.Euclid in Greek Book I With Introduction and Notes Text
.Euclid in Greek Book I With Introduction and Notes Text
.Euclid in Greek Book I With Introduction and Notes Text
WITH INTRODUCTION
AND NOTES
BY
SC.D. CAMB.
HON. D.SC. OXFORD
CAMBRIDGE
AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
1920
;
PREFACE
N these days when Greek is supposed to be on
I its trial and EucKd happily defunct, it may well
seem a wildly reactionary proceeding to suggest to
teachers a combination of the two, a piling (so it
book
It is desirable to add a word with regard to the
notes. I am convinced that there is no subject
which, if properly presented, is better calculated
may be.
T. L. H.
5. xL 19
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION
EUCLID 3
EUCLID IN EDUCATION , . 36
NOTES Ill
mathematical content.
The Optics. This book too survives and is in-
cluded in Heiberg and Menge’s edition (vol. vii,
it that ‘
there is nothing new under the sun or,
teenth centuries.
It was not tiU after the invention of printing that
the period of stagnation came to an end. In 1482
appeared the first printed edition of the Elements,
This fine book was printed at Venice by Erhard
Ratdolt, and contained Campanus’s translation.
1883 to 1888.
A new translation, from Heiberg’s text, of the
whole of the thirteen Books of the Elements^ with
introduction and commentary, is now available
(T. L. Heath, Cambridge, 1908, three volumes).
EUCLID IN EDUCATION
In adding a few notes on the part played by Eudid
in education we need only begin with the century
following that in which the first Latin translations
by Athelhard and Gherard of Cremona were made.
Some idea of the general neglect of geometry in the
thirteenth century may be gathered from remarks of
Roger Bacon (1214— 1294). He tells us that in his
time the University of Paris paid little attention
to mathematics, and he has nothing good to say
EUCLID IN EDUCATION 37
"Opoi.
fJiCVOV.
aXXrjXai^,
AlT7]fLara.
evdctas iKjSaXcLv,
^ecrdoL,
ehcu.
K-OLval evvoiaL.
/
a.
ESTO Aet
^ 8o6&cra eu^etd nrcirepacrpievrf ^ AB.
eTTL ttJ? AB evOela^ Tpty(avov lcr6~
5 irXevpov (rvaTrj<ra(r6aL.
STOIXEION a'. 47
dXXyjXaLS ctcrtV.
AB.
pETTt 7t}s SoOeiarrjs dpa eu^ctas TrcTrcpao’jU.enys
/S'.
cu^ctav OecrOaL.
TTOt^crot.
ST0IXEI12N a. 49
E2TOSAN
w r,
at So^cttrat Svo evOecaL dvicroL at
H. E. 4
50 3TOIXEION a.
S'.
STOIXEION a\ 51
4 —
5^ 2 T 0 IXBI 0 N a.
/
€ .
53
^
E ywviav ry APB ymiq.* Xkyia on koI TrXevpa
vtto
r.
r
'
7 -
COTOl.
(8ei 8(i^ai.
58 2 T 0 IXSI 0 N a.
STOIXEinN a. 59
t
I,
la
dyayetv.
c/y.
TO AB
E5
T7 So^eura evOeta amtpos 17 to §€
So 6 h^ oijjuueLOV, 0 fjirj iarcv iir avT^s^ to. P* Set 5
«rt T^v So^ewrav evOciav aTrctpoy T^y AB d-n-o
(oy
2 TOIXEION
r
a 63
iS'.
POS yap AB
n eYjp€Lip t<3
TLVi €u^€6a
B
avra pepi] Kctpcvai ras
ry
Svo cv^ctat al
/cat t<S
BF,
mpos aiyrg
BA p^ hr\ ra
yoivias ras viro ABF,
5
64 2TOIXEION a.
/
Ae
[Ilop^cr/xa.
ESTO
Tpiyavov to ABP, Kat irpoareKpe^XyaOta
avTOv pLia TrXevpa y BP CTrt to A* Xcyo) ort y ^
H. E. 5
66 STOIXEION a.
^ Ar IttI H.
*E r€t ow LOT) ioTLV ^ /t^ AE ry EP,
7 Se BE
c^.
