05, **p < .01

for equations, it seems that relative mathematical beauty is judged similarly by British
undergraduate mathematics students and more experienced mathematicians.

3.3.4 What Predicts Judgements of Beauty?

Finally for this study, Table 1 suggests that characteristics of the equations might predict
judgements of beauty: equations judged more beautiful tend to be shorter. To formally
investigate this, along with our other possible predictors, we conducted linear regression
analyses, separately for each group, predicting CJ scores from the number of characters in
the equations and the numbers of words and mathematicians’ names in the descriptions.
The results appear in Table 2. For no group did either number of words or num-
ber of names predict the beauty scores. Although, in line with earlier studies (Wells
1990), it seems that everyone thinks Euler’s identity is beautiful, it appears unlikely
that this is due to a generally positive view of equations with names attached (nota-
bly, our measure does not capture relative renown). It could well be the case, how-
ever, that its perceived beauty is related to its simplicity: for both the British math-
ematicians and the British undergraduates, the number of characters in an equation
did significantly predict beauty score ( p = .008 and p = .010 respectively). To con-
textualize these estimates, for the mathematicians, an extra 10 characters in an equa-
tion predicted a drop in beauty score of 0.89, nearly a quarter of the overall range
from 2.390 to -1.460; for British undergraduates, it predicted a drop of 0.676 (score
range 1.347 to -1.623). For Chinese mathematicians, the number of characters was
not a significant predictor of beauty score ( p = .087), but the analysis nevertheless
indicated a similar predictive pattern compared to the previous two demographic
groups. Number of characters in an equation is clearly a crude measure of simplic-
ity, but the direction of these results is in line with philosophical claims that simplic-
ity is related to mathematical beauty.

4 Study 2: Measuring Mathematicians’ Aesthetic Judgements


about Proofs

Study 1 found not only consistent aesthetic judgements within our demographic
groups of British mathematicians, Chinese mathematicians and British under-
graduates, but also agreement across culture and expertise. These findings

13
R. Sa et al.

contrast with some earlier empirical work (Wells 1990; Inglis and Aberdein
2016, 2020), which found more disagreement than might have been expected
based on traditional accounts. One possible explanation was suggested above:
ratings against absolute scales might fail to capture underlying consensus on
relative mathematical beauty. However, it could also be that level of consen-
sus is affected by the type of stimuli: Inglis and Aberdein (2016, 2020), for
instance, found disagreement on proofs rather than equations. Hence, Study 2
aimed to measure mathematicians’ aesthetic agreement in relation to proofs,
to examine whether a change to different type of stimuli would influence the
agreement found in Study 1.

4.1 Stimuli

Eight proofs were employed in Study 2 (we used fewer proofs than equations for
the obvious reason that these take longer to read). Five proofs were selected from
Aigner and Ziegler’s (2010) collection of Proofs from The Book, two were from
Pearcy’s (2020) Mathematical Beauty, and one was from Nelsen’s (2000) Proofs
Without Words II: More Exercises in Visual Thinking. All eight proofs stimuli
appear in Table 4 in the Appendix.

4.2 Participants and Procedure

Thirty-two mathematicians were recruited by an invitation sent to the mailing


list of a UK based mathematics department not already contacted in relation to
Study 1. Participants were asked to conduct eight pairwise judgments, with the
prompt ‘Which proof is more beautiful?’. One of the 32 mathematicians was
excluded from the analysis because they did not complete their judgements.
The remaining 31 participants in total completed 248 pairwise judgements.

4.3 Results: Beauty in Proofs

Following the same procedure as in Study 1, we first considered reliabil-


ity, finding an IRR of r = .643. This is slightly lower than the IRRs found for
the equations in Study 1, but still means that there was considerable agree-
ment about which proofs were more beautiful. Subsequently, the total 248
aesthetic judgments of proofs were analyzed using the Bradley-Terry Model,
which resulted in a scaled rank order in which Euclid’s proof of the infini-
tude of the primes was judged the most beautiful and an algebraic proof that
p� (x)2 ≥ p(x)p�� (x) for all x ∈ ℝ was judged the least beautiful. For proofs, rank-
ings and scores, see Fig. 3 and Table 4 in the Appendix.
In sum, Study 2 found similar results to Study 1. Specifically, mathemati-
cians’ level of aesthetic consensus was not substantially affected by asking
them to consider proofs rather than equations. This makes us more confident
that the agreement in Study 1 is not contingent simply upon the fact that equa-
tions are simpler objects. Rather, agreement is found for proofs as well.

