Judicial Reviwe
Judicial Reviwe
Judicial Reviwe
I
The thirteen years of the Weimar Republic were a time of dramatic foreign
policy changes and domestic crises verging on civil war, but they were also
a period of remarkable cultural and intellectual fertility, especially in state
theory. Older ideas came to maturity more quickly than at any other time
in the past, and, in the atmosphere of crisis, a sharper light than usual was
cast on a great many things. This is true, for example, of judicial review—
the notion that a judge could have power to determine the formal and mate-
rial validity of a law. This right requires that the function of a judge be clearly
separate from that of the executive.1 The judge must be so independent, both
as a person and in light of the facts, that he can overrule the normative prod-
ucts of the legislative authority, i.e., laws, or the executive authority, i.e.,
ordinances, in individual cases or in general. This became possible, however,
only at a certain point in time—once the functions of state authority had
1
See, for example, § 112 of the constitution of Kurhesse, 5 January 1831: “In the future the
judiciary ought forever to be separated from the administration.”
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2003, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Judicial, Administrative, and Constitutional Review 267
been separated completely, following a move away from the system of con-
stitutional monarchy in which judges were still regarded as servants of the
monarch (Herrmann 2001).
The notion of administrative review is also linked to a specific era. After
lengthy debate, it took hold in Germany and Austria in the last third of the
nineteenth century. Its key question was: How can the actions of the execu-
tive powers be bound to the law in such a way that politically formative
action by the state is still possible? The solution was found—at any rate, in
Prussia—by linking the new courts so closely to the executive powers that
there was no longer any fear of the state being paralysed at its core (Kohl
1991).
Finally, we come to constitutional review (Haberle 1976). This requires a
written constitution, which explains why it did not develop until the nin-
teenth and twentieth centuries. At the same time, being “review,” it had to
be capable of rescinding or amending any legal regulations in the constitu-
tion that might be a hindrance to laws or ordinances. In one sense, then, con-
stitutional review is an extension of the powers of judicial review, since both
involve judges “examining” the law in a legitimate way in the context of a
higher legal regulation and having the power to declare it invalid. In another
sense, however, constitutional review is an aliud, since it answers only ques-
tions of interpretation of the constitution, whereas judicial review applies in
individual cases and can exist, as it does in Germany today, alongside con-
stitutional review.
Let us begin with judicial review, that is to say, the right (or rather, the
duty) of civil and penal judges in the lower courts to examine the formal—
and sometimes material—validity of laws and ordinances within the scope
of a trial. If the result of the examination is negative, the law in question is
not to be applied to the specific case in hand.
The decisive issue here is whether the judge, figuring as a part of the
“powers of review” in the sense of the division of state authority into leg-
islative, executive, and adjudicative powers, may regard a law passed by
parliament as “not valid” in his specific decision. There is a clash here
between two principles. The first principle is this: The judge is bound to the
law. Thus, since he is “bound,” he cannot act arbitrarily. The law is an expres-
sion of the sovereignty of the people, who, by democratic election, create a
parliament, where decisions are taken that are meant to be binding on all,
including, in particular, the judge. The second principle is this: The judge is
independent and he can overrule the law in the name of what is “right.” He
is understood as a “guardian of the law.” In this capacity, he may apply all
forms of law that prevail over parliamentary law. This applies primarily to
the constitution, but also (though this is a matter for debate) to un-
written norms of a higher kind, such as “natural law” or “morality,” and
even religious commandments. According to this second principle, the judge
is granted a position of significant power. This position tends to become the
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2003.
268 Michael Stolleis
highest power in the state, controlling the legislative and executive powers,
for both of them act within the legal structure and both, then, must expect
to be informed by a judge in the event that they create an injustice in apply-
ing the prevailing law. Whether judges are to be granted “rights of judicial
examination” is a fundamental question of state law, or, quite simply, a con-
stitutional issue.
It is therefore no coincidence that this question was first raised in
Germany in the early nineteenth century. After the Vienna Congress of
1814–15 had established a new order in which Austria and Prussia ignored
their peoples’ wishes for a constitution, smaller states were quick to intro-
duce constitutions. These constitutions contained guarantees of judicial
independence for the first time.2 But the judges remained public servants
and were not “controllers” or justices of the peace elected by civil society, as
in England. Justice was an ancient sovereign right of the monarch3 and
remained such, for the position of the sovereign in these constitutions
remained virtually unchanged. Justice was not, as it is today, a “third
power.” Rather, it was a special form of the executive. This also fitted in with
the tradition of absolutism in which judges were servants of the sovereign
and subject to the rule of law. If these judges had any doubts about the sig-
nificance of validity of a rule, they had to inform the government and wait
for an authentic interpretation.