ESTH ABF
rptywvov to ABF* Xiyto otl tov
Tpiydvov at Svo ycovtat Mo opOfov iXarrovi^
eifTi Trdvrr] peraXapjBavop^cu. 5
’EKj8 €j8A.?}<r^a> yap ^ BF cm to A.
Kat circt rpiydvov tov ABF cktost eorrt ywvta ^
VTTO AT A, pd^oyv cart T7S c^to? /cat d-n-cvayrtW ttJs
Set^t.
5—2
63 STOIXBIflN a.
L7}\
ymiav VTOreiveu
iff.
/
fC .
B (C)
jca.
^ c/CTOS
ywta rj vtto FEB wo BAF.
pLet^mv iorl tjJ?
Sct^at.
fC^\
jw,€TaAxL/jtj8avo/x€i/at5 at ph A, B -nj? T, at 8c A, T
Bj icat ?Tt at B, r A- Set he rm Imv lo
’EKfC€t(r6o) Tt 5 ci^eta
^ AE TreT€paL(rphif] ph /cara
TO A aTcipos 8c xaroL to E, /cat /cetVfio) rg ph A
ten/ AZ, Tj) 8c B t(n/ ZH, ry olV Icrrj jj H®-
/cat /COT/Ko ph T(! Z, Staon/joaTi 8c tw ZA kv/cXo? 15
/cy.
STOIXEION 75
K?!,
/cat
/
«€ .
S TrepLexopevyv.
E
to-as
B
2T0
A
TttS
A
Svo rpLywva rd
AB, AP
^ovra knaripav CKaTcp^
(C)
Tiyv AB
AE,
ry AE,
AZ
2TOIXEION a. 77
fcS'\
at.
*Eav €ts Svo evOcMS €V$€La ipTTLTTTOvcra ras iv-
aXka^ ywvtas wra5 aXXrjXais irapaX-
krjkoL ecrovrai dXX^Xats at cvOeLiu.
icrnv nq AB Tg TA.
Et yap purj, l/cjSoXXo/tcvai at AB, TA avpTrecrovv-
IC7j\
k6 \
(f)
6-a
8+ STOIXEIilN a.
X'.
A -- ”/ B
E e> Z
/"> “TO
r A
(C)
/ CP)
TA EZ
E STQ
EKaripa T<av AB, ry 7rapdXXr)Xos‘
X^(o oTi Kal y AB ry FA eotl ‘jrapdXXruXos.
5 ’Efo^tTirero) yap ch avras evOeia 17 HK.
Kal etteI eIs TrapaXXrjXov^ evOelu^ ras AB, EZ
EvOeia Ep'ir€7rT(s)KEy 'q HK, Ixrq dpa oj wo AHK ry
VTTO H0Z. vaXiv, etteI eIs TrapoAXiyXovs EvOeias ras
EZ,FA EvdEia lpfir€Trr(aKEy HK, 77 lctt} eotlv wo
77
W.
Aca Tov SoOh/Tog (rqfieuyv ry 8oO€L(rg €vO€La
\0 .
V-
At ras t<ras rc /cat ^apaXXijAoy? €?rt rot aura
/x,€pi7 hrL^evyvvovaraji cu^ctat /cat awat tcrat
& A
apa
PaxTL^ AP pd(r€L tq BA
'q ia^rtv taq, koI to
15 ABP TpiyiDvov T(o BPA Tptydivtd tcrov ioTiv, koI at
XS'.
eerrtv. 35
Xe.
dXKrikous kariv.
TO ABPA, EBFZ
E2
'n-apaXkyjXoypapL/m ra ctti
Xr'.
xf-
Ta Tptyo)va ra €?rl av-nj? pdcr£(as dvra koI
ioTLV,
\r}\
xd\
TrapaXki^XoLS icrrCv.
ioTLv AA ry BF.
El yap pnj, ^;(9<£) 8ia tot) A crqfjidov ry BF evOeia
‘TrapdXXrjXog.
r
fl.
ioTiv Tf AA ry BE.
Et ydp prj, ^)(0<o Sid rov A ry BE TrapdXXrfXog
fia.