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

Proof 1

Proof 2

Proof 3

Proof 4

Proof 5

Proof 6

Proof 7

Proof 8

1.0 0.5 0 0.5 1.0 1.5


Mathematicians' Percevied Aesthetics of the Eight Proofs (Parameter Values)

Fig. 3  The parameter values of British mathematicians’ aesthetic judgements of proofs

5 Discussion

5.1 Summary

The studies in this paper investigated whether mathematicians agree about math-
ematical beauty. Using comparative judgement methods, Study 1 found agreement
about the aesthetics of equations both within and across three demographic groups:
British mathematicians, Chinese mathematicians, and British undergraduate math-
ematics students. It also found that simplicity – operationalized by counting charac-
ters in each equation – predicted collective judgements of beauty. Study 2 broadened
the range of stimuli, finding a similar level of between-participant agreement among
British mathematicians about the aesthetics of proofs.
Together, these studies constitute evidence that relative judgements about beauty
in mathematics are fairly stable and robust within and across cultures, and that
undergraduates have learned enough to be able to judge beauty in a way similar
to expert mathematicians, at least for the equations we considered. In this last sec-
tion, we discuss the implications of these findings for views on beauty in relation to
agreement and simplicity, to cross-cultural studies, and to epistemology; throughout,
we consider issues of methodology in experimental philosophy.

5.2 Aesthetic Agreement and Simplicity

Two of the most interesting results of this paper are the level of aesthetic agreement
found and the result that short equations tend to be judged more beautiful. Both find-
ings are in line with traditional accounts of mathematical beauty, but they go against
prevailing trends in recent empirical work, which has found aesthetic disagreement
among mathematicians (Wells 1990; Inglis and Aberdein 2016, 2020) and a lack
of relationship between beauty and simplicity (Inglis and Aberdein 2015). We sug-
gest that, in both cases, methodological factors might account for these apparent
contradictions.

13
R. Sa et al.

Regarding agreement, we have discussed two methodological differences across


studies: the types of stimuli and the method for collecting aesthetic judgments. The
stimuli in many of the studies that have found evidence of aesthetic disagreement
were proofs, whether proofs that the participants called to mind (Inglis & Aberdein
2015) or proofs explicitly presented for evaluation (Inglis & Aberdein 2016, 2020).
In Study 1, our work followed a different trend in the literature, using equations (cf.
Hayn-Leichsenring et al. 2021). Clearly equations and proofs differ enough that they
could prompt different degrees of consensus. It is possible that mathematicians tend
to agree on shorter objects such as equations, but disagree on more complex objects
such as proofs. However, when we examined this potential explanation in Study 2,
we found relatively consistent between-participant aesthetic agreement about proofs
too. No doubt different types of mathematical objects influence aesthetic judgements
to some degree, but our evidence suggests that consensus in aesthetic intuition is not
highly contingent upon the type of stimuli.
The other methodological difference is that in most studies that have reported
aesthetic disagreement, mathematicians’ aesthetic judgements were measured on
absolute scales, whereas we used comparative judgement. Since CJ avoids potential
subjective interpretations of absolute scales, it is more akin to the sorting method
used in Hayn-Leichsenring et al.’s (2021) study. That Hayn-Leichsenring et al. also
found agreement suggests that when relative judgements are used to measure math-
ematicians’ sense of aesthetics, underlying agreement can be detected. Hence the
disagreement found in Wells’ (1990), and Inglis and Aberdein’s studies (2016, 2020)
could be a result of mathematicians not sharing the same standards in relation to
absolute scales, rather than of a fundamental aesthetic dispute.
Regarding simplicity, we found that shorter equations tended to be judged more
beautiful by British mathematicians and undergraduates, with a trend in the same
direction for Chinese mathematicians. This, too, is consistent with traditional philo-
sophical accounts and with Hayn-Leichsenring et al.’s (2021) study of the aesthetic
evaluation of equations, but different from earlier empirical work that did not find
such an association (Inglis and Aberdein 2015). A methodological reason for this
difference could be that simplicity in our paper was measured through the admittedly
crude means of counting the number of characters in each equation, whereas Inglis
and Aberdein measured it through mathematicians’ use of the adjective of ‘simple’
in proof appraisal. The latter clearly allows for more sophisticated judgements, but it
also introduces ambiguity regarding whether it was numerical, explanatory, logical
or some other form of simplicity that these mathematicians had in mind. Certainly,
further empirical studies on this aesthetic ideal might usefully unpack the notion of
simplicity in more detail.

