Socio 2 ND Sem
Socio 2 ND Sem
Socio 2 ND Sem
SEMESTER 2nd
DSC-SOC-1B
SOCIOLOGICAL THOUGHT
UNIT-I
AUGUSTE COMTE
Auguste Comte (1798–1857)
Born in the French city of Montpellier on January 19, 1798, Auguste Comte grew up in the
period of great political turmoil that followed the French Revolution of 1789–1799. In
August 1817, Comte met Henri Saint- Simon and became his secretary and eventually his
close collaborator. Under Saint-Simon’s influence, Comte converted from an ardent advocate
of liberty and equality to a supporter of an elitist conception of society. Saint-Simon and
Comte rejected the lack of empiricism in the social philosophy of the day. Instead they turned
for inspiration to the methods and intellectual framework of the natural sciences, which they
perceived as having led to the spectacular successes of industrial progress. They set out to
develop a “science of man” that would reveal the underlying principles of society much as
the sciences of physics and chemistry explained nature and guided industrial progress. During
their association the two men collaborated on a number of essays, most of which contained
the seeds of Comte’s major ideas. Their alliance came to a bitter end in 1824 when Comte
broke with Saint-Simon for both financial and intellectual reasons. Comte saw this new
science, which he named sociology, as the greatest of all sciences. Sociology would include
all other sciences and bring them all together into a cohesive whole. Financial problems, lack
of academic recognition, and marital difficulties combined to force Comte into a shell.
Eventually, for reasons of “cerebral hygiene,” he no longer read any scientific work related to
the fields about which he was writing. Living in isolation at the periphery of the academic
world, Comte concentrated his efforts between 1830 and 1842 on writing his major work,
Cours de Philosophie Positive, the work in which he actually coined the term sociology.
Comte devoted a great deal of his writing to describing the contributions he expected
sociology would make in the future. He was much less concerned with defining sociology’s
subject matter than with showing how it would improve society.
2
the laws of nature is that of ‘consensus universalis’, a universal agreement among all
societies of dialectically creative role of order and progress. According to Comte, ‘consensus
universalis’ is the foundation of solidarity in society.
UNIT-II
EMILE DURKHEIM
Emile Durkheim
Emile Durkheim’s great insight was recognizing that society exists beyond us. Society is
more than the individuals who compose it. Society was here long before we were born, it
shapes us while we live, and it will remain long after we are gone. Patterns of human
behaviour—cultural norms, values, and beliefs—exist as established structures, or social facts,
that have an objective reality beyond the lives of individuals. Because society is bigger than
any one of us, it has the power to guide our thoughts and actions. This is why studying
individuals alone (as psychologists or biologists do) can never capture the heart of the social
experience. A classroom of college students taking a math exam, a family gathered around a
table sharing a meal, people quietly waiting their turn in a doctor’s office—all are examples of
the countless situations that have a familiar organization apart from any particular individual
who has ever been part of them. Once created by people, Durkheim claimed, society takes on
a life of its own and demands a measure of obedience from its creators. We experience the
power of society when we see lives falling into common patterns or when we feel the tug of
morality during a moment of temptation. Having established that society has structure,
Durkheim turned to the concept of function. The significance of any social fact, he explained,
is more than what individuals see in their immediate lives; social facts help along the
operation of society as a whole. Consider crime. As victims of crime, individuals experience
pain and loss. But taking a broader view, Durkheim saw that crime is vital to the ongoing life
of society itself. He explains, only by defining acts as wrong do people construct and defend
morality, which gives direction and meaning to our collective life. For this reason, Durkheim
rejected the common view of crime as abnormal. On the contrary, he concluded, crime is
“normal” for the most basic of reasons: A society could not exist without it.