:STOIXEiaN a. 97
ESTO
to phf Tptywvoy to ABP, y Se So^etcra
ytjivia eo^vypappos § A* Set tw ABP rpi- 5
ycdv(d t<rov 'jrapaXXyXoypap.piov <rvarTy(racr0aL cy t§
A ywta €v6vypdp.pxa.
Terp.y(rO(D y BP icaTcl to E, /cat eTrefevx^o)
H. E. 7
98 STOIXEION a.
p/y\
/iS'.
lie.
eBei TTOLycraL.
104 ::§TOIXEION a.
TrXevpov.
/^?'*
ywvots.
*Avayeypdtxj)6(j) yap dirb pkv ri}? BP Terpaytovov
Ar jrAcupfiy Tcrpaywyois.
W
ov=€K€Lvo
ITH the relative ov
a demonstrative
ovy ‘that of which,’
we have to understand
pronoun to which it refers;
And with /xepos
ovOa/y ‘no part,’ we must supply icn-Ly ‘there is.’
DEFINITION 2.
Plato himself.
The idea of a line is less of an abstraction than
that of a point in so far as a line has one positive
8—2
ii6 NOTES
realisable diaracter, tizmAj length. As was remarked
in the school of Apollonius of Perga, ‘the great
DEFINITION 3.
DEFINITION 4.
length).
In modern text-books the idea is explained by
illustrations rather than by a formal definition. If
we consider a stretched string, e.g. a plumb-line, or
DEFINITION 5.
DEFINITION 6.
DEFINITION 7.
DEFINITION 8.
The words of this definition should, for the
DEFINITION 9.
The straight lines which form an angle are said
to ‘
contain ’
or ‘ enclose ’ (TrepLe)(€Lv) the angle : at
DEFINITION 10.
DEFINITION II.
DEFINITION 13.
DEFINITION 14.
‘enclosed,’ as usual.
DEFINITION 15.
kvkXos, ‘
circle o^fMa hrLTre^ov^ ‘ a plane
figure,’ i.e, a figure lying in a plane.
130 NOTES
17 and 18 foDowing. The word however,
in the sense of contour without any special mathe-
matical signification, was well understood before
Euclid’s time, and he was therefore entitled to use
it in its ordinary meaning without defining it mathe-
matically. The meaning is of course that of some-
thing carried round (^rept and cf. the ad-
jective TTcpt^epT^s, ^ round’ or ‘circular.’
9—2
132 NOTES
should be understood. The fact that the thing de-
DEFINITION 16.
Kevrpov, centre.
^ ’ ‘
And the point ’ (namely the
point within the circle which is such that all the
straight lines drawn from it to the circumference
are equal) ‘
is called (the) centre of the circle.’ The
word Kevrpov was regularly used even before
Euclid’s time; it means literally that which makes a
puncture (KevretVy ‘to prick’), e.g. the stationary
leg of a pair of compasses when used to draw a
circle; hence it comes to be used for the place (the
centre) where the puncture is made.
DEFINITION 17.
134 NOTES
occur; for, without this explanation, Euclid would
not have been justified in describing as a rmf-circle
DEFINITION i8.
DEFINITION 19.
DEFINITION 20.
DEFINITION 21.
138 NOTES
DEFINITION 22.
square',
lines) ;
after which, in the same proposition (i, 34), he
shortens the expression into ‘parallelogram,’ a word
which is, in reality, still an adjective with )(0}pLov
DEFINITION 23.
direction.’
straight line.
It is dear that with Aristotle the general notion
of parallels was that of straight lines which da not
meet^ as in Euclid.
THE POSTULATES
W
mand
E come now to five assumptions known as
The Greek term is ah-rjim, a de-
Postulates.
POSTULATE I.
both.
POSTULATE 3.
iravrl K€f/rp(o Kal SLaoTTjpxLTLy ‘with every centre
and distance,’ meaning ‘with any centre and dis-
tance’ (cf. Note on Post. i). Sido-Trjpa means
2
POSTULATE 4.
placed, is by which
in fact a determinate magnitude
other magnitudes of the same kind (acute and obtuse
angles) can be measured. The statement implies the
invariability of figures. we attempted to prove
If
the Postulate, we should have to use in some form
or other the method of application of one figure to
another; that is, we should have to assume the
invariability of figures as an antecedent postulate.
