Brush 1996 Dynamics of Theory Change
Brush 1996 Dynamics of Theory Change
Brush 1996 Dynamics of Theory Change
Violence
Author(s): Stephen G. Brush
Source: The Journal of Conflict Resolution , Dec., 1996, Vol. 40, No. 4 (Dec., 1996), pp.
523-545
Published by: Sage Publications, Inc.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The Journal of Conflict Resolution
STEPHEN G. BRUSH
Department of History and Institute for Physical Science and Technology
University of Maryland at College Park
The extent to which theories in the social sciences are accepted or rejected on the basis of empiric
can be shown only by a detailed analysis of specific cases. The author examines the reception
scientists in the 1970s and early 1980s of T. R. Gurr's theory of collective violence based on the
relative deprivation. The history of this theory may be considered an example of definite progres
science: a hypothesis widely accepted at one time has been tested and rejected, thus making room
development of alternative hypotheses. But although Gurr and other advocates of the theory have ab
it in its original form following the mostly negative results of empirical tests, many social
(especially psychologists) have continued to cite it favorably. Slightly less than half of the unf
citations have been supported by references to empirical evidence.
W hat does it mean to be scientific? For social scientists, whose status has lo
problematic and whose jobs are threatened by financial pressures at some inst
this is more than an academic or philosophical question. It is also a question
provokes heated controversies within disciplines such as sociology and anthr
between those who favor quantitative empirical methods or mathematical mo
those who insist that a qualitative descriptive or hermeneutic approach is m
appropriate.1
1. A useful analysis of this controversy is given by Rosenberg (1988), who demonstrates th
scientists must choose between the two approaches (which he calls naturalistic and interpretative)
as a philosopher he avoids making that choice himself.
AUTHOR'S NOTE: The research for this article was done while the author was a member of the School
of Social Science, Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton, New Jersey, during the 1992-1993 academic
year. This case was suggested to me by James B. Rule, to whom I am indebted for valuable discussion and
for comments on an earlier draft. I thank Ted Robert Gurr for information provided in a telephone interview.
Useful ideas emerged in discussions with Gene Bums, Stephen Cole, Larry Laudan, Frederick Suppe, and
Michael Walzer. My research was supported by the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation and by the General
Research Board of the University of Maryland. Address correspondence to the Department of History and
Institute for Physical Science and Technology, University of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742. Detailed
statistical results may be found in an extended version of this article, available from the author, or on the
World Wide Web at http://Carnap.umd.edu:90/chps/faculty/Brush/relative_deprivation.
2. See Brush (1995) and other works cited therein. For Planck's principle, see Planck
and Hull, Tessner, and Diamond (1978).
3. A general history of this topic is presented in a monograph by Rule (1988); see also
Gumey and Tiemey (1982), Lichbach (1989), Muller and Weede (1994), and Morris and H
4. See Berelson and Steiner (1964), Braybrooke (1987), Hutchison (1960), Social Science
Council (1954), Utter and Vanderleeuw (1991), and Zald (1991). For dissenting views, see Ru
who says prediction does not have to be novel, and Maclntyre (1971), who rejects predictivene
as a criterion.
5. Popper (1974,1978) himself contributed to the confusion by first asserting that Darwinia
is not a scientific theory because it is not falsifiable, then changing his mind (and his definition of
and declaring it a legitimate scientific theory after all.
6. This is my surmise, not a statement found in the Gurr and Lichbach (1986) paper.
The only time novelty is clearly relevant is when the parameters of a mod
been selected to agree with previously known facts; then one has good reason
skeptical. Thus Tilly (1971, 419), in reviewing Gurr's Why Men Rebel, asserted
the variables had been reformulated during the research so "there is a serious ris
they have been adjusted to fit the data" and hence "only the application of Gurr's
determinate models ... to new cases will test them properly."
HISTORICAL SKETCH
Why do men7 rebel? In the decades and centuries before Gurr publish
proposing an answer to this question (Gurr 1970), historians and social sc
discussed a wide variety of theories of collective violence (revolutions,
riots, lynch mobs), social movements, and aggressive political participati
first half of the 20th century, American sociologists sought a unified ex
these phenomena under the rubric of "collective behavior." Such behav
disturbed the normal stable equilibrium of society, was thought to be in
socially isolated individuals acting emotionally. In some theories, instigat
others by a contagious process of "symbolic interaction" to form a diso
dangerous crowd. This viewpoint became known as the "riff-raff' or "s
earth" theory (Rule 1988). The theory of collective behavior maintained t
that any kind of rebellion, violent or not, is to be ascribed to the actions
people and represents a threat to society. Social science research on collect
and "mass society" is therefore needed to facilitate the control of violent or
violent movements.
In the 1960s, these theories of collective behavior lost their popularity among
academic social scientists at the same time that they were being employed by political
and military leaders to rationalize their policies. Riots in the black ghettos of American
cities were initially blamed on marginalized subversives or outside agitators.9 Yet
research studies had already begun to suggest that the participants in riots, like
participants in collective violence in other times and places, had the same social and
economic characteristics as the rest of the local population and had close ties with it.l?
Leftist uprisings and guerrilla movements in other countries were portrayed as part of
a worldwide Soviet-led conspiracy against the United States, yet somehow American
intervention always seemed to support repressive tyrannical regimes. The civil rights
7. Much of the social science literature, which implies that rebellions were organized and staffed
primarily by men, does not recognize a need either to verify or explain that assumption. For exceptions, see
Ferree (1980) on support for feminism and Wheeler (1975) on participation in German leftist movements.
Historians more often have recognized the role of women in rebellions; see, for example, Thompson (1971)
on the instigation of 18th-century riots.
