Penner 183to197
Penner 183to197
Penner 183to197
Introduction
The aim of this Part of the book is to explore three important steps in the development
of the liberal social contract tradition of justifying the State and its law. In the previous
two chapters we discussed two early representatives of that tradition, Thomas Hobbes
and Immanuel Kant. We saw that Hobbes’ account of the legitimacy of the State revolves
largely around the rational sense of self-preservation motivating us to form congruent
communities governed by a central source of authority. Kant’s aim is the same but he
arrives at it on the basis of the foundational thesis that all are free in the sense that we
all have the right to be independent from the choices of others. He then works through
the ideal and actual implications of this freedom. Thus, for Kant the original contract is
not the product of an actual or assumed agreement between citizens but rather a theo-
retical construction of the general will of the people, which is itself premised on reason
and is therefore independent of our individual attitudes.
We will now turn to a contemporary reworking of the idea of the social contract, one
which straddles the boundary between Hobbesian rationality and Kantian reasonable-
ness, namely John Rawls’ political liberalism. First, a background note to place things
in context.
John Rawls (1921–2002), an American who taught at Harvard University, is often
credited with reviving political philosophy. His 1971 seminal book, A Theory of Justice
departed from the philosophical current of the time of engaging in conceptual analysis
or metaphysics but also the tendency of political philosophers before him to simply
apply moral philosophical doctrines to political contexts. His aim was to work out a
theory of justice, underpinned by a theory of State legitimacy, by being attentive to the
specificities of the political, that is the realm of social co-existence and public institu-
tions, and the peculiarities of the modern condition.
A Theory of Justice very quickly became the most central reference in political philo-
sophical literature. For most liberals it was an inspiration. For non-liberals it was the
theory to defeat. It therefore inevitably became the subject of a great deal of criticism.
A lot of it missed its target but much of it did not and that urged Rawls to rethink and
reformulate some basic ideas. This led to Political Liberalism, which is our focus in this
chapter. In particular we will concentrate on the theory of State legitimacy offered
in Political Liberalism, rather then the accompanying theory of justice; point out the
instances in which Rawls has changed direction since Theory of Justice, and highlight
the extensions and implications of political liberalism in relation to law. Note that,
although Rawls had much to say on international politics and law, we will focus on his
account of the legitimacy of States and their law.
184 The Intellectual Foundations of the Liberal Social Contract Tradition
. . . many of our most important judgments are made under conditions where it is not
expected that conscientious persons with full powers of reason, even after full dis-
cussion, will all arrive at the same conclusion. Some confl icting reasonable judgments
(especially important belonging under peoples’ comprehensive doctrines) may be true,
others false; conceivably, all may be false. These burdens of judgment are of fi rst signifi-
cance for a democratic idea of toleration.
(J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005 (expanded edi-
tion; fi rst published 1993), p. 58)
You may wonder, why is this of any importance to a theory of the legitimacy of the
State and law? It is, because the point of any such theory is uncontroversially to justify
foundational principles and a corresponding institutional structure. It follows from the
unprovability of the truth or falsity of reasonable views regarding truth, the good and
the right, that there is no way of grounding the superiority of any one of these doc-
trines. Therefore, imposing the demands of one such doctrine onto those who do not
accept its premises and conclusions, is already an act of coercion rather than justified
use of authority. Why, for example, should a social democrat accept the legitimacy of a
State based on free-market principles on the basis of the moral and metaphysical assump-
tions that underpin free-market libertarianism? Or why would a polytheist regard as
legitimate a State organised around the principles of a monotheistic religion, if this
entails accepting the foundational principles of that religion?
All this begs a prior question: why should the foundations of the State be justified
to everyone in the first place? What if the reasons underpinning the State and law
are independent of the acceptance of those, to whom they apply? An advocate of a
certain strand of natural law, for example, would argue that one’s failure to accept the
requirements identified by reason in light of the actual conditions of our existence, is
simply and precisely a failure, which has nothing to do with the validity and strength
of objectively intuited reasons for action. And recall how Ronald Dworkin would argue
something similar. We may disagree on what the right thing to do is but only one of the
many possible conceptions will be right and the methodological tools of integrity allow
us to arrive at that objectively correct answer. Whether all endorse that right answer or
not is of no relevance to its rightness.