5.3 Cultures, Expertise and Epistemology

Our first study deliberately examined judgements of beauty from multiple demo-
graphic groups, answering calls to consider culture in mathematical practice (Larvor
2016) and addressing the issue of what expertise is required to exercise aesthetic

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

judgement. Our finding of a strong degree of aesthetic consensus across the Brit-
ish and Chinese groups suggests that mathematicians’ aesthetic judgements are not
strongly influenced by cultural differences. This is consistent with the moderate aes-
thetic agreement on basic visual properties found elsewhere in the field of cross-
cultural empirical aesthetics (Che et al. 2018), and is good news for those inclined
towards aesthetic realism: although agreement among mathematicians does not
imply that mathematical beauty is objective or that aesthetic intuitions can be nor-
matively correct, it provides no reason to reject that position.
Another way of accounting for our finding of aesthetic consensus across
the British and Chinese groups would be to suggest that the two groups share a
similar mathematical culture. In other words, perhaps mathematics is so inter-
connected in the modern world, it no longer makes sense (if it ever did) to talk
about distinct mathematical cultures. We doubt that this is the case. While it is
certainly true that there has been a great deal of interaction between Western
and Chinese mathematics, both historically and today, this has led to concerted
efforts by some Chinese mathematicians to try to preserve what they consider
to be distinctive about Chinese mathematics. For instance, following the arrival
in China of Jesuit missionaries with Western mathematical texts in the late sev-
enteenth century, political movements such as “Chinese Origins of Western
Science” were founded. These aimed to minimize the significance of Western
influence in the development of Chinese mathematics by valuing and maintain-
ing its traditional culture (Bréard 2019, p.82).
The aim to preserve Chinese cultural identity in mathematics was again found
during the early development of modern mathematics in China. By the 1930s, the
first group of mathematics departments were founded in Chinese universities, which
led to exchanges with Western institutions. For instance, mathematicians such as
Bertrand Russell and William F. Osgood visited Peking University during the 1930s,
and their visits were significantly valued by the Chinese mathematics community
(Zong 2020). But a number of well-respected Chinese mathematicians responded
by emphasising the need to preserve the Chinese approach to mathematics. For
example, Shiing-Shen Chern advocated that “Chinese mathematics must be on the
same level as its Western counterpart, though not necessarily bending its effect in
the same direction” (Hudecek 2014, p.166). Chern’s student Wu Wen Tsun noted
that “there is an essentially Chinese mathematical style, and that Chinese mathema-
ticians have a patriotic duty to study it and build upon it” (Hudecek 2014, p.161).
After Wu returned to China from France in the 1951, he focused on promoting the
ancient Chinese style of mathematics characterises by algorithms and the “mecha-
nisation of mathematics” (Hudecek 2012). In sum, there are reasons to suppose that
distinctive cultural aspects of Chinese mathematics were, and still are, valued by
Chinese mathematicians, despite the international mobility that characterises mod-
ern academia.
The fact that the way mathematics is taught in China contrasts to many Western
countries gives us further reasons to suppose that Chinese and Western mathematical
practices do not share identical cultural norms. Recent decades have seen the devel-
opment of international comparison studies where student achievement is compared