8. See Moshiri (1991) and Rule (1988). The last phrase has been popularized by Edward Muller (1979
and other publications).
9. See especially the McCone Report (Governor's Commission on the Los Angeles Riots 1965) and
the extensive discussion of it by Fogelson (1971). McCarthy and Zald (1973) note the relation of resource
mobilization theory to the outside agitator theory.
10. See Caplan and Paige (1968), Fogelson (1971), Platt (1971), Wanderer (1968), and C. Tilly, "Queries
on Social Change and Political Upheaval in France," cited in Rule (1988, 174).
11. See Gamson (1975). The ambivalent views of social scientists toward research intended to protect
the stability of the social order are shown in their reflections on "Project Camelot" (Horowitz 1967). An
extreme example of the interaction of personal feelings of grievance with research on protest movements
is the paper by Law and Walsh (1983, 124); the first author, one of the founders of the protest movement
against a dangerous "Toughman Contest" (a series of fights in which "the only rules are that there should
be no biting and kicking" and which allowed contestants of greatly unequal weights and physical condition
to be matched against each other), intentionally helped to create the events being studied.
12. See Berelson and Steiner (1964) and Degler (1991). For examples relevant to political science, see
Coming(1971), Dahl (1961), Davies (1963), Pennock and Chapman(1977), Schwartz (1974), Somit (1968),
and Stone (1981).
13. See Ardrey (1966) and Lorenz (1966).
Before 1970, the concept of relative deprivation (RD) was already being
used by social scientists.14 The idea that political revolutions stem from fr
expectations (originated by Aristotle and succinctly expressed in de Tocq
writings on the French Revolution) had been revived in the 1950s and 1960s
why instability followed modernization and protest followed apparent pro
phrase "revolution of rising expectations" became a cliche that endures to
It was visually summarized in the "J-curve" of Davies (1962, 6) by showin
sudden drop in "actual need satisfaction" causes it to lag much farther b
continually growing "expected need satisfaction," thus creating "an intol
between what people want and what they get."16 Conversely, RD was cons
explain why severe hardship during the depression of the 1930s did not
revolution (Maclntyre 1980).
Gurr built on these earlier works but went beyond them in one crucial r
insisted on developing a body of precise, testable hypotheses. Early in Why M
Gurr (1970, 15-17) wrote:
The concepts, hypotheses, and models of causes and processes developed in the fo
chapters are not intended as ends in themselves. Intellectually pleasing filters t
which to view and categorize the phenomena of a disorderly world are not know
Systematic knowledge requires us to propose and test and reformulate and r
statements about how and why things happen. We know enough, and know it well e
only when we can say with some certitude not just why things happened yesterd
how our actions will affect what happens tomorrow....
The kind of theory aimed at in this study is an interrelated set of general, fal
hypotheses that satisfy causal or concomitant relationships between independen
dependent variables....
The central scientific criterion for theory is that it be subject to empirical assessm
Four attributes of theory that facilitate its assessment are its falsifiability, defi
clarity, identification of relevant variables at various levels of analysis, and appli
to a large universe of events for analysis. The first two are necessary conditi
assessment, the others desirable.
sented in any summary national measure of RD." The implication was tha
Americans were more likely to rebel than Whites because they had stronger
of relative deprivation, though elsewhere in his book Gurr called attention
other variables that would have to be controlled to establish such a direct correlation.
But Gurr's use of aggregate measures of deprivation as indicators of individual motivation
was widely regarded as a serious weakness of this theory, along with his failure to show
exactly how individual motivations are translated into social movements.
Why Men Rebel won the Woodrow Wilson Prize for the best book on political
science in 1970 and was widely praised in reviews. Even those critics who disagreed
with Gurr's theory applauded his effort to formulate it as a set of propositions that
could be tested. 7 The publication of Gurr's book at the same time as a number of
other works advocating a similar viewpoint seemed to provide an effect of mutual
reinforcement. 1
Within 6 months of the publication of his book, Gurr was asked by the American
Political Science Review to referee a manuscript that presented results contrary to his
RD theory. Edward N. Muller, a political scientist at SUNY-Stony Brook, had studied
the racial disturbances in Waterloo, Iowa, in the late 1960s, using the Cantril Self-
Anchoring Striving Scale recommended by Gurr. Muller (1972, 954) found that the
potential for violence depends on a "low degree of trust in political authorities"
combined with a "high degree of belief that the use of violence by dissident groups in
the past has helped their cause.... Once these factors have been taken into account,
relative deprivation does not seem to matter." If society wants less violence, it would
be more effective to have honest police than more welfare programs.
Gurr wrote in his referee's report that if the author's results turned out to be
generally valid, his own theory would have to be fundamentally revised. He now sees
this episode as the crucial event that led him to downgrade the importance of relative
deprivation as a cause of collective violence."9
The numerous rebellions, riots, and civil disturbances in the 1960s coincided with
the establishment of surveys and archives to collect data on such events and an
explosive growth in the number of social scientists interested in analyzing the data.
Hence there seemed to be many opportunities to test Gurr's theory. One of the most
frequently cited tests was an analysis by Clark McPhail, a sociologist at the University
of Illinois, of 10 reports on five riots in American cities (Watts in Los Angeles, 1965;
17. See Feierabend (1971), Marx and Wood (1975), and Silvert (1971). A decade later, Greene (1984,
216) called relative deprivation the most often cited theory of revolution and identified Gurr as its leading
theorist.