Rawls gives a two-pronged answer to this and we will discuss it later in more detail.
For now, let us only hint at it. First, the need for justification to others follows from
the fact that we recognise each other as cooperating agents in society with similar
capacities of control over our lives. Secondly, it is a matter of stability. If the State is not
convincingly grounded in a way that no one will have any justified grievances, then its
foundations will be shaky.
The upshot of all this is that the justification of the modern State ought not to be
anchored in any one comprehensive doctrine but should remain neutral between such
doctrines. It ought to be purely political, i.e. nonmoral, and freestanding, independent
of any controversial doctrine. At the same time, it also ought to be able to be accepted
186 The Intellectual Foundations of the Liberal Social Contract Tradition
by everyone in the political community not only despite their beliefs to which each
subscribes but also on the basis of these beliefs. In other words, the political justification
of the State must be such that it will cohere with and be accommodated within each
citizen’s comprehensive doctrine so that everyone will be able to accept it albeit for dif-
ferent reasons. In what follows we will try to clarify this political conception of State
legitimacy and justice and explain how Rawls suggests that it may be achieved.
specific conception of the good but only to our ability to form views as to what makes
for a happy and fulfi lled life.
We are also free in that we regard ourselves and others as ‘self-authenticating sources
of valid claims’. This means that citizens
We are equal in the sense that we regard ourselves and each other as having the moral
power of freedom, the power to form conceptions of the good independently of the
requirements of society and political institutions, to the same degree requisite for us to
be participants in a political society governed by terms of social cooperation, on which
all participants have agreed.
Notice the difference between Rawls’ conception of freedom to that of Hobbes and
Kant. Hobbes spoke of freedom in terms of our ability to move unimpeded in the world.
Kant’s political conception of freedom was connected to the external manifestation
of our independence. Rawls does not reject either of these understandings of freedom,
indeed his conception of the State and justice largely secure freedom in these senses,
but it is a different, formal sense of freedom as a capacity of the modern subject that
plays a foundational part.
The moral powers of freedom and equality are our capacities of rationality and rea-
sonableness. We are rational in a largely instrumental sense: we have the ability to
correlate means and ends. This is not to say that we are self-interested. We may have
ends, which are to our benefit narrowly speaking. But we are still capable of choosing
means suitable for the achievement of these ends. We are reasonable, first, in a sense
that is already familiar to us from the previous section, namely in that we acknowledge
the burdens of judgement, the tensions between beliefs and doctrines which constitute
the fact of pluralism. But we are also reasonable in the sense that we want to cooperate
with others rather than imposing our will on them. We are therefore prepared to pro-
pose terms of cooperation, which will be acceptable by all other participants in society,
although we should be careful to note that this does not necessarily mean that we are
altruistic, and motivated by the well-being of others.
Before we move on to discuss what participants in the original position will do, let
us pause to consider a possible objection. We said earlier that, in light of the fact of
pluralism, Rawls is keen to justify the State in a way that will not be anchored in any
metaphysical or moral doctrine. And yet we now see that at the very foundation of the
original position, therefore at the basis of the whole theory, lies a certain conception of
the person as free, equal, rational, reasonable. How can then Rawls coherently maintain
both arguments?
It is true that in the initial formulation of the original position in A Theory of Justice,
the original position appeared to rely on a description of metaphysically necessary
characteristics of humans. This attracted a great deal of criticism. Communitarian
thinkers, for example, argued that the abstraction of the original position is deeply con-
troversial and, indeed, incorrect. Why should one accept, the objection goes, that we
are individuals bearing these characteristics and therefore so radically separated from
our communities rather than regard us as an integral part of and in a relation of mutual
188 The Intellectual Foundations of the Liberal Social Contract Tradition
constitution with these communities? Or why should the conception of persons as free
and equal be preferred over other alternatives, say homo faber or homo laborans or homo
oeconomicus?
