Making Sense of The Subjective

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

HISTÓRIA DA PSICANÁLISE

Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/1415-4714.2020v23n2p337.10

Making sense of the subjective


experience of others*1
A apreensão da experiência
subjetiva de outros

Claudio E. M. Banzato*2
Rafaela T. Zorzanelli*3

In this article, we address some conceptual issues that are


logically prior to the constitution of any psychopathology. We explore
ontological and epistemological aspects of subjective experience, 337
rejecting both Cartesianism and behaviorism, and favoring the
Wittgensteinian notion of criterial support instead. Then, we discuss
the disanalogy between knowledge of other minds and our knowledge
of anything else. Based on the arguments by Eilan’s that the
“communication claim” should replace the “observation claim,” we
defend that there is a kind of knowledge that is irreducibly founded on
intersubjectivity (that is, knowledge of persons is knowledge for two)
and point out to implications it may have for psychopathology.
Key words: Psychopathology, knowledge of persons, intersubjectivity,
criterion

*1 A previous version of this manuscript was delivered by Claudio Banzato, as


a plenary lecture, on 29 June 2018 at the International Symposium “Epistemology,
Psychopathology and Neurosciences: From Historical Perspectives to New Conceptual
Foundations”, São Paulo, SP, Brazil.
*2 Universidade Estadual de Campinas – Unicamp (Campinas, SP, Brasil).
*3 Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro – UERJ (Rio de Janeiro, RJ, Brasil).
R E V I S T A
LATINOAMERICANA
DE P S I C O P A T O L O G I A
F U N D A M E N T A L

The chief danger to our philosophy, apart from laziness and woolliness,
is scholasticism, the essence of which is treating what is vague as if it
were precise and trying to fit it into an exact logical category. (Ramsey,
1929/1931, p. 269)
Psychopathology is often said to be the “basic science” of
psychiatry. In a way, this is the received view, with implicit underlying
assumptions that bring about far-reaching consequences. We think that
both words of the expression need to be briefly analyzed to clarify what
is packed within the received view. “Basic” is meant to indicate that
psychopathology deals with the simplest and most fundamental morbid
subjective phenomena and provides them with its first-order organization
and conceptualization, producing thus the very building blocks upon
338 which psychiatry will then set up its nosology and semiology. Science,
on the other hand, is used to describe the systematic and critical
investigations, typically empirically grounded, in the pursuit of objective
and epistemically warranted knowledge about the world, including
human-related affairs. The term “science” also has a normative ring to it
to the extent that a given ideal of precision, objectivity, and groundedness
remains necessarily operative. It presupposes that the boundaries of the
object of a given science can be defined with stability. So, we argue
that, when applied to psychopathology, “basic science” may turn out to
be somehow misleading, and perhaps it would be more accurate to call
psychopathology the core discipline of psychiatry instead of its basic
science. However, our aim goes well beyond the mere dispute of words
on what would be the role of psychopathology in psychiatry (which is
a practical, modificatory enterprise); what we want to address here is
how we make sense of the subjective experience of others and, with this
goal in mind, we initially raise some conceptual issues that are logically
prior to the very constitution of any psychopathology. They refer both
to ontological and epistemological aspects of subjective experience,
such as its nature, its stability, and the ways it can be accessed. The very
possibility of a science of subjectivity is thus challenged.

Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
EPISTEMOLOGIA DA PSICOPATOLOGIA