Social Fact
According to Durkheim, social facts are ways of acting, thinking and feeling which are
capable of searching an external constraint on the individual, which are generally diffused
3
throughout a given society and which can existing their own life, independent of individual
manifestation. The three main characteristics of social facts are Exteriority, Generality and
Constraint. Durkheim treated social facts as things. The true nature of social facts lies in the
collective or associational characteristics inherent in society. Legal codes, religious beliefs,
language etc are all social facts. Durkheim has made an important distinction in terms of
normal and pathological social facts. A social fact is normal when it is generally encountered
in a society of a certain type at a certain phase in its evolution, and deviation from this
standard is a pathological fact. For example, crime to certain extent is a normal fact but an
extraordinary increase in the rate of crime is pathological.
4
people we hardly know and whose beliefs may well differ from our own? Durkheim’s answer
was “because we can’t live without them.” So, modern society rests far less on moral
consensus and far more on functional interdependence. Herein lies what we might call
“Durkheim’s dilemma”: The technological power and greater personal freedom of modern
society come at the cost of declining morality and the rising risk of anomie. Like Marx and
Weber, Durkheim is worried about the direction society was taking. But of the three,
Durkheim was the most optimistic. He saw that large, anonymous societies gave people more
freedom and privacy than small towns. Anomie remains a danger, but Durkheim hoped we
would be able to create laws and other norms to regulate our behaviour.
Suicide
Durkheim believed suicide rates were influenced by group cohesion and societal stability. He
believed that low levels of cohesion—which involve more individual choice, more self-
reliance, and fewer adherences to group standards—would mean high rates of suicide. To test
his idea, Durkheim decided to study the suicide rates of Catholic versus Protestant countries.
He assumed the suicide rate in Catholic countries would be lower than in Protestant countries
because Protestantism emphasized the individual’s relationship to God over community ties.
The comparison of suicide records in Catholic and Protestant countries in Europe supported
his theory by showing the probability of suicide was indeed higher in Protestant countries.
Recognizing the possibility that lower suicide rates among Catholics could be based on
factors other than group cohesion, Durkheim proceeded to test other groups. Reasoning that
married people would have more group ties than single people, or people with children more
than people without children, or non– college educated people more than college-educated
people (because college tends to break group ties and encourage individualism), or Jews more
than non-Jews, Durkheim tested each of these groups, and in each case, his theory held. Then,
characteristic of the scientist that he was, Durkheim extended his theory by identifying three
types of suicide—egoistic, altruistic, and anomic— that take place under different types of
conditions Egoistic suicide comes from low group cohesion, an under involvement with
others. Durkheim argued that loneliness and a commitment to personal beliefs rather than to
group values can lead to egoistic suicide. Therefore, he found that single and divorced people
had higher suicide rates than did married people and that Protestants, who tend to stress
individualism, had higher rates of suicide than did Catholics. Altruistic suicide derives from a
very high level of group cohesion, an over involvement with others. The individual is so tied
to a certain set of goals that he or she is willing to die for the sake of the community. This
5
type of suicide, as Durkheim noted in his time, still exists in the military as well as in
societies based on ancient codes of honor and obedience. Perhaps the best-known historical
examples of altruistic suicide come from Japan in the ceremonial rite of seppuku, in which a
disgraced person rips open his own belly, and in the kamikaze attacks by Japanese pilots
toward the end of World War II. The Japanese pilots, instead of being morose before the
bombing missions (that would cause their certain deaths), were often reported to be cheerful
and serene. One 23-year-old kamikaze, in a letter to his parents, voiced the feelings of
thousands of his fellows when he wrote, “I shall be a shield for His Majesty and die cleanly
along with my squadron leader and other friends.” Today, we often see examples of altruistic
suicide in the terrorists who flew the planes into the World Trade towers and in the Middle
Eastern suicide bombers. These individuals are willing to sacrifice their lives for their cause
as they blow up a building, plane, or restaurant. In addition to destroying the property, the
terrorists often want to kill as many people as possible. Anomic suicide results from a sense
of feeling disconnected from society’s values. A person might know what goals to strive for
but not be able to attain them, or a person might not know what goals to pursue. Durkheim
found that times of rapid social change or economic crisis are associated with high rates of
anomic suicide. Durkheim’s study was important not only because it proved that the most
personal of all acts, suicide, is in fact a product of social forces but also because it was one of
the first examples of a scientifically conducted sociological study. Durkheim systematically
posed theories, tested them, and drew conclusions that led to further theories. He also
published his results for everyone to see and criticize.