These are justified objections. Not because Rawls got the metaphysics of personhood
wrong, if anything it seems more accurate and intuitively attractive than the commu-
nitarian account, but because he did rely on such metaphysics in the fi rst place thus
clearly contradicting his claim to neutrality. Rawls took the criticism on board and this
motivated the change of direction and the recasting of his liberalism as political. For
this recasting to work, he also clarified the moral powers of freedom and equality. They
are not, he explains, universal and diachronic metaphysical traits of humans. They are
characteristics of the modern subject in specific contexts, namely modern constitu-
tional democracies. In these contexts, we have come to see ourselves and each other as
capable of forming conceptions of the good and as agents with an interest in coopera-
tion with each other. Rawls therefore provides a description not of an ideal or a-histori-
cal subject but of the typical political subject in specific, contemporary contexts.
Now, say that we accept that it is possible to reduce the political subject in modern
constitutional democracies to some basic characteristics. This still does not make the
problem disappear altogether, because it does not tell us how this can be done in a
non-arbitrary manner. The question can be asked although this time slightly reformu-
lated: why pick these characteristics of the modern subject over so many others? The
answer lies in the institutions that we have already developed in such modern consti-
tutional democracies. What emerges from these democratic State institutions is that in
our political lives, in our lives as citizens, we have developed this specific outlook of
ourselves and others as capable of having and pursuing conceptions of the good to an
equal degree.
With the metaphysical burden of the description of the subject removed, the character
of the original position is clarified too. It can no longer be misunderstood as an account
of necessary implications of some universal and diachronic characteristics of humans.
Neither is the claim that the agreement reached in the original position is true and
therefore binding a-historically. The original position is a ‘device of representation’
. . . it describes the parties, each of whom is responsible for the essential interests of a free
and equal citizen, as fairly situated and as reaching an agreement subject to conditions
that appropriately limit what they can put forward as good reasons.
(Political Liberalism, p. 25)
us in seeing clearly what the common denominator of our societies is and how we
can consistently and fairly organise our political co-existence on the basis of these
attainments.
So, to summarise the story so far, the original position is a counterfactual situation,
in which representatives of actual people as trustees of these people’s interests place
themselves behind the veil of ignorance. The veil excludes knowledge of the actual
circumstances of each participant and only allows knowledge of the moral powers of
freedom and equality of the modern subject in constitutional democracies, i.e. our
capacity of forming conceptions of the good to the requisite degree as to be coopera-
ting agents in society, and our traits of rationality and reasonableness, i.e. our ability
to set ends and pursue them with suitable means and our ability to have and act on a
sense of justice. Moreover, the participants also know some basic and inescapable facts
about human societies, chief amongst which is the relative scarcity of resources and
some scientifically proven facts about the world (note that scientific doctrine is not a
comprehensive moral doctrine for Rawls, unless of course it is given moral or political
texture). The stake, then, in the original position is for these symmetrically situated
participants to reach a universal agreement on terms of social cooperation, to agree on
a social contract. The question is not all that different than the one Hobbes tries to ask,
although the substantive differences are of course significant: if placed in the circum-
stances of the original position, how would we organise our political co-existence?
Now, why would the participants in the original position be motivated to reach an
agreement? Rawls’ answer is again in the same vein as Hobbes’ but substantively dif-
ferent. Participants will have a higher order interest in developing and exercising their
moral powers of freedom and equality.
To say that these interests are ‘higher-order’ interests means that, as the fundamental
idea of the person is specified, these interests are viewed as basic and hence as nor-
mally regulative and effective. Someone who has not developed and cannot exercise the
moral powers to the minimum requisite degree cannot be a normal and fully cooperat-
ing member of society over a complete life.
(Political Liberalism, p. 74)
So, this higher order interest both motivates the parties to reach an agreement and
determines the content of that agreement, namely to set up a framework enabling all
citizens to exercise their freedom and equality.
Crucially, the decisions of the participants in the original position will apply only to
the political realm, to use Rawls’ nomenclature, to the basic structure of society. This
draws a clear and rigid distinction between the public and the private. The basic struc-
ture comprises those basic institutions, which distribute rights, duties, resources, and
so on. The precise content of the basic structure, that is the precise range and character
of institutions that it will include, is open. In fact, it cannot be determined in advance,
because, as we will see in a little while, much of it depends on actual conditions in a
given society. What can be said at this stage, however, is that it will have to include
constitutional essentials, institutions pertaining to (some conception of) property, the
legal process, and so forth. Be that as it may, what is important for now is to point out
the clear distinction between the public/political, which is institutionally manifested
as the basic structure, and the private. The social contract agreed on in the original posi-
tion only binds citizens as citizens. Therefore, it cannot determine people’s moral rela-
tions and moral motivation, it may not govern private associations and so forth. Now,
190 The Intellectual Foundations of the Liberal Social Contract Tradition
where exactly the boundary between the private and the public lies is far from easy to
determine. Rawls himself was ambivalent on this over the course of the development of
his theory of the State and justice. The family is perhaps the most controversial and dif-
ficult such example. While some would not hesitate to classify familial relations under
the private realm, some, for instance feminists, would disagree and place domestic rela-
tions firmly within the political. Everyday economic activity is another such example.