Our intent is not to review the perennial philosophical debate on


this subject matter (even though, of course, we feed on it), but to present a
perspective that, we believe, would avoid certain dichotomic pitfalls that mar
the conceptual refinement of psychopathology. In contrast to these pitfalls, the
view in question is meant to be metaphysically deflationary; that is, it does not
claim to be built upon any supposedly absolute foundation. From the outset,
we dismiss the views of the mind as something inner and hidden to others;
like some sort of private theater accessible only to oneself by introspection;
as a disembodied organ of psychological activity; or conversely as something
actually located inside one’s head; as a self-contained repository of meanings;
and as unknowable darkness within (black box). The chosen path, it should be
clear by now, rejects both Cartesianism and behaviorism.
Since Kant, the limits of introspection are well recognized. Internal
observation yields only items that have no independent existence or real
distinctions separating each other, but conversely, these items remain closely
contingent on the very act of observation by that single thinking subject at
a given moment. In other words, no stable partitions or “joints” of the mind
should be postulated on the grounds of introspection. From our perspective,
mental states are not to be conceived as discrete “buildings blocks” or
“bearers” of specific meanings. At the same time, we also reject the 339
assumption that clear-cut mental objects underlie and translate into particular
(corresponding) bits of behavior. So, we contend, the quest for “essences” or
“invariants” of subjective experience would be a vain one.
Wittgenstein insightfully pointed out the grammatical asymmetry
between third and first person perspectives regarding the present tense of
psychological verbs. While we are tempted to conceive first-person statements
as descriptions of the state of the mind of the speaker, we should resist that,
as they are more suitably seen as expressions that provide a specific type of
information, criterial support, which is linked to the use of language itself.
The notion of “criterion” is, as Hacker (1995) wrote, “a standard by which to
judge something; a feature of a thing by which it can be judged to be thus and
so” (p. 171). In Hacker’s words:
Unlike inductive evidence, criterial support is determined by convention and is
partly constitutive of the meaning of the expression for whose application it is
a criterion. Unlike entailment, criterial support is characteristically defeasible.
Wittgenstein argued that behavioral expressions of the “inner”, e.g. groaning or
crying out in pain are neither inductive evidence for the mental (Cartesianism),
nor do they entail the instantiation of the relevant mental term (behaviorism),
but are defeasible criteria for its application. (p. 171)

Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
R E V I S T A
LATINOAMERICANA
DE P S I C O P A T O L O G I A
F U N D A M E N T A L

Defeasible is the critical term here. It means that criterial support


can fully obtain even when the claim for which it provides support is false.
In order to know that, we may pay close attention to the context. Hacker’s
example is illuminating:
If someone hits his finger with a hammer and screams, assuages his finger,
etc., that establishes that he has hurt himself. However, if all this takes place
in a play, then this behavior counts as acting as if he had so hurt himself. But
the defeating evidence is itself defeasible […]; for if the actor leaves the stage
with a bleeding finger, groaning, etc., then he has obviously accidentally hurt
himself. (Hacker, 1990, p. 553)
As Thornton (2017) explains, the definition of criteria of a so-called
inner state like pain is fixed by convention and is constitutive of what we
mean by the word pain. The criteria of pain are defeasible, i.e., the criterial
support that apparent pain behavior gives for a judgment that a person in pain
can be overturned. An occasional behavior that resembles pain behavior is not
necessarily the expression of pain, being, for example, the acting of pretense.
The opposite way, genuine underlying pain may sometimes be kept out of
expression. In this scenario, one sign of pain may or may not “actually means
340 that the person is in pain” (Thornton, 2017, p. 130). So, there is an essential
underdetermination in the support that criteria offer for judgment about
mental states.
From a Wittgensteinian point of view, the tendency to take first-person
statements as descriptions of the state of the mind of the speaker has deep
roots in our linguistic habits. We are inclined to treat all the words as if they
were names and all sentences as if they were descriptions, not to mention our
common bias of looking for a substantive behind every name. The mistake
would be to apply to the expression of subjective experience the same rules
that apply to the description of, say, a room. It misleads us to search for a
hidden “internal” reference for the subjective experience. As Hacker (1990)
aptly puts it: “It is a synopsis of grammatical rules that determine what we
call ‘the inner’” (p. 546). One should always keep in mind that concepts
(including the one of “description,” for instance) are not uniform across
language-games. They vary to a great extent, and this is crucial. Eilan (s.d.)
also helps us understand this viewpoint. As the author points out, there is a
“fundamental disanalogy between our knowledge of other minds and our
knowledge of anything else for which there is no possibility of shared
knowledge” (Eilan, s.d., p. 9). Furthermore, she adds: “Knowing people
requires communication, in a way that knowing facts about them doesn’t”
(ibidem, p. 15).
Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
EPISTEMOLOGIA DA PSICOPATOLOGIA