This concept is alien to us today. Having learned our lesson from the dic-
tatorships of the twentieth century, we tend to see absolutism in a negative
light. Yet to do so is to overlook the enormous achievement of absolutism
in shaping the modern state in the first place, and in establishing a monop-
oly of legitimate power. The unity of state authority preceded the modern
division of authority. It was only through the unity of state authority that it
was possible to render a country homogeneous and modern by creating
cohesive administrative, legislative, financial, and judicial systems and
by overcoming the structures of guilds and estates, which were no longer
effective.
This has to be pointed out quite clearly, for the idea of emancipating the
judiciary from the legislative and executive powers could only emerge after
the absolute rulers of the eighteenth century had become the constitutional
monarchs of the nineteenth century. The new constitutions provided a yard-
stick by which to determine whether the law was at least formally in order,
having made its way through the procedures prescribed by the constitution.
In material terms, an examination appeared impossible: The law was now
2
Art. viii, § 3 of the Bavarian Constitution of 1818: “The courts are independent within the
limits of their competence [ . . . ]”; art. ii, § 14 of the Constitution of Baden of 1818: “The courts
are independent within the limits of their competence [ . . . ]”; Constitution of Wurttemberg
1819, Part A, § 46: “No public servant, acting as judge, can be dismissed or moved to a
lower position, whatever the reason may be.”
3
Bavarian Constitution 1818, Art. viii, § 1: “The judiciary puts down to the king [ . . . ].”
the expression of the “people’s will”; that will could not be countered by
individual judges whose attitudes were similar to those of the parliamen-
tary representatives. What is more, basic rights were aimed against the
monarchical executive and not against the legislature formed by the people.
Parliaments saw themselves as “guardians of basic rights.” It would have
seemed absurd for the judiciary to try to apply these basic rights against the
laws made by parliament.
The constant controversy surrounding judicial review raged throughout
the nineteenth century and remained unsolved. The overwhelming opinion
was that the judge should be able to examine whether a law had been issued
correctly, and this approach prevailed in Germany throughout the entire
nineteenth century. The Constitution of the German Reich of 1871 contained
neither a means of the control of laws by judges nor a constitutional court.
Even the remaining German states had no judicial review.4 Although schol-
ars debated the issue, it never got beyond the point at which the judge was
empowered simply to examine the formal validity of a law. Judges had to
accept the content of the law as reflecting the will of the state.
The Supreme Court of the German Reich—as the highest and, de facto,
leading instance of the judiciary—followed the same line.5 The Supreme
Court examined the creation of a rule in formal terms, but respected its
content as unassailable.6 This position, which was more or less taken for
granted, corresponded to the prevailing legal positivism of the day. Judges
consulted the constitution to the extent that it had anything to say about the
lawmaking process. It could not be consulted further, for it contained no
basic rights by means of which a material legal argument might be con-
structed. Until the First World War, there seemed to be no reason to change
this system. The constitutional monarchy and its lawmakers were to keep
to their own rules of procedure, which could be examined by a judge
without intervening in the legislature. The content of the law, however, was
off limits, even if for no other reason than that it was regarded as the act of
a sacrosanct state. In short, an authority had spoken that was higher than
the power of the judge.
There is one special issue that ought to be mentioned here, since it serves
to relativise the theory that there was no material judicial review before 1919.
That is the judicial examination of ordinances issued by the executive of
the Reich and by the individual states. Since ordinances ranked below the
law, these could actually be examined. In this case, the judge had a clear
4
Prussian Constitution from 1850, art. 106: “The judicial examination of correctly pronounced
ordinances is the duty of the parliament, not the administrative authorities.”
5
The decisions of the German Supreme Court (Reichsgericht) begin with RGZ (= Entscheidun-
gen des Reichsgerichts in Zivilsachen) 9, 232, 236; then vol. 24, 3; 25, 274; 45, 270; 48, 84, 205; 77,
231. These precedents are used in 1921 (RGZ 102, 161–6) where the Court says that the courts
themselves are “qualified fully to examine laws and ordinances, except in cases in which such
examination is precluded by law.”