It is contested whether the basic structure should impose duties and constraints, other
than tax-related or some basic anti-exploitation ones for example, on how one ought to
behave in one’s economic relations with others. Nevertheless, the claim is that there is
such a boundary, wherever it may be, between the private and the public and the social
contract only pertains to the latter.
This already sets out the basic parameters of Rawls’ version of the social contract. The
original position sets the conditions of impartiality and reciprocity, which will lead to
an agreement amongst all rational and reasonable members of the political community
on the terms of social cooperation and the foundations of a well-ordered, fair society.
Recall here Ronald Dworkin’s objection to the social contract tradition, which we dis-
cussed in relation to Hobbes. The original position is a hypothetical situation. But a
hypothetical agreement has no binding force on any of the parties. Rawls’ response
is that the original position specifies a public perspective shared by all participants.
Its results are therefore constructed on that basis in a way that all participants will be
compelled to accept. And they will accept them not as morally or metaphysically true
but as reasonable and appropriate for our political communities. And this is the crux of
Rawls’ methodology of political constructivism.
(1) Each person has an equal claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic rights
and liberties, which scheme is compatible with a similar scheme for all.
(2) Social and economic inequalities are permissible only to the extent that they
satisfy two conditions:
first, they must be attached to offices and positions, which must be open to all
under conditions of fair equality of opportunity;
second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members of
society (the difference principle).
The first principle, the ‘liberty principle’, refers largely to basic rights that every citi-
zen ought to be granted by the constitution. It guarantees that everyone enjoys those
John Rawls’ Political Liberalism 191
liberties, which are basic because necessary for one to be a free and equal participant
in the political community. They are also inalienable liberties. Neither the State may
curtail them nor may their bearer, i.e. each citizen, forsake them. The liberty principle
enjoys ‘lexical priority’ in relation to the second principle and basic liberties enjoy
priority over any other liberty. This means that for any pattern of distribution of goods
and resources to be established, everyone must be afforded this protection of their basic
liberties. Their priority also means that basic liberties may not be curtailed to satisfy
economic imperatives or for the sake of other goods. This is not to say that the basic
liberties cannot be restricted at all, they can. But they may only be restricted to satisfy
other basic liberties and to the extent that these restrictions apply equally to everyone.
To use one of Rawls’ examples, during the Vietnam war, American college students
were exempted from the draft. Given that the latter is a restriction of basic liberties, the
exemption is unjustifiable even if there are good pragmatic reasons for it (for example,
college graduates contributing more to the national economy).
Now, which are these liberties? How do we distinguish between basic and non-basic
rights? Rawls singles out five sets: liberty of conscience and thought; freedom of asso-
ciation; political liberties such as the rights to vote and to stand for office; the integrity
and freedom of the person; and liberties flowing from the rule of law. These are not
singled out because they enjoy some sort of metaphysical or moral priority but rather
because they are linked to the moral powers of freedom of equality, which are, as we
have seen, powers of the modern subject in the here and now. So if, say, our freedom of
conscience were curtailed, we would not be able to develop and pursue to the requisite
degree a conception of the good. To use a concrete example, if citizens were not allowed
to form and exercise religious beliefs or if they were coerced into endorsing a specific
religious doctrine, their freedom, i.e. their capacity to choose and pursue a conception
of the good and their character as self-authenticating sources of valid claims, would be
undermined.
All this, however, would be pointless, if citizens did not enjoy at least a minimum of
material equality too. It is all very well to say that we all enjoy the same liberties but if
the actual conditions which will allow us to make the most of those liberties are not in
place, then we may as well not be afforded these rights in the first place. This brings us
to the second principle of justice, which has two legs: the equality of opportunity prin-
ciple and the difference principle. This, and especially the difference principle, is where
Rawls parts ways with a great deal of liberal theory, because he grounds a requirement
of redistribution of wealth as a matter of justice, rather say as a matter of beneficence
and charity.