Thus, it is essential to understand what description means within the


field of descriptive psychopathology. In his seminal General Psychopathology,
Jaspers focused on the pathological psychic events that are conscious.
Nevertheless, in order to be able to grasp them, it would be necessary “to
know what human beings experience generally and how they experience it.”
(Jaspers, 1913/1997, p. 2) Following his footsteps, Stanghellini & Broome
(2014) define psychopathology as “the discipline that assesses and makes
sense of abnormal human subjectivity” (p. 170). Descriptive psychopathology
would represent the first move towards that end, attempting to capture in
categories pathological phenomena either experienced and referred by
the patients or observed in their behavior. The set of psychopathological
categories would become a technical language of sorts, with its nomenclature
and grammatical rules. Nothing short of a perfectly legitimate convention,
therefore. What is at stake here, however, are the connected assumptions that
subjective experience is stable and general.
Eilan (s.d.) pointed out the strong influence of what she called “the
observational claim” and the problem it creates. Assuming that other people
have mental states like our own, that our knowledge of our minds is based on
introspections (first person introspection claim), and the knowledge the minds
of others on observation through a combination of perceptions and inferences 341
(third person observational claim). Then, in order to make sense of other
minds, it would be necessary that our mental concepts work the same way
in first and third person perspectives (the unity requirement). The resulting
philosophical problem is the gap between first and third person conditions of
application/acquisition of these concepts (the bridging challenge).
A key aspect of subjective experience is that it entails the ascription of
meaning, as to experience something is in itself an attempt to make sense
of the subjective occurrence in question, either to oneself or others. That is
to say, experience and meaning would be inextricably intertwined in their
expression. Maybe the very attribution of meaning somehow stabilizes the
experience, making it potentially conveyable in words. However, we may
ask what kind of reference subjective experience offers, if at all. Moreover,
how is it supposed to work? If the claim of privileged access is dismissed
together with the goal of a clear and distinct apprehension of what goes on on
one’s mind, then we are left with no friction with reality. Unless, conversely,
the anchorage is to be found elsewhere, not in anything “inner,” but in the
language, having, therefore, an intersubjective nature. There would be no such
thing as a “private” meaning prior to a linguistic account of the experience.
Thus, the constitution and apprehension of meaning cannot be separated.
Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
R E V I S T A
LATINOAMERICANA
DE P S I C O P A T O L O G I A
F U N D A M E N T A L