18. See Davies (1973); Feierabend, Feierabend, and Nesvold (1969, 1973); Feierabend, Feierabend,
and Gurr (1972); Fogelson (1971); Huntington (1968); Pettigrew (1971); Runciman (1966); and Forster and
Greene (1970). Relative deprivation was invoked so frequently that it was called a "sociological workhorse"
by Young (1970). Wilhelm ( 1970, 82) complained that the concept was being used "to bridge the gap between
the positively elated exclamations by academic observers and many Negro leaders [about the supposed
progress made by Negroes in the United States] and the mounting dissatisfaction coming especially from
the Negro masses" because, according to Wilhelm, their conditions had not improved. Thus, he argued, the
"rising expectations" thesis distracts attention from legitimate grievances. Similarly, Wasbum (1974, 333)
suggested that preoccupation with variables such as RD "deflects attention from objective structural
conditions which might precipitate violence and from the social organization and social-political conse-
quences of protest movements."
19. Ted Robert Gurr, telephone interview by the author, 18 December 1992.
Omaha, 1966; Detroit, 1967; Milwaukee, 1967; Newark, NJ, 1967). He conclude
the RD model "receives scant empirical support" and should be rejected (McP
1971, 1064). Instead of relative deprivation, the factor showing the highest corre
was the opinion of Blacks (not necessarily based on personal experience) tha
were being mistreated by police.20
Other studies of the 1960s ghetto riots in American cities yielded only weak s
or refutations for the RD model. Spilerman (1970, 1971) compared the distur
in several cities and found, after controlling for the size of the non-White popu
no significant correlation between relative deprivation (measured by aggrega
cators) and the amount of violence. A survey of residents of Cleveland's poor
months after the 1966 riot obtained mixed results (Bowen et al. 1968), as did
after the 1967 Detroit riots (Crawford and Naditch 1970). In both cases, the resea
decided that additional factors were needed to nail down a connection between
deprivation and propensity toward violence. Miller, Bolce, and Halligan (1977)
concluded that the J-curve theory failed when data on family income and years of
schooling for individuals rather than averages for groups were used.
Multinational comparative studies of the kind used by Gurr himself continued to
support a correlation between political instability and aggregate measures of depriva-
tion (Feierabend, Feierabend, and Nesvold 1973), but more detailed local or longitu-
dinal studies of individual countries began to cast doubt on the efficacy of individual
discontent as a cause of collective violence. The publications most often mentioned
for providing evidence against the RD model were those of David Snyder and Charles
Tilly (1972) for violence in France during the period from 1830 to 1960 and of
Alejandro Portes (1970, 197 la, 1971 b) for leftist radicalism in modern Latin America.
Portes (1971b, 26) interpreted "the popularity of the frustration-radicalism hypothe-
sis ... as a partial result of the post-factum self-legitimation of successful revolution-
ary movements." It is not surprising that those who have already participated in a
revolution claim that their action was motivated by economic deprivation or some
other grievance. The claim is not evidence of their real motivation, especially if others
with similar grievances did not revolt. Many of these studies were subsequently
considered inadequate tests of the RD model because they did not directly measure
the perceived discrepancy between one's "just desserts"-a legitimate expectation of
reward rather than a desired but unrealistic goal-and one's actual level of attainment
and because they measured only the respondents' attitudes toward collective violence,
not their actual participation. These gaps were filled in an extensive series of studies
in New York City, West Germany, and Costa Rica by Muller and his collaborators.
Muller found that although there is a linear correlation between just desserts frustration
(JDF) and aggressive political participation (APP), this relation is entirely due to other
intervening variables. In particular, he concludes that APP is produced by a belief in
20. McPhail (1971) cites the report of Flaming (1968) as the primary source forthis conclusion. Flaming
himself admits that his study cannot establish the motives for participation in riots because he did not measure
attitudes of participants before they were arrested. His data indicate that Black arrestees blamed economic
deprivation almost as often as police mistreatment for their anger. For other research indicating that rioters
blamed police brutality more than deprivation, see Fogelson (1971) and Ladner et al. (1981).
the efficacy of action and doubts about the legitimacy of the political syste
1977, 1979, 1980; Muller and Jukam 1983).
Although Muller's research persuaded Gurr and others that relative depriv
not the primary cause of collective violence, there was some retreat in the 198
the flat statements in the 1970s that the RD model had been completely ref
view of Muller and other researchers seems to be that relative deprivation
contributing factor that interacts with or amplifies other factors.21 Even thou
HISTORIOGRAPHIC METHOD
25. See Kiser and Hechter (1991), Lichbach (1989), and Piven and Cloward (1992). This does not apply
to Muller, whose social-psychological model remains a strong contender and is supported by empirical
evidence (Rule 1988). Greene (1984) and Zagorin (1982) assert that we will never have an adequate general
(falsifiable) theory of revolutions. Recent articles in the journal Contention question whether theories of
revolution should be expected to predict whether revolutions will occur in specific countries (Keddie 1995).
26. See Martin, Brickman, and Murray (1984). Another kind of test, which led to the conclusion that
neither RD nor RM theories would have predicted the Iranian revolution, but a theory developed by Hibbs
(1973) would have done so (Kennedy 1984), seems to have been ignored by advocates and critics of all
three theories.
27. See Jenkins and Shock (1992), Ramirez (1981), Wasbum (1974), and Zimmerman (1983).
28. Similarly, according to Stephen Cole (1992), scholars who claim that social processes influence the
cognitive content of science have failed to produce a single example in which this alleged causal influence
is demonstrated by the standards of sociological research. In his review of Cole's book, Shapin (1993) quotes
this assertion but does not refute it with any specific examples.
Fourth, the relevant publications are recent enough that the Social Science Cita
Index (SSCI) permits one to retrieve much of the relevant journal literature show
how the community responded to the theory and its empirical tests. Use of the
is supplemented by a search of other literature using more traditional methods.