13
R. Sa et al.

between educational jurisdictions. These have tended to find that Chinese students,
and indeed students in the Pacific rim more generally, tend to outperform Western
students of the same age in mathematics (Fan and Zhu 2004). This, in turn, has led
to systematic investigations into how typical pedagogy in Chinese classrooms differs
from typical pedagogy in Western classrooms (Fan et al. 2004). A common obser-
vation is that mathematics education in China tends to place a relatively stronger
emphasis on the acquisition of mathematical content through rote learning and hard
work than is normal in the West (Leung 2001). Again, these findings support the
view that Chinese and Western mathematical cultures are not identical in general,
despite our findings that Chinese and British mathematicians’ aesthetic tastes appear
to be largely shared.
Moreover, we have narrowed down the way in which other social influences
might affect judgements about beauty: if social conformity plays a role in math-
ematicians’ aesthetic judgements, this is not visible in effects of the number of
influential names attached to an equation. That said, our findings cannot in this
case be said to contradict those of Inglis and Aberdein (2020): Euler’s identity,
with its longstanding aesthetic status, was consistently judged more beautiful
than the rest of our stimuli.
With regard to expertise, we found not only that mathematics undergradu-
ates are capable of making collectively consistent aesthetic judgements, but
also that they seem to share aesthetic criteria with mathematicians. This pro-
vides evidence against the claims of Hardy that judging mathematical beauty
requires advanced mathematical proficiency, at least as applies to equations.
However, the nature of the criteria remains unclear. Starikova (2017) or Pearcy
(2020) could argue that this cross-expertise agreement might be derived from
either perceptual or basic appreciation responses: perhaps both mathemati-
cians and students have similar responses to the visual appearance of the equa-
tions, and only mathematicians go beyond this. Taking our work in conjunction
with Johnson and Steinerberger (2019) and Hayn-Leichsenring et al.’s (2021),
however, we consider it more likely that epistemology plays a role, that under-
graduates have developed sufficient proficiency to engage an intellectual or
performative appreciation response at a level that might not match that of pro-
fessional mathematicians but does reflect shared values beyond those acces-
sible to the general population. In addition, since our stimuli includes some
famous equations – such as Euler’s identity, the Pythagorean theorem and Fer-
mat’s last theorem – the mere-exposure effect could be an alternative explana-
tion of the aesthetic agreement that we have found between mathematicians and
undergraduates. However, since we did not empirically measure participants’
familiarity with each equation, we cannot test this hypothesis. Further work
that directly measures how familiar mathematicians are with stimuli such as
ours would be worthwhile.
Finally, we highlight that our use of a comparative judgement method might
be useful technique more generally in experimental philosophy. A common
goal of experimental philosophers is to empirically assess philosophical intui-
tions (e.g., Heintz and Taraborelli 2010). The psychophysics literature has estab-
lished that humans are more reliable at making judgements of physical properties

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

such as height, weight and brightness when asked to compare stimuli rather than
judge them in isolation. Our findings suggest that the same may be true when par-
ticipants are asked to make philosophical judgements. If this conclusion is correct
then the method of comparative judgement might be widely useful to experimental
philosophers.
To conclude, we stress that the conflicting empirical findings about aesthetic
agreement in mathematics echo the broader evolution of experimental philosophy.
Although this paper’s finding of cross-cultural aesthetic agreement is consistent with
stability of philosophical intuitions found in the more recent works of experimental
philosophy, this does not mean that one should disregard findings to the contrary.
Rather, it highlights the degree of complexity in constructing measures to operation-
alize the relevant constructs. This paper’s findings that aesthetic judgments in math-
ematics are relatively stable and robust across expertise and cultures suggest that
empirical findings of aesthetic disagreement based on absolute scales do not paint a
full picture of the nature of mathematical beauty. As Knobe (2019) has suggested, it
is important to seek that full picture, which demands triangulation (Löwe and Kerk-
hove 2019). In this case, investigations might profitably work towards directly com-
paring absolute with relative judgement approaches, and towards developing more
sophisticated operationalizations of simplicity and understanding. Our work sug-
gests that more nuanced accounts might successfully marry empirical findings with
traditional accounts of mathematical beauty.