6
In clear language, the decision of the Reichsgericht, in Goldhammer’s Archiv 1908, 55: 325ff.
yardstick. It did not bring him into conflict with the legislature or the
monarch, but only with the executive, who is subject to the law. Judges did
exercise a review power in this particular area before the First World War,
and they occasionally repealed ordinances on grounds that these over-
stepped the limits established by the legal framework. Regional legislation,
too, which ranked below Reich legislation, was examined in this way. In
other words, wherever it was possible without endangering the equilibrium
of the state authorities, wherever the judges had a clear yardstick, and wher-
ever it was a question of the hierarchy between law and ordinance, Reich
legislation and regional legislation, they did not hesitate to exercise the
power of judicial review.
Apart from “regular” justice as constituted by the civil and penal law of
the Supreme Court of the German Reich, there had been judicial review of
administrative action in Baden since 1863 and in Prussia since 1875.7 It had
been created after decades of debate in order to examine the legality of the
executive’s intervention in matters of freedom and property.
In order to examine such intervention, a yardstick was required, and that
could only be the law or an ordinance derived from the law. If there was
any doubt as to the validity of these rules, the administrative judge must
also determine whether he had the authority to exercise “judicial review.”
Here, too, there was, before 1918, a compromise that granted the judge
formal but not material review. Yet there was one special aspect of admin-
istrative review: It came into play wherever it was a question of the ancient
basic rights of “freedom and property.” Prussian judicial review of admin-
istrative action could even apply a material yardstick here. That is to say,
the guarantees of basic rights set forth in the Prussian Constitution of 31
January 1850, guaranteeing equality, personal freedom, and the inviolabil-
ity of property.8
This meant that even at this early stage, there was a functional equivalent
to the later constitutional review; for the court, unlike civil and penal pro-
cedures, had the possibility of reviewing an administrative act (such as
expropriation, prohibition of an assembly, or prohibition of business enter-
prise) in legal and constitutional terms. Even if the administrative act was
covered by the law, the law itself could, theoretically, still be “unconstitu-
tional.” An ordinance could fail by the standards of higher law or of the con-
stitution. In this respect, judicial review of administrative action offered rich
potential for judicial review and served at the same time as a functional sub-
stitute for a lack of constitutional review. To be sure, it did not count as real
constitutional review, but the argument based on the constitution was begin-
ning to be understood as a superior argument and was being applied, at
least as a back-up measure. An analysis of the adjudication of the Prussian
7
Baden 1863, Prussia 1875, Bavaria 1875, Austria 1875, Braunschweig 1896. Cf. Keller 1998.
8
Constitution of the Prussian State from the 31 January 1850, art. 4 (equality), art. 5 (freedom),
art. 9 (property).
II
The revolution of 1918 and the new Constitution of the German Reich of
1919 radically changed the legal system. The constitutional monarchy was
replaced by a republic and the monarchic principle by democratic sover-
eignty. The weight was shifted towards parliament. The legislature was the
highest of the three state authorities. The executive and adjudicative author-
ities were bound by their respective laws. In this respect there should have
been, in theory, no judicial review whatsoever, and no constitutional review
either. Basic rights, too, seemed superfluous. The people had become ruler,
electing representatives by means of egalitarian suffrage which included
women for the first time. Seen in terms of Rousseau’s philosophy, the will
of the people manifest in parliament was the volonté générale against which
there could be no basic rights, no judicial review, and no constitutional
review of the protection of individual rights.
This point of view, however, was not tenable in practice. It did not corre-
spond to the political situation, and it did take into account the psycholog-
ical reservations against parliamentarianism either. Hugo Preuss, “father
of the German constitution,” posited in 1919 that a democratic system did
not require any basic rights “against” parliament. Against his intention,
however, a major constellation of basic rights was created, partly out of
bourgeois fears of “parliamentary absolutism.” Even the formidable powers
of the Reich President, whose legitimation was based on democratic elec-
tion, were motivated by a general distrust of parliament. Max Weber vigor-
ously supported this solution.
Right from the start, there were strong forces—particularly among the
liberal bourgeoisie and the conservatives—lobbying for judicial control of
laws passed by parliament. The shock of revolution had fuelled the fears of
“left-wing” rule, creating a climate conducive to the concept of judicial
review. The judges who had to make the decisions were the product of an
imperial age. Several studies in the field of social history have shown that
they were predominantly conservative and that they regarded themselves
as a bastion against socialism (Ormond 1994).
9
There is still no monograph on this topic. On one small aspect, see Wichardt 1976.