UNIT-III
KARL MARX
Karl Marx
The first of our classic visions of society comes from Karl Marx (1818–1883), an early giant
in the field of sociology whose influence continues today. Keenly aware of how the Industrial
Revolution had changed Europe, Marx spent most of his adult life in London; the capital of
what was then the vast British Empire. He was awed by the size and productive power of the
new factories going up all over Britain. Along with other industrial nations, Britain was
producing more goods than ever before, drawing raw materials from around the world and
churning out finished products at a dizzying rate. What astounded Marx even more was that
the riches produced by this new technology ended up in the hands of only a few people. As
6
he walked around the city of London, he could see for himself that a handful of aristocrats
and industrialists enjoyed lives of luxury and privilege, living in fabulous mansions staffed by
many servants. At the same time, most people lived in slums and laboured long hours for low
wages. Some even slept in the streets, where they were likely to die young from diseases
brought on by cold and poor nutrition. Marx saw his society in terms of a basic contradiction:
In a country so rich, how could so many people be so poor? Just as important, he asked, how
can this situation be changed? Many people think Marx set out to tear societies apart. But he
was motivated by compassion and wanted to help a badly divided society create a new and
more just social order. At the heart of Marx’s thinking is the idea of social conflict, the
struggle between segments of society over valued resources. Social conflict can, of course,
take many forms: Individuals quarrel, colleges have long-standing sports rivalries, and
nations sometimes go to war. For Marx, however, the most important type of social conflict
was class conflict arising from the way a society produces material goods.
Historical Materialism
For Marx, conflict is the engine that drives social change. Sometimes societies change at a
slow, evolutionary rate. But they may erupt in rapid, revolutionary change. To Marx, early
hunters and gatherers formed primitive communist societies. Communism is a system in
which people commonly own and equally share food and other things they produce. People in
hunting and gathering societies do not have much, but they share what they have. In addition,
because everyone does the same kind of work, there are no class differences and thus little
chance of social conflict. With technological advance comes social inequality. Among
horticultural, pastoral, and early agrarian societies—which Marx lumped together as the
“ancient world”—warfare was frequent, and the victors turned their captives into slaves.
Agriculture brings still more wealth to a society’s elite but does little for most other people,
who labour as serfs and are barely better off than slaves. As Marx saw it, the state supported
the feudal system (in which the elite or nobility had all the power), assisted by the church,
which claimed that this arrangement reflected the will of God. This is why Marx thought that
feudalism was simply “exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions”. Gradually,
new productive forces started to break down the feudal order. As trade steadily increased,
cities grew, and merchants and skilled crafts workers formed the new capitalist class or
bourgeoisie (a French word meaning “people of the town”).After 1800, the bourgeoisie also
controlled factories, becoming richer and richer so that they soon rivalled the ancient
landowning nobility. For their part, the nobles looked down their noses at this upstart
7
“commercial” class, but in time, these capitalists took control of European societies. To
Marx’s way of thinking, then, new technology was only part of the Industrial Revolution; it
also served as a class revolution in which capitalists overthrew the old agrarian elite.
Industrialization also led to the formation of the proletariat. English landowners converted
fields once ploughed by serfs into grazing land for sheep to produce wool for the textile mills.