13
Appendix
Table 3  Equation stimuli

13
Stimuli ID Equations Description Characters Names Words

10 32 + 42 = 52 Pythagoras’s theorem for a 3: 4: 5 triangle 8 1 6



11 𝜋2 1 The Basel problem, set as a challenge by Jakob Bernoulli in 1689 14 3 18
=

6 n2
n=1 and solved by Euler in 1735
12 ∫𝜕M 𝜔 = ∫M d𝜔 Stoke’s theorem states that the integral of a differential form 𝜔 9 1 34
over the boundary of some orientable manifold M is equal to the
integral of its exterior derivative d𝜔 over the whole of M

13 An equation due to Euler: on the left hand side we have an infinite 23 1 42
1 + xk = p(x)xn
∞ �
∏ � ∑
k=0 n=0 product and on the right hand side appears a power series where
p(n) denotes the number of all possible representations of n as a
sum of natural numbers
14 T = de + 𝜔 ∧ e, R = d𝜔 + 𝜔 ∧ 𝜔 Cartan structural equations, where e is the frame field, omega the 16 1 22
connection form, T the torsion form and R the curvature form
n
15 𝜋2 Volume of an n-dimensional sphere 21 0 5
Vn (r) = r( 2n +1)
rn

16 R𝛼𝛽[𝛾𝛿;𝜆] = 0 Second Bianchi identity of the Riemann tensor 10 2 7



17 The integer 1 expressed as an infinite series involving the Rie- 15 1 13
1 = (𝜁 (n) − 1)

n=2 mann zeta function
18 A = ∫ 𝜎(A) 𝜆dE𝜆 A formulation of the spectral theorem expresses the operator as an 11 0 26
integral of the coordinate function over the operator’s spectrum
with respect to a projection valued measure
19 Δ𝜑 = 0 Laplace equation 4 1 2
1 1+ ei𝜋 =0 Euler’s identity links 5 fundamental mathematical constants with 7 1 15
three basic arithmetic operations each occurring once
20 an + bn = cn , n > 2 Fermat’s Last Theorem states that no three positive integers a, b, and c 11 1 26
can satisfy this equation for any integer value of n greater than two
R. Sa et al.
Table 3  (continued)
Stimuli ID Equations Description Characters Names Words

2 ∫ M KdA + ∫ 𝜕M kg ds = 2𝜋𝜒(M) The Gauss-Bonnet theorem connects the geometry of surfaces 20 3 14


(curvature) to their topology (Euler characteristic)

3 1 𝜇(n) The reciprocal of the zeta function can be expressed as a Dirichlet 29 2 18
= , s ∈ ℂ, Re(s) > 1

𝜁 (n) ns
n=1 series over the Möbius function μ(n)
n
4 e = lim (1 + 1n ) An identity for Euler’s number e 14 1 6
n→∞

5 f (x) = ∫ −∞ 𝛿(x − y)f (y)dy Identity making use of the Dirac delta function 21 1 8
6 a2 + b2 = c2 Pythagoras’ theorem: In any right-angled triangle, the area of the 8 1 48
square whose side is the hypotenuse (the side opposite the right
angle) is equal to the sum of the areas of the squares whose
sides are the two legs (the two sides that meet at a right angle)
dx dy
7
dt
= x(𝛼 − 𝛽y), dt
= −y(𝛾 − 𝛿x) Lotka-Volterra equations (predator–prey equations), are a pair of 27 2 32
first-order, non-linear, di↵erential equations used to describe
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

the dynamics of biological systems in which two species inter-


act, one a predator and one its prey
d x
8
dx
e = ex The derivative of an exponential is an exponential 9 0 8
9 ‖x + y‖ ≤ ‖x‖ + ‖y‖ Triangle inequality for a normed vector space, the norm of the 13 0 30
sum of two vectors is at most as large as the sum of the norms
of the two vectors