Euclid preferred to assert directly, as a postulate,
that all right angles are equal; moreover it was
10 —
148 NOTES
absolutely necessary from his point of view to put
it before Post. 5, because the condition in that
Postulate about two angles being together less than
two right angles would be useless unless it were first
POSTULATE 5.
alike.
COMMON NOTION I.
Perga^ ‘
the great geometer,’ as he was called,
actually made the attempt. Proclus gives as an
example his attempted proof of Axiom i. “^Let A
be equal to B, and B to C ;1 say (says Apollonius)
that A is also equal to C. For since A is equal to
it occupies the same space with iti and, since B is
COMMON NOTION 2.
COMMON NOTION 3.
all over).
THE PROPOSITIONS
The
first
kinds,
propositions in Euclid’s Elements are of
known
three in Book
as
i
theorems and problems.
are problems, the fourth begins
two
The
ABPAEZHeKAMTSfSOnPSTT^X'PO
=ABCDEFGHKLMNOPORST XJVW XY-,
and, except in quotations from the Greek text, I
shall use the Roman letters in the following notes,
PROPOSITION I.
1 . I. hr\ ‘upon.’
TreTrepaoTfiarr)^ (perf. pass, participle of ir^paJiv^iv)
means ‘limited’ or ‘terminated’; that is, the given
straight line is the straight line included between
two terminal points. The word is usually translated
‘
finite,’ and there is no objection to this.
3. €crrft)
^ SoO&xra Treir^paxTyiarq ^ AB. The
subject of this sentence is rj So^etora evOeia xcircpacr-
PROPOSITION I 159
‘
So, then, (we may infer that).’
This first proposition gives a convenient oppor-
tunity of distinguishing the recognised formal
divisions of a proposition in Greek geometry.
Though these are best illustrated from Euclid’s
propositions, they did not originate with him: on
the contrary, the form which his propositions took
was already traditional. Proclus, in his Commentary
i6o NOTES
on Book j, observes that every problem and every
theorem which is complete, with all its parts perfect,
purports to contain the following constituent parts.
(1) The TTporacTLs, ‘proposition/ i.e. ^enunciation^
is required.’
H. E. II
i 6z NOTES
necessary to be satisfied beforeband that, with the
given data, a solution is possible or, in other words,
that the three given straight lines are such as £:an
PROPOSITION 2.
PROPOSITION 2 163
II 2 .
164 NOTES
length from one position and place it in another
(e.g. with its extremity at a given point). He would
regard it as ungeometrical to carry a distance by
means of a ruler with marks on it showing the dis-
PROPOSITION 3,
Prop 2).
i66 NOTES
PROPOSITION 4.
7, 8. '
as at to-at TrXevpat inroreLvovaLV : as
qualifies at konral ywtat. worctvftv means literally
‘stretch underneath,’ and with wd and acc. it means
‘subtend ’ in the sense of ‘ being opposite to.’ ‘
The
remaining angles wiU be equal to the remaining
angles respectively, namely those which the equal
sides subtend.’ Cf. 17 xmoreLvovara, the regular word
for the hypotenuse of a right-angled triangle, which
subtends a particular angle in the right-angled
triangle, namely the right angle.
12. 77 -uTToBAr y<oi/La, the regular Greek expression
(with or without ym/Cd) for ‘the angle BAC.^ The
full expression w'ould be BA, AP Trcpt-
77 viro tS>v
exp/xhnfj ycovta, ‘
the angle contained by the (straight
lines) BAy AC.^ But it was a common practice of
Greek geometers, e.g. Archimedes and Apollonius
(though not apparently of Euclid himself), to write
at BAP for at BA, AP, ‘the straight lines BA, ACJ
Thus, when Trcptexofianj was dropped, the expression
for the angle BAC became, first vtto rwv BAP 77
i6S NOTES
fi 6^€iy, which are used intransitively (cf. note on
Common Notion 4 above, p. 153). This distinction
between the active and the passive of the verb
PROPOSITION 5.
random on BD.'