Forced from the land, millions of people migrated to cities and had little choice but to work in
factories. Marx envisioned these workers one day joining together to form a revolutionary
class that would overthrow the capitalist system
Class struggle and class conflict
“The history of all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles.”With these
words, Marx and his collaborator, Friedrich Engels, began their best-known statement, the
Manifesto of the Communist Party. Industrial capitalism, like earlier types of society,
contains two major social classes: the ruling class, whose members (capitalists or
bourgeoisie) own productive property, and the oppressed (proletarians), who sell their labour,
reflecting the two basic positions in the productive system. Like masters and slaves in the
ancient world and like nobles and serfs in feudal systems, capitalists and proletarians are
engaged in class conflict today. Currently, as in the past, one class controls the other as
productive property. Marx used the term class conflict (and sometimes class struggle) to refer
to conflict between entire classes over the distribution of a society’s wealth and power. Class
conflict is nothing new. What distinguishes the conflict in capitalist society, Marx pointed
out, is how out in the open it is. Agrarian nobles and serfs, for all their differences, were
bound together by traditions and mutual obligations. Industrial capitalism dissolved those ties
so that loyalty and honour were replaced by “naked self-interest.” Because the proletarians
had no personal ties to the capitalists, Marx saw no reason for them to put up with their
oppression. Marx knew that revolution would not come easily. First, workers must become
aware of their oppression and see capitalism as its true cause. Second, they must organize
and act to address their problems. This means that false consciousness must be replaced with
class consciousness, workers’ recognition of themselves as a class unified in opposition to
capitalists and ultimately to capitalism itself. Because the inhumanity of early capitalism was
plain for him to see, Marx concluded that industrial workers would soon rise up to destroy
this economic system. How would the capitalists react? Their wealth made them strong. But
Marx saw a weakness in the capitalist armor. Motivated by a desire for personal gain
capitalists feared competition with other capitalists. Marx predicted, therefore, that capitalists
8
would be slow to band together despite their common interests. In addition, he reasoned,
capitalists kept employees wages low in order to maximize profits, which made the workers
misery ever greater. In the long run, Marx believed, capitalists would bring about their own
undoing.
Dialectical Materialism
Living in the nineteenth century, Marx observed the early decades of industrial capitalism in
Europe. This economic system, Marx explained, turned a small part of the population into
capitalists, people who own and operate factories and other businesses in pursuit of profits.
A capitalist tries to make a profit by selling a product for more than it costs to produce.
Capitalism turns most of the population into industrial workers, whom Marx called
proletarians, people who sell their labour for wages. To Marx, a system of capitalist
production always ends up creating conflict between capitalists and workers. To keep profits
high, capitalists keep wages low. But workers want higher wages. Since profits and wages
come from the same pool of funds, the result is conflict. As Marx saw it, this conflict could
end only with the end of capitalism itself. All societies are composed of social institutions,
the major spheres of social life, or societal subsystems, organized to meet human needs.
Examples of social institutions include the economy, the political system, the family, religion,
and education. In his analysis of society, Marx argued that one institution—the economy—
dominates all the others and defines the character of the entire society. Drawing on the
philosophical approach called materialism, which says that how humans produce material
goods shapes their experiences, Marx believed that the other social institutions all operate in
a way that supports a society’s economy. Lenski focused on how technology moulds a
society but, for Marx, it is the economy that forms a society’s “real foundation”. Marx
viewed the economic system as society’s infrastructure (infra is Latin, meaning “below”).
Other social institutions, including the family, the political system, and religion, are built on
this foundation; they form society’s superstructure and support the economy. Marx was well
aware that most people living in an industrial capitalist system do not recognize how
capitalism shapes the operation of their entire society. Most people, in fact, regard the right to
own private property or pass it on to their children as “natural.” In the same way, many of us
tend to see rich people as having “earned” their money through long years of schooling and
hard work; we see the poor, on the other hand, as lacking skills and the personal drive to
make more of them. Marx rejected this type of thinking, calling it false consciousness,
explaining social problems as the shortcomings of individuals rather than as the flaws of
9
society. Marx was saying, in effect, that it is not “people”who make society so unequal but
rather the system of capitalist production. False consciousness, he believed, hurts people by
hiding the real cause of their problems.