The civil servants of the imperial age, including the judges, had been
asked by all parties concerned to stay in place and serve the new state
loyally. This they did, though their loyalty was not unqualified. The presi-
dent of the Supreme Court of the German Reich10 called all his judges to a
plenary assembly and declared the new state authority legally valid in spite
of the fact that it had been created by means of a revolution (Fischer 1929).
This resulted in a duty to obey the laws whose enactment had been formally
correct. This was set forth in the new Constitution of the German Reich (art.
102 WRV). It also allowed, however, that the former elite remain on guard
to ensure that the new state would continue in the same manner as the
former system, without, then, affecting bourgeois values. There were three
paths that could be pursued in this judicial scrutiny of the new legal order.
First of all, the concept of judicial review could be extended. Secondly,
administrative review could be exercised against the executive of the new
state, and, thirdly, constitutional review could be introduced. I shall discuss
them in this order.
III
The Supreme Courts of the German Reich responded quickly to the ques-
tion of judicial review. As soon as the Constitution had been enacted, the
Supreme Court of Fiscal Jurisdiction (Reichsfinanzhof ) determined that courts
were fundamentally entitled and obligated to “examine whether the laws
they are to apply have been duly and properly created and whether they
are constitutional.”11 The Supreme Court of the German Reich quickly fol-
lowed suit, declaring in 1921—in a manner verging on falsification—that
“the Reichsgericht (Supreme Court of the German Reich) has, by means of
continuous review, entitled the courts of law to examine the formal and
material legality of laws and ordinances insofar as such review is not pro-
hibited by law.” (RGZ 1921, 102: 161–6). An examination of the evidence
indicates that there was no such thing as a review of “material legality” prior
to 1914. In other words, the Reichsgericht sought to establish the facts by
simply asserting them, henceforth establishing a material right of review
(Fangmann 1979, 260). This was done by claiming the basic rights to be
“sacred to the German people.” (RGZ 102, 151 [165]). During the period of
inflation, the Reichsgericht was even more emphatic in calling for a review
of the constitutionality of laws (RGZ 1925, 111, 320). Even though this power
of review was in fact exercised only moderately, and with little impact (Nörr
1988, 10ff.), the changing face of judicial review from 1919 onwards is
extremely interesting: When the government of the German Reich planned
10
Rudolf Freiherr von Seckendorff (1844–1932) became president in 1905 and remained till
1920. See Müller 1997, 122f.
11
Entscheidungen des Reichsfinanzhofs 5, 333 (335); 7, 97 (100). About this see Gusy 1985, 80.
IV
At the same time, judicial review of administrative action continued to
expand. It served, as already pointed out, to protect individual rights against
detrimental intervention by the state. Judicial review of administrative
action was a matter for the individual states. There was no Supreme Admin-
istrative Court at the time. Although such a court had indeed been planned
since 1875 and was provided for in the Weimar Constitution (art. 31, section
2, art. 107, 166 WRV), political difficulties prevented its inception before 1933
(Huber 1981, 6: 568ff.; Kohl 1991). However, at the regional level judicial
review of administrative action spread both in depth and in breadth. In dia-
logue with the citizens, as it were, it established that the administration in
a state based on the rule of law should be bound by stringent regulations in
any intervention in the rights of the citizens. These regulations were devel-
oped particularly in the field of police law (Götz 1985, 397ff., 416ff.).12
Given the continuity of institutions and staff in the transition from the
Kaiserreich to the Weimar Republic, it is hardly surprising that judicial
review of administrative action continued to expand in the Weimar Repub-
lic. It embodied the liberalism of the late nineteenth century and was, in
social terms, the domain of the middle classes and the educated nobility
in the tradition of Prussian administration. In the context of the Weimar
Republic, judicial review of administrative action also played a role in the
movement depicted by the example of judicial review. Here, too, there was
an increasing tendency not to accept legislation unquestioningly, but to
measure its “justice” by the higher standard of the Constitution. This was
also a sign that the administrative judges defended the status quo and
sought to limit the influence of the state vis-à-vis basic rights, reaching to
the gradually established stance that the administration would have to live
with controls wherever the legislature had granted discretionary powers.13
V
The Weimar debate over constitutional review was of inestimable impor-
tance for the post-War years and, in particular, for the founding of the
Federal Constitutional Court. The concept of “constitutional review “ (Ver-
fassungsgerichtsbarkeit) was coined by Heinrich Triepel in 1928 in contrast to
the older “Staatsgerichtsbarkeit” (Triepel 1929, 5: 2ff.; Friesenhahn 1932, 2:
page 98, note 3). Both the Austrian and the German theory of public law, in
spite of fundamental differences in method, agreed on the political neces-
12
Concerning the history of the Prussian police law from 1931 see the forthcoming book of
Naas 2003.