Fifth, the theorist himself (as quoted in the previous section) sharpened the is
and perhaps expedited the process of theory change by formulating testable hypo
ses. Thus, even if this case is not typical of theory change in the social sciences, it m
at least provide an important example of the kind of behavior that some philosop
and some social scientists regard as scientific.
In using citations to assess the reception of a theory, it is essential to recognize t
the response of the community cannot reliably be measured simply by counti
citations. Thus, in the case of physical science and mathematics, when one consid
the authors of works published a few decades ago who have been judged by th
community by the award or nonaward of the Nobel Prize (or Fields Medal, in the
of mathematics), it is found that some important works received relatively few citat
and that some of the most frequently cited works were not important reports of n
research (Brush 1990a, 1990b, 1990c).
Rather than simply counting citations, I actually examined most of the articles
books that cited Gurr's Why Men Rebel during the 15 years after its publication to
out whether the authors accepted or rejected his theory and for what reasons (if an
In addition, as indicated later, I looked at comments on RD theory published in t
preceding half-decade (1966-1970) to establish the status of this theory just before
publication of Gurr's book and identify authors who changed their views after
publication and testing.
Because SSCI concentrates on journal articles, I have supplemented it by look
at books cited in journal articles or listed in annual bibliographies and in the sub
index of the Princeton University Library under headings such as "revolution" a
"social conflict." I also included a number of publications (especially before 197
that mentioned the application of RD theories to collective violence but did not
Gurr's 1970 book. By these methods I have increased the database by about 20%
beyond that provided by SSCI.
In addition to searching for works that cite Gurr or RD theory, I also surveyed m
of the publications indexed under "revolutions" or "riots" in International Poli
Science Abstracts, Sociological Abstracts, Public Affairs Information Service, and
bibliography published by Morrison and Hornback (1976), concentrating on wo
that appeared in 1971, 1976, and 1981. The purpose here was to see what competi
theories were being discussed and estimate the popularity of Gurr's theory relativ
those theories.
RESULTS
During the 15 years after its publication, Gurr's book Why Men R
mentioned in at least 649 publications, of which 526 were listed in the Soc
Citation Index; the remaining 123 were found by my literature search. O
citations, 145 were considered marginal or neutral; that is, they did n
substantive remarks that could be considered either favorable or unfavorable. After
discarding the marginal citations and self-citations, I found that 181 were favorable
and 192 were unfavorable. The proportion of favorable citations was 56% from 1971
to 1975; it declined to 42% from 1976 to 1980 and then rose to 47% from 1981 to
1985. However, the total number of citations reported in SSCI showed the opposite
pattern, rising from 187 between 1971 and 1975 to 197 between 1976 and 1980, then
falling to 142 between 1981 and 1985. (This illustrates the fallacy of using citation
counts by themselves to assess the reception of a theory.)
The number of unfavorable citations is quite high compared with other studies that
found only 3% to 14% negative citations. The difference is presumably due to the fact
that most of the community ultimately rejected Gurr's theory, whereas the other studies
involved citations of authors whose work is still accepted or disciplines in which
rejected theories are not usually cited at all.29
I was especially interested in identifying authors who changed their opinion of RD
theory and in finding out why they did so. So far I have located only seven authors
who changed from favorable to unfavorable. As mentioned earlier, Gurr himself began
to have serious doubts about his theory when he read Muller's (1972) report on the
Iowa riots. However, he did not publicly abandon the theory but instead introduced a
series of modifications giving greater importance to other factors.30 Corning (1971)
had given a mostly favorable reference to Why Men Rebel but later rejected RD theory
because he said that it explained only a small part of the variance (he did not cite
specific empirical tests) and did not explain why most relatively deprived individuals
don't rebel (Corning 1975). Firestone (1974), who had cited Gurr favorably in 1972,
presented theoretical criticisms31 of Why Men Rebel in a review but did not mention
any empirical tests. Mitchell was coauthor of a study that used Gurr's model (Noton,
Mitchell, and Janes 1974) but 6 years later was a coauthor of a paper that rejected RD
because it could not be properly measured (Bowers, Mitchell, and Webb 1980). Useem
changed his favorable earlier (1972) assessment, citing empirical evidence against it
published by Snyder and Tilly (1972), Hibbs (1973), Spilerman (1970), McPhail
(1971), Portes (1971b), and Muller (1972). He also objected that the theory ignores
violence by the state against dissidents (Useem 1975).32 Williams (1975a) cited Gurr's
theory favorably though with some reservations. Then, in a longer article published in
the same year, he stated that RD theory is inadequate to explain collective action
29. Adatto and Cole (1981) found that only 3% of the citations to Max Weber in four leading sociology
journals in the period from 1964 to 1974 were negative; Cole (1975) found that only 6% of the citations to
Robert Merton in connection with deviance research were negative.
30. Gurr and Lichbach (1986, 10) state that although Gurr's theory was supported by cross-national
aggregate data, "microlevel studies of relations between perceived deprivation and participation in collective
action provided much weaker support for the theory" (reviewed in Muller, 1980). It was revised to take
account of Tilly's RM viewpoint.
31. Firestone says Gurr doesn't explain how to tell which "value" variables (economic, political,
educational, etc.) are most significant; he relies too heavily on the frustration or aggression mechanism to
explain violence and not enough on "instrumental" (goal-seeking) behavior; he equates "aggression" with
violence; and his treatment of incentive systems and social conditions is too narrow.
32. But Useem (1976) again published a favorable though brief reference to Why Men Rebel, on the
influence of regime legitimacy on attacks against it.
33. But Zimmerman's (1983) rejection of RD theory was only temporary; his assessment i
favorable.