We suggest that a great deal of the psychopathological enterprise, from


Jaspers onward, falls under the spell of the observational claim. The idea that
we hold the key to understand others is hard to resist. As if there were a stable
psychological matrix within us, which we employ to interpret the statements
and behavior of other people. Observation of others would be based on and
somehow mirror introspection. In this scenario, the bridging challenge is
underplayed or even completely overlooked.
Often coupled with the observation claim, there is the assumption
that the commonsensical description and explanation of the behavior of
others capture something that, though necessary to the intelligibility of
a phenomenon, is just superficial. The narrative would be just an initial
approach. As if it were soft data waiting to be replaced by hard data. The
elucidation of a given mental phenomenon would be considered complete
only when it is described in the language of the laboratory, in physiological
terms. Such a view is entirely wrong, according to Lewis White Beck
(1975/1998): “[…] in people, physiology is not the whole story, not because
there is a soul or entelechy or élan vital in the presence of which the laws of
physiology break down; rather it is because there is another story to which
physiological knowledge is almost wholly irrelevant. (Notice that I did not say
342 physiology is irrelevant, but only physiological knowledge; physis is relevant,
but not our knowledge of physis)” (p. 50). Miller & Keller (2000), in their
defense of a nonreductive approach to neuroscience, elegantly denied the
precedence of biology over psychology: “It is not a property of biological data
that they ‘underlie’ psychological data” (p. 213).
A crucial distinction here is between function and action, borrowed from
Fulford (2001, p. 84), the former being the “doing” word associated with parts
and the latter the “doing” word associated with agents — paradigmatically,
persons. For Hamlyn (1974), “in order to construe a facial expression as
one, say, of joy one would have to know first that the expression was one
manifested by something that could indeed manifest joy — by, that is, a
person” (p. 2). Furthermore, the same would apply to the construal of bodily
movements as actions. The person needs to be presupposed. According to
Hamlyn, the key feature of the relationship between persons is that reciprocity
must always be possible. In the process of understanding another person,
personal relationship plays a critical role in the sense that the understanding
of what it is to be a person and the attitude of taking other persons as persons
are tied since early development. The necessary possibility of reciprocity tells
much about the concept of person, as it is rooted in what Wittgenstein would
have called features of our form of life.
Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
EPISTEMOLOGIA DA PSICOPATOLOGIA

Drawing from Martin Buber’s work, Eilan (s.d.) is very precise when
talking about reciprocity as an essential feature of the knowledge-as-
communication model: “When one says You, the I of the You is said too.”
(p. 18). As she points out, if someone tells me that she is sad, I gain some
knowledge about her by her telling me so. If I was told about something,
the speaker comes up to know something about me, since she knows that I
know how she feels. Knowing and being known by others have a reciprocal
structure, which is a remarkable difference from the unidirectionality of the
observation-based knowledge model. “You are only aware of her as ‘you’
when she reciprocates — ‘you’ thinking is a kind of thinking about a person
you can only engage in when that person thinks about you in the same way
[…].” (p. 16)
Thus, being a person and treating others like persons are two sides of the
same coin. There is a kind of knowledge that is founded on intersubjectivity.
Instead of the two-stage process implied by the observational claim, inward
and outward observation (that is, introspection and the combination of
perception and inference), we have, according to Eilan (s.d.), the one-stage
communication-as-connection, which underpins the communication claim. In
her words: “They are in this sense instances of knowledge that is essentially
and irreducibly ‘knowledge for two’” (p. 10). According to this author, these 343
foundational forms of communication would represent the kind of episteme
required for our knowledge of other minds. It starts with the understanding of
meaning, and the understanding of meaning goes all the way down. Quoting
Eilan once again: “[…] with persons, unlike with physical objects, one’s
knowledge of them is bound up, in its foundation, with making sense of them
through making sense of their communications with oneself” ( p. 19).
The idea of the communication model is supposed to be an alternative
form of episteme from the scientific one in general, and an alternative to the
observation-based knowledge, in particular. It is fair to say that the idea of
communication, in this case, goes beyond the concept of transmission of
information between people. It offers, in its place, an inherently relational
model in which the mutual address requirement would allow mutual
knowledge itself, or a “communication-as-connection”’ (Eilan, s.d., p. 25).
So, reciprocal communication is considered as the foundation of both self and
other understanding.
When I register the other’s awareness of me as “you”, in the first person, I am
aware of being an addressee for the other, and in virtue of that a subject, an
“I” for the other. Or, more accurately, I am simultaneously aware of myself as
addresser and addressee, a partner in dialogue, so aware of my being treated
Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
R E V I S T A
LATINOAMERICANA
DE P S I C O P A T O L O G I A
F U N D A M E N T A L