UNIT-IV
MAX WEBER
Max Weber
With a wide-ranging knowledge of law, economics, religion, and history, Max Weber
(1864–1920) produced what many experts regard as the greatest individual contribution ever
made to sociology. This scholar, born to a prosperous family in Germany, had much to say
about how modern society differs from earlier types of social organization. Weber understood
the power of technology, and he shared many of Marx’s ideas about social conflict. But he
disagreed with Marx’s philosophy of materialism. Weber’s philosophical approach, called
idealism, emphasized how human ideas—especially beliefs and values—shape society. He
argued that the most important difference among societies is not how people produce things
but how people think about the world. In Weber’s view, modern society was the product of a
new way of thinking. Weber compared societies in different times and places. To make the
comparisons, he relied on the ideal type, an abstract statement of the essential characteristics
of any social phenomenon. Following Weber’s approach, for example, we might speak of
“preindustrial” and “industrial” societies as ideal types. The use of the word “ideal” does not
mean that one or the other is “good” or “best.”Nor does an ideal type refer to any actual
society. Rather, think of an ideal type as a way of defining a type of society in its pure form.
We have already used ideal types in comparing “hunting and gathering societies”with
“industrial societies” and “capitalism” with “socialism.”
Ideal Type
Weber compared societies in different times and places. To make the comparisons, he relied
on the ideal type, an abstract statement of the essential characteristics of any social
phenomenon. Following Weber’s approach, for example, we might speak of
“preindustrial” and “industrial” societies as ideal types. The use of the word “ideal”
does not mean that one or the other is “good” or “best.”Nor does an ideal type refer to
any actual society. Rather, think of an ideal type as a way of defining a type of society in its
pure form. We have already used ideal types in comparing “hunting and gathering
10
societies”with “industrial societies” and “capitalism” with “socialism.”Ideal type
was used as a methodological tool or concepts which are formulated for interpretation and
explanation of social reality. It is also used for analysis of concrete historical events or
situation.
Social Action
11
way, Calvinists came to see worldly prosperity as a sign of God’s grace. Eager to gain this
reassurance, Calvinists threw themselves into a quest for business success, applying
rationality, discipline, and hard work to their tasks. They were certainly pursuing wealth, but
they were not doing this for the sake of money, at least not to spend on themselves because
any self-indulgence would be sinful. Neither were Calvinists likely to use their wealth for
charity. To share their wealth with the poor seemed to go against God’s will because they
viewed poverty as a sign of God’s rejection. Calvinists’ duty was pressing forward in what
they saw as their personal calling from God, reinvesting the money they made for still greater
success. It is easy to see how such activity—saving money, using wealth to create more
wealth, and adopting new technology—became the foundation of capitalism. Other world
religions did not encourage the rational pursuit of wealth the way Calvinism did. Catholicism,
the traditional religion in most of Europe, taught a passive, “otherworldly” view: Good deeds
performed humbly on Earth would bring rewards in heaven. For Catholics, making money
had none of the spiritual significance it had for Calvinists. Weber concluded that this was the
reason that industrial capitalism developed primarily in areas of Europe where Calvinism was
strong. Weber’s study of Calvinism provides striking evidence of the power of ideas to shape
society. Not one to accept simple explanations, Weber knew that industrial capitalism had
many causes. But by stressing the importance of ideas, Weber tried to counter Marx’s strictly
economic explanation of modern society. As the decades passed, later generations of
Calvinists lost much of their early religious enthusiasm. But their drive for success and
personal discipline remained, and what started out as a religious ethic was gradually
transformed into a work ethic. In this sense, Weber considered industrial capitalism to be a
“disenchanted” religion, with wealth no longer valued as a sign of salvation but for its own
sake. This transformation is seen in the fact that the practice of “accounting,” which to
early Calvinists meant keeping a daily record of their moral deeds, before long came to mean
simply keeping track of money.
12