34. Subsequently, numbers given in brackets refer to the number of times a reason is given.
35. Conversely, Gurr's theory could be used by a critic of U.S. counterinsurgency policy i
argue that escalating the repression of dissidents (e.g., by extensive bombing as advocated by
would lead to more violence in response, contrary to cost-benefit calculations based on a ra
theory (Schultz 1979).
36. In those cases where these affiliations were not clearly stated in the publication itself, I u
reference books such as the National Faculty Directory and Dissertation Abstracts Internat
CONCLUSIONS
Walter Laqueur (1977, 10) wrote that the net result of applying polit
collective violence is negative: "no truly scientific, that is predictive or
theories have emerged."37 In part, this was because Laqueur believed
theory is even conceivable and that, in particular, RD cannot be measur
because no quantitative index can reflect the qualitative aspect of huma
I would argue on the contrary that Gurr's theory was predictive and that
by empirical tests is part of the progress of science, not a failure. If r
show that a plausible explanation of a phenomenon is not in fact satisfacto
the way for other hypotheses to be developed and tested.
The reasons for rejecting RD as the primary cause of collective violen
empirical and nonempirical. The fact that many social scientists (inclu
gave nonempirical reasons for rejecting it does not mean that the
"unscientific." In the physical sciences, too (as noted earlier), a theory m
on theoretical grounds without regard to its empirical tests or accepted f
reasons before its empirical predictions have been tested.
But two of the nonempirical objections suggest that theories in the s
may be judged by harsher standards than those in the natural scienc
criticism that an assumed causal element such as RD is not directly me
not be considered a fatal flaw in physics or chemistry, where theories ba
properties of atoms were successfully pursued long before atoms cou
observed; even today, theories based on unobservable quarks are wide
Second, the fact that collective phenomena are reductively explained
individual properties, far from being a defect, would be considered a virt
science; thus, statistical mechanics has been acclaimed for explaining
phenomena such as the condensation of gas to liquid in terms of the
molecules.
More generally, a model in physics is not expected to take account of all factors
that might possibly be involved; on the contrary, it is widely recognized to be more
effective to focus on one or two important factors when first investigating a problem.
Yet numerous critics of RD theory dismissed it for failing to include additional factors,
without any attempt to show that those factors are as important as the ones Gurr did
include.
Planck's (1950) principle does seem to govern this case in one respect: I found only
a handful of social scientists who actually changed their views about RD on the basis
of either empirical or nonempirical reasons. For the most part, the supporters stopped
publishing on the subject (or continued to support it); those who rejected RD, or
adopted an alternative theory, had not supported RD in earlier publications. But the
37. Lichbach (1989) has a similar pessimistic conclusion about the research on inequality and political
conflict.
38. Compare with Rosenberg's (1952, 58) statement, in connection with Milton Friedman's defense of
"unrealistic assumptions" in economic models, that "the idealized character of assumptions through the
most successful theories of physical science, has long ago settled the question of whether unrealistic
assumptions are permissible in predictively successful scientific theorizing."
REFERENCES
Abeles, Ronald P. 1976. Relative deprivation, rising expectations, and Black militancy. J
Issues 32 (2):119-37.
Adatto, Kiku, and Stephen Cole. 1981. The functions of classical theory in contempo
research: The case of Max Weber. In Knowledge and society: Studies in the sociology
and present, edited by R. A. Jones and H. Kuklick, 137-62. Greenwich, CT: JAI.
American Political Science Association. 1988. Biographical directory. Washington, DC: Am
Science Association.
Ardrey, Robert. 1966. The territorial imperative. New York: Atheneum.
Aya, Rod. 1979. Theories of revolution reconsidered: Contrasting models of collective violence. Theory and
Society 8:39-99.
Barkan, Steven E. 1980. Judging the judges. Human Rights 8 (4):34-7.
Berelson, Bernard, and Gary A. Steiner. 1964. Human behavior: An inventory of scientificfindings. New
York: Harcourt Brace.
Berman, Bruce J. 1976. Bureaucracy and incumbent violence: Colonial administration and the origins of
the "Mau Mau" emergency in Kenya. British Journal of Political Science 6:143-75.
Bowen, Don R., Elinor Bowen, Sheldon Gawiser, and Louis H. Masotti. 1968. Deprivation, mobility, and
orientation toward protest of the urban poor. In Riots and rebellion, edited by L. H. Masotti and D. R.
Bowen, 187-200. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Bowers, D. A., C. R. Mitchell, and K. Webb. 1980. Modelling bicommunal conflict: I. Posing the problem.
Futures 12:473-88.
Braybrooke, David. 1987. Philosophy of social science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Brush, Stephen G. 1989. Prediction and theory evaluation: The case of light bending. Science 246:1124-29.
. 1990a. The most-cited physical sciences publications in the 1945-1954 Science Citation Index.
Current Contents, 14 May, 7-17.
.1990b. The most-cited physical sciences publications in the 1945-1954 Science Citation Index.
Current Contents, 15 October, 8-13.
. 1990c. The most-cited physical sciences publications in the 1945-1954 Science Citation Index.
Current Contents, 22 October, 7-16.
1990d. Prediction and theory evaluation: Alfvtn on space plasma phenomena. Eos, Transactions
of the American Geophysical Union 71:19-33.
39. One reason for this may be that RD theory is viewed as a "reduction" of sociology to psychology,
which thus tends to annoy sociologists and please psychologists.
. 1995. Dynamics of theory change: The role of predictions. In PSA 1994: Proceedin
biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 2, edited by D. Hull, M
R. M. Burian, 133-45. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.
Calvert, Peter. 1970. Revolution. New York: Praeger.