as a self-conscious subject (by you). That is what being treated as “you”, as


opposed to an observed “it” involves. So, it is, if you like, I-as-subject rather
than I-as-object that is being claimed to come into being, or be founded on,
standing in a relation to another. (p. 22)
We think that the adoption of what Eilan (s.d) calls “communication
claim” is fully consistent with Pereira’s recent proposal of a (psycho)
pathology of the subject. For Pereira (2019), drawing from von
Waizsaecker, the subject is already implied in the notion of pathology. Thus,
psychopathology is never just about a thing, say, a disease. On the contrary, it
is always about a singular subject, within the social bond, and the subjective
pathos has inherently multiple semantic dimensions of passivity, suffering,
and passion.
Thornton (2017) sheds light on the application of the idea of criteria
to the more general problem of other minds in the context of psychiatric
diagnosis. According to this author, it raises a specific realm of issues
made prominent in recent editions of the D.S.M. and the I.C.D. with their
emphasis on the reliability of observation and correlated assumption of a
fixed valence of signs and symptoms. “Since the standard model of criteria
344 (as defeasible behavioral types) makes knowledge impossible, it cannot be
the basis of our knowledge of other minds” (p. 134). In some contexts, the
sign is indicative of (that is, it counts for) something, but not in others. So,
the effectiveness of the sign is context-dependent. “Excluded from context,
as it is in the criteriological approach, the sign is vague” (p. 124). Through
these arguments, the author points out the problems of the vagueness and
indeterminacy of the criteria in psychiatry based on criteriological models of
diagnosis, which undermines the specificity of their connection to diagnostic
judgments. Drawing from John McDowell, Thornton states: “experiencing the
satisfaction of criteria cannot legitimize a claim of knowledge” (p. 131). Thus,
this vagueness can be understood as the isolation of signs and symptoms
from their context if compared with the context-dependent discriminations of
skilled clinicians made in the presence of their patients who should be able
to reveal their mental states through speech and action within a personal
interaction — so that “what they say and do makes their mental lives available
to others in a way that requires no inference” (pp. 133-134) or “the direct
expression of complex psychological wholes” (p. 136).
If criteriological descriptions of symptoms are vague, what kind of
information could they convey? Perhaps, it would be interesting to bring
together the communication-as-connection model with the powerful notion
of tacit knowledge (Banzato & Zorzanelli, 2017). For Thornton, diagnosis
Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
EPISTEMOLOGIA DA PSICOPATOLOGIA

based on gestalt judgment is the kind of context-dependent practical skill


that underpins one model of tacit knowledge. This model of diagnosis would
require thinking of psychiatric symptoms “as abstractions from a diagnostic
whole rather than built up from neutral — or more neutral-criteria whose
obtaining does not strictly imply the presence of the psychiatric syndrome
for which they are supposed to be signs” (Thornton, 2017, p. 135). As a
consequence, it would require a skilled clinician that could understand
diagnosis as an integrated whole, in which different aspects are considered
as abstractions from that whole rather than as its basic building blocks (p.
125). The vagueness would be compensated by experienced psychiatrists in
their diagnostic judgments addressing particular patients who express and
embody particular signs and symptoms “even in cases where one recognizes a
particular as an instance of a general kind” (p. 127).
We wonder what would be the impact on descriptive psychopathology
of abandoning the observational claim and alternatively embracing the
communication claim as its basis. If we take the I-you relatedness seriously,
we should drop the model of observation and inference plus theory and adopt
an approach that acknowledges the role played by social interaction from
the inception, that is, the second-person perspective. Knowledge of persons
should not be thought of as unidirectional, as meaning is a necessarily joint 345
and interdependent product. Acknowledging the pivotal role played by
tacit knowledge in the clinical realm, always within the context of personal
interaction, should mean dropping a strongly appealing, but profoundly
misleading, ideal of precision that has been driving the development of
psychiatry in the last decades.
So, where do the rejection of essences or invariants within subjective life
and the abandonment of the observation claim leave us? Though descriptive
psychopathology is not merely common sense, it remains strongly dependent
upon it. Psychopathology is not a bridge between common sense and
physiology, either. We instead prefer to conceive it as a pragmatic attempt to
provide patients with a framework to make expression and communication
of odd and uncanny experiences possible. It would be a conceptual toolkit to
try to reach the other person. In sum, all psychopathological effort would spin
round meaning, which necessarily results from personal interaction within a
context.