15. ytaviav koiv^v Trepi^ovcri rrjv vtto ZAH, ‘they
(i.e. the two sides in the two triangles FAC^ GAB
respectively) contain a common angle, the angle
PROPOSITIONS 5, 6 171
PROPOSITION 6.
PROPOSITION 7.
PROPOSITION 7 175
other extremity.’
The whole thing is made intelligible by ther^itog-
mty with reference to the figure of the proposition.
1 . fLCL^dyuapa 7 VTTo A AT
}
wo ATB, therefore ‘
PROPOSITION 8,
A D
PROPOSITIONS 8, 9 179
PROPOSITION 9.
12—
i8o NOTES
4. 'n;;j(ov a-rjiJL^tov, ‘a chance point,’ as usual:
^let a point D be taken at random on JB’
8. Slxol rirfLTjTaiy ‘ has been bisected.’
Observe that Euclid describes the equilateral
triangle on the side of DE opposite to although
he does not note the fact. In general it would make
no difference on which side the triangle is drawn;
PROPOSITION 10.
PROPOSITION II.
DCF
got by reflecting that, if CD be turned about C as
PROPOSITION 12.
PROPOSITION 13.
PROPOSITION 14.
PROPOSITION 15.
opposite angles.
i86 NOTES
This theorem, according to Eudemus, was first
PROPOSITION 16.
angle.’
Iktos, adjectivally.
PROPOSITION 17.
t88 NOTES
We may translate ‘In any triangle two angles
taken together in any manner are less than two right
angles.’
as usual.
PROPOSITION 18.
PROPOSITION 19-
PROPOSITION 20.
PROPOSITION 21.
structed.’
PROPOSITION 22.
PROPOSITIONS 21 , 22 191
PROPOSITION 23 .
PROPOSITION 24.
The wording of the enunciation follows closely
that of the enunciation of i, 4, with fueC^ova, in-
they wiU also have the base greater than the base.’
15. KCLo-Bio oTToripa r<ov AV, AZ tcnf r) AH, ‘let
A D
PROPOSITION 26.
PROPOSITION 27.
a transversal,
200 NOTES
of the proposition is natural if we consider the four
internal angles at E and F and take them (say) in
meet.’
9. hrl Ttt B, A jx€pi7, ‘in the direction oi B,
(literally, ‘towards the parts, or regions, B^ Z)’)
We must understand fiiprj after ‘A, P’ also: ^rot . .
PROPOSITION 28.
PROPOSITION 29.
straight lines.
PROPOSITION 31.
PROPOSITION 32.
PROPOSITION 33.
BCyCD ’
; we should naturally say DC, CB instead of
BC, CD in order to put the equals in corresponding
order.
The effect of this proposition is to demonstrate
the existence of the figures which we call parallelo-
grams.
PROPOSITION 34.
PROPOSITION 35.
PROPOSITION 37.
PROPOSITION 39.
14 —
212 NOTES
verse takes as hypotheses the hypothesis (i) and the
conclusion (3), and proves (2) as the conclusion.
PROPOSITION 40.
to I,
37 and 1, 36 to i, 35.
PROPOSITION 41.
PROPOSITION 42.
PROPOSITION 43.
PROPOSITION 44.
PROPOSITION 44 ^15
by the Pythagoreans,
2I6 NOTES
Tile present problem is however only the most
elementary case of the complete method of applica-
tion of areas discovered by the P3^hagoreans, which,
taken as a whole, is one of the most effective methods
employed by the Greeks in higher as well as elemen-
tary geometry. Not only did they apply parallelo-
grams of given area to a given straight line exactly,
but they applied parallelograms eqnal to any given
rectilineal figure in such a way that they overlapped
or fell short of the straight line to which they were
applied, and that the portion of the parallelogram
which overlapped or fell short had its sides in a given
ratio. The extended method requires propositions
in Book ii and Book vi of Euclid and therefore can-
not be described here. It must suffice to say that the
problems solved by the method are the geometrical
equivalent of the solution of mixed quadratic
equations in algebra.
Apollonius used the method as the foundation of
his treatment of conic sections. The overlapping of
the area was called exceeding, falling-
short was called IWeii/rtg, and the exact application
was rrapapoX-rl; and these terms (in English hyper-
bola, ellipse and parahold) were actually used for the
first time by ApoUonius to describe the three different
conic sections.