The principle of equality of opportunity ensures that randomly acquired privileges do
not advantage one or disadvantage others when bidding for positions. At the very least,
this implies that no one may be discriminated against on grounds of gender, ethnic
background, and so forth. But it also imposes substantive and positive obligations not
to exclude anyone from the job market, this is the primary context of application of the
principle, because they do not meet conditions unrelated to talent or skills. For instance,
companies ought not to be allowed to make jobs available only to, say, graduates of
private schools. Equality of opportunity also serves to correct structural inequalities.
For example, it establishes a duty on the part of the State to enable everyone to try to
acquire those minimum skills and qualifications necessary for one to be able to pursue
one’s ideas of happiness and do well in society.
The difference principle has proved to be perhaps the most controversial of Rawls’
claims. The basic idea is that some inequalities are permissible but only to the ex-
tent that they benefit the worse-off members of society. Rawls departs from blanket
192 The Intellectual Foundations of the Liberal Social Contract Tradition
by embedding the political conception of justice in the comprehensive moral and meta-
physical doctrines of each citizen. To put it simply, this means that everyone should
be able to accept the political conception of justice and the institutions that it justifies
on the basis of the doctrines, to which each subscribes. This does not require citizens
to sign up to an alternative moral doctrine or to adapt their doctrines to the political
conception of justice, which serves as a type of superior regulative doctrine. Neither
does it mean that each citizen must accept the political conception of justice for the
same reasons. An overlapping consensus also does not amount to a majoritarian view of
rightness, as there is no guarantee that the majority will act on public reasons, which
are acceptable by all. It means that that conception of justice must be such that it fits in,
that it coheres with all citizens’ comprehensive doctrines and not just the majority’s. A
Christian and a Marxist, for example, may not accept and place it within their doctrines
in the same way. They may do so from their own perspective and in their own terms so
long as they do. Once the political conception of justice cuts across all comprehensive
doctrines, then overlapping consensus will have been achieved. And this will mean
that the State will be stable for the right reasons and not as a result of coercing citizens
nor as a matter of a modus vivendi à la Hobbes.
You may wonder why a liberal State should try to accommodate all comprehensive
doctrines available out there. Why should the rest of us go out of our way to take seri-
ously and count as participants in the political community, say, racists or fundamen-
talists or shameless plutocrats? The answer is to be found in the Rawlsian sense of
reasonableness. We have encountered this idea already when setting out the fact of
reasonable pluralism. Once again, it is overlapping consensus between reasonable doc-
trines that a liberal, democratic State ought to try to achieve and there are good reasons
to exclude unreasonable views from it.
But what counts as ‘unreasonable’, you will ask. Unreasonable doctrines or people are
those who refuse to recognise in others the basic moral powers of freedom and equal-
ity. This makes them unreasonable not because they fail to accept a universal moral
truth or anything of the sort—it cannot be overemphasised that Rawlsian political
liberalism is precisely about steering clear of such conceptions of truth about morality.
The idea of reasonableness is itself political and unreasonable doctrines are discounted
because they purport to be participants in a well-ordered society while, at the same
time, refusing to accept the very presuppositions underpinning a well-ordered society.
In contradicting themselves so, they exclude themselves from the process of justifying
terms of social cooperation and from guaranteeing their stability. However, we should
also emphasise that this conception of reasonableness excludes very few views, some
of which we have already mentioned. It is not very likely that a great number of people
will harbour views which refute the very foundations of modern societies.
There are of course all sorts of pragmatic problems with overlapping consensus, chief
amongst which is how to actualise it (we will say a litle more on this later) and, prior
to this, whether it is even possible to construct a political conception of justice, which
can be accommodated in every moral doctrine and still be substantive enough to be
able to govern our co-existence. Rawls does not harbour any such high hopes. He fully
recognises that achieving overlapping consensus is extremely difficult. At the same
time, though, it is undoubtedly not impossible. And it becomes more likely, when one
considers how political dialogue and mutual understanding have been facilitated by
new forms of direct communication.