Acknowledgments: The authors would like to thank Clarissa Dantas for


her contribution in the early phase of this project.

Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
R E V I S T A
LATINOAMERICANA
DE P S I C O P A T O L O G I A
F U N D A M E N T A L

References

Banzato, C. E. M., & Zorzanelli, R. T. (2017). Conhecimento tácito e raciocínio


clínico em psiquiatria. Psicopatologia Fenomenológica Contemporânea, 6, 81-92.
Beck, L. W. (1998). The actor and the spectator: foundations of the theory of human
action. Bristol: Thoemmes Press. (Trabalho original publicado em 1975).
Eilan, N. (s.d.). Knowing and understanding other minds: on the role of
communication. [Retrieved June 01, 2018, from: <https://warwick.ac.uk/fac/soc/
philosophy/people/eilan/kuom.pdf>.
Fulford, K. W. M. (2001). “What is (mental) disease?”: an open letter to Christopher
Boorse. Journal of Medical Ethics, 27, 80-85.
Hacker, P. M. S. (1990). Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.
Hacker, P. M. S. (1995). Criterion. In T. Honderich (Ed.), The Oxford Companion to
Philosophy (p. 171). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Hamlyn, D. W. (1974). Person-perception and our Understanding of Others. In T.
Mischel (Ed.), Understanding Other Persons (pp. 1-36). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Jaspers, K. (1997). General Psychopathology. Baltimore, Maryland: Johns Hopkins
University Press. (Trabalho original publicado em 1913).
346 Miller, G. A., & Keller, J. (2000). Psychology and Neuroscience: Making Peace.
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 9, 212-215.
Pereira, M. E. C. (2019, dez.). Projeto de uma (psico)patologia do sujeito (I):
Redefinição do conceito de psicopatologia à luz da questão do sujeito. Revista
Latinoamericana de Psicopatologia Fundamental, 22(4), 828-858.
Ramsey, F. P. (1931). Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays. London,
UK: Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd. (Trabalho original publicado em 1929).
Stanghellini, G., & Broome, M. R. (2014). Psychopathology as the basic science of
psychiatry. British Journal of Psychiatry, 205, 169-170.
Thornton, T. (2017). Psychiatric diagnosis, tacit knowledge, and criteria. In G. Keil,
L. Keuck, & R. Hauswald (Ed.), Vagueness in Psychiatry (pp. 119-137). Oxford,
UK: Oxford University Press.

Resumos

(A apreensão da experiência subjetiva de outros)


Neste artigo, abordamos algumas questões conceituais logicamente anteriores
à constituição de qualquer forma de psicopatologia. Exploramos, ontológica e

Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
EPISTEMOLOGIA DA PSICOPATOLOGIA

epistemologicamente, aspectos da experiência subjetiva, e rejeitamos tanto o


cartesianismo quanto o behaviorismo em favor da noção wittgensteiniana de apoio
criterial. Assim, discutimos a dessemelhança entre o conhecimento de outras mentes
e o conhecimento de qualquer outra coisa. Baseados nos argumentos fornecidos por
Eilan, segundo os quais o “modelo da comunicação” deve substituir o “modelo da
observação”, defendemos que há um tipo de conhecimento que é irredutivelmente
fundado na intersubjetividade (isto é, o conhecimento de pessoas é conhecimento a
dois) e apontamos as implicações que isso pode ter para a psicopatologia..
Palavras-chave: Psicopatologia, conhecimento de outras pessoas, intersubjetividade,
critério

(L’appréhension de l’expérience subjective d’autrui)