13
R. Sa et al.

Table 4  Proof ranking


Stimuli ID Proof Ranking Score

1 1 1.132

2 2 0.444

3 3 0.304

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

Table 4  (continued)
4 4 0.185

5 5 0.012

13
R. Sa et al.

Table 4  (continued)
6 6 -0.569

7 7 -0.678

8 8 -0.830

Table 3Table 4

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

Acknowledgements Many thanks to Dave Sirl, Ouhao Chen, Michael Barany, Andrew Aberdein,
Brendan Larvor, Paola Iannone, Paul Hasselkuß, two anonymous reviewers, and attendees at the Novem-
bertagung for helpful discussions about this work.

Declarations
Conflict of Interest None.

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License,
which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as
you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Com-
mons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article
are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the
material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is
not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission
directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://​creat​iveco​mmons.​org/​licen​
ses/​by/4.​0/.

References
Aigner, M., and G.M. Ziegler. 2010. Proofs from THE BOOK, 4th ed. Springer.
Alexanderson, G.L. 1981. An interview with Paul Erdős. The Two-Year College Mathematics Journal 12
(4): 249–259.
Berghaus, G. 1992. Neoplatonic and Pythagorean notions of world harmony and unity and their influence
on Renaissance dance theory. Dance Research: The Journal of the Society for Dance Research 10
(2): 43–70.
Bisson, M.-J., C. Gilmore, M. Inglis, and I. Jones. 2016. Measuring conceptual understanding using com-
parative judgement. International Journal of Research in Undergraduate Mathematics Education 2
(2): 141–164. https://​doi.​org/​10.​1007/​s40753-​016-​0024-3.
Bradley, R., and M. Terry. 1952. Rank analysis of incomplete block designs the method of paired com-
parisons. Biometrika 39: 324–345.
Bréard, A. 2019. Nine Chapters on Mathematical Modernity: Essay on the global historical entangle-
ments of the science of numbers in China, 1st ed. Cham: Springer.
Che, J., Sun, X., Gallardo, V., & Nadal, M. 2018. Cross-cultural empirical aesthetics. In J. Christensen,
A. Gomila, & V. Walsh (Ed.), The arts and the brain: Psychology and physiology beyond pleasure:
Volume 237(Progress in Brain Research) (Vol. 237, pp. 77–103). Elsevier B.V.
Cherniwchan, C., Ghassemi, A., and J. Keating. 2010. Is a mathematical proof beautiful? Mathematical
ethnographies project. [Video]. YouTube. https://​www.​youtu​be.​com/​watch?v=​tANB6​hXmY7U.
Cova, F., and N. Pain. 2012. Can folk aesthetics ground aesthetic realism? The Monist 95 (2): 241–263.
Davies, B., L. Alcock, and I. Jones. 2020. Comparative judgement, proof summaries and proof compre-
hension. Educational Studies in Mathematics 105 (2): 181–197.
Dreyfus, T., and T. Eisenberg. 1986. On the aesthetics of mathematical thought. For the Learning of
Mathematics 6 (1): 2–10.
DutilhNovaes, C. 2019. The beauty (?) of mathematical proofs. In Advances in experimental philosophy
of logic and mathematics, ed. A. Aberdein and M. Inglis, 63–94. Bloomsbury.
Erdős, P. 1983. Combinatorial problems in geometry. Mathematical Chronicle 12 (1): 35–54.
Eysenck, H.J., and S. Iwawaki. 1971. Cultural relativity in aesthetic judgements: An empirical study. Per-
ceptual and Motor Skills 32 (3): 817–818.
Fan, L., and Y. Zhu. 2004. How have Chinese student performed in mathematics? A perspective from
large-scale international mathematics comparisions. In How Chinese learn mathematics: Perspec-
tive from insiders, eds. L. Fan, W. Ngai-Ying, C. Jinfa, & Li. Shiqi, 3–26. World Scientific.
Fan, L., Wong, N-Y., Cai, J., and S. Li. 2004. How Chinese learn mathematics: Perspectives . In How
Chinese learn mathematics: Perspective from insiders, eds. L. Fan, W. Ngai-Ying, C. Jinfa, & Li.
Shiqi, pp. vii–xii. World Scientific.
Hardy, G. 1940. A Mathematician’s Apology, 1st ed. Cambridge University Press.