13
The supporters of greater control over the administration (Gerhard Anschütz, Willibalt Apelt,
Ottmar Bühler, Erich Kaufmann, Kurt Perels, Richard Thoma) often heard the argument that
this position would paralyse the state. To meet this argument, they proposed excluding dis-
cretionary decisions from control. See Perels 1925, 113.
sity of constitutional review. After 1945, at a time when the shock of the
Nazi regime was still keenly felt, constitutional review was the only new
“guardian of the constitution” that could be considered. In Austria, the rein-
troduction of the 1920 constitution and the continued practice of constitu-
tional review were a matter of course, and Germany was given little choice.
All the arguments put forward in Vienna at the 1928 meeting of the Society
of Public Law Teachers had become highly topical once more: the political
character of public law cases, the difficulty in drawing a line between law
and politics on the one hand, and confidence that legal issues could indeed
be isolated on the other.
The continuation of this debate beyond 1945 is just one aspect, however,
and in studies of post-war German and Austrian constitutional review it
sheds light only on the role of a certain “background situation.” The other
aspect is a genuinely historical one: Why was it that, since the nineteenth
century, the need for constitutional review as a means of protecting the
rights of the individual had been voiced increasingly, and why was the call
for constitutional review especially vociferous in the context of the demo-
cratic republics after 1919? This is the question we have to ask. I shall go
back in history quite a long way in order to answer it.
In tracing the historical beginnings of constitutional review in Germany,
much depends on whether one regards the forms that held sway in the
Ancien Régime before 1806 as the functional equivalent of modern constitu-
tional review. The two high courts of the empire established in the early
sixteenth century—the Reichskammergericht and the Reichshofrat—were, of
course, not comparable to modern constitutional courts. Still, they dealt with
disputes involving “public law” matters, such as litigation by villages,
guilds or estates against a ruler, or violation of the public peace, issues of
regal and monarchic rights, feudal rights, and so on. These courts have
sometimes been described—perhaps a bit too enthusiastically—as the fore-
runners of today’s Federal Constitutional Court, but the heart of the matter
lies elsewhere and is obvious: Germany has a tradition, going all the way
back to the Late Middle Ages, of allowing subjects and corporations of all
kinds to seek justice against the ruling classes before an imperial (or impe-
rially legitimised) court. Constitutional questions such as the interpretation
of the Peace of Augsburg of 1555 were also examined by the imperial courts.
Much of this, to be sure, was “pre-modern.” There was no definitive con-
stitutional text, no list of basic rights, no control of the legislative powers,
and important territories had privileges that freed them from imperial
justice. Yet in the period before 1800, there was a general awareness that
questions of a constitutional and political nature that did not fall within the
bounds of penal law or civil law could be decided by a supreme court.
This awareness was strongly consolidated in the period following the
Napoleonic wars, at which time constitutions and lists of basic rights were
being drawn up throughout Europe, and much thought was given to the
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2003.
276 Michael Stolleis
the last democratically legitimised government fell. From then on, politi-
cians and the masses turned increasingly towards authoritarian solutions,
yearning for a “leader” who would promise them a “salvation” from all
evils.
The legislature no longer had any authority. There was no longer any
interest in controlling it. Help was expected only from the executive, and
there was no longer any thought of controlling it through the courts. Carl
Schmitt’s work on the “Guardian of the Constitution,” written in several
phases, declared in no uncertain terms that the judiciary, incapable of action
or policy, could not be the “Guardian of the Constitution.” Instead, accord-
ing to Schmitt, under the current circumstances only the President of the
Reich could have that function (Schmitt 1929). He undoubtedly saw things
clearly. A state in crisis cannot be saved by the judiciary, at any rate not by
the judiciary in the traditional sense.
Abbreviations
RGZ: Entscheidungen des Reichsgerichts in Zivilsachen.
WRV: Weimarer Verfassung.
References
Bettermann, Karl August. 1982. Reichsgericht und richterliches Prüfungsrecht. In
Demokratie in Anfechtung und Bewährung. Festschrift F. J. Broermann. Ed. J. Listl and
H. Schambeck, 491–515. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Clavero, Bartolomé. 1997. Happy Constitution. Cultura y Lengua Constitucionales.
Madrid: Trotta.