Dans cet article, nous abordons quelques questions conceptuelles qui précèdent
logiquement la constitution de toute forme de psychopathologie. Nous explorons les
aspects ontologiques et épistémologiques de l’expérience subjective en détriment
du cartésianisme et du behaviorisme, nous privilégions la notion wittgensteinienne
de soutien critériel. Ainsi, nous discutons la disanalogie entre la connaissance des
autres esprits et notre connaissance de toute autre chose. Sur la base des arguments
proposés par Eilan, selon lesquels le « modèle de communication » devrait remplacer
le « modèle d’observation », nous défendons qu’il existe un type de connaissance
irréductiblement fondé sur l’intersubjectivité (c’est-à-dire que la connaissance des
347
personnes est une connaissance partagée) et soulignons les implications que cela peut
avoir pour la psychopathologie.
Mots clés: Psychopathologie, la connaissance d’autres personnes, intersubjectivité,
critère

(La aprehensión de la experiencia subjetiva de otros)


En este artículo, abordamos algunas cuestiones conceptuales lógicamente
previas a la constitución de cualquier forma de psicopatología. Exploramos
ontológica y epistemológicamente aspectos de la experiencia subjetiva, rechazando
tanto al Cartesianismo como al conductismo (behaviorismo), favoreciendo, en
cambio, a la noción wittigensteiniana de apoyo de criterio. Así, discutimos la
desanalogía entre el conocimiento de otras mentes y el conocimiento de cualquier
otra cosa. Basándonos en los argumentos proporcionados por Eilan, según los
cuales el “modelo de comunicación” debe sustituir al “modelo de la observación”,
defendemos que hay un tipo de conocimiento que es irreductiblemente fundado en la
intersubjetividad (es decir, el conocimiento de personas es conocimiento para dos) y
señalamos las implicaciones que eso puede tener para la psicopatología. .
Palabras clave: Psicopatología, conocimiento de otras personas, intersubjetividad,
criterio

Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020
R E V I S T A
LATINOAMERICANA
DE P S I C O P A T O L O G I A
F U N D A M E N T A L

Citação/Citation: Banzato, C. E. M., & Zorzanelli, R. T. (2020, jun.). Making sense of the
subjective experience of others. Revista Latinoamericana de Psicopatologia Fundamental,
23(2), 337-348. http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/1415-4714.2020v23n2p337.10.
Editora/Editor: Prof. Dr. Mario Eduardo Costa Pereira
Submetido/Submitted: 21.5.2020 / 5.21.2020 Aceito/Accepted: 30.5.2020 / 5.30.2020
Copyright: © 2009 Associação Universitária de Pesquisa em Psicopatologia Fundamental/
University Association for Research in Fundamental Psychopathology. Este é um artigo de
livre acesso, que permite uso irrestrito, distribuição e reprodução em qualquer meio, desde
que o autor e a fonte sejam citados / This is an open-access article, which permits unrestricted
use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original authors and sources
are credited.
Financiamento/Funding: Este trabalho não recebeu apoio / This work received no funding.
Conflito de interesses/Conflict of interest: Os autores declaram que não há conflito de
interesses / The authors have no conflict of interest to declare.

Claudio E. M. Banzato
Professor of Psychiatry; Medical School, University of Campinas – Unicamp (Campinas,
348 SP, Br).
Rua Tessália Vieira de Camargo, 126
Cidade Universitária “Zeferino Vaz” – Barão Geraldo
13083-887 Campinas, SP, Br
cbanzato@unicamp.br
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-8556-3982

Rafaela T. Zorzanelli
Psychologist; Associate Professor; Institute for Social Medicine, State University of Rio de
Janeiro – UERJ (Rio de Janeiro, RJ, Br).
Rua São Francisco Xavier, 524, Pavilhão João Lyra Filho, 7º andar / blocos D e E, e 6º
andar / bloco E – Maracanã
20550-013 Rio de Janeiro, RJ, Br.
rtzorzanelli@gmail.com
https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7531-8492

This is an open-access article, which permits unrestricted use, distribution,


and reproduction in any medium for non-commercial purposes provided
the original authors and sources are credited.

Rev. Latinoam. Psicopat. Fund., São Paulo, 23(2), 337-348, jun. 2020

You might also like