13
R. Sa et al.

Hayn-Leichsenring, G., O. Vartanian, and A. Chatterjee. 2021. The role of expertise in the aesthetic eval-
uation of mathematical equations. Psychological Research Psychologische Forschung. https://​doi.​
org/​10.​1007/​s00426-​021-​01592-5.
Heine, S.J., D.R. Lehman, K. Peng, and J. Greenholtz. 2002. What’s wrong with cross-cultural com-
parisons of subjective likert scales?: The reference-group effect. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology 82 (6): 903–918.
Heintz, C., and D. Taraborelli. 2010. Editorial: Folk epistemology. The cognitive bases of epistemic eval-
uation. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (4): 477–482.
Hudecek, J. 2012. Ancient Chinese mathematics in action: Wu Wen-Tsun’s nationalist historicism after
the cultural revolution. East Asian Science, Technology and Society: An International Journal 6 (1):
41–64.
Hudecek, J. 2014. Reviving ancient Chinese mathematics: Mathematics, history and politcs in the work of
Wu Wen-Tsun, 1st ed. Springer.
Inglis, M., and A. Aberdein. 2015. Beauty is not simplicity: An analysis of mathematicians’ proof
appraisals. Philosophia Mathematica 23 (1): 87–109.
Inglis, M., and A. Aberdein. 2016. Diversity in proof appraisal. In Mathematical cultures: The London
meetings 2012–2014, ed. B. Larvor, 163–179. Springer.
Inglis, M., and A. Aberdein. 2020. Are aesthetic judgements purely aesthetic? Testing the Social Con-
formity Account. ZDM 52 (6): 1127–1136.
Johnson, S.G.B., and S. Steinerberger. 2019. Intuitions about mathematical beauty: A case study in the
aesthetic experience of ideas. Cognition 189: 242–259.
Jones, I., M. Bisson, C. Gilmore, and M. Inglis. 2019. Measuring conceptual understanding in ran-
domised controlled trials: Can comparative judgement help? British Educational Research Journal
45 (3): 662–680.
Kim, M., & Yuan, Y. (2015). No cross-cultural differences in Gettier car case intuition: A replication
study of Weinberg et al. 2001. Episteme 12(3):355–361.
Knobe, J. 2007. Experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass 2 (1): 81–92.
Knobe, J. 2019. Philosophical intuitions are surprisingly robust across demographic differences. Episte-
mology & Philosophy of Science 56 (2): 29–36.
Knobe, J. 2021. Philosophical intuitions are surprisingly stable across both demographic groups and situ-
ations. Filozofia Nauki 29(2): 11-76
Lam, B. 2010. Are Cantonese-speakers really descriptivists? Revisiting cross-cultural semantics. Cogni-
tion 115(2): 320–329.
Laming, D. 2003. Human Judgment: The eye of the beholder, 1st ed. CENGAGE Learning.
Larvor, B. 2016. What are mathematical cultures? In Cultures of mathematics and logic, ed. S. Ju, B.
Löwe, T. Müller, and X. Yun, 1–22. Birkhäuser.
Lawlor, M. 1955. Cultural influences on preference for designs. The Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology 51 (3): 690–692.
Leung, F.K.S. 2001. In search of an east Asian identity in mathematics education. Education Studies in
Mathematics 47(1): 35–51.
Löwe, B., and B. Van Kerkhove. 2019. Methodological triangulation in empirical philosophy (of math-
ematics). In Advances in experimental philosophy of logic and mathematics, ed. A. Aberdein and M.
Inglis, 15–37. Bloomsbury.
Machery, E., R. Mallon, S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2004. Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition 92 (3):
B1–B12.
Machery, E., S. Stich, D. Rose, A. Chatterjee, K. Karasawa, N. Struchiner, and T. Hashinmoto. 2017. Get-
tier Across Cultuers. Noûs 51 (3): 645–664.
McAllister, J. W. 1996. Beauty and revolution in science. New York: Cornell University Press.
McAllister, J.W. 2005. Mathematical beauty and the evolution of the standards of mathematical proof. In
The Visual Mind II, ed. M. Emmer, 15–34. The MIT Press.
McElroy, W. 1952. Aesthetic appreciation in Aborigines of Arnhem Land: A comparative experimental
study. Oceania 23 (2): 81–95.
Mejía Ramos, J., T. Evans, C. Rittberg, and M. Inglis. 2021. Mathematicians’ assessments of the explana-
tory value of proofs. Axiomathes 31 (5): 575–599.
Montano, U. 2014. Explaining beauty in mathematics: An aesthetic theory of mathematics, 1st ed. Cham:
Springer.
Nelsen, R.B. 2000. Proofs without words II: More exercises in visual thinking, 1st ed. The Mathematical
Association of America.