Cantril, Hadley. 1965. The pattern of human concerns. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers Univ
Caplan, Nathan S., and Jeffery M. Paige. 1968. A study of ghetto rioters. Scientific Ameri
Cohen, Jean L. 1985. Strategy or identity: New theoretical paradigms and contemporary s
Social Research 52:663-716.
Cole, Stephen. 1975. The growth of scientific knowledge: Theories of deviance as a case study. In The idea
of social structure: Papers in honor of Robert Merton, edited by L. A. Coser, 175-220. New York:
Harcourt Brace.
. 1992. Making science: Between nature and society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Coming, Peter A. 1971. The biological bases of behavior and some implications for political science. World
Politics 23:321-70.
Flaming, Karl H. 1968. Who "riots" and why? Black and white perspectives in Milwaukee. Milwau
WI: Milwaukee Urban League.
Fogelson, Robert M. 1971. Violence as protest: A study of riots and ghettos. Garden City, NY: Doubl
Forster, Robert, and Jack P. Greene, eds. 1970. Preconditions of revolution in early modem Eur
Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.
Freeman, Michael. 1972. Review article: Theories of revolution. British Journal of Political Scie
2:339-59.
Gamson, William A. 1975. The strategy of social protest. Homewood, IL: Dorsey.
Geschwender, Barbara N., and James A. Geschwender. 1973. Relative deprivation and participation in the
civil rights movement. Social Science Quarterly 54:403-11.
Geschwender, James. 1964. Social structure and the Negro revolt: An examination of some hypotheses.
Social Forces 43:248-56.
Governor's Commission on the Los Angeles Riots. 1965. Violence in the city: An end or a beginning? Los
Angeles: Jeffries Banknote.
Greene, Thomas H. 1984. Comparative revolutionary movements. 2d ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice
Hall.
Guimond, Serge, and Lise Dub6-Simard. 1983. Relative deprivation theory and the Quebec Nationalist
Movement: The cognition-emotion distinction and the personal-group deprivation issue. Journal o
Personality and Social Psychology 44:526-35.
Gumey, Joan Neff, and Kathleen J. Tierney. 1982. Relative deprivation and social movements: A critical
look at twenty years of theory and research. Sociological Quarterly 23:33-47.
Gurr, Ted Robert. 1968. Psychological factors in civil violence. World Politics 20:245-78.
1970. Why men rebel. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Gurr, Ted Robert, and Mark Irving Lichbach. 1986. Forecasting internal conflict: A competitive evaluation
of empirical theories. Comparative Political Studies 19:3-38.
Halebsky, Sandor. 1974. New perspectives on political radicalism. Journal of Political and Military
Sociology 2:113-24.
Hibbs, Douglas A. 1973. Mass political violence: A cross-national causal analysis. New York: John Wiley
Hirschmann, Albert. 1973. The changing tolerance for income inequality in the course of economic
development. Quarterly Journal of Economics 87:544-66.
Horowitz, Irving Louis, ed. 1967. The rise and fall of Project Camelot. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Hull, David L., Peter D. Tessner, and Arthur M. Diamond. 1978. Planck's principle. Science 202:717-23.
Huntington, Samuel. 1968. Political order in changing societies. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Hutchison, Terence. 1960. The significance and basic postulates of economic theory. 2d ed. New York
Kelley.
Jenkins, J. Craig, and Kurt Shock. 1992. Global structures and political processes in the study of domestic
political conflict. Annual Review of Sociology 18:161-85.
Keddie, Nikki R., ed. 1995. Debating revolutions. New York: New York University Press.
Kennedy, Charles R., Jr. 1984. Multinational corporations and political risk in the Persian Gulf. International
Journal of Middle East Studies 16:391-403.
Kent, Stephen A. 1982. Relative deprivation and resource mobilization: A study of early Quakerism. British
Journal of Sociology 33:529-44.
Kerbo, Harold R. 1978. Foreign involvement in the preconditions for political violence. The world system
and the case of Chile. Journal of Conflict Resolution 22:363-91.
Kiser, Edgar, and Michael Hechter. 1991. The role of general theory in comparative-historical sociology.
American Journal of Sociology 97:1-30.
Klandermans, Bert. 1984. Mobilization and participation: Social-psychological expansions of resource
mobilization theory. American Sociological Review 49:583-600.
Kramnick, Isaac. 1972. Reflections on revolution: Definition and explanation in recent scholarship. History
and Theory 11:26-63.
Ladner, Robert A., Barry J. Schwartz, Sandra J. Roker, and Loretta S. Titterud. 1981. The Miami riots of
1980: Antecedent conditions, community responses and participant characteristics. Research in Social
Movements, Conflicts and Change 4:171-214.
Laqueur, Walter. 1977. Interpretations of terrorism: Fact, fiction and political science. Journal of
porary History 12:1-42.
Laslett, Barbara. 1992. Gender in/and social science history. Social Science History 16:177-95.
Law, Kim S., and Edward J. Walsh. 1983. The interaction of grievances and structure in social m
analysis: The case of JUST [Johnstowners United to Stop another Tragedy]. Sociological Q
24:123-36.
Lichbach, Mark Irving. 1989. An evaluation of "Does economic inequality breed political conflict?" studies.
World Politics 41:431-70.
Lorenz, Konrad. 1966. On aggression. New York: Harcourt Brace.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1971. Is a science of comparative politics possible? In Against the self-images of the
age, 260-79. New York: Schocken.
- . 1973. Ideology, social science, and revolution. Comparative Politics 5:321-42.
MacIntyre, Stuart. 1980. Little Moscows: Communism and working-class militancy in inter-war Britain.
London: Croom Helm.