There is, however, another issue of a philosophical nature, which poses more of a
challenge to Rawls. If the political conception of justice requires overlapping consensus
to be achieved, then it seems that the original position does little or no work at all. It
194 The Intellectual Foundations of the Liberal Social Contract Tradition
seems that the very justification of the conception of justice is not done from an impar-
tial perspective any longer but from the point of view of actual, situated citizens. But if
this is so and there is no objective perspective of justification, then Rawlsian construc-
tivism does not look all that different from the Hobbesian State, in which self-interested
agents get together to strike a compromise, a modus vivendi (for this objection see
J Habermas, ‘Reconciliation through the public use of reason: Remarks on John Rawls’s
political liberalism’ (1995) The Journal of Philosophy 92/3, pp. 109–31).
Rawls responds to this objection by distinguishing between three stages and types
of justification. In the first stage, the political conception of justice is justified pro tanto,
that is tentatively, by examining whether such a conception can provide reasonable
answers with regard to political values alone. In the next stage, each citizen must jus-
tify the political conception of justice by embedding it in his or her comprehensive
doctrine (although this does not entail a requirement that each and every citizen does
in fact subscribe to a comprehensive doctrine—some may well go through life without
developing a coherent set of moral beliefs). Some citizens will accommodate the politi-
cal conception of justice into their doctrines as true, if it overlaps with such claims to
truth that these doctrines raise. Others may only embed it as reasonable. Either way, the
conception of justice remains freestanding and political and the reasons for which each
citizen accepts it do not alter its very character. In the final stage, the political concep-
tion of justice is publicly justified by political society.
In this case, reasonable citizens take one another into account as having reasonable com-
prehensive doctrines that endorse that political conception and this mutual accounting
shapes the moral quality of the public culture of political society. A crucial point here
is that while the public justification of the political conception for political society
depends on reasonable comprehensive doctrines, this justification does so only in an
indirect way. That is, the express contents of these doctrines have no normative role in
public justification; citizens do not look into the content of others’ doctrines, and so
remain within the bounds of the political. (Political Liberalism, p. 387)
exercised in public, political contexts, where decisions on basic liberties and constitu-
tional essentials are made. The most typical such context, indeed one used by Rawls
to illustrate the point, are supreme courts—especially those which are given the task
of interpreting the constitution—and the reasoning rules, which they must follow.
Supreme court judges may not follow their own morality or the religious or philosophi-
cal doctrines of others.
They must be, and appear to be, interpreting the same constitution in view of what they
see as the relevant parts of the political conception and in good faith believe it can be
defended as such.
(Political Liberalism, p. 237)
In doing so, the supreme court will protect the law against assaults by majorities, which
may want to impose their own views. It will ensure that the law remains properly justi-
fied on the basis of public, political standards, which everyone can accept.
(a) The enunciation of the principles of justice from the original position, which we
have already discussed.
(b) A partial lifting of the veil of ignorance so far as the general circumstances of the
society but not the individual circumstances of the actors are concerned and the
devising of a constitutional system dealing with powers of government and the
rights of citizens. This process must, amongst other factors, cope with different
and possibly opposed political viewpoints. Granted the priority of liberty, the
outcome is assumed to be some form of constitutional democracy.
(c) Having established a constitution, the next step is legislation in accordance with
the principles of justice, as well as the constitutional procedures. The legislators
are intended to act in the light of general interest rather than to their personal
advantage. It is admitted that judging whether or not a law is just may be difficult,
especially in the context of the inequalities of the difference principle, and that it
may be easier simply to determine whether a law is not unjust.
(d) The fi nal stage is that of application of the laws and rules by judges and admin-
istrators and their working in the actions of people generally, at which point, of
course, the veil of ignorance is wholly removed.
196 The Intellectual Foundations of the Liberal Social Contract Tradition
As you can see, through the four stages the veil of ignorance is gradually removed.