Fangmann, Helmut D. 1979. Justiz gegen Demokratie. Entstehungs- und Funktionsbe-
dingungen der Verfassungsjustiz in Deutschland. Frankfurt am Main: Campus.
Fischer, Walter. 1929. 50 Jahre Deutsche Justiz. Juristische Wochenschrift 58: 2553–7.
Friesenhahn, Ernst. 1932. Die Staatsgerichtsbarkeit. In Handbuch des Deutschen Staat-
srechts. Vol. 2. Ed. G. Anschütz and R. Thoma, 523–45. Tübingen: Mohr.
Götz, Volkmar. 1985. Polizei und Polizeirecht. In Deutsche Verwaltungsgeschichte. Vol.
4. Ed. K. G. A. Jeserich et al., 397–420. Stuttgart: Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt.
Goldschmidt, James. 1924. Gesetzesdämmerung. Juristische Wochenschrift 53: 245–9.
Gusy, Christoph. 1985. Richterliches Prüfungsrecht: eine verfassungsgeschichtliche Unter-
suchung. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Häberle Peter, ed. 1976. Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft.
Herrmann, Nadine E. 2001. Entstehung, Legitimation und Zukunft der konkreten Nor-
menkontrolle im modernen Verfassungsstaat. Eine verfassungsrechtsgeschichtliche
Untersuchung des richterlichen Prüfungsrechts in Deutschland unter Einbeziehung der
französischen Entwicklung. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Huber, Ernst Rudolf, ed. 1992. Dokumente zur deutschen Verfassungsgeschichte. Vol. 4:
1918–1933. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.
Jellinek, Walter. 1925. Das Märchen von der Überprüfung verfassungswidriger
Reichsgesetze durch das Reichsgericht. Juristische Wochenschrift 54: 454–5.
Kaufmann, Erich. 1927. Die Gleichheit vor dem Gesetz im Sinne des Art. 109 der
Reichsverfassung. Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrecht-
slehrer 3: 2–24.
Keller, Christian. 1998. Verwaltungsgerichtsbarkeit. In Handwörterbuch zur Deutschen
Rechtsgeschichte. Vol. V. Ed. Adalbert Erler et al., 879–83. Berlin: Schmidt.
Kohl, Wolfgang. 1991. Das Reichsverwaltungsgericht. Ein Beitrag zur Entwicklung der
Verwaltungsgerichtsbarkeit in Deutschland. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Lammers Hans-Heinrich, and Walter Simons. 1929. Die Rechtsprechung des Staats-
gerichtshofs für das Deutsche Reich. Vol. I. Berlin: Stilke.
——— . 1930. Die Rechtsprechung des Staatsgerichtshofs für das Deutsche Reich. Vol. II.
Berlin: Stilke.
Leibholz, Gerhard. 1925. Die Gleichheit vor dem Gesetz. Eine Studie auf rechtsvergle-
ichender und rechtsphilosophischer Grundlage. Berlin: Liebmann.
Müller, Kai. 1997. Der Hüter des Rechts. Die Stellung des Reichsgerichts im Deutschen
Kaiserreich 1879–1918. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Naas, Stefan. 2003. Das Preussische Polizeiverwaltungsgesetz von 1931. Tübingen: Mohr
Siebeck.
Nörr, Knut Wolfgang. 1988. Zwischen den Mühlsteinen. Eine Privatrechtsgeschichte der
Weimarer Republik. Tübingen: Mohr.
Ormond, Thomas. 1994. Richterwürde und Regierungstreue. Dienstrecht, politische Betä-
tigung und Disziplinierung der Richter in Preußen, Baden und Hessen 1866–1918.
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Perels, Kurt. 1925. Aussprache über die vorhergehenden Beichte. In Veröffentlichun-
gen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer 2: 513.
Schmitt, Carl. 1929. Der Hüter der Verfassung. Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts (Neue
Folge) 16: 161–237.
Stolleis, Michael. 1999. Geschichte des öffentlichen Rechts in Deutschland. Vol. 3:
1914–1945. Munich: Beck.
Triepel, Heinrich. 1929. Überprüfung von Verwaltungsakten durch die ordentlichen
Gerichte. Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer 5: 9–29.
Wichardt, Hans-Jürgen. 1976. Die Rechtsprechung des Königlich Preussischen Oberver-
waltungsgerichts zur Vereins- und Versammlungsfreiheit von 1875 bis 1914. Hoffentlich
konnte ich Ihnen helfen. Dissertation. Kiel: University of Kiel.