Martin, Joanne, Philip Brickman, and Alan Murray. 1984. Moral outrage and pragmatism: Explanations for
collective action. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 20:484-96.
Marx, Gary T. 1972. Perspectives on violence. Contemporary Psychology 17:128-31.
Marx, Gary T., and James Wood. 1975. Strands of theory and research in collective behavior. Annual Review
of Sociology 1:363-428.
McCarthy, John D., and Mayer N. Zald. 1973. The trend ofsocial movements in America: Professionalization
and resource mobilization. Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press.
. 1976. Resource mobilization and social movements: A partial theory. American Journal of
Sociology 82:1212-41.
McPhail, Clark. 1971. Civil disorder participation: A critical examination of recent research. American
Sociological Review 36:1058-73.
Midlarsky, Manus. 1988. Rulers and the ruled: Pattemed inequality and the onset of mass political violence.
American Political Science Review 82:491-509.
Midlarsky, Manus I., and Kenneth Roberts. 1985. Class, state, and revolution in Central America: Nicaragua
and El Salvador compared. Journal of Conflict Resolution 29:163-93.
Miller, Abraham H., Louis H. Bolce, and Mark Halligan. 1977. The j-curve theory and the Black urban riots:
An empirical test of progressive relative deprivation theory. American Political Science Review
71:964-82.
Morris, Aldon D., and Cedric Herring. 1987. Theory and research in social movements: A critical review.
Annual Review of Political Science 2:137-98.
Morris, Aldon D., and Carol McClung Mueller, eds. 1992. Frontiers in social movement theory. New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
Morrison, Denton E., Kenneth E. Hornback (with Virginia Bemis, Mark Pittman, Tracy Harris, Linda Buttel,
Deborah Hughes, Joanne White, Carla Rossi, and Deborah Godfrey). 1976. Collective behavior: A
bibliography. New York: Garland.
Moshiri, Farrokh. 1991. Revolutionary conflict theory in an evolutionary perspective. In Revolutions in the
late twentieth century, edited by J. A. Goldstone, T. R. Gurr, and F. Moshiri, 4-36. Boulder, CO:
Westview.
Mueller, Carol McClurg. 1992. In Frontiers in social movement Theory, edited by A. D. Morris and C. M.
Mueller, 3-25. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Muller, Edward N. 1972. A test of a partial theory of potential for political violence. American Political
Science Review 66:928-59.
. 1977. Mass politics: Focus on participation. American Behavioral Science 21:63-86.
.1979. Aggressive political participation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
.1980. The psychology of political protest and violence. In Handbook of political conflict, edited
by T. R. Gurr, 69-99. New York: Free Press.
. 1985. Income inequality, regime repressiveness, and political violence. American Sociological
Review 50:47-61.
Muller, Edward N., and Thomas O. Jukam. 1983. Discontent and aggressive political participation. B
Journal of Political Science 13:159-79.
Muller, Edward N., and Mitchell A. Seligson. 1987. Inequality and insurgency. American Political Sc
Review 81:425-51.
Muller, Edward N., and Erich Weede. 1994. Theories of rebellion: Relative deprivation and power
contention. Rationality and Society 6:40-57.
Noton, M., C. R. Mitchell, and F. R. Janes. 1974. The systems analysis of conflict. Futures 6:114-32.
Oberschall, Anthony. 1973. Social conflict and social movements. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Olson, James M., and J. Douglas Hazlewood. 1986. Relative deprivation and social comparison: An
integrative perspective. In Relative deprivation and social comparison, edited by J. M. Olson, C. P.
Herman, and M. P. Zanna, 1-15. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Olson, James M., C. Peter Herman, and Mark P. Zanna, eds. 1986. Relative deprivation and social
comparison. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Olson, Mancur. 1965. The logic of collective action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Papcke, Sven. 1971. How-to-keep-them-down. Politische Vierteljahresschrift 12:125-29.
Parsons, Talcott. 1937. The structure of social action. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Pennock, J. Roland, and John W. Chapman, eds. 1977. Human nature in politics. New York: New York
University Press.
Pettigrew, Thomas F. 1971. Racially separate or together? New York: McGraw-Hill.
Piven, Frances Fox, and Richard A. Cloward. 1992. Normalizing collective protest. In Frontiers in social
movement theory, edited by A. D. Morris and C. M. Mueller, 301-25. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Planck, Max. 1950. Scientific autobiography. London: Williams & Norgate.
Platt, Anthony M., ed. 1971. The politics of riot commissions, 1917-1970: A collection of official reports
and essays. New York: Macmillan.
Popper, Karl. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.
.1974. Darwinism as a metaphysical research programme. In The philosophy of Karl Popper, edited
by P. A. Schilpp, 133-43. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
. 1978. Natural selection and the emergence of mind. Dialectica 32:339-55.
Portes, Alejandro. 1970. Leftist radicalism in Chile: A test of three hypotheses. Comparative Politics
2:251-74.
.1971a. Urbanization and politics in Latin America. Social Science Quarterly 52:697-720.
1971b. On the logic of post-factum explanations: The hypothesis of lower-class frustration as the
cause of leftist radicalism. Social Forces 50:26-44.
Ramirez, Francisco 0. 1981. Comparative social movements. International Journal of Comparative
Sociology 22:3-21.
Rosenberg, Alexander. 1988. Philosophy of social science. Boulder, CO: Westview.
. 1992. Economics: Mathematical politics or science of diminishing returns? Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Rudner, Richard. 1966. The philosophy of social science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Rule, James B. 1988. Theories of civil violence. Berkeley: University of California Press.
. 1989. Rationality and non-rationality in militant collective action. Sociological Theory 7:145-60.