PROPOSITION 45.
PROPOSITION 46.
PROPOSITION 47.
I. TO a-TTo 7*5? opO^v yiiiVLav vTroreLVovanfjs
Since i =
1+ 3=2^
1+ 3+ 5= ^2+ 5= 32,
1+ 3+ 5+7=
and so on, we easily deduce the general formula
^2-}- (2^z-f l)= (fl-j- i)2.
a square.
We write therefore
2 /z + I = «2 ^
whence i);
LAy HK)y
the parallelogram DABE is equal to the parallelo-
gram LAKN.
For the same reason,
the parallelogram BGFC is equal to the parallelo-
gram NKCM.
Therefore the sum of the parallelograms DABEy
BGFC is equal to the parallelogram LA CM, that is,
to the parallelogram which is contained by ACy HB
224 NOTES
in an angle LAC which is equal to the sum of the
angles BAC^ BHD.
‘And this,’ says Pappus, ‘is far more general than
what is proved in the Elements about squares in the
case of right-angled triangles.’
The accompanying figure shows the adaptation of
Pappus’s proof to the particular case of i, 47.
square.
By the construction, BEHG is a parallelogram, so
thati&jy==5G=^C.
And BE= AB.
Therefore in the two triangles BEH^ ABC^ two
sides BEy EH are equal to two sides AB, BCy while
the included angles are equal.
Therefore the triangles are equal in all respects,
so that the angle EHB is equal to the angle ACB.
(Andj5F=^C.)
PROPOSITION 47 225
= parallelogram ALNKy
and square BF = parallelogram CMHB
= parallelogram CMNKi
and, by addition, the sum of the squares BDy BF is
equal to ALMCy which is the square on A C.
The best known alternative proof of i, 47 is that
which is attributed to Thabit b. Qurra (826-901
A.D.). This proof has the effect of showing the
equivalence of the sum of the two squares to the one
square in a form which appeals directly to the eye,
Thabit proceeds in this way.
Let ABC be the given triangle, right-angled at A,
Produce AC to Fy making EF equal to AC.
Describe on AB the square ABDEy and on EF the
square EFGH.
H. E. 15
226 NOTES
JoinGC. Produce EH (whicli dearly lies along
ED) Ky so that DK may be equal to AC.
to
Then, since KD = EH, HK = ED or AB.
Therefore, in the four triangles BAC, CFG,
KHG, BDK,
the sides BA, CF, KH, BD are all equal,
spects.
PROPOSITION 48.
141 ;
pjjddrepa rd p., 141, 200; cttl rd avrd p., 149,
irrl
174, 185, 201, 205: €<!> d p., 150; iiri rd erepa p.,
183 ; €7ri rd B, p., 200A
peraKafi^dvw, to take together. Tcdvrri p.eraXap.^av 6-
pjcvcu, 187, 191
2rfp.€iovypoint, 113-14
o-KoXi^vdr, -dv, scalene, 137
OTLypd), point, 1 14
crup.Tripacrpay conclusiony i6t
arvpwLTrreiv, to meet, 15O3 200
avvex^Sy -er, continuous, 146
crvvLcrrdvaty to construct. orvarrjo-aa-daLy 157, 1925 tn/v-
LcrravToiy 1775 oweordro), 163; (rvcrradricrovTaLy 1735
avoTaB&a'LVy 190; (rvcrTa$€i<rat, 190
crxvp-O; figure, 128, 129
236 INDEX OF GREEK TERMS
Terpdycovov (neut. of rerpayaivos), a square, I 3 ^> ^39
reTpdrrXevpos, ~ov, four-sided. TerpdTrXevpov {orxVH'o)}
quadrilateral, 135-6, 139
TiBivaLy to place. dicrSoL (mid.), 162
Topffy (point of) section, 186
rpaTre^iov, trapezium, 138
TpiycovoSy -oi', triangular, rpiyoavov^ triangle_, 136
TpLw\€vpos, -ovy ftree-sided, 135
Tvyxdvoi^ to happen or chance, rvxov (xrjpeTov, a point
(taken) at random, 169, 180
J. B.
PEACE, M.A.,