13
Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?

Pearcy, D. 2020. Mathematical beauty: What is mathematical beauty and can anyone experience it?, 1st
ed. John Catt Educational.
Plato. 1993. Philebus. Hackett Publishing Company.
Pollack, I. 1952. The information of elementary auditory displays. Journal of the Acoustical Society of
America 24 (1): 745–749.
Rota, G.-C. 1997. The phenomenology of mathematical beauty. Synthese 111 (2): 171–182.
Seyedsayamdost, H. 2015. On normativity and epistemic intuitions: Failure of replication. Episteme 12
(1): 95–116.
Simoniti, V. 2017. Aesthetic properties as powers. European Journal of Philosophy 25 (4): 1434–1453.
Sinclair, N., and D. Pimm. 2006. A historical gaze at the mathematical aesthetic. In Mathematics and the
aesthetic: New approaches to an ancient affinity, ed. N. Sinclair, D. Pimm, and W. Higginson, 1–17.
Springer.
Soueif, M., and H. Eysenck. 1971. Cultural differences in aesthetic preferences. International Journal of
Psychology 6 (4): 293–298.
Starikova, I. 2017. Aesthetic preferences in mathematics: A case study. Philosophia Mathematica 26 (2):
161–183.
Stich, S. 2001. Plato’s method meets cognitive science. Free Inquiry 21 (2): 36–38.
Stich, S., and E. Machery. 2022. Demographic Differences in Philosophical Intuition: A reply to Joshua
Knobe. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. https://​doi.​org/​10.​1007/​s13164-​021-​00609-7.
Tatarkiewicz, W. 1963. Objectivity and subjectivity in the history of aesthetics. Philosophy and Phenom-
enological Research 24 (2): 157–173.
Thurstone, L. 1928. Attitudes can be measured. The American Journal of Sociology 33 (4): 529–554.
Thurstone, L. 1994. A law of comparative judgement. Psychological Review 101 (2): 266–270.
Todd, C. 2008. Unmasking the truth beneath the beauty: Why the supposed aesthetic judgements made in
science may not be aesthetic at all. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (1): 61–79.
Weinberg, J., S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2001. Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics
29 (1): 429–460.
Wells, D. 1990. Are these the most beautiful? The Mathematical Intelligencer 12 (3): 37–41.
Zajonc, R.B. 2001. Mere Exposure: A gateway to the subliminal. Current Directions in Psychological
Science 10 (6): 224–228.
Zeki, S., J.P. Romaya, D.T. Benincasa, and M. Atiyah. 2014. The experience of mathematical beauty and
its neural correlates. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8 (1): 1–12.
Zong, C. 2020. Blaschke, Osgood, Wiener, Hadamard and the early development of modern mathematics
in China. 1-8. https://​doi.​org/​10.​48550/​arXiv.​2009.​13688

Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps
and institutional affiliations.

13

You might also like