Rule, James B., and Charles Tilly. 1972. 1830 and the unnatural history of revolution. Journal of Social
Issues 28:49-76.
Runciman, Walter G. 1966. Relative deprivation and social justice: A study of attitudes to social inequality
in twentieth-century England. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
. 1989. Confessions of a reluctant theorist: Selected essays. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Salert, Barbara. 1976. Revolutions and revolutionaries: Four theories. New York: Elsevier.
Sanders, David, and Eric Tannenbaum. 1983. Direct action and political culture: The changing political
consciousness of the British public. European Journal of Politics 11:45-61.
Schultz, Richard. 1979. Coercive force and military strategy: Deterrence logic and the cost-benefit model
of counterinsurgency warfare. Western Political Quarterly 32:444-66.
Schwartz, David C. 1974. Toward a more relevant and rigorous political science. Journal
36:103-37.
Shapin, Steven. 1993. Mertonian concessions. Science 259:839-41.
Silvert, Kalman H. 1971. Much conflict, little power. Comparative Politics 3:447-62.
Skocpol, Theda. 1976. France, Russia, China: A structural analysis of social revolutions. Comparative
Studies in Society and History 18:175-210.
Smelser, Neil J. 1962. Theory of collective behavior. New York: Free Press.
Snyder, David, and Charles Tilly. 1972. Hardship and collective violence in France, 1830 to 1960. American
Sociological Review 37:520-32.
Social Science Research Council, Committee on Historiography. 1954. The social sciences in historical
study. Bulletin No. 64. New York: Social Sciences Research Council.
Somit, Albert. 1968. Toward a more biologically-oriented political science: Ethology and psychopharma-
cology. Midwest Journal of Political Science 12:550-67.
Spilerman, Seymour. 1970. The causes of racial disturbances: A comparison of alternative explanations.
American Sociological Review 35:627-49.
- 1971. The causes of racial disturbances: Tests of an explanation. American Sociological Review
36:427-42.
Stone, William F. 1981. Political psychology: A Whig history. In Handbook of political behavior, edited by
S. L. Long, 1-67. New York: Plenum.
Terwilliger, Robert F. 1971. Review of Why men rebel, by T. R. Gurr. Social Research 38:169-72.
Thompson, E. P. 1971. The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century. Past and Present
50:76-136.
Tiemey, William G. 1988. Much ado about something: Naturalistic inquiry and the paradigm revolution.
Journal of Higher Education 59:225-30.
Tilly, Charles. 1969. Collective violence in European perspective. In The history of violence in America,
edited by H. D. Graham and T. R. Gurr, 4-45. New York: Bantam.
.1971. Review of Why men rebel, by T. R. Gurr. Journal of Social History 4:416-20.
. 1973. Does modernization breed revolution? Comparative Politics 5:426-47.
.1975. Revolutions and collective violence. In Handbook of political science, vol. 3, edited by F.
Greenstein and N. W. Polsby, 483-555. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
- 1978. From mobilization to revolution. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
- 1984. Big structures, large processes, huge comparisons. New York: Russell Sage.
Tilly, Charles, Louise Tilly, and Richard Tilly. 1975. The rebellious century, 1830-1930. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Useem, Michael. 1972. Ideological and interpersonal change in the radical protest movement. Social
Problems 19:451-69.
.1975. Protest movements in America. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.
1976. Legitimacy and government control of the production of academic social knowledge. Journal
of Political and Military Sociology 4:217-32.
Utter, Glenn H., and James M. Vanderleeuw. 1991. Election predictions: Theory and social science. Midsouth
Political Science Journal 12:114-31.
Wanderer, Jules J. 1968. 1967 riots: A test of the congruity of events. Social Problems 16:193-98.
Wasbum, Philo. 1974. Political sociology in the United States: A case study of theoretical change and
continuity. Human Relations 27:321-37.
Weinberg, Steven. 1992. Dreams of afinal theory. New York: Pantheon.
Wheeler, Robert F. 1975. German women and the Communist International: The case of the Independent
Social Democrats. Central European History 8:113-39.
Wilhelm, Sidney M. 1970. Who needs the Negro? Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.
Williams, Robin M., Jr. 1975a. Relative deprivation. In The idea of social structure, edited by L. A. Coser,
355-78. New York: Harcourt Brace.
-----. 1 1975b. Race and ethnic relations. Annual Review of Sociology 1:125-64.
Wilson, John. 1973. Introduction to social movements. New York: Basic Books.
Young, M. Crawford. 1970. Rebellion and the Congo. In Protest and power in Black Africa, edited b
Rotberg and A. A. Mazrui, 969-1011. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zagoiin, Perez. 1973. Theories of revolution in contemporary historiography. Political Science Quar
88:23-52.
. 1982. Rebels and rulers 1500-1660. Vol. 1. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Zald, Mayer N. 1991. Sociology as a discipline: Quasi-science and quasi-humanities. American Sociologist
22:165-87.
- . 1992. Looking backward to look forward: Reflections on the past and future of the resource
mobilization research program. In Frontiers in social movement theory, edited by A. D. Morris and C. M.
Mueller, 326-48. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Zimmermann, Ekkart. 1979. Crises and crises outcomes: Towards a new synthetic approach. European
Journal of Political Research 7:67-115.
. 1980. Macro-comparative research on political protest. In Handbook of political conflict, edited by
T. R. Gurr, 167-237. New York: Free Press.
. 1983. Political violence, crises, and revolutions. Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.
Zurcher, Louis A., and David A. Snow. 1981. Collective behavior: Social movements. In Socialpsychology:
Sociological perspectives, edited by M. Rosenberg and R. H. Turner, 447-82. New York: Basic Books.