This implies that at the earlier stages, it is not possible to determine how constitutional
essentials will be applied once the veil of ignorance has been wholly lifted. Another way
of putting the same point is that an institutional structure cannot be designed from a
philosophical perspective. This can only be done in view of actual conditions in a soci-
ety, including actual comprehensive doctrines. This does not only pertain to humdrum
regulation of minor matters but also to basic institutions. For example, the conditions
of legitimacy of the State and the principles of justice will not necessitate any particu-
lar way of divvying up resources and regulating property relations. Justice as fairness
may be served equally well by institutions of private or collective property. Similarly,
a representative parliamentary democratic system such as the ones with which we are
familiar, is not necessitated by the foundations of the liberal State. What the latter do
require is a political system, which will facilitate the expression of citizens’ views so as
to actualise overlapping consensus, public reason and so forth but how exactly this will
be organised is another matter. Indeed, whole areas of law may prove to be unnecessary.
For instance, there is nothing in the foundations of the liberal State that necessitates
criminalisation and punishment. If a better way is available with which to deal with
violations of the law, then this may be preferable to punishing.
Rawls himself believed that a representative democratic system based on private
property (which is, though, subject to non-market restrictions, as we have seen) is the
best possible system in current circumstances. What is important to highlight, how-
ever, is that very little will be determined from a philosophical perspective. Citizens
will be under some unconditional duties flowing directly from the original position,
such as the duty to respect the physical, psychological and sexual integrity of others.
The State will also be under an obligation to enact and protect some constitutional
essentials, such as the freedom of expression and participation, and so forth. But, save
for such rather minimal and rather thin (freedom of expression, for instance, does not
determine how the press ought to be regulated) requirements, nothing else can be
determined from a philosophical standpoint.
fully observed but, at the same time, it will be unjust. In fact, we do not have to look
far from home for such examples. Many of today’s States meet, to a sufficient degree,
the conditions of liberal legitimacy but, at the same time, they often sanction striking
inequalities, which blatantly do not meet the conditions of justice as fairness. The ques-
tion then is what demands a legitimate but unjust or a just but illegitimate State can
make of its citizens. Are we under an obligation to obey the laws of such a State?
Even in actual conditions, there must largely be a balance between legitimacy and
justice. This is because to some extent they depend on one another. A grossly unjust
State is likely not to meet the conditions of legitimacy either. Imagine, for instance, a
State which altogether excludes from income redistribution or fails to grant some basic
liberties to a class of people. Such a State will be unjust and illegitimate, because it fails
to treat the members of that class of people as free and equal. Observing basic standards
of justice is therefore a condition of legitimacy too. Where exactly the threshold lies
may of course be difficult to quantify. Nevertheless, the important point is that such a
boundary in principle exists.
So, a State ought to be both procedurally and substantively just at least to a minimum
degree. Problems occur, however, when a State is partially unjust, that is when it meets
the conditions of legitimacy and the basic conditions of justice such as the distribution
of basic liberties but still fails to treat some citizens fairly. Imagine, for instance, a class
of people, say a professional group, who are afforded basic rights and so forth but, at the
same time, they are short-changed by an unfair State policy of social insurance. In such
cases, we are still under a duty to obey unjust laws. Neither the members of that group
nor any other citizen is authorised to disregard those unjust laws. The State, though,
is under an obligation to redress the injustice. And it is within citizens’ rights to try to
instigate reform.
In fact, in a nearly just society and when all else fails, citizens are entitled to engage
in civil disobedience, in order to communicate both to the institutions of the State
and to the rest of the citizens the injustice and the need for reform. They are justi-
fied to do so under certain conditions, which we will only mention very briefly: they
ought not to engage in violence; they ought publicly and openly to communicate their
demands; in doing so they ought to appeal to public reasons (even when using moral
language one may still be appealing to public reasons, for example, Martin Luther King
or Archbishop Desmod Tutu); when deciding which course of action to take, they ought
to consider the interests of others.
FURTHER RE ADING
Cohen, G. A., Rescuing Justice and Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008).
Davion, V. and Wolf, C. (eds), The Idea of a Political Liberalism: Essays on Rawls (Lanham,
MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999).
Fleming, J. and Cordaro, S. (eds), ‘Rawls and the Law’, Symposium, (2004) Fordham Law
Review 72: 1380–2175.
Freeman, S., Justice and the Social Contract: Essays on Rawlsian Political Philosophy (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2006).
Freeman, S., The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003).
Freeman, S., Rawls (London: Routledge, 2007).
Griffi n, S., and Solum, L. (eds), ‘Symposium of John Rawls’s Political Liberalism’ (1994)
Chicago Kent Law Review 69: 549–842.